Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                
Skip to main content

Toward cognitivist ontologies

On the role of selective attention for upper ontologies

  • Research Report
  • Published:
Cognitive Processing Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Ontologies play a key role in modern information society although there are still many fundamental questions regarding their structure to be answered. In this paper, some of these are presented, and it is argued that they require a shift from realist to cognitivist ontologies, with ontology design crucially depending on taking both cognitive and linguistic aspects into consideration. A detailed discussion of central parts of a proposed cognitivist upper ontology based on qualitative representations of selective attention is presented.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Subscribe and save

Springer+ Basic
$34.99 /Month
  • Get 10 units per month
  • Download Article/Chapter or eBook
  • 1 Unit = 1 Article or 1 Chapter
  • Cancel anytime
Subscribe now

Buy Now

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Explore related subjects

Discover the latest articles, news and stories from top researchers in related subjects.

Notes

  1. “Descriptive Ontology for Linguistic and Cognitive Engineering” (Masolo et al. 2003).

  2. I will be using the term “type” here in the sense of what is called “property” in Masolo et al. (2003).

  3. This scenario is taken from a short story of Polish science fiction author Stanislav Lem (1976), “Do you exist, Mister Johns?”, German version “Gibt es Sie, Mister Johns?” in Nacht und Schimmel, Suhrkamp Taschenbuch Verlag, Frankfurt am Main. There are corresponding classical puzzles in philosophy, e.g., the “ship of theseus” puzzle of Thomas Hobbes cited in Scholl (2007).

  4. Note also that while there seems to be a correspondence of endurants and their expression as nouns, and perdurants and their expression as verbs, there are also nouns expressing perdurants (the last ride, too much riding etc.).

  5. And is, in fact, common practice, cf. e.g., http://www.opencyc.com.

  6. The neglected role of Stuff in Ontology has been discussed in detail in the work of Henry Laycock, e.g., Laycock (1972).

  7. Note also that TemporalStuff can be linguistically expressed, e.g., too much riding can cause severe back pain.

  8. This translates to diese Möbel (’these [!] furniture’) in German.

  9. Suggested Upper Merged Ontology, see http://www.ontologyportal.org.

  10. Personally, I find “cognitive ontology” the better term (as in “Cognitive Science”). However, as it might be misunderstood merely as an ontology of psychological notions, I do not use it.

  11. The illustrating example Kahneman et al. give is the well-known reaction of onlookers watching the approaching superman: “It’s a bird; it’s a plane; it’s Superman!”. They refer to a persistent object, although both perceptual features and attributed types change.

  12. To my knowledge, there is no comparable approach viewing Stuff like this. Usually (cf. e.g., vanMarle and Scholl 2003), Stuff is equated with Amount of stuff ( Amount of matter ), which, being of type Object , is a different thing.

  13. It is important to point out here that the author and the authors cited are aware of the fact that there is no simple word-to-ontological category mapping (cf., e.g., Jackendoff 1996).

  14. Cf. Krifka (1989) for a formal approach on what he calls the relation between nominal reference and temporal constitution.

  15. The corresponding linguistic test here is asking how many / wie viele (aggregate) or how much / wie viel (stuff).

  16. Point instances are also called “semelfactives”.

  17. These features obviously correspond to ±b and ±i.

  18. This corresponds to evidence for micro-scale motion detectors whose input is glued together in a larger-scale motion area.

  19. This is in line with “the idea that time-sensation derives, specifically, from perceiving the changes [\(\ldots\)] entailed by the activity of attention” (Marchetti 2009, p. 33, his emphasis).

  20. This correlates with the distinction of having to represent changes in the world (conceived time) and changes in cognitive processing (processing time) in Langacker (1987). Note that although these aspects can be dissociated, both can cooccur.

  21. The Kleene plus in the following depictions is to be interpreted as ‘one frame or more of type X/Y’.

  22. As mentioned, a FTE entity somehow is a “transitional blob” (or mostly: “temporal blob”) as the middle frame “stands out” wrt. to its surrounding frames.

