John Dewey
THEORY FOR A GLOBAL AGE
Series Editor: Gurminder K. Bhambra
Globalization is widely viewed as a current condition of the world, but there is little
engagement with how this changes the way we understand it. The Theory for a Global
Age series addresses the impact of globalization on the social sciences and humanities.
Each title will focus on a particular theoretical issue or topic of empirical controversy
and debate, addressing theory in a more global and interconnected manner. With
contributions from scholars across the globe, the series will explore different perspectives
to examine globalization from a global viewpoint. True to its global character, the Theory
for a Global Age series will be available for online access worldwide via Creative Commons
licensing, aiming to stimulate wide debate within academia and beyond.
Previously published by Bloomsbury:
Connected Sociologies
Gurminder K. Bhambra
Eurafrica: The Untold History of European
Integration and Colonialism
Peo Hansen and Stefan Jonsson
On Sovereignty and Other Political
Delusions
Joan Cocks
Postcolonial Piracy: Media Distribution and
Cultural Production in the Global South
Edited by Lars Eckstein and Anja Schwarz
The Black Pacific: Anticolonial Struggles
and Oceanic Connections
Robbie Shilliam
Democracy and Revolutionary Politics
Neera Chandhoke
Published by
Manchester University Press:
Debt as Power
Richard H. Robbins and Tim Di Muzio
John Dewey
The Global Public and Its Problems
John Narayan
Manchester University Press
Copyright © John Narayan 2016
The right of John Narayan to be identified as the author of this work
has been asserted by him in accordance with the Copyright,
Designs and Patents Act 1988.
Published by Manchester University Press
Altrincham Street, Manchester M1 7JA
www.manchesteruniversitypress.co.uk
This work is published subject to a Creative Commons Attribution
Non-commercial No Derivatives Licence. You may share this work for
non-commercial purposes only, provided you give attribution to the copyright
holder and the publisher. For permission to publish commercial versions
please contact Manchester University Press.
British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data applied for
ISBN
978 1 7849 93245
978 1 5261 01020
hardback
open access
First published 2016
The publisher has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of URLs
for any external or third-party internet websites referred to in this book,
and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain,
accurate or appropriate.
Typeset by
Integra Software Services Pvt. Ltd.
TJ International Ltd, Padstow
For Rosie
Contents
Series Editor’s Foreword
Acknowledgements
ix
Introduction: Retrieving a ‘Global’ American Philosopher
The enigma of democratic globalization
Back to the future
Outline of the book
A ventriloquist’s disclaimer
1
1
2
3
4
x
4
9
10
13
Creative Democracy
Unfashionable democracy
Problematic states and their problematic publics:
The futility of state theory
The history of publics and the spectre of violence
Making the case for democracy as a way of life
Democracy as a way of life + political democracy =
creative democracy
15
The Global Democrat
The Great Society as the First Great Globalization
Dewey’s plea for a global Great Community
Global creative democracy
41
The Obstacles to Creative Democracy at Home and Abroad
The eclipse of the public
The national and global eclipse of creative democracy
55
Social Intelligence and Equality
The habits of social intelligence
The planning society
75
15
19
28
31
36
42
45
51
57
66
77
85
Contents
viii
Democracy and equality
Global democracy and equality
5
88
95
New Lessons from the Old Professor
Lesson 1: A Great Society does not equal
a Great Community
Lesson 2: The Great Community and the nation
Lesson 3: Democracy begins at home
Lesson 4: The spectre of bourgeois democracy
must be exorcised!
Global democracy: A new name for an old problem
103
Conclusion: Inheriting the Task of Creative Democracy
127
Notes
Bibliography
Index
131
104
106
109
115
119
155
165
Series Editor’s Foreword
The fate of democracy under conditions of neoliberal globalization
is the focus for John Narayan’s comprehensive re-examination of the
work of philosopher and proto-sociologist, John Dewey. While, as
Narayan argues, Dewey did not himself make a sustained argument
for global democracy, a powerful idea of global democracy can be
constructed from his philosophical and sociological writings. In this
way, in John Dewey: The Global Public and Its Problems, Narayan
expertly demonstrates the continuing relevance of John Dewey’s
thought for the consideration of contemporary problems of modern
sovereignty and questions of political and democratic legitimacy in a
global age.
Narayan starts with a discussion of Dewey’s understanding
of democracy as a creative process of reform and renewal. This
discussion is located in terms of examining the global conditions of
‘the Great Society’ and the global institutions and publics that are part
of its functioning at the larger scale. While the focus is strongly on
‘the global’, there is also consideration of the national contexts which
dominate in the debates and political practices of democracy. As
Narayan sets out, democracy, for Dewey, had to be articulated both
‘at home’ and ‘abroad’. In the latter sections of the book, Narayan pays
due attention to the ideas of global justice and equality that are often
neglected aspects of Dewey’s thought and makes a robust argument for
egalitarian democracy on a global scale.
The book is an excellent illustration of one of the motivating aspects
of the Theory for a Global Age series, namely, a concern to reconsider
existing understandings of the global such that we might better understand
our contemporary global condition. Dewey’s call to renew and refresh
our thinking in light of changes is nicely exemplified by Narayan’s own
rethinking of Dewey’s thought for our contemporary times.
Gurminder K. Bhambra
Acknowledgements
Although the intellectual process is often a lonely existence, it is
undoubtedly not a sole endeavour. Indeed, without the help of others
it would be nigh on impossible. I wish to thank the following for their
help during the formation of this piece.
To my wonderful wife, Rosie Narayan, whose intellect and
unconditional love and support have always been a place where I could
take refuge or draw strength from whenever the books have started to
hit back! This would not have been possible without you.
I must also mention the life form who I spend the majority of my
time with during the day, our family dog, Nina, who has spent most
days sleeping in her basket under my desk as I edited the manuscript,
and whose daily walks have provided the thinking space needed to get
over any bump in the road along the way.
I would also like to extend my deepest gratitude to:
The Economic and Social Research Council for funding the doctoral
study upon which this work is based and the University of Nottingham
for providing the institutional support to complete my doctorate.
Professor John Holmwood for his intellectual companionship
and general tolerance of my unabashed trait of disagreeing with him
on the principle that he was my PhD supervisor! Thank you for the
support through the years and the hard work that you have put into
my own work.
Professor Gurminder K. Bhambra whose support for this project
is only outweighed by the support she has given to my most recent
intellectual endeavours. Thank you for helping me wade through the
murky waters of academia!
My wonderful friends: Ross and Sian Abbinnett, Kehinde and Nicole
Andrews, Martin Culliney, Ruairi Hughes, Uzo and Heidi Ibechukwu
and Christopher and Louise Twardowski. It is a privilege to count on
you as friends. I love you all!
Acknowledgements
xi
I must also send love to the little ones: Simon Abbinnett, Assata and
Kadiri Andrews, Esme Ibechukwu, Naeva Twardowski, my little cousin,
Eleanor Wood, and my nephew, Gustav, and niece, Galia Nickson. You
all promise hope to a desperate world.
A special thank you must be sent to the Narayan clan for their support
of my intellectual endeavours down the years. Also to the Browns and
Nicksons, especially Lorna and Joe, for welcoming me into their family.
And I must mention the Dass family in Fiji, whose reconnection has
brought extra happiness to the writing process.
A special thanks must also be reserved for Rosie’s mum, Louise
Brown, and Tilly the dog. A lot of this work was initially conceived
at Louise’s house during my PhD and she even took to correcting the
manuscript’s many spelling mistakes. Thank you for your support over
the years.
Finally, I would like to thank my mother, Evelyn Narayan, and my
father, Vijendra Narayan, for their love and for dreaming for me long
before I knew what it was to dream. I owe you everything.
Introduction: Retrieving a ‘Global’
American Philosopher
There are two requests I should like to make to readers of the volume,
not to forestall criticism but that it may be rendered, perhaps, more
pertinent. Three lectures do not permit one to say all he thinks, nor
even all that he believes that he knows. Omission of topics and themes
does not, accordingly, signify that I should have passed them by in a
more extended treatment. I particularly regret the enforced omission
of reference to the relation of liberalism to international affairs. I
should also like to remind readers that not everything can be said
in the same breath and that it is necessary to stress first one aspect
and then another of the general subject. So I hope that what is said
will be taken as a whole and also in comparison and contrast with
alternative methods of social action. (LW11: 4)1
It might seem rather bizarre to claim that a return to the work of John
Dewey can offer a greater appreciation of globalization and global
democracy at the start of the twenty-first century. Dewey appears to be
a creature of a wholly different epoch; born in 1859, the year Darwin
published Origin of the Species and just short of eighteen months
before the Battle of Fort Sumter, Dewey’s life would end only some six
years after the beginning of the ‘Cold War’. To read his body of work
is therefore to enter a world that does not include bearing witness to
some of the most momentous events of American and world history
in the twentieth century. This includes the success of the American
Civil Rights Movement, the Vietnam War and the winds of change
that flattened European imperialism and empire. This is to say nothing
of events such as the rise and fall of the Bretton Woods regime, the
hegemonic ascent of neo-liberalism, the end of the Cold War and the
2
John Dewey
rise of communications technology such as the Internet. Dewey’s world
thus appears to be alien to contemporary concerns about rampant
globalization and the need to move democracy beyond the confines of
the nation state to regulate a runaway world.
Indeed, one might also label the attempt to call Dewey a ‘global’
thinker pure and utter philosophical folly in the first place. After
all, there doesn’t seem to be, philosophically at least, anything more
quintessentially American than Dewey and his brand of philosophical
pragmatism. This view is common amongst various critical interpreters
of Dewey’s work, who saw pragmatism as a foil for American capitalism
(Westbrook 2005: 139–41). Famously, Bertrand Russell (1909) labelled
the work of Dewey and his fellow philosophical pragmatists, such
as William James and Charles Sanders Pierce, as little more than the
philosophical accomplice to American corporate capitalism. This
viewpoint was repeated by Lewis Mumford (1926: 77) in the 1920s, who
charged Dewey and his fellow pragmatists with a form of philosophical
‘acquiescence’, which propounded an uncritical body of philosophy
that was ‘permeated by the smell of the Gilded Age’. Whilst Martin
Heidegger (1977: 153) would label philosophical pragmatism as the
‘American interpretation of Americanism’, a philosophy that simply
replicated American capitalism’s ‘technological frenzy’ and constant
‘reorganization of man’.
In the light of these statements, an uninformed reader would
seemingly be quite justified in believing Dewey to be a ‘local’ American
philosopher, whose work is unable to offer us in the present any insight
about ‘global’ issues. On one hand, one cannot deny that Dewey was
a local philosopher whose accent was unmistakably American. In
writing back to Mumford, for instance, Dewey argued that pragmatism
was not the expression of American industrialism but rather the rearticulation of American values that were now opposed to those ‘most
in evidence’ in the Gilded Age (LW3: 127). These were the values of a
‘radical democratic tradition’ that could be traced back to the history
of the United States of America and the words and creeds of Lincoln,
Jefferson and Emerson (Bernstein 2010: 88). From these democratic
Introduction: Retrieving a ‘Global’ American Philosopher
3
foundations, Dewey came to a profound understanding that democracy
was fragile and needed to be rejuvenated and reinterpreted to live up to
its ideal of a ‘democratic way of life’. Dewey’s philosophical oeuvre, and
in particular his political philosophy in works such as The Public and
Its Problems (LW2) and Liberalism and Social Action (LW11), therefore
often looked to pit ‘America against itself ’ so that the country could
achieve the democratic hopes and dreams that were the foundation of its
independence (Westbrook 2005: 140). In this vein, Dewey’s philosophy
can be seen as an earlier incarnation of the democratic spirit that
Richard Rorty (1999) evoked when he sought to show how intellectual
labour could help American citizens to ‘achieve our country’.
On the other hand, however, Dewey was not just concerned with
American democracy but rather American democracy in a global
context. From the conquest and founding of the North American
continent by the Europeans, or the importation of chattel slaves
from Africa, to its war of independence right through to the nascent
industrial world Dewey would be born into, America had always been
a country animated and related to global flows of people, technology
and politics. The American Civil War (1861–65) in which Dewey grew
up in was fought just as much as a result of the diametrically opposed
views on international trade policy between Southern and Northern
states as it was fought over the immorality of chattel slavery. At the end
of his life, Dewey would see the global ramifications of the atomic bomb
and the emergence of the Truman Doctrine that effectively committed
the United States to a global struggle against the Soviet Union and her
allies. In between Dewey visited or taught in Europe, China, Turkey,
Mexico, the USSR, and aged seventy-eight, he departed in 1937 for
Mexico to chair an international committee created to inquire into
the charges made by the Soviet state against Leon Trotsky (Cochran
2010: 310). When one adds to this that Dewey lived through the
Spanish-American War, the First World War, the rise of communism
and fascism, the Great Depression and (the fait accompli that was) the
Second World War, it is clear that Dewey was an American inhabitant
of a global world.
4
John Dewey
Whilst Dewey’s political philosophy was thus a creature of late
nineteenth century and early twentieth-century America, it was more
importantly about America in a globalized and interdependent world,
or rather what Dewey called ‘The Great Society’. Indeed, as the preface
to Liberalism and Social Action cited earlier makes clear, even when
Dewey could not find the room to talk about the global context in
his philosophy it was never too far from his mind. This dual aspect of
Dewey’s life and his work, where he was an American living in a global
world, appears to have been lost in translation throughout the years.
This book aims to show how the retrieval of the ‘global’ John Dewey not
only highlights that it was the global context of American democracy
that forced Dewey’s political philosophy into the task of ‘restoring the
spirit of America and its origin and propelling it, revised and renewed,
into the future’ (Martin 2002: 397–8). But that the global context also
led Dewey to become a fully fledged global democrat, who sought
to revise and renew American democracy along and within global
dimensions. The overall aim of this book is to show how the fruits of
Dewey’s attempts to reconstruct democracy, both at home and abroad,
in the first half of the twentieth century provide rich food for thought
about our twenty-first-century attempts to rethink democracy in the
age of globalization.2
The enigma of democratic globalization
The obvious question that arises out of the claim that we need to recover
a ‘global’ Dewey is why do we need such retrieval in the first place?
The answer revolves around the relationship between globalization and
democracy. The fate of democracy in the age of globalization, especially
globalization under the auspices of neo-liberalism, has preoccupied
scholars across the social sciences since the fall of the Berlin Wall
(Fine 2007; Calhoun 2008). This preoccupation has revolved around
the argument that globalization demands that we become postWestphalian in ‘a deep ontological sense’ and let go ‘not only of the
Introduction: Retrieving a ‘Global’ American Philosopher
5
idea of the sovereign state, but also of the individualistic basis for the
establishment of sovereign authority formalised by Thomas Hobbes at
the same time as the Treaty of Westphalia…’ (Dryzek 2012: 113–14).
Within this narrative, globalization is not to be taken, as it so often is,
as a word to be causally thrown around or as some sort of theoretical
cushion that appears to mould to the posterior of whoever sits upon
it. Rather, propelled by neo-liberal imperatives, modern globalization
is said to have unleashed a historically unprecedented form of
interconnectedness through intercontinental or interregional forms
of trade, production and finance that have fundamentally altered the
status of the nation state and national democracy (Held 2010: 28–9).3
The primary effect of neo-liberal globalization is that ‘modern
sovereignty’, where autonomous nation states exercise unquestionable
authority within bounded political communities and resolve their
differences with one another through reason of state and diplomacy, is
said to have collapsed (Held and McGrew 2007: 211). This is because
neo-liberal globalization has encouraged the deterritorialization of
political authority and sovereignty away from the nation state and the
subsequent reterritorialization of such power beyond the nation state.
This now not only makes the nation state largely subservient to the
tenets of free-market economics but also establishes the authority of
global governance institutions (IMF, WTO, World Bank) and global
markets over the nation state (Hardt and Negri 1999; Habermas 2001).
The ramifications of neo-liberal globalization and the supposed
collapse of modern sovereignty for the legitimacy and power of
national democracy are stark. If we take democracy to be the sign of
a legitimate order and define its normative meaning as all affected
persons being included, either directly or through their representatives,
in the deliberation and formation of decisions and legislation which
shape their common circumstance and destinies, then it becomes
clear that globalization’s creation of global interconnectedness and
the decline of modern sovereignty render nation states incapable of
securing democratic accountability for their citizens. The embrace of a
post-Westphalian ontology and very normative strictures of democracy
6
John Dewey
therefore demands the extension of ‘ … political decision making
capabilities beyond national borders … ’ (Habermas 2012: 15) at the
same time as the scope of decisions within them is also being undercut.
Those who embrace such a post-Westphalian ontology include a
variety of scholars who are not necessarily happy bedfellows. However,
they are united by the belief that statist solutions, where global
democracy is envisaged to centre on multilateral collaboration between
democratic nation states, are unable to achieve global democracy.
This includes modern statist positions, which argue that democracy
beyond the state is secure when democracy within the state is secure.
Whilst post-Westphalian ideas of global democracy see the state and
its democracy as having provided key pivots for global democracy,
such as forming the UN system, their belief is that such a system is
still a deficient and flawed medium to achieve global democracy
in present circumstances. This centres on the internal political and
economic stratification within states, the transnational nature of global
interconnectedness, the inability of national leaders to further global
democracy beyond national interests and the continuing hegemony of
rich and powerful nations at the international level. Whilst the state
should play a part in global democracy, post-Westphalian positions
believe that global democracy cannot begin and end with the state and
interstate relations (Scholte 2012: 4–6).
Following Cochran (2002), we can divide these post-Westphalian
positions on global democracy very roughly into those who favour
‘top-down’ pathways to global democracy and those who favour
‘bottom-up’ pathways. Top-down pathways can be seen as revolving
around the idea of modern cosmopolitanism. Premised upon the
theoretical foundations provided by Kant and the work of twentiethcentury world federalists, modern cosmopolitanism purports that the
world should be taken as a unit of society that has political rights and
obligations transcending its nation state-based counterparts (Brown
and Held 2010). This has seen a plethora of work arguing for the
supplementing and transcending of elements of liberal democracy’s
national framework to regional and/or global dimensions (Held 1995,
Introduction: Retrieving a ‘Global’ American Philosopher
7
2004; Habermas, 2006; Archibugi 2008; Hale et al., 2013). This would
see nation states pool sovereignty through submitting their national
interests to regional (EU) and global governance (UN) institutions, and
the extending of liberal democracy’s national framework of citizenship
rights, civil society (Kaldor 2003), the public sphere (Bohman 2007)
and elements of political democracy, such as parliaments and political
parties (Patomäki 2011), from national to regional or global levels.
Modern cosmopolitanism has come under criticism for privileging
the roles of elites and a form of spatial globalism that revolves around
global institutions and organizations without examining how global
democracy is linked to local, national and regional democracy
(Smith and Brassett 2008; Calhoun 2010). At the same time, modern
cosmopolitanism is also accused of a failure to tackle the global
economic inequalities that are created and perpetuated by neo-liberal
globalization (Hardt and Negri 2004) and of universalizing Eurocentric
ideas of citizenship, sovereignty, human rights and democracy without
any transcultural dialogue with non-Western epistemologies (Rao
2010; Bhambra 2011; Hobson 2012).
To circumvent the failings of modern cosmopolitanism, a wide
range of authors have attempted to reimagine global democracy from
below and have argued for bottom-up strategies for achieving global
democracy. These include conceiving spaces such as global civil society
(Brassett and Smith 2010), the international public sphere (Dryzek
2006, 2010) and the World Social Forum (Sen and Escobar 2007) as
arenas that retain their independence from governance institutions
and provide a platform for social movements, activists and citizens to
communicate and politically organize on a global level. More radical
positions look to social movements such as the Zapatistas, antiglobalization and Occupy Movement not only to transcend the spatial
globalism and Eurocentrism of modern cosmopolitanism but also to
displace global capitalist relations in the formation of a new and novel
form of global democracy (Hardt and Negri 1999, 2004, 2011).
Post-Westphalian global democracy is not without its own critics,
however. As Scholte (2012: 10) points out, some see global democracy
8
John Dewey
as an ‘oxymoron’ because democracy beyond the space of the local
or national container becomes impossible to manage or implement
(Dhal 1999, 2001). This has led to the argument that the way to
secure greater global democracy is to actually ‘deglobalize’ the global
economy and allow nations to assert their sovereignty in economic
and political matters (Bello 2005, 2013). The debate surrounding postWestphalian ideas of global democracy can therefore be seen as a site of
competing and unresolved dualisms. On one hand, there is a dualism
between statist and post-Westphalian ideas of global democracy. On
the other hand, within ideas of post-Westphalian democracy there is
also a dualism between top-down and bottom-up approaches to global
democracy.
These unresolved dualisms, which plague ideas of global democracy,
are not mere theoretical abstractions. Behind them resides a current
world order governed by neo-liberal globalization and insufficient
democratic control. Neo-liberal imperatives, which identify private
markets and free economic enterprise as meeting human needs and
freedom vis-à-vis largely inefficient state intervention and regulation,
have increased systemic inequality within and between states and
regions of the world. Moreover, forms of global governance are both
undemocratic and unable to govern globalization democratically
(Chang 2007; Wade 2009a, 2009b; Rodrik 2011). The result of failing
to increase democratic control over neo-liberal globalization could
not be bleaker. At the dawn of the twenty-first century, there are very
few theoretical debates that have such potential practical permutations
and relevancy than the theoretical debate about the best way to secure
global democracy. Indeed, the debate about global democracy would
appear to centre on nothing short of the survival or extinction of the
human race:
Unresolved global challenges such as nuclear proliferation, global
inequality, global infectious diseases, environmental degradation, and
financial crises not only risk affecting the life chances of men, women,
and children across the world in the future, but do so now in numerous
ways. At the core of daily human insecurity, as well as uncertainty
Introduction: Retrieving a ‘Global’ American Philosopher
9
created by risks ranging from new forms of terrorism to nuclear war
or accelerating climate change, lie fundamental issues of survival,
freedom, the rule of law, and social justice. (Hale et al. 2013: 311)
Back to the future
It might seem counter-intuitive to attempt to interpret how we
can democratize neo-liberal globalization through the work of
a philosopher who died midway through the twentieth century.
However, through returning to and recovering the neglected global
dimensions of John Dewey’s political philosophy and international
writings, this book will aim to highlight the ‘global’ Dewey. I argue
that his insights about globalization and democracy can contribute
towards present theoretical debates about globalization and global
democracy. Moreover, John Dewey’s work from the end of the First
World War onwards prefigures an approach to global democracy
that not only dispels the dualisms that plague modern ideas of global
democracy but also has important points to make about the role
of national democracy in the expansion of democracy beyond the
confines of the nation state.
The book discloses the ‘global Dewey’ through examining how
his works – especially The Public and Its Problems (LW2) – set out
an evolutionary form of global and national democracy in response
to a rapidly globalizing economy. The global dimensions of Dewey’s
thought have received relatively little study and although they are
underappreciated they provide valuable lessons for those of us in the
twenty-first century who hold out hopes for global democracy. These
lessons centre on how Dewey’s work illuminates the following:
l
l
The problem of globalization and democracy is rooted in the
emergence of the First Great Globalization of the nineteenth
century.
The rise of globalization and increased industrial complexity does
not necessarily create reflexive and cosmopolitan individuals.
10
l
l
l
John Dewey
Nationalism and national democracy are not the archenemies of
planetary democracy.
The fate of extending democracy beyond the nation state is twined
with the fate of democracy at the national level, and the nation state
is the starting point for any form of planetary democracy.
Liberal capitalism and democracy are, to a large extent,
incompatible with one another.
Above all, the book will conclude that Deweyan lessons highlight that
what we often take to be the problems of ‘globalization’, the collapse
of ‘modern sovereignty’ and ‘global democracy’ are simply new ways
of expressing old concerns and debates. Those of us in the present
would therefore be well served by returning to Dewey’s reflections on
these old concerns as a source of new insights into our own present of
globalization and its deadly discontents.
Outline of the book
The book consists of five chapters. Chapters 1 and 2 highlight how
Dewey’s defence of democracy in the context of what he denotes as
the Great Society leads him to confront the problems of globalization
and global democracy. Chapter 1 thus returns to Dewey’s 1927 text
The Public and Its Problems and fleshes out how his conception of
‘creative democracy’ defines democracy as an evolutionary ideal whose
institutions change and adapt to the demands of the environment.
This entails re-examining Dewey’s debate with Walter Lippmann and
democratic realism about the nature of the state, publics, expertise and
the value of democracy and outlining his subsequent argument that
publics, government and consequently the state are historically relative
properties. This is followed by an examination of Dewey’s argument
that democracy is the best way to deal with such historical relativity
due its ability to efficiently update the institutions of government
without unnecessary recourse to violent revolution or the suppression
Introduction: Retrieving a ‘Global’ American Philosopher
11
of others. The chapter ends by outlining how Dewey believed the ideal
of ‘creative democracy’ conjoined the ideal of democracy (what he
called ‘democracy as a way of life’) with a practical agenda of reforming
and renewing what he saw as the institutions and practices of ‘political
democracy’.
Chapter 2 explores how Dewey’s conception of creative democracy
had global connotations. This entails recovering how Dewey’s political
philosophy of publics and democracy was forged with globalization
and the extension of democracy beyond the nation state in mind. This
is achieved by firstly contextualizing Dewey’s work from the 1920s
onwards and its evocation of the emergence of ‘The Great Society’ as
being a reaction to the First Great Globalization, which had taken place
in the nineteenth century and continued through the early parts of the
twentieth century. The chapter continues by examining how Dewey’s
texts from The Public and Its Problems onwards called for the creation of
a global Great Community and global democracy to regulate the global
dimensions of the Great Society. The chapter concludes by highlighting
how Dewey believed that global democracy was a realizable endeavour
and outlines some of his recommendations for how it should be
practised through the empowerment of publics and global institutions.
Chapter 3 will examine how Dewey problematized his own conception
of democracy through arguing that the public within modern nation
states was ‘eclipsed’ under the regime he called ‘bourgeois democracy’.
In this scenario, citizen publics were unable to map the forces affecting
their lives and disenchanted with a political democracy that had been
captured by the interests of capital. It has become the norm to read
Dewey’s account of the eclipse of the public and the stunting of creative
democracy as simply being concerned with the American nation state.
However, the chapter will conclude by demonstrating that Dewey’s claim
that the Great Society had no ‘political agencies worthy of it’ extended to
matters of global democracy and that he twined the fate of democracy
beyond the nation state to democracy within the nation state.
Chapter 4 shifts the terrain of Dewey’s global focus to ideas of
global justice and equality. This chapter demonstrates that Dewey’s
12
John Dewey
idea of global democracy was linked with an idea of global equality,
which would secure social intelligence on a global scale. The logical
result of this argument is a radical conception of global justice and the
need for economic equality within and beyond nations. This revolves
around examining how Dewey’s idea of creative democracy was based
upon a form of deliberation he called social intelligence and how social
intelligence is essentially an adoption of the ‘scientific attitude of the
mind’ into moral and political matters. It will be argued that Dewey
did not believe that liberal capitalism’s culture and political economy
could support the conditions of equality, which would make creative
democracy through social intelligence possible. Dewey’s politics of
democratic socialism subsequently reveals his views on the relationship
between economic and political equality within the Great Society. The
final section highlights how Dewey’s views on economic and political
equality translate into an argument for the extension of a global
egalitarianism, which would allow all nations of the world to pursue
the democratic way of life.
To conclude the study, Chapter 5 turns to outlining what I believe
are the four main lessons Dewey provides about global democracy.
All four of these lessons foresee the contemporary obstacles faced
in moving democracy beyond the nation state and, importantly,
how Dewey realized that democracy abroad was impossible without
democracy at home. Moreover, these lessons revolve around what
we can denote as Dewey’s rooted cosmopolitanism, which argues
that without a thriving democracy within the nation state there
can be very little chance of democracy beyond the nation state. The
chapter concludes by arguing that Dewey’s work on the problems of
bourgeois democracy at home and abroad highlights significant gaps
in post-Westphalian conceptions of global democracy. This will reveal
that the nature, political efficacy or viability, of any conception of
‘global democracy’ in the twenty-first century can only be adequately
conceptualized by revisiting and confronting Deweyan concerns
about the political efficacy or viability of publics and their relation to
democratic praxis within the nation state.
Introduction: Retrieving a ‘Global’ American Philosopher
13
A ventriloquist’s disclaimer
Before I start my exposition of John Dewey as a global philosopher, a quick
note about intellectual interpretation must be made. Robert Westbrook
(2005: 177), perhaps John Dewey’s key intellectual biographer, makes a
pertinent point about intellectual history when he states that intellectual
historians bear a responsibility to read philosophers accurately in order
to illuminate how these figures can provide useful guidance on our
present problems. In the act of ventriloquism that is intellectual history
we therefore bear the responsibility of making our philosophical puppet
utter words it would have uttered if he or she were actually alive or
present in the room. This is less about a rigid conception of objective
truth, argues Westbrook, but rather a rough and ready rule to stop us
imagining intellectual playmates who may never have existed in the first
place.4 In this book, I try to follow Westbrook’s advice as much as I can,
but I do bend Westbrook’s rule for intellectual historians slightly, not by
elucidating an argument Dewey would never have made, but by outlining
an argument Dewey did not outline in one systematic statement but one
he could have made in a systematic way if had chosen to. Dewey did not
make a great systematic statement on global democracy but a philosophy
of global democracy is scattered throughout his body of work. Indeed,
Dewey’s lack of a book on global democracy seems more due to a lack
of time and the fact that he was busy writing as a concerned American
citizen in a global world. However, as we shall see, this makes perfect
sense when you understand Dewey’s belief in the fact that democracy at
home was fundamentally linked to democracy abroad.
1
Creative Democracy
Optimism about democracy is today under a cloud. (LW2: 304)
Unfashionable democracy
When Dewey published The Public and Its Problems in 1927, democracy
had become somewhat of an unfashionable aspiration, with populations
in Europe beginning to turn to the extreme Left and Right for their
political settlements. In Russia the October Revolution was nearly ten
years old, in Italy Mussolini had been in power for three years and in
Germany both volumes of Mein Kampf had been published. At home
in the United States of America, even the pretence of democracy in the
country had come under attack.1 The catalyst for this attack on American
democracy revolved around the dissipation of post–First World
War optimism about reconstructing America in fairer and more just
terms. Whilst Progressives put forward ideas for economic justice and
fairness, such reforms were ‘strangled’ by older patterns of thought and
behaviour that re-emerged in the climate of revolution (Kloppenberg
1986). The breakdown of this optimism amongst American progressives
in turn gave way to the rise of trenchant intellectual critiques of the
suitability of democratic government for 1920s America. Conducted
by American political scientists and commentators, these critiques of
the suitability of democratic government would form what became
known as ‘democratic realism’. And by the 1930s, the paradigm had
become near hegemonic in American social science (Westbrook 1991:
281–6).
16
John Dewey
The main charge of democratic realism was that democracy was
now unable to provide a stable or efficient government for advanced
industrial societies. For democratic realism, the institutions of
democratic government, which were based on democracy’s core
beliefs in the capacity of all people for rational political action and
the belief in maximizing civic participation in public life, were in
fact counterproductive to good government in industrial societies
(Westbrook 1991: 281–2). The main articulation of this position was to
be found in the work of Walter Lippmann and his two treatises against
standard liberal thought, Public Opinion (1922) and The Phantom
Public (1925). Within these works, Lippmann puts forward the idea
that America had entered into the Great Society, which made the core
beliefs of democracy unrealizable.
The concept of the Great Society, adapted by both Lippmann and
later Dewey from Graham Wallas’ (1914) book of the same name,
was essentially shorthand for the complex industrial and mass
consumer society America had become in the aftermath of the First
World War. The end of the American Civil War had signalled that
America would use its vast reserves of raw materials and land to
become a continental nation state with an industrial economy rather
than being a decentralized federation of states with a slave-based
agrarian economy.2 This process had seen America not only master
the steam-, coal- and railway-based technologies and industries
of the first industrial revolution, but also become the leader of
the second industrial revolution of the late nineteenth and early
twentieth centuries. This saw the systematic application of science
to the industrial process in the new oil-, electricity- and chemicalbased industries of automobiles, synthetic material production
and consumer durables (Frieden 2006: 152; Morris 2011: 510; Lind
2012: 5–10). The result was that, as early as 1914, the US economy,
in both absolute figures and per capita terms, had overtaken Britain
as the biggest economy in the world. By 1919, due in part to the
economic consequences of the First World War, US economic output
was greater than all of Europe (Kennedy 1987: 242–4).
Creative Democracy
17
Dewey argued that the Great Society’s improvements in industrial
production, travel and transportation (railways, cars), media (radio,
newspapers) and communications (telegraph, telephone) not only
eliminated distance as an economic and social factor but also created
‘interaction and interdependence’ on an unprecedented complex and
wide scale (LW2: 307). In industry, for example, the new corporations
of 1920s America such as General Motors, Ford and General Electric
did not just produce oligopolistic industries but had become vertically
integrated entities. Such vertically integrated corporations and the
widespread use of electricity, cheaper steel production, the chemical
industry and the advent of the assembly line thus delivered mass
industrial production.3
The move from an agrarian to such an advanced capitalist society
had essentially brought about massive changes in the day-to-day life
of Americans. The revolution in corporate structure and industrial
production, which saw consumer durables such as cars, radios and
refrigerators become the driving force of economic growth, had seen
a concomitant revolution of mass consumption. And as productivity
soared, the prices of consumer durables dropped. Ford’s Model T, for
example, reduced in price from $700 (US) in 1910 to $350 (US) in 1916
and by 1916 it took only six months for the average American to earn
enough money to buy one. By 1929, Americans were driving some
26 million cars or trucks. And this is to say nothing of the 20 million
phones installed by 1930, new public highways and railway lines, the
advent of chain stores and modern advertising, radio set sales, electric
stoves and heaters, consumer credit and the fact that by 1924 one could
even buy sliced bread (Leuchtenburg 1993: 178–202; Frieden 2006:
62–3, 155–72).
For writers such as Lippmann, the emergence of the Great Society
created a far too complex industrial and corporate environment for a
normal citizen to exercise rational political judgement about how such
a society should be governed. For Lippmann the common citizen was
being driven along by industrial innovation and expertise that they could
not grasp and was also distracted by mass consumption. As a result,
18
John Dewey
modern citizens were incapable of grasping their immediate present,
their own interests and essentially living in a world they ‘cannot see,
[do] not understand and [are] unable to direct’ (Lippmann 1925: 4). The
democratic goal of maximizing the civic participation of all citizens in
public life was thus simply ‘bad only in the sense that it is bad for a fat
man to try to be a ballet dancer’ (Lippmann 1925: 29). The only solution,
argued Lippmann, was for normal citizens to give up the concept of selfrule and move towards a system of elitism, whereby experts who are in a
position to grasp the complexities of the Great Society would create and
enact social policy. In this context, citizens would only play the role of
siding with or against different elites, playing no role in policy formation
and simply voting for the ‘Ins when things are going well and the Outs
when things are going badly’ (Lippmann 1925: 126).
In Dewey’s eyes, the attacks upon democracy by communism,
fascism and democratic realism were bound to fail miserably or end up
in violence and bloodshed. Quite simply, democratic realism’s quasiPlatonism and communism and fascism’s authoritarianism, which held
experts or rulers as the only ones capable to enact policies that would
be wise and beneficial to the common good of society, contradicted
the historical record. The emergence and practice of democracy itself
had shown that it is only through wide consultation and discussion
that wider social needs and common goods are uncovered. As Dewey
colourfully put it, the man ‘ … who wears the shoe knows best that it
pinches and where it pinches, even if the expert shoe maker is the best
judge of how the trouble is to be remedied’ (LW2: 364). To subsequently
remove the input of the masses and leave government policy to an elite
was to create a class closed off from the knowledge of the needs that
they were supposed to serve. Dewey therefore feared that rule by an
elite group in which the masses could not express their needs would
resemble an oligarchy managed in the interests of the few rather than
the many. And as Dewey reminded his readers, such fears were not
mere abstractions when history patently highlighted how the ‘ … world
has suffered more from leaders and authorities than from the so-called
folly of masses’ (LW2: 365).4
Creative Democracy
19
The Public and Its Problems is thus best seen as attempting to walk
along the path that Dewey believed the far Left and Right in Europe and
democratic realism in America shed light upon but refused to travel:
the contemporary problem of democracy within the Great Society.
Moreover, Dewey sets himself the goal of answering the question that he
believed Lippmann and others hastily skimmed over by rendering the
masses innately incapable of civic organization: Why is the contemporary
public seemingly unable to intelligently perform the tasks that
democracy requires of them? To accomplish this, Dewey embarks upon
two interrelated tasks within The Public and Its Problems. The first task,
which I examine below, involves Dewey reconstructing the concept of
democracy as a form of ‘creative democracy’, simultaneously redefining
the political concepts of the ‘state’, ‘public’, ‘government’ and ultimately
‘democracy’ itself. As I outline in Chapter 2, this task saw Dewey stretch
those concepts beyond the remit of the nation state. The second task,
which we will discuss in Chapter 3, involves the examination of why
the democracy of Dewey’s present within the Great Society bore a poor
resemblance to his own vision of democracy as a way of life.5
Problematic states and their problematic publics:
The futility of state theory
It was Dewey’s belief that the meaning of democracy and the justification
for its practice had seemingly become lost in the hubris of democratic
realism. In the journey to reconstruct and redefine the concept of
democracy, Dewey initially returns to another, if not the most, perennial
question of political philosophy: What is the origin and nature of the
state? In reference to what he believed were prior flawed theories of the
state, from the works of Aristotle through to and beyond Hegel, Dewey
cautions his readers that the ‘moment we utter the words “The State” a
score of intellectual ghosts rise to obscure our vision’ (LW2: 240).
