Satis Coleman’s Philosophy Through Progressive Educational Thought
Daniel J. Shevock
Penn State Altoona
Paper presented at the MayDay Group Colloquium 28: Music Education and Cultural
Context. Phoenix, AZ. June 17, 2016.
Abstract: In order to confront patriarchal values in music education, music educators
must know the philosophies of historic women music educators. Music educators’
general underestimation of the value of historic women is a critical concern. In this paper,
new light is shed on the life of historically underrepresented, but important, female music
educator Satis Coleman (1878-1961); exploring her philosophy of music education from
the perspective of progressive educational thought. There were two guiding questions:
How does Satis Coleman’s music education philosophy relate to and diverge from the
educational philosophies of John Dewey and Jane Addams? And what does each educator
believe about students living the good life and how does education foster this? Nine
themes emerged from analysis: social, agency, interest, continuity, interdisciplinarity,
nature, inner person, critiques, and the other.
Keywords: Satis Coleman, music education history, philosophy, progressive education,
John Dewey, Jane Addams, George Santayana, environmental philosophy, ecofeminism
In order to confront patriarchal values in our field today, music educators must
know the philosophies of historic women music educators. Music educators’ general
underestimation of the value of historic women is a critical concern; “underestimation
devalues women for future girls and boys” (Howe 2009, 179). “Sadly, until fairly
recently the lives and experiences of women … have not constituted legitimate
knowledge” (Koza 1993-1994, 3). Historians often recommend more studies on women
music educators (McCarthy 2012, 162); and I have been interested in understanding one
historic woman in particular, Satis Coleman (1876-1961), through studying her music
education philosophy, which is resonant today (Shevock 2015).
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
2
Feminist theorist bell hooks (2000) named feminism as “a movement to end
sexism, sexist exploitation, and oppression” (1). Since feminism is about “consciousness
raising,” as a male music educator influenced by the feminist “vision of masculinity
where self-esteem and self-love of one’s unique being forms the basis of identity” (70), I
recognize oppressive systems of patriarchy as exploitative, negatively affecting me and
people of all genders. In this history of (music education) philosophy, new light is shed
on the life of underrepresented, but important, female music educator, exploring her
philosophy from the perspective of progressive educational thought. Further, as one small
step in undermining oppressive patriarchy today, I will weave Coleman’s insights into the
thinking of contemporary feminist music educators.
After my initial study of Coleman, I asked, “Why did I not know Coleman’s name
before examining her work?” (60). I suggest it might be systematic sexism or the move in
music education from progressive to aesthetic philosophies. She also used the music (and
wisdom) of non-Western cultures, and she was likely the first music educator to use
ethnomusicology research (Volk 1996). Because of progressive education theorists’
importance to MayDay scholarship, understanding Coleman’s philosophy may be
particularly pertinent to this group which is “mindful, reflective, and critically aware of
cultural contexts” (Action Ideal #1).
Progressive education was prominent during the first half of the 20th century and
focused on learning as social experience and teaching as reflective practice. John Dewey,
who is often cited in music education literature, was progressive education’s foremost
philosopher (Noddings 2012). Sharing common roots, Coleman and Dewey both taught
at Teachers College, Columbia University; both educators’ philosophies were influenced
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
3
by the educational theories of Johann Herbart (Boston 1992, 28-29; Howe 2014, 109 +
168); and, according to Southcott (2009), Coleman’s ideas “echo those of Dewey” (23),
including her referencing Dewey in her discussion of student interest in music (Coleman
1939, 16).
Dewey’s educational philosophy didn’t emerge in a vacuum. Lamb (2014) lists
eleven women who influenced Dewey, and, from this list, Jane Addams was broadly
influential as “the first female public philosopher in the U.S.” (197). She founded Hull
House; was a Nobel Peace Prize winner in 1931; and a founding member of WILPF,
NAACP, and the ACLU. Further, Dewey named his daughter for Addams (Addams
1994, 29). Addams also appears in music education literature, though not as frequently as
Dewey. In music education scholarship, Coleman has been studied since 1990—
Southcott 1990; Boston 1992; Volk 1996; Southcott 2009; Shevock 2015. Coleman has
been understood within the context of progressive education (Boston 1992, 107; Shevock
2015; Southcott 2009; Tellstrom 1971). A deeper understanding of how Coleman’s
philosophy relates to that of Dewey and Addams seems relevant.
Guiding Questions
In Tellstrom’s Music in American Education, Coleman was used to typify tenets
and teaching techniques of progressive music education, especially in contrast to fellow
progressive educator Will Earhart (Tellstrom 1971). More recently, her philosophy has
“been partially lost to the annals of music education history” (Shevock 2015, 57),
possibly because our history is “gendered” (60). For instance, other than Tellstrom, and
Howe’s more recent text, Coleman doesn’t seem to appear in major music education
histories. Previous scholarship has focused on: Coleman’s teaching as an antecedent to
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
4
world music pedagogy (Volk 1996); as an antecedent to eclectic music education (Boston
1992); the spiritual aspects of Coleman’s philosophy (Shevock 2015); and in relation to
Johann Herbart’s Theory of Recapitulation (Southcott 2009). Because she wrote
extensively, having more than thirty publications (Boston 1992), scholars are able to cast
light on her philosophy within the context of varied theories that are relevant today.
