JOURNAL OF
SOCIAL AND POLITICAL STUDIES
June 2012
Volume III (1)
ISSN-2229-3647
A Bi-annual journal of Department of Political Science,
University of Allahabad, Allahabad-211002 (INDIA)
CONTENTS
Editorial—Changing Dimensions of Social Justice
6
M.P. Dube
Exploring the Conceptual Roots of Local Government in India
14
B.K. Joshi
A Look at Theory: Civil Society, Democracy and Public Sphere in India
31
Javeed Alam
The Question of Justice in the Contemporary Global Order—
Some Guiding Considerations
43
Anand P. Mavalankar
Social Inclusion through Exclusive Provisions in India:
The Glass is Half Full
51
P.K. Chaubey
State and Talent: Exploring the Dynamics of Talent and Significance
in the State System
79
I.D. Mishra
The Fifth and Sixth Schedule and Tribal Autonomy
89
Dr. Nisheeth Rai
Constitutional Structure, Mechanism and Working of Federalism
in India
101
H.M. Jain
Antony and Cleopatra: Shakespeare’s Epic in Drama
126
Lakshmi Raj Sharma
Book Review
Indo-Persian Historiography up to the Thirteenth Century
147
Women’s Rights as Human Rights
150
An Outsider Everywhere
158
Advisory Board
Prof. Mohit Bhattacharya
Former Vice-Chancellor, Burdwan University, West Bengal, India
Prof. B K Joshi
Former Vice Chancellor, Kumaon University, Nainital, India
Prof. Sudha Pai
Centre for Political Studies, J.N.U., New Delhi, India
Prof. K.L.Sharma
Former Vice-Chancellor, University of Rajasthan, Jaipur, India
Prof. Pratap Bhanu Mehta
Director, Centre for Policy Research, New Delhi, India
Prof. Naresh Dadhich
Vice-Chancellor, M.V. Open University, Kota (Rajasthan), India
Prof. M.P. Singh (Rtd.)
Professor of Political Science, Delhi University, Delhi, India
Prof. M P Dube
Editor, Professor of Political Science, University of Allahabad, India
Contributors
• B.K. Joshi, former Vice Chancellor, Kumaon University, Nainital, India
• Javed Alam, former Chairman, Indian Council of Social Sciences and
Research, New Delhi, India
• Anand P. Mavalankar (Rtd.), Professor of Political Science, Baroda
University, Baroda (Gujarat), India
• P.K. Chaubey, Professor of Economics, Indian Institute of Public
Administration, New Delhi, India
• I.D. Mishra, former professor & Head, Department of Political Science,
D D U Gorakhpur University, Gorakhpur (UP), India
• Nisheeth Rai, Department of Anthropology, Mahatma Gandhi
Antarrashtriya Hindi Vishwavidyalaya (M.G.A.H.V.) Wardha (Maharashtra),
India
• H.M. Jain (Late), former Professor & Head Department of Political Science,
University of Allahabad, (UP) India
• L.R. Sharma, Professor of English, University of Allahabad, Allahabad, (UP)
India
• N.R. Farooqi, Dean, Research & Development, University of Allahabad,
Allahabad (UP) India
• M.P. Singh (Rtd.), Professor of Political Science, Delhi University, Delhi,
India
• Ashok Kaul, Professor of Sociology, Banaras Hindu University, Varanasi
(UP) India
Editor: M.P. Dube
Published Bi-annually by Department of Political Science,
University of Allahabad, Allahabad-211002 (INDIA)
Copyright © 2012 by Department of Political Science, University of Allahabad
All Rights Reserved. Material Published in this Journal cannot be reproduced without the
express permission of the Publisher.
Distributed by
PENTAGON PRESS
206, Peacock Lane, Shahpur Jat,
New Delhi-110049
Phones: 011-64706243, 26491568
Telefax: 011-26490600
email: rajan@pentagonpress.in
website: www.pentagonpress.in
Pentagon Press New Delhi.
Printed at New Elegant Printers, New Delhi.
Journal of Social and Political Studies
• The JSPS is a refereed journal published in June and December.
• Prospective authors are advised to submit the manuscript with an abstract
which should be original and unpublished work.
• The responsibility for statement of facts, quotations given and opinion
expressed in the articles and book reviews published in this journal is borne
entirely by the respective authors. The Editor, Editorial office is in no
way responsible for them.
• 4000-5000 words with endnotes for the articles and 500-1000 words for
book reviews is suggested as an appropriate length.
• Decision on publication is made pursuant to the referees’ comments. No
responsibility is assumed for unsolicited manuscripts.
• Manuscripts should be submitted online as Microsoft Word Document
only to <jsps.au@gmail.com>
Subscription Rates
Institutional (India) 1 NR 500.00
Individual (India) 1 NR 250.00
Elsewhere US $ 25 or equivalent
Correspondence concerning contributions, book reviews, advertisements, orders
and other information’s regarding the journal should be addressed to Editor,
Journal of Social and Political Studies, Department of Political science, University
of Allahabad, Allahabad-211002 (India).
Editorial
6
Editor’s Note
Changing Dimensions of Social Justice
M. P. Dube
John Rawls, the most important and influential liberal theorist of justice in recent
decades, maintained that justice is the first of the virtues of social institutions in
the way that truth is of scientific theories. It has been the subject of intense
argument during the last quarter of 20th century and onwards. The idea of justice
is generally distinguished between formal and substantive senses. In the formal
sense, Justice is correct weighting and proportion in judgments. The core element
of the idea of justice is that like cases should be treated alike. It is a rule of logical
impartiality. On the other hand, what counts as like cases and what involves equal
treatments are domains of substantive principles. What substantive principles are
appropriate in particular situations and what they imply has been debated since
ancient times. Today the most significant kinds of justice are: Procedural or
unpatterned and distributive or patterned or Social Justice. Procedural theories
of justice uphold the ‘rule of law’; justice is concerned with rule-following. The
main concern of justice for proceduralists is not a teleocratic order, rather
maintaining procedural rules to provide conditions for individual freedom. The
most important procedural justice theories are Friedrich Hayak’s commutative
account of justice and Nozick’s entitlement theories. But distributive justice has
become the principal normative concern of modern political life. It has been
defined as a question of equity in the distribution of social goods. Brighouse rightly
claims that “the fundamental question is this: how and to what end, should a
just society distribute the various benefits. (resources, opportunities, and freedoms)
it produces, and the burdens, (costs, risks, and unfreedoms) required to maintain
it?”
Distributive Justice deals with the distribution of benefits and burdens ‘to
each according to his due or fare allocation of burdens and benefits in society.’
There are various principles that determine ‘due’. Each principle can be formulated
in the form of rights, deserts, needs, services, work, moral worth, ability, skill, or
status, and so forth. These principles can be sub divided into desert and nondesert-oriented distributive principles. There is no problem with desert-oriented
distributive principles because a person with merit worthy activity or a valuable
quality should be rewarded in relation to that activity or quality. But most
contentious are non-desert oriented distributive principles. Since the 1970s the
much attention has fallen to these principles of which a larger bulk of
contemporary justice the theorizing is based on contractarian claims- wide ranging
agreement or consensus on a rational procedure- and empirical assumptions
(needs).
Editorial
7
In theorizing distributive justice, Gauthier and Buchanan advance a
sophisticated form of argument of rational choice. To them justice is an outcome
of a mutual bargaining process among individuals in an initial position. They
regard justice as mutual advantage. On the other hand, John Rawls, Barry and
Scanlon regard justice as impartiality. In Rawls theory justice is not seen as a
bargaining position, as in Gauthier. It is the outcome of rational agreement
between discreet individuals. To him justice is ‘the appropriate division of social
advantages’. However, Michael Walzer and Miller attempt to establish a plural
concept of justice.
John Rawls develops a fair way of developing such principles of distribution.
The basic idea in Rawls is ‘to identify a fair arrangement in society for all parties
to agree to without knowing how it will affect them.’ It will cut out the possibility
of arbitrariness in decision about justice. For Rawls, justice should not reflect or
reenforce arbitrary chance or interests, but rather should aim to nullify them for
the sake of basic fairness. Rawls initial task, and his primary innovation, was to
evolve a device to achieve this nullification. For this he conceives an ‘original
position’- a form of rational disinterestedness. Thus the principles of justice for
basic structure of society are the object of the original agreement.
Rawls maintains that justice regulates the distribution of primary goods. The
primary goods include basic rights and liberties, powers and offices, income and
wealth, the bases of self-respect and leisure. The distribution of these goods is
regulated by two principles, the first of which has lexical priority over the second.
The first principle holds that basic rights and liberties are distributed in a suitably
fair way, income and wealth and the rest should be distributed equally unless the
unequal distribution would increase the share going to the least well off.
Rawls’ is an egalitarian vision of justice. It combines values of equality and
liberty in a single conception. These principles are ones that free and equal persons
could accept as a fair basis for social cooperation (Andrew Vincent). Brian Barry
also follows John Rawls. He emphasizes the need for impartiality in the
contractualist method of constructing principles of justice. His central argument
is that we should agree on the rules of distributive justice while remaining impartial
to different notions of the good life individuals have. To both Barry and Scanlon
impartiality reflects a commitment to equality. To them impartiality is primarily
a requirement on the moral and legal rules of society.
The views of Rawls have been attacked both by Robert Nozick and F A Von
Hayak. In their view, justice is not a matter of how benefits or burdens are
distributed, but a matter of protecting individual rights to resources. They
maintain that the concept implies an agency entitled to achieve it, which is
incompatible with the individual liberty. To them goods and opportunities are
justly distributed when they are in the hands of their rightful owners.
The traditional distributional approach has been challenged by various
theorists during the 1990s and onwards; the sole emphasis on distribution without
an examination of the underlying causes of the maldistributions was not acceptable
8
Editorial
to several contemporary political theorists. Iris Young, Nancy Frazer, Axel Honneth
and Charles Taylor argue that while justice must be concerned with classic issues
of distribution, it must also address the process that constructs mall distribution.