This obfuscation, Dewey contended, arose because theories of
the state resorted to mythological ‘state-forming forces’ or ‘political
20
John Dewey
instincts’ to explain the state and its functions. For example, Aristotle’s
claim that man by nature is an animal that lives in a state and Social
Contract Theory’s claim that the state emerges after a fictional state
of nature tell us nothing about how actual states come into being or
why states take on different forms at different points in history. Such
theories merely repackaged the outcome of a given social process
(Greek City State/Liberal Democracy) as its cause and reduplicated it
in ‘ … a so called causal force the effects to be accounted for.’ Ultimately,
Dewey charged, that such theories hold no more explanatory value
than the statement that opium had sleep-inducing effects because of its
‘dormative powers’ (LW2: 240–1).
Following his dismissal of the explanatory value of prior theories of
the state, Dewey begins his own analysis of politics – its institutional
forms and practices – from the very empirical starting point he believes
the aforementioned theories neglect: the history of human activity and
its consequences (LW2: 243). Building upon his prior engagement with
Darwin’s theory of evolution and the psychology of William James,
Dewey puts forward an argument for the social nature of both the self
and morality. The foundation of this argument is that like all objects
within nature, human beings exist in an environment where ‘conjoint,
combined, associated action is a universal trait of the behaviour of
things’ (LW2: 257). What we take to be human nature or what we
take to be the human ‘self ’ is said by Dewey not to be an immutable
property or instinct which individuals then utilize to interact with their
environment, but rather an entity which is produced as the outcome of
the interaction of the human organism with its environment.6
This interaction of the human organism with its environment takes
place through what Dewey denotes as habits, which ‘bind us to orderly
and established ways of action’ (LW2: 335).7 In this sense, habits are
not simply recurrent or routine ways of behaving but rather acquired
predispositions or modes of response, which generate ease, skill and
interest when individuals interact with their environment:
For we are given to thinking of a habit as simply a recurrent external
mode of action, like smoking or swearing, being neat or negligent
Creative Democracy
21
in clothes and person, taking exercise or playing games. But habit
reaches even more significantly down into the very structure of the
self; it signifies a building up of and solidifying of certain desires;
an increased sensitiveness and responsiveness to certain stimuli, a
confirmed or impaired capacity to attend to and think about certain
things. Habit covers in other words the very make up of desire, intent,
choice, disposition which gives an act its voluntary quality. (LW7:
170–1)
The important point to consider here, however, is that we do not simply
create our habits out of thin air, but rather acquire and learn our habits
from what Dewey calls ‘social customs’. Much like the language we
speak, individuals inherit and form their personal moral habits from
the uniformities, habits or set ways of conduct of the respective social
groups they are born into or are associated with throughout their lives.
From birth onwards individuals find that established social customs,
which saturate such habits with meaning, are taught and transmitted
to them through the associated life they have with other humans
(MW14: 43–52). As Dewey points out, the sailor, miner, fisherman
and farmer think about their actions, but their thoughts fall within the
framework of accustomed occupations and social relations. What an
individual actually is as a self – that is, how an individual thinks and
acts – is ultimately dependent upon the nature and movement of their
associated life (LW5: 275).
These habits and customs are structured through what Dewey calls a
society’s ‘cultural matrix’.8 The idea of a ‘cultural matrix’ thus corresponds
to a society’s socio-economic, technological and intellectual (religion/
science/philosophy/politics) practices, which determine the associative
relations (occupations, family structures and geographical links) and
the meanings (habits/customs) attached to those associated relations
by various social groups (LW12: 481–2). As such, a society’s cultural
matrix provides an:
… inalienable and ineradicable framework of conceptions which
is not of our own making, but given to us ready-made by society –
a whole apparatus of concepts and categories, within which and by
22
John Dewey
which individual thinking, however daring and original, is compelled
to move. (LW12: 482)
It may be tempting to think from the above that Dewey assigns
priority of society over the individual and that the individual is only an
expression of society. However, Dewey’s point is that the human self is
produced through pre-existent associations and the social customs of
other humans not society at large (M14: 44, cf. Gouinlock 1972: 105–6).
This does not discount that social customs can stretch across society
but such a subtle distinction highlights how societies are not uniform
but rather pluralistic entities:
Society is one word, but many things. Men associate together in all
kinds of ways and for all kinds of purposes. One man is concerned
in a multitude of diverse groups, in which his associates may be quite
different. It often seems as if they had nothing in common except
that they are modes of associated life. Within every larger social
organisation there are numerous minor groups; not only political
subdivisions but industrial, scientific, religious, associations. There
are political parties with differing aims, social sets, cliques, gangs,
corporations, partnerships, groups bound closely together by ties of
blood, and so in endless variety. In many modern states, and in some
ancient, there is great diversity of populations, of varying languages,
religions, moral codes and traditions. From this standpoint, many a
modern political unit, one of large cities for example, is a congeries of
loosely associated societies rather than an inclusive and permeating
community of action and thought. (MW9: 87–8)
At any given synchronic moment within a cultural matrix, there exist
individuals and groups who share different associated relations and
different habits and different social customs. Indeed, Dewey suggests,
that the more complex a society’s cultural matrix, the more likely it is to
include individuals who possess habits that are informed by differing or
even conflicting patterns of social customs (MW14: 90).
The ability of a society’s cultural matrix to produce groups with
different or even conflicting habits and social customs revealed for
Dewey that morality, when taken as defining acceptable parameters
Creative Democracy
23
of both individual behaviour and behaviour between individuals and
groups within society, is also a socially determined activity. Whilst all
humans form associations with and are formed by associations (habits/
social customs) with natural objects and other human beings within
a cultural matrix, it is also the case that all human action has possible
consequences for other natural objects and other human beings who
share in association or who inhabit the same society:
Some activity proceeds from a man; then it sets up reaction in the
surroundings. Others approve, disapprove, protest, encourage, share
and resist … Conduct is always shared; this is the difference between
it and a physiological process. It is not an ethical ‘ought’ that conduct
should be social. It is social, whether bad or good. (MW14: 16)
Importantly, however, Dewey contends that what separates human
associations from that of natural objects, such as assemblies of electrons,
unions of trees, swarms of insects, herds of sheep or constellations of
stars, is the ability of humanity to intelligently perceive, reflect upon
and subsequently plan to secure certain consequences and avoid others
(LW2: 243, 250, 257). This ability of humans to intelligently perceive
the consequences of associated action is structured around two kinds
of consequences: those that directly affect individuals engaged in a
transaction of associated behaviour and those that indirectly affect
individuals beyond those immediately concerned in the transaction.
Within this distinction, Dewey finds the germ of the distinction
between conceptions of private and public transactions. Transactions
where the consequences of action were confined, or thought to be
predominantly confined, to those directly engaged in such associative
behaviour are said to be private. Transactions where the consequences
are perceived to be extensive, enduring and serious for persons beyond
those immediately engaged in such transactions are said to be of a
public disposition. However, Dewey refines his position further by
stating that this distinction was ultimately drawn on the scope and
extent to which consequences were deemed important by a society to
warrant control, whether through inhibition or promotion. In essence,
24
John Dewey
all private transactions of associative behaviour have the propensity to
become public when they are perceived to have extensive, enduring
and serious consequences for others beyond those directly engaged
in them. As such, there is no domain of activities that is intrinsically
private (LW2: 243–5, 252–3).9
It is within the distinction between private and public transactions
that Dewey finds the key to the origins of the ‘nature and office of
the state’, arguing that the perception of public transactions leads to
emergence of what he calls a ‘Public’ and subsequently the founding of
a state. In Dewey’s sense of the term, a public comes into existence when
persons, having become conscious of and sufficiently affected by the
consequences of associative behaviour (habits) to deem it unacceptable,
form a collective group or movement with a common interest in having
such consequences systematically controlled or cared for (LW2: 245,
cf. 52–3, 260). However, such a public faces a dilemma due to the fact
that the very consequences that call forth a public expand beyond those
directly engaged in such associative behaviour.
The regulation of such consequences cannot be conducted by the
primary groupings involved in the respective associative behaviour
in the first place (although self-organization by a group to regulate
its activities is also an important phenomenon). Consequently, in
organizing themselves to deal with such indirect consequences, such a
public creates special agencies and appoints officials such as legislators,
judges and executives (which might include members of a public acting
as citizens) to regulate behaviour and protect (through laws, rights and
establishment of practices) their interests. These officials and special
agencies, argues Dewey, are what we nominally call government and
help bring forth a state. However, as Dewey is at pains to point out, the
state does not solely consist of the inaugurating of government or the
rise of a public but rather it is the political organization of the public
through government:
The lasting, extensive and serious consequences of associated activity
bring into existence a public. In itself it is unorganised and formless.
By means of officials and their special powers it becomes a state. A
Creative Democracy
25
public articulated and operating through representative officers is a
state; there is no state without a government, but also there is none
without a public. (LW2: 277, cf. 245–57, 260)
The central premise of Dewey’s conception of the state is its foregoing
of any attempt to find the true nature or essence of the state in order to
embrace an anti-essentialist view of the state. In this sense, Dewey argues
that after the formation of a state through the political organization
of a public, its functions (governmental practices, parameters and
composition) are themselves prone to changing in character and tone
due to the changing historical conditions of associative behaviour and
the rise of new publics. In simple terms, Dewey argues that the state
possesses a historical relativity of form and function rather than a static
and enduring nature.10
The reason for this historical relativity of state form and function,
Dewey suggests, involved the fact that the consequences of associative
behaviour are linked to a society’s cultural matrix and the historical
propensity for the properties of a society’s cultural matrix to change
(Dewey, LW2: 263). A cultural matrix, Dewey contends, is itself always
open and prone to change due to socio-economic and technological
transformation, migration, exploration or wars that modify preexisting associations or create new associations (habits/customs) and
consequences. At the same time, the very perception or meaning
attached to the consequences of associated behaviour and the best
methods to deal with such consequences can itself shift in terms of a
change in intellectual habits. For instance, scientific discoveries or the
emergence of a new political paradigm may radically alter how people
approach the consequences of associated behaviour (LW2: 263–5,
cf. 254–5, 278–9). On the back of this, Dewey stresses that change in
a cultural matrix, what we can also call societal change, is a historical
fact, which injects perpetual and potentially revolutionary change
in multifarious and different marks of intensities across the various
relations of associative behaviour within a society (LW11: 41).11
As such, Dewey’s concept of a public does not denote a static and
homogenous body of people but rather plural and ever-changing
26
John Dewey
publics brought into existence in reaction to changes in a society’s
cultural matrix and the consequences of associated behaviour.12 On
a synchronic level, publics are plural, ranging in size, strength and
interests due to the variety of associations, habits and social customs a
cultural matrix puts into practice and the perceptions of consequences
a cultural matrix provides (LW2: 254–5). For instance, if one considers
issues such as animal rights, immigration, homosexuality, women’s
equality or welfare provision, it is clear that at any one moment in
time there are potentially multiple publics with their own agendas and
interests, who may or may not support another public’s cause.
A person may belong to many different publics, based on how they
are subjected to or perceive the consequences of associative behaviour.
No two publics are therefore likely to ever have the same membership
but a public may possibly possess members from other publics. In turn,
because publics are differentiated by the associative behaviour invoked
by the contours of material culture, publics may even be constructed
in response to other publics. It is quite often the case, for example, that
some publics hold interests and ideas of how the state could manage
such interests, which other publics may find inherently unreasonable
or even dangerous because they conflict with their own interests and
values. Consequently, there is, Dewey stresses, often room for dispute
or conflict between the interests of differing publics (LW2: 275, 354, cf.
LW11: 56).
On a diachronic level, publics also come into existence and pass
out of existence in response to the variety of associations a cultural
matrix puts into practice and the perceptions of consequences a
material culture provides. Publics may not only continue on from and
modify the interests from where previous publics left off (e.g. religious/
socialist/feminist movements) but may be entirely original movements
whose values and interests differ markedly from publics that precede
them. All publics, however, emerge within a strategic context where
the state and its institutions of government bear the hallmarks of the
interests of previous publics. For example, new publics engendered by
new conditions in material culture have often found that their inherited
Creative Democracy
27
institutions, beliefs and traditions of government, which reflect the
interests of older publics, suffer from a cultural ‘lag’ and are unfit to
meet their needs (LW2: 255, cf. LW13: 97, LW11: 54, LW12: 82–3).
New publics will therefore often seek to modify the institutions and
officials of government to suit their present interests and consequently
modify the nature and functions of the state (LW2: 255).13 This may
include fundamentally changing the nature and functions of a state as it
has been laid down by previous publics, such as those that founded the
state in the first place. In turn, the modification of the state’s institutions
of government, through changing the nature of associative behaviour
and creating new forms of cultural norms and values, will affect and
modify a society’s cultural matrix and subsequently provide a new
cultural matrix (consequences/perceptions of associative behaviour)
for the possible emergence of future publics.
In the light of the perpetual propensity of a cultural matrix to
change and call forth synchronically and diachronically differentiated
publics, Dewey declares that the state is a historically relative entity
whose functions were ‘ever something to be scrutinized, investigated,
and searched for’ and hence remade and reorganized in reaction to the
conditions of culture (LW2: 255). Dewey sums up his historicist view of
the state by propounding that:
The consequences vary with concrete conditions; hence at one time
and place a large measure of state activity may be indicated and at
another time a policy of quiescence and laissez-faire. Just as publics
and states vary with conditions of time and place, so do the concrete
functions which should be carried on by states. There is no antecedent
universal proposition which can be laid down because of which the
functions of a state should be limited or should be expanded. Their
scope is something to be critically and experimentally determined.
(LW2: 281)
Concluding his examination of the state, Dewey argues that the
philosophical preoccupation with an all-encompassing theory of the
state’s nature had always been a mirage of a goal in the first place.
In provisional terms, whilst one could declare that the state was the
28
John Dewey
political organization of the public via government and that such
arrangements had certain historical traits of function, ultimately
‘ … what the public may be, what the officials are, how adequately they
perform their function, are things we have to go to history to discover’
(LW2: 253–6).14
The history of publics and the spectre of violence
The qualification that publics, government and consequently the state
are historically relative properties based on the movements of a society’s
cultural matrix is the cornerstone of Dewey’s recasting of the meaning
of democracy and the justification for its practice vis-à-vis other forms
of political settlement. This gambit involves Dewey initially reminding
his readers that historical relativity of the state meant examining the
formation of statehood and its evolution in the messy reality of human
history. Detached from an appreciation of history, it is quite easy to read
Dewey’s theory of a state being based on a functional logic of publics
emerging and progressively altering the institutions and practices of
government in response to the changing conditions of culture.
In this schema, the state’s evolution would resemble the progressive
role set out for it in pluralist philosophy, whereby the state neutrally
arbitrated and included the interests of differing publics, who have
similar potential and resources for accessing and modifying the
formation of government and state functions. Contra pluralism’s vision
of the state, however, Dewey pointed out that the very history that
highlighted that states evolved via changes in the cultural matrix and
the rise of publics also brought home the fact that such an evolution
did not necessarily guarantee the ‘propriety or reasonableness’ of the
publics or the political acts, measures or systems which emerged from
such a process (LW2: 254).
For instance, Dewey highlights that the intellectual foundations
(science/political ideologies) of a cultural matrix do not necessarily
provide publics or governments with correct or just perceptions about
Creative Democracy
29
associative behaviour. One has only to think about certain ideologies
and subsequent government policies towards women, immigrants,
non-whites or homosexuals over the eighteenth, nineteenth and
twentieth centuries to see that the observation of the consequences of
associated human behaviour is open to the same error and illusion as
the perception of natural objects. The emergence of a public can also
not be equated with an a priori expression of correctness or justness. As
highlighted above, publics can emerge in response to other publics or
often come into conflict with one another due to incompatible interests.
This process itself can lead to the emergence of illiberal or unreasonable
publics. Again, one has only to look to history to find how illiberal
publics have shaped unjust state formations or even how what we
today would call progressive publics, such as the ones that emerged to
demand the abolition of New World Slavery and women’s suffrage, were
opposed by publics who demanded the status quo or even a heightening
of illiberal practices. As a consequence, Dewey contends that mistaken
prescriptions, based on such false observations or stemming from
the wishes of illiberal publics, can consolidate themselves in laws and
administrative policies of government creating retrogressive rather
than progressive consequences (LW2: 254).
The historical evidence that culture could facilitate incorrect
perceptions of associative behaviour or even invoke illiberal publics
served to underline for Dewey that publics have rarely been of equal
standing in a society. The historical relativity of the state’s form revealed
not only that other social groups precede the state, but that the state
always exists as a ‘distinctive and restricted social interest’– an agency
whose form and functions are set up to meet the demands and protect
the interests of specific publics within specific cultures at specific
junctures in history (LW2: 253–4). For example, although states are
brought into existence via the emergence of a public there are often
other publics who are excluded from forming government in the very
act of founding a state.
This process itself normally reflects socially stratified relations
between groups within society at that juncture in history. And whilst
30
John Dewey
the parameters of such social stratification may shift over time due to
shifts in power, for example from heredity and lineage to economic class,
the power and prestige of government is nearly always held in esteem
by dominant groups. Thus, Dewey suggests that the primary task for
any public is to achieve such recognition of itself across wider society
to give weight to its attempts to modify government and associative
behaviour in its interests (LW2: 283). The ability to gain access to the
privileges of government has therefore often been distributed through
birth into a dominant class, caste, race or gender rather than an ability to
govern (LW2: 254, 283–4).15 This has created circumstances throughout
history, where various publics and their interests have found themselves
excluded, often unjustly and to their detriment, from the very process
of the state being rediscovered and remade.
Moreover, Dewey suggests that well-institutionalized states and
their incumbent governments, which reflect the interests and often
contain members of previous publics, have historically hindered the
process of the remaking of the state. This transpires because the needs
of newly formed publics often challenge the moral values or interests
of the previous public(s) that have shaped the present state and its
government. Subsequently, well-institutionalized incumbent states and
their governments have historically used the institutions and practice
of government to counteract, discredit or suppress the rival interests
of new publics. This expulsion of new publics from partaking in the
remaking of the state and government has, Dewey contends, often been
the catalyst for violent revolution:
The new public which is generated remains long inchoate, unorganized,
because it cannot use inherited political agencies. The latter, if elaborate
and well institutionalized, obstruct the organization of the new public.
They prevent that development of new forms of the state which might
grow up rapidly were social life more fluid, less precipitated into
set political and legal molds. To form itself, the public has to break
existing political forms. This is hard to do because these forms are
themselves the regular means of instituting change. The public which
generated political forms is passing away, but the power and the lust of
Creative Democracy
31
possession remains in the hands of the officers and agencies which the
dying publics instituted. This is why the change of the form of states is
so often effected only by revolution. (LW2: 254–5)
What is of pertinence here is Dewey’s belief that the historical relativity
of culture and the emergence of new publics translate into a situation
where a society is always in a process of transition and hence potential
moral conflict. This conflict between the needs of old experience and of
new experience, what we often refer to as social problems, is inherently
a moral conflict because it concerns what should be within a society.
Such conflicts, brought about by the events of a shifting cultural matrix,
inherently question the values, principles and ends and corresponding
social institutions (practices and institutions of government) that should
exist at that specific historical juncture (LW13: 151, 184, cf. LW11: 36–7).
All societies, in some form, thus have to come face to face with
the dilemma of integrating potentially conflicting moralities of old
experience and new experience (Dewey, LW11: 36). However, as the
prior notation of the historic propensity of violent revolution makes
clear, striking the balance between (or even contemplating integrating
the old and the new) has typically been beyond the political wit of
humanity. Moreover, Dewey believed that the dilemma of integrating
potentially conflicting moralities of old experience and new experience
had led some into a belief in the necessity of violent coercive revolution
(LW11: 41, 56–61, cf. LW14: 113). On this basis, Dewey concludes that
the fundamental problem of political settlement in any society revolves
around the question of how to manage social change and mediate
potential moral conflict between the old and new experience without
the necessity of coercive or violent politics.16
Making the case for democracy as a way of life
Rallying against democratic realism’s caricature of democracy as merely
being a set of defunct institutions, whose failings are only outweighed
by the erroneous belief in their ability to succeed in the first place,
32
John Dewey
Dewey puts forward democracy as the answer to the problem of how to
manage societal change and mediate its potential moral conflicts without
recourse to coercive or violent politics. In making such a statement,
Dewey begins his attempt at deepening, clarifying and ultimately
reconstructing the idea of democracy. Although acknowledging the
embodiment of the concept in popular suffrage and elected officials,
what we commonly call ‘political democracy’, Dewey contends that
the idea of democracy must be separated from its external organs and
structure. To reduce democracy to specific institutions or practices is
quite simply to miss the fact that democracy is inherently something
‘broader and deeper’ than such institutions (LW2: 325, cf. LW11: 217
and LW7: 349). This broader and deeper meaning revolves around
viewing democracy as the best method for establishing and maintaining
a society’s sense of community. And as we shall see, Dewey sees the
establishment of community through democracy as paramount to
peacefully managing moral conflict as it emerges throughout history
(LW11: 56, 182, cf. LW7: 329).17
Dewey’s reconstructed meaning of democracy is principally
exemplified in his demarcation between democracy as a ‘way of life’ and
‘political democracy’ as a system of government (LW11: 217, cf. LW2:
325 and LW14: 226). The key to understanding Dewey’s conception of
democracy as a method for dealing with social change and moral conflict
centres around viewing the former as providing the ethical mandate for
the constant renewal of the institutions and practices of the latter (LW2:
325, cf. LW11: 182, 218). In its simplest expression, democracy as a way
of life represents for Dewey the expression of the democratic ideal or
idea (LW7: 348–9, cf. LW2: 327).18 Underpinned by the Lincolnesque
belief that no human is wise enough to rule others without their consent,
democracy as a ‘way of life’ is premised on the necessity for the equal
‘participation of every mature being in the formation of the values that
regulate the living of men together’ (LW11: 217–18, cf. LW13: 294).
The values in question here are the moral values (principles, ends) that
justify and inform the social institutions (habits/customs/institutions
of the cultural matrix) that influence how individuals both act and
Creative Democracy
33
relate towards themselves and one another. Within these parameters,
democracy as a way of life is best seen as an ethical commitment to
the principle that those who are affected by social institutions should
have a certain share in the production and management of those
institutions through contributing to the formation of social policy
(proposed reforms of social institutions). Dewey describes this ethical
commitment as:
… the opportunity, the right and the duty of every individual to form
some conviction and to express some conviction regarding his own
place in the social order, and the relations of that social order to his
own welfare; second, the fact that each individual counts as one and
one only on an equality with others, so that the final social will comes
about as the cooperative expression of the ideas of many people.
(LW13: 295–6).
What is worth noting here is that such an ethical commitment operates
on a balanced notion of an equality of participation and communication
in the formation of social policy. On one hand, each individual or a
group of like-minded individuals who have grouped together (publics)
is taken to be equally affected in quality, if not in quantity, by the social
institutions under which they live. All individuals or groups of likeminded individuals, regardless of any native (sex) or artificial (race,
class, intelligence, political beliefs) endowments, should subsequently
have the chance and opportunity to communicate their own conception
of moral value. This fundamentally entails an equality of opportunity
to express their own needs and desires, their conceptions of how social
life should go on and how the social problems they perceive to exist can
be solved via reforming social policy. In short, all individuals or groups
should have an equality of opportunity to have their moral values
solicited and potentially registered in social policy, so as to secure the
social institutions that they believe will bring about the full development
of their capacities as individuals (LW11: 219–20, cf. LW7: 349–50).
On the other hand, however, this equality of opportunity to contribute
to the formation of social policy is balanced by the recognition of the
34
John Dewey
aforementioned social nature of morality. As Dewey points out, ‘…capacity
to endure publicity and communication is the test by which it is decided
whether a pretended good is spurious or genuine. Communication,
sharing, joint participation are the only actual ways of universalizing
the moral law and end’ (MW12: 197). The drive for the solicitation and
registration of individual or group morality in social policy must always
be refracted through the knowledge that such policy will affect and have
consequences for ‘other’ individuals or groups within society, who in all
likelihood, due to stratification and different interests engendered by the
contours of culture, may share different or competing moral standpoints.
The equality of opportunity to express moral value is therefore always
used to facilitate the ‘mutual conference and consultation’ between those
groups or individuals who hold differing or competing conceptions of
moral value. The overall aim of such mutual conference and consultation
is a form of collective problem-solving, where members of society cooperatively collaborate in the appraisal and forming of new social policy
in regard to mediating moral conflicts.19
In essence, then, the balanced equality of democracy as a way of life
and its focus on collective problem-solving highlights Dewey’s faith in
a deliberative (conference, consultation, negotiation and persuasion)
form of political settlement – a process which, Dewey believed, would
allow moral conflicts and the resultant social policy decisions to
be settled in the ‘widest possible contribution of all – or at least the
great majority’ (LW: 56). However, this deliberative form of political
settlement is only able to deal competently with moral conflict both
synchronically and diachronically, argues Dewey, because democracy
as a way of life facilitates the establishment and maintenance of a
society’s community.
As detailed earlier, just as atoms, stellar masses and cells behave in
the natural world, Dewey states that humans within a society directly
and unconsciously combine in associated behaviour. Such associated
behaviour needs no explanation or meaning; it is simply the way
things are structured by culture. The attempt to provide explanation
or meaning to associative behaviour and its consequences is for Dewey
Creative Democracy
35
based on communication, whereby symbols or signs are produced
about such associative behaviour and its consequences. The creation
of symbols and signs or what we call a common language is thus
exactly what publics do when they offer their narrations of associated
behaviour and its consequences to wider society. The pivotal point
here is that such a process, whereby explanation or meaning is given to
associative behaviour and its consequences and then communicated to
others, is for Dewey the move towards the establishment of community
(LW13: 176).
A community thus represents an order of energies transmuted into
one of meanings which are appreciated and mutually referred by each
to every other on the part of those engaged in combined action. ‘Force’
is not eliminated but is transformed in uses and direction by ideas and
sentiments made possible by means and symbols. (LW2: 331)
On this basis, Dewey takes the form of community invoked by
democracy as a way of life, what we call the democratic community, to
be the best means to deal with moral conflict and social problems on
both synchronic and diachronic levels. Dewey’s idea of the democratic
community does not so much do away with moral conflict, which itself
is an impossibility, but looks to mediate conflict and avoid violence
through facilitating the communicative inclusion of all publics. This is
quite simply because the ethical commitment of democracy as a way of
life translates into the perpetual maintenance of a community, whereby
everyone is afforded an equal opportunity to express moral value and
potentially, through deliberation, have that moral value embodied in
social policy.
On a synchronic level, as we have seen, due to stratification and the
clash of interests that regularly occur between old and new publics,
historically new publics have often been cut out of the process of
remaking the state and have had to resort to violent revolution to
achieve their objectives. Within the remit of the ethical commitment of
democracy as a way of life, however, all individuals and groups possess
the right to express their moral value. Dewey subsequently believed
that the movement towards the necessity of violence to facilitate the
36
John Dewey
changing of the state is largely eradicated under democracy as a way of
life because such an ethical commitment aimed:
… to bring these conflicts out into the open where their special claims
can be seen and appraised, and where they can be discussed and judged
in the light of more inclusive interests than are represented by either
of them separately … The more the respective claims of the two are
publicly and scientifically weighed, the more likely it is that the public
interest will be disclosed and be made effective. (LW11: 56)
The democratic way of life and its democratic community also shed
light upon Dewey’s hopes for a diachronic form of deliberative and cooperative problem-solving to mediate the moral conflicts which are
‘bound to arise’ in society (LW14: 227–8). Under the tenets of democracy
as a way of life, the problematic of facilitating the participation of every
mature being in the formation of the values that inform a society’s
social institutions is never deemed to be permanently solvable, but
rather considered a challenge whose demands change across time and
space. This is because the ethical commitment that all members of a
society will have the chance to voice their moral value and have the
potential to inform social policy recognizes the historical relativity of
culture and publics – a process where all forms of moral value espoused
by new publics, across time and space, would always possess the right
to be heard and be deliberated and, if sufficient evidence of its merit
emerged, the chance of ultimately changing social policy (LW7: 350).
At the heart of the democratic way of life and its sense of community
thus beats an educative rhythm, which looks to ensure a perpetual
equality of communication and co-operative problem-solving as social
conditions and conceptions of moral value shift throughout history.20
Democracy as a way of life + political democracy =
creative democracy
The question that now remains, however, is how does Dewey’s
conception of democracy as a way of life relate to what we commonly
Creative Democracy
37
call political democracy as a system of government? What should be
clear from the preceding discussion is Dewey’s belief that democracy as
a way of life and its sense of community provides the respective ethical
and deliberative foundations for the mediation of conflict via facilitating
the co-operative reform and remaking of social institutions in response
to changing contours of culture and the rise and fall of publics. The
interesting point here is that Dewey conceives that democracy as a way
of life is not just about political democracy but about the perpetual
participation of every mature being in the formation of the values of
the social institutions under which they live. As such, Dewey believes
that the justification and purpose of the institutions and practices of
political democracy are also bound to the democratic way of life.
On one hand, Dewey asserts that the institutions and practices of
political democracy should always endeavour to further the pursuit
of democracy as a way of life. This means that the institutions and
practices of political democracy should endeavour to facilitate the
evolution of other social institutions to mediate the changes in
culture and conflict between old and new experience. To this end,
Dewey contends that the institutions and practices that we commonly
associate with political democracy, such as universal suffrage, recurring
elections, responsibility of those who are in political power to the voters
and the freedom of speech, inquiry and assembly, are the means which
have been most expedient at various historical junctures towards the
pursuit of the ethical commitment of democracy as a way of life and
the upholding of a democratic community (LW11: 218). This is because
such institutions and practices of political democracy, through their
commitment to equality of discussion, consultation and publicity, are
premised on the uncovering and communicating of social needs and
troubles and hence facilitate both the ethical mandate of democracy
as a way of life and the collective solving of such problems (LW2: 364).
On the other hand, however, the institutions and practices of
political democracy are themselves simply social institutions. They are
not the final ends or values of democracy as a way of life but rather the
mechanisms towards the ‘effective operation’ of the ideal (LW2: 325).
38
John Dewey
Against the trend of what he saw as the quasi-religious idealization
of political democracy’s institutions and practices and other social
institutions in general, Dewey argues that we must not see democracy as
being ‘fixed in its outwards manifestation’ (LW11: 182). The institutions
and practices of political democracy are not beyond criticism or
innovation themselves and are to be appraised on how far they, and
the consequences they produce, contribute to the effective operation
of the democratic ideal (LW11: 218). For instance, the emergence of
moral conflict and the pursuit of deliberatively solving such a problem
may uncover that an institution or practice of political democracy is
unfit or unsuited to meet the demands of facilitating the democratic
way of life in the current contours of culture. Consequently, such
defunct institutions and practices of political democracy, just like other
social institutions, must be adapted or updated, through deliberative
problem-solving, to meet the needs, problems and the conditions of
the contemporary configuration of culture (LW11: 182, cf. LW13: 299).
The linkage between democracy as a way of life and political
democracy brings home Dewey’s conception of ‘creative democracy’.21
Creative democracy is simply shorthand for the working link between
the democratic ideal and its outward manifestation in social institutions.
For democracy as a way of life is not so much to be statically handed
down across generations, argues Dewey, but rather to be inherited and
creatively interpreted and enacted anew by each generation and its
various publics in regard to their present:
The very idea of democracy, the meaning of democracy, must be
continually explored afresh; it has to be constantly discovered,
and rediscovered, remade and reorganized; while the political and
economic institutions and social institutions in which it is embodied
have to be remade and reorganized to meet the changes that are going
on in the development of new needs on the part of human beings and
the new resources for satisfying these needs. (LW11: 182)
Dewey concludes that creative democracy, where the democratic ideal is
used to structure the evolution of social institutions through mediating
Creative Democracy
39
the conflict of publics, was the only way to master the changes in social
reality both that are already here and that are destined to come forth.
Indeed, Dewey saw his approach to democracy as not only potentially
radical and revolutionary, but also socially cohesive because of its
refusal to ground violence and bloodshed as first principles in the act
of being radical and revolutionary. To borrow the words of Dewey’s
friend and intellectual collaborator George Herbert Mead (1915),
this conception of the democratic community was nothing short of
the ‘institutionalizing of revolution’. This is the sense in which Dewey
(LW11: 296) suggests, contra its critics, that ‘democracy is radical’ and
that the ‘cure for the ills of democracy is more democracy’ (LW2: 325).
Taking in his immediate context, Dewey warned that the choice
between creative democracy and other forms of political settlement
was stark. He argued that any attempt to merely stand still and not deal
with an ever-shifting social reality and ever-changing publics – whether
this be through an uncreative and static democracy, a Third Reich,
communist utopia or reformulation of philosopher kings as experts –
would likely place humanity on the road to extinction. Moreover, as
we shall explore in the next chapter, Dewey believed that creative
democracy was needed not just within the nation state but beyond and
between the nation states of the globe. This was because the violence
of revolution had itself been revolutionized, whereby humanity now
possessed the unprecedented ability to be the authors of its own
collective destruction.
2
The Global Democrat
The new era of human relationships in which we live is one marked
by mass production for remote markets, by cable and telephone, by
cheap printing, by railway and steam navigation. Only geographically
did Columbus discover a new world. The actual new world has been
generated in the last hundred years. (LW2: 323)
As the last chapter made clear, John Dewey’s conception of creative
democracy points towards the perpetual adaption of social institutions,
including democratic institutions and practices themselves, as new
publics are engendered by social change. In this chapter, I aim to
highlight how Dewey’s conception of creative democracy was also
informed by what he took to be the global interdependence of the
Great Society. This centres on how Dewey believed that creative
democracy needed to be exercised not only within America, but also
outside and between nation states and the various publics engendered
and scattered across the globe by what we have come to call the First
Great Globalization. To achieve this, the chapter will consist of three
sections. The first section highlights the globalized nature of the
Great Society by showing how such a time period has today become
known as the ‘First Great Globalization’. The second section focuses
not only on how Dewey acknowledged the global dimensions of the
Great Society but also on why he was compelled to propound the
need for global democracy. The final part of the chapter outlines
Dewey’s concrete ideas about what global democracy would look like
in reality.
42
John Dewey
The Great Society as the First Great Globalization
Pragmatist scholars often fail to recognize that Dewey saw the Great
Society as more than the radical transformation of the American nation
state from an agrarian to a corporate capitalist society.1 He also saw it as
the concomitant radical transformation of the global economy that took
place during what has become known as ‘the long nineteenth century’
(1815–1914). What exactly, then, was this great transformation? Prior
to the nineteenth century, there existed a well-defined intercontinental
trade system that linked Europe, Asia and the Atlantic colonies of
European empires (Findlay and O’Rourke 2007: 365). This had seen
world trade grow at 1 per cent per year during the seventeenth and
eighteenth centuries. However, as writers such as Frieden (2006), Findlay
and O’Rourke (2007) and Rodrik (2011) point out, the long nineteenth
century saw the radical transformation of global trade and finance. The
transformation of the global economy that took place during the long
nineteenth century is now taken to be ‘The First Great Globalization’.2
The First Great Globalization was driven by historical factors such
as the industrial revolution and its new forms of travel (steamships,
railways) and communications technology (wireless telegraphs
and telephones) that reduced inefficiency and the transaction costs
of world trade. Factors such as the hegemonic ascent of free trade
ideas as espoused by Smith and Ricardo; the subjection of national
macroeconomics to the priorities of the international monetary system
of the gold standard; the economic hegemon’s (Britain) embrace and
upholding of the gold standard; free trade and the consequent export
of investment capital by the City of London; the global migration from
the Old World to the New World; and European imperialism and the
opening up of Asia to free trade combined to create the first genuine
integrated world economy. The First Great Globalization thus translated
into a scenario in which:
… the world economy was essentially open to the movement of people,
money, capital and goods. The leading businessmen, politicians,
and thinkers of the day regarded an open world economy as the
The Global Democrat
43
normal state of affairs. They assumed that people and money would
flow around the world with few or no restrictions. Trade protection,
although common, was seen as an acceptable departure from the
norm, driven by the exigencies of short-term domestic or international
politics. Capitalism was global, and the globe was capitalist. (Frieden
2006: 29)
By the mid-nineteenth century, the onset of the First Great Globalization
saw world trade grow at a rate of 4 per cent per year for the rest of the
century (Rodrik 2011: 24–5). By 1913, every country in Western Europe,
bar Spain and Portugal, had industrialized and such developments also
took place in countries such as Argentina and Japan. Moreover, a global
economic regime emerged across what we today call asymmetric global
North and South relations. In this global division of labour, the rich
and industrial North, normally under a regime of formal or informal
imperialism, exported industrial products in exchange for the primary
commodity exports of the poor and largely agricultural South (Findlay
and O’Rourke 2007: 402–7, 412–15). Writing in 1919, and over what
he perceived as the burning embers of such an order, John Maynard
Keynes provides a wonderfully colourful first-hand account of what is
meant by the First Great Globalization:
What an extraordinary episode in the economic progress of man that
age was which came to an end in August 1914 … The inhabitant of
London could order by telephone, sipping his morning tea in bed,
the various products of the whole earth, in such quantity as he might
see fit, and reasonably expect their early delivery upon his doorstep;
he could at the same moment and by the same means adventure his
wealth in the natural resources and new enterprises of any quarter
of the world, and share, without exertion or even trouble, in their
prospective fruits and advantages; or he could decide to couple the
security of his fortunes with the good faith of the townspeople of any
substantial municipality in any continent that fancy or information
might recommend … But, most important of all, he regarded this state
of affairs as normal, certain, and permanent, except in the direction
of further improvement, and any deviation from it as aberrant,
scandalous, and avoidable. The projects and politics of militarism
44
John Dewey
and imperialism, of racial and cultural rivalries, of monopolies,
restrictions, and exclusion, which were to play the serpent to this
paradise, were little more than the amusements of his daily newspaper,
and appeared to exercise almost no influence at all on the ordinary
course of social and economic life, the internationalization of which
was nearly complete in practice. (Keynes 1919: 6–7)
As Keynes alludes to above, the long nineteenth century and its
globalization was eventually brought to a shuddering halt by the
outbreak of the First World War and the rise of trade protectionism
that arose from such a global conflict. The period after the war is
commonly held to be a period of ‘de-globalization’ with the onset of
1920s hyperinflation, the Great Depression, trade protectionism and
xenophobic nationalism, seeing the world economy split into autarkic
economic blocs (Findlay and O’Rourke 2007).3 However, the evocation
of the term ‘de-globalization’ is slightly misleading as it misses the
foolish attempt, between 1925 and 1929, of the developed powers such
as Great Britain and the United States to restore the world economy
through the re-establishment of the gold standard.4 As such, even after
the war, and in the midst of some trade protectionism and the project
of rebuilding Europe, the world’s industrial production grew by more
than a fifth between 1925 and 1929. And with the rise of Americanstyle mass production and mass consumption, exports swelled to
double pre-war levels and world trade became 42 per cent greater in
1929 than in 1913.
