Abstract
We propose a simple model of value formation in two societies (communities). When forming values, individuals face conformity pressure within their own society and they are intolerant toward the other society. When such a value formation process is noisy, the interaction between conformity, intolerance and noise can give rise to interesting dynamic outcomes including two polarized societies and polarization across the two societies.








Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
When we check if a certain state is steady or stable, we drop the time subscript and use \(E_i, E_j\).
The derivation is provided in Anderson et al. [2].
The Fokker–Planck equation is not yet widely used in the economic analysis. See Binmore et al. [10], Friedman and Yellin [30] and Anderson et al. [2, 3] for applications of the Fokker–Planck equation in game theory; and Benhabib et al. [7] for an application of the Fokker–Planck equation to the study of income distributions.
We discretize both the set of values [0,1] (with grid size being 0.0001) and time to make the simulation work. By discretizing time, we use a normal distribution with mean 0 to approximate the noise. In addition, to ensure the dynamic stays in [0, 1], we impose boundary conditions to revert the dynamic back in range every time it escapes. Hence, in the plot we show, a very small portion of the graph is situated outside of [0,1]. The program is available upon request.
The results remain the same if we instead run 100,000 periods.
References
Afridi F, Li SX, Ren Y (2015) Social identity and inequality: the impact of China’s Hukou System. J Public Econ 123:17–29
Anderson S, Goeree J, Holt C (1999) Stochastic game theory: adjustment to equilibrium under noisy directional learning. Working paper
Anderson S, Goeree J, Holt C (1999) Stochastic game theory: for playing games, not just for doing theory. Proc Natl Acad Sci 96:10564–10567
Akerlof GA, Kranton RE (2000) Economics and identity. Q J Econ 115(3):715–753
Akerlof GA, Kranton RE (2010) Identity economics: how identities shape our work, wages, and well-being. Princeton University Press, Princeton
Akerlof R (2017) Value formation: the role of esteem. Games Econ Behav 102:1–19
Benhabib J, Bisin A, Zhu S (2016) The distribution of wealth in the Blanchard–Yaari model. Macroecon Dyn 20:466–481
Benjamin DJ, Choi J, Strickland AJ (2010) Social identity and preferences. Am Econ Rev 100(4):1913–1928
Bilancini E, Boncinelli L, Wu J (2018) The interplay of cultural intolerance and action-assortativity for the emergence of cooperation and homophily. Eur Econ Rev 102:1–18
Binmore K, Samuelson L, Vaughan R (1995) Musical chairs: modeling noisy evolution. Games Econ Behav 11:1–35
Bénabou R, Tirole J (2006) Incentives and prosocial behavior. Am Econ Rev 96:1652–1678
Bernhard H, Fehr E, Fischbacher U (2008) Group affiliation and altruistic norm enforcement. Am Econ Rev 96(2):217–221
Bernheim DB (1994) A theory of conformity. J Polit Econ 102:841–877
Bisin A, Verdier T (2001) The economics of cultural transmission and the dynamics of preferences. J Econ Theory 97(2):298–319
Bisin A, Verdier T (2011) The economics of cultural transmission and socialization. In: Jess Benhabib MJ, Bisin A (eds) Handbook of social economics, vol 1, Chapter 9, pp 339–416
Boyd R, Richerson PJ (1988) Culture and the evolutionary process. University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Brewer MB (1991) The social self: on being the same and different at the same time. Pers Soc Psychol Bull 17:475–482
Bomze IM (1990) Dynamic aspects of evolutionary stability. Monatsh Math 110:189–206
Bomze IM (1991) Cross entropy minimization in uninvadable states of complex populations. J Math Biol 30:73–87
Candelo N, Croson RT, Li SX (2017) Identity and social exclusion: an experiment with Hispanic immigrants in the U.S. Exp Econ 20:460–480
Carvalho J-P (2013) Veiling. Q J Econ 128:337–370
Carvalho J-P, Pradelski B (2019) Identity and underrepresentation. Working paper
Cavalli-Sforza LL, Feldman MW (1981) Cultural transmission and evolution: a quantitative approach. Princeton University Press, Princeton