There were two guiding questions for this research:
How does Satis Coleman’s music education philosophy relate to and diverge from
the educational philosophies of John Dewey and Jane Addams?
What does each educator believe about students living the good life and how does
education foster this?
Analysis
Data for analysis include Coleman’s Creative Music for Children (1922) and Your
Child’s Music (1939), books that bookended her New York teaching career. The first
book was written for the music education community, while the second was written for a
broader audience. These are analyzed in relation to John Dewey’s Moral Principles in
Education (1909), Experience and Education (1938); and Jane Addams’s Educational
Methods (1902), and Education by the Current Event (1930).
To analyze each educator’s philosophy, educational aims, means, and
assumptions were identified (written in the margins) within the initial texts for analysis:
Creative Music for Children, Moral Principles in Education, Educational Methods, and
Education by the Current Event. Aims, means, and assumptions served as “provisional
codes” (Saldaña 2009, 120) to reveal important themes of each educator’s philosophy.
To understand educational assumptions, The Moral Work of Teaching (MWT)
Framework (Sanger & Osguthorpe 2009) was employed.i While the entire MWT
framework was not used, the current study drew from Sanger and Osguthorpe’s
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
5
normative moral assumptions, “regarding what is good/right/virtuous/caring” (18) and
educational assumptions, “regarding the nature and scope of teaching and education in
society” (19). These two assumptions seem to overlap in music education philosophy. For
instance, a music teacher may think education can help cultivate the ability for people to
understand others, and that understanding others is virtuous. Because of the connection to
virtue, assumptions are connected to living the good life. It also follows that a teacher’s
assumptions can influence aims (people who understand others) and means (introducing
musics students might be unfamiliar with). Assumptions were identified by asking the
question “what is living the good life?”
For Gossett (2015), content, means, and aims were used to understand pedagogic
values of band directors (14). Similarly, in this paper, aims and means are used to
understand each educator’s philosophy. While Gossett’s pedagogic values are context
dependent (see 11-12), the philosophies of Coleman, Dewey, and Addams were more
generally intended. Educational aims were identified by asking the question “what type
of people should education cultivate?”
Means were defined by asking the question “what practices are used to
accomplish aims?” Educational means can include methods of instruction and curricular
materials (Sanger & Osguthorpe 2005, 61). Teachers utilize means to reach aims, but are
guided more fundamentally by their assumptions about living the good life.
The coded initial texts, guided by these definitions, were copied into a Word
document table. Thirty coded sections were emailed to another music education
researcher to “provide a ‘reality check’” (Saldaña 2009, 27) by agreeing or disagreeing
with each code. A “minimal benchmark” (28) of agreement of 85-90% was surpassed (at
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
6
97% agreement), and no modifications were made to the initial codes. Inductive analysis
was employed to construct and group emerging themes (descriptive codes in relation to
each educators philosophy), and secondary texts (Experience and Education, and
Creative Music for Children) were coded by these nine themes: social, agency, interest,
continuity, interdisciplinarity, nature, inner person, critiques, and the other. An
additional text, which was identified by Coleman, Dewey’s (1913) Interest and Effort in
Education was analyzed to better understand the theme interest. The nine themes were
used to find similarities and difference among each educators’ philosophy (aims, means,
and assumptions).
Satis Coleman
Music education historians began studying Coleman’s scholarship with Jane
Southcott’s (1990) British Journal of Music Education article. Sheila C. Boston’s (1992)
dissertation provides broad description of Coleman’s life. After this, Terese M. Volk
(1996) placed Coleman’s pedagogy as a predecessor of world music education in Music
Educators Journal. Jane Southcott’s (2009) Journal of Historical Research in Music
Education clarifies Coleman’s philosophy, especially how Johann Herbart’s Theory of
Recapitulation influenced it. In 2015 I published my Music Educators Journal article,
sharing a qualitative analysis of the spiritual aspects of Coleman’s philosophy.
Coleman was perhaps the first music educator to use ethnomusicology research
(Volk 1996, 47). Moreover, Coleman published influential ethnomusicology studies. For
instance, her historical and cultural studies of bells were referenced scholarship as diverse
as English (Wood 2013) and philosophy (Illich 1990). An important part of her pedagogy
was taking students on field trips to the Metropolitan Museum of Art, where they would
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
7
observe instruments from other cultures, and upon returning to class would construct
these instruments (Volk 1996). However, students improvised on these instruments and
used number notation to record their compositions, rather than performing music from
other cultures in an “authentic manner” (47).