This boom was primarily created by the rise of American economic
hegemony and Wall Street’s usurpation of the City of London as the
world’s financial centre. Although the United States rejected Britain’s
political engagement and formal imperialistic underpinning of the
long nineteenth century, the rise of American investment capital,
taking over from the role of European investment capital, saw over
£1 billion a year in loans emanating from New York to foreign
destinations between 1919 and 1929. Between 1924 and 1928, America
lent on average $500 million per year to Europe, $300 million per year
to Latin America, $200 million per year to Canada and $100 million
The Global Democrat
45
per year to Asia. In tandem, American industrialists and corporations
also scoured the globe for foreign direct investment in plants and other
ventures. Over the 1920s, American firms invested some $5 billion
overseas and saw the rise of multinational corporations such as Ford
and General Motors (GM), who became well established in major and
minor economies across the globe, and the internationalization of the
activities of American commercial banks (Frieden 2006: 140–1, 160–1).
Despite this global economic integration, the reality was that
the United States during this period embraced forms of political
isolationism in comparison to the international political ‘conductor’
Great Britain had been when she was the world’s pre-eminent economic
power. This, of course, was all to lead into the void of the Great
Depression and the spread of autarky and ultranationalism. However,
the key point is that the ideals of the long nineteenth century and the
First Great Globalization still cast a large shadow over the activities
of not only America but also the globe post-1914. The question this
book seeks to answer is how the casting of such a shadow appeared to
John Dewey. As I discuss later, Dewey fully understood that the Great
Society was inherently both a national and an international creature.
Dewey’s plea for a global Great Community
By 1927, when Dewey wrote The Public and Its Problems, he was aware
that the First Great Globalization was heavily linked to the problems
of publics and the practice of creative democracy within what he
called the Great Society. The conception of the Great Society in The
Public and Its Problems encompasses not only the great transformation
of American life but also the global interdependence created by the
First Great Globalization. Unfortunately, Deweyan scholars rarely
take the global dimensions of the Great Society seriously enough.5 As
a result, what is often missed is how the global dimensions of the Great
Society fundamentally informed Dewey’s conception of the praxis
of creative democracy. Moreover, if read with this understanding
46
John Dewey
in mind, Dewey’s political writings from the 1920s onwards can be
seen as untangling two intertwined threads concerning the pursuit
of democracy as a way of life and the practice of creative democracy
within the Great Society.
The first thread, which has been covered by some authors such
as Westbrook (1991) and Kadlec (2007), but which has been largely
marginalized in other appraisals of Dewey’s work, concerns the effects
of the Great Society, the rise of democratic realism and the need for
democracy as a way of life within America. Nevertheless, Dewey was
also aware that much of the complexity and stratification he associated
with American corporate capitalism and what he took as the Great
Society were engendered by developments of the global economy
and the relations between nation states. The second thread, which is
even more marginalized than the first in accounts of Dewey’s work,
recognizes the Great Society not only as an American phenomena but
as a state of affairs engendered by what we today call the First Great
Globalization and establishes the need for creative democracy at the
international level:
It can be confidently affirmed that every aspect, content, structure
and phase of human life has been radically changed, directly or
indirectly, for weal or woe, by proliferating and accelerating industrialtechnological revolutions. For example: they have changed the
structure of family life, the status of women, the relations of the sexes,
of parents and children; education has been changed in every respect,
quantitatively and qualitatively; vast populations have been urbanized,
imposing new occupations and new ways of life; transportation and
communication have been revolutionized, with incalculable human
consequences; intra-national and international relations, friendly
and hostile, cooperative and competitive have been multiplied and
intensified; local and world-wide class and race problems have been
generated or exacerbated. (LW1: 358)
In The Public and Its Problems, Dewey summed this state of affairs
up as a ‘new era of human relationships’ (LW2: 323).6 Not only did
Dewey recognize such unprecedented economic interdependence in
The Global Democrat
47
and between nation states as the greatest change in human history,
but also that such change now created forms of associated behaviour
and consequences of associated behaviour that spanned national and
continental boundaries. Hence, Dewey believed that the irony of the
nineteenth and early twentieth century was that the ‘ … consolation
of peoples in enclosed, nominally independent, national states has its
counterpart in the fact that their acts affect groups and individuals in
other states all over the world’ (LW2: 315, cf. LW13: 190).
In The Public and Its Problems, the most striking exemplar of the
global nature of the Great Society provided by Dewey is the First World
War and its aftermath. Dewey begins by highlighting how the war
itself was truly global with the involvement of ‘every continent upon
the globe’. Colonial possessions were drawn in, self-governing nations
entered voluntarily and countries with racial and cultural differences,
such as Great Britain and Japan and Germany and Turkey, formed
alliances. However, the global nature of the conflict aside, Dewey took
the First World War to reveal the interdependence of countries in the
Great Society and that the consequences of associated behaviour often
did not respect national borders. For instance, Dewey highlights how
the breakdown of world trade during the war saw a consequent scramble
by the belligerents to secure commodities such as raw materials, distant
economic markets and foreign capital, which had previously been in
abundance due to economic interdependence prior to the war (LW2:
314–17).
At the same time, Dewey saw that the breakdown of such global
economic relations created consequences for the everyday life of
people across the globe. For example, American farmers, who had
experienced temporary prosperity through the increase in demand
for agricultural products during the war, saw their economic outlook
become bleak when the consequences of the establishment of peace
(war debts, the centralization of gold reserves in the United States,
depreciations of foreign currencies) meant that wartime levels of export
demand declined and failed to return to pre-war levels. Dewey fully
acknowledged that the misfortune of American farmers was relatively
48
John Dewey
insignificant in comparison with the other consequences of peace, such
as the hyperinflation in Germany and the stimulation of European
nationalisms, but it revealed how day-to-day life in one region of the
world was now fundamentally linked to, and affected by, the behaviour
of others on the far side of the world (LW2: 316).
In essence, the First World War vividly brought home for Dewey
how the interdependence of nation states in the Great Society meant
the consequences of associative behaviour now spanned across borders.
Rather than being a matter of sheer empirical description, however,
Dewey found that the case of the American farmer illustrated how little
‘prevision and regulation’ of such transcontinental interdependence
actually existed and how people had as much control over such events
as they had over the vicissitudes of the climate (LW2: 316). In 1927,
then, the political conclusion he drew from the global nature of the
Great Society and the World War it had helped to facilitate was how the
existing political and legal institutions and practices were incapable of
dealing with the current situation. Contrasting his present with that of
Pax Romana, Dewey contended that:
There was a critical epoch in the history of the world when the Roman
Empire assembled in itself the lands and peoples of the Mediterranean
basin. The World War stands out as an indubitable proof that what then
happened for a region has now happened for the world, only there is
now no comprehensive political organization to include the various
divided yet interdependent countries. Any one who even partially
visualizes the scene has a convincing reminder of the meaning of the
Great Society: that it exists, and that it is not integrated. (LW2: 315)
Dewey was all too aware that the reality of globalization now
required reform of government that would allow for transnational
communication and collaboration and global forms of democratic
government. The Great Society needed to become a Great Community
which could perfect ‘ … the means and ways of communication of
meanings so that genuinely shared interests in the consequences of
interdependent activities may inform desire and effort and thereby
direct action’ (LW2 332, cf. 314, 327).
The Global Democrat
49
One can find the same sustained, if not ever-growing, conviction
that the Great Society was engendered by modern globalization and
lacked political regulation at the international level when one reads
elements of Dewey’s work through the Great Depression and the rise
of trade protectionism, the build-up to the Second World War and
in the aftermath of the defeat of the Axis Powers.7 The intervening
years made it clear for Dewey that without a common rule of law and
a machinery of government at the international level to manage the
effects of the Great Society, the only way nation states knew or sought to
deal with the effects of such globalization was economic (autarky, trade
protectionism) or military form of warfare (LW11: 261–2).
The fait accompli that was the Second World War highlighted for
Dewey the ‘ … futility of all thinking, planning and practical effort
that is not global in reach’ (LW17: 545). Writing in 1944, Dewey
outlined again that the Great Society was engendered by the First Great
Globalization and had created an interdependent world:
Commerce, industry, growth of the means of communication between
countries physically far apart, did in fact produce interdependence. As
Mr. Willkie recently reminded us, we now live in what to all intents
and purposes is One World. Distance, the isolating and divisive power
of the seas and vast spaces, has been overcome. Steamship and ocean
cables began a work which radio and airplane have carried through.
For good or bad, we are now and henceforth more like close neighbors
in a crowded city than like the widely separate peoples in which our
grandparents carried on their affairs in government and industry.
(LW17: 453)8
Dewey now identified the biggest problem facing the emergence of the
Great Community to be the fact that our political beliefs and standards
had fallen out of synch with reality. The First Great Globalization had
not only brought about physical interdependence across the globe
but also engendered a raft of ideas about the teleological advance
of democracy, peace and prosperity across the globe. The mistake,
Dewey argued, was not the embrace of physical interdependence but
the mistaken belief that the breaking down of ‘ … physical barriers,
50
John Dewey
the mere bringing of peoples together into physical contact, would
automatically create moral unification’ (LW17: 453–4). Humanity was
now literally stuck in between ‘two worlds’ where its political ideas did
not match its physical realities:
One does not have to argue to prove the existence of global physical
conditions. It is enough to point to the war in which this country along
with almost every country of the globe is engaged. But the fact that it
is war which provides the evidence is also proof of absence of moral
unification. It points to the nature of the scope, the immensity and the
intensity, of the task which lies ahead of us. It points to the futility of
all thinking, planning and practical effort that is not global in reach. As
yet these things are still largely local, provincial. Politically, our beliefs
and standards are nationalistic, not global. (LW17: 454–5)
After the Second World War, Dewey strengthened this line of
argument by adding that the war highlighted that the old traditions,
customs, habits of belief and institutions of ‘old-time diplomacy, power
blocs, power politics and precepts of international law’ were now as
‘outworn and impotent as the old-time muzzle-loading gun’ in dealing
with the transnational reality of the Great Society. Dewey argued that
a world with such interdependence, lacking the means to deal with
the effects of such interdependence short of forms of warfare, was
essentially a form of ‘anarchy’. It was now the ‘tragedy of our time’
that every person on the planet belonged to a ‘world unit’ which did
not possess a common rule of law and a machinery of government at
the international level to manage the international effects of the Great
Society (LW15: 204). As such, Dewey declared that:
… the responsibility now placed upon us is that of creating the
intellectual and moral attitudes that will support institutions,
international and domestic, political, educational and cultural, that
correspond to the physical revolution which has taken place; and
whose consequences are so largely negative just because of the absence
of corresponding institutional change. (LW17: 456)9
This fact became all the more poignant in the light of the unprecedented
destructiveness of the Second World War and the rise of atomic age,
The Global Democrat
51
which now handed humanity the ability to seemingly wipe itself out of
existence (LW1: 358; LW15: 199–202)
Global creative democracy
What, then, of Dewey’s concrete ideas about how global democracy
could provide governance of the Great Society and how did he think
it could be brought into being? Dewey never explained his plans for
what such global democracy would look like in a systematic way.
Indeed, given his conception of publics amending social institutions in
reaction to change and its consequences, such overarching blueprints
of global democracy would be somewhat antithetical to Dewey’s own
idea of creative democracy. However, Dewey as a citizen and public
intellectual was also part of publics throughout his life, and his own
views of what creative democracy at the global level would look can be
teased out from his writings on international affairs. These references
to global democracy were not just taken by Dewey as being mere
flights of political fancy but based on concrete possibilities in the
present.
Dewey’s approach to global democracy is essentially two-pronged: it
deals with relations between nation states and publics in, and between,
those national populations. In the first instance, Dewey’s writings in the
aftermath of the destruction left by the First World War highlight his
belief that the old order of international liberal capitalism, underwritten
by imperialism and asymmetric global North/South relations, could
be replaced if humanity realized that it was democracy ‘for which we
are fighting’ (MW11: 98–106). Writing in 1918, Dewey argued that
peace now brought new problems for social regulation between nation
states such as the distribution of labour, immigration and production
for export. To subsequently ‘ … annihilate or reduce the agencies of
international regulation which already exist …’, instead of stabilizing
and expanding their scope, Dewey argued, would therefore be ‘almost
incredible stupidity’ (MW11: 130). The world now faced the choice
52
John Dewey
between a return to the status quo of imperialistic rivalry and a new form
of global democracy through new institutions of global governance:
While one can say here as in the case of international relations that
a more highly organized world is bound to result, one cannot with
assurance say which of the two types of organization is going to
prevail. But it is reasonably sure that the solution in one sphere will be
congruous with that wrought out in the other. Governmental capitalism
will stimulate and be stimulated by the formation of a few large
imperialistic organizations which must resort to armament for each to
maintain its place within a precarious balance of powers. A federated
concert of nations, on the other hand, with appropriate agencies of
legislation, judicial procedure and administrative commissions would
so relax tension between states as to encourage voluntary groupings all
over the world, and thus promote social integration by means of the
cooperation of democratically self-governed industrial and vocational
groups. (MW11: 105)
Dewey furthered this idea of a new form of global democratic
government when he turned his attention to the newly founded League
of Nations. In 1918, Dewey saw the League of Nations as a chance to
‘end international anarchy’ through an embracement of a new form
of ‘diplomacy’, which would displace the elite and aristocratic style of
‘old diplomacy’ (M11: 132). Despite his eventual disillusionment with
post-war international politics, Dewey believed that global democracy
required forms of global or international institutions (legislative,
judicial, economic) that could regulate the Great Society. These
institutions would be pivotal to balance the inequality of power smaller
and weaker nations faced from economically and militarily powerful
nations and empires (MW11: 139–42).10
Dewey did, however, augment his embrace of new international
institutions with the notion that to have a ‘safe world for democracy’ and
a world in which democracy was ‘anchored’ required not only a worldfederated government but also the emergence of a ‘variety of freely
experimenting and freely cooperating self-governing local, cultural and
industrial groups’ (MW11: 105). This can be seen as Dewey offering a
The Global Democrat
53
forerunner for ideas of global civil society or the global public sphere.
However, by the 1920s, Dewey pushed this argument about the role of
public even further. The reformation of the international order towards
global democracy was now only possible through both the emergence
of a new global architecture of institutions and the ‘non-political forces
organising themselves to transform existing political structures: that
the divided and troubled publics integrate’ (LW2: 315).
In order to turn the Great Society into the Great Community, Dewey
recognized that the practice of democracy as a way of life needed to be
a transnational endeavour, not only between nation-state leaders but
also between the various publics scattered across the globe. Reform of
democracy between nation states would therefore require transnational
communication and collaboration between the peoples of the world
and formation of publics that would bring about changes that would
bring forth global democracy. This was nothing short of a call for the
global inheritance of democracy as a way of life and the rethinking and
renewal of the practices and institutions of democracy in the face of the
global nature of the Great Society:
The peoples of the Earth, not just their governmental officials, must find
effective answers to the following questions. Is a world-government
possible? How shall it be brought into being? By the unilateral and
coercive action of some or one nation, or by general cooperative action?
What shall be its machinery? What responsibilities shall it possess in
order that a common rule of law, expressing the needs of a worldsociety, may substitute a system of peace and security for the present
war system? These questions are urgent; it is imperative to face them
at once, directly, and with utmost seriousness. They are not matters of
abstract theory but of utmost practical concern. (LW15: 206)
The challenge of ‘discovering and implementing politically areas
of common interest’ between publics and national units in such an
interdependent world was now, Dewey decreed, the new political
‘imperative’ of the twentieth century (LW2: 379). Dewey was himself
buoyed by developments after the Second World War. In the second
preface to The Public and Its Problems, written in 1946, Dewey cited
54
John Dewey
the formation of the United Nations and the opening of debate about
the nature of the organization as evidence that there was a growing
sense ‘ … that relations between nations are taking on properties
that constitute a public and hence call for some measure of political
organisation’. Dewey argued that the debate within nation states as to
what was ‘public’ and what was ‘private’ was being extended into the
context of relations between national units. The formation of the UN
signalled an acceptance by nation states of the political responsibility
that each national unit had towards one another within the Great
Community, as opposed to the weak moral responsibility that so
easily broke down in the 1930s (LW2: 375–6). And in organizations
such as UNESCO Dewey found more evidence that armed conflict
was potentially being usurped as the primary method to deal with the
effects of globalization. Dewey believed that UNESCO offered ‘ … the
peoples of the world a symbol of what is now desirable, and of what
may become an actuality’ (LW16: 400–1). Yet, as we shall examine in
Chapter 3, Dewey’s hope that humanity could live up to meeting the
challenges of the new imperative of the twentieth century was tempered
by what he saw as the eclipse of the public and democracy at home.
3
The Obstacles to Creative Democracy
at Home and Abroad
Only sheer cynicism and defeatism will deny that it is possible to
create a workable world government. There have been times when
the moral ancestors of present day defeatists would have scornfully
declared that a rule of law over a territory anything like as large
as our present United States was impossible. They would have said
that outside of family groups and small neighbourhoods, the custom
of every man’s hand against other men could not be uprooted … If
peoples, especially their rulers, devoted anything like the energy –
physical, intellectual, and moral – that now goes into planning war,
to planning for an enduring peace system, they could achieve world
government. To surrender to defeatism is for intelligence to abdicate.
It is to give up the struggle in a cause in which nothing less than
the destiny of civilization is at stake. It is, however, as necessary to
appreciate the immense difficulty of the undertaking as it is to have
the will to take unreserved part in it. (LW15: 206)
In much the same vein as contemporary advocates of global democracy,
Dewey firmly believed that the nature of globalization meant that
global forms of democracy were necessary to manage the Great Society.
However, Dewey ultimately problematized his own thought when
examining the feasibility of global democracy. Writing just after the end
of the Second World War, Dewey initially counters ‘defeatism’ over the
ability to govern the globe by reminding his readers that it was once
believed that the United States was too big a land mass over which
to create rule of law and democracy. Going further, Dewey suggests
56
John Dewey
that if as much thought was put into global democracy as it had been
for planning war, it would be more than feasible to create a Great
Community and govern the Great Society. However, this optimism
towards the project of global democracy is tempered by Dewey’s belief
that there was an ‘immense difficulty’ in creating global democracy.
The ‘immense difficulty’ in the enacting of global democracy was the
fact that the Great Society had ‘ … invaded and partially disintegrated
the small communities of former times without generating a Great
Community’ (LW2: 314). As a result, Dewey concludes that the
‘ … new age has no symbols consonant with its activities’ and provides
no communication of signs and symbols between citizens who are
involved in national and transnational associations and consequences
engendered by the Great Society. Given the Great Society’s technological
advancement in communications (telephone, wireless telegraph), the
irony of this state of affairs was not lost on Dewey:
The ties which hold men together in action are numerous, tough and
subtle. But they are invisible and intangible. We have the physical
tools of communication as never before. The thoughts and aspirations
congruous with them are not communicated, and hence are not
common…. Our Babel is not one of tongues but of the signs and
symbols without which shared experience is impossible. (LW2: 323–4)
This is why, within The Public and Its Problems, Dewey pleaded for the
‘divided and troubled publics’ across not just America but the world
to integrate in order to create a Great Community that could bring
forth democratic governance at both the national and international
level. And this plea is reiterated again in Dewey’s work during the
Great Depression and in the events that led to the Second World War.
Why, then, did Dewey argue that the publics of the Great Society were
divided and troubled publics? What was stopping the emergence of a
Great Community?
Somewhat expediently, and all too typically in the abstract, Dewey
ends the 1946 essay with the answers to such questions when he
warns that whilst it was imperative to ‘begin’ the path towards global
democracy it was important to recognize that:
The Obstacles to Creative Democracy at Home and Abroad
57
As has been only too proved by the two devastating world wars
the movement toward production of more comprehensive social
organisation, the very movement that brought national states into
being has been widely arrested. (LW15: 209)
When taken with Dewey’s conception of democracy in mind, it becomes
clear that the forestalling of the emergence of a Great Community was
not down to any spatial-temporal limits on the practice of democracy,
but rather resulted from what Dewey saw as the arresting of creative
democracy and the democratic community at the level of the nation
state. The arresting of creative democracy and its ability to update the
practices and institutions of democracy were forestalling the ‘production
of more comprehensive social organization’ not only within the nation
state but also outside the nation state. Of course, this answer itself begs
the questions: What did Dewey take to be the reason for the arresting of
creative democracy within the nation state? And how did this arresting
of creative democracy within the nation state impact on the cause of
global democracy?
The eclipse of the public
The answers Dewey provides to the questions above see him initially
outdo democratic realism at its own game. In superficial agreement
with democratic realism, Dewey argued that it was the complexity of
the Great Society, which had led to the ‘eclipse’ of publics and a sense
of community within nation states and the subsequent arresting
of creative democracy. This had transpired because the Great
Society’s multiplication, intensification and trans-nationalization
of associative behaviour now outstripped the comprehension and
knowledge of average citizens (LW2: 314–17). The age when citizens
could adopt a few general political principles, such as embracing
states’ rights vis-à-vis centralized federal government or free trade
vis-à-vis protectionism, and apply them with confidence through
supporting one political party over another was now essentially
58
John Dewey
over. Citing the example of the problem of industrial tariffs, Dewey
explained,
For the average voter today the tariff question is a complicated medley
of indefinite detail, schedules of rates specific and ad valorem on
countless things, many of which he does not recognize by name, and
with respect to which he can form no judgment. Probably not one
voter in a thousand even reads the scores of pages in which rates of toll
are enumerated and he would not be much wiser if he did. The average
man gives it up as a bad job. (LW2: 317)
Due to the fact that modern industry was ‘too complex and intricate’,
citizens were essentially ‘bewildered’ by the machinations of the Great
Society. Unable to correctly locate where the indirect consequences
that were affecting their daily lives came from, citizens could now not
generate publics who could foster the reform of the social institutions
of the state to control and regulate such consequences:
An inchoate public is capable of organization only when indirect
consequences are perceived, and when it is possible to project agencies
which order their occurrence. At present, many consequences are felt
rather than perceived; they are suffered, but they cannot be said to
be known, for they are not, by those who experience them, referred
to their origins. It goes, then, without saying that agencies are not
established which canalize the streams of social action and thereby
regulate them. Hence the publics are amorphous and unarticulated.
(LW2: 317)
At first glance, one may find Dewey’s account of what he took to be the
eclipse of publics as not too dissimilar to the view of democratic realism.
In fact, Dewey appears to hold the same conviction as Walter Lippmann
when highlighting how the voting public struggled to cope intellectually
with the complex manoeuvrings of the Great Society. However, whilst
both Dewey and democratic realism locate the ‘intelligence’ of the
masses as a key reason for the stuttering of democracy, they radically
differ on what they believe were the reasons for such a state of affairs.
Democratic realism took it to be the case that the masses were a priori
The Obstacles to Creative Democracy at Home and Abroad
59
incapable of ever grasping the contours of the Great Society because it
was too complex and demanded expert rule. Dewey, on the other hand,
saw the lost nature of the public and the collapse of democracy to be
down to wholly contingent reasons that limited the intelligence of the
masses.
Primarily, Dewey identified the limiting of the public’s intelligence
and subsequent eclipse as being a result of the fact that modern liberal
democracy within the Great Society had only achieved ‘bourgeois
democracy’ rather than actual creative democracy. The historic
emergence of liberal democratic governments in the nineteenth
century ‘had been an accompaniment of the transfer of power from
agrarian interests to industrial and commercial interests’. Whilst there
had been a change in the social order, with the rise of democratic
government and the handing of power to industrial and commercial
interests, the ability to ‘ … command the conditions under which the
mass of people have access to the means of production and to the
products of their activity … ’ continued to give ‘power to the few over
the many’. The reality was that in liberal bourgeois democracies, power
lay in the hands of ‘finance capitalism’, no matter the claims of so-called
governments of, by and for all the people. And whilst Dewey freely
admitted that it would be ‘silly’ to deny that there had been great gain
for the masses within liberal democracies, such as qualified suffrage,
freedom of speech, press and assembly, he also viewed it as intellectual
hypocrisy to ‘glorify these gains and give no attention to the brutalities
and inequities, the regimentation and suppression’ which plagued the
system of economic liberalism (LW11: 296–7).
This was no understatement. Although US society in the 1920s
was one of apparent prosperity, it was still marked by severe racist
segregation, economic inequality, regressive income tax, precarious
employment, lack of industrial democracy and a relatively non-existent
welfare state. By the time of the Great Depression, when such material
inequality and the lack of means to deal with such conditions became
even more acute, Dewey lamented that there were now ‘millions of
people who have the minimum of control over the conditions of
60
John Dewey
their own subsistence’ (LW13: 300).1 Yet, as Dewey pointed out, ‘no
economic state of affairs is merely economic’ (LW11: 295). The most
unjust and immoral aspect of such an unequal economic state of affairs
was the role they played in the eclipse of the public and the stunting of
creative democracy:
The same forces which have brought about the forms of democratic
government, general suffrage, executives and legislators chosen by
majority vote, have also brought about conditions which halt the social
and humane ideals that demand the utilization of government as the
genuine instrumentality of an inclusive and fraternally associated
public. (LW2: 303)
The halting of the social and humane ideals Dewey associated with
creative democracy was inherently down to bourgeois democracy
being founded on the idea that laissez-faire capitalism was the true
expression of human liberty. This had arisen, Dewey stressed, because
in the fight against arbitrary government action and for religious
freedom, mid-nineteenth century philosophical branches of liberalism
had identified the ‘immutable truth’ that human liberty was to be found
in the practices of laissez-faire capitalism. In this sense, human nature
and natural law could be said to be fulfilled when liberty was perceived
as the equal right of every individual to conduct economic enterprise
free from government constraint, so long as they broke no law on the
statute books. This, in turn, was said to be socially beneficial because
the activities of self-interested individuals would automatically create
competition that would provide socially needed commodities and
services. Any government intervention that interfered with this form
of liberty was to be taken as an attack on liberty itself. This conception
of liberty, which was presented by eighteenth and nineteenth-century
liberals – from Adam Smith to Mill – as an ‘immutable truth’ across
time and space, was ultimately used by the commercial and industrial
classes to firstly usurp the vested interests of mercantilism and then
serve as the hegemonic justification for bourgeois democracy (LW11:
26–7, cf. LW2: 291–3).2
The Obstacles to Creative Democracy at Home and Abroad
61
Dewey found that the hegemonic perpetuation of the ideal that
laissez-faire capitalism equalled the ‘philosophy of liberty’ had had a
profound impact upon the intelligence of the masses and the subsequent
eclipse of the public. By the 1930s, it was apparent that laissezfaire capitalism and its conception of liberty had delivered extreme
stratification rather than the liberty of all. However, defenders of the
status quo, such as commercial and industrial interests who benefited
from these conditions and philosophies as social Darwinism, argued
that the supposed natural inequalities of individuals in moral and
intellectual make-up not only explained economic inequality but were
the consequences of natural law. Against the failure of those who were
naturally deficient in being innovative, independent and economically
proactive stood the success of those ‘rugged individuals’ who managed
to practise liberty and gain wealth and property (LW11: 286–7).
Defenders of the status quo again argued that any government
intervention interfered with this form of liberty was therefore to be
taken as an attack on liberty itself. Such arguments were indicative to
Dewey of how, within the confines of bourgeois democracy, the very
concept of intelligence itself had fallen under the strictures of laissezfaire capitalism. However, as he reminded his readers, this simply
reflected the failure of modern proponents of liberalism and industrial
and commercial interests to recognize, or admit, that individuals were
formed by the interaction of the human organism with its environment,
and how the current economic regime affected such interaction (LW11:
29–32, 47–8, 286).
In this sense, ‘effective intelligence’ was not an ‘original, innate
endowment’. No matter the differences in native intelligence between
individuals, the reality was that the ‘actuality of mind’ was deposited by
social habits and customs (LW2: 366). Rallying against apologists of both
laissez-faire capitalism and democratic realism, Dewey highlighted how
economic relationships and hegemonic ideals of bourgeois democracy
worked in tandem to limit the access of the masses to information and
educative practices that could bolster their intelligence. The majority
engaged in the production and distribution of economic commodities,
62
John Dewey
argued Dewey, have ‘ … no share – imaginative, intellectual, emotional –
in directing the activities in which they physically participate’ (LW5:
104). The strictures of industrial and economic relations within the
Great Society, such as the mass-production techniques of Fordism,
meant that individuals tended to ‘become cogs in the vast machine
whose workings they do not understand, and in whose management
they have no part or lot in’ (LW11: 252).
However, Dewey’s use of the term ‘cogs’ needs to be clarified
because it does not simply translate into a belief that the masses had
regressed and become less advanced humans in the Great Society. On
the contrary, reflecting on the new habits of knowledge and industry in
1927, for example, Dewey highlighted how present-day citizens could,
due to education and a relative popularizing of science, talk about and
understand science in ways far more complex than their predecessors:
Capacities are limited by the objects and tools at hand. They are still
more dependent upon the prevailing habits of attention and interest
which are set by tradition and institutional customs. Meanings run
in the channels formed by instrumentalities of which, in the end,
language, the vehicle of thought as well of communication, is the
most important. A mechanic can discourse ohms and amperes as Sir
Isaac Newton could not in his day. Many a man who has tinkered with
radios can judge of things which Faraday did not dream of. It is aside
from the point to say that if Newton and Faraday were now here, the
amateur and mechanic would be infants besides them. The retort only
brings out the point: the difference made by different objects to think
of and by different meanings in circulation. A more intelligent state of
social affairs, one more informed with knowledge, more directed by
intelligence, would not improve original endowments one whit, but it
would raise the level upon which the intelligence of all operates. The
height of this level is much more important for judgment of public
concerns than are differences in intelligence quotients. (LW2: 366)
Contra democratic realism, Dewey held that citizens could, through
improving education and media practices and forging a greater
involvement in industry and politics, develop habits that would allow
The Obstacles to Creative Democracy at Home and Abroad
63
them to act more intelligently without necessarily making them
‘omnicompetent’ or improving their native levels of intelligence. The
proof itself was already apparent in the skill and knowledge of the
amateur and mechanic compared to that of Newton and Faraday.
The struggle of masses to adequately judge public matters within the
Great Society transpired because of a lack of habits rather than inability
of the masses to ever master such habits.
Dewey argued that this lack of emphasis on developing the mind
of the masses could also be found in the wider public education
policies of liberal democracies, which failed to provide the masses
with the knowledge they needed in order to make correct judgements
about the nature of the Great Society they inhabited. The public
school system merely reproduced the hegemony of laissez-faire
capitalism and its conception of liberty. For example, between 1929
and 1935, 12 million Americans had reached the employment age
and at least half had not found steady employment as a result of
the Great Depression. What Dewey found equally appalling was how
public education had ill-equipped young people to comprehend the
Great Society and had perpetuated the so-called merits of laissezfaire capitalism:
It is terrible enough that so many youths should have no opportunity to
obtain employment under the conditions set by the present economic
system. It is equally terrible that so many young people should be
refused opportunity in what we call a public educational system, to
find out about the causes of the tragic situation, and, in large measure,
should be indoctrinated in ideas to which the realities about them
give the lie. Confusion and bewilderment are sufficiently rife so that
it is not necessary to add to them a deliberately cultivated blindness.
(LW11: 354)
Added to the intellectual hegemony of stratification, Dewey believed
that technological innovation and subsequent integration into consumer
capitalism also affected the ability of the public to comprehend their
present circumstances. This largely concerned the nature of the new
media technologies and their integration into mass production and
64
John Dewey
mass consumption. Man after all, Dewey contended, was a ‘consuming
and sportive animal as well as a political one’, and the power of ‘bread
and circuses’ to distract citizens from political concerns was nothing
new. But he took the sheer number and variety of modern cheap
consumer products, such as the ‘movie, radio, cheap reading matter and
motor car’, as a wholly unprecedented scenario of political distraction:
In most circles it is hard work to sustain conversation on a political
theme; and once initiated, it is quickly dismissed with a yawn. Let there
be introduced the topic of the mechanism and accomplishment of
various makes of motor cars or the respective merits of actresses, and
the dialogue goes on at a lively pace. The thing to be remembered is
that this cheapened and multiplied access to amusement is the product
of the machine age, intensified by the business tradition which causes
provision of means for an enjoyable passing of time to be one of the
most profitable of occupations. (LW2: 321–2)
Although Dewey did not hold that such modern media technologies
and products had been purposefully created as a culture industry, the
fact that they did not originate in deliberate desire to divert political
interest did not lessen their effectiveness in that direction (LW2: 321).
The use of modern technology and mass-production techniques to
create mass consumer products thus lead to forms of mass consumption
that often distracted citizens from political issues.3
When Dewey examined how new media technologies, such as the
‘telegraph, telephone, radio, cheap and quick mails’, impacted upon the
dissemination of information as ‘news’ to the public, he saw even more
cause for concern. News, as Dewey stated,
… signifies something which has just happened, and which is new just
because it deviates from the old and regular. But its meaning depends
upon relation to what it imports, to what its social consequences are.
This import cannot be determined unless the new is placed in relation
to the old, to what has happened and been integrated into the course
of events. Without coordination and consecutiveness, events are not
events, but mere occurrences, intrusions; an event implies that out of
which a happening proceeds. (LW2: 347)
The Obstacles to Creative Democracy at Home and Abroad
65
The problem Dewey found with news coverage was that it centred
on triviality and sensationalism. Driven by the ‘catastrophic, namely
crime, accident, family rows, personal clashes and conflicts,’ such news
coverage did not supply continuity of coverage to its audiences but
rather supplied whatever would be taken as the ‘new par excellence’. As
a result, Dewey quipped that the contents of news coverage became so
interchangeable that only the ‘date of the newspaper’ could inform us
whether such events happened ‘last year or this, so completely are they
isolated from their connections’ (LW2: 346–7).
The explanation of this state of affairs, argued Dewey, was also
down to the mixing of business practices and interests with modern
media technology. Bourgeois democracy’s ‘quasi-democratic’ habits
of free speech, free press and free assembly created fertile ground for
different sources of news production and public discussion. However,
such freedoms were structurally prone to being undermined by
the fact that the centralization and concentration of the means of
production and distribution also had concomitant effects upon the
organization of the public press. As Dewey noted, the smoothest road
to control of political matters was through the construction of public
opinion, and it was no coincidence that the gathering and sale of
news had become part of the existing system of ‘pecuniary profit’
(LW2: 348–9). This resulted in not only the influence of ‘private
interests in procuring suppression, secrecy and misrepresentation,’
but also the importing of the hegemony of consumer capitalism into
news production and dissemination. This was what Dewey took as
the explanation for the sensationalist and triviality of what passed
for news. Thus, either through the perpetuation of a certain style
of consumer capitalism in news production and dissemination or
through direct ownership and influence, Dewey believed that large
corporate capitalism naturally influenced the publishing business
(LW13: 168).
Contra the arguments of democratic realism and defenders of the
laissez-faire capitalism, Dewey argued that the eclipse of the public was
not down to its innate intellectual deficiency but largely down to the
66
John Dewey
artificial intellectual inequality engendered by bourgeois democracy
and elements of its consumer culture:
The indictments that are drawn against intelligence of individuals are
in truth indictments of a social order that does not permit the average
individual to have access to the rich store of the accumulated wealth
of mankind in knowledge, ideas and purposes. There does not now
exist the kind of social organization that even permits the average
human being to share the potentially available social intelligence. Still
less is there a social order that has for one of its chief purposes the
establishment of conditions that will move the mass of individuals to
appropriate and use what is at hand. Back of the appropriation by the
few of the material resources of society lies the appropriation by the
few in behalf of their own ends of the cultural, the spiritual, resources
that are the product not of the individuals who have taken possession
but of the cooperative work of humanity. (LW11: 38–9)
It was therefore useless, Dewey lamented, to ruminate about the
apparent failure of democracy until the sources of its failure had
been grasped and steps were taken, namely using government action
to address such economic and intellectual inequality, to bring about
that type of social organization that would deliver the masses with
the correct knowledge to comprehend the Great Society and practise
creative democracy. Quite simply, Dewey argued, without enacting such
a change we ‘have no way of telling how the apt for judgment of social
policies the existing intelligence of the masses may be’ (LW2: 366).4
The national and global eclipse of creative democracy
The effects of the eclipse of the public meant that creative democracy
at the level of the nation state had essentially been eclipsed. Not only
did ordinary citizens have no real democratic control over the Great
Society at the national level, but also publics were not able to emerge and
articulate demands that could generate the reform of social institutions
in the first place. Dewey realized that the eclipse of the public allowed
The Obstacles to Creative Democracy at Home and Abroad
67
the regime of ‘bourgeois democracy’ to continue to underpin the
institutions and practices of political democracy at the nation state
level. Due to the fact that democratic government had arisen along side
laissez-faire ideas of liberty, capitalism and the practice of democracy
were now seen as ‘Siamese’ twins, where to attack one was to threaten
the life of the other (LW13: 137). Indeed, Dewey took the example of
the application of laissez-faire to individual intelligence to be indicative
of how liberalism’s tenets had become part of a wider political malaise
within political democracy, which now acted as ‘an instrument of
vested interests’ (LW11: 35).
