Wright 1
Leland Wright
Instructor M. Leggs
ENGL 1711, Section 5
13 December 2012
Routine Circumcision – A Needless Harm
In traditional Judaism, it is a religious commandment – in the Islamic world, it is a nearuniversal custom. In the United States, it is seen as both a medical practice and a cultural one,
often no longer specific to religion. Whatever its perception, male infant circumcision is one of
the world's oldest medical practices still in existence. But is this time-honored tradition as
innocuous an operation as we're led to think? Male infant circumcision raises a host of concerns
that should make any new parents think twice before giving this doubtful gift to their son. Infant
circumcision denies the right of a boy to have a say in a permanent and controversial decision
about his natural biological identity. It is an extremely painful operation which no newborn baby
should be forced to undergo, and it can have negative consequences for a man's sexual life.
Those are just three reasons that we should abandon infant circumcision as the harmful and
unnecessary custom that it is.
Everyone understands the basic idea of circumcision – it surgically removes the foreskin
from the male penis. Yet many people in the United States do not actually understand what the
foreskin is, so it's important to begin with some background knowledge. The foreskin is a
double-sided tube or “sheath” of skin which, in its normal position, is pulled over the head of the
penis (the glans) so that the glans is not directly visible. An article on Psychology Today's
website describes how in the newborn, and throughout childhood, the foreskin is fused to the
glans with connective tissue as part of its natural development, and thus has to be forcibly
retracted for circumcision to take place (Narvaez).
Wright 2
In an intact (uncircumcised) man, the foreskin pulls back to reveal the head of the penis
and provide a large amount of skin to cover the shaft of the penis – an intact man's foreskin
constitutes approximately 15 square inches of skin, according to the same Psychology Today
article (Narvaez). And although in the United States we are accustomed to the circumcised
penis, a survey by the World Health Organization found that 70% of the male world population is
intact (World Health Organization 6).
Infant circumcision is the permanent and painful removal of the foreskin, at a time when
the child can have no possible say in this decision. It's important to remember that every male
child is born with a foreskin, and that it is a natural piece of evolved, human anatomy. Do we
have any reason to think it is ethical to permanently remove part of a baby's natural anatomy at
birth? A man was born with a foreskin just like he was born with eyelids, fingernails, and
toenails. They are all parts of his body. It's no stretch of reasoning to say that a child has a right
to keep any part of his body until he is mature enough to make his own decision regarding it,
especially since, as we'll see, routine infant circumcision is NOT indicated by medical necessity.
Baby boys across the United States are being subjected to an irreversible operation that
will change their natural biological identities forever, but their inability to speak for themselves
has resulted in a negligence of their future ability to make their own decision. And it doesn't
matter if, for the boy's parents, circumcision is a religious or cultural decision. Today, we
recognize that it's the right of every person to choose their religion or culture themselves. Take
circumcision in Judaism as an example: in the past, there would be no question that a boy born to
Jewish parents would be Jewish when he grew up, and thus it made sense to decide for him that
he would be circumcised as part of Jewish law. But today, there isn't a guarantee that a man born
to Jewish parents will want to have been circumcised – even if he chooses to keep his religion.
The right to decide on one's body should be available to everybody in the case of circumcision,
Wright 3
not just starting at the moment when one is legally adult, because the circumcision of an infant
cannot be changed later – a man circumcised as a baby is stuck that way for his whole life.
Though medical decisions are often made for young children without their express
consent, those decisions are typically made because they cannot be decided at a later time, or in
response to an already existing problem. But circumcision can be performed at any time in a
man's life - and infant circumcision is not a treatment for a pre-existing medical condition. The
problems which circumcision has the potential to reduce – urinary tract infections, HIV/AIDS,
penile cancer, and sexually transmitted infections – are either years ahead of the newborn, or are
quite uncommon (more about this later on). As Hutson says, “routine circumcision in babies
defies standard principles of surgery, as there is no absolute medical indication.” An unnecessary
procedure is a procedure that should not be performed, particularly a surgical one.
With all this discussion on the ethicalness of infant circumcision, let's not forget that it is
extremely painful to a newborn baby. Proponents of infant circumcision sometimes say that
newborns feel little pain, and that that is a reason to circumcise during infancy. But, according to
Romberg, “absolutely no studies have been conducted that support the belief that infants feel
little or no pain” (279). Remember that the foreskin, at birth and during childhood, is fused to
the glans with connective tissue (Narvaez). It seems simple, common sense that the procedure of
having the foreskin both ripped from the surface of the glans and then amputated would be very,
very painful, especially in the newborn. General anaesthesia is considered unsafe for infants,
rendering complete pain alleviation impossible – and it's uncertain whether other, partial
anaesthetic solutions are adequate to numb the pain of the operation (Romberg 388-9).
Moreover, anaesthetic is certainly not employed during the baby's recovery period, and the baby
must still endure the trauma of being strapped immobile to an operating board for the surgery.