Chen Y, Li SX, Liu TX, Shihd M (2014) Which hat to wear? Impact of natural identities on coordination and cooperation. Games Econ Behav 84:58–86
Cheung M-W (2014) Pairwise comparison dynamics for games with continuous strategy space. J Econ Theory 153:344–375
Cheung M-W (2016) Imitative dynamics for games with continuous strategy space. Games Econ Behav 99:206–223
Cheung M-W, Wu J (2018) On the probabilistic transmission of continuous cultural traits. J Econ Theory 174:300–323
Elster J (1989) Social norms and economic theory. J Econ Perspect 4:99–117
Fokker AD (1914) Die mittlere Energie rotierender elektrischer Dipole im Strahlungsfeld. Ann Phys 348:810–820
Friedman D, Yellin J (1997) Evolving landscapes for population games. Working paper
Goette L, Huffman D, Meier S (2006) The impact of group membership on cooperation and norm enforcement: evidence using random assignment to real social groups. Am Econ Rev 96(2):212–216
Goette L, Huffman D, Meier S (2012a) The impact of social ties on group interactions: evidence from minimal groups and randomly assigned real groups. Am Econ J Microecon 4(1):101–115
Goette L, Huffman D, Meier S, Sutter M (2012b) Competition between organizational groups: its impact on altruistic and anti-social motivations. Manag Sci 58(5):948–960
Granovetter M (1978) Threshold models of collective behavior. Am J Sociol 83:1420–1443
Hofbauer J, Oechssler J, Riedel F (2009) Brown von Neumann Nash dynamics: the continuous strategy case. Games Econ Behav 65:406–429
Hoff K, Pandey P (2006) Discrimination, social identity, and durable inequalities. Am Econ Rev 96(2):206–211
Kolmogorov A (1931) Über die analytischen Methoden in der Wahrscheinlichkeitstheorie. Math Ann 104(1):415–458
Kranton RE (2016) Identity economics 2016: where do social distinctions and norms come from? Am Econ Rev 106(5):405–409
Kuran T (1995) The inevitability of future revolutionary surprises. Am J Sociol 100:1528–1551
Kuran T, Sandholm WH (2008) Cultural integration and its discontents. Rev Econ Stud 75:201–228
Lewis DK (1969) Convention: a philosophical study. Harvard University Press, Cambridge
Li SX, de Oliveira A, Eckel C (2017) Common identity and provision of public goods: an experimental investigation. J Econ Behav Organ 142:32–46
Lindbeck A, Nyberg S, Weibull JW (2003) Social norms and welfare state dynamics. J Eur Econ Assoc 1:533–542
Manski CF, Mayshar J (2003) Private incentives and social interactions: fertility puzzles in Israel. J Eur Econ Assoc 1:181–211
Michaeli M, Spiro D (2015) Norm conformity across Societies. J Public Econ 132:51–65
Michaeli M, Spiro D (2017) From peer pressure to biased norms. Am Econ J Microecon 9:152–216
Oechssler J, Riedel F (2001) Evolutionary dynamics on infinite strategy spaces. Econ Theor 17:141–162
Oechssler J, Riedel F (2002) On the dynamic foundation of evolutionary stability in continuous models. J Econ Theory 107:223–252
Planck M (1917) Über einen Satz der statistischen Dynamik und seine Erweiterung in der Quantentheorie. Sitzungsberichte der Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin 24:324–341
Schelling T (1978) Micromotives and macrobehavior. Norton, New York
Shayo M (2009) A model of social identity with an application to political economy: nation, class, and redistribution. Am Polit Sci Rev 103(2):147–174
Snower DJ, Bosworth SJ (2016) Identity-driven cooperation versus competition. Am Econ Rev 106(5):420–24
Tajfel H, Turner J (1979) An integrative theory of intergroup conflict. In: Worchel S, Austin W (eds) The social psychology of intergroup relations. Brooks/Cole, Monterey
Tanaka T, Camerer CF, Nguyen Q (2009) Status and ethnicity in Vietnam: evidence from experimental games. Social computing and behavioral modeling. Springer, New York, pp 217–218
Young HP (1996) The economics of convention. J Econ Perspect 10:105–122
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Additional information
Publisher's Note
Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
I sincerely thank the editor, the associate editor and two anonymous reviewers for their constructive suggestions. I also thank Jimmy Hicks for his excellent research assistance.