This in turn had a pincer effect on the nature of political democracy
under bourgeois democracy and its perpetuation of the eclipse of
the public. On one hand, Dewey argued that in the 1920s and 1930s
political parties ruled but they did not govern, acting as quasi ‘servants
of the same dominant railway, banking, and corporate industrial forces’
(LW6: 186, cf. LW5: 442). This was not just through blatant corrupt
control of government, but rather because the hegemonic identification
of capitalism and democracy and the ability of business to actually
organize itself as a public meant that it was able to reform the state
and government in much the same way as ‘dynastic interests’ controlled
government two centuries earlier (LW2: 302). In the inevitable clash
between private property interests and the interests of the masses, all
the ‘habits of thought and action’ impelled the institutions of political
democracy to side with the former over the latter (LW6: 159).
On the other hand, the fact that political parties acted in the interests
of capital rather than people had significant impact on the actual
eclipse of the public. Government intervention on the effects of such an
economically and intellectually stratified society was always palliative
and dealt with symptoms rather than what Dewey took as the causes of
such a state of affairs. This, in turn, locked the masses into the perpetual
supporting of one impotent political party over the other, breeding a
swing-style democracy where the ‘tidal wave’ swamps one party and the
‘landslide’ carries the other into office. In such a form of politics, instead
of real policy difference, it was rather ‘habit, party funds, the skill of
68
John Dewey
managers of the machine, the portrait of the candidate with his firm
jaw, his lovely wife and children, and a multitude of other irrelevancies’
determined the outcome of political democracy (LW2: 311).
The impotency of existing political forms to direct and manage the
social effects of the Great Society was also now generating ‘distrust
in political democracy and all forms of popular government’ (LW13:
105–6). This was because political democracy, with its established
institutions and practices under the hegemonic control of laissez-faire
capitalism, had seen its ‘symbols lose connection with the realities
behind them’ (LW11: 51). The majority of the voting public convinced
that there was ‘no important difference between the two old parties’
and that to vote for one over the other was to signify very ‘little’ had
lost faith with democracy (LW6: 185). Not only did this further add to
the political apathy engendered in the majority under the auspices of
bourgeois democracy and its consumer culture, but with such public
apathy, political democracy itself became stratified and turned into just
another ‘business’ run by the ‘bosses’ and ‘managers’ of the ‘political
machine’. Political democracy was thus now left to the machinations of
professional politicians and elites, who rather than attempting to serve
the public looked to keep or obtain power for the sake of keeping or
obtaining power within the confines of bourgeois democracy (LW2:
321, LW7: 353–4).
The ultimate political effect of the eclipse of the public within the
nation state was destruction of the Deweyan sense of democratic
community and disharmony within the nation state. This point is
pivotal; whilst Dewey believed citizens were unable to correctly locate
where the indirect consequences that were affecting their daily lives
came from, and hence could not generate publics which could foster
the reform of social institutions of the state to control and regulate the
consequences of the Great Society, he did not believe that citizens could
no longer generate publics. As he pointed out,
It is not that there is no public, no large body of persons having a
common interest in the consequences of social transactions. There
is too much public, a public too diffused and scattered and too
The Obstacles to Creative Democracy at Home and Abroad
69
intricate in composition. And there are too many publics, for conjoint
actions which have indirect, serious, and enduring consequences are
multitudinous beyond comparison, and each one of them crosses the
others and generates its own group of persons especially affected with
little to hold these different publics together in an integrated whole.
(LW2: 320)
The irony of the Great Society was that the more it made citizens more
interdependent through its division of labour and production, the more
it seemed to create divisions of interest between various groups across
society. In fact, due to the inequality and stratification of bourgeois
democracy, Dewey saw that groups and their publics referred back to an
approach of being antagonistic and hostile towards one another, rather
than democratically addressing the cause of their dissatisfactions. The
emergence ‘in political life of populist movements, square deals, new
deals, accompanies depressions on the part of those most directly
affected – farmers, factory labourers –’ was indicative of how such
groups were kept from ‘uniting politically by divergence of immediate
interests’ (LW13: 106). Under bourgeois democracy, then, the educative
rhythm of creative democracy, which looks to ensure a perpetual
equality of communication and co-operative problem-solving as social
conditions and conceptions of moral value shift throughout history,
was non-existent.
Stuck with old and outdated social institutions, a form of democracy
that was actually not democratic, and an eclipse of the public and
community which could bring reform to such social institutions,
creative democracy was thus stunted at the nation state level. Political
democracy in America was a prime example of this process, where the
state had not reformed its social institutions, such as wider and reformed
education, workplace democracy and comprehensive unemployment
insurance, and was now unable to deal with the consequences of the
Great Society. Indeed, the American institutions and practices of
political democracy themselves had not been updated and struggled to
cope with the new demands placed upon them. As Dewey noted, whilst
Americans had inherited the local town hall meetings of their agrarian
70
John Dewey
forefathers, these practices were now insufficient to enact reforms
suitable for ‘national affairs – now also affected by world conditions’
(LW13: 95, cf. LW2: 306).
Even at the federal level, the success of industrial forces in controlling
political parties had locked in what Dewey viewed as a flawed system
of two-party adversarial politics. The idea that the conflict between
political parties would bring out ‘public truths’, stressed Dewey, was a
kind of ‘political watered down version of the Hegelian dialectic, with
its synthesis arrived at by a union of antithetical conceptions’ (LW11:
51). And whether it was the ‘rugged individualism’ of the Hoover
regime or the ‘piecemeal policies undertaken ad hoc’ of Roosevelt’s
New Deal, which whilst seeming radical did not really reform the
‘institutional scheme of things’, political democracy merely ‘drifted’
along, largely consolidating the economic and intellectual stratification
of bourgeois democracy (LW11: 45, 61–2, cf. LW13: 315). The result, as
Dewey observed, was that the Great Society and its new age of human
relationships had ‘no political agencies worthy of it’ (LW2: 303).
It has become the norm to read Dewey’s account of the eclipse of
the public and the stunting of creative democracy as simply being
concerned with the American nation state. However, there is no doubt
that Dewey’s claim that the Great Society had no political agencies
worthy of it extended to matters of global democracy. As outlined
above, one of the underlying themes of The Public and Its Problems and
his writings thereafter is of the need for the Great Society to become
a Great Community. And Dewey knew that the Great Society did not
just stretch across North America but rather traversed the world’s
continents. That such an international Great Community and global
democracy was not forthcoming due to the eclipse of the public was
also paramount in Dewey’s mind. Writing in 1939, Dewey reflected
on how, since the First World War, the ‘world communities’ had failed
to ‘meet and forestall’ needed change and left ‘us with old problems
unsolved and new ones added’ (LW13: 316).
Dewey held that the failure to initiate such change was undoubtedly
down to the fact that bourgeois democracy and the breakdown
The Obstacles to Creative Democracy at Home and Abroad
71
of creative democracy within the nation state made such change
improbable. This was down to two interrelated reasons. The first reason
was that the hegemony of bourgeois democracy always meant that
political leaders would attempt palliative measures that maintained the
hegemony of capitalism and its conception of liberty. We have seen how
this strangled the reform that Dewey thought was needed at the level of
the nation state. However, bourgeois democracy’s control of the Great
Society was not only based on domestically stratified societies in the
West, but functioned through a global economy based on asymmetric
relations between the global North and South. As a basic provision
of global democracy, the wretched of the earth would have been set
free from the shackles of imperialism and the whole of the global
economy would have restructured (MW11: 139–42). This, however,
was unforthcoming as leaders replicated their palliative measures that
maintained the hegemony of capitalism and its conception of liberty in
the global economy.
The second reason was that the eclipse of the public meant citizens
were in no position to demand their leaders enact such changes. In fact,
the consequences of the Great Society and the eclipse of the public and
community at the nation state undoubtedly had detrimental effects
on how nation states viewed and conducted international relations
towards one another. As Dewey noted in The Public and Its Problems,
throughout history man has had problems getting on with his fellows,
even in his neighbourhood. With the Great Society’s engendering of
the transnational forms of relationships and interdependence, Dewey
noted that man was not now ‘more successful’ in getting on with his
fellows ‘when they act at a great distance in ways invisible to him’ (LW2:
317). The subsequent problem of there being too many publics who
were ‘diffused and scattered and too intricate in composition’, who
were subsequently antagonistic towards one another, was therefore
not confined to groups within the nation states, but also extended to
publics between nation states.
As the 1930s had shown, antagonism towards citizens of other nation
states, either through outright fascism or ideals of isolationism, could
72
John Dewey
be seen to be one of the last points of unity that the divided and troubled
publics of nation states had left. It was therefore no surprise to Dewey
that the failure of world communities to meet and forestall the failings
of bourgeois democracy and regulate the transnational consequences
generated by the Great Society through creative democracy at home
and abroad had seen the growth of ‘exacerbated Nationalism’ and left
democracy both as an ideal and as a form of government under attack
from both the ‘right and left’ (LW13: 106, 316). As Dewey noted,
The career of individuals, their lives and security as well as prosperity
is now affected by events on the other side of the world. The forces
back of these events he cannot touch or influence – save perhaps by
joining in a war of nations against nations. For we seem to live in a
world in which nations try to deal with the problems created by the
new situation by drawing more and more into themselves, by more
and more extreme assertions of independent nationalist sovereignty,
while everything they do in the direction of autarky leads to ever closer
mixture with other nations – but in war. (LW13: 180)
The rise of fascism and hyper-nationalism was the exemplar of this
process and was essentially explained by the inequality and stratification
of bourgeois democracy and its inability to provide citizens with the
intellectual and political means of perceiving and controlling the
consequences generated by the Great Society. Dewey saw the success
of fascist movements as being down to their ability to fill the political
void citizens experienced in bourgeois democracy by momentarily
appearing to offer an explanation and political solution to the drastic
changes engendered by living in such an interdependent world. Of
course, such explanations and political solutions were a mirage that led
to totalitarianism. Rather than creating a community in Dewey’s sense,
such movements attempted to restore a simulacrum of a community,
such as völksgemeinschaft, that were hostile not only to bourgeois
democracy but also to the ideals of creative democracy and the Great
Community (LW13: 176, 315–16).5
This was the scenario Dewey feared most when considering the
future of global democracy: the eclipse of the public in nation states
The Obstacles to Creative Democracy at Home and Abroad
73
and the consequences engendered by the Great Society leading citizens
to turn away from forming a Great Community and turning upon
one another. This view is summed up when, in the midst of the Great
Depression, trade protectionism and the increasing threat of another
world war, Dewey castigates the hostility of not only fascism, but also
the eclipsed publics contained within bourgeois democracies towards
the ideals of global democracy and a Great Community:
We cannot blame our Government or any other government for not
instituting new policies as long as the peoples themselves are engaged
in the futile task of identifying patriotism with isolation, and trying to
obtain independence without regard to the interdependence that now
exists. It is for us, the people, first to develop a genuine cooperative
spirit and sense of mutual interests that bind the nations of the world
together for weal or woe – and at the present time so largely for woe.
The principle of good neighborliness is as fundamental in international
matters as in the village and city … We shall refuse to live up to it at our
peril, the peril of depression, unemployment, degraded standard of
living, and of war that will kill millions more and destroy billions more
of property. (LW11: 263–4)
Dewey believed that this call for a new generation to inherit democracy
as a way of life and reinvent democracy globally was a responsibility
that the world could not afford to turn its backs on. However, Dewey’s
underlying point was that this inheritance could not be claimed under
the auspices of bourgeois democracy. It was thus bourgeois democracy
and the Great Society’s engendering of ‘divided and troubled publics’
within and between nation states and the breakdown of creative
democracy at the nation state level that Dewey saw as the ‘immense
difficulty’ facing global democracy. Without informed and educated
publics who could comprehend the complexity and trans-national
nature of the Great Society, communicate transitionally and challenge
the hegemony of bourgeois democracy, there was simply no chance of
real democratic innovation at home or abroad. Put simply, until the
Great Society was converted into a Great Community, the public would
perpetually remain eclipsed (LW2: 324).
4
Social Intelligence and Equality
The democratic faith in human equality is belief that every
human being, independent of the quantity or range of his personal
endowment, has the right to equal opportunity with every other
person for development of whatever gifts he has. (LW14: 227)
We talk a great deal about democracy as equality of opportunity and
then we adopt a system of private ownership of opportunities that
makes our boast a farce and a tragedy. (LW11: 256)
Throughout his life and beyond it, Dewey’s work on creative democracy
has largely been criticized as being complicit with capitalism or being
toothless in its opposition to capitalism. We have already seen that
Bertrand Russell (1922) and Lewis Mumford (1926) argued that
pragmatism was an expression of the material excesses of American
capitalism and the Gilded Age. The Frankfurt School would echo
similar critiques of the complicity between Dewey, his fellow classical
pragmatists and the capitalist social order (Lukacs 1971; Horkheimer
1972; Adorno 1973). Reinhold Niebuhur (1932) would label Dewey as
a politically apathetic thinker, who had lurched towards believing in
the idea of a self-correcting form of reason – a thought rearticulated
by C. Wright Mills in the 1960s when he would declare that Dewey’s
work lacked an account of the power structures of the modern capitalist
social order (Mills 1964). Even sympathetic interlocutors like Robert
Westbrook (1991, 2005), Michael Eldridge (1998) and Cornel West
(1989) appear to suggest that Dewey provided far too few concrete
practical means to achieve his own democratic ends. As Richard
Bernstein (2010: 87) puts it, Dewey’s idea of democracy as way of life
76
John Dewey
argues for a ‘social goal based on an inclusive plan’ but fails to spell out
the details of such an ‘inclusive plan’.1
Both sets of these claims seem to miss the mark. As we have seen,
Dewey certainly was no apologist for liberal capitalism at home or
abroad. And whilst Dewey was often unforthcoming or rather unwilling
to offer definitive blueprints for how to achieve creative democracy, it is
also unfair to say that Dewey left behind few concrete practical means
to achieve his own democratic ends. Dewey thought that the collapse of
European democracy into totalitarianism and the eclipse of the public
in America transpired because democratic habits were no longer part
of the ‘bone and blood of the people in daily conduct of its life’. To this
end, Dewey put forward a whole raft of reforms that he believed would
help democracy as a way of life become part of the ‘fibre’ of the people
(LW11: 225). These included reforms such as new approaches to the
American economy, public education, the role of social science and the
social scientist as an ‘expert’, media regulation and the role of the arts
in democracy.2
All of these concrete proposals deserve attention and serve as an
example of how Dewey believed reforms could bring forth a greater
array of democratic habits that would facilitate the practice of creative
democracy. However, for the purposes of our exposition of a ‘global’
Dewey, in this and the next chapter, I want to focus on the concrete
lessons Dewey put forward on how to achieve democracy at home
and abroad and how both spheres of democracy were intertwined. In
this chapter, I specifically want to focus on Dewey’s ideas about the
economic reforms needed to facilitate what he called social intelligence
in the midst of a liberal-capitalist order that stunted the intelligence of
its citizens. Moreover, I want to focus on Dewey’s ideas about how the
Great Society and its regime of bourgeois democracy needed to shift
to a form of democratic socialism to achieve the goal of becoming a
Great Community. These economic reforms not only seemingly laid
the grounds for all of Dewey’s other reforms but were also based on the
need to provide the ethical commitment at the heart of democracy as
a way of life and the grounds for an expanded social intelligence both
Social Intelligence and Equality
77
within and beyond the nation state. This chapter will therefore outline
how Dewey believed that the Great Society was to be regulated not only
to avoid the mutual destruction of humanity but also to succeed in
harnessing ‘available human energy’ (LW13: 312).
To illustrate the above, the chapter will proceed through four
movements of argument. The first section will outline how Dewey’s idea
of creative democracy was based upon a form of deliberation he called
social intelligence and how social intelligence is essentially an adoption
of the ‘scientific attitude of the mind’ in moral and political matters.
The second section will outline how Dewey believed liberal capitalism
was unable to support social intelligence and needed replacing with
a form of democratic socialism. The third section will outline how
Dewey’s call for democratic socialism was animated by his view about
the relationship between economic inequality and political equality
within the Great Society. The final section will highlight how Dewey’s
views on economic and political equality translate into an argument for
an extension of global egalitarianism that would allow all nations of the
world to pursue the democratic way of life.
The habits of social intelligence
As we have seen, the emergence of the Great Society fundamentally
altered reality for citizens in the United States of America and beyond.
This process had been set in motion by the industrial and technological
revolutions, which had been driven by modern science and ushered in
modernity. Dewey highlighted the fact that whilst the physical forces
of the industrial-technological revolutions had ‘revolutionised the face
of the globe’, the political and moral ‘ideas and ideals that rule us are
still largely those of a pre-scientific, pre-industrial, pre-technological
age’. With this in mind, Dewey declared that it was understandable,
even if one could not sympathize with such views, why reactionary
and conservative ideologies clamoured for a return to ‘simpler
conditions’. These viewpoints resorted to a ‘mixture of exhortation
78
John Dewey
and with reliance upon traditions, habits, institutions, which were
adjusted to bygone conditions’. And although they clamoured for the
impossible – a return to political isolation – the rise of fascism, Nazism
and state totalitarianism was ‘no accident’ but the logical conclusion of
a disjunction between our political ideals and the reality of the Great
Society (LW17: 454, 459).
The problem of the Great Society and its politics, Dewey contended,
was that monolithic theories and ideologies of social action tended
to have ‘ready-made’ answers to a context that was prone to changing
and which demanded new solutions. However, if Dewey (LW1: 358)
was adamant that the ‘industrial-technological revolution was largely,
if not wholly, responsible for the two world wars and the threat of
another of ultimate destructiveness’, he was also adamant about the
‘potential alliance between scientific and democratic method and the
need of consummating this potentiality’ in tackling the problems and
publics generated by the Great Society (LW13: 135). Moreover, Dewey
believed that the ‘crisis in democracy’ demanded the ‘substitution of
intelligence that is exemplified in scientific procedure for the kind of
intelligence that is now accepted’ (LW11: 51). This alliance between
the scientific and the democratic method is what Dewey calls ‘social
intelligence’.
To understand Dewey’s idea of social intelligence, we must first
recall Dewey’s ideas of creative democracy and democratic community
that we explored in Chapter 1. Creative democracy points towards
the perpetual adaption of social institutions, including democratic
institutions and practices themselves, as new publics are engendered by
social change. This is founded on the ethical commitment of democracy
as a way of life to the principle that those who are affected by social
institutions should have an equality of opportunity to contribute to
the production and management of those institutions. The balanced
equality of democracy as a way of life and its focus on collective
problem-solving highlights Dewey’s faith in a deliberative (conference,
consultation, negotiation and persuasion) form of political settlement
and the establishment of a democratic community.
Social Intelligence and Equality
79
What, then, is the role of social intelligence in creative democracy
and in the maintenance of the democratic community? The answer
centres on the form of deliberation within the democratic community.
Dewey cautioned that public discussion and comparison of ideas alone
were inherently too weak to meet the problems brought about by the
movements of the Great Society (LW11: 50–2).3 Social intelligence is
thus not simply the practice of democratic deliberation, but rather a
certain way of democratically practising deliberation. Quintessentially,
social intelligence attempts to adapt the ‘experimental method’ of
natural science in the arena of human relations. This does not mean that
particular techniques of natural science were to be simply transposed
into social contexts or that laboratory experimentation was to be carried
out on society at large. Whilst Dewey did not discount the use of such
scientific methods in social affairs, he primarily saw the key part of
social intelligence as centring on the transposition of the ‘attitude of the
mind exemplified in the conquest of nature by experimental science’
into ‘social affairs’ (LW9: 108). Social intelligence therefore attempts to
utilize elements of natural science’s ‘attitude of the mind’ to promote an
array of habits, a personal way of living, which perpetuates democracy
as a way of life in the day-to-day lives of citizens (LW7: 329–30).
In the first instance, Dewey outlines that social intelligence would
see individuals possess ‘democratic habits of thought and action’, which
stem from the scientific attitude of the mind, and that they would
practise such methods in ‘all social relationships’ (LW11: 225). Dewey
outlines this ‘distinctive type of disposition and purpose’ as habits of
thought and action that would promote:
… willingness to hold beliefs in suspense, ability to doubt until
evidence is obtained; willingness to go where evidence points instead
of putting first a personally preferred conclusion; ability to hold ideas
in solution and use them as hypotheses to be tested instead of dogmas
to be asserted; and (possibly the most distinctive of all) enjoyment of
new fields for enquiry and of new problems. (LW13: 166)
Through such habits, Dewey contends, members of a society can
substitute the utilization of unquestioned moral truths, such as class
80
John Dewey
interests, pride and prejudice, commands of the state, constitutions
or traditions, with a process of social intelligence that utilizes the
‘experimental method’ of forming social policy and morality as ‘cooperative undertakings’ between members of a community (LW7: 329;
LW14: 228).
The term ‘experimental method’ may erroneously suggest Dewey’s
embracement of moral relativism or the belief that all past moral
precedents that provide the basis for established social policy are to
be lightly discarded. However, the overriding point of the adoption
of the scientific attitude to the appraisal of moral conflict is the belief
that there can be no assumption of an a priori truth that would
automatically adjudicate moral conflict or provide the basis for social
policy. Eschewing moral relativism, the experimental method places its
faith in demonstrable evidence rather than dogmatic moral absolutes
when appraising moral conflict and the merits of social policy. In the
light of this, an experimental method of forming social policy and
morality is simply how members of a society, who share a common
embracement of the scientific attitude, collectively appraise moral
conflict and the merits of respective social policy. Dewey defines the
experimental method as a ‘reflective morality’ that:
… demands observation of particular situations, rather than fixed
adherence to a priori principles; that free enquiry and freedom of
publication and discussion must be encouraged and not merely
grudgingly tolerated; that opportunity at different times and places
must given for trying different measures so that their effects maybe
be capable of observation and of comparison with one another.
(LW7: 329)
In this scenario, the machinations of the cultural matrix and social
policy are to be approached in terms of an analysis of cause and effect
and means and consequences (LW11: 52). Just as past principles,
precedents or points of authority are used in natural science, social
policies are to be used as ‘working hypotheses’ which, based on the
knowledge of past experience, act as tools that help us manage material
culture towards desired ends. Established social policies are to be no
Social Intelligence and Equality
81
more easily discarded than established scientific principles but they
are to be continually subject to ‘constant’ and ‘well-equipped’ inquiry,
observation and reflection upon the consequences they entail. Dewey
dubs such an approach ‘experimental’, however, because on the back
of such observation and reflection, which may bring to light newly
discovered evidence or conditions within the cultural matrix that lead
to doubt over their soundness or acceptability, all social policies and
the moral values which engender them are to be open to revision or
alteration (LW7: 329–30).4
Social intelligence therefore mandates that deliberation within the
democratic community is not to be a fight over notions of antecedent
and independent conceptions of morality or social policy but rather the
experimental formation of moral value and social policy in response
to evidence. The underlying premise of this process is that ‘day-to-day
working together with others’ is the best solution to social problems.
As Kloppenburg (1994: 79) contends, Dewey’s idea of the democratic
community and the use of social intelligence replicate what Dewey saw
as the chief tenets of the scientific community:
No scientific inquirer can keep what he finds to himself or turn it
to merely private account without losing his scientific standing.
Everything discovered belongs to the community of workers.
Every new idea and theory has to be submitted to this community
for confirmation and test. There is an expanding community of
cooperative effort and of truth. (LW5: 115)
Under the remit of social intelligence, differing or conflicting moral
parties do not merely deliberate their positions but actually explore
their conflict as a problem to be solved by embracing the scientific
attitude and the experimental method of forming social policy and
morality. This means not only having the willingness to learn from
the moral positions and evidence about the machinations of society
and associated behaviour put forward by different publics, but also
having the willingness to surrender such a conflict to constant and
well-equipped inquiry and observation, and then for both sides to cooperate in solving such moral conflict:
82
John Dewey
…. even when needs and ends or consequences are different for each
individual, the habit of amicable cooperation – which may include, as
in sport, rivalry and competition – is itself a priceless addition to life. To
take as far as possible every conflict which arises – and they are bound
to arise – out of the atmosphere and medium of force, of violence as
a means of settlement into that of discussion and of intelligence is to
treat those who disagree – even profoundly – with us as those from
who we may learn, and in so far, as friends … To cooperate by giving
difference a chance to show themselves because of the belief that the
expression of difference is not only a right of the other persons but
is a means of enriching one’s own life experience, is inherent in the
democratic personal way of life. (LW14: 228)
Dewey’s idea of creative democracy must therefore be seen as an
evolutionary form of democracy predicated upon the widespread
use of social intelligence in the appraisal of moral conflict over social
policy. It was the maintenance of the democratic community through
the methods of social intelligence, Dewey believed, which would allow
moral conflicts and the resultant social policy decisions to be settled in
the ‘widest possible contribution of all – or at least the great majority’
(LW11: 56).
The obvious question that follows from this discussion is this:
Why did Dewey believe social intelligence to be the best method
for approaching moral and political conflict? Dewey believed that
social intelligence, whilst not a panacea for all social problems, held
the greatest hope of bringing ‘order and even abundance to societies
plagued by strife and uncertainty’ (Gouinlock 1990: 268). In the first
instance, this was based on the non-absolutism of social intelligence
allowing for all moral positions to be voiced, heard and evaluated
through social intelligence. In this sense, social intelligence provided
publics with the best method of voicing grievances and a collaborative
process of political settlement that avoided the recourse to violence and
coercive control:
When democracy openly recognizes the existence of problems and the
need for probing them as problems as its glory, it will relegate political
Social Intelligence and Equality
83
groups that pride themselves upon refusing to admit incompatible
opinions to the obscurity which already is the fate of similar groups in
science. (LW13: 135)
Dewey pushed this position even further by suggesting that ‘social
control effected through organised application of social intelligence’
was the only form of political settlement that could deal with ‘existing
evils without landing us firmly in some form of coercive control from
above and outside’ (LW 13: 320).
Dewey’s faith in a form of creative democracy through social
intelligence was also based on what he saw as the productive gains the
scientific community had bequeathed to humanity and the possible
gains it could provide for humanity within the sphere of moral and
political matters. This process within science seemingly validated the
co-operative inquiry of social intelligence:
The contrast between the state of intelligence in politics and in the
physical control of nature is to be taken literally. What has happened
in this latter is the outstanding demonstration of the meaning of
organized intelligence. The combined effect of science and technology
has released more productive energies in a bare hundred years than
stands to the credit of prior human history in its entirety … The
stationary engine, the locomotive, the dynamo, the motorcar, turbine,
telegraph, telephone, radio and moving picture are not the products of
either isolated individual minds nor of the particular economic régime
called capitalism. They are the fruit of methods that first penetrated
to the working causalities of nature and then utilized the resulting
knowledge in bold imaginative ventures of invention and construction.
(LW11: 52)
Dewey located the revolutions of science that in turn led to the
industrial-technological revolutions as revealing the social nature of
intelligence. In this regard, science highlighted how intelligence was a
‘social asset’ with a public origin based on social co-operation (LW11:
48). Moreover, science and its sense of community highlighted to
Dewey that allowing individuals to share in the fruits of community
84
John Dewey
would allow the effective intelligence of all to rise considerably.
Indeed, Dewey stated that in ‘a social medium in whose institutions
the available knowledge, ideas and art of humanity were incarnate
the average individual would rise to undreamed of heights of social
and political intelligence’ (LW11: 50). Beyond this, however, science
also highlighted how the social nature of intelligence could lead to
unthinkable advancements across society when teamed with the
experimental method of approaching problems through the cooperative undertakings. Dewey’s hope was that the democratic
community could realize the method of the scientific community
through using social intelligence, and in doing so, correct the failure to
utilize ‘human power’ in the same way science had utilized nature to
realize productive energies:
The general adoption of the scientific attitude in human affairs would
mean nothing less than a revolutionary change in morals, religion,
politics and industry. The fact we have limited its use so largely
to technical matters is not a reproach to science, but to the human
beings who use it for private ends and who strive to defeat its social
application for fear of destructive effects upon their power and profit.
A vision of a day in which the natural science and the technologies that
flow from them are used as servants of a humane life constitutes the
imagination that is relevant to our own time. (LW5: 115)
This may all sound like wishful thinking and Dewey was willing to
admit that he himself may be exaggerating the power of co-operation
vis-à-vis ideas of class conflict or the inherent evil within humanity.
But in the context of the greatest crisis of liberal democracy and the
rise of totalitarianisms, Dewey contended that social intelligence was
‘worth a trial’ and that ‘illusion for illusion’, this particular one may be
better ‘than those humanity has usually depended upon’ (LW9: 108).
More to the point, Dewey was adamant that a society and culture that
permitted science to destroy traditional values but which distrusted its
power to create new ones was a culture which was ‘destroying itself ’
(LW13: 172).5
Social Intelligence and Equality
85
The planning society
Dewey believed that social intelligence highlighted that humans were
capable of ‘intelligent’ judgement and action, both individually and
collectively, when appraising social problems and forming social policy
(creative democracy), if equipped with an equality of communication
and participation in democratic life (democracy as a way of life), the
right intellectual sensibility and habits (scientific attitude) and the free
play of facts and ideas (experimental method). This was the co-joining of
the democratic method with the scientific method. However, Dewey was
certainly no believer that bourgeois democracy was hospitable to such
a method or that citizens widely possessed democratic habits of social
intelligence. As we encountered in Chapter 3, Dewey’s take on bourgeois
democracy and its pernicious effects on the ‘intelligence’ of the masses
are quite clear. The hegemony of finance capitalism and its creation
of vast material and cultural inequality stunted any chance of creative
democracy through limiting both the participation and intelligence
of the masses. This not only neglected the ethical commitment of the
democratic as a way of life but also failed to utilize them as a resource
for the practice of social intelligence. As Dewey outlines, bourgeois
democracy gave no opportunity for the great mass of people:
… to reflect and decide upon what is good for them. Others who are
supposed to be wiser and who in any case have more power decide the
question for them and also decide the methods and means by which
subjects may arrive at the enjoyment of what is good for them. This
form of coercion and suppression is more subtle and more effective
than is overt intimidation and restraint. When it is habitual and
embodied in social institutions, it seems the normal and natural state
of affairs. The mass usually become unaware that they have a claim to
a development of their own powers. Their experience is so restricted
that they are not conscious of restriction. It is part of the democratic
conception that they as individuals are not the only sufferers, but that
the whole social body is deprived of the potential resources that should
be at its service. (LW11: 218–19)
86
John Dewey
Dewey argued that the ‘ultimate’ institution, which could help mitigate
the lack of democratic habits amongst the masses, was education
and educational reform. Education ‘more than other single agency,
is concerned with the development of free inquiry, discussion and
expression’ (LW11: 253). However, Dewey did not believe that
bourgeois democracy and the results it generated could be patched up
‘here and there’ through sporadic reforms to areas such as education.
Instead, what was first and foremost needed was the recognition of the
‘moral, emotional and intellectual effect’ the day-to-day workings of the
political economy of bourgeois democracy had upon all citizens:
… every one who reflects upon the subject admits that it is impossible
that the ways in which activities are carried on for the greater part of
the waking hours of the day; and the way in which the shares of the
individuals are involved in the management of affairs in such a matter
as gaining a livelihood and attaining material and social security, can
only be a highly important factor in shaping personal dispositions; in
short, forming character and intelligence. (LW11: 221)
In order to facilitate the spread of democratic habits of social
intelligence amongst the masses, it was imperative, Dewey argued,
that the ‘profit system’ of capitalism be reoriented to one which would
realize that the ‘ultimate problem of production is the production of
human beings’ (LW13: 318). To accomplish this, Dewey put forward
the idea of reorientating the American economy around a form of
democratic socialism. This centred on adopting various ideas from the
‘British Labour Party and Social Democratic Parties of Europe’ and
required the socialization of the ‘commanding heights of the economy’
through creating publics works, enacting taxes that could deliver a
thorough redistribution of wealth and the nationalization of industries
(LW9: 289–90). However, Dewey envisioned a socialized economy
that was not simply a form of state socialism. A socialized economy
was to provide the platform that would facilitate creative democracy
through the practice of social intelligence. This move for economic
freedom was thus geared towards securing the cultural freedom
needed to perpetuate social intelligence (LW11: 254). This included the
Social Intelligence and Equality
87
aforementioned reforms to education, the media and the arts, but also
an increased workplace democracy and a remodeling of the state and its
political democracy towards resolving moral conflicts between publics
(Westbrook 1991: 457).
The twining of a socialized economy with participatory democracy
provided the grounds for what Dewey saw as the difference between
the ‘planning society’ of democratic socialism vis-à-vis the ‘planned
society’ of bourgeois democracy and its communist and fascist
alternatives. A planning society was essentially another name for what
Dewey believed would be the practices of creative democracy in the
Great Community. Such a society would not just drift from problem to
problem but actively use social intelligence in order to practise creative
democracy and perpetuate the future use of social intelligence through
a diffusion of democratic habits across society:
What claims to be social planning is now found in Communist and
Fascist countries. The social consequence is complete suppression
of freedom of inquiry, communication and voluntary association,
by means of a combination of personal violence, culminating in the
extirpation, and systematic partisan propaganda. The results are such
that in the minds of many persons the very idea of social planning
and of the violation of the integrity of the individual are becoming
intimately bound together. But an immense difference divides the
planned society from a continuously planning society. The former
requires fixed blueprints imposed from above and therefore involving
reliance upon physical and psychological force to secure conformity
to them. The latter means the release of intelligence through the
widest form of cooperative give-and-take. The attempt to plan social
organization and association without the freest possible play of
intelligence contradicts the very idea of social planning. For the latter is
an operative method of activity, not a predetermined set of final truths.
(LW13: 321)
Dewey’s faith in the democratic planning can be found not only in his
philosophical work but also in his political activism during the Great
Depression and the New Deal era. Many of his statements on democratic
88
John Dewey
socialism come from publications and activism linked to the People’s
Lobby (PL) and the League for Independent Political Action (LIPA).
Even critics of Dewey’s social theory point to the fact that groups such
as the PL, LIPA and the Farmer-Labour Political Federation (FLPF)
provided the politics that Dewey’s ‘ … ideals and his political theory
demanded’. These were organizations that showed Dewey’s belief that
the two dominant political parties of the United States were under the
spell of bourgeois democracy and were unable and unwilling to stand
up to the power of capital. These groups therefore campaigned to
create new forms of alliance between agricultural farmers, the working
class and the middle class in the pursuit and hope of founding a new
third political party. Moreover, Dewey’s pursuit of radical ‘third party’
politics within the United States sought to create the very organizations
that could help educate and inform the eclipsed public he had talked
about since the 1920s, and also sought to ‘invest them with the power to
define their interests and reconstruct the state’ (Westbrook 1991: 452).
Democracy and equality
The details of Dewey’s democratic socialism have always stoked debate
amongst Deweyan scholars and interlocutors. In the essay the ‘End of
Leninism’, Richard Rorty, perhaps Dewey’s most infamous philosophical
interpreter of the twentieth century, states that Dewey was calling for
nothing short of the wide-scale replacement of the market economy.
Rorty goes on to argue that such thought, in the light of the latter
half of the twentieth century and the fall of organized communism,
was simply outdated and proven to be a political and moral dead end
(Rorty 1998: 329n15). On the other hand, Robert Westbrook (2005:
171) – Dewey’s most famous historical interpreter – believes Rorty’s
own interpretation went too far and concealed the fact that Dewey’s
vision of democratic socialism was of a ‘semi-socialist’ market economy
regulated in the interests of the least well off. It is beyond the remit
of this book to settle the debate about the details of Dewey’s vision of
Social Intelligence and Equality
89
the democratic socialism and its political economy.6 However, we can
make the argument as to why Dewey sought to achieve democratic
socialism in the first place. At the heart of Dewey’s vision of political
economy were ideas about the need to secure economic equality to
ensure the ethical commitment of democracy as a way of life and the
diffusion of democratic habits that would facilitate social intelligence.
This was because the Great Society had unleashed forces which, when
interpreted through the lens of bourgeois democracy and its ideas of
liberty, could perpetually undermine the democratic way of life and the
use of social intelligence.
Dewey’s ideas about the relationship between economic and political
equality can be gleaned from his critique of the New Deal. Castigating
it as an inadequate ‘half-way house’ between unregulated capitalism
and democratic socialism, Dewey saw that the New Deal as ideological
enterprise designed ‘to save the profit system from itself ’ (LW9:
289). The reforms of Roosevelt, Dewey argued, were nothing more
than temporary measures which as ‘sure as night follows day’ would
inevitability lead back to restoring the power and privilege of bourgeois
democracy (LW9: 77). By 1939, Dewey was even more adamant that
the ‘profit’ system of capitalism was incapable of democratic ends:
The means have to be implemented by a social-economic system
that establishes and uses the means for the production of free human
beings associating with one another on terms of equality. Then and
then only will these means be an integral part of the end, not frustrated
and self-defeating, bringing new evils and generating new problems.
(LW13: 320)
The question then becomes why did Dewey believe that the socialeconomic system he encountered was incapable of producing free
human beings associating with one another on terms of equality? And
how did this result in Dewey arguing for democratic socialism within
the confines of the Great Society?
The answers to these questions are best illustrated in Dewey’s
reconstruction of liberalism and liberty in Liberalism and Social
Action (LW11) and a whole swathe of essays written throughout the
90
John Dewey
Great Depression. In these works, Dewey puts forward the idea that
‘liberalism’ and its idea of liberty had become a much-confused concept
and departed from its initial meaning (LW11: 5). If we recall the
discussion of philosophical liberalism in Chapter 3, Dewey highlighted
that the advent of bourgeois democracy had seen the ideas of liberty,
individualism and democracy become fused with the ideal of laissezfaire capitalism (LW11: 250). Dewey, however, took this conception of
liberty and individualism to task. Outlining the fact that liberty is not a
static or general concept, Dewey contends that liberty is best conceived
as ‘power, the effective power to do specific things’. This demand for
power was always historically located and based on the distribution
of power that ‘exists at the time’. The system of liberties is always just
a ‘system of restraints or controls that exists at that time’. As a result,
Dewey argued that there was no such thing as ‘liberty or effective power
of an individual group, or class’ except in relation to the ‘liberties, the
effective powers, of other individuals, groups and classes’. This revealed
the social nature of liberty, where ‘the liberties that any individual
actually has depended upon the distribution of powers and liberties’
engendered by the legal, political and economic structures of society
(LW11: 361–2).