Boston (1992) concluded her dissertation by suggesting Coleman’s philosophy
was “analogous” to the eclectic approach to music education, “less concerned with
particular methods and techniques than with the child itself and the child’s musical
development” (145). However, today eclecticism is challenged as not being based on an
underlying theory—not having an underlying unity. Dewey (1938) also challenged the
idea of eclecticism in education: “an eclectic combination of points picked out hither and
yon from all schools (5). If in the current study Coleman’s philosophy demonstrates an
underlying unity it is not “eclectic,” however diverse Coleman’s educational means seem.
Southcott (2009) connects Coleman’s philosophy to Recapitulation Theory. For
instance, Psychologist G. Stanley Hall, who was referenced by Coleman, was a big
proponent of Recapitulation Theory (29). Dewey was also influenced by Recapitulation
Theory (Howe 2014, 109). However, Coleman (1922) did not seem to see her work as
Recapitulation Theory, though it does draw on it for a specific purpose:
This work does not attempt to support to discuss the once popular Recapitulation
Theory. The natural evolution of music, however, does give a line of progression
from simple forms upward, which is especially suited to the growing capacities of
the child. (143 footnote, emphasis added)
Coleman’s use of terminology connected to Recapitulation Theory was to help her
formulate her understanding of childhood development, a part of progressive education.
Findings
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
8
Nine themes—social, agency, interest, continuity, interdisciplinarity, nature, inner
person, critiques, and the other—emerged from analysis. Each theme also had subthemes,
which helped to understand how the theme was discussed in the texts. For instance, social
had the subthemes cooperation, and gender. Agency had the subthemes body,
experimenting. Interdisciplinarity had the subthemes course of study, unity of knowledge,
and toward simplicity. Sections of text were labeled with one of these themes and the
initial code—aims, means, or assumptions. When an initial code fell into two categories,
a choice was made to label the text as one, rather than having them double coded.
However, texts were, at times, double coded for as themes. For instance, text describing a
father’s opportunities to sing birdsongs with his child was coded under two themes social
(and its subtheme, gender) and nature providing a conceptual link between the two
themes. While all nine themes were analyzed, this write-up focuses on six themes—
social, agency, interdisciplinarity, nature, critiques, and the other—which are particularly
relevant to praxis today. The other three themes—continuity, inner person, and interest—
provided relational (between the three educators) but not substantial divergent data. In
particular, these three serve to reinforce Satis Coleman’s philosophy as connected to the
educational philosophies of John Dewey and Jane Addams.
Social
The theme social was foremost in the texts under analysis for Dewey, Addams,
and Coleman. A core assumption of Dewey’s (1909) education philosophy may be
summed up in the assertion, “The moral responsibility of the school, and of those who
conduct it, is to society” (7). Coleman discussed music as serving to help socialize
students, and connects it to needs: “He [sic] will need the opportunities for social
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
contacts, which music-making will bring him [sic], and he [sic] will need the many
socializing effects on his [sic] personality which will result from his [sic] playing and
singing with others” (4). Marissa Silverman (2012) connects needs and care, a
contemporary thread of feminist educational theory: “Foundationally, music education
should be ‘needs based.’ A music classroom should be founded on reciprocity between
the carer and the cared-for” (111). As such, Coleman’s philosophy can be read from the
perspective of music education as a caring profession.
Image 1: “Ready for the March” (Coleman 1922, 32 insert)
Promoting cooperation, rather than individual desire to show-off, was a major
concentration in Coleman’s writings. Promoting cooperation was also a concern for
Dewey and Addams. Addams (1902) assumption that “The situation demands the
9
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
10
consciousness of participation and well-being which comes to the individual when he
[sic] is able to see himself [sic] ‘in connection and cooperation with the whole” (118)
seems linked to Coleman’s (1939): “As we know, music should not be a ‘showing off’
affair; but it should be a social activity—having fun together—where neither fear of
criticism nor craving for applause enters in” (62-63). The primary means Coleman
recommends to foster cooperation are “group singing, group dancing, and group
playing” (63 emphasis in original).
Gender was a subtheme of social, which was discussed heavily by Coleman.
Connected to the progressive concept of melioration, she discussed the changing genderexpectations in society:
The changing points of view and the changing goals of society greatly affect the
attitude toward music-making. My grandmother wanted her daughters to learn to
sing and play piano merely to add to their social graces. … Men musicians, for
the most part, were considered effeminate, good-for-nothings (Coleman 1939, 80)
For Coleman, the social acceptance of male musicians was an advancement from
previous beliefs.