To them individual and social recognition, rather than simply fair process for the
distribution of goods and benefits, are the key elements of attaining justice. In
fact, they are influenced by the real world of political injustice. Their central
concern is recognition. They argue that ‘a lack of recognition in the social and
political realms, demonstrated by various forms of insults, degradation and
devaluation at both individual and cultural level, inflicts damage to oppressesed
individuals and communities in the political and cultural realms’. To them it is
the foundation for distributive injustice; therefore the social context in which
unjust distributions exist becomes much more significant. Young says that the
examination of social, cultural, symbolic, and institutional conditions, underlying
unjust distribution is an important component of justice. She says that ‘while
distributional issues are crucial to a satisfactory conclusion of justice, it is a mistake
to reduce social justice to distribution’. A lack of recognition of group differences
determines unjust distributions. She argues that ‘Distributional injustice comes
directly out of social structures, cultural beliefs and institutional contexts. If
distributional differences are constituted, in part, by social, cultural, economic,
and political processes, any examination of justice needs to include discussions
of the structures, practices, rules, norms, language, and symbols that mediate social
relations.’ For Young, distribution is not the only problem; a concepts of justice
needs to focus more on elimination of institutionalized domination and
oppression, particularly of those who represent difference and remain un-, mis,
or mal-recognized.
Likewise, Nancy Frazer also argues that justice is ‘bivalent’. It requires attention
to both distribution and recognition. Both are distinct, though often linked in
practice. She argues that culture is a legitimate and necessary terrain of strugglea sight of justice in its own right, yet also deeply tied to economic inequality. She
focuses on both the structural nature of the construction of the subordinate and
disrespected identities and communities, and on the mal-distribution experienced
by these subjects. To her the recognition- redistribution dilemma is centered on
the problem of ‘group differentiation’. ‘In struggling against cultural injustice, the
politics of recognition tends to promote the specificity of social groups, while the
politics of redistribution works to undermine such specificity. While former is
primarily affirmative the latter is transformative. Sometimes these two modes of
politics create problems for social groups that have both the traits. Frazer tries to
resolve this dilemma between conferring respect upon misrecognized groups
(recognition) and transferring resources to the under privileged (distribution) by
endorsing an across – the – board transformative approach. Thus, to examine
the context of oppression, to understand and remedy existing injustices are the
key issues of the Fazer’s concept of justice. In the political realm, she calls for
‘participatory parity’ of all affected parties for justice. Understanding the social
Editorial
9
norms, language, and mores is key to the understanding of recognitional injustice
in the social and cultural realm. She says that cultural injustice is ‘rooted in patterns
of representation, interpretation and communication’.
For Frazer, misrecognition is an ‘institutionalized relation of social
subordination, rather than an individual experience.’ She claims that a general
practice of cultural domination, a pattern of non-recognition and disrespect are
three processes of misrecognition. Unlike Frazer, Taylor and Honneth focus on
the psychological nature of recognition. Taylor argues that self- worth comes from
the recognition given by others. ‘Misrecognition can inflict harm; can be a form
of oppression imprisoning someone in a false, distracted, and reduced mode of
being.’ For Taylor adequate recognition involves treating others in ways that
confirm and affirm their distinctive identities. He argued that ‘difference blind’
liberalism is deficient to meet the human demand for identity. To him ‘Canon
Wars in Higher Education and Canadian constitutional crises are examples of the
‘politics of recognition’, in which ‘people seek to transform the ways in which
they are being seen and esteemed by others, and so to satisfy the deeply rooted
human need to be recognized as the bearer of distinctive identity.’(Oxford
Handbook of Political Theory,2006,pp.451-55)
For Honneth, recognition involves valuable qualities of individuals or groups.
And injustice is felt in the first instance as a denial of inter-subjective recognition
that violently disrupts a subject’s relationship to herself, whether through the
violation of body, the refusal of basic moral respect or legal protection, or the
denigration of individual or collective ways of life. What is crucial in the analysis
of injustice is not the inflicting of the pain, but the perception of misrecognition
on the part of the victim; that is, injustice is a psychological condition. For both
Honneth and Taylor psychological recognition is crucial element of justice.
In addition to distribution and recognition, there is a third dimension to the
concept and practice of justice, namely Procedural justice. Procedural Justice is
the fair and equitable institutional process of a state. Frazer, Honneth and Young
insist on an integrated approach to the understanding of justice. Young argues
that ‘Justice must focus on the political process as a way to discuss both inequitable
distribution of social goods and the condition undermining social recognition.’
Democratic and participatory decision-making procedures are both an element
of, and condition for, social justice. Young argues that a concept of justice needs
to focus on the elimination of institutionalized domination and oppression. For
this justice must focus on institutions and political processes as a way to address
injustices based on inequitable distribution and misrecognition.
Frazer also advocates integration of Procedural Justice with distributive and
recognitional theory of justice. She argues that ‘when patterns of disrespect and
disesteem are institutionalized, for example, in law, social welfare, medicines, public
education, and/or the social practices and group mores that structure everyday
interaction, they impede parity of participation, just as surely as do distributive
inequities.’ Frazer argues for ‘parity of participation’ She is of the firm conviction
10
Editorial
that ‘to remedy mall distribution we must focus on politico- economic
restructuring; but such considerations will only come along with recognition,
where the remedy is in cultural and symbolic changes in how we regard the
presently misrecognized, only then will participatory parity and procedural justice
be attained.’
These notions of justice based on distribution, recognition and democratic
participation are not contradictory, rather they are integrated. David Schlosberg’s
rightly comments that ‘both distributive inequity and misrecognition hamper real
participation in political and cultural institutions. Issues of justice are not just
bivalent but trivalent. Improved participatory mechanism can help meliorate both
other forms of injustice; but those other forms of injustice must be addressed in
order to improve participation.’
Amartya Sen and Martha Nussbaum expand the conception of justice beyond
John Rawls (distributive justice) by advancing the “capability approach”. They
have developed a theory of justice that focuses on the capacities necessary for
individuals and groups to function and flourish. Along with distribution of goods,
the focus is on how those goods are transformed into the functioning and
flourishing of individuals and communities; the focus is to judge how those
distributional affect our well-being and how we ‘function’. Amartya Sen objects
to fair distribution on the ground that individuals born with different physical
and psychological propensities will generally be unequally efficient transformers
of resources into whatever goals they might seek. Therefore, we should look beyond
distribution and see to what extent individuals are able to be and do with their
primary goods allotments, given their circumstances. Capabilities are about a
person’s freedom to do and to be what they choose in the context of a given society;
the focus is on individual agency, functioning and well-being, rather than more
traditional distributive indicators. Our concern is not in what amount of goods
we get, rather the capabilities that translate the basic goods into the functioning
of human life. Functioning refers to various doings and beings;
Sen argues that while making normative evaluation the focus should not be
on what people can consume, or on their incomes, rather on what they are able
to be and to do. He insists on taking note not only of the ownership of the primary
goods and resources, but also of interpersonal differences in converting them into
the capability to live well. Indeed, he has tried to argue in favour of judging
individual advantage in terms of the respective capabilities, which the person has,
to live the way he or she has reason to value. This approach focuses on the
substantive freedoms that people have, rather than only on the particular outcomes
with which they end up. (Sen’s lecture delivered in Stockholm, Dec.8,1998)
According to Nussbaum, ‘to see each thing flourish as the sort of thing it is’,
is the basis of capability approach. Here it is not important the how much we
have, ‘but whether we have what is necessary to enable a more fully functioning
life as we choose to live it.’
Sen has not prepared a well-defined list of capabilities. He insists on public
Editorial
11
discussion, flexibility, and context specificity in making a list of capabilities. On
the other hand, Nussbaum proposes a list of ten capabilities, which she claims as
universal, although she is not against the contextual modification of the list.
The ‘capability approach’, distribution, recognition and participation are
linked together. Robeyns argues that the capability theory can accommodate both
issues of re-distribution and recognition and yet is broader than even Frazer’s biviolent or tri-violent approach. However, she remarks that the capability approach
is a framework of thought, a normative tool, but it is not a fully specified theory
that gives us complete answers to all our normative questions. It is not a complete
theory of justice. Theorists, Wolf and D-Shalit have tried to modify the approach.
They argue that it also matters whether people can sustain their functioning, and
that therefore the risk and vulnerability also need to be taken into account.
However, the capability approach has been extremely influential in development
economics and has added a new dimension to the concept of social justice.
Traditionally, questions of justice have been central to political life. But in
recent years issues of environment have become an integral part of the discourse
of justice. The Reason is that the environmentalist issues are very much political
in nature. Dobson, environmental philosopher, rightly remarks that ‘the natural
world – normally invisible in political theory – affects and is affected by political
decisions in a way which makes it necessary to consider it a site for political
activity.’ Today environmental and ecological justice have become very important
themes of discussion for social and political theorists and movements. Central to
environmental justice is the distribution of the goods and bads, but, at the same
time, it is tied to some discussion of recognition, political participation and
capabilities at both the individual and community level. In the U.S.A., it is used
to cover the antitoxics movement and the movement against environmental racism.
Generally things like, sewage, industrial waste sites, municipal and hazardous waste
dumps have been concentrated near the working poor, the minorities, deprived
sections and politically disempowered groups. The movement against
environmental racism in the U.S.A. popularized the term “environmental justice”.
It emphasizes that there is a connection between environmental risk and poverty,
that there is also connection between race and environmental hazards. Generally,
deprived sections bear the brunt of the pollution.
Today the neoliberal model of globalization and development has turned the
inequity from bad to worse, both between the North and the South, and between
the elite and the empoverished in Southern nations. It creates a threat to food
security and sustainable livelihood of deprived sections, specially tribals, women
and children. It drains off natural resources for economic gains. Current
development process has devastated natural resources and habitats, created
environmental refugees and is posing a serious threat to the continuation of life
on the earth itself.
Along with equity, demand for recognition and respect for cultures, tradition,
local knowledge and expertise, and ways of economic, social and religious life,
12
Editorial
for authentic participation and capability of functioning of both affected
individuals and communities constitute the elements of environmental justice.