Anaesthesia is always used for circumcision in children and adults – why do we think
Wright 4
circumcision wouldn't be painful for a baby? What must it mean for a newborn, upon entering
the world, to have one of their first experiences be such a shocking and painful ordeal? They
may not remember it consciously later in life – but they will feel the pain as infants.
Moreover, though the field of research into infants' long-term physiological response to
circumcision is rather sparse, at least one study has indicated that circumcision's impact lasts
much longer than the amount of time it takes for the wound to heal – babies in the study who
underwent circumcision showed a stronger pain response to routine vaccination months after the
procedure, suggesting “an infant analogue of a post-traumatic stress disorder” (Taddio, Katz).
Indeed, it's counterintuitive to think that such a traumatic experience would not have lasting
negative repercussions in the newborn baby.
It's also important to remember that the foreskin, like almost every other part of the
human body, is not just there for kicks. It's a valuable organ which contributes to the health of
the penis and to the sexual pleasure of its owner. Fleiss describes several important purposes of
the foreskin, which are paraphrased throughout the rest of this paragraph: the foreskin serves to
cover the glans of the penis, protecting it from dirt, scratches, and abrasions, and keeps the
surface of the glans healthy through gland secretions. It rolls back during sex to accommodate
the full length of the erection and cover the shaft with skin that is rich in nerve endings,
providing a great range of sexual feeling. The rolling sheath of skin acts as a natural lubricant
during sexual intercourse, stimulating the female partner without the rougher friction that is
inevitable with a circumcised penis. Furthermore, Fleiss writes, “the foreskin fosters intimacy
between the two partners by enveloping the glans and maintaining it as an internal organ. The
sexual experience is enhanced when the foreskin slips back to allow the male's internal organ, the
glans, to meet the female's internal organ, the cervix - a moment of supreme intimacy and
beauty” (Fleiss).
Wright 5
Evidence of the detrimental effect that circumcision can have on both male and female
sexual partners was found in a rigorous study in Denmark by Frisch, Lindholm, and Grønbæk,
which found male circumcision to be linked to orgasm difficulty in men and sexual
dissatisfaction in women. The negative effect of circumcision is especially dramatic with
regards to masturbation; in a study of men circumcised as adults, 63% reported more difficulty in
masturbating after the operation (DaiSik, Pang 2). It makes sense that masturbation after
circumcision would be reported to be more difficult – the foreskin provides an easily obtainable
measure of frictionless stimulation (by rolling over the glans) that would be unavailable to a
circumcised man.
This is not to say that sex for men is not extremely pleasurable, regardless of their
circumcision status. The most important factors in any man's sex life are his feelings for his
partner and the satisfaction of his entire sexual experience, which is far more than the sum of one
sexual organ – and some men who elected to be circumcised as adults have reported that their
sexual experience changed for the better (Bazelon). However, the body of research showing that
circumcision generally decreases sexual pleasure should make it clear that routine infant
circumcision is an extremely unethical decision, having the potential to take away value from
one of the most worthwhile experiences in a man's life. A man who wishes to become
circumcised can have the procedure done, and should be allowed to do so, but a circumcised man
who wishes to get his foreskin back has no such option. It is only ethical that men should be
allowed to make this decision for themselves, rather than have that decision made for them as
infants without any guess as to their feelings on the matter (though a baby's cry of pain will tell
you how the baby feels - an adult, at least, can undergo the procedure with full anesthesia and
post-operative pain relief.)
So why is circumcision performed at all? By far the most common arguments brought up
Wright 6
in favor of routine, male infant circumcision are those that claim circumcision to be an effective
way to combat a range of health issues, including HIV/AIDS, urinary tract infections (UTIs),
penile cancer, and numerous STIs. Earp takes the UTIs argument to task by pointing out that
urinary tract infections in boys are rare, and are easily treated with antibiotics – what is the point
of circumcising all of a population in order to pre-emptively treat a problem that will only affect
a few, particularly when there is a much more conservative treatment available for those it will
affect? And penile cancer in men is extraordinarily rare. Using circumcision to combat these
health problems is like hitting in a roofing nail with a sledgehammer – maybe it works, but is the
collateral damage worth the solution?
On to HIV/AIDS transmission. The argument that male circumcision combats the
transmission of HIV/AIDS is almost entirely based upon three randomized control trials (RCTs)
conducted in South Africa, which each showed a 60% comparative reduction in the transmission
of AIDS following male circumcision. Randomized control trials are typically seen as the height
of medical reliability, yet both the findings and the relevance of these studies is questionable.
Earp sums up the results of a study that took a hard look at the design of the African RCTs, and
the problems with them are many and serious: “Clinically relevant flaws included 'problematic
randomization and selection bias ... lack of placebo-control … experimenter bias … not
investigating non-sexual HIV transmission … participant expectation bias, and time-out
discrepancy (restraint from sexual activity only by circumcised men)' ” He then goes on to
describe the statistical misrepresentation where the studies reported a 60% relative reduction in
HIV transmission, when the absolute reduction in the study groups of all three trials was only
1.3% (Earp).