Dewey argued that when liberty was rightfully taken as a historically
relative concept, philosophical liberalism’s rendering of ‘liberty’,
‘individualism’ and ‘democracy’ as historically chained to ideas of
laissez-faire capitalism was simply a denial of the historical relativity of
liberty. More to the point, such an ahistorical idea of liberty concealed the
fact that ideas that once espoused freedom, bringing about the ‘glorious
revolution’ of 1688 and eighteenth- and nineteenth-century democratic
revolts against oligarchical government, had become a form of ‘pseudoliberalism’ that ossified an illiberal form of social organization (LW11:
287, 291). The ideas of liberty, individualism and democracy that were
tied to laissez-faire capitalism were now undeniably unfit for purpose
and stood against the very ideas they were supposed to represent:
… laissez-faire liberalism is played out, largely because of the fruits of
its own policies. Any system that cannot provide elementary security
Social Intelligence and Equality
91
for millions has no claim to the title of being organized in behalf of the
liberty and the development of individuals. (LW11: 287)
Dewey was adamant that the entire meaning of liberalism and liberty
must now be reconstructed to help facilitate creative democracy and
the habits of social intelligence in the midst of the Great Society. To this
end, Dewey recovered what he called the ‘formula of early democratic
political liberalism’ that located the relationship between equality and
liberty and recognized the historical relativity associated with obtaining
this goal. This conception of democratic liberty, which in the hands of
Dewey was another name for the democratic way of life, viewed that
all humans are and were ‘born free and equal’. This was not a foolish
belief in the equality of individual endowments but rather the belief
that political equality was the product of social institutions, laws, and
customs and habits. Within this idea of liberty, social institutions and
laws should always act ‘as such to secure and establish equality for all’
in order to perpetuate the democratic ideal. This recovering of the
‘formula of early democratic political liberalism’ revealed that equality,
liberty and fraternity were not incompatible but rather that the ‘actual
liberties of one human being depend upon the powers of action that
existing institutional arrangements accord to other individuals’ (LW11:
369–70). To secure its ethical commitment, the democratic way of
life therefore always demanded a historically relative democratic
distribution of liberties (Westbrook 1991: 436).
When Dewey utilized this ‘formula of early democratic political
liberalism’, it became clear to him that an economic reorganization of
the Great Society must be at the centre of a democratic distribution of
liberties. Whilst Dewey did not discount the importance of economic
relations across history, the context of the Great Society now meant that
industry, banking and commerce had reached a point where ‘private
business enterprise’ affected so many people in ‘deep and enduring
ways’ that all ‘business’ was held a potential ‘public interest’. Since
the ‘consequences of business’ were now social, society must itself
look after ‘the industrial and financial causes of these consequences’
(LW11: 287). This in turn formed the rationale of Dewey’s ideas that a
92
John Dewey
reconstructed liberalism would have to centre on a form of democratic
socialism in order to live up to the democratic way of life because the
social consequences of laissez-faire liberalism, namely its cultural and
economic inequality, now prevented liberty for all:
… the ends which liberalism has always professed can be attained
only as control of the means of production and distribution is taken
out of the hands of individuals who exercise powers created socially
for narrow individual interests. The ends remain valid. But the means
of attaining them demand a radical change in economic institutions
and the political arrangements based upon them. These changes are
necessary in order that social control of forces and agencies socially
created may accrue to the liberation of all individuals associated
together in the great undertaking of building a life that expresses and
promotes human liberty. (LW11: 367)
What is pivotal to note here, however, is that Dewey’s reconstructed
liberalism along democratic socialist lines makes a distinct statement
about the role of economic equality in the maintenance of the
democratic way of life and the possibility of social intelligence
within the context of the Great Society. The industrial-technological
revolutions of the Great Society and their control by ‘finance-capitalism’
through the ideology of laissez-faire liberalism had given liberty of
action to certain citizens and groups with ‘ … abilities of acquiring
property and to the employment of that wealth in further acquisitions’.
The favouring of such abilities not only created an insidious link
between capital and industry and science, but also saw the creation
of economic inequalities that impoverished political democracy and
secured the ‘monopoly of power in the hands of the few to control
the opportunities of the wide masses and to limit their free activities
in realizing their natural capacities’ (LW11: 369–70). Dewey stressed
that this meant that a democratic distribution of liberties was now only
possible through the establishment of economic equality:
The democratic ideal that unites equality and liberty is, on the other
hand, recognition that actual and concrete liberty of opportunity and
action is dependant upon equalization of the political and economic
Social Intelligence and Equality
93
conditions under which individuals are alone free in fact, not in some
abstract metaphysical way. The tragic breakdown of democracy is
due to the fact that the identification of liberty with the maximum
of unrestrained individualistic action in the economic sphere, under
the institutions of capitalistic finance, is as fatal to the realization of
liberty for all as it is fatal to the realization of equality. It is destructive
of liberty for the many precisely because it is destructive of genuine
equality of opportunity. (LW11: 370)
This was because the genie of the industrial-technological revolutions
and the ideas of laissez-faire liberalism could not simply be put back
in the lamp. It was inevitable, Dewey argued, that if such ideas and
practices were left unchecked and remained hegemonic that they would
seize the fruits of industrial-technological revolutions and generate a
form of economic inequality that would perpetually nullify any chance
of creative democracy:
The drift of nominal democracy from the conception of life which
may properly be characterized as democratic has come about under
the influence of a so-called rugged individualism that defines the
liberty of individuals in terms of the inequality bred by existing
economic-legal institutions. In so doing, it puts almost exclusive
emphasis upon those natural capacities of individuals that have
power to effect pecuniary and materialistic acquisitions. For our
existing materialism, with the blight to which it subjects the cultural
development of individuals, is the inevitable product of the
exaggeration of the economic liberty of the few at the expense of the
all-around liberty of the many. And, I repeat, this limitation upon
genuine liberty is the inevitable product of the inequality that arises
and must arise under the operations of institutionally established and
supported finance-capitalism. (LW11: 371)7
If one took liberty to mean the ‘power to act’ and a democratic
conception of liberty to mean the ‘power to act equally’, then it
became clear to Dewey that only an equal distribution of power within
economic circles would now facilitate genuine political equality within
the context of the Great Society. Dewey thus declared that the ‘future of
94
John Dewey
democracy’ within the context of cultural matrix of the Great Society
now centred on how democracy could be made secure in a context
where most people have the ‘minimum’ of control over the conditions
of their own subsistence. The democratic way of life would now have
to be twined with the idea of using ‘political action to bring about
equalisation of economic conditions in order that the equal right of all
to free choice and free action be maintained’ (LW13: 178, 300). When
this is taken into consideration, Dewey’s arguments for democratic
socialism read as nothing more as the means to achieve a democratic
distribution of liberty (power) within the Great Society:
Power today resides in control of the means of production, exchange,
publicity, transportation and communication. Whoever owns them
rules the life of the country, not necessarily by intention, not necessarily
by deliberate corruption of the nominal government, but by necessity.
Power is power and must act, and it must act according to the nature of
the machinery through which it operates. In this case, the machinery
is business for private profit through private control of banking, land,
industry, reinforced by command of the press, press agents and other
means of publicity and propaganda. In order to restore democracy,
one thing and one thing only is essential. The people will rule when
they have power, and they will have power in the degree they own and
control the land, the banks, the producing and distributing agencies
of the nation. Ravings about Bolshevism, Communism, Socialism are
irrelevant to the axiomatic truth of this statement. They come either
from complaisant ignorance or from the deliberate desire of those in
possession, power and rule to perpetuate their privilege. (LW9: 76–77)
Whatever the debate about the details of Dewey’s democratic socialism
and its political economy, it becomes apparent that Dewey believed that
economic security and equality for the masses would have to be secured
in order for democracy as a way of life to live up to its own ethical
commitment within the context of the Great Society. Unlike Marxist
positions, which posited a metaphysical argument about alienation to
call for a wholesale change of the economic system (LW13: 116–35),
Dewey did not turn to democratic socialism because he believed it would
Social Intelligence and Equality
95
reconcile man with himself but because he saw such ideas and practices
as the best means to achieving a democratic distribution of liberties in
the midst of the industrial-technological revolutions of the Great Society
and laissez-faire liberalism. Moreover, this move towards securing
‘greater measures of economic freedom for the mass of people’ was not
an end in itself but rather was the means to secure political equality and
the ‘means’ within the Great Society to secure the ‘cultural freedom’
which would facilitate the emergence of the Great Community and allow
the human ‘ … development through science, art and unconstrained
human intercourse’ (LW11: 254). This cultural freedom was about
securing the diffusion of habits that would help facilitate the use of social
intelligence. However, the chief point here is that Dewey put forward a
historically rooted argument that such cultural freedom was now only
possible through mutually reinforcing forms of equality of political
opportunity and equality of economic outcome.8
Global democracy and equality
The obvious question that arises from the discussion of Dewey’s idea
about the relationship between economic equality and democracy in
the Great Society surrounds its global connotations. After all, the Great
Society was shorthand not simply for American corporate capitalism
but also for the complex global capitalist economy that was initiated by
the long nineteenth century and the First Great Globalization. Would
Dewey’s work then lend itself towards a global democratic distribution
of liberties and a global equalization of economic conditions? Moreover,
can Dewey’s work on democracy and equality offer us a form of global
justice?
This question has most recently been approached by Phillip Deen
(2013), who has attempted to see if philosophical pragmatism and, in
particular, Dewey’s work can offer an account of global distributive
justice. Taking the process of social intelligence and its use to solve moral
problems as the essential commitment of philosophical pragmatism,
96
John Dewey
Deen outlines that for writers such as Dewey ‘a just global order is one
that provides the conditions for fruitful democratic inquiry on matters
crossing boundaries, both physical and conceptual, between states or
peoples’. Moreover, Deen contends that pragmatism, and in particular
Dewey’s work, develops two ends of a continuum between the ideal and
non-ideal conditions for producing a just international order (Deen
213: 112–16). These two ends are:
1.
2.
A just order that addresses concrete problems at the international
level – such as global climate change, gross economic inequality
between nations and human rights – that utilizes the social
intelligence and its experimental method to form moral value
and social policy between nation states and publics within and
between nation states. The use of ideal models here would be to
test ‘experimentally’ in order to show how they can solve global
problems.
Certain practical conditions must be brought about to ensure
that social intelligence can take place. These include institutional
arrangements, such as rights of expression and freedom of
information and assembly, that facilitate social intelligence and
lessening of the distorted effects of poverty and inequality.
Deen goes on to argue that ‘long experience’ has determined the
‘necessary conditions’ for social intelligence and allows us to assert that
‘relatively stable ends for inquiry’ require us to now ‘free people from
great want, oppression or ignorance’ (Deen 2013: 116).9 Deen prefigures
his paper with two disclaimers. One is that his work does not take into
account historical development of Dewey’s writings on international
politics. The second is that his work is ‘unabashedly speculative’ (Deen
2013: 112). In response to this, we can say that Deen’s work need not be
speculative as creative democracy through social intelligence was what
Dewey wished to come to pass both at home and aboard. As Dewey
stated in 1944:
Just as genuinely peaceful relations amongst nations cannot be secured
save by systematic intelligent study, foresight and planning, so with
Social Intelligence and Equality
97
democracy within a nation. The development of procedures and
techniques, legal, political, economic, which will foster and sustain
equal freedom for all, instead of irresponsible freedom for a few and
constraint and depression for the many, is the outstanding social
problem of our age. It requires the kind of vigilance which is positively
expressed in study, planning, experimentation, to establish institutions
which will make equality of opportunity and hence freedom realities
for all – not slogans to be manipulated by a class for its one separate
interest. (LW17: 462)
Moreover, had Deen examined Dewey’s work on international politics
and the need for creative democracy at the international level, he
would have found arguments that both support and extend beyond
his own ideas. Dewey believed that the ethical commitment of
democracy as a way of life and social intelligence must be supported at
the international level. However, Dewey did not just throw his weight
behind a regime that would secure a global minimalism that would
only free people from great want, oppression or ignorance. Rather,
Dewey extended his arguments about equality and democracy within
the confines of bourgeois democracy at home into the international
arena of the Great Society.
As Dewey outlined, the ideas of philosophical liberalism about
equality and liberty seemed even more hegemonic at the international
level. This regime of ‘free-trade’ was ‘hopelessly defective’ because it
failed to see how ‘intelligent supervision’ and ‘positively controlling
action’ were needed to maintain ‘equality of conditions’ (MW11: 141).
This state of affairs had led to a game of ‘rivalry and competition in
industry and nationalistic ambitions’ that had ‘extended to become
a deadly competition in all the means of destruction’ (LW17: 454).
Nations and their publics now routinely neglected the social aspects of
their interdependence and saw global interdependence as a zero-sum
game:
Bad results work both ways. In order to compete with other nations, a
competition artificially made harder by the present system of barriers,
labour standards are lowered at home. Then other nations find that
98
John Dewey
unless wages are reduced at home and labour speeded up, they are at
a disadvantage. Their standards are put in peril. We have made almost
universal the inquiry of Cain: “Am I my brother’s keeper?” We have
erected indifference and antagonism into a positive virtue, although
we know in domestic affairs that depression of one group and section,
means loss to all others. (LW11: 262)
As early as Dewey’s post–First World War writings, one can glean a
sense of disdain for such liberal ideas about international free trade and
the global economy and how such ideas expressed themselves through
imperialism, asymmetric North/South relations and large-scale
inequalities. As Dewey outlined in 1918 on the subject of President
Wilson’s new diplomacy, the League of Nations and economic freedom,
these material inequalities ultimately prohibited the extension of
democracy as a way of life at the international level:
It has been demonstrated that more is needed to secure freedom and
equality of conditions between individuals than to declare them legally
all free and equal, while leaving them to unrestricted competition with
one another. Immense inequality of power is compatible with formal
equality. The same thing will surely develop with respect to any merely
legal equality among nations. Certain nations have a tremendous
superiority in population, natural resources, technical progress in
industry, command of credit, and shipping. Nothing better calculated
to develop inequality of trade relationship among nations could well
be found than a system which set up a nominal mathematical equality
and then threw matters practically into the hands of the present big
nations. (MW 11: 139)
Dewey’s idea of equality between nations thus did not centre on free
trade within a liberal-capitalist global economy but a system of trade
and commerce that would eradicate imperialism and inequality in its
economic, political and cultural manifestations. This resembled a form
of democratic socialism at international level and would require, as
Dewey outlined at the end of the First World War, a global economy
that was democratically controlled, and international organizations
that could deal with matters such as ‘equality of labour standards, the
Social Intelligence and Equality
99
regulation of shipping … of food, raw materials and immigrants, and
above all else the exportation of capital and distribution of the available
credit of the world. Equality of trade conditions means equalisation
of conditions’ (MW11: 139–40). Global democracy for Dewey would
therefore require that rich nations of the world give up their hegemonic
control of the global economy and allow the self-government and
development of wealth amongst poor nations (Westbrook 1991: 237).10
What the above reveals is that Dewey believed that the practice of
creative democracy through social intelligence between nations was
unlikely to transpire within a global regime based on liberal capitalism.
This is quite simply because the global economic regime based on the
tenets of liberal capitalism, as it was at home within the nation state,
was antithetical towards creating or allowing a context in which such a
state of affairs could arise. In short, a liberal-capitalist global economy
would always be focused on profit, imperialism and empire rather
than democracy as a way of life. To provide the conditions that would
allow all members of the world to potentially live the democratic way
of life and participate in social intelligence would require furnishing
conditions for political equality and of economic development
(political, educational, scientific, industrial) that would allow for
democratic habits of social intelligence to become widespread both
at home and abroad. Thus, Dewey did not believe that transforming
the Great Society into the Great Community at international level was
simply about managing the economic interdependence of nations or
creating equal political standing between nation states. Rather, given
the forces of industry the Great Society had unleashed, what was needed
was a fundamental reformation of the global liberal-capitalist economy
and a form of political and economic equality at the global level. This
democratic distribution of liberties in the international arena would
allow countries to embark upon pathways that would allow them to
acquire and utilize the habits of social intelligence and in turn facilitate
the democratic way of life between countries.11
Towards the end of the Second World War, Dewey repeated this
argument that democracy at the international level also required
100
John Dewey
a democratic distribution of liberties and that to achieve such a
distribution of liberties required a fundamental reconfiguration of ideas
of equality and liberty and political economy in the international arena:
The opportunities for us, the people of the United States, will be
tremendous. A means for widely distributing the world’s goods among
all nations must be provided … A way of carrying health and education
and a higher standard of life to the utmost corners of the earth must be
assured. The mechanical means have already been produced by science
and invention. Physically, the world is now one and interdependent.
Only human beings – interested that men everywhere have a society
of peace, of security, of opportunity, of growth in cooperation – can
assure its being made morally one. A genuine democratic victory will
be achieved only when it is made by democratic governments for the
well-being of the common people of the earth. (LW17: 131–2)
When it comes to issues of global distributive justice, we can say that
Dewey was far more radical than critics and supporters are willing to
give him credit for. Dewey seems to have been a democratic socialist,
both at home and abroad, because the inefficiency of wasting our
human resources was not just an American issue but also a global issue.
Wasting of such resources not only was a moral problem, which denied
various individuals and publics access to the democratic way of life,
but was symptomatic of how the Great Society was split between the
two worlds of the pre-scientific and the scientific. This not only cost
everyone the potential of individual intelligences, who perished each
year to the effects of stratification, but such a social order also negatively
effected ‘effective intelligence’ through the cultural subjugation of the
great mass of people and denied society and the world at the large the
fruits of using socialized intelligence to conduct its moral affairs.
For Dewey, bourgeois democracy and liberal capitalism, both
at home and abroad, were thus morally repugnant and physically
inefficient; a society which had managed to utilize the natural power
of steam, electricity and machines but failed to fully engage, enlist and
release available human energy (LW13: 312).12 The overriding point
Social Intelligence and Equality
101
of this chapter, however, is that Dewey did not believe such problems
would be solved without a fundamental reordering of political economy,
both at home and abroad, along the lines of economic equality. The
gains of the Great Society had quite simply created a situation, where it
would be impossible to create the ‘enduring opportunity for productive
and creative activity and all that signifies for the development of the
potentialities of human nature’ without ‘remaking the profit system’ in
the first instance (LW13: 318).13
5
New Lessons from the Old Professor
The finished and done with is of import as affecting the future, not on its
own account: in short, because it is not, really, done with. (MW10: 10)
We do not merely have to repeat the past, or wait for accident to force
change upon us. We use our past experiences to construct new and
better ones in the future. (MW12: 134)
Dewey’s focus on the ‘reconstruction’ of philosophical and political
concepts of democracy was linked, as McDermott (LW11: XXV) argues,
to a belief that history was a way of reconstructing the past. The meaning
of history was therefore always to be refracted through the perspectives
and needs of the present. With that in mind, after journeying through
the work of John Dewey and his views on global democracy, it seems
that we come to a logical set of questions concerning the relationship
between Dewey’s time and our own. How are we to use his work for
our own purposes? How does Dewey’s work help us contemplate and
theorize our present form of globalization? And how does Dewey’s
work inform an analysis of post-Westphalian ideas of global democracy
in the twenty-first century?
In the last chapter, I argued against the view that Dewey offered few
ideas about how to achieve democracy at home and abroad through
examining his views about economic equality. In this chapter, I
want to push this line of thought further by outlining what I believe
are the solutions Dewey offered to his own problematizing of global
democracy and how we can utilize these prescient lessons within our
own debates about the nature of global democracy. To highlight this,
the chapter will be split into two parts. In the first part, I will outline
104
John Dewey
four key Deweyan lessons about the problem of global democracy.
These centre on the nature of society and community, the role of the
nation state in furthering democracy beyond the nation state, the use
of democracy at home to create a rooted cosmopolitanism and the
problem of bourgeois democracy at home as the biggest impediment
to global democracy. What all these lessons highlight is how Dewey
believed that the problem of democracy at home needed to be tackled
in order to facilitate democracy abroad. In the second part, I use these
lessons to re-evaluate contemporary ideas about post-Westphalian
global democracy and how Dewey’s work can offer new ways of
appraising global democracy.
Lesson 1: A Great Society does not equal
a Great Community
One of the most galling aspects Dewey would have encountered when
reading modern ideas about global democracy is how such theorists
often conflate the division between society and community and neglect
the implications of such a division. From a Deweyan perspective,
the first lesson we can learn about global politics is to hold a healthy
and historically based scepticism of narratives where our current
period of globalization and advancement in modern communications
technology or industrial co-operation are said to presuppose the
emergence of ‘communities of fate’, ‘transnational public spheres’ or
any other movement towards a global community. Whilst we may live
in a globalized world, it does not automatically mean that our political
ideals and identities have also become globalized. Moreover, Dewey
provides a historical lesson that such globalized conditions may not
necessarily lend themselves to the actual emergence of what he took to
be community both on a national and on a global level. For example,
Dewey outlines that:
Associated or joint activity is a condition of the creation of a
community. But association itself is physical and organic, while
New Lessons from the Old Professor
105
communal life is moral, that is emotionally, intellectually, consciously
sustained. Human beings combine in behaviour as directly and
unconsciously as do atoms, stellar masses and cells … They do so
in virtue of their own structure, as man and woman unite, as the
baby seeks the breast and the breast is there to supply its need.
They do so from external circumstances, pressure from without, as
atoms combine or separate in presence of an electric charge, or as
sheep huddle together from the cold. Associated activity needs no
explanation; things are made that way. But no amount of aggregated
collective action of itself constitutes a community … Even if “society”
were as much an organism as some writers have held, it would not
on that account be society. Interactions, transactions, occur de
facto and the results of interdependence follow. But participation in
activities and sharing in results are additive concerns. They demand
communication as a prerequisite. (LW2: 330)
This distinction between society and community held, for Dewey,
not just across local and national societies but also the international
associative relationships created by the advent of the Great Society.
Although the associative relationships and technological advancements
engendered by the Great Society created large-scale global
interdependence and industrial co-operation, Dewey did not believe
that such conditions alone were sufficient to create, politically and
morally, a Great Community. In fact, Dewey believed technological
advancements and the accompanying new habits and social customs,
engendered by the Great Society’s associative relationships, to actually be
counterproductive to ideas of community. For instance, we have already
seen that Dewey thought that the mass communication revolution
(wireless telegraphs, telephones, radio) did not by default create a
greater sense of community, or rather the type of communication that
generated a sense of community, both within and beyond the nation
state. This is even the case when the ‘global’ context is actively part of
our daily discussions:
We cannot pick up a daily newspaper in which the word “global”
does not remind us of the new situation in which we live physically,
106
John Dewey
but without the intellectual, the educational, the moral preparation
that might enable us to cope with the problems it thrusts upon us.
(LW17: 454)
Dewey was adamant that a democratic community was enacted
through the conscious creation of signs and symbols, habits of thought,
language and action and institutions which ‘ … add the function of
communication in which emotions and ideas are shared as well as joint
undertakings engaged in’ (LW13: 176). The emergence and conditions
of the Great Society did not automatically lend themselves towards
the creation of a Great Community but rather held the potential to
facilitate such a goal. In short, the global public or rather global publics
will not emerge without conscious action and the conscious dispersion
of democratic habits that induce social intelligence both within and
beyond the nation state. Dewey therefore provides us with the lesson
that democratic communication through habits of social intelligence
and the subsequent practice of creative democracy are not things that
merely arise from an interdependent society, whether that be across a
nation state or the globe, but rather need to be established on the back
of the interdependence which arises from societal associations.1
Lesson 2: The Great Community and the nation
The discussion of forming a Great Community brings us to the
question of the best means of bringing about such a Great Community
and the forms of government that would serve it. One of the chief
lessons of Dewey’s work on the potential for global democracy is that
it must include, and also arise within, the nation state. Examining
Dewey’s account of the Great Society, we can see that his work
highlights that the collapse of modern sovereignty is actually a lot
older than we care to admit. Throughout the 1920s and 1930s, Dewey
continually highlighted how the interdependence of the world’s
nations had not only seen consequences of associated human action
become transnational but also how these transnational consequences
New Lessons from the Old Professor
107
affected the ability of nation states to govern properly (LW11: 262). In
fact, writing in 1944, Dewey mocked the idea of national sovereignty,
arguing that ‘something that is wholly unreal in the present state of the
world’ was being appealed to and employed as if it had ‘significance’
(LW17: 455). It was on the back of these conditions and outdated
policies of nation states that Dewey constructed his own arguments for
the extension of democracy globally and took to task what he saw as
a bullheaded nationalism which turned ‘indifference and antagonism
into a positive virtue’ in the face of such global interdependence. His
subsequent conclusion was that the doctrine of national ‘sovereignty’,
which had buttressed regressive protectionism, quests of autarky and
global war, was a complete denial of the political responsibility nation
states had towards one another (LW2: 376).
In the light of such statements, one might infer that Dewey would
take the national political arena and nationalism to be mere transitory
stages in the extension of global democracy. In this sense, the extension
of democracy as a way of life would be best served by politically
empowering those affected by the consequences of associated action,
irrespective of nationality, through cosmopolitan law, global civil
society, a transnational public sphere or supranational democratic
institutions. After all, as Dewey made clear, political democracy was
only effective when the ‘government exists to serve its community, and
that this purpose cannot be achieved unless the community itself shares
in selecting governors and determining their policies’ (LW2: 327).
Dewey was also under no illusion that the Great Society must become
a Great Community that it should be the Great Community that picks
its governors.
The problem with this account, however, is whilst Dewey (LW2: 377)
recognized the decline of modern sovereignty and his anti-essentialism
saw him claim that ‘The State is pure myth’, he also understood that
the loyalty of citizens to the cultural membership of the nation and its
political fusion in the nation state would have to be taken seriously if
global democracy was to be successful (LW15: 208–9). Dewey argued
that the rise of European nationalism, which was cemented by the
108
John Dewey
Napoleonic Wars and the resistance to foreign rule, had created a
form of nationalism that consolidated ‘formerly disperse political
and social forces’ (LW15: 208). However, this ‘modern state unity’
had been created not only by resistance to foreign rule but also by
the Great Society’s technological advancements (railways, telegraph
and telephone). These technological advancements in turn created
not only the aforementioned economic interdependence amongst the
citizens of the nation state, but even more importantly the ‘rapid and
easy circulation’ of opinion and information, which created a national
identity beyond the face-to-face communities of people’s daily lives and
laid the possibility of new forms of national democratic government
(LW2: 306–7). This process of cultural membership, contended Dewey,
creates a national ‘culture’ which is exemplified in ‘ … ways of living so
ingrained by long habituation that they form the very fibre of a people’.
And as the interwar and post–world war periods had made clear, this
fibre was so tough ‘that it will resist, often unto death, attempts made
from without to destroy it’ (LW15: 208).2
At the start of the twentieth century, then, Dewey recognized what
modern writers such as Anderson (1991) and Billig (1995) have pointed
out, which is that nation states offer not only legal inclusion but a
cultural membership that is always in the process of being remade. Such
nationalism, with its exclusive and aggressive side, forms a ‘conspicuous’
obstacle towards global democracy. However, Dewey also noted that
nationalism was ‘two-sided’ and that the sense of wider social order and
organization provided by the nation state and its nationalism should
be seen as ‘positive advance’ (LW15: 208–9). By this, Dewey viewed
the nation state as a serious unit of social action not only because of
the aggressive side of nationalism but because it was exactly one of
those means which have been most expedient in the pursuit of the
ethical commitment of democracy as a way of life. The nation state
was therefore valuable because it was capable of upholding a national
democratic community and a national practice of creative democracy.
With both sides of nationalism in mind, Dewey argued that the
nation state and its institutions of democracy could not simply be
New Lessons from the Old Professor
109
deemed surplus to requirements or superseded but must play an active
part of global democracy:
A wider community of interests cannot possibly be attained by the
negative process of wiping out the communities of belief, action and
mutual support which have behind them centuries of loyalty. Without
a basis in them, a world government would lead a precarious existence.
If such a government is to deserve the hearty support of the peoples of
the earth, it must actively enlist the energies of the national states as
dependable organs for execution of its politics. It can accomplish this
result only as those policies give the social value of the National States a
more secure opportunity to flourish than they now possess. (LW15: 209)
Whilst this belief was based on the power of nationalism and national
democracy, Dewey also understood the sheer naked power of the nation
state. Even within the parameters of declining modern sovereignty,
given the role of the nation state in underwriting the structure of the
global economy and international institutions, the nation state and,
more importantly, national democracy would have to be key focal
points of any global democracy. As Dewey’s views on the nature of
international political economy and political experiments such as the
League of Nations highlight, it would simply be impossible to reform
the global economy without changing the policies of powerful nation
states. The lesson Dewey therefore provides here for twenty-first
century observers is that global democracy, which depends on forms
of transnational communication and collaboration, equally cannot
function on the reification of the global at the expense of the nation
state and its politics.3
Lesson 3: Democracy begins at home
A Deweyan position mandates that we take the nation state as one
of the primary building blocks of any global democracy. The logical
consequence of this appraisal of how global democracy could best
be enacted is Dewey’s subsequent lesson that national conditions of
110
John Dewey
democracy and community are pivotal to forming a Great Community
and the practice of global democracy. Moreover, Dewey suggests that
without the pursuit of democracy as a way of life and the practice of
creative democracy within the local community, there is little chance
of the pursuit of democracy as a way of life and practice of creative
democracy through social intelligence beyond the nation state:
It is said, and said truly, that for the world’s peace it is necessary that we
understand the peoples of foreign lands. How well do we understand,
I wonder, our next-door neighbors? It has also been said that if a man
love not his fellow man who he has seen, he cannot love the God
whom he has not seen. The chances of regard for distant peoples being
effective as long as there is no close neighbourhood experience to bring
with it insight and understanding of neighbors do not seem better. A
man who has not been seen in the daily relations of life may inspire
admiration, emulation, servile subjection, fanatical partisanship, hero
worship; but not love and understanding, save as they radiate from the
attachments of near-by union. Democracy must begin at home, and its
home is the neighborly community. (LW2: 368)
The above highlights two interrelated points about the role of the
local and national community in the pursuit of global democracy. The
first is that the local community, the one of face-to-face intercourse
in institutions such as the family, school and neighbourhood, is
pivotal in forming other forms of community such as a possible Great
Community within the nation state and beyond. This is because it is
within these daily and ‘face to face’ relations that the primary aspects
of communication and habits of social intelligence take place. It was
therefore within the neighbourly community that the ideals and practice
of pursuing a democratic way of life would be taught, learned and put
into initial practice. This is why Dewey said that the daily interactions
and discourse between members of the local neighbourhood were the
‘heart and final guarantee of democracy’ (LW14: 227).
The second point is that the local is fundamentally informed and
affected by the national and the international dimensions of a globalized
world. The Great Society was taken by Dewey to invade and destroy
New Lessons from the Old Professor
111
elements of local communities and led to the ‘immediate source of
the instability, disintegration and restlessness which characterise the
present epoch’ (LW2: 367). Dewey was adamant that only with the
reformation of local community would democracy and community be
achievable both within and beyond the state:
Whatever the future may have in store, one thing is certain. Unless
local communal life can be restored, the public cannot adequately
resolve its most urgent problem: to find and identify itself. But if it
be reestablished, it will manifest a fullness, variety and freedom of
possession and enjoyment of meanings and goods unknown in the
contiguous associations of the past. For it will be alive and flexible
as well as stable, responsive to the complex and world-wide scene
in which it is enmeshed. While local, it will not be isolated. Its
larger relationships will provide an inexhaustible and flowing fund
of meanings upon which to draw, with assurance that its drafts will
be honoured … We lie, as Emerson said, in the lap of an immense
intelligence. But that intelligence is dormant and its communications
are broken, inarticulate and faint until it possesses the local community
as its medium. (LW2: 370–2)
What should be noted here is that Dewey was not calling for a nostalgic
return to the local democracy that was once characterized by the
local ‘town-meeting’. Dewey understood that the old ideas of local
community town hall meetings that once animated local democracy
were now outdated and unable to cope with the engendering of ‘national
affairs – now also affected by world affairs’ (LW13: 95). Whilst Dewey
argued for a reconstruction of the local community, this was to be a local
community that possessed publics who were adapted to the national
and global conditions of the Great Society. The regulation of the Great
Society through creative democracy may have depended on a vibrant
practice of democratic habits within the local community but Dewey
was aware that this could only be facilitated through a national and, in
turn, international form of Great Community and creative democracy.
Dewey was not a nostalgic advocate of localism but an advocate of a
localism now linked to and prepared for the wider world.4
112
John Dewey
This brought Dewey back to the problems of ‘home’ but this time in
the guise of the national community and nation state. The reconstruction
of the local community was only possible, Dewey suggested, on the
back of a national form of democratic socialism and social intelligence.
Furthermore, democracy beyond the state also depended on the vitality
of creative democracy within the nation state:
Our first defence is to realize that democracy can be served only
by the slow day by day adoption and contagious diffusion in every
phase of our common life of methods that are identical with the ends
to be reached and that recourse to monistic, wholesale, absolutist
procedures is a betrayal of human freedom no matter in what guise
it presents itself. An American democracy can serve the world only
as it demonstrates in the conduct of its own life the efficacy of plural,
partial and experimental methods in securing and maintaining an
ever-increasing release of the powers of human nature, in service of
a freedom which is cooperative and a cooperation which is voluntary.
(LW13: 187)
Without citizens and publics who can comprehend the complexity and
transnational nature of the Great Society and renew democracy as a
way of life within the nation state, there is no chance of real political
innovation beyond the nation state. The pursuit of global democracy
therefore needs publics at home who could not only communicate or
organize politically on a transnational basis with other publics, but
who could also uphold a form of democratic community and creative
democracy at home, which through the use of social intelligence would
live up to the ideal of democracy as a way of life both nationally and
internationally.
This reveals that Dewey’s approach to global democracy was
ultimately one of a ‘rooted cosmopolitanism’ (Bernstein 2010: 88),
whereby democracy at home would be key to forging and encouraging
democracy abroad. This is an approach where publics approach the
global, including transnational activism, in the space of nation states
and the resources and opportunities of that national context (Tarrow
2005: 42). This would entail citizens not only creating transnational
New Lessons from the Old Professor
113
publics but also seeing their nation state’s role in the world not just
as a form of moral charity but as a form of political responsibility.
This form of political responsibility would include an ethical foreign
policy, the use of multilateralism by their leaders to pursue social
intelligence between states and an acknowledgement by nation
state leaders of transnational publics (Cochran 2001: 56). Above all,
however, it would require citizens within nation states to be willing
to change their own habits and forms of associative action in order
to provide and maintain the democratic way of life for those beyond
their borders.5 As Dewey outlined when commentating on the
practice of economic imperialism by US capital and the support of
such imperialism by the US state, there was no chance of real political
innovation in the relations between the United States and nations it
held economic hegemony over without changes in policy and habits
within the United States and publics within the United States who
could bring such change forward:
Public opinion has spoken with unusual force and promptitude
against interference in Mexico. But the causes of the difficulty, the
underlying forces which make for imperialistic ventures, are enduring.
They will outlast peaceful escape from the present crisis, supposing
we do escape. Public sentiment, to be permanently effective, must
do more than protest. It must find expression in a permanent change
of our habits. For at present, both economic conditions and political
arrangements and traditions combine to make imperialism easy. How
many American citizens are ready for an official restatement of the
Monroe Doctrine? (LW3: 162)
This view of the need to establish democracy at home in order to help
facilitate democracy abroad can also be found in Dewey’s thought on
the school system in the midst of totalitarianism. Dewey saw the nation’s
school system as not just a place of training for industry, but also an
underutilized arena where there could be a positive and constructive
cultivation of the democratic way of life both within and beyond the
nation state. Dewey believed that the school, as an institution that
taught the democratic way of life, could be reformed and better utilized
114
John Dewey
to ‘ … break down class division, creating a feeling of greater humanity
and of a membership in a single family …’ through spreading the
habits of social intelligence (LW13: 302). However, Dewey reiterated
that he saw this relationship as one where such a global commitment
to democracy as a way of life abroad would only be secured through
democracy as a way of life at home:
What do we mean when we assume that we, in common with
certain other nations, are really democratic, that we have already
so accomplished the ends and purposes of democracy that all
we have to do is to stand up and resist the encroachments of nondemocratic states? We are unfortunately familiar with the tragic racial
intolerance of Germany and now Italy. Are we entirely free from that
racial intolerance, so we can pride ourselves upon having achieved a
complete democracy? Our treatment of the Negroes, anti-Semitism,
the growing (at least I fear it is growing) serious opposition to the
alien immigrant within our gates, is, I think, a sufficient answer to
that question. Here, in relation to education, we have a problem; what
are our schools doing to cultivate not merely passive toleration that
will put up with people of different racial birth or different colored
skin, but what are our schools doing positively and aggressively and
constructively to cultivate understanding and goodwill which are
essential to democratic society? (LW13: 301)
Without the realization and practical experience of what ‘cooperation,
goodwill and mutual understanding’ looked like at home, Dewey feared
that the ideas of peace that schools were doing a great deal to ‘inculcate’
would go little beyond ‘sentimental attachment to a realisation of what
peace would actually mean in the world …’ (LW13: 303). This reflection
on education was, in a sense, a microcosm of Dewey’s belief that
democracy abroad was always linked with democracy at home. It is not
just that we cannot examine the chances of global democracy without
taking into consideration the status and vitality of our democracy at
home, but rather that without a strong form of creative democracy at
home, at both the local and national level, there will never be creative
democracy away and beyond from home. This is the case even if our
New Lessons from the Old Professor
115
ultimate goal is to make the ‘away and beyond’ our ‘home’ in the final
instance.6
Lesson 4: The spectre of bourgeois democracy
must be exorcised!