In fact demand for equal, informed and respectful participation in decision-making
is central to environmental justice.
Prior to the development of the welfare state, many societies had made
provision for the support of their vulnerable members through religious and
charitable institutions. These provisions were not regarded as a requirement of
justice, rather a matter of charity. It was during the 20th century that the argument
for support centred around justice. Charity, such as assistance to the sick, the old,
and those in poverty, are regarded as a duty. Such duties of charity are private
and a matter of individual choice, whereas duties of justice are generally taken to
be enforceable by the state. It is Gandhi who tries to synthesize tradition and
modernity by presenting a very comprehensive view of justice.
Gandhi believed in the doctrine of man’s oneness with God and humanity.
The moment a man awakens to the spirit within he cannot remain violent; the
passions, selfishness and violence do not belong to the immortal spirit of man.
‘Since all men’, argued Gandhi, ‘partake in divine essence, they are ultimately one’.
They are not only equal, but identical. Since all mankind in essence are alike,
what one man is capable of achieving is possible for all to attain. As such, violence
has no place in relations amongst mankind; love is the only proper form of relation
between them. It is ‘the law of our being’, of ‘our species’. Love implies care and
concern for others and total dedication to the cause of ‘wiping every tear from
every eye’. The immediate service of all mankind becomes a necessary part of the
activities of human beings. Negatively, it implies non-violence. “In its negative
form it means not injuring any living being whether by body or mind. In its
positive form, Ahimsa means the largest love, the greatest charity. The complete
nonviolence is complete absence of ill-will and active non-violence is goodwill
towards all life. He equated it with humility, forgiveness, love, charity, selflessness,
fearlessness, strength, non-attachment, meekness and innocence.
The state represents violence in a concentrated and organized form. It speaks
in the language of compulsion and uniformity. It weakens its subjects’ ‘spirit of
initiative’, freedom, creativity and self-help. State, therefore, should be organized
in such a way as its activities employ coercion as little as possible and that as large
an area of human life as possible is left to voluntary efforts. A truly non-violent
state is composed of small scale self-governing and relatively self-sufficient,
politically empowered village communities relying on moral and social pressure
and running their own affairs on the basis of local resources and local needs. The
Police are basically social workers enjoying the confidence and support of the local
community and relying not on brute force but on moral suasion and public
opinion to enforce the law. Crime is not an offence requiring punishment rather
it is to be treated as a disease requiring understanding and help. Decisions are
taken by the majority but without overriding the minority. No one should be
compelled to do things contrary to his/her conscience.
Editorial
13
A non-violent state is committed to sarvodaya, the upliftment of all human
beings. It is concerned for the downtrodden – the daridranarayan. His emphasis
on ‘Daridranarayan’ and ‘Swadeshi’ was an outright rejection of capitalism as the
instrument of development and modernization. This concern for the downtrodden
gives Gandhi’s thought its universal relevance in all times and climes. To Gandhi
private property is immoral; it denies the ‘identity’ and oneness of all men. Roots
of exploitation, sensual indulgence and contempt for one’s fellow men lie in private
property. In Gandhi’s view it is a sin against humanity to posses superfluous
resources when others cannot even meet their basic needs. Since the institution
of private property already exists and men are attached to it, it was suggested by
Gandhi that the ‘rich should take only what they need and hold the rest in trust
for the community.
The tactics of Satyagraha, non-violent resistance to injustice and wrong, can
used to develop the capability for functioning. It can be used to end human misery
and degradation. Gandhi said:
My humble occupation has been to show people how they can solve their
own difficulties. ... My work will be finished if I succeed in carrying conviction
to the human family, that every man or woman, however weak in body is the
guardian of his or her self-respect and liberty.
In theorizing justice and its realization, distribution, recognition, participation,
capability, and environmental and ecological components put together, Gandhian
ideas need to be made the basic foundation on which just relations between man,
nature and society should be founded and sustained. The Need to create just order
demands serious research of Gandhian ideas to enable man and nature to live in
peace and harmony with mutual respect and recognition.
14
Journal of Social and Political Studies
Exploring the Conceptual Roots of Local
Government1 in India
B. K. Joshi
Modern local government in India has a rather long and interesting history going
back to the earliest years of British rule under the East India Company i.e. towards
the end of the seventeenth century. However, it was only in the nineteenth century
that the first important steps for the establishment of local government in the
modern form were taken in India.2 The evolution of modern local government
in India has taken place in four phases. The first phase was from the last quarter
of the seventeenth century corresponding with the early years of British rule under
the East India Company to about 1870. The next phase extended from around
1870 to the end of British rule. The third phase began with independence in 1947
and continued to the end of the decade of the eighties of the last century. The
final phase, which commenced in 1989, is continuing.
Corresponding to each phase there is a dominant conceptual view
underpinning the approach. The first phase was largely influenced by a pragmatic
view that in order to get the native population to contribute money for local civic
functions, efforts would have to be made to also involve them, even if in a token
fashion, in local administration. The second phase, which began with the
Viceroyalty of Lord Mayo and reached its culmination with Lord Ripon’s famous
resolution of 1882, shows a departure from pragmatism by conceptualising the
role of local government in terms of the liberal ideal as a means of political
education of the people. Unfortunately, this liberal approach clashed with the
dominant view of British administration in India and by the end of the period
was overtaken by a tendency towards centralisation and strong bureaucratic
control. In the third phase, which began with independence, a strong attempt
was made to make local government subserve the needs of development. Since
development after 1950 was located within a strong centralised framework
spearheaded by the Nehruvian Planning Commission, there was little place for
autonomous local bodies. Following the report of the Balwantrai Mehta
Committee a uniform three-tier structure of panchayati raj institutions was
inaugurated all over the country. The term panchayati raj also came into currency
at this time, although it did not connote a ‘raj’ of panchayats, but a ‘raj’ linking
panchayats to development as subservient institutions. These two thematic ideas
viz. a three tier structure and the erroneous nomenclature have persisted to this
day. The final (contemporary) phase commenced with the introduction of the
64th and 65th constitution amendment bills by the Rajiv Gandhi government in
1989. Though they failed to garner support in the Rajya Sabha in this instance,
Exploring the Conceptual Roots of Local Government1 in India
15
they were subsequently passed as 73rd and 74th constitution amendment acts in
1992 when P. V. Narsimha Rao was the Prime Minister. These amendments were
influenced by the recommendations of the Balwantrai Mehta Committee (1957)
and the Ashok Mehta Committee (i978) and the penchant displayed by Rajiv
Gandhi as Prime Minister for the Union Government to deal directly with local
bodies, bypassing state governments.
Early Phase
In the early phase local government institutions were confined to larger and more
important cities i.e. those with a sizable British population. The first municipal
body was established in Madras in 1688. The other two Presidency towns of
Bombay and Calcutta soon followed suit. These earliest corporations did not have
any legislative backing. They were set up on the instructions of the Directors of
the East India Company with the consent of the Crown. They were, moreover,
non-representative bodies consisting entirely of nominated members from among
the non-native population, and were set up mainly with a view to provide
sanitation in the Presidency towns, as the situation in this respect left a lot to be
desired.3 These early municipal bodies were also not very effective institutions even
in respect of the limited civic function of sanitation entrusted to them.
Act X of 1842 was the first formal measure for the establishment of municipal
bodies in India; but it was applicable only to the Bengal Presidency. It provided
for the setting up of a Town Committee for purposes of sanitation on the
application of two-thirds of the householders. Incidentally, the Act remained
inoperative in Bengal; but Town Committees under it were set up in the two hill
stations of Mussoorie (in 1842) and Nainital (in 1845) on the request of European
residents. Their record too was not very encouraging. When the Government of
India passed Act XXVI in 1850, the municipal bodies of Mussoorie and Nainital
were reconstituted under it. The period after 1850 saw the establishment of a
number of municipal bodies in the country: about 540 between 1850 and 1870
(Tinker: 1954, Table 1, pp. 30-31). The chief among these were Darjeeling (1850),
Simla (1851), Dehradun (1857), Bareilly (1858), Kanpur (1861), Lucknow,
Thana, Howrah (1862), Delhi, Agra, Allahabad, Moradabad (1863), Meerut,
Almora (1864), Saharanpur (1867), and Benares (1868).
It needs to be emphasised that the motivation for establishing municipal
bodies in the initial years was not any commitment to local government on the
part of the British; it was the desire to raise money from the local population for
provision of civic services. Thus, when the Directors of the East India Company
decided to establish a municipal corporation in Madras, they wrote to the Madras
Council on 28 September 1687 that “the people would more willingly and liberally
disburse five shillings towards the public good being taxed by themselves, than
sixpence imposed by our despotical powers (notwithstanding they shall submit
when we see cause)...” (Tinker: 1954, p. 25). A secondary motive was the desire
for “mentoring native political leadership and ameliorating the causes of political
16
Journal of Social and Political Studies
dissent in India, while at the same time reinforcing the structure of colonial rule
by directing native political aspirations towards constructive forms of self
government” (Singh: 2009).
The transformation of municipal bodies from a body of Europeans to
representation of the native population, and from a nominated to an elected body
was a slow and long-drawn process accomplished only in stages. According to
Tinker the main reason for the development of local institutions along these lines
in the 1860s was the financial constraints faced by the government in the aftermath
of the 1857 uprising. Indian finances had been under strain for quite some time
before 1857 as income was almost exclusively dependent on the inelastic land
revenue, while expenditure had been constantly rising due to the number of wars
undertaken by the colonial government. The result was constant deficits. The
response, articulated by James Wilson, the newly appointed Finance Member was
financial decentralisation viz., transfer of responsibility for roads and public works
to local bodies. Similar views were articulated by another Finance Member, Laing,
in 1861underlining the importance of teaching people not to look to the
government for things they could better handle themselves. A resolution of the
Government of India of 1864 also emphasised the principle of local autonomy
by stressing that the business of the country should be done by the people by
means of funds raised by themselves, and the government must confine itself to
doing things that could be done by it alone (Shukla: 1970, p. 45). The process
was carried forward by the decision of Lord Mayo’s administration to introduce
a system of provincial finance whereby importance was assigned to “the necessity
of taking further steps to have local interest and supervision to bear on the
management of funds devoted to education, sanitation, medical help and local
public works” (Shukla: 1970, p. 46).