Coleman also made distinctions between mother’s work and father’s work in the
musical raising of children. Mothers fostered creativity and singing voice, “The habit of
spontaneous singing should begin early. If a mother sings spontaneously to her child, he
[sic] may begin to answer her in a singing voice even before he can talk distinctly”
(Coleman 1939, 43). In contrast, fathers were responsible for cultivating experiences with
Nature (another theme of Coleman’s philosophy):
In his outings with the child, the father has valuable opportunities to quicken the
small ears to sounds of Nature, to keen perception and imitation of them: together
they may learn bird songs—to know them and to whistle them; and so in
numberless ways the father may contribute to the musical education of his child,
even without having had musical training himself. (Coleman 1922, 189-190)
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
11
Perhaps because of Coleman’s description of music as too effeminate a generation earlier,
she seems to have had a higher expectation for the musical training of mothers than
fathers. This seems to resonate with Oglala Lakota and American Indian Movement
activist Russell Means’s discussion of a father’s duty to sing to the child “in the womb”
and fourth quadmester (first three-months of life) (see https://youtu.be/CWnk0FAYG9A).
Perhaps Coleman’s conception of the duties of mothers and fathers was responsive to the
American Indian music she was familiar with as an ethnomusicologist and music
educator.
Agency
All three educators discuss agency within their aims, means, and assumptions. For
Dewey and Coleman, agency is embodied. Dewey’s (1909) means involved educating for
“a trained and sound body, skillful eye and hand” (10). Coleman (1939) went as far as to
say, “Activity is a law of life”; aiming for “the child’s bodily activity [to] be free from
nervous strain and self-conscious tensions” (87). For Gould (2009), music is experienced
“emotionally and cognitively in terms of our bodily engagement with it”; affirming
“selves as mindful bodies in relationship with each other in the social world” (42).
Coleman’s conception, a sort of embodied agency, seems like a worthy precursor to
Gould’s work.
Experimenting is a central means for agency. Coleman (1922) further connects
that to another theme, nature:
One day Florence [one of Coleman’s students] brought to me with great pride a
musical instrument of her own discovery which was neither a wind, stringed, nor
percussion instrument. It was a large thorny cactus plant which grew in a pot in
her mother’s window. She had discovered that the long thorns on it would vibrate
and make musical sounds when she flipped them; also that their tones were not all
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
12
alike. … What better proof that the world—even the barren western prairie—is
rich in musical possibilities if we only have eyes to see and ears to hear! (49)
While Dewey (1909) connected social life (through complexity) to the natural
environment (38), Coleman (1939) assumption (about living the good life) connects
agency to nature. “He [sic] who creates in the field of the arts falls most naturally to the
contemplation of Nature, the source of all beauty” (7). While Deweyan thought expresses
the possibility of living “by means of a musical environment” (Gates 2005, 12), suggests
a normal end for creative musicing (also living by means of a musical environment) is
contemplation—a musical praxis leading to a spiritual praxis.
Interdisciplinarity
Interdisciplinarity (thought not using that terminology) was a central part of
progressive education. Dewey (1909) argued against “A barren ‘course of study’” (31).
Coleman (1939) recommends (as a means), “Parallel studies in different arts” because
they “are always valuable in developing an understanding of the principles that underlie
all the arts” (36 emphasis added). Klein (1990) suggests educators rely on
interdisciplinarity to realize a variety of ends: “to answer complex questions; to address
broad issues; to explore disciplinary and professional relations; to solve problems that are
beyond the scope of any one discipline; to achieve unity of knowledge, whether on a
limited or grand scale” (11 emphasis added). Because “Dewey himself was educated in
the Hegelian tradition of internal, organic relations” (24), Coleman’s principles that
underlie all the arts, as a unity of knowledge epistemological position, places Coleman
within progressive educational thought.
Coleman (1939) adds an additional critique: “If interest naturally follows ability,
it is to be expected that where the individual has gifts in more than one line, the interests
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
13
will probably be divided” (35). Coleman suggested versatility can lead toward living
more simply, which was identified as an assumption of Coleman’s in my previous
research (Shevock 2015). Because of this belief that interdisciplinary experiences lead to
students finding the art(s) through which they best experience the good life, she
suggested students not study music when interests lie elsewhere. This seems in sharp
contrast to much of the music education for all ethos embedded in our profession. This
belief in the authority of students’ interest may even be seen as a challenge to the music
education profession (connected to another theme, critiques).
Nature
Nature was a major theme for Coleman, and was discussed by Dewey but not
Addams within the texts under analysis. Dewey (1909) expressed an assumption that
seems anthropocentric [human centered], “The ultimate significance of lake, river,
mountain, and plain is not physical but social; it is the part which it plays in modifying
and directing human relationships” (35). Coleman’s (1939) assumptions (about nature
and humans’ relationships with it) stand in contrast:
Many people go through life deaf to some of the most beautiful sounds in Nature.