A fuller appreciation of Dewey’s work reveals that whilst he embraced
multiple routes towards global democracy, he also believed that those
routes must include the nation state and the vitality of the local and
national community. This point is exemplified in the double mandate
Dewey gave his call for democratic renewal within the American
nation state. The democratic community within the nation state,
Dewey argued, needed to become a Great Community (democratic
community) that would help facilitate a Great Community beyond
and between nation states. Only through this process would the world
secure the democratic way of life for all humans and reap the benefits of
social intelligence. However, this brought Dewey back to the problem
of bourgeois democracy and the eclipse of the public within the nation
state and how bourgeois democracy as an economic, cultural and
political formation was fundamentally at odds with creative democracy
within and beyond the state.
The main problem that Dewey identified with bourgeois democracy
and its influence on global democracy is that the material and cultural
inequalities engendered by liberal capitalism are the product of the
hegemonic cultural ideas of liberal capitalism (individualism, liberty,
profit), which are antithetical to the spread of democratic habits of
social intelligence within the nation state. This was confined not only
to the level of the nation state but at the international level, where
the doctrine of liberal capitalism and free trade between states
underpinned a regime of imperialism and inequality between the
global North and South. However, Dewey pushes beyond simply
equating the culture of liberal capitalism as being incompatible with
creative democracy at home and abroad by positing a fundamental
116
John Dewey
relationship between the lack of democracy at home and the lack of
democracy abroad.
Moreover, Dewey highlights how the hegemony of the tenets of
liberal capitalism and the perpetuation of high levels of material and
intellectual inequality within nation states, what Dewey called bourgeois
democracy, often bred an anti-cosmopolitan nationalism and the
rejection of greater democracy and co-operation at the international
level amongst citizens and their governments. This is why Dewey was
adamant that it was the eclipse of the public and the breakdown of
creative democracy at a national level that explained the lack of global
democracy. Dewey therefore extends his narrative of the collapse of
community and democracy at the local and national level into the
narrative of why the democratic community and creative democracy
are absent abroad. The lesson Dewey provides here is that democracy
abroad fails due to the same reason democracy at home fails: the eclipse
of the public engendered by the cultural and structural inequalities of
bourgeois democracy.
Dewey’s reflection on the relationship between bourgeois
democracy and global democracy therefore outlines his thinking on
the relationship between liberal capitalism and democracy. This pivots
on Dewey’s belief that the ideas and virtues of liberal capitalism are
fundamentally unable to support democracy at home or abroad. To this
end, the cultural hegemony of the former must be tackled in order to
facilitate the emergence of the latter. We have, of course, seen that Dewey
was adamant that without the provision of democratic knowledge and
habits facilitating social intelligence within social institutions, such
as political democracy and education, there was little to no chance
of creative democracy at the national level and smaller chance of
creative democracy beyond the state. However, Dewey’s overriding
message was that for the above to happen there must be a fundamental
reorganization of liberal capitalism and its ideas of individualism and
liberty. This, as we have seen, was Dewey’s argument for the extension
of a form of democratic socialism and egalitarianism both at home and
abroad.7
New Lessons from the Old Professor
117
This reflection on the incompatibility of liberal capitalism and
democracy and its effects on hopes for democracy beyond the state
has knock-on effects on how we should judge Dewey’s idea that
democracy abroad would only be truly effective on the basis of
democracy at home. Dewey’s perspective of the nation state as a key
vehicle for global democracy translates into the view that we cannot
disconnect the current state of national democracy, or a lack of
national democracy within bourgeois democracy, from the issues of
forming a Great Community and practising creative democracy both
within and beyond the state. Although Dewey (LW5: 442) claimed
that national democratic practices and institutions had become the
‘the errand boys’ of a ‘privileged plutocracy’ and were inflexible
and uncreative under the hegemony of bourgeois democracy, it was
nevertheless:
… sheer defeatism to assume in advance of actual trial that democratic
political institutions are incapable either of further development or of
constructive social application. Even as they now exist, the forms of
representative government are potentially capable of expressing the
public will when that assumes anything like unification. (LW11: 60)
The analytical lesson Dewey provides is that the interconnection
between the auspices of bourgeois democracy and the possibility of
global democracy is exactly why political democracy at home cannot
simply be transcended or deemed unimportant when examining global
democracy. Quite simply, the issue of who controls the nation state and
its institutions and whose interests it serves are too important to the
founding of a Great Community and the practice of creative democracy
internationally:
The dominant issue is whether the people of the United States are to
control our government, federal, state and municipal, and to use it in
behalf of the peace and welfare of society or whether control is to go
on passing into the hands of small powerful economic groups who use
all the machinery of administration and legislation to serve their own
ends. (LW6: 149)
118
John Dewey
Dewey believed that democratic renewal at home must include a
reorganization of both the politics and political economy of bourgeois
democracy. This demanded the re-emergence of publics within nation
states from their perpetual eclipse in the face of the Great Society and
their use of creative democracy through the lens of social intelligence.
However, this also demands publics who see that only radical reform
of the political economy of bourgeois democracy will facilitate such
change (LW11: 298–9).
This reveals Dewey’s final lesson on the fate of global democracy
in the midst of the Great Society. The renewal of democracy at home
demanded the guarantee of the ethical commitment of the democratic
way of life and the practising of creative democracy through a
community of citizens who possessed the habits of social intelligence.
Without such democratic renewal at home and the use of the nation state
to pursue a form of rooted cosmopolitism, it would be impossible, Dewey
argued, to achieve the change needed within the international sphere to
guarantee the democratic way of life. The chief point, however, is that
such a renewal of democracy at home would be half-hearted and unable
to secure creative democracy at home or abroad without the political
and cultural reorganization of bourgeois democracy at home and the
aspiration to effect change in the global liberal-capitalist economy. It was
Dewey’s hope that America would heed these words and embark upon
such a renewal of democracy at home that would provide the conditions
for America to help bring about creative democracy abroad:
With our fortunate position in the world I think that if we used
our resources, including our financial resources, to build up among
ourselves a genuine, true and effective democratic society, we would
find that we have a surer, a more enduring and a more powerful defence
of democratic institutions both within ourselves and with relation to
the rest of the world than the surrender to the belief in force, violence
and war can ever give. (LW13: 302–3)
This should be seen as the final element in Dewey’s lessons on the
relationship between local and national community and the hopes of
forging the Great Society into a Great Community both at home and
New Lessons from the Old Professor
119
abroad. Having identified that communities are conscious constructions
rather than automatically arising out of societal relations, and that
the nation state represented a form of political power and sense of
community that could not be easily discarded, Dewey naturally shifted
to examining how the politics of the nation and its idea of democratic
community could help facilitate democracy beyond the state. This not
only required the formation of a democratic community and social
intelligence at home but came with a warning that global democracy
would be bound to fail without the economic, cultural and political
exorcism of the spectres of bourgeois democracy that haunted the
Great Society.8
Global democracy: A new name for an old problem
John Dewey died in 1952, and his hopes for greater global
democracy have remained largely unfulfilled throughout the late
twentieth and early twenty-first centuries.9 However, as prior work on
his international thought has shown, it is quite easy to see Dewey as the
great resolver of the dualisms that plague the theorizations of global
democracy. We can therefore herald Dewey as providing an approach
to global democracy that challenges the dualisms between top-down
and bottom-up approaches to post-Westphalian global democracy,
and between statist and post-Westphalian democracy. Dewey believed
in not only macro-reform of international institutions and global
governance through a reformation of state relations but also bottomup processes of publics uniting across the global contours of the Great
Society. These ideas not only prefigure an increased role for global
governance institutions, such as the UN’s responsibility for human
security and networks of state special agencies, but also call for an
international public sphere of citizens, activists and social movements.
Dewey can therefore be seen as an early advocate of the management of
international interdependence through the multiple routes of state and
non-governmental institutions and practices (Cochran 2010: 323–8).
120
John Dewey
This take on Dewey’s approach to global democracy is superficially
correct: the dualisms between top-down and bottom-up ideas of
global democracy, and statist and post-Westphalian approaches to
global democracy are simply unsustainable. However, this narrative
still does not reveal the fullest expression of Dewey’s approach to
global democracy and how he fundamentally believed the problem
of bourgeois democracy at home impacted on democracy abroad.
The key lesson of Dewey’s work for ideas about global democracy is
that whilst a rejection of statist conclusions about global democracy
is correct, the importance of the nation state and the status of its
democracy and community cannot be discounted within non-statist
formulas. Dewey understood that without changes at the national
level and in particular its bourgeois democracy, which itself could
be helped through transnational communication and collaboration,
democracy beyond the state would be hampered and ineffective.
Dewey’s rooted cosmopolitanism was therefore just that: the strong
roots of democracy at home supported the crown of democracy
abroad.
This is not the unmasking of Dewey as a proxy statist who dismissed
the importance of transnational and non-governmental spaces, such
as global civil society and regional or global political forums. As we
saw in Chapter 2 and highlighted at the start of this chapter, Dewey
can be seen as a thinker who would breach the dualism between state
and post-Westphalian positions and between top-down and bottom-up
approaches to global democracy. Moreover, his evocation of global civil
society reflected his belief that citizens and publics could increase their
participation in global democracy through voluntary organizations
rather than just investing their hopes of global democracy in national
governments or other forms of bureaucracy (Cochran 2010: 327).
This would be equally important in the formation and conduct of
international institutions, which without the input of the masses of the
world would end up as elitist arenas dislocated from the concerns of
common humanity. However, Dewey believed that such tactics could
only be piecemeal or marginally successful if publics within the nation
New Lessons from the Old Professor
121
state did not support such causes and eventually achieve change at the
national level.
Dewey would have undoubtedly supported the use of global civil
society and transnational forms of activism and communication that
use ‘boomerang’ (Keck and Sikkink 1998) tactics to reach out from
local sites to global arenas in order to reverberate back on national
policy. Such forms of transnational activism and communication would
offer the signs and symbols needed to create elements of community
beyond the national context. This today would be what modern
writers call transnational coalition formation between publics across
borders (Tarrow 2011: 255). This assertion is strengthened by Dewey’s
own participation in such forms of activism as the Outlawry for War
Movement, the Council for a Democratic Germany, the League of Free
Nations and the American Friends for Spanish Democracy (Cochran
2010: 310). However, the American base of such activism highlights
Dewey’s view that without the power of the nation and the vitality of
the democratic community, at both the local and national level, there
was little chance of democracy beyond the nation state. Dewey’s ‘rooted
cosmopolitanism’ therefore reflects the term’s modern usage whereby
the conduct of global or transnational politics is always domestically
rooted (Appiah 1996, 2005: 213–72).
Indeed, contemporary conditions would seem to highlight the
continuing saliency and purchase of Dewey’s appraisal of global
democracy. Writers such as Tarrow (2011: 257) point to fact that ‘it has
become clear – if it was ever unclear’ at the dawn of the twenty-first
century, with American military power and government action to tackle
the 2008–2009 financial crisis, ‘that the power of states is not going
to disappear in short order’. Those sceptical of the economic reality
of globalization, for example, point to the persistence of nation state
power within the confines of neo-liberal globalization and its effects
upon modern sovereignty (Mosley 2005; Hay 2007; Hirst et al. 2009).
These authors argue that the nature of the flow of trade, investment
and finance reveals that the world economy is not global but rather a
highly ‘internationalized’ economy separated into a triad of trade blocs
122
John Dewey
(Europe, East Asia and North America). Whilst this has changed the
nature of global North/South relations, where select nations in the
global South have produced miraculous economic growth through
exports for consumption zones in the North, the reality is still a highly
uneven and unequal global economy largely controlled by and for the
global North. This is compounded by the reluctance of hegemonic
Western nation states, even in the face of rising Southern powers such
as Brazil, China and India, to cede their power within international
institutions, such as the UN, IMF and World Bank, and help facilitate
greater democracy at the international level (Wade 2013).
In fact, even the runaway world that is neoliberal globalization
can be regulated towards democratic ends by nation states. For
instance, Hirst et al. (2009) argue that the major economic powers of
the G8, China and India have the capacity, if they were to coordinate
multilaterally, to bring about greater democratic governance over
financial and other international economic practices. However, the
current scope of such governance is constrained by the interests of the
major economic powers and the hegemony of neo-liberalism amongst
political and economic elites (Hirst et al. 2009: 3; Weiss 2009). This
viewpoint has gained even more credence in the light of the 2008
financial crisis and the onset of the Great Recession, where the power
of the state to intervene in global markets and reform the international
order has been shown to outrank international institutions and
forums such as the UN, the IMF and the Basel Committee on Banking
Supervision (Rodrik 2012). This would seemingly make nation state
politics the key for any form of global democracy and is corroborated
by the fact that the majority of citizens still predominately value
their national identity over other allegiances and see their national
governments as the primary providers of public goods (Rodrik 2011;
Tarrow 2011).
Concurrently, our present forms of national political democracy are
said to be in crisis (Hay 2007). This pivots on the collapse of post-war
social democracy and the rise of neo-liberalism, which has engendered
large-scale wealth inequality and the hegemony of finance capitalism
over the state, its elites and citizens (Stiglitz 2010, 2012; Englen et al.
New Lessons from the Old Professor
123
2011; Wade 2012). This has seen the stagnation of political democracy
within the nation state, where national politicians and elites have
underwritten globalization and effectively outsourced, renounced or
relinquished elements of their political power over to global markets.
Concurrently, wealthy citizens whose interests are served by such an
ideology find great ease in bending the ear of government to their
interests (Gilens 2012). Neo-liberalism’s ‘atomisation of society, citizens,
and classes’ has brought forth a mass public who are now ‘consumers
of goods or information’ and have more trust in the Internet than their
political representatives (Mazower 2012: 425–6).
Does any of this sound familiar? Our current situation is based
upon rich Western nation states who control the global economy
and international institutions in their interests; the hegemony
of economic liberalism and its idea of economic liberty within
international and domestic political contexts; the control of national
democratic structures by wealthy citizens and the persistence of largescale inequality within state; and the continuing pull of nationalism
for modern citizens within nation states even in the midst of the
breakdown of trust between a large sway of those citizens and their
respective governments. Even though there has been so much change
since Dewey’s death, one could not paint a better picture of the
hegemony of liberal capitalism over democracy at the international
level and the persistence of bourgeois democracy at home.10 At the
start of the twenty-first century, the regime of liberal capitalism and
bourgeois democracy is still partying like it was 1929!11
With these facts in mind, the clamour for post-Westphalian global
democracy appears more like an evasion rather than a confrontation
of this reality (Chandler 2010). This conclusion becomes even more
apparent when one considers the reactions of advocates of postWestphalian global democracy to the failure to secure adequate forms
of global democracy. For example, Hale et al. (2013) see greater global
democracy facing ‘gridlock’ in the aftermath of the 2008 financial crisis
and in response to global problems such as climate change. This is
to be explained as the result of growing multipolarity and politicians
privileging national over global interests. Habermas (2012) and Beck
124
John Dewey
(2013) find the Eurozone crisis to be a political rather than economic
problem, which stems from national and European elites perpetuating
forms of ‘post-democratic bureaucratic rule’ and the lack of a European
identity and public sphere amongst the citizens of European nation
states. Bottom-up advocates such as Dryzek (2012) point to the inability
of global civil society to achieve significant change at the international
level and argue that this reveals the different nature of democracy at the
global level in contrast to democracy at the national level.
In seeming to ignore the realm of national democracy in order to
argue for global forms of democracy that transcend the state, these
authors fail to register how the crisis of democracy at home influences
the crisis of democracy abroad. For example, the gridlock facing
global multilateralism is not simply a case of growing multipolarity
or nationalism amongst politicians but also the hegemony of neoliberalism amongst political elites, anti-cosmopolitanism at home and
the fact that countries in the global North are unwilling to cede power
within international institutions. The same could be said for the neoliberal settlement that is currently being sought within the Eurozone,
where national politicians from northern European countries and
elites within institutions, such as the European Central Bank and the
IMF, appear to be defending the interests of European finance capital
by enforcing austerity on southern European countries (Blyth 2013).
This state of affairs remains unchallenged because, as Dryzek (2012)
himself laments, the political power associated with global democracy
from below is incapable of holding governments to account on such
issues.
National democracy and its vitality, as Dewey suggests, is one of the
keys to global democracy. Why, for example, are citizens not currently
forcing their national representatives to pursue greater multilateralism
and cede power at the international level? Why are citizens in northern
European states not forcing their governments to back the interests of
Europe’s citizens rather than its finance capital? Why are global issues
such as climate change not key issues for national publics? It is beyond the
focus of this present study to offer a full-blown empirical examination
New Lessons from the Old Professor
125
of these events but it is safe to say that the answers or at least a large part
of the answers to such questions would seemingly revolve around the
hegemony of bourgeois democracy and the eclipse of national publics,
who are unable to force their political representatives to pursue the
democratic way of life both at home and abroad. Moreover, Dewey’s
work reflects the work of modern writers such as Bandy and Smith
(2005: 293, cf. Smith 2008), who upon surveying transnational politics
have concluded that the success of global democracy must ‘ … rely on
well-established national or local movements’. Yet, this perspective is
lost in translation when post-Westphalian positions underplay the
role of the state and national democracy in the formation of global
democracy as a result of the obvious failures of statist positions.
From a Deweyan perspective, the challenge for conceptualizations of
global democracy must be to overcome the failings of post-Westphalian
ideas of global democracy without having recourse to statist solutions.
Rather than abandoning the realm of national democracy and the
nation state as defunct political spaces, we must examine the interplay
between the present regime of bourgeois democracy at home and
the hopes and practice of democracy beyond the nation state. This
opens up questions such as: How are our educational and wider
cultural practices facilitating global democracy through creating a
rooted cosmopolitanism? How are xenophobia and anti-cosmopolitan
attitudes linked to income inequality and democratic disillusionment
at home? What are the politics and policies through which we can help
rediscover the radical faith in democracy and bring forth publics which
can exorcise bourgeois democracy at home and abroad? And how is
this process helped or hindered by the machinations of globalization
and forces outside the state?
These are questions that go beyond mere academic reflection
and conjoin with the need for democratic renewal through political
activism at the local and national level. As Dewey and his own activism
of the 1930s remind us, we must fight for democratic renewal at home
to help facilitate democratic renewal abroad. However, what is clear
is that the nature, political efficacy or viability, of any conception of
126
John Dewey
‘global democracy’ in the twenty-first century can only be adequately
conceptualized by revisiting and confronting Deweyan concerns
about the political efficacy or viability of publics and their relation to
democratic praxis within the nation state. Contrary to post-Westphalian
positions on global democracy, the problems of democracy within
the nation state cannot be avoided or transcended simply by taking
democracy to transnational or global dimensions. Indeed, to phrase the
problem in this manner is to miss Dewey’s point altogether that without
democracy at home there is very little chance of democracy abroad.
Conclusion: Inheriting the Task
of Creative Democracy
At all events this is what I mean when I say that we now have to
re-create by deliberate and determined endeavour the kind of democracy
which in its origin one hundred and fifty years ago was largely the
product of a fortunate combination of men and circumstances. We have
lived for a long time upon that heritage that came to us from the happy
conjunction of men and events in an earlier day. The present state of
the world is more than a reminder that we have now to put forth every
energy of our own to prove worthy of our heritage. It is a challenge to
do for the critical and complex conditions of today what the men of an
earlier day did for simpler conditions. (LW14: 225)
The use of historical analogy is always a curious endeavour, as no
matter how similar such history is to the present day, the reality is
that history, by its very definition, can never be a true reflection of the
present. However, maybe the focus on reflection and symmetry is itself
a false endeavour and the use of history is best seen as providing extra
colour to the spectrum through which we view the present. Just like
the death of a dying star light-years away, then, the actual unfolding
of events and the lessons to be learnt from the past can only be truly
seen long after those events have actually taken place. The life and
work of John Dewey would seem to fit this characterization of history.
From within our present, Dewey’s work, which at its latest point is
still over sixty years old, seems to now offer fresh ways of seeing and
approaching our contemporary conundrum of managing globalization
along democratic lines.
The overriding point of Dewey’s work on democracy was that
democracy as a way of life, just as other forms of life, was not
128
John Dewey
something that could stand still. The democratic way of life must
always move towards meeting those challenges that are present and
those that will undoubtedly arise as the conditions of life change
(LW13: 299). The democratic ideal therefore always needs updating
and unpacking. If democracy were to stand still, it would surrender to
circumstance and start on the ‘backward road that leads to extinction’
(LW11: 182). It was this viewpoint that led Dewey towards becoming
a ‘global’ philosopher and global democrat. This was because Dewey
understood that the Great Society and the globalization and scientific
revolutions that underpinned it both demanded and offered potential
avenues to renew and refresh democracy as a way of life across and
between nation states. This held the potential of helping humanity not
only move forwards and away from extinction but also move towards
a more enhanced and enriched shared existence. This was the dual
promise Dewey saw in creative democracy and social intelligence
within a global Great Community.
In many ways, this narration of Dewey as a global democrat replicates
the contemporary call for the innovation of democracy beyond the
state. However, Dewey’s work also illuminates the blind spot of our
contemporary problematizations of globalization and democracy.
This centres on Dewey’s idea that democracy is not only simply about
governments, states and institutions but a form of life for all of us. It is
the spread of democratic habits and dispositions across and between
communities that offers us the best chance of renewing and refreshing
the democratic ideal in the midst of changing conditions:
… democracy is a personal way of individual life; that it signifies the
possession and continual use of certain attitudes, forming personal
character and determining desire and purpose in all the relations
of life. Instead of thinking of our own disposition and habits as
accommodated to certain institutions we have to learn to think of
the latter as expressions, projections and extensions of habitually
dominant personal attitudes. Democracy as a personal, an individual,
way of life involves nothing fundamentally new. But when applied it
puts a new practical meaning in old ideas. (LW14: 226)
Conclusion: Inheriting the Task of Creative Democracy
129
These words taken from his eightieth birthday address mark out
both Dewey’s great contribution and challenge as a global philosopher.
As this book has tried to show, Dewey’s contribution as a global
philosopher centres on the theorization of the link between democracy
at home and democracy abroad. The formation of the democratic
community at the international level is inherently dependant upon
the vitality of the community and the diffusion of democratic habits at
the national and local level. The possibility of democratic community
at the international level is therefore inherently dependant upon the
health and status of the democratic community at home. This in
turn always takes us back to Dewey’s identification of the problem of
bourgeois democracy both at home and abroad as the biggest obstacle
towards the emergence of creative democracy at home and abroad –
a situation that seemingly speaks directly to the social, economic and
political contours of our neo-liberal present.
Yet, if Dewey’s work brings into analytical focus how the problem of
democracy abroad is linked to the problem of bourgeois democracy at
home, then his work also challenges us to renew and refresh democracy
as a way of life in such circumstances. This is the idea that our democratic
inheritance is not static but that:
… every generation has to accomplish democracy over again for itself;
that its very nature, its essence, is something that cannot be handed on
from one person or one generation to another, but has to be worked
in terms of needs, problems and conditions of the social life of which,
as years go by, we are a part, a social life that is changing with extreme
rapidity from year to year. (LW13: 299)
The creative task facing us today very much resembles Dewey’s time,
in that we need to reformulate democracy in order to cope with
the contours of a globalized world. Yes, some of the details may be
different. However, when turning to modern issues that demand global
democracy, such as climate change and global inequality, it becomes
clear that the creative task facing us today is very much the same task
that faced Dewey: the eradication of capital’s hegemonic control over
democratic government and dispelling the political apathy such a state
130
John Dewey
of affairs casts over the masses. Our problem, just like Dewey’s, is how
to help reorganize the public towards the democratic way of life and
the practice of creative democracy. This requires that we recognize that
democracy abroad is only possible with democracy at home and that
we re-establish what Dewey called the ‘fighting faith’ of democratic
politics. These challenges mark the continuity between Dewey’s Great
Society and our own present of neo-liberal globalization and also the
continuing relevance of Dewey’s warning that the failure to meet such
a challenge would place humanity further along the road to extinction.
For humanity to survive, we must therefore use our democratic
inheritance to help us succeed in what Dewey (LW13: 303) called the
‘experiment in which we are all engaged, whether we want to be or not,
the greatest experiment of humanity’, that of living together in ways
in which life is profitable in the deepest sense of the word, not just for
some, but for all of humanity and the world we inhabit.
Notes
Introduction
1
2
3
4
Citations of John Dewey’s works are to The Collected Works of John
Dewey, edited by Jo Ann Boydston and published by Southern Illinois
University Press, 1967–90, and are indicated by EW (Early Works of John
Dewey), MW (Middle Works of John Dewey) or LW (Later Works of John
Dewey) followed by the respective volume and page numbers.
Globalization as a historical process is a much-contested field with
estimates of the rise of modern globalization ranging from the eleventh
century right up to the nineteenth century. I shall return to the history of
globalization and its relationship to Dewey’s work in Chapter 2.
The main policy recommendations of neo-liberal globalization basically
update eighteenth-century economic liberalism with modern-day
notions of political democracy and monopoly, for example, patent
law. However, neo-liberal globalization is still fundamentally founded
on the old liberal’s twin belief in the ‘efficient market hypothesis’ and
‘comparative advantage theory’. These two theories, when combined,
provide the foundation of the argument that the free market offers
maximum economic efficiency and growth, whilst government
intervention (capital controls, import quotas, welfare schemes) is
harmful because it reduces such competition. Such unhindered
competition on a global scale allocates national economies to areas of
specialization in which their production techniques are as high in value
as possible. For more details on the history of the rise of neo-liberal
globalization as a hegemonic economic paradigm and its political
implementation, see Harvey (2005), Dumenil and Levy (2004), Blyth
(2002) and Frieden (2006), and for an insightful account of the rise of
neo-liberalism outside the West, see Prashad (2013).
Westbrook’s words were undoubtedly aimed at Richard Rorty and his use
of Dewey’s philosophy. It is beyond doubt that Rorty’s Philosophy and the
Mirror of Nature (1979), more or less, single-handedly revived interest in
Dewey’s philosophy. However, Rorty’s interpretation of Dewey is far from
132
Notes
accepted and has been deemed erroneous by more than one Deweyan
scholar (see Westbrook 1991: 540–1, 2005: see Chapter 6 for a summary
of the differences between Dewey and Rorty’s version of Dewey). Rorty’s
(1989: 38) response to such criticisms was to argue that he was simply
making up ‘imaginative playmates’ for both himself and his readers and
that the accuracy of these playmates to their original inspirations was not
important.
Chapter 1
1
2
3
4
I say pretence because America in 1927 cannot be deemed a full
democracy in the normal liberal sense because most of its African
American population did not possess the ability to participate fully in
civil or political life. America became a full liberal democracy only in
1965 with the passing of the Voting Rights Act, which built on the Civil
Rights Act of 1964, to stop racist-inspired literacy tests and poll taxes
preventing African American citizens from taking up their right to vote.
This process was largely achieved through direct state intervention and
the ‘infant industry’ protection devised by Alexander Hamilton and the
use of high industrial tariffs – a practice that saw America enforce the
highest industrial tariffs of any developed nation right up until 1945. See
Chang (2003, 2007) and Lind (2012).
For example, whereas prior to 1890 manufacturing could be completed
in small factories, after 1890 the average plant size in industries such as
automobiles increased immensely. The average car plant in 1909 had
around 200 workers and produced ten cars per week; by 1929, this figure
had turned into 1,000 workers and more than 400 cars per week. This
meant that although in 1929 there were fewer car plants than there had
been in 1909, car production in 1929 (5.4 million) far outstripped the
1909 figure (126,000) and the average American worker now produced
ten times as many cars (Frieden 2006: 61–3, 161).
For Dewey, democratic realism represented a revival of the Platonic
notion of philosopher kings, substituting the expert for the philosopher
because ‘philosophy has become something of a joke, while the
image of the specialist, the expert in operation, is rendered familiar
Notes
5
6
7
8
133
and congenial by the rise of the physical sciences and the conduct of
industry’ (LW2: 363).
Please note that although I shall primarily focus here on Dewey’s The
Public and Its Problems (LW2), when necessary I shall also utilize work
that precedes and succeeds the aforementioned title. The reason for
doing this, as noted by others such as Kadlec (2007: 100) and Campbell
(1995: 147), revolves around the incremental appreciation of economics
and politics that Dewey’s social philosophy exhibits from the First
World War onwards through the Great Depression in works such as
Individualism Old and New (LW5), Liberalism and Social Action (LW11)
and the onset of the Second World War in works such as Freedom and
Culture (LW13). Indeed, Axel Honneth (1998) believes that The Public
and Its Problems marks a wholesale shift, whereby Dewey throws off his
previous Hegelian shackles and finds a more coherent argument to justify
democracy. Thus, despite his earlier political radicalism, The Public
and Its Problems marks a focal point in the trajectory of Dewey’s social
philosophy.
Dewey’s conception of individuality as not being originally given but
constructed under the influences of associated living is evident from his
earliest writings (EW1: 48–9), but finds its most sustained expression
in Human Nature and Conduct (MW14). For Dewey’s take on Darwin’s
influence on his philosophy, see the essays in MW4 and for his thoughts
on William James, see the essay ‘The Vanishing Subject in the Psychology
of James’ (LW14: 155–67).
It should also be noted that native biological instincts or impulses are not
deemed by Dewey to be non-existent but rather dynamically interpreted
and structured into ways of behaving with the environment through
habits. For instance, the impulse of hunger does not ordinarily, except
in situations of starvation, define the means of its pacification. Rather,
the pacification of the impulse is determined through the ways (habits)
humans have formed or have found access to food in their environment
(See MW14: Chapter 12).
The conception of cultural matrix being utilized here originates from
Logic: The Theory of Inquiry (LW12) and not The Public and Its Problems,
but its assumptions are easily found throughout Dewey’s prior work in
general.
134
9
10
11
12
13
Notes
There are many private associations, such as the family, in which as a
society we deem it necessary for public bodies to intervene in (e.g. social/
child services). Commentators such as Gouinlock (LW2: xxv) therefore
argue that Dewey would have been better off speaking of the problem of
regulating the adverse consequences of social behaviour per se. However,
as outlined earlier, Dewey does this and more by acknowledging that
the very definition of public and private is historically relative, open to
contestation and ultimately defined by those within a society. In short,
Dewey’s position leads us to constantly question the presentation of the
public and private, especially any presentation of the public and private
as historically static and mutually exclusive spheres.
Although Dewey uses the terms ‘publics’, ‘state’ and ‘government’, he
points out that these terms are not shackled to modern conceptions
of the nation state. As Dewey (LW2: 276n7) points out, ‘the text is
concerned with modern conditions, but the hypothesis propounded is
meant to hold good generally’. The terms ‘state’, ‘government’ and ‘officer’
are therefore freely used by Dewey to denote functions rather than
elements distinct to the modern state and could be feasibly used in other
contexts. As I shall show in Chapter 5, however, this did not mean that
Dewey did not see the historical shackles the nation state seemed to place
on publics and how they went about reforming government and the state.
As we shall see, Dewey believes that the rate of change of the cultural
matrix in industrial/capitalist-based societies is far more pronounced
than in the agrarian societies that preceded them. However, the
important point here is that Dewey highlights how social change is
often differentiated, in its form and intensity, across different relations of
associative behaviour (family, school, church, science, art and economic
and political relations) rather than mono-causally across the whole of
society.
As Westbrook (1991: 305) notes, Dewey’s use of the ‘ … definite and
indefinite articles tended to obscure his contention that in any given
society the Public was, at most, a collective noun designating plural
publics that concerned themselves with the indirect consequences of
particular forms of associated activity’.
It should be noted here that ‘new’ public in this context does not
necessarily mean that the consequences of associated behaviour in
Notes
135
question are newly created by changes in material aspects of a cultural
matrix. It is quite possible for a new public to emerge in response to a
change in the cultural foundations, which facilitate a new perception of
long-established relations of associative behaviour. It is also possible that
a new public may newly reflect the interests of previous older publics
who were themselves marginalized or whose grievances were deemed
unworthy for public control via government.
14 As Westbrook (1991: 303–5) points out, although Dewey seems to follow
pluralism in regarding the state as secondary and functional in response
to the interests of publics, it should be noted that he did not see the state
as simply balancing the interests of publics. Moreover, Dewey backs the
role states could take independent of direct public formation but on the
basis that the government and their officers could take actions in the
wider interest:
It is quite true that most states, after they have been brought into
being, react upon the primary groupings. When a state is a good state,
when the officers of the publics genuinely serve the public interests,
the reflex effect is of great importance … A measure of a good state is
the degree to which it relieves individuals from the waste and negative
struggle and needless conflict and confesses upon him positive
assurance and reinforcement in what he undertakes. (LW2: 280)
Moreover, as we shall see below, this form of state activism only becomes
problematic for Dewey when it does not facilitate the ability of publics to
democratically challenge or remodel the government and state.
15 There is an obvious link between the power of dominant groups and
the ability to control the cultural foundations of a material culture. For
instance, it would be very helpful to the interests of dominant groups
to have cultural foundations that deem the causes of subordinate
groups and their publics as irrational or incorrect and hence unsuited
for remaking the state. Dewey is, however, very careful not to fall into
a Marxist-style conspiracy narrative that simply equates knowledge as
ideology and thus a simple expression of power. Nevertheless, as we shall
see, although Dewey never uses the terms ‘hegemony’ or ‘ideological
control’, he was quite aware of how the interests of dominant groups
within society were ultimately refracted through ideas and conceptions
of common sense within material culture (LW7: 326).
136
Notes
16 There are some who argue that violence is a legitimate form of politics
and in fact is the only way to bring about change within society where
there are strongly resistant organized publics. Dewey’s reaction to
such claims would be to agree with the first statement under certain
conditions but to totally dismiss the second statement. Dewey’s take
on revolutionary violence is driven by a reaction to the argument for
violence’s historical necessity and an historical appreciation of violence’s
limits. Dewey’s aversion to violence was driven by what he saw in
theories such as Marxism, which posited the historical inevitability of
violence between two polar classes. This for Dewey seemed illogical
because such a dogmatic view of history limits the use of non-violent
means a priori. Moreover, Dewey saw revolutionary violence as an
option that had become historically discredited and limited. On one
hand, Dewey saw history as showing that violence between two groups
had produced pyrrhic victories where much that was done had to be
done over to restore democracy (LW9: 110–11). On the other hand,
the advancement of military technologies meant that the civil or
international wars that would see the changeover of power would have
the potentiality to ruin all parties and indeed civilization itself. This point
itself made it doubly important that violence was seen as means that
should be employed only as a last resort (LW11: 55–8). Despite this, and
the interpretations that paint him as a card-carrying pacifist, Dewey did
not rule out the use of violence altogether. In certain circumstances, and
having come via the use of collective and collaborative intelligence rather
than sheer dogmatism, Dewey believed that the positive use of force
could be pursued (LW14: 75–6).
17 The most sustained narration of Dewey’s democracy as a form of ‘conflict
resolution’ is to be found in William R. Caspary’s Dewey on Democracy
(2000). However, Caspary’s account, although very good on highlighting
Dewey’s similarities to contemporary positions of conflict resolution,
fails to really get to grips with both the evolutionary nature of Dewey’s
conception of democracy in response to changes in the global economy
and the lessons such work hold in the midst of contemporary economic
globalization.
18 Confusingly, across different texts and sometimes within the same
text interchangeably, Dewey also uses the terms ‘democracy as a social
idea’, ‘method of social intelligence’, ‘intelligence’, ‘experimentalist
Notes
137
method’, ‘collective intelligence’, ‘co-operative intelligence’, ‘liberalism’
and ‘democracy as a way of life’ to describe his take on democracy as
the best method for dealing with social change. This is because Dewey
is describing both an ethical ideal (democracy as a way of life) and
a method of value formation (social intelligence) that make up his
conception of creative democracy. In Chapter 4, I expand on this method
of value formation Dewey called ‘social intelligence’. For conceptual
clarity, I will henceforth use democracy as a way of life to sum up the
ethical commitment Dewey attaches to his idea of creative democracy.
19 The ethical commitment of democracy as a way of life should not be seen
as Dewey advocating a formal equality between all opinions. Dewey did,
after all, believe in political democracy acting as an intermediary between
the democratic ideal and also favoured expert opinion on matters.
However, democracy as a way of life looks to ensure the opportunity of
all to express their opinion about social institutions so as not repeat the
key failure of elitism, whether based on expertise or naked power, which
creates a class that is cut off from the concerns of common affairs.
20 As this and the earlier narration of Dewey’s conception of the state
and publics should make clear, contra James Livingston’s (2001:
51–6) otherwise excellent reading of The Public and Its Problems as
the valorization of cultural politics via an active civil society, Dewey’s
concept of creative democracy makes distinct claims about the ability
of publics to gain access to and modify the state and the political
representations of government (LW2: 245–54, 327). The existence of an
active civil society of publics is therefore not taken by Dewey to be the
ultimate guarantee of having a successful democracy.
21 I use the term ‘creative democracy’ not only because it best sums up the
evolutionary nature of Dewey’s idea of democracy but because Dewey
himself uses the term to sum up his position in an address given on his
eightieth birthday: ‘Creative Democracy – The Task Before Us’ (LW14:
224–30).
Chapter 2
1
Major studies of Dewey such as Caspary (2000), Hickman (2007),
Kadlec (2007) and Westbrook (1991) rarely deal with the global nature
138
2
3
4
Notes
of Dewey’s political writings or his political philosophy. For instance,
Kadlec (2007) has no real take on Dewey and global democracy.