Decentralisation of powers and responsibility for raising resources to fulfil
the new mandate necessarily entailed inducting more natives into the local bodies
through provincial legislation. This process continued apace during the 1860s and
1870s. As expected, the results varied from province to province as the following
table shows.
Composition of Municipal Boards, 1881
Province
Bengal
Bombay
Madras
N-W Province
Punjab
CP
Total number of
municipalities
Municipalities with
members partly or
wholly elected
Municipalities with
members all nominated
138
162
47
107
197
61
3
10
12
75
5
61
135
152
35
32 (all in Oudh)
192
—
Source: Tinker: 1954, Table 2, p.
38.
Exploring the Conceptual Roots of Local Government1 in India
17
More than three-fourths of the municipalities (546 of the 712 listed) remained
fully nominated. This has led Tinker to remark “by 1880 the principle of local
self-government had been put into practice only in the cities of Calcutta and
Bombay, and in a few of the towns of Central Provinces and North-Western
Province. Elsewhere, although a framework of local administration and local
taxation existed, control was firmly in the hands of the servants of the government”
(Tinker: 1954, p. 42).
Second Phase
The second phase in the evolution of modern local government in India can be
considered to begin with the viceroyalty of Lord Mayo (1869-1872). His most
significant contribution is the policy of fiscal decentralisation initiated by the
Resolution of 1870, whereby provincial governments were given responsibility for
allocating funds for education, sanitation, medical relief and public works.
Provincial governments were expected to rely on local taxation, which, in turn,
would help in the growth of self-government. One result of this reform was that
many provincial administrations like North-West, Punjab, Bengal and Madras
introduced municipal taxation.4
The process of reform of local government took a large step forward in 1882
with Lord Ripon’s famous Resolution on Local Self-Government of 18th May. The
general principles underlying the resolution bear repetition as they underline the
liberal values that motivated it and provided the template for organisation of local
government for many years to come. They may be summarised as follows5:
• Political education is the primary function of local government, of greater
importance than administrative efficiency
• Rural boards, similar to municipal boards, should be set up: the unit of
administration to be small—the subdivision, tehsil or taluka
• All boards should contain a two-thirds majority of non-officials, preferably
elected
• Chairmen of all local boards should preferably be non-officials
• Elections to begin immediately in more progressive towns and extended
gradually to smaller towns and the countryside
• Control over local bodies should be exercised from without rather than
within
• Each province to interpret the general directions of the Resolution according
to local conditions. (Tinker: 1954, p. 45)
Unfortunately, as usually happens, the above principles were not followed in the
legislation that followed. 6 The legislation reflected the prejudices of the
administrators, some of whom were not fully in tune with the liberal ideals of
the Resolution. The main cause of disagreement was whether the Chairman should
be a non-official or the District Officer. The Heads of all major provinces were
in favour of the District Officer; only the Central provinces were in tune with its
spirit. Elsewhere the District Magistrate remained the dominant figure. The
18
Journal of Social and Political Studies
situation was somewhat better in the towns than in the rural areas. These
shortcomings were also recognised by the Indian Statutory Commission, 1929
when it remarked, “No real attempt was made to inaugurate a system amenable
to the will of the local inhabitants” (quoted in Shukla: 1970, p. 54).
By 1885, there was a gradual increase in both the number of municipal boards
that were wholly or partly elected and the proportion of elected members in the
boards. In a matter of four years, between 1881 and 1885, while the number of
municipalities remained almost constant, the number that were wholly or partly
elected went up from 166 to 472 (or from 23 per cent of all municipalities to
about 65 per cent). At the same time, elected members constituted a significant
percentage of the total membership of municipalities in some provinces. This
situation remained almost unchanged for the next twenty years. Despite being
partly or wholly elected bodies, municipalities in the 19th century could hardly
be called democratic bodies in the modern sense of the term. Two features of
elections vitiated their democratic credentials. Members did not represent territorial
constituencies or wards, but were chosen by caste or religious groups. Hence, they
could not claim to represent all people living in a specified geographical space,
but only their caste or religious brethren. Secondly, the electorate was extremely
limited. Tinker estimates that in most provinces it comprised less than two per
cent of the urban population. In Bengal, it was about five per cent. A further
constraint was the system of open voting. As a result, people were reluctant to
vote for fear of annoying powerful citizens. Not more than four or five hundred
voters participated in elections even in the large towns. It was quite common for
candidates to be returned unopposed. (Tinker: 1954, p. 50).
Until the second half of the nineteenth century, any progress in the area of
local government remained confined to the urban areas. The first small step for
bringing rural areas within the ambit of local government was taken in 1869 when
District Local Fund Committees were set up to manage the newly established
local fund consisting of a cess of one anna in the rupee of land revenue, tolls,
ferry charges and surplus cattle pound receipts. One third of the receipts were
required to be earmarked for expenditure on education and the rest for local works.
The District Local Fund Committee, precursor of District Boards, was a
nominated body of landlords and officials, the latter being ex officio members. It
was headed by the district Collector. Taluka Committees were also set up. These
Committees could hardly be considered representative of rural communities.
The system of provincial finance introduced by Lord Mayo in 1970
significantly enhanced the process of financial devolution, though it did not do
much to make the local committees representative bodies. It did, however, lead
to improvement of education, sanitation and communication in the local areas
as more funds became available for these activities. The seeds of a proper system
of local “self ” government are to be found in Lord Ripon’s Resolution of 1882.
It is worth remembering that Lord Ripon sought to bring rural areas in India
within the framework of local self-government, six years before there were any
Exploring the Conceptual Roots of Local Government1 in India
19
rural councils in England. Shukla refers to Ripon’s Resolution as the Magna Carta
of local democracy in India (Shukla: 1970, p. 47).
Lord Ripon’s Resolution envisaged a two-tier structure of rural local bodies
with the ‘sub-division, taluka or tehsil ordinarily forming the maximum area to
be placed under a local board’. The district board was envisaged as only a
supervising or co-ordinating authority. In the course of implementation, this
provision came to be subverted in most provinces. The provincial acts entrusted
the district boards with all the funds and most of the functions. They could
delegate functions and money to the lower bodies at their discretion. Since district
boards themselves were short of funds and without adequate functions, the lower
level bodies hardly got any functions or money. In short, they failed to become
effective institutions of local government. The district boards were, in practice,
largely nominated bodies dominated by the local landlords, who considered it
beneath their dignity to contest elections. In fact, the elected members were
generally looked down upon by the nominated members. They were fully
subservient to the district administration (Tinker: 1954, p. 54). Ripon’s desire
was to develop rural local government on the foundations of the ancient village
system. This remained only a pious wish.
Ripon’s grand dream of establishing a strong and vibrant local self-government
remained a dream. Writing in 1906, Gokhale said that local government “still
remains all over the country where it was placed by Lord Ripon a quarter of a
century ago, and in some places it has even been pushed back”. In support Tinker
points out: “In the early 1900s there were even fewer non-official chairmen in
U. P. and Punjab than in 1882: there were two in U.P. and twenty nine in Punjab,
all presiding over petty municipalities ... and only ten non-officials—all
nominated—as chairmen of ‘city’ municipalities in Bombay, right up to 1910.”
(Tinker: 1954, p. 57).
The next important landmark in the evolution of local government in India
was the appointment of the Royal Commission upon Decentralisation in 1907
‘to enquire into the financial and administrative relations of the Government of
India and provincial governments—and of ‘authorities subordinate to them’, and
to report ‘whether by measure of decentralisation or otherwise’, the system of
government might be ‘simplified and improved’. The Commission submitted its
report in 1909, which incidentally was also the year of the Morley-Minto reforms,
called ‘the first major reform package since the 1892 Councils Act’ as it introduced
the representative principle to the councils attached to the central and provincial
governments. (Keay: 2000, p. 469).
The recommendations of the Royal Commission have been characterised as
“sound but cautious; conceived in terms of administrative improvement, rather
than of national political aspirations.” (Tinker: 1954, p. 85). These
recommendations may be summarised as follows:
• The village must be the foundation of any system of associating the people
with the administration.
20
Journal of Social and Political Studies
• It was no longer possible to restore the ancient village system, but the
panchayat should be re-established as the instrument of a new kind of village
government. The new system should be introduced ‘gradually and
cautiously’.
• The village headman should become the sarpanch with other members being
elected informally. The functions of the village panchayat should include
petty civil and criminal cases, sanitation, minor public works and building
and managing village schools. They should not be burdened with taxation.
They should be supervised by district officers and not by district boards.
• The problem with district boards stemmed from the shortage of funds and
absence of power to manage services for which they were made responsible.
The funds of the district boards should be augmented by (a) transferring
all of the land revenue cess (b) authorising them to raise the cess to two
annas in the rupee (12.5%) and (c) giving block grants to the poorer boards
on a long term basis and not tying funds to specified purposes. Non-local
duties like plague and famine relief and upkeep of trunk roads should
become provincial responsibilities. They should be given a freer hand in the
field of education, public works and medical services. The District Magistrate
should continue to be the chairman of the district board, but he should
function as a ‘constitutional’ head abiding by the feelings of the board.
Control from above should be strictly limited with the provincial
government intervening only to suspend or abolish a board if it failed to
discharge its statutory obligations.
• Taluka and tehsil boards should again be established as the ‘principal agencies
of local government’. They should be assigned specific duties: management
of minor roads, primary education and rural dispensaries, and given 50 per
cent of the district board income.
• Urban bodies should be almost entire free of official control. The chairman
and a majority of members should be elected non-officials. Committees
should be set up for routine supervision of different services. Municipal
boards should have full powers of taxation as well as control over budgets.