They walk in the woods and never hear the soft crunch of their feet on the dry
leaves, the whirr of the bird that flies overhead, or even the song which the bird
sings when he alights in the tree. They never think to listen to the wind blowing
through the branches or notice the musical babble of the stream rushing over the
stones. And that delightful little time-beater of the evening, the cricket under the
leaves—all this rare music is missed, probably because the traveler was never
taught, as a little child, to listen for these things and to love Nature with his [sic]
ears as well as with his other senses” (95 emphasis added)
Not only does Coleman connect the theme nature with her conception of embodied
agency (ears and other senses), but the position between humans and nature seems to
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
14
involve reciprocity—humans love nature—and the cricket has musicing agency (his/r
musicing occurs whether or not people are there to learn from him/r).
Coleman’s (1939) music education means also connect to nature, including the
“dramatization of songs … representing an animal or other character” (134-135), and
recommend students attend summer music camps because they include “out-of-door life,
and all other healthy summer activities which are so fine for the child’s health and social
development” (129)
Image 2: “Some Music Lessons are Best Out of Doors” (Coleman 1922, 86 insert)
Coleman (1939) felt using nature as a music education means led to spiritual wellbeing:
Did you ever go far from the sound of paved streets, whirring machinery, trains,
street-cars, automobile horns, radios, and from the shrill, shouting voices of
people, and realize that only there in sweet silence, could you feel the harmony of
the spheres that the Greeks talked about, hear the rhythmic beat of Nature, and
have a bit of understanding of the voice of God [sic]? If so, then you know what I
mean when I say that an important requisite for the best development of your
child’s musical powers, expressed by a healthy well-poised body, is a great deal
of silence. (91-92)
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
15
While Addams did not discuss nature, and Dewey’s environmental philosophy
was, at a minimum, less robust than in the texts under analysis, Coleman’s environmental
philosophy seemed to connect that of to another pragmatist and progressive philosopher
of that era, George Santayana.
A Californian whom I had recently the pleasure of meeting observed that, if the
philosophers had lived among your mountains, their systems would have been
different from what they are. Certainly, I should say, very different from what
those systems are in which the European genteel tradition has handed down since
Socrates; for these systems are egotistical; directly or indirectly they are
anthropocentric, and inspired by the conceited notion that man [sic], or human
reasons, or the human distinction between good and evil, is the centre [sic] and
pivot of the universe. That is what the mountains and the woods should make you
at last ashamed to assert. (106)
Not only does it seem Coleman spent time in the woods, leading to a less anthropocentric
conception of non-human life, but Coleman’s valuing of creativity, spirituality, and
simplicity is found in Santayana’s (1911) work. “[Primeval solitudes/ the mountains and
the woods] allow you, in one happy moment, at once to play and to worship, to take
yourself simply, humbly, for what you are, and to salute the wild, indifferent, noncensorious infinity of nature” (106-107).
I have yet to find a reference to Santayana in Coleman’s work, or vice versa, so it
might be dubious to assert that she developed her environmental philosophy directly from
his work. They may draw from the same well, so to speak, as ecocentric ideas were
present to some degree in the American humorists, whose anthropomorphizing of nonhuman life Santayana saw as a positive contrast to the European genteel tradition.
However, it seems Coleman (1922) may have developed her philosophy experientially:
For several years I had the opportunity to observe the methods of mother robins
teaching their little ones to sing, as the trees around my home were nesting places
for several families and several generations. These robins, year after year, held
their singing school near my windows, and invariably they used the same little
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
16
song for the baby birds to practice on—one much simpler than the wonderful
songs the grown-up robins usually sang” (101-102)
This type of appeal to experience may have put Coleman’s popular music
education method in danger of becoming illegitimate after her retirement from Teachers
College in the 1940s, with the supremacy of music education as aesthetic education.
Roberta Lamb (1996) explains, “While feminist education often legitimates life
experiences as an appropriate subject of analysis, few experiences could be more
illegitimate in music study: Music, according to aesthetic theories, transcends life” (125).
In Coleman, instead of a music education towards transcending life through music-asobject, we see a musicing rooted in actual life, human and non-human, and spiritual
wellbeing being the aim: “To be happy, he [sic] must be a well-adjusted human being
first and an artist afterwards” (Coleman 1939, 30).
Image 3: “Four Stages in Our Development of the Lyre” (Coleman 1922, 142 insert)
An aspect of Coleman’s philosophy that resonated Dewey’s environmental
philosophy was drawing on evolutionary theory to construct educational means. As
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
17
Dewey (1909) wrote, “We must know what these instincts and impulses are, and what
they are at each particular stage of the child’s development, in order to know what to
appeal to and what to build upon” (47?). Development and evolutionary discourse are
found throughout both educators’ writings. As mentioned above, both drew from
Recapitulation Theory, and Charles Darwin influenced both. Coleman connected
evolutionary theory to sonic aspects of music education (simplifying rhythms and
melodies) and instrument construction, such as having students construct more complex
lyres as students aged (see image 3).