  23. They are sometimes called “pofective” (Herweg 1991). Note that a bounded process (or state) is neither an accomplishment nor a “punctual” event and hence a gap in standard classifications.

  24. This includes the characteristic motions of movement verbs. Note that one can run/walk on the spot.

  25. Similar, but not identical to, the FINSTs (“fingers of instantiation”) of Pylyshyn (2009), and quite probably at a higher level of representation. Similar, if not identical to, Talmy‘s plexity.

  26. This is corroborated by the observation that one has to use much for the modification of the process verbs used in (3) and (4): much/*many flashing/breathing.

  27. For example, there are at least countable objects (a time), aggregates (many times) and stuff (much time) in the time domain.

References

  • Baddeley A (2000) The episodic buffer: a new component of working memory. Trends Cogn Sci 4(11):417–423

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bellugi U, Korenberg JR, Klima ES (2001) Williams syndrome: an exploration of neurocognitive and genetic features. Clin Neurosci Res 1:217–229

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berners-Lee T, Hendler J, Lassila O (2001) The semantic web. Sci Am 284(5):24–30

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bierwisch M, Lang E (eds) (1989) Dimensional adjectives. Springer, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Bihrle AM, Bellugi U, Delis D, Marks S (1989) Seeing either the forest or the trees: dissociation in visuospatial processing. Brain Cogn 11(1):37–49

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Bittner M (2006) Ontology for human talk and thought (not robotics). Theor Linguist 32:47–56

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bittner M, Trondhjem N (2008) Quantification as reference: evidence from q-verbs. In: Matthewson L (eds) Quantification: a cross-linguistic perspective. Emerald, Amsterdam, pp 7–66

    Google Scholar 

  • Boroditsky L (2003) Linguistic relativity. In: Nadel L (eds) Encyclopedia of cognitive science. MacMillan Press: London, pp 917–921

    Google Scholar 

  • Carstensen KU (1995) Focused spatial attention and spatial semantics: the case of ‘to follow’. In: Proceedings of the TSM’95, Toulouse, pp B15–B27

  • Carstensen KU (2007) Spatio-temporal ontologies and attention. Spatial Cogn Comput 7(1):13–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carstensen KU (2009) Nicht-sprachliches Wissen [Non-linguistic knowledge]. In: Carstensen KU, Ebert C, Ebert C, Jekat S, Klabunde R, Langer H (eds) Computerlinguistik und Sprachtechnologie—Eine Einführung [Computational linguistics and language technology—An introduction], 3rd edn. Springer, Berlin

  • Chun MM (1997) Types and tokens in visual processing: a double dissociation between the attentional blink and repetition blindness. J Exp Psychol Hum Percept Perform 23:738–755

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Cimiano P, Voelker J, Buitelaar P (2010) Ontology construction. In: Indurkhya N (eds) Handbook of natural language processing. CRC Press, London, pp 577–604

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark HH, Carpenter PA, Just MA (1973) On the meeting of semantics and perception. In: Chase W (eds) Visual information processing. Academic Press, New York, pp 311–381

    Google Scholar 

  • Dahlgren K (1988) Naive semantics for natural language understanding. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dahlgren K (1995) A linguistic ontology. Int J Hum-Comput Stud 43(5-6):809–818

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dahlgren K, McDowell J (1986) Kind types in knowledge representation. In: Proceedings of the 11th international conference on computational linguistics (COLING), pp 216–221

  • Gangemi A, Guarino N, Masolo C, Oltramari R (2001a) Understanding top-level ontological distinctions. In: Proceedings of IJCAI-01 workshop on ontologies and information sharing. AAAI Press, Menlo Park, pp 26–33

  • Gangemi A, Guarino N, Oltramari A (2001b) Conceptual analysis of lexical taxonomies: the case of wordnet top-level. In: FOIS (Formal Ontology in Information Systems), pp 285–296