They should be relieved of non-local duties like famine relief, town police,
and maintenance of district headquarters hospital. Municipal administration
must be strengthened by appointment of competent persons as Executive
Officer, Medical Officer of Health and Engineer. Higher control was to be
similar to that recommended in the case of district boards: the provincial
government intervening only to suspend or abolish a municipal board if it
failed to discharge its statutory obligations. (Tinker: 1954, pp. 85-87)
The Montagu-Chelmsford Report of 1918, which formed the basis of the
Government of India Act, 1919 (which came into operation in 1921) recognised
the defects of the system. Under the Act, local government became a subject
transferred to provincial governments and placed in charge of provincial ministers.
Powers of local boards were enhanced and the functions were freed from official
Exploring the Conceptual Roots of Local Government1 in India
21
control to a considerable degree. They became responsible to an enlarged electorate
and came to have elected Chairmen, except in extraordinary situations. This Act
spurred the interest of provincial governments in the progress of rural local
government leading to much legislative activity to progressively eliminate official
and nominated membership, widen the franchise and democratise their
functioning, enhance their powers and functions and provide a schedule of taxes
that could be levied by or for local bodies (Shukla: 1970, p. 55).
Between 1919 and 1925 eight provincial governments viz. Bengal (1919),
Madras, Bombay, Bihar, C.P. & Berar, U.P. (all 1920), Punjab (1922) and Assam
(1925) passed legislation for the establishment of village panchayats. These Acts
did not go beyond reviving the old institutions with limited powers and few
financial resources with which to provide a fairly large array of services, viz., water
supply, construction and maintenance of roads, drains, tanks, bridges, wells,
culverts etc, and also perform a number of obligatory functions like village
sanitation, conservancy, prevention and abatement of nuisances, maintenance,
preservation and use of public buildings, street lighting, village school, cattle
pounds and any other duty assigned to them (Shukla: 1970, p. 55). It is hardly
surprising that these bodies remained largely non-functional. Interestingly 27
native states from across the country also enacted similar legislation between 1919
and 1948. The earliest to do so were Cochin (1919), Holkar (1920), Travancore
(1925), Baroda, Kolhapur, Mysore (all 1926) and Bikaner (1928). The last off
the block were Sirohi (1947) and Jaipur (1948) (Shukla: 1970, p. 56).
Third Phase
After independence, the trajectory of local government in India has been shaped
largely by the imperatives of development and the reluctance of state governments
to permit local bodies—both urban and rural—to emerge out of their stranglehold.
In fact, in many instances, local bodies today may be said to be less powerful
than they were in the past. The most important development after independence
was the report of the Balwantrai Mehta Committee, 1957. This committee was
appointed to study the Community Development (CD) projects and National
Extension Service (NES), which it may be recalled, had been initiated for the
uplift of rural areas in 1952 and 1953 respectively. The Committee found that
the progress of CD and NES was hampered by the absence of “a representative
and democratic institution, which will supply the local interest, supervision and
care necessary to ensure that expenditure of money upon local objects conforms
with the needs and wishes of the locality”. Such an institution, in the opinion of
the Committee should be invested with adequate power and appropriate finances
to enable it to evoke local interest and excite local initiative in the field of
development. The Committee accordingly recommended the creation of a threetier system of democratic decentralization (which later came to be known as the
Panchayati Raj System), consisting of the village Panchayat at village level, the
Panchayat Samiti at block level and the Zilla Parishad at district level, and
22
Journal of Social and Political Studies
recommended that the entire development administration should be handed over
to these bodies.
Based on the recommendations of the Balwantrai Mehta committee most of
the states established a three-tier panchayati raj structure. Unfortunately, the
experience of the working of these bodies was none too happy. Many states, it
turned out, were not fully committed to the principle of democratic
decentralization. As a result, despite the existence of legislation, panchayats in many
cases remained a neglected lot. Elections were not held for years at a stretch, and
they were not given adequate powers, functions or role. According to the
assessment of the panchayat system during this period by the UNDP:
However, the legislation that followed the Committee’s Report
continued the earlier enactments of Provincial Governments to re-iterate
the three-tier structure and provide for over-riding powers of the State
Government acting through the Collector. Panchayati Raj was a strategy
for rural development in a context of centralism that was then seen as a
historical necessity. The moral weight of the national movement required
that the aspirations of the peasantry to better conditions of life be fulfilled.
The Government that came to power initiated land reforms and
institutional change to do away with nefarious traditions of discrimination
and domination based on religion and caste. This required the will of
strong Central and State Governments to be pitted against local vested
interests, whether landlords or ‘superior castes’. Moreover, land revenues
had to be reduced and since income levels were low and highly skewed
between individuals and regions, reliance on the spread of indirect rather
than the narrow incidence of direct taxes was necessary, which naturally
resulted in a centralised system of finance. These constraints, along with
others related to the legacy of the Raj, partition of the country and the
enthusiasm for a planned economy, shaped centralism. However, this
centralism was not conducive to the growth in the status of local bodies.
As the funding for Community Development projects dried up by the
mid-1960s, panchayats stagnated. They languished for decades without
funds, superseded by decisions of district collectors, without elections
being held to reconstitute them and remained insufficient to provide
representation for women, Scheduled Castes and Scheduled Tribes.
In 1977, another committee under Ashok Mehta was appointed, which submitted
its report in 1978. The main recommendations of this committee were:
• The 3-tier system of Panchayati Raj should be replaced by the 2-tier
system: Zilla Parishad at the district level and Mandal Panchayat consisting
of a group of villages covering a population of 15,000 to 20,000
• District should be the first point for decentralisation under popular
supervision below the state level
• Zila Parishad should be the executive body and made responsible for
planning at the district level
Exploring the Conceptual Roots of Local Government1 in India
23
• Development functions should be transferred to the Zila Parishad and all
development staff should work under its control and supervision
• Panchayat Raj institutions should have compulsory powers of taxation to
mobilise their own financial resources
• There should be a regular social audit by a district level agency and by a
committee of legislators to check whether the funds allotted for the
vulnerable social and economic groups are actually spent on them
• The state government should not supersede the Panchayat Raj institutions.
In case of an imperative supersession, election should be held within 6
months from the date of supersession
• Nyaya Panchayats should be separate from development Panchayats. They
should be presided over by a qualified judge
• The Chief Electoral Officer of the state in consultation with the Chief
Election Commissioner should organise and conduct the Panchayati Raj
elections
• Seats for SCs and STs should be reserved on the basis of their population
States like Karnataka and Andhra Pradesh reconstituted their panchayati raj system
on the lines recommended by the Ashok Mehta Committee. These, especially the
Karnataka system, were held out as the model for other states to follow. Most of
the other states, however, persisted with the old system.
Critiques of the approach to panchayati raj inherent in the recommendations
of these two Committees have been provided by the noted Gandhian, and onetime president of the Congress Party, U.N. Dhebar (in relation to the Balwantrai
Mehta Committee) and by the noted Marxist and leader of the Communist Party
of India (Marxist) EMS Nambooripad. In his Foreword to L.P. Shukla’s book
Dhebar poses the question whether “self-governing institutions dealing with the
village problems” are “prepared to be media for installing social and economic
democracy or whether they will be simply governmental tools to carry on the
day-to-day administration in the village areas” (Shukla: 1970, p. 2). The question
remains valid today as well, especially in the context of the increasing tendency
to make local bodies function as mere agents for implementation of government’s
development programmes. This question also harks back to Lord Ripon’s position
on the role of local bodies.
EMS who, incidentally was also a member of the Ashok Mehta Committee,
added a note of dissent to the report of the Committee. EMS’s critique emerged
from the larger issue of his understanding of democracy and the imperatives of
federalism within a democratic structure. According to Thomas Isaac “EMS had
a very wide conception of decentralisation, which went far beyond the usual
conceptions of it as bureaucratic decentralisation, or as a process where the local
bodies confined themselves just to civic functions or even development functions.”
In his view decentralization was part of a larger political process whereby
democratic governance would be extended from the central and state level to the
local level (Isaac: 1998). This becomes quite clear from the following excerpt from
24
Journal of Social and Political Studies
EMS’s note of dissent to the Ashok Mehta Committee Report”
The Constitution itself according to me, failed to envisage an integrated
administration in which, apart from the Centre and the states there will
be elected bodies, which will control the permanent services at the district
and lower levels. Democracy at the Central and states levels, but
bureaucracy at all lower levels—this is the essence of Indian polity as spelt
out in the Constitution. Added to this is the fact, in the actual working
of the Constitution, the Centre made increasing encroachments into the
rights and powers of the states.
It was with such a centralized administration at its core that Panchayats
were envisaged in the Constitution and the Balvantrai Mehta Report. It
is, therefore, not surprising that neither the bureaucrat nor the politician
at the states level is prepared to decentralise whatever power has been
conferred to the state under the Constitution. The point is to make a
radical change in the concept of democracy and adopt what is called fourpillar democracy (quoted by Isaac: 1998).
He goes on to say:
I cannot therefore, think of Panchayati Raj Institutions as anything other
than the integral part of the country’s administration with no difference
between what are called the “development” and “regulatory” functions
(quoted by Isaac: 1998).
Final Phase
The final phase can be identified with the efforts of Rajiv Gandhi as Prime
Minister to provide constitutional protection to local bodies and rescue them from
the “whims” and arbitrary actions of state governments. As Prime Minister he
had started the practice of interacting directly with district Collectors on the
development problems of the districts. In 1989, his government introduced the
64th and 65th Constitution amendment bills in Parliament to bring rural and urban
local bodies respectively within the ambit of the Constitution. The amendment
bills provided the template for compulsory constitution of local bodies (rural and
urban) in all states. The intention was to ensure that every state would have to
constitute such bodies within their jurisdiction and not supersede them at will.
Unfortunately for the Prime Minister, these amendments could not pass muster
in the Parliament. Though approved by the Lok Sabha, they were rejected by the
Rajya Sabha. Rajiv Gandhi ceased to be Prime Minister soon after. The Congress
Party government, which returned to power under P. V. Narsimha Rao in 1991,
was successful in getting these bills passed as the 73rd and 74th amendments to
the Constitution in 1992.