Critiques
All three teachers critiqued professions. Both Addams and Coleman considered
the professions overcrowded. “The overcrowding of the professions by poorly equipped
men [sic] arises from much the same source, and from the conviction that, ‘an education’
is wasted if a boy goes into a factory or shop” (Addams 1902, 105-106). For Coleman
(1939) “the music profession is greatly overcrowded” (81) and shouldn’t be the aim of
music education. Rather, as a means, “The remedy for these unfortunate conditions seems
to lie in parents training their children to make music for the love of it, and not for
professional or exhibition purposes” (83). Coleman talked extensively about ways parents
might help students avoid a showing-off attitude, and this critique of professional
ambitions connects to a previous theme, social.
The Other
Interestingly Addams and Coleman also shared a belief about the musics of
African Americans. When discussing race relations, Addams (1930) suggested:
There is one exception to this lack of recognition, in the admiration of those
melodies which we have learned to call the only American folksongs and which
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
18
have become the basis of the Negroes’ contribution to American music. Perhaps
because an oppressed people have always been sustained by their dreams the
spirituals became the support of their failing spirits. (219-220 emphasis added)
America is truly musical. The negroes of the South are (or were) musical. They
came from Africa with rich, musical voices, a natural capacity for melody and
harmony and a tendency to musical production. Out of their natural gifts has come
the most beautiful folk-song literature America has. The sorrows that civilization
has forced upon the negro in removing him [sic] from his [sic] African home have
doubtless had a part in the development of his music, but it is certainly not the
result of any training that our civilization has given him [sic]. (Coleman 1922, 1011 emphasis added)
Here we see the other, African Americans being held up for having the most beautiful
folk-song literature America has, and that beauty being the result of something they lack,
civilization, which is lacking because of oppression/ sorrows. Because each generation
“produces its own distorted knowledge of the other” (Said 2004, 874), it would be vain to
assume contemporary terminology avoids defining the other the way Addams and
Coleman seem to. Further, it is likely the messy business of coming to know the other
(rooted in the early 20th Century) that provides a foundation for why scholars find
Addams and Coleman so compelling to ethical praxis today.
Coleman’s discussion of the music of African Americans adds an additional
professional critique: “but it is certainly not the result of any training that our civilization
has given him [sic]” (Coleman 1922, 11). This leads to the unasked question, “To reform
or abandon education? \ That is the question that no respectable professional dares to ask
without facing the threat of disrepute” (Prakash & Esteva 2008, 15 emphasis in original).
And this adds another layer to Coleman’s disappearance from our profession’s history:
her critiques of music education (and willingness to music educate outside of schooling
structures, such as the home and in nature) may have been professionally unpalatable to a
profession that dares not face the threat of disrepute when music for all is really code for
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
19
schooling for all, music as work/ toil/ labor, even when it means less musicing in the
community.
Image 4: “A Lazy Oboe Player” (Coleman 1922, 106 insert)
Conclusions
The current study can deepen our understanding of Satis Coleman’s philosophy
by focusing qualitatively on aims, means, and assumptions and comparing and
contrasting these with Dewey and Addams’s aims, means, and assumptions. To answer
the second guiding question first—What does each educator believe about students living
the good life and how does education foster this?—I looked at the assumptions of each
educator. Assumptions for all three educators centered around the individual well-being,
and changing society. Spontaneous activities (especially improvisation for Coleman)
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
20
were valued because they increase an individual’s agency in society. Complexity of
social life led to an interdisciplinary view of knowledge. Epistemologically, a unity of
knowledge position was taken—people know the world through various disciplines/ the
arts because there are underlying principles to all disciplines/ the arts. Interdisciplinarity
may be problematic because as Lamb (1996) explains, “Unlike the interdisciplinary
nature of feminist education, music education is discipline based” (125). Also, Coleman
carried anti-profession critiques into music education. Addams and Coleman shared
assumptions about African Americans, and Coleman admits that western civilization and
music education didn’t make this important music, extending her critique of the
profession. Coleman’s assumptions about nature seem more ecocentric than Dewey’s.
The second research question—How does Satis Coleman’s music education
philosophy relate to and diverge from the educational philosophies of John Dewey and
Jane Addams—provided many interesting resonances among social; agency; interest;
continuity; interdisciplinarity; inner person; critiques; and the other. Interesting
divergences were found in the theme nature. For Coleman, experimentation led naturally
to contemplation of nature. Coleman’s attempts to understand the other through music
education can be understood in relation to socially conscious music education today. “A
radical music education then first and foremost recognizes difference, positionality and
degrees of privilege and works to counter structural inequities” (Hess 2014, 16 emphasis
added). Coleman seems to have begun the work of coming to the other with hopes to
recognize, and understand, though the work of positionality and understanding and
countering structural inequities have progressed since Coleman’s time (an occurrence any
progressive educator, with their belief in melioration, would cheer).