Hickman (2007: 32) acknowledges that Dewey put forward an idea of
global citizenship but simply locates this as an earlier account of global
civil society. As I show in Chapter 5, this is not entirely what Dewey had
in mind. Caspary’s study of Deweyan democracy (2000: 3) acknowledges
that Dewey wrote about issues of globalization and democracy but then
states it will not talk about such issues because they can be detached
from an assessment of Dewey’s take on democracy. My argument in
this chapter, however, is that Deweyan democracy in relation to the
Great Society cannot be understood properly without considering
issues of globalization and democracy on a global scale. Westbrook
(1991) expounds upon Dewey’s international writings but he fails to see
how globalization and its interplay with national democracy are key to
Dewey’s ideas of the Great Society and the Great Community.
I follow Dani Rodrik (2011) in calling this the First Great Globalization
but it should be pointed out that the actual dating of globalization is
contested. Janet Abu-Lughod (1989), for instance, traces networks of
global connections back to before the 1500s and writers such as Findlay
and O’Rourke (2007) and Hopkins (2002) acknowledge earlier forms of
globalization. However, as my use of the term ‘First Great Globalization’
suggests, the form of globalization initiated by the industrial revolution
and its technologies is distinct in the way it connected various parts of
the world vis-à-vis earlier forms of globalization.
Findlay and O’Rourke (2007), for example, call their chapter on the
global economy between 1918 and 1939 ‘De-globalisation’.
This folly was at the heart of works, such as A Tract of Monetary Reform
(1923) and A Treatise on Money (1930), where Keynes attempted to
point out to policymakers that the gold standard and the policies
linked to its maintenance were unsuited to post-war conditions. This
was because early twentieth-century capitalism’s new structure of
corporations, more organized labour markets and the advent of trade
unions vis-à-vis independent farmers, small businesses and individual
workers meant that the subordination of national economies to the
priority of world conditions was now both economic and political
dynamite. The details of this great political and economic folly during
Notes
5
6
7
139
the interwar period are covered remarkably well in Ahamed’s
Lords of Finance (2009).
There have been some writers such as Cochran (2002, 2010) and Bray
(2009, 2011) who have attempted to deal with international ramifications
of Dewey’s thought. Molly Cochran’s work is probably at the foremost
of this endeavour and her work has made a valuable contribution
through highlighting that Dewey’s theory of democracy provides a
better approach to democracy at a global level than those mapped out
by writers such as Habermas, Dryzek and Held. However, her initial
approach was let down by the fact that she viewed Dewey’s work as
indirectly addressing the global and hence failed to the see how Dewey
both espouses global democracy but then questions its feasibility
and links this back to domestic politics. In her most recent work, she
has attempted to update this position by seemingly acknowledging
Dewey’s direct confrontation of the problem of globalization and global
democracy (see Cochran 2010). However, her work traces Dewey’s
work only up to the end of the First World War and fails to adequately
grasp Dewey’s developing thought about the role of nation state in
the formation of global democracy. Whilst Cochran rightfully sees
Dewey as the resolver of the dualisms that plague the debate about
global democracy, her approach fails to adequately see how Dewey
believed domestic and global forms of democracy were interlinked and
interdependent and how bourgeois democracy at home impinges on
democracy abroad (for more on this, see Chapter 5).
Dewey refined this position further towards the later years of his life.
He saw the melting away of the ‘old world’ as beginning in the fifteenth
century with the discovery, exploration and exploitation of new parts
of the world and the concomitant revolution of science, commerce and
technology. The ‘latter part of the nineteenth century and first decades of
the twentieth century’ were ‘but the physical completion of the expansive
movement which for four centuries had first encroaching upon and
the breaking down the walls that kept peoples of the earth separate and
divided’ (LW17: 456).
For example, see ‘International Co-operation or International Chaos’
(LW11: 261–5), ‘Contribution to Democracy in a World of Tensions’
(LW16), ‘What Kind of World Are We Fighting For?’ (LW17: 131–2)
140
Notes
and the unpublished essays ‘World Anarchy or World Order?’ (LW15:
204–9) and ‘Between Two Worlds’ (LW17: 451–65). The international
dimensions of Dewey’s thought can also be found in major works of this
period such as Freedom and Culture (LW13).
8 The Mr. Willkie in question here is Wendall Willkie, the Republican
nominee for the 1940 general election. Willkie was ultimately defeated
by Roosevelt, but he was the author of the 1943 bestseller One World,
which is part travel monologue detailing his various meetings with global
leaders and part political treatise on the need for world government.
9 In this essay, Dewey seems to confuse matters by using the term ‘world
society’ to stand in for Great Community, but his conception of world
society is inherently another term for Great Community and should not
be seen as breaking the society/community distinction laid out in the
previous chapter.
10 Dewey would, for example, lose faith in League of Nations as a vehicle
of global democracy as it itself was colonized by the re-emergence of an
ever more muscular nationalism and continued Western imperialism.
This led to a situation where the League no longer offered the hopes
of global democracy but had become a league of governments ‘whose
policies played a part in bringing on the war and that have no wish to
change their policies’ (MW15: 378; Westbrook 1991: 262–3). For some
this was just the logical conclusion to Dewey’s naive backing of American
participation in the First World War as part of a wider project of reform
both at home and abroad. Moreover, as Cochran (2010: 310) highlights,
Dewey’s apparent folly and separation of theory and practice has received
much scholarly attention. I do not wish to tread over old ground but
what is apparent is that Dewey’s disillusionment with the post-war
settlement should be seen as sign of the old professor learning from his
mistakes (see Westbrook 1991: 195–230).
Chapter 3
1
As Leuchtenburg (1993: 200–2) highlights, the prosperity of the 1920s
made it seem to some that the United States was achieving the goals of
socialism without socialism’s means. The Great Society did have some
Notes
2
3
4
141
significant good effects on the lives of ordinary American citizens. The
United States in 1928 spent as much on education as the rest of the world;
radically improved school and college attendance; cut infant mortality
rates by two-thirds; and increased life expectancy for Americans from
forty-nine to fifty-nine years. However, as Leuchtenburg goes on to show,
these statistics do not touch on the aforementioned racial segregation
at the heart of the US life or the fact that material inequality actually
increased by the end of 1920s before the onset of the Great Depression.
As Livingston (2011: 54) points out, the 1920s saw income shares
shift from wages to profits. By 1929, 90 per cent of taxpayers had less
disposable income than in 1922, whilst corporate profits rose 63 per
cent, dividends doubled and the top 1 per cent of taxpayers increased
their disposable income by 63 per cent. In the same period, there had
also been a net loss of 1 million manufacturing jobs due to the increased
efficiency of technology, which resulted in around a 20 per cent fall in
the share of wages in the expenditure of industrial corporations. These
numbers seem to bring home Dewey’s point that whilst there had been
gains for wider society, these changes had been tempered by even wider
gains for certain parts of society at the expense of others.
Dewey argued that the notion that laissez-faire capitalism equalled the
‘philosophy of liberty’ was itself incorrect. Such a philosophy failed to
acknowledge how ‘liberty’ was a historically relative concept based on
the social conditions of the cultural matrix at a given moment in time. I
return to this theme in more depth in Chapter 4.
Dewey’s belief that the advent of mass communication technology
actually helped to create habits, which contributed to the breakdown
of the public sphere, places him as a precursor to later media critics
ranging from Adorno and Horkhemier and Habermas to the enfant
terrible Jean Baudrillard. Even if he was not totally sold on conspiracy
narratives of his successors, Dewey recognized what Tim Wu (2011: 6)
has recently highlighted, which is that mass communication technologies
of the twentieth and early twenty-first centuries have often been brought
within the structures of industrial capitalism and had become a ‘highly
centralized and integrated new industry’ in their own right.
On this issue, Dewey sounded a warning to the American nation that the
country needed to embrace democracy as a way of life and enact creative
democracy domestically to deal with the complexity and stratification
142
5
Notes
he saw within American corporate capitalism and avoid the embrace of
the authoritarian politics he associated with fascism, communism and
the expert governance of democratic realism. Examples of this train of
thought can be found throughout Dewey’s work from the 1920s onwards
where he puts forward ideas about a form of democratic socialism. Many
of Dewey’s reforms came to be enshrined in the post-war settlement
and the rise of welfare state capitalism in the mid-twentieth century (see
Ruggie 1982; Blyth 2002; Harvey 2005). However, it should be pointed
out that many of Dewey’s reforms were not implemented. Contemporary
issues such as the balance between work and leisure, industrial
democracy, education provision and the socialization of the economy
would benefit from a return to some of the old professor’s ideas. I return
to this argument in Chapter 4 when I argue that Dewey’s idea of creative
democracy via social intelligence depends on a radical idea of equality of
opportunity and economic outcome.
Dewey opposed fascism and communism because they essentially did
what corporate America did through substituting a bureaucratic state
for big business. As Westbrook (1991: 452) outlines, Dewey thought
communism and fascism used violent state power to enforce a form of
autocratic corporatism that stifled democracy.
Chapter 4
1
Pappas (2008: 271–2) points out that critics such as Westbrook and
Eldridge are fundamentally asking the wrong questions when they seek
democratic blueprints from Dewey. This is because Dewey does not
want to tell us what to think about democracy but rather how to think
democratically. The true lesson of Dewey’s work is therefore to be as
contextualist as Dewey and examine our own present. I find much to
agree with in Pappas, and I would echo his sentiments that critics often
ask questions of Dewey that he would have thought rather odd. However,
the value of Dewey’s work is not simply in teaching us how to think
about issues such as global democracy but also centres on important
lessons we have seemingly forgotten. As I outline below, Dewey did
provide concrete ideas on the future of democracy, which centred on a
Notes
2
3
4
5
143
critique of capitalism and liberalism’s conception of liberty. These ideas
were not blueprints but always provisional and subject to their own
revision through the process he called social intelligence. However, in
the midst of neo-liberal globalization, Dewey’s ideas about securing
the grounds for the habits of creative democracy and the use of social
intelligence may be as pertinent as ever.
As Jay Martin (2002: 384) highlights, there are an ‘astonishing number
of political proposals’ that Dewey made during the Depression through
his work with the People’s Lobby (PL) and the League for Independent
Political Action (LIPA) that centred on the economy and politics. This is
to say nothing of his earlier co-founding of groups such as the National
Association for the Advancement of Colored People (NAACP).
Dewey’s work has recently been seen as precursor to modern ideas of
deliberative democracy (see Putnam 1991, 1994; Westbrook 2005; Kadlec
2007). This idea would have some purchase given Dewey’s commitment
to communication between publics. However, the key difference centres
on Dewey’s faith in habits and virtues of social intelligence in comparison
to deliberative democratic rules of discourse. For more on the difference
between the two approaches, see Pappas (2008: 251–5); and on the
differences between Dewey and deliberative democracy’s key thinker
Jürgen Habermas, see Honneth (1998); Kadlec (2007); Bernstein (2010).
As Gouinlock (1972: 345n119) argues, this dependence of the
experimental method on evidence does highlight a key role for experts.
However, as we encountered in Chapter 1, Dewey argued that a
dependence on the evidence of experts was disabling for democracy.
The evidence that would be up for debate here would not just be based
on the testimony of experts. Gouinlock (1986 cf. Pappas 1998: 252) goes
on to highlight that social intelligence would not be solely based on
empirical ‘facts’ but would also incorporate emotions and non-cognitive
and non-discursive expressions into the process of co-operative problem
solving.
This is one of those moments where the ventriloquist must admit to
writing his subject’s speech for them. Dewey never outlines social
intelligence in the systematic way I have done so and my own narration
of it owes much to Gouinlock (1972, 1986). The nature of social
intelligence is itself an issue of debate. Some Deweyan scholars argue that
144
6
7
Notes
Dewey’s idea of social intelligence provides an epistemic justification for
democracy, predominantly deliberative democracy, over other political
regimes (Putnam 1991, 1994; Westbrook 2005: 175–200). In this sense,
democracy is justified and most suited to the conditions of the Great
Society because it provides the conditions for ‘increasing the rationality
of solutions to social problems’ (Honneth 1998: 773). Others, such
as Pappas (2008: see also Gouinlock 1972, 1986; McDermott 2007),
have argued that Dewey’s work does not pivot on such an epistemic
justification of democracy and that Dewey’s idea of democracy was more
an approach to experience than epistemology.
Colin Koopman (2009a), drawing on the work of Livingston (1994,
2001), has written an excellent piece that highlights that this debate
about Dewey’s political economy seemingly replicates a dualism Dewey
would have sought to dismantle. Indeed, Koopman even draws parallels
Dewey was unable to see, highlighting the similarities between Hayek
and Dewey’s thought. Dewey himself might have recoiled at such a
contention given his distaste for The Road to Serfdom (see Westbrook
1991: 460–1). For Koopman, Dewey’s work would undoubtedly lead
to the use of both governments and markets to secure democratic
aspirations. I think Koopman is generally on the right track here in
shifting the debate about Dewey’s political economy towards democratic
ends. However, I would offer a note of caution about this approach. As I
highlight below, Dewey’s work reveals significant claims about the role
of economic inequality in the perpetuation of bourgeois democracy at
home and asymmetric relations between nations. Dewey’s work therefore
calls for equality of economic outcome to be part of a democratic
settlement of the economy. This is based on Dewey’s own inquiry into
the effect economic inequality has on the democratic way of life. In some
ways, the statement that Dewey would utilize both market-based and
government means to achieve democratic ends, without really spelling
out what those democratic ends entail, doesn’t actually get us beyond the
dualisms Koopman wishes to negate.
At different times, Dewey seems to suggest that laissez-faire liberalism
was once a harbinger of liberty and then fell a foul of being ahistorical.
This would resemble Dewey’s ideas of cultural and institutional ‘lag’.
However, here and at other times, Dewey suggests that laissez-faire
liberalism might have always been unfit for democratic purposes in
Notes
8
145
the first place. What once may have promised liberty of all through
providing an equality of opportunity, unhampered by differences in
‘status, birth and family antecedents, and finally, in name at least, of race
and sex’, during the economic and social conditions of the American
frontier had also placed an ‘ … inordinate emphasis upon one aspect of
opportunity, namely, upon the narrow phase of economic opportunity
which is material and pecuniary’. Dewey argues that the result, which
no intelligent observer could deny, was that the eclipse of democratic
institutions through inequality was actually the product of the liberty
‘ … which has been striven for and upheld in the name of the maxim of
economic liberty of the individual’ (LW11: 249–50). The chief point here
is that Dewey seems to suggest the undemocratic results of laissez-faire
liberalism were always going to transpire because the ahistorical ideas
of individualism, liberty and democracy that underpin laissez-faire
liberalism were always destined to create vast material and cultural
conditions of inequality.
Dewey never fully explicates how the standard of this equality should
be set. His own prescription of reforms to help dismantle the structural
inequality of corporate America ranged from the minimum wage, social
insurance, higher income tax on high earners and higher corporation
tax to all-out federal control and socialization of the economy. However,
from his words about the need to at times create ‘equalization’, Dewey
would seemingly leave such a process to the experimental method
based on the evidence that significant inequality between individuals
and nation states was detrimental to the democratic way of life and
should be alleviated. The standards of such equality would have been
therefore left up to the practice of social intelligence to formulate. What
is important to point out here is that Dewey was not widely legislating
or laying down the blueprints for the Great Community but rather
conducting his own form of inquiry based on the evidence accrued
by himself and others about the nature of liberal capitalism and its
ideas of liberty, individualism and equality. These findings could be
proven incorrect through further inquiry but appeared provisionally
valid, based on evidence to suggest that liberal capitalism and the
inequalities it generated were incapable of securing the conditions for
creative democracy through the auspices of social intelligence. This
view also departs somewhat from Honneth (1998), who seems to argue
146
Notes
that Dewey’s sense of economic equality comes from a valorization of
an earlier and more just agrarian-based division of labour. This holds
some merit but neglects what Livingston (1994) notes is Dewey’s
understanding of the strengths of the corporate structure and seemingly
deposits a primordial conception of economic equality Dewey would
have been uncomfortable endorsing. Dewey argued that conditions of
modern capitalism demanded a form of economic equality to provide the
ethical commitment of democracy as a way of life and for the diffusion
of habits of social intelligence. This was not a valorization of the past but
more so a reflection upon the needs of the present.
9 The rest of Deen’s paper centres on trying to deal with the minimalist
arguments about global justice, such as the one advocated by Thomas
Nagel (2005). These minimalist conceptions of global justice follow the
lead of Rawls (1999) in arguing that the principles of distributive justice
only apply to citizens within the same nation state. In Nagel’s case, the
argument is that justice only exists in the midst of jointly authored
coercive institutions that create thick political commitments between
citizens. As the global realm does not have these institutions, such as a
global state or global citizenship, global justice does not exist and we are
therefore confined to a minimal humanitarianism to alleviate absolute
poverty. Deen goes through a convoluted process of trying to highlight
how a global form of social intelligence would create the very thick
political commitments Nagel demands. This inherently gives Nagel too
much credit and devalues Dewey’s own contribution to this debate.
Dewey would have certainly disagreed that the lack of institutions at the
global level means that global justice is not possible. Moreover, Dewey
took the non-existence of such institutions in the midst of the Great
Society to contradict the democratic way of life. This, in turn, called for
the creation of such institutions and community rather than providing
grounds for the status quo or minimal humanitarianism. In fact, as I
show below, Dewey took the context of the Great Society to demand not
only such institutions but also a form of economic equality to safeguard
the democratic way of life and help facilitate social intelligence across the
Great Community.
10 It should be noted that Dewey’s work on global democracy following
the First World War can be said to harbour Eurocentric ideas, which are
rooted in American exceptionalism. However, Dewey’s work throughout
Notes
147
the 1920s and 1930s demonstrates a gradual displacing of this idea.
Although Dewey places the emphasis here on rich and powerful
countries ceding power, he was more than aware that countries which
were undergoing imperialism were beginning to exercise their own
power and would eventually become key components of the move to
force rich and powerful Western nation states to cede power in the global
economy (see LW3: 158–62; LW15: 204–9).
11 As I highlight in the next chapter, one of the ways Dewey believed
America could help facilitate this process was also by being an example
of a successful democracy along the lines of creative democracy and
the use of social intelligence. The irony is that throughout the latter half
of the twentieth century America has portrayed itself as a successful
democracy along lines (liberal capitalist) that Dewey found abhorrent
and antithetical to the democratic way of life. Moreover, its use of
military force to display its power has been both awe-inspiring and
largely self-defeating. Somewhat ironically, Dewey argued against the
ability of global hegemon to secure world government through force
having seen the rise of Third World nationalism in regions such as Asia
(LW15: 204–9).
12 This may give the impression that Dewey saw the natural world as being
efficiently utilized. However, it should be noted that Dewey not only
saw the incompatibility between bourgeois democracy and democracy
as a way of life as centring around the negative effects it had on human
lives but also saw the negative effects it had upon the natural world and
the environment in which humans lived. Liberal capitalism had seen
vast portions of the environment and its natural resources reduced
to a ‘desert’ for future generations, who would have to pay for ‘past
indulgence in an orgy of so-called economic-liberty’ (LW11: 251).
Although this book has cast the democratic way of life as concerning the
equality of human beings, it has been suggested that Dewey’s idea of the
democratic way of life seems to posit equality between all existences in
nature (Gouinlock 1986; Pappas 2008). This would seemingly remove the
hierarchy created between the dualism of man and nature, and lead to an
idea that ‘every existence deserving the name of existence has something
unique and irreplaceable about it’ (MW 11:51). As Pappas (2008: 226)
notes, this leads to Dewey’s position advocating a form of ecological and
environmental democracy. It is beyond the scope of this study to flesh
148
Notes
out the contours of Dewey’s ecological and environmental democracy
beyond saying that ecological concerns would be paramount to how
Deweyan democracy would reorient the political economy of liberal
capitalism (for more on this strand of Dewey’s thought, see Light and
Katz 1996; Ralston 2013).
13 There is, of course, a question to be answered here about pluralism and
its relationship to Dewey’s idea of the Great Community and global
democracy. Dewey was convinced of and committed to the idea that the
democratic way of life and social intelligence offered America and the
world the chance to not only avoid conflict but obtain a more productive
form of life. Contemporary pragmatist writers such as Robert Talisse
(2007a, 2007b) have argued that this approach makes Dewey’s work
undemocratic due to an inability to deal with the problem of pluralism.
Talisse (2007b: 20–2) begins his argument with the problem John Rawls
(1996) called ‘reasonable pluralism’, that is, ‘the view according to which
there are several substantive moral visions of the human good that
are consistent both with liberal-democratic politics and with the best
employment of moral reasoning, but are nonetheless inconsistent with
each other’. If we accept this argument, within the democratic order
with other fellow citizens who hold moral visions incommensurable
with our own, we cannot expect to justify that order and its practices
by reference to any common substantive moral vision. Deweyan
democracy is therefore both undemocratic and oppressive because it
attempts to enlist the coercive power of the state in the task of realizing
a set of moral values, democracy as a way of life and social intelligence,
which reasonable citizens could reject. Talisse goes on to argue that
a combination of a Rawlsian commitment to put substantive moral
visions (religious, philosophical) to one side in democratic deliberation
and Charles Sanders Pierce’s version of pragmatism and its epistemic
requirement that all belief aims at truth-apt statements, rather than
oppressive Deweyan ideas about democracy as a way of life, provides
a conception of pragmatic democracy that can actually deal with the
problem of pluralism.
The stakes of such debates have obvious implications for Dewey’s ideas
about global democracy, whose faith in transnational publics and
global institutions is bound to face and elicit competing ideas of the
good. However, as Koopman (2009b) argues, the problem of reasonable
Notes
149
pluralism is only one way to deal with the problem of pluralism. Dewey’s
work and his idea of social intelligence takes the problem of pluralism
not to mean that we shun our substantive ideas of the good for a thin
epistemic proceduralism but that we take the problem of pluralism to
orient our substantive normative commitments in the first place. As
Koopman (2009b: 62) states, this is:
… because conflict over substantive commitments is entirely
consistent with Deweyan pluralism in a way that Rawlsian pluralism
fails to affirm. The Rawlsian response to pluralism is to rule out a
commitment to contentious comprehensive conceptions, which
generate conflict. The Deweyan response is to regard pluralism as
a condition of politics, which orients or inflects each and every
contentious conception that gets put forth, including the contentious
conceptions put forth by Deweyans themselves. Whereas Rawls
demands that we rule out certain kinds of political commitments,
Dewey accepts all comers demanding only that every commitment
orient itself as one amidst a plurality of other such commitments.
The view motivating the Deweyan approach is that the intractable
conflicts generated by pluralism are something we should work with
rather than around.
Quite simply, the ethical commitment of democracy as a way of life and
the practice of social intelligence would always seek conditions that
would allow pluralism to flourish and allow for different viewpoints
to put forward their conception of moral value. This would include
positions that challenge the ideas of what we take to be the democratic
way of life and social intelligence. Indeed, Dewey’s arguments about
the need for economic equality are based on the need to secure such
conditions in order for such a situation to emerge. Dewey did not see
the democratic way of life and the use of social intelligence as a coercive
and oppressive silencing of pluralism but rather as the most reflexive
method to deal with the problem of pluralism and provide a way for
different competing ideas of the good to interact, engage and form ways
of living together that would be prosperous for all involved. He was quite
aware, for example, of the differences between the respective cultural
matrices of places such as China, India, Japan, France, Germany, the
United Kingdom and the United States without homogenizing these
150
Notes
into antagonistic blocs (LW17: 35–6). Thus, one may question if this is
actually possible in current circumstances, where the habits of social
intelligence are not common and publics appear ever committed to
dogmatic forms of moral value. But it seems rather perverse to argue that
Deweyan democracy is somehow an oppressive force.
Chapter 5
1
2
This reflection on the nature of the industrial and complex habits of
the Great Society also brings home the fact that just because citizens
are conducting complex tasks and have interdependent relations
with one another, it does not follow that such habits will produce an
understanding of community. Moreover, Dewey’s reflections on the
division between society and community prefigure Kymlicka’s point
that a community is not defined by ‘the forces people are subject to,
but rather how they respond to such forces …’ (1999: 437). This also
outlines a response to contemporary neo-Marxist critics such as Hardt
and Negri (2004), who argue that Dewey’s ideas are now outdated and
inconsequential because of the rise of information-based and networkbased industries. In such a narrative, ‘immaterial labour’ is said to
cultivate co-operative relationships and holds the potential to see the rise
of the ‘multitude’ across the globe. Dewey would have been sceptical of
such a rewriting of the Marxist narrative, however, because of the fact
that the industrial and technological revolutions of his age also created
large swathes of co-operative relationships. There is a distinct difference,
something Hardt and Negri fail to realize, between what Dewey saw as
physical interdependence and moral co-operation.
The spread of such nationalism outside of the West and into regions
such as Asia also brought home for Dewey that the age of European
imperialism was now over and that the idea of a global military hegemon
was also unfeasible. Dewey thus understood in 1946 the ramifications
of what was to become known as ‘Third World Nationalism’ and no
doubt would have recoiled in horror had he had lived to see the Vietnam
War and other countless apparent interventions in the Third World by
the United States and Western countries throughout the Cold War and
beyond (See LW3: 159; LW15: 208).
Notes
3
4
5
151
It is also important, however, to note that the above does not commit
the reverse sin of reifying the nation state, nationalism and nation
state politics at the expense of the global or transnational. The irony
of Dewey’s position is that it refutes essentialism but deals with the
harsh reality of such anti-essentialism. Although embracing antiessentialist conceptions of the public, state and government, which do
not exclusively link those concepts and functions with the nation state,
Dewey’s view seems to posit that the emergence of the nation state
and nationalism places a historically contingent limit on the nature of
global democracy. It may very well be that eventually the nation states
and nationalism cease to be as important or even disappear. However,
in Dewey’s eyes, the nation state and nationalism were to be taken very
much like solid brick walls: whilst they are undoubtedly constructions,
one would be very hard-headed to believe that one could simply walk
through them.
Dewey’s focus on the face-to-face communication and his claim that the
Great Community would not have the same intimacy of communication
as the local setting has been presented as the ramblings of an old man
with a rose-tinted nostalgia for a form of localism lost to the confines of
history (see Westbrook 1991; Ryan 1995; Cochran 2002). This in turn
has often clouded assessments of Dewey’s global thought. However,
as my exposition highlights, this is actually far from the truth. The
local community was important for Dewey but only as a reconstructed
local community within the Great Community at both national and
international level. Indeed, such nostalgia for earlier, and so-called
‘simpler’ times, made Dewey downhearted: ‘I find myself resentful and
feeling sad when, in relation to present social, economic, and political
problems, people point simply backward as if somewhere in the past
there were a model for what we should do today’ (LW 13: 299).
One could argue that Dewey’s work prefigures a form of cosmopolitan
nationalism as outlined by writers such as Eckerlsey (2007) and Tan
(2008). Whilst there are similarities to such approaches, the key
difference between Dewey and writers such as Tan is that Dewey
does not adhere to two-stage process where democracy within the
state must be obtained before democracy beyond the state can even
be contemplated. Whereas Dewey saw democracy at home as key to
152
6
7
Notes
securing democracy abroad, the fact was that securing the democratic
way of life was not simply about choosing respective focal points
of political action such as the local, national or global. Rather, the
struggle for democracy as a way of life was to be ‘ … maintained on as
many fronts as culture has aspects: political, economic, international,
educational, scientific and artistic, religious’ (LW13: 186).
It should be noted that this adage that democracy must begin at home
would also stand for countries that are economically weaker and
under the coercion of stronger nations or who find themselves under
undemocratic conditions in the first instance. Without democracy at
home, any movement for freedom would be bound to end in ruins.
History would see this unfold after Dewey’s death with the rise and fall
of the Third World project. Whilst the new postcolonial states of Africa,
Asia and Latin America forged some of the most coherent policies
for regulating the global economy in democratic terms, two assailants
assassinated the movement. The first was the continued informal
economic and political imperialism, what we today call neo-imperialism,
conducted by Western nations against their former colonies. The second
factor was the failure of elites within such new countries to create stable
democracies in the midst of such conditions. Whilst these elites can
rightfully shift some of the blame to factors outside their borders, it was
also the failure of such dominant classes to create a vibrant democracy
at home that led to collapse of the rooted cosmopolitanism at the heart
of the Third World project and the rise of the destructive and divisive
cultural nationalism that followed. For greater details on this, see
Prashad (2008, 2013).
This point also highlights how Bray’s (2009, 2011, 2013) attempt
to reorient modern cosmopolitanism to a form of pragmatic
cosmopolitanism undersells the power of Dewey’s work on global
democracy. Bray’s argument is that Dewey’s work on publics opens up
the chance to bypass the ethnocentrism of modern cosmopolitanism.
This would see the ‘hardwiring’ of cosmopolitanism into the attitudes
of citizens through practices and institutions such as education. The
hope being that such practices could facilitate the emergence of citizens
and publics who would implore and force their leaders to create a ‘selfsacrificing nation committed to foreign aid and global justice’ (Bray 2013:
Notes
8
9
153
462–3). Bray does suggest, however, that Dewey is too naive about how
such a process could come about in an economically stratified society
and unprepared to face up to the real obstacles of asymmetrical power
relations facing the pursuit of the democratic way of life both within
and beyond the nation state (Bray 2011: 160–2). The main problem is
that Bray’s portrayal of Dewey as being politically naive on issues of
power neglects Dewey’s problematic of bourgeois democracy and his
appreciation of the stratified nature of the global economy. Indeed, Bray
seemingly neglects how Dewey’s problematic of bourgeois democracy
complicates his own idea of creating cosmopolitan leadership at the
national level. In doing this, Bray fails to grasp Dewey’s key intervention
on global democracy, which located the hopes and aspirations of
democracy abroad with the challenge of destroying bourgeois democracy
at home.
This point marks out a significant moment where Dewey failed to
consistently apply his own philosophy to some of his insights. Much like
Karl Polanyi, Dewey seems to have become fixated on the British Labour
Party as embodying the type of democratic socialism he envisioned.
However, whilst being more progressive than Roosevelt and the New
Deal, Dewey seems blind to the fact that, based upon his own criteria,
Attlee’s government did not practise creative democracy at home or
abroad. As Dale (2010: 205) outlines, the post-war Labour government
did not represent a wholesale rejection of market capitalism but rather
a continuation of the liberal-imperialist agenda that came beforehand.
This is evidenced by the post-war Labour government’s continuance
of the British Empire and its secret nuclear weapon programme. In
short, the Atlee government may have pursued some elements of
democratic socialism at home but it was not an example of the rooted
cosmopolitanism and form of democratic socialism Dewey imagined
both at home and abroad.
Mazower (2012) provides an excellent account of the travails of
extending democracy beyond the nation state throughout Dewey’s
lifetime and beyond. For a view of such events from outside of the Anglo
and European world, see Vijay Prashad’s wonderful history of the Third
World project (2008, 2013).
154
Notes
10 The demise of old economic liberalism and the rise of neo-liberalism
sandwich the period now known as ‘embedded liberalism’. This saw
the post-war international monetary system facilitate the emergence of
‘embedded liberal states’, or what we commonly see as modern welfare
states and perhaps the most productive and fairly distributed form of
capitalism ever known (Ruggie 1983; Blyth 2002; Harvey 2005; Frieden
2006; Rodrik 2011). I do not have the space here to expand on this but
Dewey would have seen great promise and great flaws in such a regime.
The proof of this resides in his critique of the New Deal, which can be
seen as a precursor to the modern welfare states of the embedded liberal
period. Dewey would have seen the move towards a more regulated form
of capitalism as only a half-way house towards securing the equality
of opportunity needed to secure the democratic way of life both at
home and abroad because of the persistence of large-scale economic
inequalities. What is needed is not just a fairer capitalism for a brief
period but a fair social economic system that can be productive in terms
of both economic output and human development.
11 This analogy becomes even more pertinent when one considers the levels
of wealth inequality in neo-liberal hotbeds such as the United States
and the United Kingdom. As Wade (2009b: 541) outlines, the Reagan/
Thatcher policy changes were phenomenally successful, helping to
produce the biggest upwards redistribution in the West in over a century.
From 1980, the share of the top 1 per cent in the United States took off
like a rocket to regain by 2006 its 1929 peak.
Bibliography
Abu-Lughod, J. (1989), Before European Hegemony: The World System A.D.
1250–1350. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Adorno, T. (1973), Negative Dialectics. New York: Continuum Press.
Ahamed, L. (2009), Lords of Finance. London: Windmill Books.
Anderson, B. (1991), Imagined Communities. London: Verso.
Appiah, K.W. (1996), ‘Cosmopolitan Patriots’, in J. Cohen (ed.) For the Love of
Country. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Appiah, K.W. (2005), The Ethics of Identity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Archibugi, D. (2008), The Global Commonwealth of Citizens: Toward
Cosmopolitan Democracy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Bandy, J. and Smith, J. (eds.) (2005), Coalitions Across Borders: Transnational
Protest and the Neo-Liberal Order. Lantham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
Beck, U. (2013), German Europe. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Bello, W. (2005), Deglobalization Ideas for a New World Economy. London:
ZED Books.
Bello, W. (2013), Capitalism’s Last Stand: Deglobalization in the Age of
Austerity. London: Zed Books.
Bernstein, R.J. (2010), The Pragmatic Turn. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Bhambra, G.K. (2011), ‘Cosmopolitanism and the Postcolonial Critique’, in
M. Nowicka and M. Rovisco (eds.) The Ashgate Research Companion to
Cosmopolitanism. Aldershot: Ashgate, pp. 313–28.
Billig, M. (1995), Banal Nationalism. London: Sage Publications.
Blyth, M. (2002), Great Transformations: Economic Ideas and Institutional
Change in the Twentieth Century. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Blyth, M. (2013), Austerity: The History of a Dangerous Idea. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Bohman, J. (2007), Democracy Across Borders: From Demos to Demoi.
Cambridge: MIT Press.
Brassett J. and Smith, W. (2010), ‘Deliberation and Global Civil Society:
Agency, Arena, Affect’, Review of International Studies, 36(2): 413–30.
Bray, D. (2009), ‘Pragmatic Cosmopolitanism: A Deweyan Approach to
Democracy beyond the Nation-State’. Millennium: Journal of International
Studies, 37(3): 683–719.
156
Bibliography
Bray, D. (2011), Pragmatic Cosmopolitanism: Representation and Leadership in
Transitional Democracy. London: Palgrave Macmillan
Bray, D. (2013), ‘Pragmatic Ethics and the Will to Believe in
Cosmopolitanism’, International Theory, 5(3): 446–76.
Brown, G.W. and Held, D. (2010), The Cosmopolitanism Reader. Cambridge:
Polity Press.
Calhoun, C. (2008), Nations Matter: Culture, History, and the Cosmopolitan
Dream. New York: Routledge.
Calhoun, C. (2010), ‘Beck, Asia and Second Modernity’, British Journal of
Sociology, 61(3): 597–617.
Campbell, J. (1995), Understanding John Dewey. Chicago: Open Court.
Caspary, W.R. (2000), Dewey on Democracy. Ithaca, NY and London: Cornell
University Press.
Chandler, D. (2010), Hollow Hegemony: Rethinking Global Politics, Power and
Resistance. London: Pluto.
Chang, H.J. (2003), Kicking Away the Ladder: Development Strategies in
Historical Perspective. London: Anthem.
Chang, H.J. (2007), Bad Samaritans. London: Random House.
Cochran, M. (2001), ‘A Pragmatist Perspective on Ethical Foreign Policy’,
in K. Smith and M. Light (eds.) Ethics and Foreign Policy. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, pp. 55–72.
Cochran, M. (2002), ‘A Democratic Critique of Cosmopolitan Democracy:
Pragmatism from the Bottom-Up’, European Journal of International
Relations, 8(4): 517–48.
Cochran, M. (ed.) (2010), The Cambridge Companion to Dewey. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Dahl, R. (1999), ‘Can International Organizations be Democratic? A Skeptical
View’, in I. Shapiro and C. Hacker-Cordon (eds.) Democracy’s Edges. New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Dahl, R. (2001), ‘Is Post-National Democracy Possible?’, in S. Fabbrini (ed.)
Nation, Federalism and Democracy. Trento: Editrice Compositori.
Dale, G. (2010), Karl Polanyi: The Limits of the Market. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Deen, P. (2013), ‘Justice and Global Communities of Inquiry’, in S.J. Ralston
(ed.) Pragmatism and International Relations: Essays for a New Bold World.
Plymouth: Lexington Books.
Dewey, J. (EW1), ‘Early Essays and Leibniz’s New Essays’, in J. Boydston
(ed.) John Dewey The Early Works 1882–1898, Volume 1: 1882–1888.
Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.
Bibliography
157
Dewey, J. (MW4), ‘Journal Articles and Book Reviews in the 1907–1909
Period, and The Pragmatic Movement of Contemporary Thought and
Moral Principles in Education’, in J. Boydston (eds.) John Dewey The
Middle Works 1899–1924, Volume 4: 1907–1909. Carbondale: Southern
Illinois University Press.
Dewey, J. (MW9), ‘Democracy and Education’, in J. Boydston (ed.) John
Dewey The Middle Works 1899–1924, Volume 9: 1916. Carbondale:
Southern Illinois University Press.
Dewey, J. (MW10), ‘Journal Articles, Essays and Miscellany’, in J. Boydston
(ed.) John Dewey The Middle Works 1899–1924, Volume 10: 1916–1917.
Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.
Dewey, J. (MW11), ‘Journal Articles, Essays and Miscellany’, in J. Boydston
(ed.) John Dewey The Middle Works 1899–1924, Volume 11: 1918–1919.
Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.
Dewey, J. (MW12), ‘Reconstruction in Philosophy’, in J. Boydston (ed.) John
Dewey The Middle Works 1899–1924, Volume 12: 1920. Carbondale:
Southern Illinois University Press.
Dewey, J. (MW14), ‘Human Nature and Conduct’, in J. Boydston (ed.) John
Dewey The Middle Works 1899–1924, Volume 14: 1922. Carbondale:
Southern Illinois University Press.