These amendments created a uniform structure of rural and urban local
government in the country. The noteworthy features of these amendments, which
added Part IXA to the Constitution, are:
Exploring the Conceptual Roots of Local Government1 in India
25
• Three-levels of local bodies (district, intermediate and village) are now
mandatory for the rural areas (for States and Union Territories with a
population less than 20 lakhs the intermediate level is not mandatory)
• Three categories of local bodies (Municipal Corporations , Municipal
Councils and Nagar Panchayats) are mandatory in the urban areas
• Elections to rural and urban local bodies are to be held compulsorily every
five years
• If, for some reason, a local body is dissolved prematurely then elections to
elect a new body have to be held within a period of six months
• Elections to rural and urban bodies are to be conducted by an independent
State Election Commission
• Every state is required to constitute a State Finance Commission at interval
of every five years to advise on what portion of the State’s revenues should
be devolved to the local bodies; what the principle of devolution should
be; what should be the principle of distribution of shares between rural and
urban bodies and inter se distribution between different categories of local
bodies; and what steps need to be taken for strengthening local bodies and
augmentation of their resources
• Reservation of one-third of the seats for women and for SCs/STs in
proportion to their population
The import of these amendments was to establish direct links between the Central
government and PRIs bypassing the state governments and devolving funds
directly to them. This was quite the opposite of real decentralisation. In a strong
critique of the 73rd and 74th Constitution amendments EMS argued: “The
Panchayati Raj—Nagar Palika legislations that came out of Parliament is (sic.)
thus a complete negation of all the principles upheld by the ruling and opposition
parties in the state (Kerala) for a quarter century. It forced on the state the threetier set-up, which had been consistently opposed by all the political parties in the
state. It brought about a complete separation of rural and urban self-governing
institutions, making the Collector and other bureaucrats at the district level lords
of all they surveyed.” (Isaac: 1998).
Conceptual Strands
The foregoing analysis shows that there have been at least three main conceptual
strands that have influenced the evolution of modern local government in India
at various periods. The first is represented by the desire of the British rulers to
transfer some of the responsibility to the native population for management of
cities and towns initially, and rural areas subsequently. The motivation for doing
so was to raise money from the local people through taxation in order to pay for
local civic and social services like sanitation, drainage, maintenance of streets and
roads, street lighting, primary education, health facilities etc. This followed from
the hallowed principle ‘no taxation without representation’ that goes back to the
Magna Carta of 1066, and was stated most forcefully by the American colonies
26
Journal of Social and Political Studies
at the end of the eighteenth century. It needs to be remembered that the principle
of local involvement and representation within this framework was always subject
to strict limits and control imposed by the official administrative system.
Incidentally, the paternalism underlying this approach to local government persists
even today in many essentials.
The second strand of thought is represented by the attempt to see local
governments as institutions for promoting development. The reports of the
Balwantrai Mehta and the Ashok Mehta committees are the best examples of
this approach. I would venture to add that it also permeates the 73rd and 74th
constitutional amendments in substantial measure, though they have also made
some hesitant attempts to promote local bodies as institutions of selfgovernment. It is useful to bear in mind that these amendments derive their
inspiration and validity from Article 40 in Part IV (Directive Principles of State
Policy) of the Constitution, which directed the State to “organise village
panchayats and endow them with such powers and authority as may be necessary
to enable them to function as units of self-government”. This Article, it may
be recalled, was a grudging concession to Mahatma Gandhi’s concept of
Panchayati Raj, about which Dr Ambedkar had serious misgivings. On one
point, however, I am quite clear: the basic structure of Panchayati Raj as it exists
in India today bears little relation to Gandhi’s ideas on the subject. The
Gandhian concept of governance moves in concentric circles from the village
upwards, not downwards from the central government, as is the pattern today.
There is, however, some built-in tension, reflected in the language of the 73rd
Constitution Amendment Act, between the Gandhian notion of ‘village
republics’ exemplified by Art. 243 G that gives the panchayats responsibility
for “preparation of plans for economic development and social justice”, and their
dominant role as implementing arms of state and central governments as
mentioned in sub-section (b) of the same article which says the PRIs will be
responsible for “implementation of schemes for economic development and
social justice as may be entrusted to them including those in relation to the matters
listed in the Eleventh Schedule” (emphasis added) (IRMA, p. 35).
A recent analysis that attempts to widen and link the developmental role of
the PRIs to the changing relationship between the state, civil society and discourses
of citizenship within the context of an evolving liberal democratic political order
deserves attention and may be identified as a fifth conceptual strand. The State of
Panchayats: 2007-08 by IRMA provides the clearest statement in this respect as
will be evident from the following quote:
The current appreciation of the importance of ‘bottom-up planning
and the role of PRIs in facilitating such processes marks a significant
conceptual shift in the way that the relationship between the state and
citizen is being imagined. In this regard, the idea of civil society, that
space in which citizens act in concert (formally or informally) to exercise
critical surveillance over the state to keep it accountable becomes
Exploring the Conceptual Roots of Local Government1 in India
27
important. PRIs represent an important step in bringing the citizenry,
civil society and the state’s developmental objectives into greater harmony.
This has significant implications for the changing contours of our liberal
democratic political order, one that had its origins in a colonial past.”
(IRMA, p. 20)
The third conceptual strand is represented by the liberal approach of viewing
local governments as essentially political institutions fulfilling the needs of
representation and political education. From this perspective they are entitled
to distinctive powers and functions, a specific fiscal domain and not subject to
unnecessary control from higher levels of government. They have to be seen as
part of the structure of governance at the local level. Lord Ripon’s Resolution
is the earliest expression of this approach to local government. Unfortunately,
as I have shown, his ideas were subverted in actual practice. Dhebar’s comment
on the Balwantrai Mehta Committee Report also echoes the liberal view of seeing
local government essentially in the context of democracy and politics. In this
context it is useful to bear in mind that in an important sense only the village
panchayat and the urban municipality can be considered as local government.
It is also not accidental that they alone among local bodies have the power of
taxation (SARC: 2007, p. 88).
A fourth conceptual strand, which may be called the radical view, can be
found in the ideas of EMS Namboodiripad. EMS’s critique of the Balwantrai
Mehta Committee and Ashok Mehta Committee, though supportive of the idea
that local government has to be seen in the context of political democracy, goes
beyond this limited framework. He also brings in the notion of federalism and
enlarges the ambit of the critique to encompass the constitutional scheme of
centre-state relations, especially the centralisation inherent in it, as well as the
subsequent steps to further centralise power in the hands of the Union
government. As the Chairman of the Administrative Reforms Committee of
Kerala (1958) EMS was instrumental in proposing a two-tier structure of local
government with panchayats and municipalities at the grass root level and a
district council at the district level. The powers and functions of the panchayats
included major responsibilities in revenue administration and many regulatory
functions, besides normal civic and development responsibilities. He visualised
the district councils as comprehensive bodies that would coordinate the functions
of panchayats and municipalities and be made responsible for the entire field
of development administration in the district in a phased manner. He coined
the term ‘district government’ to define the role that he envisioned for district
councils (Isaac: 1998).
The Second Administrative Reforms Commission (SARC) in its report on
Local Governance (2007) reiterated the need for a District Council somewhat
similar, though not fully so, to what EMS had proposed in Kerala. It also used
the term District Government just as EMS had done. A major point of difference
between the two related to the role of the Collector. While EMS wanted the
Journal of Social and Political Studies
28
Collector to be subservient to the district council, the SARC favoured the retention
of the Collector system as an ‘interim mechanism’. After examining arguments
against and in favour of the Collector’s role in relation to the District Council
the SARC concluded:
The Commission is of the considered view that a golden mean between
these two positions is desirable and the District government must be fully
empowered while utilising the institutional strength of the District
Collector.
The Commission believes that these two objectives can be realised by
making the District Collector function as the Chief Officer of the District
Council. In such a case the Collector’s appointment should be in
consultation with the District Council. The District Collector-cum-the
Chief Officer would have dual responsibility and would be fully
accountable to the elected District Government on all local matters, and
to the State Government on all regulatory matters not delegated to the
District Government (SARC: 2007, p. 31),
Conclusion
Finally, I wish to emphasise that restructuring the system of local government in
India is an essential prerequisite for an effective and empowered representative
democracy (see Joshi: 2010 for a fuller discussion of this theme). Effective
representation of the people at large in institutions capable of taking care of their
immediate problems can only be provided by decentralised institutions that are
fully empowered. There is little doubt that it will also lead, in course of time, to
improved governance. The argument of efficiency and administrative convenience,
generally given in support of decentralisation and local government can only be
a secondary one at best. The primary argument is political—promoting
participation and representation, deepening the roots of the liberal democratic
structure and giving voice to the citizens. A necessary reform for achieving this
goal is a radical re-orientation of the civil service. Reform of the administrative
system has to accompany any attempt at bringing about effective decentralisation.
As long as the Collector system, along with its attendant mindset and attitudes,
persists at the local level, any hope of meaningful empowerment of local bodies
and effective decentralisation would remain only a hope. We will have to go back
to the drawing board to fashion anew the framework of the administrative
structure conducive to an empowered decentralised polity. Clearly, I do not share
the optimism of the Second Administrative Reforms Commission that it is possible
to integrate the office of the Collector into the framework of a genuinely
empowered local government structure.
NOTES
1.
I have preferred to use the term ‘local government’ instead of the more prevalent ‘local-self
government’, which appears to be unique to India since elsewhere (including Britain that has
been the model in this case, as in many others) the preferred term is simply local government.
Exploring the Conceptual Roots of Local Government1 in India
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
29
The reason for this idiosyncracy is an interesting one. On the one hand it refers to the
sharing of power between the colonial government and the native population, whereby the
latter were given some limited powers over local affairs, whereas there was no such sharing at
the former level. On the other hand, it was a convenient device to distinguish municipalities
from the Presidency or provincial government, which at that time were known as the local
government (Singh: 2009).