Appendix
Appendix
Proof of Proposition 1
For any \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) that satisfies \(\mu _a(\{x\})=\mu _b(\{x\})=1\) for some \(x\in [0, 1]\), we have \(\frac{\partial u_i(x_i)}{\partial x_i}|_{x_i=x}=0\), for \(i \in \{a, b\}\). Therefore, it is a steady state. This gives us Proposition 1 (1).
If \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) satisfies \(\mu _a(\{0\})=1\) and \(\mu _b(\{1\})=1\), we have \(\frac{\partial u_a(x_a)}{\partial x_a}|_{x_a=0}=-\beta <0\) and \(\frac{\partial u_i(x_b)}{\partial x_b}|_{x_b=1}=\beta >0\). Hence, it is a steady state. Similarly, If \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) satisfies \(\mu _a(\{1\})=1\) and \(\mu _b(\{0\})=1\), we have \(\frac{\partial u_a(x_a)}{\partial x_a}|_{x_a=1}=\beta >0\) and \(\frac{\partial u_i(x_b)}{\partial x_b}|_{x_b=0}=-\beta <0\). Hence, it is a steady state. This gives us Proposition 1 (2).
When \(\alpha =\beta \), we have \(\frac{\partial u_i(x_i)}{\partial x_i}=E_i-E_j\), for \(i ,j \in \{a, b\}\) and \(i \ne j\). Hence, any \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) that satisfies \(E_a=E_b\) is a steady state. This gives us Proposition 1 (3).
Finally, we prove Proposition 1 (4). Suppose that \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) such that \(\mu _a(\{0\})+\mu _a(\{1\})=1\), \(\mu _b(\{0\})+\mu _b(\{1\})=1\), and \(\mu _a(\{1\}), \mu _b(\{1\}) \in (0, 1)\) is a steady state. Then, it must satisfy that, for \(i \in \{a, b\}\)
These give us
When \(\beta >\alpha \), both can hold at the same time. Q.E.D. \(\square \)
Proof of Proposition 2
Proving the following four statements would give us Proposition 2:
-
(1)
\((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) that satisfies either \(\mu _a(\{0\})=\mu _b(\{0\})=1\), or \(\mu _a(\{1\})=\mu _b(\{1\})=1\), is not stable.
-
(2)
There is no stable state in which there exists \(x \in (0, 1)\), such that for one of the society \(i\in \{a, b\}\), \(\frac{\partial u_i(x_i)}{\partial x_i}|_{x_i=x}=0\) and x is in the support of \(\mu _i\).
-
(3)
\((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) that satisfies for \(i \in \{a, b\}\), such that \(\mu _i(\{0\})+\mu _i(\{1\})=1\) and \(\mu _i(\{0\}), \mu _i(\{1\})>0\), is not stable.
-
(4)
\((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) that satisfies either \(\mu _a(\{0\})=1\) and \(\mu _b(\{1\})=1\), or \(\mu _a(\{1\})=1\) and \(\mu _b(\{0\})=1\), is stable.
For \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) that satisfies \(\mu _a(\{0\})=\mu _b(\{0\})=1\), consider an alternative state \((\nu _a, \nu _b)\) such that \(\nu _a(\{\varepsilon \})=1\) and \(\nu _b(\{0\})=1\), for some \(\varepsilon \in (0, 1)\). Then, under \((\nu _a, \nu _b)\)
implying that individuals in society a moves toward higher values, and individuals in society b remain holding value 0. Since this is true for any \(\varepsilon \in (0, 1)\), the dynamic keeps evolving until everyone in society a holds value 1 while society b stays at 0. Hence, \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) that satisfies \(\mu _a(\{0\})=\mu _b(\{0\})=1\) is not stable. Similarly, \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) that satisfies \(\mu _a(\{1\})=\mu _b(\{1\})=1\) is not stable either. This gives us statement (1).