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
21
Perhaps the most interesting divergence between Coleman’s philosophy and that
of Dewey and Addams comes in the theme nature. In these texts, Dewey (1909) portrays
nature’s “significance” in subservience to “human relationships” (35). This seems
anthropocentric. Environmental philosopher George Sessions (1995) draws on Bertrand
Russell’s criticism of Dewey (and Marx) suggesting the desire for social power over
nature furthers ecological destruction (168). In contract, MacDonald (2004) recognizes
that a large body of environmental philosophy views Dewey’s philosophy as
anthropocentric, but counters that Dewey “can be defended against charges of antienvironmentalism and anthropocentricity” (xiv). He draws on Dewey’s Darwinism
(Sessions also describes Darwin as non-anthropocentric): “Human nature is indeed
specified, but Dewey argues that it cannot be understood outside of its natural
environment. His project is to bring human nature back into nature as a whole” (88).
To return focus to Coleman, non-human life has value itself (ecocentrism), such
as her descriptions of the cricket and Coleman’s learning pedagogy from robins. Nature
deserves “love” (Coleman 1939, 95) rather than “modifying and directing” (Dewey 1909,
35). And Coleman’s means follow this belief in the intrinsic value of Nature—listening to
the rhythmic beat of Nature; recommending outdoor music camps; representing nonhuman animals in song.
Sessions (1995) states, during “two to four million years of human history” as
hunter/ gatherers, “ecocentrism has been the dominant human religious/ philosophical
perspective throughout time” (158), but has only been a minority perspective among
Western philosophers. Some of the philosophers he suggested tried to get us off of the
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
22
anthropocentric detour included Spinoza, Mill, Thoreau, John Muir, and Santayana.
Coleman’s environmental philosophy seems more in line with Santayana than Dewey.
Why is music education scholarship largely missing both Coleman’s voice and a
robust expression of environmental philosophy in an era of ecological crises?
Ecofeminist Vandana Shiva (2007) suggests it may be because the feminine principle,
which is ecologically sustainable, is challenging to economic progress.
The recovery of the feminine principle is an intellectual and political challenge to
maldevelopment as a patriarchal project of domination and destruction, of
violence and subjugation, of dispossession and the dispensability of both women
and nature. The politics of life centered on the feminine principle challenges
fundamental assumptions not just in political economy, but also in the science of
life-threatening processes. (14)
Is it a coincidence that Coleman’s voice was lost near the same time music
education founded its first research journals, Journal of Research in Music Education,
and Bulletin of the Council for Research in Music Education? Is Shiva correct in her
assessment that the feminine principle challenges political economy (profession) and
science (research)? Taking students outside, where they lazily experiment with music
while learning from nature does not seem economically or politically efficient—though it
seems healthier than sitting students under fluorescent lighting for eight hours a day.
After two decades of reputation in music education, did Satis Coleman disappear because
structural sexism; the move from progressive to aesthetic values; the agency
improvisation gives children (upending hierarchy); her interdisciplinarity; her hope to
understand the other; her environmental philosophy; or some combination of all of these?
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
23
References
Addams, Jane. 1902. “Educational Methods.” In On Education, edited by Ellen Condliffe
Lagemann, 98-119. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers. [1994]
___. 1930. “Education by the Current Event.” In On Education, edited by Ellen Condliffe
Lagemann, 212-224. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers. [1994]
Boston, Sheila C. 1992. “Satis N. Coleman (1878-1961): Her Career in Music
Education.” PhD diss., University of Maryland College Park. 9315605.
Coleman, Satis N. 1922. Creative Music for Children. New York: G. P. Putnam’s Sons.
___. 1939. Your Child’s Music. New York: The John Day Company.
Dewey, John. 1913. Interest and Effort in Education. Boston: The Riverside Press
Cambridge. [Library of Congress reproduction]
___. 1975. Moral Principles in Education. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University
Press. [Originally published 1909]
___. 1997. Experience & Education. New York: Touchstone. [Originally published 1938]
Gates, J. Terry. 2005. “Dewey, Communication, and Habitus.” Action, Criticism, and
Theory for Music Education 4, no. 1 (March): 1-17.
http://act.maydaygroup.org/articles/Gates4_1.pdf.
Gould, Elizabeth. 2009. “Music Education Desire(ing): Language, Literacy, and Lieder.”
Philosophy of Music Education Review 17, no. 1 (Spring): 41-55.
http://www.jstor.org/stable/40327309.
Gossett, Jason B. 2015. “Values to Virtues: An Examination of Band Director Practice.”
PhD diss., The Pennsylvania State University.
https://etda.libraries.psu.edu/paper/26462/29722.
Hess. Juliet. 2014. “Radical Musicking: Towards a Pedagogy of Social Change.” Music
Education Research 2014. DOI: 10.1080/14613808.2014.909397.
hooks, bell. 2000. Feminism is for Everybody: Passionate Politics. Cambridge: South
End Press.