Two caveats need to be entered here. Firstly, India of the nineteenth century refers, for the
purposes of this paper, only to British India as defined in the Interpretation Act passed by the
British Parliament in 1889 as follows: “The expression British India shall mean all territories
and places within Her Majesty’s dominions which are for the time being governed by Her
Majesty through the Governor-General of India or through any Governor or other officer
subordinate to the Governor-General of India”. It excludes any territory under the native
rulers or princes. The state of local government in princely India constitutes an area of
complete ignorance to me, and maybe considered a shortcoming of this paper. I keenly look
forward to the labours of a researcher to fill this gap. Secondly, I have not made any reference
to the pre-British history of local government, as I agree with (a) Tinker (1954, p.15) who
says that “Local government in present-day India…..has inherited but little from indigenous
local institutions”; (b) IRMA (2009, p. 33) according to which “The local government
institutions set up during the colonial period and subjected to various degrees of
transformation in the post-independence period were not the outcrop of …traditional
institutions. There was a definite ontological break, from being traditional and hence
deriving legitimacy from the cultural sphere, to being statutory/administrative creatures
belonging to the rational-legal sphere of the state.” In similar vein B. Maheshwari in Studies
in Panchayati Raj argues “However in our search in the past we should not forget that the
tradition of village bodies was much different from the system of Panchayati Raj today. The
old Panchayats were a spontaneous growth from the people and did not depend on any
statutory regulations. They served a society based on Varnashram Dharm. The domination of
higher castes in the old panchayats indicated the emphasis on natural leadership in the
village. They were the basic units of government and were conspicuous by the totality of their
functions. There may have been some control and supervision of the central government, but
by and large, these bodies wielded great independence and were more well knit units of local
government, looking after the entire administration of the village.” (Quoted by Shukla:
1970, p. 29).
About Calcutta S. W. Goode wrote in Municipal Calcutta: Its institutions in their Origin and
Growth (1916): “The city was little better than an undrained swamp, surrounded by malarial
jungle and pervaded by a pestilential miasma” (quoted in Singh: 2009).
The resolution stated: “Local interest, supervision, and care are important to success in the
management of funds devoted to education, sanitation, medical relief, and local public
works. The operation of this resolution in its full meaning and integrity will afford
opportunities for the development of self-government, for strengthening municipal
institution, and for the association of Natives and Europeans to a greater extent than
heretofore in the administration of affairs.” www.indianetzone.com/24/mayo_s_resolution_
1870.htm and www.indianetzone.com/24/lord_mayoo.htm
The full text of paragraphs 5, 6 and 7 the Resolution, which contain the most important
ideas set forth by Ripon, can be found in Shukla (1970), pp. 48-49
Municipal Acts: 1883, North-Western Province; 1884, Madras, Bombay, Bengal and Punjab
District Board Acts: 1883, North-Western Province, Punjab, Central Provinces; 1884,
Madras, Bombay; 1885 Bengal.
30
Journal of Social and Political Studies
REFERENCES
Institute of Rural Management (IRMA), State of Panchayats: 2007-08, Vol. I, Thematic Assessment
Isaac, Thomas (1998), “EMS on Economics and Politics of Decentralisation”, The Marxist, Vol.
14, No. 01-02 (http://www.cpim.org/marxist/marxist_index.htm).
Joshi, B. K. (2010), “Towards a New Architecture of Local Government with Special Reference to
Uttarakhand”, Doon Library & Research Centre, Dehradun & Centre for Budget and Policy
Studies, Bengaluru
Keay, John (2000), India: A History, New Delhi: Harper Collins
Report of the First State Finance Commission of Uttaranchal: 2002–2006, Vol I, Main Report
(June 2002)
Report of the Second State Finance Commission of Uttaranchal: 2006–2011 (June 2006)
Second Administrative Reforms Commission—SARC (2007), Sixth Report, Local Governance: An
inspiring journey into the future
Shukla, L.P. (1970), A History of Village Panchayats in India, Smt.Chandrika Shukla, Trimbak
Vidya Mandir, Nasik
Singh, Arkaja (2009) “Local Self-Government in Colonial India: self-government by natives and
the development of municipal institutions” (unpublished mimeo.)
Tinker, Hugh (1954), The Foundations of Local Self-Government in India, Pakistan and Burma,
London: The University of London, The Athlone Press UNDP, Human Development
Resource Centre (n.d.), “Decentralisation in India: Challenges & Opportunities”(http://
data.undp.org.in/hdrc/dis srs/challenges/DecentralisationCO.pdf )
Civil Society, Democracy and Public Sphere in India
31
A Look at Theory: Civil Society, Democracy
and Public Sphere in India
Javeed Alam
By looking at the case of India and working on the margins of theory, I want to
examine and reformulate two received notions about civil society and the public
sphere. In the first place it is of some consequence to look at the conceptual
baggage we get from Habermas. The Pattern of emergence of and the manner of
evolution of social institutions and the surrounding conditions has been radically
different in the post-colonial societies. What are the issues of general interest in
these societies around which dialogues take place? What is the manner of public
debate? What are the relations between the ends undertaken and the means
adopted? What kind of dialogic space for debate gets created? What also needs
critical inquiry is the received belief based on the historical experience of Western
Europe, that civil society is necessary or democracy and that is deeply supportive
of it.
Such an investigation is called for because civil society and public sphere are
professional terms; that is, concepts given for an earlier historical experience by
social scientists. Terms, which emerge out of or get constructed at certain inaugural
moments of, in history, have a tendency to carry original assumptions when these
are applied universally, globally at different historical junctures, some problems
arise. How, in spite of the internal colouring, will it be possible to rework their
relevance and adequacy for different historical moments. Different countries are
all caught up in comparable historical developments marked by the rapid growth
of capitalism and the simultaneous expansions of modernity. I believe that while
we cannot go back in history, it is equally true that history never replays itself. So
to look for in India what was there in Europe will be a futile exercise.
Take Democracy as an idea and how popular aspirations articulate around
that. Or, what are the modes of self-articulation of civil society in different parts
of the world. I will continuously move, as I look at India, from one to the other.
The nature of the relationship between Democracy and the Civil Society in
India is a rather complex one, unlike in most of the western democracies. The
route and the itinerary of an institutional set up or a political formations or a set
of practices is never quite the same in two different situations. When the historical
epoch and the conditions within which these take shape are different then the
dissimilarities can be quite pronounced. Similar institutions with their associated
values get transcribed in different socio-economic conditions and cultural practices
in entirely distinct ways.
Any universal trait pertaining to the social life of man can exist only as molded
32
Journal of Social and Political Studies
in and infinite variety of historical circumstances. This is so because practices
around the same value tend to vary a great deal. Practices around the value of
friendship or hospitality among the Eskimos are not quite the same as among
the Andharas in India. In the same way a value or virtue like (personal) autonomy
may have a different reflection in the cultural practices of different societies. At
what point it becomes excess from moderation, to see this in Aristotelian terms,
and turns into anarchy or license cannot be answered theoretically for all times
or for all societies at any particular point of time. Such a question has to be settled
with prudence within the circumstantial and contextual constraints; there are
certain givens in every society, which the actors cannot remove from the sense of
action. For instance, assume the case of public display to body as a choice of
autonomy; it obviously varies a great deal from one society to another. Such
therefore is the case with democracy and civil society or the public sphere. Thus
what we get in the world is not a Democracy but much rather democracies, similar
yet so different.
The story will be the same with those surrounding features or conditions, or
the overall atmosphere in general, which became facilitative to the development
and functioning of democracy. One such facilitative condition was, and a necessary
one at that, was the rise of the civil society- the market and the public sphere.
Civil society had a fraternal relation with the national community in west
European societies. The two together were a result of the beginning of the same
democratic awareness. This awareness was democratic in special sense. Ascendant
capitalism was, at one level, breaking down the local isolation of people by forcing
them into market exchanges of goods, services and contracts. Along with this there
was the emergence of new types of conflicts that market societies have always been
prone to. People thus started developing common understanding and new ways
of handling discord; this to the extent that they could communicate and therefore
the vernacular languages too became important. In this, in Europe, was the
beginning of national communities. Growing capitalism by bringing people into
direct interaction was also, at another level, rapidly dissolving the hold of feudal
communities in which people were bound in relations of dependence as superior
and inferior. Because of this, the sense of subservience was breaking down. It is
in this escape that we see the emergence of individuated persons with
accompanying changes in their sense of being person. Such an emerging sense of
person also gave rise to new imaginings about life and society. We therefore see
in Europe of the time a festive play of ideas. The interplay and clash of these
created contestants and the public sphere comes to be what it is out of this
contestation. This is what made the social formation emerging with the rise of
capitalism liberal in spirit, if not yet democratic in content.
The awareness of this was therefore democratic, though in a nascent sense.
Civil society crystallizes in the course of evaluation of this change. In that sense
the two the civil society and democracies were deeply supportive and facilitative
Civil Society, Democracy and Public Sphere in India
33
for each other. This historic development is the source of belief that democracy
needs civil society to survive and thrive; that it cannot do without its support.
I want to examine the relevance of this proposition and then to see in what
way does the civil society relate to democracy in India. This is important because
a vast literature has been growing over the last many years arguing the importance
of civil society for democracy it is true that the civil society has been growing
and has become quite vibrant. Powerful new “social movements” have entered
the common space of contestations and taken roots in society. Today it is not
possible to talk of popular movements without also considering these NGO’s.
The mass media—both print and electronic- have seen an enormous expansion.
Many other more conventional modes of articulation have also seen vast increase
in their reach. Around all of these there is greater publicity and knowledge of
worldly affairs, as if a large part of society is in constant communication. It can
still be argued that in spite of its visibility, but on a closer look, below the surface,
we can also see it getting eroded. It is both expanding and getting challenged at
the same time. If this is so then in the background of what has been said so for
the question that needs to be addressed is whether civil society is necessarily a
pre-condition for the success of democracy, in the present times?