Putting all these flaws with the trials to the side, another obvious problem can be seen
with the application of the results of those RCTs to America – they were conducted in Africa!
Wright 7
No such studies have been conducted in the United States, a place with higher medical standards
and a different HIV problem. Our best course of action against heterosexually transmitted AIDS,
and against STIs in general, is to promote safe sex and condom use – in the event that
circumcision does have a mild protective benefit against STIs, it is far less effective than condom
use, which offers near-100% protection. How is it a good idea to circumcise America's children
when we must still tell them they have to wear condoms? Rates of STI transmission prevention
in circumcised adults are low across the board. It makes no sense to circumcise ten children in
their infancy, breaching their ethical rights in a rather alarming way, when only one may end up
not receiving an STI as a result. The rest will either contract an STI anyway or do a fine job of
practicing safe sex.
And even putting that aside, HIV and STD transmission is a complete non-issue for at
least the first decade of any man's life. It's completely illogical to circumcise the male infant
population as a pre-emptive solution to problems that are all years ahead of them. While the
statement that circumcision helps reduces the risk of transmission of sexual infections sounds
good at first, closer examination of this argument reveals it to be riddled with holes and
fundamentally unsound.
Another statement often used in favor of circumcision is that it is “more clean” to be
circumcised – with a circumcised penis, there is no moist space formed by the foreskin,
susceptible to the buildup of bodily fluids and germs. But contrary to the expectations of
circumcised men, this is a non-issue with intact men. Typically, intact men are glad that an
optional surgery to remove a part of their penis for good was not performed on them without
their consent. Moreover, what's been said about the “lack of cleanliness” of the male foreskin is
many times more true for the female vagina – and this is not a problem for women. The glans of
the penis, like the woman's vagina, is simply not meant to be exposed like the rest of the skin on
Wright 8
the human body – evolution did not design them that way. Both women and the majority of the
world's men do fine with the sex organs they were born with; and, besides, such an incredibly
personal choice should not be taken away from a man without compelling reason: our personal
opinion on how clean a man's penis will be is hardly a sufficient reason to circumcise him at
birth.
Perhaps one of the greatest reasons that children continue to be circumcised in the United
States is that, with our high circumcision rate, we are used to the circumcised penis. The idea of
moving skin on the penis weirds us out or disgusts us. But it's important to place mainstream
American feelings about the penis in their context – circumcision is simply what we've gotten
used to. Before the advent of circumcision, our ancestors couldn't have thought the foreskin to
be strange in the slightest. And for the majority of the world's population, the intact penis is
what's normal. Abandoning the idea of the natural penis as strange or unwanted will require hard
work for some, yet the result for coming generations can only be positive – returning the choice
over each man's body into his own hands, and re-acquanting ourselves with our natural body.
The potential consequences for a child's later sexual life, the extreme pain of the
operation that has to be endured by the newborn, and perhaps most importantly, the inability of
an infant to have a choice in the permanent removal of a piece of his natural identity, are all
compelling reasons to abandon routine infant circumcision. The arguments in favor of such a
radical surgery have fallen short. Let's better ourselves and our society by removing it from the
routine hospital environment, so that each man may fully enjoy the right to his natural body.
Wright 9
Works Cited
Bazelon, Emily. “Or Not To Snip?” Slate. The Slate Group, 13 Feb. 2006. Web. 21 Nov. 2012.
DaiSik, Kim, and Pang, Myung-Geol. “The effect of male circumcision on sexuality.” BJU
International 99.3 (2007): 619-622. Web. 2 Dec. 2012.
Earp, Brian. “The AAP report on circumcision: Bad science + bad ethics = bad medicine.”
Practical Ethics. University of Oxford, 30 Aug. 2012. Web. 21 Nov. 2012.
Fleiss, Paul M. “The Case Against Circumcision.” Peaceful Parenting. n.p., 6 Nov. 2009. Web.
2 Dec. 2012.
Frisch, Morten, Lindholm, Morten, and Grønbæk, Morten. “Male circumcision and sexual
function in men and women: a survey-based, cross-sectional study in Denmark.”
International Journal of Epidemiology 40.5 (2011): 1367-1381. Web. 2 Dec. 2012.
“Male circumcision: global trends and determinants of prevalence, safety and acceptability.”
World Health Organization. n.p., 2007. Web. 30 Nov. 2012.
Narvaez, Darcia. “Myths About Circumcision You Likely Believe.” Psychology Today. Sussex
Publishers, LLC, 11 Sep. 2011. Web. 20 Nov. 2012.
Romberg, Rosemary. Circumcision, the Painful Dilemma. South Hadley: Bergin & Garvey, 1985.
Print.
Taddio, Anna, and Katz, Joel. “Effect of neonatal circumcision on pain response during
subsequent routine vaccination.” Lancet 349.9052 (1997): 599. Web. 1 Dec. 2012.