Howe, Sondra Wieland. 2009. “A Historical View of Women in Music Education
Careers.” Philosophy of Music Education Review 17, no. 2 (Fall): 162-183.
http://www.jstor.org/stable/40495498.
___. 2014. Women Music Educators in the United States: A History. Lanham: Scarecrow
Press.
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
24
Illich, Ivan. 1990. “The Loudspeaker on the Tower.” 1-13. Retrieved April 19, 2016 from
http://www.davidtinapple.com/illich/2000_loudsppu.pdf.
Klein, Julie Thompson. 1990. Interdisciplinarity: History, Theory, and Practice. Detroit:
Wayne State University Press.
Koza, Julia Eklund. 1993-1994. “A Place at the Table.” The Quarterly. 4-5, no. 5-1: 3-4.
(Reprinted in Visions of Research in Music Eduation 16, no. 5 (Autumn): 2010).
Lamb, Roberta. 1996. “Discords: Feminist Pedagogy in Music Education.” Theory Into
Practice 35, no. 2 (Spring): 124-131. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1476798.
___. 2014. “Where Are the Women? And Other Questions, Asked Within an Historical
Analysis of Sociology of Music Education Research Publications: Being a Selfreflective Ethnographic Path.” Action, Criticism, and Theory for Music Education
13, no. 1 (March): 188-222. http://act.maydaygroup.org/articles/Lamb13_1.pdf.
McCarthy, Marie. 2012. “Developments and Trends in Historical Research as Reflected
in the Journal of Historical Research in Music Education, Volumes 21-30 (19992009).” Journal of Historical Research in Music Education 33, no. 2 (April): 152171. DOI: 10.1177/153660061203300204.
McDonald, Hugh P. 2004. John Dewey and Environmental Philosophy. Albany: State
University of New York Press.
Noddings, Nel. 2012. Philosophy of Education. 2nd ed. Boulder: Westview Press.
Prakash, Madhu Suri. 1995. “Ecological Literacy for Moral Virtue: Orr on [Moral]
Education for Postmodern Sustainability.” Journal of Moral Education 24, no. 1
(July): 3-18. DOI: 10.1080/0305724950240101.
Prakash, Madhu Suri & Gustavo Esteva. 2008. Escaping Education: Living as Learning
Within Grassroots Cultures, 2nd ed. New York: Peter Lang.
Said, Edward. 2004. “Orientalism Once More.” Development and Change 35, no. 5.
Saldaña, Johnny. 2009. The Coding Manual for Qualitative Researchers. Los Angeles:
Sage Publications.
Sanger, Matthew & Richard Osguthorpe. 2005. “Making Sense of Approaches to Moral
Education.” Journal of Moral Education 34, no. 1 (March): 57-71. DOI:
10.1080/03057240500049323.
___. 2009. “Analyzing the Child Development Project Using the Moral Work of
Teaching Framework.” Journal of Moral Education 38, no. 1 (March): 17-34.
DOI: 10.1080/03057240802601490.
Daniel J. Shevock 2016
25
Santayana, George. 1911. “The Genteel Tradition in American Philosophy.” In Selected
Critical Writings of George Santayana, Vol. 2, edited by Norman Henfrey, 85107. London: Cambridge University Press.
Shevock, Daniel J. 2015. Satis Coleman—A Spiritual Philosophy for Music Education.
Music Educators Journal 102, no. 1 (September): 56-61. DOI:
10.1177/0027432115590182.
Shiva, Vandana. 2007. Staying Alive: Women, Ecology and Development. Atlantic
Highlands: Zed Books. [Originally published 1989]
Silverman, Marissa. 2012. “Virtue Ethics, Care Ethics, and ‘The Good Life of
Teaching’.” Action, Criticism, and Theory for Music Education 11, no. 2
(September): 96-122. http://act.maydaygroup.org/articles/Silverman11_2.pdf.
Southcott, Jane. 1990. “A Music Education Pioneer—Dr Satis Naronna Barton
Coleman.” British Journal of Music Education 7, no. 2: 123-132.
___. 2009. The Seeking Attitude: Ideas That Influenced Satis N. Coleman. Journal of
Historical Research in Music Education 31, no. 1 (October): 20-36.
http://www.jstor.org/stable/25597933.
Tellstrom, A. Theodore. 1971. Music in American Education: Past and Present. New
York: Holt, Reinhart and Winston, Inc.
Volk, Terese M. 1996. Satis Coleman’s “Creative Music”. Music Educators Journal 82,
no. 6. (May): 31-33+47. http://www.jstor.org/stable/3398949.
Wood, Jennifer Linhart. 2013. “Sounding Otherness in Early Modern Theater and Travel
Writing.” PhD diss., George Washington University. 3587221.
i
It has been asserted by followers of Dewey that “all education is moral education” (see
Prakash 1995), a sentiment with which I agree. Therefore, looking at educational
philosophy based on a moral framework seems appropriate.