Suppose \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) is a steady state such that there exists \(x \in (0, 1)\), such that for one of the society \(i\in \{a, b\}\), \(\frac{\partial u_i(x_i)}{\partial x_i}|_{x_i=x}=0\) and x is in the support of \(\mu _i\). First, assume that \(\alpha =\beta \). In this case, we must have \(E_a=E_b=\bar{x}\), for some \(\bar{x} \in (0, 1)\). Consider a shift from \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) to \((\nu _a, \nu _b)\) such that \(E_a=\bar{x}-\varepsilon \) for some arbitrarily small positive \(\varepsilon \) and \(\nu _b=\mu _b\). Then, we have
implying that the entire distribution in society a shifts to the left, and the entire distribution in society b shifts to the right, which further ensures that \(E_a<E_b\). Hence, the dynamic keeps evolving until everyone in society a holds value 0 and everyone in society b holds value 1. Therefore, when \(\alpha =\beta \), there is no stable state in which there exists \(x \in (0, 1)\), such that for one of the society \(i\in \{a, b\}\), \(\frac{\partial u_i(x_i)}{\partial x_i}|_{x_i=x}=0\) and x is in the support of \(\mu _i\).
Next, assume that \(\alpha \ne \beta \). Without loss of generality, assume that there exists a steady state \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) such that a \(x\in (0, 1)\) is in the support of \(\mu _a\). It must satisfy:
We obtain that \(x=\frac{\beta E_b-\alpha E_a}{\beta -\alpha }\), which is unique. Hence, there exists no other value in (0, 1) in the support of \(\mu _a\). This implies that \(\mu _a\) must satisfy \(\mu _a(\{x\})>0\) and \(\mu _a(\{0\})+\mu _a(\{x\})+\mu _a(\{1\})=1\).
Consider a shift from \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) to \((\nu _a, \nu _b)\) such that \(\nu _a(\{0\})=\mu _a(\{0\})\), \(\nu _a(\{1\})=\mu _a(\{1\})\), \(\nu _a(\{x-\varepsilon \})=\mu _a(\{x\})\) for some arbitrarily small positive \(\varepsilon \) and \(\nu _b=\mu _b\). Then, we have
When \(\alpha >\beta \), we have
Therefore, we must have \(\mu _a(\{0\})=\mu _a(\{1\})=0\) and \(\mu _a(\{x\})=1\). Hence, \(\frac{\partial u_a(x_a)}{\partial x_a}|_{x_a=x-\varepsilon }<0\). When \(\alpha <\beta \), \(\frac{\partial u_a(x_a)}{\partial x_a}|_{x_a=x-\varepsilon }=(\alpha (1-\mu _a(\{x\}))-\beta )\varepsilon<(\alpha -\beta )\varepsilon <0\). Therefore, the mass on value \(x-\varepsilon \) in society a is moving to the left.
If \(\mu _a(\{0\})>0\), we must have \(\frac{\partial u_a(x_a)}{\partial x_a}|_{x_a=0}=\alpha E_a-\beta E_b=\alpha (\mu _a(\{x\})x+\mu _a(\{1\}))-\beta E_b\le 0\) under \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\). Then, under \((\nu _a, \nu _b)\), \(\frac{\partial u_a(x_a)}{\partial x_a}|_{x_a=0}=\alpha (\mu _a(\{x\})(x-\varepsilon )+\mu _a(\{1\}))-\beta E_b<0\), implying that the mass on value 0 in society a if there is any remains the same. If \(\mu _a(\{1\})>0\), we must have \(\frac{\partial u_a(x_a)}{\partial x_a}|_{x_a=1}=(\beta -\alpha )+\alpha E_a-\beta E_b=(\beta -\alpha )+\alpha (\mu _a(\{x\})x+\mu _a(\{1\}))-\beta E_b\ge 0\) under \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\). Then, under \((\nu _a, \nu _b)\), \(\frac{\partial u_a(x_a)}{\partial x_a}|_{x_a=0}=(\beta -\alpha )+\alpha (\mu _a(\{x\})(x-\varepsilon )+\mu _a(\{1\}))-\beta E_b\), which can be negative or positive. Hence, the mass on value 1 in society a if there is any either remains the same or is moving to the left. Hence, \(E_a\) is decreasing.