Dewey, J. (MW15), ‘Journal Articles, Essays and Miscellany’, in J. Boydston
(ed.) John Dewey The Middle Works 1899–1924, Volume 15: 1923–1924.
Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.
Dewey, J. (LW1), ‘Experience and Nature’, in J. Boydston (ed.) John Dewey The
Later Works 1925–1953, Volume 1: 1925. Carbondale: Southern Illinois
University Press.
Dewey, J. (LW2), ‘The Public and Its Problems’, in J. Boydston (ed.) John
Dewey The Later Works 1925–1953, Volume 2: 1925–27. Carbondale:
Southern Illinois University Press.
Dewey, J. (LW3), ‘Essays, Reviews, and Miscellany and Impressions of Soviet
Russia’, in J. Boydston (ed.) John Dewey The Later Works 1925–1953,
Volume 2: 1925–27. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.
Dewey, J. (LW5), ‘Individualism Old and New’, in J. Boydston (ed.) John
Dewey The Later Works 1925–1953, Volume 5: 1929–30. Carbondale:
Southern Illinois University Press.
Dewey, J. (LW6), ‘Essays, Reviews, and Miscellany’, in J. Boydston (ed.)
John Dewey The Later Works 1925–1953, Volume 6: 1931–32, 131–32.
Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.
158
Bibliography
Dewey, J. (LW7), ‘Ethics’, in J. Boydston (ed.) John Dewey The Later Works
1925–1953, Volume 7: 1932. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.
Dewey, J. (LW9), ‘A Common Faith’, in J. Boydston (ed.) John Dewey The
Later Works 1925–1953, Volume 9: 1933–34. Carbondale: Southern Illinois
University Press.
Dewey, J. (LW11), ‘Liberalism and Social Action’, in J. Boydston (ed.) John
Dewey The Later Works 1925–1953, Volume 11: 1935. Carbondale:
Southern Illinois University Press.
Dewey, J. (LW13), ‘Freedom and Culture’, in J. Boydston (ed.) John Dewey The
Later Works 1925–1953, Volume 13: 1938–1939. Carbondale: Southern
Illinois University Press.
Dewey, J. (LW14), ‘Essays, Reviews, and Miscellany’, in J. Boydston (ed.) John
Dewey The Later Works 1925 –1953, Volume 14: 1939–1941. Carbondale:
Southern Illinois University Press.
Dewey, J. (LW15), ‘Essays, Reviews, and Miscellany’, in J. Boydston (ed.) John
Dewey The Later Works 1925–1953, Volume 15: 1942–1948. Carbondale:
Southern Illinois University Press.
Dewey, J. (LW16), ‘Essays, Typescripts, and Knowing and the Known’, in
J. Boydston (ed.) John Dewey The Later Works 1925–1953, Volume 16:
1949–1952. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.
Dewey, J. (LW17), ‘Essays, Reviews, and Miscellany’, in J. Boydston (ed.) John
Dewey The Later Works 1925–1953, Volume 17: 1885–1953. Carbondale:
Southern Illinois University Press.
Dryzek, J. (2006), Deliberative Global Politics: Discourse and Democracy in a
Divided World. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Dryzek, J. (2010), Foundations and Frontiers of Deliberative Governance.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Dryzek, J. (2012), ‘Global Civil Society: The Progress of Post-Westphalian
Politics’, Annual Review of Political Science, 15: 101–19.
Duménil, G. and Lévy, D. (2004), Capital Resurgent: Roots of the Neo-Liberal
Revolution. London: Harvard University Press.
Eckerlsey, R. (2007), ‘From Cosmopolitan Nationalism to Cosmopolitan
Democracy’, Review of International Studies, 33: 675–92.
Eldridge, M. (1998), Transforming Experience: John Dewey’s Cultural
Instrumentalism. Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press.
Englen, E., Erturk, I., Froud, J., Johal, S., Leaver, A., Moran, M., Nilson, A.,
and Williams, K. (2011), After the Great Complacence: Financial Crisis and
the Politics of Reform. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bibliography
159
Findlay, R. and O.Rourke, K.H. (2007), Power and Plenty: Trade, War, and
the World Economy in the Second Millennium. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press.
Fine, R. (2007), Cosmopolitanism. Abingdon: Routledge.
Frieden, J.A. (2006), Global Capitalism: Its Rise and Fall in the Twentieth
Century. New York: Norton.
Gilens, M. (2012), Affluence and Influence: Economic Inequality and Political
Power in America. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Gouinlock, J. (1972), John Dewey’s Philosophy of Value. New York: Humanities.
Gouinlock, J. (1986), Excellence in Public Discourse: John Stuart Mill, John
Dewey and Social Intelligence. New York: Teachers College Press.
Gouinlock, J. (1990), ‘What Is the Legacy of Instrumentalism? Rorty’s
Interpretation of Dewey’, Journal of the History of Philosophy, 28(2):
251–69.
Habermas, J. (2001), The Post-National Constellation. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Habermas, J. (2006), The Divided West. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Habermas, J. (2012), The Crisis of the European Union. Cambridge: Polity
Press.
Hale, T., Held, D., and Young, K. (2013), Gridlock: Why Global Cooperation Is
Failing When We Need It Most. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Hardt, M. and Negri, A. (1999), Empire. London: Harvard University Press.
Hardt, M. and Negri, A. (2004), Multitude: War and Democracy in the Age of
Empire. London: Penguin Books.
Hardt, M. and Negri, A. (2011), ‘The Fight for Real Democracy at the
Heart of Occupy Wall Street’, Foreign Affairs, www.foreignaffairs.com/
articles/136399/michael-hardt-and-antonio-negri/the-fight-for-realdemocracy-at-the-heart-of-occupy-wall-street (accessed 4 April 2014).
Harvey, D. (2005), A Brief History of Neoliberalism. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Hay, C. (2007), Why We Hate Politics. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Heidegger, M. (1977), The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays.
New York: Harper and Row.
Held, D. (1995), Democracy and the Global Order. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Held, D. (2004), Global Covenant: The Social Democratic Alternative to the
Washington Consensus. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Held, D. (2010), Cosmopolitanism. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Held, D. and McGrew, A. (2007), Globalization/Anti-Globalization.
Cambridge: Polity Press.
160
Bibliography
Hickman, L. (2007), Pragmatism as Post-Postmodernism: Lessons from John
Dewey. New York: Fordham University Press.
Hirst, P., Thompson, G., and Bromley, S. (2009), Globalization in Question:
The International Economy and the Possibilities of Governance. Cambridge:
Polity Press.
Hobson, J.M. (2012), The Eurocentric Conception of World Politics: Western
International Theory 1760 –2010. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Honneth, A. (1998), ‘Democracy as Reflexive Cooperation’, Political Theory,
26(6), 763–83.
Hopkins, A.G. (2002), ‘The History of Globalization – and the Globalization
of History’, in A.G. Hopkins (ed.) Globalization in World History. London:
Pimlico.
Horkheimer, M. (1972), Critical Theory. Trans. Mathew J. O’Connel.
New York: Continuum Press.
Kadlec, A. (2007), Dewey’s Critical Pragmatism. Lanham, MD: Lexington
Books.
Kaldor, M. (2003), Global Civil Society: An Answer to War. Cambridge: Polity
Press.
Keck, M. and Sikkink K. (1998), Activists Beyond Borders. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
Kennedy, P. (1987), The Rise and Fall of the Great Powers. New York: Random
House.
Keynes, J.M. (1919), The Economic Consequences of the Peace. New York:
Harcourt Brace.
Keynes, J.M. (1923), A Tract on Monetary Reform. London: Mcmillan.
Keynes, J.M. (1930), A Treatise on Money. London: Mcmillan.
Kloppenberg, J.T. (1986), Uncertain Victory: Social Democracy and
Progressivism in European and American Thought: 1870–1920. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Kloppenburg, J.T. (1994), ‘Democracy and Disenchantment: From Weber
and Dewey to Habermas and Rorty’, in D. Ross (ed.) Modernist Impulses
in the Human Sciences. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press,
pp. 69–90.
Koopman C. (2009a), ‘Morals and Markets: Liberal Democracy through
Dewey and Hayek’, Journal of Speculative Philosophy, 23(3): 151–79.
Koopman, C. (2009b), ‘Good Questions and Bad Answers in Talisse’s A
Pragmatist Philosophy of Democracy’, Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce
Society: A Quarterly Journal in American Philosophy, 45(1): 60–4.
Bibliography
161
Kymlicka, W. (1999), ‘Citizenship in an Era of Globalization: Commentary
on Held’, in I. Shapiro and C. Hacker-Cordon (eds.) Democracy’s Edges.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Leuchtenburg, W. (1993), The Perils of Prosperity: 1914–32. Chicago: Chicago
Press.
Lind, M. (2012), Land of Promise: An Economic History of the American
Economy. New York: HarperCollins.
Light, A. and Katz, E. (eds.) (1996), Environmental Pragmatism. New York:
Routledge.
Lippmann, W. (1922), Public Opinion. New York: Free Press.
Lippmann, W. (1925), The Phantom Public. New York: Transaction Publishers.
Livingston, J. (1994), Pragmatism and the Political Economy of Cultural
Revolution, 1850–1940. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina.
Livingston, J. (2001), Pragmatism, Feminism, and Democracy: Rethinking the
Politics of American History. New York: Routledge.
Livingston, J. (2011), Against Thrift. New York: Basic Books.
Lukacs, G. (1971), History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist
Dialectics. Trans. Rodeny Livingston. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Martin, J. (2002), The Education of John Dewey. New York: Columbia
University.
Mazower, M. (2012), Governing the World: A History of an Idea. London:
Penguin Books.
McDermott, J. (2007), The Drama of Possibility: Experience as Philosophy.
New York: Fordham University Press.
Mead, G.H. (1915), ‘Natural Rights and the Theory of Political Institution’,
The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods, 12(6):
141–55.
Mills, C.W. (1964), Sociology and Pragmatism: Higher Learning in America.
New York: Paine Whitman Publishers.
Morris, I. (2011), Why the West Rules for Now: Patterns of History and What It
Reveals about the Future. London: Profile Books.
Mosley, L. (2005), ‘Globalization and the State: Still Room to Move?’, New
Political Economy, 10(3): 355–62.
Mumford, L. (1926), The Golden Day: A Study in American Experience and
Culture. New York: Horace Liveright.
Nagel, T. (2005), ‘The Problem of Global Justice’, Philosophy and Public Affairs,
33(2): 113–47.
Niebuhr, R. (1932), Moral Man and Immoral Society. New York: Scribners.
162
Bibliography
Pappas, G.F. (2008), John Dewey’s Ethics: Democracy as Experience.
Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Patomäki, H. (2011), ‘Towards Global Political Parties’, Ethics and Global
Politics, 4(2): 81–102.
Prashad, V. (2008), The Darker Nations: A People’s History of the Third World.
New York: The New Press.
Prashad, V. (2013), The Poorer Nations: A Possible History of The Global South.
London: Verso.
Putnam, H. (1991), ‘A Reconsideration of Deweyan Democracy’, in M. Brint
and W. Weavers (eds.) Pragmatism in Law and Society. Boulder, CO:
Westview Press, pp. 217–42.
Putnam, H. (1994), Words and Life. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Ralston, S.J. (2013), Environmental Pragmatism. Leicester: Troubadour
Publishing.
Rao, R. (2010), Third World Protest: Between Home and the World. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Rawls, J. (1996), Political Liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.
Rawls, J. (1999), The Law of Peoples. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Rodrik, D. (2011), The Globalisation Paradox: Democracy and the Future of the
World Economy. London: Norton.
Rodrik, D. (2012), ‘The Nation State Reborn’, Project Syndicate, 13 February
2012, www.project-syndicate.org/commentary/the-nation-state-reborn
(accessed 4 April 2014).
Rorty, R. (1979), Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Rorty, R. (1989), ‘Philosophy of the Oddball’, New Republic, 19 June 1989.
Rorty, R. (1998), Truth and Progress: Philosophical Papers: Volume 3.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rorty, R. (1999), Achieving Our Country: Leftist Thought in the Twentieth
Century. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Ruggie, J.G. (1982), ‘International Regimes, Transactions and Change:
Embedded Liberalism in the Postwar Economic Order’, International
Organization, 36(Spring): 557–83.
Russell, B. (1909), Philosophical Essays. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Russell, B. (1922), ‘As a Radical European Sees It’, Freeman, 4: 608–10.
Ryan, A. (1995), John Dewey and the High Tide of American Liberalism.
New York: W.W. Norton
Bibliography
163
Scholte, J. (2012), ‘Reinventing Global Democracy’, European Journal of
International Relations, first published online 29 May 2012.
Sen, J. and Escobar, A. (eds.) (2007), World Social Forum. New Delhi: Viveka
Foundation.
Smith, J. (2008), Social Movements for Global Democracy. Baltimore, MD:
John Hopkins University Press.
Smith, W. and Brassett, J. (2008), ‘Deliberation and Global Governance:
Liberal, Cosmopolitan and Critical Perspectives’, Ethics and International
Affairs, 22(1): 69–92.
Stiglitz, J.E. (2010), Freefall: Free Markets and the Sinking of the Global
Economy. London: Penguin Books.
Stiglitz, J.E. (2012), The Price of Inequality. London: Alan Lane.
Talisse, R.B. (2007a), A Pragmatist Philosophy of Democracy. New York:
Routledge
Talisse, R.B. (2007b), ‘Two Democratic Hopes’, Contemporary Pragmatism,
4(2): 19–28.
Tan, K.C. (2008), ‘Global Democracy: International, Not Cosmopolitan’,
in D.K. Chatterjee (ed.) Democracy in a Global World. Lanham, MD:
Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 161–83.
Tarrow, S. (2005), The New Transnational Activism. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Tarrow, S. (2011), Power in Movement. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Wade, R. (2009a), ‘Is the Globalisation Consensus Dead?’, Antipode, 41(S1):
142–65.
Wade, R. (2009b), ‘From Global Imbalances to Global Reorganizations’,
Cambridge Journal of Economics, 33(4): 539–62.
Wade, R. (2012), ‘Why Has Income Inequality Remained on the Sidelines of
Public Policy for So Long’, Challenge, 55(6): 21–50.
Wade, R. (2013), ‘The Art of Power Maintenance: How Western States Keep
the Lead in Global Organizations’, Challenge, 56(1): 5–39.
Wallas, G. (1914), The Great Society. London: Allen and Unwin.
Weiss, L. (2009), ‘The State in the Economy: Neoliberal or Neoactivist?’, in
J. Campbell et al. (eds.) Oxford Handbook of Comparative Institutional
Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
West, C. (1989), The American Evasion of Philosophy: A Genealogy of
Pragmatism. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.
164
Bibliography
Westbrook, R. (1991), John Dewey and American Democracy. New York:
Cornell University Press.
Westbrook, R. (2005), Democratic Hope. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Wu, T. (2011), The Master Switch: The Rise and Fall of Information Empires.
New York: Vintage Books.
Index
Note: locators followed by ‘n’ indicate notes section
Abu-Lughod, J. 138
Adorno, T. 75, 141 n.3
agrarian-based division of labour
146 n.8
Ahamed, L. 139 n.4
American Civil War 3, 16
American Friends for Spanish
Democracy 121
Americanism 2
American pragmatism 2
Anderson, B. 108
animal rights 26
antagonism 71, 98, 107
anti-cosmopolitanism 124
anti-essentialism 107, 151 n.3
anti-globalization movement 7
Appiah, K. W. 121
Archibugi, D. 7
associated human behaviour,
observation of the
consequences 29
associative behaviour 23–7, 29–30,
34–5, 57
consequences of 24–6, 48
incorrect perceptions of 29
private transactions of 24
atomic age, rise of 50
atomic bomb, global
ramifications of 3
autarky 45, 49, 72, 107
Axis Powers 49
Bandy, J. 125
Basel Committee 122
Battle of Fort Sumter 1
Beck, U. 123
Bello, W. 8
Bernstein, R. J. 2, 75, 112, 143 n.3
Bhambra, G. K. 7
Billig, M. 108
Blyth, M. 124, 131 n.3, 142 n.4,
154 n.10
bourgeois democracy 11–12, 59–60,
67–73, 76, 85–9, 100, 115–20,
123, 125
advent of 90
artificial intellectual inequality 66
confines of 61, 68, 97
control of the Great Society 71
cultural inequalities 115–16
cultural reorganization 118
economic stratification 70
educative rhythm of creative
democracy 69
failings of 72
free speech, free press and free
assembly 65
hegemony of 60–1, 71, 73, 117,
125
inequality 69, 72
influence on global democracy
115
intellectual inequality 116
intellectual stratification 70
liberal capitalism and 100
material inequality 115–16
political economy 86, 118
political reorganization 118
problem of 104, 115, 120, 129
relation with global democracy
116
sporadic reforms 86
stratification of 69, 72
structural inequalities of 116
166
Index
Brassett J. 7
Bray, D. 139 n.5, 152–3 n.7
Brazil 122
Bretton Woods regime 1
Britain
as biggest economy in the world 16
gold standard 42, 44
political engagement 44
secret nuclear weapon
programme 153 n.8
British Labour Party 86
Brown, G. W. 6
Calhoun, C. 4, 7
Campbell, J. 133 n.5
capitalism 10, 51–2, 75, 83, 89, 115–16
American capitalism 2, 75
American corporate capitalism 2,
46, 95
consumer capitalism 65
corporate capitalism 2, 46, 95
hegemonic identification of 67
hegemony of 71
palliative measures 71
profit system of 86, 89
twentieth-century capitalism
138 n.4
welfare state capitalism 142 n.4
capitalist economy 95, 99, 118
capitalist social order 75
Caspary, W. R. 136 n.17, 137–8 n.1
centralized federal government 57
Chandler, D. 123
Chang, H. J. 8, 132 n.2
China 3, 122
citizenship rights 7
Civil Rights Act 132 n.1
Civil Rights Movement 1
climate change 9, 96, 123–4, 129
Cochran, M. 3, 6, 113, 119–21, 139,
140 n.10, 151 n.4
cogs 62
communications technology 2, 42, 104
communism 3, 18, 88
opposition of 142 n.5
communist utopia 39
comparative advantage theory
131 n.3
comprehensive unemployment
insurance 69
conflict resolution 136 n.17
conflicts 31, 36, 65
consumer capitalism
hegemony of 65
perpetuation of 65
consumer culture, elements of 66
corporate structure, revolution 17
cosmopolitanism
collapse of the 152 n.6
Eurocentrism of 7
failings of 7
modern cosmopolitanism 6–7
pragmatic cosmopolitanism
152 n.7
rooted 12, 104, 112, 120–1, 125
Council for a Democratic Germany
121
creative democracy
arresting of 57
breakdown of 73, 116
definitive blueprints 76
global level views 51
ideals of 72
international form of 111
within local community 110
national and global eclipse of 66–73
political democracy 37
social and humane 60
stunting of 11, 60, 70
through social intelligence 12, 83,
96, 99, 110
vitality of 112
cultural freedom 86, 95
cultural and institutional lag 144 n.7
cultural matrix 21–3, 25–8, 31–2,
80–1, 94
changes in 25
conception of 133 n.8
consequences of associated
behaviour 26
Index
historical propensity 25
industrial/capitalist-based
societies 134 n.11
intellectual foundations 28
material aspects 135 n.13
perceptions of consequences 26
perpetual propensity 27
variety of associations 26
cultural politics, valorization of
137 n.20
cultural subjugation 100
Dale, G. 153 n.8
Darwin, Charles 20
Deen, P. 95–7, 146 n.9
de-globalisation 138 n.3
democracy
apparent failure of 66
attacks by communism 18
bourgeois democracy 11–12
equality and 88–95
global inheritance of 53
hegemonic identification of 67
national 5, 9–10, 117, 124–5
political democracy 37
problematizations of 128
radical faith in 125
reform of 53
teleological advance of 49
way of life 31–6
conception of democracy 32
co-operative problem-solving
36
democratic realism 31
ethical commitment 13, 33,
35, 37, 78, 89, 97, 108,
137 n.19, 149
ideal or idea 32
political democracy 32
democracy at home
achievement of 76, 103
crisis of 124
cultural reorganization of 18
eclipse of 54
emergence of 129
167
form of 112
international arena 97
linked with democracy abroad
114, 116, 129–30
perpetuation of 144 n.6
persistence 123
political 117
problem of 104, 120, 129
renewal of 118
roots of 120
use of 104
vitality of 114
democratic disillusionment 125
democratic globalization 4–9
democratic governance 56, 122
democratic inheritance 129–30
democratic liberty, conception of 91
democratic politics, fighting faith of
130
democratic realism 10, 15–16, 18–19,
31, 46, 57–8, 62, 65, 132 n.4
in America 19
charge of 16
fascism, and 18
governance of 142
opposition 31
quasi-Platonism 18
rise of 46
superficial agreement with 57
democratic socialism 12, 77, 86–9,
94, 116
form of 76–7, 92, 98, 116
national form of 112
and political economy 89
distributive justice, principles of
146 n.9
Dryzek, J. 5, 7, 124, 139 n.5
Duménil, G. 131 n.3
Eckerlsey, R. 151 n.5
eclipse of the public 57–66
in America 76
cultural and structural
inequalities 116
effects of 66
168
intellectual deficiency 65
intelligence of masses 61
perpetuation of 67
political effect of the 68
ecological democracy 148 n.12
economic inequality 59, 61, 66, 77,
92–3, 96, 144 n.6
effective intelligence 61, 84, 100
efficient market hypothesis 131 n.3
egalitarianism 12, 77, 116
Eldridge, M. 75, 142 n.1
embedded liberal states 154 n.10
employment 59
Englen, E. 122
environmental democracy 148 n.12
equality
economic equality 12, 89, 92–3,
95, 99, 101, 103, 146 n.8
equality between nations 98
ethical commitment of
democracy 89
freedom of information 96
global climate change 96
global distributive justice 100
gross economic inequality 96
human rights 96
of labour standards 98
philosophical liberalism 97
political equality 12, 89, 91, 93
rights of expression 96
of trade conditions 99
women’s equality 26
Escobar, A. 7
European Central Bank 124
European democracy, collapse of 76
European imperialism 1, 42
Eurozone crisis 124
evolution theory 50. See also Darwin,
Charles
exceptionalism 146 n.10
Farmer-Labour Political
Federation (FLPF) 88
fascism 3, 18, 71–3, 78
opposition of 142 n.5
Index
finance-capitalism 59, 92–3
hegemony of 85, 122
financial crisis, aftermath of 123
Findlay, R. 42–4, 138 n.1–2
Fine, R. 4
First Great Globalization 9, 11, 41–3,
45–6, 49, 95
de-globalization period 44
global migration 42
Great Society as 42–5
industrial revolution 42
internationalization of
commercial banks 45
opening up of Asia to free trade
42
radical transformation 42
re-establishment of gold standard
44
rise of trade protectionism 44
trade growth 43
First World War 3, 9, 15–16, 44,
47–8, 70, 98
aftermath of the destruction 51
folly of masses 18
Fordism, mass-production
techniques 62
foreign currencies, depreciations of
47
foreign direct investment 45
Frankfurt School 75
free trade 42, 57, 97–8, 115
Frieden, J. A. 16–17, 42–3, 45,
131 n.3, 132 n.3, 154 n.10
Germany 15, 47–8, 114
hyperinflation 48
Gilded Age 2, 75
Gilens, M. 123
global democracy 1, 6–13, 41, 51–3,
55–7, 70, 73, 103–4, 107–10,
112, 114–26, 129
active part of 109
appraisal of 121
basic provision of 71
collapse of 10
Index
difficulty in creating 56
difficulty facing 73
equality 95–101
freedom of information 96
global climate change 96
global distributive justice 100
gross economic inequality 96
human rights 96
labour standards 98
rights of expression 96
trade conditions 99
fullest expression 120
future of 72
key focal points of 109
modern ideas about 104
nation state as a key vehicle 117
nature of 103
optimism towards the 56
overarching blueprints of 51
post-Westphalian 7–8, 120
potential for 106
problematizing of 103
statist approach 120
theorizations of 119
top-down pathways to 6
transitory stages in 107
two-pronged approach 51
global governance, forms of 8
global governance (UN) institutions 7
global inequality 8, 129
global interdependence 97–8
globalization. See also First Great
Globalization
dating of 138 n.2
economic 49, 121, 136 n.17
effects of 54
fate of democracy 4
modern 49, 131 n.2
nature of 55
neo-liberal 5, 8, 9, 121–2, 130,
131 n.3, 143 n.1
problematizations of 128
reality of 48
relation with democracy 4
rise of 9
169
global justice, minimalist
conceptions 146 n.9
global multilateralism 124
glorious revolution of 1688 90
gold reserves, centralization of 47
gold standards 42
Gouinlock, J. 22, 82, 134 n.9,
143 n.4–5, 147 n.12
Great Community
colonial possessions 47
creation of 11, 106
emergence of 49, 56–7, 95
forming issues 106–7, 110, 117
international associative
relationships 105
international form 70, 99, 111
nation and 106–9
racial and cultural differences 47
social intelligence within 128,
146 n.9
technological advancements 105
Great Depression 3, 44–5, 49, 56, 59,
63, 73, 90
material inequality 59
onset of 141 n.1
political activism 87
trade protectionism 44, 73
Great Recession 122
Great Society
associative relationships 105
complexity 73, 112
concept of 16
consequences of 68–9, 71
consequences engendered by 73
cultural freedom 95
economic equality 12
economic reorganization of 91
emergence of 17, 77
engendering of divided and
troubled publics 73
ethical commitment 94
global conditions 111
global dimensions of 11, 41, 45
globalization and 128
global nature of 47–8, 53
170
industrial and economic relations
62
international associative
relationships 105
international effects of 49–50
irony of 69
manoeuvrings of the 58
national associations 56
national conditions of 111
nature of 41, 63
political equality 12
political ideals 78
problem of democracy 19
regulation of 111
scientific revolutions and 128
social effects of 68
technological advancements 105,
108
transnational associations 56
transnational consequences 72
transnational nature of 73, 112
transnational reality of 50
world nations interdependence
106
Habermas, J. 5–7, 123, 139 n.5,
141 n.3, 143 n.3
habits
of belief 50
conflicting 22
consequences of 24
democratic 76, 79, 85–7, 89, 99,
110, 128–9
diffusion of 146 n.8
intellectual 25
personal moral 21
quasi-democratic 65
scientific attitude 85
social habits 61
social intelligence 77–84, 91, 99,
110, 150 n.13
of thought 106
Hale, T. 7, 9, 123
Hardt, M. 5, 7, 150 n.1
Index
Harvey, D. 131 n.3, 142 n.4, 154 n.10
Hay, C. 121–2, 144 n.6
Heidegger, M. 2
Held, D. 5–6, 139 n.5
Hickman, L 137–8 n.1
Hirst, P. 121–2
historical relativity of culture 31, 36
Hobbes, Thomas 5
Hobson, J. M. 7
homosexuals/homosexuality 26, 29
Honneth, A. 133 n.5, 143 n.3,
144 n.5, 145 n.8
Hopkins, A. G. 138 n.2
Horkheimer, M. 75
hyperinflation 44, 48
IMF 5, 122, 124
immigrants 29
immigration 26, 51
imperialism 43–4, 51, 98–9, 113, 115
economic 152 n.6
European imperialism 1, 42
political 152 n.6
shackles of 71
income inequality 125
India 122
individuality 133 n.6
industrial complexity, rise of 9
industrial democracy 59, 142 n.4
industrial revolution 16–17, 42, 138
first 16
second 16
industrial tariffs, problem of 58
industrial-technological revolution
46, 77–8, 83, 92–3, 95, 150 n.1
inequality 85
institutionalizing of revolution 39
intellectual hypocrisy 59
intellectual inequality 66
intercontinental trade system 42
International Chaos 139 n.6
International Co-operation 139 n.6
international order, reformation of 53
isolationism 71
Index
James, William 2, 20
Japan 43, 47
Kadlec, A. 46, 133 n.5, 137–8 n.1,
143 n.3
Kaldor, M. 7
Katz, E. 148 n.12
Keck, M. 121
Kennedy, P. 16
Keynes, J. M. 43–4, 138 n.4
Kloppenberg, J. T. 15
Koopman, C. 144 n.6, 148–9 n.13
Kymlicka, W. 150 n.1
laissez-faire capitalism 60–1, 90
conception of liberty 61
defenders of 65
democratic realism and 61
hegemony of 61, 63, 68
human liberty 60
ideal of 90
individualism 90–1
liberty 90–1
merits of 63
strictures of 61
laissez-faire liberalism 92, 95, 144 n.7
social consequences of 92
League of Free Nations 121
League for Independent Political
Action (LIPA) 88, 143 n.2
League of Nations 52, 98, 109,
140 n.10
Leuchtenburg, W. 17, 140–1 n.1
Lévy, D. 131 n.3
liberal capitalism 12, 51, 76–7, 99,
115–16, 123, 145 n.8, 147 n.12
doctrine of 115
fundamental reorganization of 116
hegemony of 123
hegemony of the tenets of 116
incompatibility of 117
tenets of 99
liberal democracy 7
gain for the masses within 59
171
liberal democratic governments,
historic emergence 59
liberalism
democratic political 91
economic 59, 123, 154 n.10
failure of modern proponents of 61
philosophical 60, 90, 97
pseudo-liberalism 90
reconstruction of 89, 92
Liberalism and Social Action 3–4, 89
liberty
democratic conception of 93
democratic distribution of 91–2,
94–5, 99–100
economic-liberty 147
historical relativity of 90
human liberty 60
individualism and 90
philosophical liberalism 97
philosophy of liberty 61
reconstruction of 89
Light, A. 148 n.12
Lind, M. 16, 132 n.2
Lippmann, W. 10, 16–19, 58
Livingston, J. 137 n.20, 141 n.1,
144 n.6, 146 n.8
local community 110–12
localism 111
Lukacs, G. 75
Martin, J. 4, 143 n.2
Marxist-style conspiracy 135 n.15
mass communication revolution
105
mass consumption, revolution of 17
material culture 26
material inequality 85, 98
Mazower, M. 123, 153 n.9
McDermott, J. 103, 144 n.5
McGrew, A. 5
Mead, G. H. 39
Mein Kampf 15
mercantilism 60
military forms of warfare 49
172
military technologies, advancement
of 136 n.16
Mills, C. W. 75
modern sovereignty 5, 10, 106, 121
collapse/decline of 5, 10, 107
parameters of declining 109
moral conflicts 32, 34, 36, 82
Morris, I. 16
Mosley, L. 121
multipolarity 123–4
Mumford, L. 2, 75
Nagel, T. 146 n.9
Napoleonic Wars 108
National Association for the
Advancement of Colored
People (NAACP) 143 n.2
nationalism
aggressive side of 108
anti-cosmopolitan 116
bullheaded 107
cosmopolitan 151 n.5
cultural 152 n.7
European 48, 107
exacerbated Nationalism 72
form of 108
hyper-nationalism 72
muscular 140
as positive advance 108
pull of 113
Third World nationalism
147 n.11, 150 n.2
two-sided 108
xenophobic nationalism 44
nationalization of industries 86
national sovereignty 107
nation state
American 42, 70, 115
autonomous 5
community sense 57
counterparts 6
creative democracy 57, 66, 71,
73, 112
democracy reforms 53
democratic praxis 126
Index
disharmony 68
eclipse of public 68, 72
emergence of 151 n.3
European citizens 124
habits of social intelligence 115
importance of 120
intellectual inequality 116
interdependence in Great Society
48
as a key vehicle 117
material inequality 116
modern conceptions 134 n.10
naked power of 109
outdated policies of 107
persistence of 121
political democracy 67
political fusion 107
political standing 99
re-emergence of publics 118
relations with publics 51
role of 104, 109, 139 n.5
stagnation of political democracy
123
status of 5
troubled publics 72
Negri, A. 5, 7, 150 n.1
neo-imperialism, Western nations
152 n.6
neo-liberal globalization 5, 7–9, 121,
130–1
deterritorialization of political
authority 5
midst of 143 n.1
policy recommendations of
131 n.3
primary effect of 5
ramifications of 5
neo-liberal imperatives 5
neo-liberalism 1, 4
hegemony of 122, 124
rise of 122
New Deal era 87
New World Slavery 29
non-whites 29
North/South relations 51
Index
Occupy Movement 7
October Revolution 15
old diplomacy, aristocratic style 52
Origin of the Species 1
O’Rourke, K. H. 42–4, 138 n.2–3
Outlawry for War Movement 121
Pappas, G. F. 142 n.1, 143 n.4,
144 n.5, 147 n.12
participatory democracy 87
Patomäki, H. 7
Pax Romana 48
pecuniary profit system 65
People’s Lobby (PL) 88, 143 n.2
Phantom Public, The 16
philosophical pragmatism 2, 95
Pierce, Charles Sanders 2
planning society 85–8
pluralist philosophy 28
Polanyi, Karl 153 n.8
political democracy
elements of 7
outcome of 68
pincer effect 67
political malaise 67
stagnation of 123
political philosophy 3–4, 9, 11, 19
political responsibility 54, 107, 113
political settlement 15, 28, 31, 34, 39,
78, 82–3
poll taxes 132 n.1
post-democratic bureaucratic rule
124
post-war social democracy, collapse
of 122
post-Westphalian global democracy
6–8, 103–4, 119
advocates of 123
clamour for 123
failings of 125
pragmatic democracy 148 n.13
pragmatism 2, 75, 95–6
Prashad, V. 131 n.3, 152 n.6, 153 n.9
privileged plutocracy 117
problematic states 19–28
173
problem-solving, co-operative 36, 69
protectionism 57, 107
Public and Its Problems, The 3, 9–11,
15, 19, 45–7, 53, 56, 70–1
Public Opinion 16
public(s)
ability of 137 n.20
bottom-up processes of 119
communicative inclusion of 35
conflicts 39
definitions 25–8
diachronic level 26
divided and troubled 56, 72–3
eclipsed 57–8, 73, 125
emergence of 27, 31
fall of 37
functional logic 28
historical relativity of 36
history of 28–31
illiberal 29
interests of 135 n.14
newly formed 30
political efficacy of 126
problems of 45
progressive 29
propriety or reasonableness 28
re-emergence of 118
resistance organized 136 n.16
rise of 28, 37
synchronically and diachronically
27
transnational leaders of 113
Putnam, H. 143 n.3, 144 n.5
racist-inspired literacy tests 132 n.1
racist segregation 59
radical democratic tradition 2
radical third party 88
Ralston, S. J. 148 n.12
Rao, R. 7
Rawls, J. 146 n.9, 148–9 n.13
reasonable pluralism 148
reformed education 69
regressive income tax 59
revolutionary violence 136 n.16
174
Index
Rodrik, D. 8, 42–3, 122, 138 n.2,
154 n.10
rooted cosmopolitism 118
Rorty, R. 3, 88, 131–2 n.4
rugged individualism 61, 70, 93
Ruggie, J. G. 142 n.4, 154 n.10
Russell, B. 2, 75
Ryan, A. 151 n.4
Scholte, J. 6–7
Second World War 3, 49–50, 55–6, 99
destructiveness of 49
developments after 53
old-time diplomacy 50
rise of atomic age 50
semi-socialist market economy 88
Sen, J. 7
sensationalism 65
Siamese’ twins 67
Sikkink, K. 121
slave-based agrarian economy 16
Smith, J. 125
Smith, W. 7
social contract theory 20
Social Democratic Parties of Europe
86
social institutions, reform of 66, 68
social intelligence
appraisal of moral conflict 82
attitude of the mind 79
in the context of Great Society 92
co-operative inquiry 83
cultural matrix and social policy 80
deliberation within the
democratic community 81
democratic habits of 85–6, 99, 115
experimental method of 79, 80
habits of 77–84, 91, 99, 106, 110,
114, 118
justification for democracy
144 n.5
moral and political conflict 82
moral relativism 80
national form of 112
nature of 143 n.5
non-absolutism of 82
organised application of 83
reflective morality 80
remit of 81
role of 79
social policy
formation of 33
participation and communication
33
Spanish-American War 3
spatial globalism 7
state activism 135 n.14
state socialism 86
state theory
futility of 19–28
political instincts 19
state-forming forces 19
Stiglitz, J. E. 122
stratification, intellectual hegemony 63
structural inequality 145 n.8
swing-style democracy 67
Talisse, R. B. 148 n.13
Tan, K. C. 151 n.5
Tarrow, S. 112, 121–2
technological advancements 105, 108
theory of psychology 20. See also
James, William
Third Reich 39
totalitarianism 72, 76, 78, 113
town-meeting 111
trade protectionism 44, 49
transactions, private and public 23–4
transnational activism 112, 121
Treaty of Westphalia 5
triviality 65
Trotsky, Leon 3
Truman Doctrine 3
Turkey 3, 47
two-party adversarial politics 70
United Nations 6, 54, 122
United States
depreciations of foreign
currencies 47
Index
economic output 16
political isolationism 45
re-establishment of gold standard
44
rejected Britain’s political
engagement 44
struggle against Soviet Union 3
Vietnam War 1
violent revolution 10, 30–1, 35
catalyst for 30–1
völksgemeinschaft 72
Voting Rights Act 132 n.1
Wade, R. 8, 122–3, 154 n.11
Wallas, G. 16
war debts 47
wealth inequality 122
wealth redistribution 86
175
Weiss, L. 122
welfare states 154 n.10
Westbrook, R. 2–3, 13, 15–16, 46, 75,
87–8, 91, 99, 132 n.4, 134 n.12,
135 n.14, 137 n.1, 138 n.1,
140 n.10, 142 n.1, 142 n.5,
143 n.3, 144 n.5–6, 151 n.4
West, C. 75, 131 n.3, 150 n.1,
154 n.11
women’s equality 26
workplace democracy 69, 87
World Bank 5, 122
World Social Forum 7
Wu, T. 141 n.3
xenophobia 125
xenophobic nationalism 44
Zapatistas movement 7