  • Gärdenfors P (1999) Some tenets of cognitive semantics. In: Allwood J, Gärdenfors P (eds) Cognitive semantics: meaning and cognition. John Benjamins, Amsterdam, pp 19–36

  • Gärdenfors P, Kopp L (2002) Attention as a minimal criterion of intentionality in robots. Cogn Sci Q 2:302–319

    Google Scholar 

  • Gruber TR (1995) Toward principles for the design of ontologies used for knowledge sharing. Int J Hum Comput Stud 43:907–928

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guarino N, Welty C (2000) A formal ontology of properties. In: Dieng R, Corby O (eds) Knowledge engineering and knowledge management: methods, models and tools. Springer, Berlin, pp 97–112

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Harnad S (2003) Categorical perception. In: Encyclopedia of cognitive science. Nature Publishing Group, Macmillan

  • Herweg M (1991) Aspectual requirements of temporal connectives: evidence for a two-level approach to semantics. In: Pustejovsky J, Bergler S (eds) SIGLEX workshop, Lecture Notes in Computer Science. Springer, Berlin, vol 627, pp 185–200

  • Holland JH, Holyoak KJ, Nisbett RE, Thagard PR (1986) Induction: processes of inference, learning, and discovery. Bradford Books/MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Horrocks I (2008) Ontologies and the semantic web. Commun ACM 51(12):58–67

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hwang C, Schubert LK (1994) Interpreting tense, aspect, and time adverbials: a compositional, unified approach. In: Gabbay D, Ohlbach H (eds) Proceedings of the 1st international conference on temporal logic. Springer, Berlin, pp 238–264

  • Jackendoff R (1983) Semantics and cognition. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff R (1991) Parts and boundaries. Cognition 41:9–45. Reprinted in Levin B, Pinker S (eds) (1992) Lexical and conceptual semantics. Blackwell, Cambridge, pp 9-45

  • Jackendoff R (1996) The proper treatment of measuring out, telicity, and perhaps even quantification in english. Nat Lang Linguist Theory 14:305–354

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johansson I (2005) Qualities, quantities, and the endurant-perdurant distinction in top-level ontologies. In: Althoff KD, Dengel A, Bergmann R, Nick M, Roth-Berghofer T (eds) WM 2005: professional knowledge management experiences and vision, LNAI, vol 3782. Springer, Berlin, pp 543–550

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman D, Treisman A, Gibbs B (1992) The reviewing of object files: object-specific integration of information. Cogn Psychol 24:174–219

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kanwisher N (1987) Repetition blindness: type recognition without token individuation. Cognition 27:117–143

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Keil FC (1989) Concepts, kinds, and cognitive development. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka M (1989) Nominal reference, temporal constitution and quantification in event semantics. In: Bartsch R, van Benthem J, von Emde Boas P (eds) Semantics and contextual expression. Foris Publication, Dordrecht, pp 75–115

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff G (1987) Women, fire, and dangerous things: what categories reveal about the mind. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Lang E, Carstensen KU, Simmons G (1991) Modeling spatial knowledge on a linguistic basis: theory−prototype−integration. Lecture Notes in Artificial Intelligence. Springer, Berlin, No. 481

  • Langacker R (1987) Foundations of cognitive grammarc I: theoretical prerequisites. Stanford University Press, Stanford

    Google Scholar 

  • Laycock H (1972) Some questions of ontology. Reprinted in Analysis and Metaphysics vol 4, March 2006

  • Laycock H (2005a) Mass nouns, count nouns and non-count nouns. Encyclopedia of language and linguistics. Elsevier, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Laycock H (2005b) Theories of matter. Synthese, reprinted with modification. In: Pelletier FJ (eds) Mass terms: some philosophical problems. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenat D, Guha RV (1990) Building large knowledge-based Systems: representation and inference in the Cyc project. Addison-Wesley, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahesh K, Nirenburg S, Cowie J, Farwell D (1996) An assessment of Cyc for natural language processing. Technical Report, MCCS-96-302. Computing Research Laboratory, New Mexico State University, Las Cruces