In society b, if there exists \(y \in (0, 1)\), such that \(\frac{\partial u_b(x_b)}{\partial x_b}|_{x_b=y}=0\) and y is in the support of \(\mu _b\), then because \(E_a\) is decreasing, the mass on value y in society b is moving to the right, the mass on value 0 in society b if there is any is moving to the right or remains the same, and the mass on value 1 on society b if there is any remains the same. Hence, the dynamic keeps evolving until the two societies reach a state with polarization across the two societies (\(\mu _a(\{0\})=1, \mu _b(\{1\})=1\)), or with at least one of the society is polarized ( there exists a \(i \in \{a, b\}\), such that \(\mu _i(\{0\})+\mu _i(\{1\})=1\) and \(\mu _i(\{0\}), \mu _i(\{1\})>0\)). Therefore, when \(\alpha \ne \beta \), there is no stable state in which there exists \(x \in (0, 1)\), such that for one of the society \(i\in \{a, b\}\), \(\frac{\partial u_i(x_i)}{\partial x_i}|_{x_i=x}=0\) and x is in the support of \(\mu _i\). This concludes the proof of statement (2).
Consider \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) that satisfies for \(i \in \{a, b\}\), such that \(\mu _i(\{0\})+\mu _i(\{1\})=1\) and \(\mu _i(\{0\}), \mu _i(\{1\})>0\). Suppose \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) shifts to \((\nu _a, \nu _b)\) such that \(\nu _a(\{0\})=\mu _a(\{0\})+\varepsilon \) and \(\nu _a(\{1\})=\mu _a(\{1\})-\varepsilon \), for some arbitrarily small positive \(\varepsilon \) and \(\nu _b=\mu _b\). Under \((\nu _a, \nu _b)\), \(\frac{\partial u_a(x_a)}{\partial x_a}|_{x_a=0}=\alpha (\mu _a(\{1\})-\varepsilon )-\beta \mu _b(\{1\})<\alpha \mu _a(\{1\})-\beta \mu _b(\{1\}) \le 0\). Hence, the mass on 0 in society a remains the same. \(\frac{\partial u_a(x_a)}{\partial x_a}|_{x_a=1}=(\beta -\alpha )+\alpha (\mu _a(\{1\})-\varepsilon )-\beta \mu _b(\{1\})\), which can be either positive or negative. Hence, the mass on value 1 in society a either remains the same or is moving to the left. Since \(E_a\) is smaller under \((\nu _a, \nu _b)\) than that under \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\), the mass on value 0 in society b remains the same or is moving to the right, the mass on value 1 in society b remains the same, and \(E_b\) under \((\nu _a, \nu _b)\) is either equal to or bigger than that under \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\). Therefore, either \((\nu _a, \nu _b)\) is a new steady state, or it sets the motion for the dynamic to move away from \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\). This gives us statement (3).
Finally, consider \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) that satisfies \(\mu _a(\{0\})=1\) and \(\mu _b(\{1\})=1\). For any \((\nu _a, \nu _b) \in U^\varepsilon \), given the definition of the Prohorov metric, we must have \(\kappa (\mu _a, \nu _a)<\varepsilon \) and \(\kappa (\mu _b, \nu _b)<\varepsilon \). Hence, under \((\nu _a, \nu _b)\), for any \(x \in [0, 1]\), and for sufficiently small positive \(\varepsilon \),
Hence, the distribution in society a moves back to \(\mu _a\) and the distribution in society b moves back to \(\mu _b\), implying that \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) that satisfies \(\mu _a(\{0\})=1\) and \(\mu _b(\{1\})=1\), is stable. Similarly, \((\mu _a, \mu _b)\) that satisfies \(\mu _a(\{1\})=1\) and \(\mu _b(\{0\})=1\), is stable as well. This concludes the proof of statement (4). Q.E.D. \(\square \)
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Wu, J. Stochastic Value Formation. Dyn Games Appl 11, 597–611 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13235-020-00370-z
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13235-020-00370-z