Abstract
Computationalist theories of mind require brain symbols, that is, neural events that represent kinds or instances of kinds. Standard models of computation require multiple inscriptions of symbols with the same representational content. The satisfaction of two conditions makes it easy to see how this requirement is met in computers, but we have no reason to think that these conditions are satisfied in the brain. Thus, if we wish to give computationalist explanations of human cognition, without committing ourselvesa priori to a strong and unsupported claim in neuroscience, we must first either explain how we can provide multiple brain symbols with the same content, or explain how we can abandon standard models of computation. It is argued that both of these alternatives require us to explain the execution of complex tasks that have a cognition-like structure. Circularity or regress are thus threatened, unless noncomputationalist principles can provide the required explanations. But in the latter case, we do not know that noncomputationalist principles might not bear most of the weight of explaining cognition. Four possible types of computationalist theory are discussed; none appears to provide a promising solution to the problem. Thus, despite known difficulties in noncomputationalist investigations, we have every reason to pursue the search for noncomputationalist principles in cognitive theory.
Similar content being viewed by others
Explore related subjects
Discover the latest articles, news and stories from top researchers in related subjects.References
Block, Ned (1986), ‘Advertisement for a Semantics for Psychology’,Midwest Studies in Philosophy 10, pp. 615–678.
Brooks, R. A. (1991), ‘Intelligence Without Representation’,Artificial Intelligence 47, pp. 139–159.
Chalmers, D. (1993), ‘Connectionism and Compositionality: Why Fodor and Pylyshyn Were Wrong’,Philosophical Psychology 6, pp. 305–319.
Cummins, R. (1989).Meaning and Mental Representation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (1980), ‘Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology’,The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3, pp. 63–73.
Fodor, J. (1987),Psychosemantics, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. & Pylyshyn, Z. (1988), ‘Connectionism and Cognitive Architecture: A Critical Analysis’ in S. Pinker & J. Mehler, eds.,Connections and Symbols, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gallistel, C. R. (1980),The Organization of Action: A New Synthesis, Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Gallistel, C. R. (1990),The Organization of Learning, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Grossberg, S. (1982), ‘How Does a Brain Build a Cognitive Code?’,Studies of Mind and Brain, Dordrecht, Netherlands: D. Reidel.
Harman, G. (1970), ‘Language and Learning’,Nous 4, pp. 33–43.
Haugeland, J. (1985),Artificial Intelligence: The Very Idea, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Nelson, R. J. (1987), ‘Church's Thesis and Cognitive Science’,Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 28, pp. 581–614.
Reeke, G. N. & Edelman, G. M. (1988), ‘Real Brains and Artificial Intelligence’, in S. R. Graubard, ed.,The Artificial Intelligence Debate, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Robinson, W. S. (1992),Computers, Minds and Robots, Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Shastri, L. & Ajjanagadde, V. (1993), ‘From Simple Associations to Systematic Reasoning: A Connectionist Representation of Rules, Variables and Dynamic Bindings Using Temporal Synchrony’,The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16, pp. 417–494.
Von Eckardt, Barbara (1993),What is Cognitive Science?, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Robinson, W.S. Brain symbols and computationalist explanation. Mind Mach 5, 25–44 (1995). https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00974188
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/BF00974188