  • Marchetti G (2006) A presentation of attentional semantics. Cogn Process 7:163–194

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Marchetti G (2009) Studies on time: a proposal on how to get out of circularity. Cogn Process 10(1):7–40

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Marchetti G (2010) Consciousness, attention and meaning. Nova Publishers, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Masolo C, Borgo S, Gangemi A, Guarino N, Oltramari A (2003) Wonderweb deliverable d18: ontology library. Deliverable D18, ISTC-CNR, Italy

  • Navon D (1977) Forest before trees: the precedence of global features in visual perception. Cogn Psychol 9:353–383

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nirenburg S, Raskin V (2004) Ontological semantics. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Oberle D, Ankolekar A, Hitzler P, Cimiano P, Sintek M, Kiesel M, Mougouie B, Vembu S, Baumann S, Romanelli M, Buitelaar P, Engel R, Sonntag D, Reithinger N, Loos B, Porzel R, Zorn HP, Micelli V, Schmidt C, Weiten M, Burkhardt F, Zhou J (2007) DOLCE ergo SUMO: on foundational and domain models in the smartweb integrated ontology (SWIntO). J Web Semant Sci Serv Agents World Wide Web 5(3):156–174

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pöppel E (2004) Lost in time: a historical frame, elementary processing units and the 3-second window. Acta Neurobiol Exp (Wars) 64:295–301

    Google Scholar 

  • Pylyshyn ZW (2009) Perception, representation and the world the finst that binds. In: Trick DDLM (eds) Computation, cognition and pylyshyn. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Scholl BJ (2001) Objects and attention: the state of the art. Cognition 80(1/2):1–46

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Scholl BJ (2007) Object persistence in philosophy and psychology. Mind Lang 22(5):563–591

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith B (2003) Ontology. In: Floridi L (ed) Blackwell guide to the philosophy of computing and information. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 155–166

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith B (2004) Beyond concepts, or: ontology as reality representation. In: Varzi A, Vieu L (eds) Formal ontology and information systems. Proceedings of the third international conference (FOIS 2004). IOS Press, Amsterdam, pp 73–84

  • Smith B (2006) Against idiosyncrasy in ontology development. In: Bennett B, Fellbaum C (eds) Formal ontology in information systems (FOIS 2006). IOS Press, Amsterdam, pp 15–26

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith B, Mark DM (2003) Do mountains exist? Toward an ontology of landforms. Environ Plan B (Plan Des) 30(3):411–427

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steedman M (2005) The productions of time: temporality and causality in linguistic semantics. Draft tutorial notes about temporal semantics 5.0. University of Edinburgh

  • Stiles J, Reilly J, Paul B, Moses P (2005) Cognitive development following early brain injury: evidence for neural adaptation. Trends Cogn Sci 9(3):136–143

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Talmy L (2000) Toward a cognitive semantics, vol I. The MIT Press, Cambridge

  • Treisman A (1988) Features and objects: the fourteenth bartlett memorial lecture. Q J Exp Psychol 40A(2):201–237

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Turatto M, Mazza V (2004) Behavioral and electrophysiological correlates of change blindness (invited paper). Int J Comput Cogn 2(4):85–113

    Google Scholar 

  • vanMarle K, Scholl BJ (2003) Attentive tracking of objects vs. substances. Psychol Sci 14(5):498–504

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank the two anonymous reviewers for their valuable comments. I also thank John Bateman, Peter Bosch, Werner Kuhn and Laure Vieu for helpful feedback on earlier versions of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Kai-Uwe Carstensen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Carstensen, KU. Toward cognitivist ontologies. Cogn Process 12, 379–393 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10339-011-0405-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10339-011-0405-0

Keywords