Let us look at the initial trajectory of the civil society in India. Colonialism
did not lead in the early period to any mass democratic awakenings. In the
beginning there were among the people, especially the peasantry, rebellions and
revolts against the colonial depredation. Among the modern emerging elite there
was no concern or even attention to what was happening in that part of the society.
There was though a vociferous debate around the value of western or our own
indigenous traditions. This interestingly has still not died down; in fact, there
has been a revival of this in the last few decades but in a virulent form unlike at
the time when it was more a civilized exchange of ideas. Nevertheless induced
modernization- bourgeois property, capital accumulation, trade and industry,
urban life, modern education and so on together with the dislocation of peasantry
led to the loosening of earlier social bonds. There was no exodus like in Europe
but people were let lose from their earlier bonds, at varying speeds from different
communities and regions but everywhere more pronouncedly from the three upper
castes. This took various structural shapes like the formation of new classes,
professional groups, etc. This was the beginning of the process of individuation
in the Indian conditions, induced from outside to begin with.
The social being of the individuated persons or one becoming such is
something which, also give rise to a sense of difference from other and therefore
also a sense of distance without necessarily, as hinted above, a sense of break from
the community one lives in. Feeling oneself to be different and also give rise to
sense of private in the sense that something of (or in) “me” cannot always be
open for monitoring, that unsolicited social regulation of my personal life is a
kind of invasion. Such a notion of being “private” is an important aspect of
34
Journal of Social and Political Studies
becoming modern. It therefore happens that these individuals with a growing sense
of private come together to constitute the modern public. The process of
individuation is the moment of birth of multiple claims on the part of the person,
of claims and preference in terms of newer ways of experiencing the world. It is
here that the need for “rights” also begins to be felt by persons who hitherto could
live without the sense of such a need. In India, in conditions like these that the
“public”, in the modern meanings, took shape. Pre-modern communities did not
dissolve. (They are still vibrant and remain ambivalently oriented to modernity.
Resistance to modernity and bargaining for its advantages were and are two sides
of the same process.) But their boundaries were loosened and redrawn. Their
persistence and resilience together with the ongoing process of individuation has
been a source of enormous strain in the life of the people and the functioning of
the Public sphere, as the site for contestations relatively free of the constrains of
power or the regulatory pressure of the state. This is part of the story of the making
of civil society in India. I will in the following pages pursue this story in relation
to the working of democracy. The Story reads so different from earlier histories.
But before a brief recount of the European experience which, is our point of
departure.
Civil Society in European Philosophical writings and western historiography
is a special kind of society. Not every society is a civil society. It comes about
through a combination of contradictory features. We have already seen that its
origin coincides with the rise of capitalist society wherein more and more people
were being pushed into the market. Market is the place where one is left to herself
to take care of all one’s needs. Communities on which one leaned are not there
to assist us get on with the life. It is also the place where everyone is a maximiser
of one’s interests. Market also is a place, which for the fist time creates a
(permanent) public (everyone is anonymously together) unlike earlier societies
where public, would get created on special occasions like pilgrimage but then at
the end of it would dissolve into the domestic. Civil society thus at its one pole
is a secularized public space made up of atomised, egoistic individual thrown into
the competitive bourgeois world. That is why Hegel considered it to be the site
of egoism, willfulness, whim, caprice, etc.: that is the world of particularities.
Capitalism created an “exodus”, to take a term from Hegel, from the pre-existing,
primordial communities, making for the society of such dissociated individuals.
If market were the only cave where to live the human life, then all of us would
die of suffocation. Ascendant capitalism was also the cause of, as we have seen
above, democratic awareness and of new bonds of interests and concerns. New
ways of imagining the society and purposes of life became available to the people
the individuals in the bourgeois society also, over time, became bearers of rights,
civil and political. In terms of emerging values, concerns, and interests people
got together for common exertions and conversations; ideally, as if everyone is in
conversation with everyone else in new ways of imaging. Something called, to
Civil Society, Democracy and Public Sphere in India
35
borrow a term from Habermass, the “bourgeois public sphere”, the other pole
of the civil society took shape; something which ought to be accessible to all
without interference of power, a world of right bearing individuals. This
combination of contradictory elements makes it a specific kind of society and we
should, at least, be clear in employing the term.
It is for the reason of contradictory presence of traits, that it has been used
in diverse ways; sometimes ideologically loaded and at other simply unnecessary.
After the collapse of the socialist bloc a lot of western commentators have talked
of market driven social life as civil society. Or, in the wake of globalization with
its attendant privatization of welfare functions, NGO’s act, on the behest of World
Bank, as if they really make up the civil society. Both these views must be resisted.
Market now, in the era of globalization, has become a place of predatory practices,
especially so in the third world countries where both the multi-national capital
and the local bourgeoisie are out to take away those small buffers that made live
livable for the poor. It is no doubt true that many of the NGO’s are doing
commendable work but the World Bank perspective of privatization of social
welfare functions is playing havoc with the lives of vulnerable sections of society
like the women, children, Dalits, tribals, the sick, and so on. Both these views of
civil society are not only restrictive but are also empty-headed in relation to the
requirements of democracy in countries like India. Many others refer to the whole
of society minus the institutions of power as civil society. Still other have employed
the term when simply saying society should do.
I would suggest that, in today’s context, the public sphere in the liberal
societies where right-bearing individuals battle for the recognition of ideas,
convictions, and social preferences is what ought to go for the civil society. This
being so, it is simply clear that a large number of people in societies like ours are
only nominally right bearing nor are they allowed, or even capable of seeking,
access to any discursive space. They are just not equipped or accomplished, by
the terms set for in received theory, to belong to the public sphere. And yet they
struggle to be part of the public contestation in terms of demands that are rational
or reasonable and therefore capable of public defense but lacking in abilities or
aptitudes to engage in a sustained rational dialogue. This is where we have to
seriously think through because according to habermas the public sphere cannot
but be a dialogic space for rational debate. What do we do in a situation where
people can make rational demands, in a strong sense, but lack in verbal skills to
carry on a critical public discussion. Take the case of the oppressed communities
for recognition and juridical equality through affirmative actions and some kind
of quota in jobs and services given a pronounced under-representations in all
institutions of civil society (e.g. media and communication) and of the state except
the legislative ones. Much of the civil society is ranged against these, backing their
opposition in terms of elaborate and painstakingly perfected arguments. Good
argument is not only critical but also involves verbal skills, which is what the poor
36
Journal of Social and Political Studies
lack.
Proceeding from such a background, I want to argue that the core of the
civil society in India, comprising the most modern and well-off sections of society,
has turned against democracy, or, at least, turned its face away from the way it
works in relation to the processes that sustain it. With the rise of the oppressed
communities, known in India as the backward castes (OBC’s and MBC’s) to
political prominence, the better educated and well-off sections in India coming
from castes have taken cudgels against this political assertion on the lower people.
The elite counter-reaction has embraced Hindutva to contain and push back this
trend. The breach between the various communities of ritual and status in
complete; in much of north India and to varying degrees in the rest of the country.
Democracy in India is working without a covenant or a consensus. It can clearly
be seen that the trajectory of democracy in India is unusual in significant ways.
This assertion needs some careful interpretation. In the first sense, it does not
mean those who are the active member of civil society are against the ideology of
democracy or the theoretical presuppositions, which inform liberal democracy.
On the contrary, they may well be deeply committed to the ways in which
democracies ought to function in their modular form. If this is so, as it clearly
seems to be the case going by the opinions aired in the civil society, then in the
second sense, it suggests that their reference is to what goes on as democratic
practice in the western societies. If we distill the opinions expressed in civil society
we will find that the articulate sections have a high regard for the autonomy of
their person, to rights as inalienable, notions of private and personal as beyond
any social monitoring, value contestation in public sphere without interventions
of power, decorum in public dealings, so on and so forth. Above all this, they
imagine themselves as free of all encumbrances like pulls of the irrational, drawn
by lures of power, given to self-aggrandizement, etc.
Given all this, what also seems beyond doubt is that these same sections of
civil society have developed deep reservations against the manner in which the
processes around democracy are working in India. The manner in which the
depressed sections of society have been functioning in the process has led to a
clogging of the political space through an unruly presence of loud noises. The
underprivileged groups have developed new capabilities of acting centered on their
notions of equality, sense of sharing power, assertions about eliciting recognition
(may be by force of slogans) of their worth as equal of the Savaranas, and so on.
They stand up and force being counted and considered as important. The kind
of struggles these ordinary people have been waging for equality and empowerment
and entitlement look more like shouting and creating a din in the political arena.
The public sphere seems to have jammed, other kinds of traffic in “rational
exchanges’, uniformed by the pressures of sheer number, seem to have become
difficult to those who stand by the values and virtues which go to constitute the
civil society. The entry of the vulnerable sections in the political arena and the
Civil Society, Democracy and Public Sphere in India
37
electoral competition has been enormous if we go by the sheer numbers involved.
In passing it is worth noting that in the last decade there has been an
enormous increase in the political participation of vulnerable sections of society.
Overall voting per centage has not significantly changed over the last 50 years.
But the internal composition of the voting public has changed. More people
belonging to lower castes, illiterate, less educated, rural based, and the poor are
voting now. And an equally sharp decline in voting has taken place among those
who are from the upper castes, educated, urban professionals, and the well off.
Democracy in India is quite unlike that in the advanced capitalist countries where
these same sociological variables operate in the opposite direction. This also is
the source of din in the public sphere. But it is a mode of functioning that gives
great satisfaction to the underprivileged because they feel that they can jam the
voice of the privilegensia (a word which I have coined in an earlier article to refer
to the vested interest that develops around the inherited privileges) which does
not care to listen to them. At this point it is important to note that the process
where different social forces contend against one another and fight out their battles
has become autonomous form the institutions and norms that are supposed to
inform participation. It is space where people stand up and force a reluctant and
grudging recognition from those who like to call the shots, the privilegensia. It is
here that the ordinary people compensate for the low verbal skills and
argumentative inadequacies. It is a place where they function with a sense of pride.
The vulnerable sections in all their diversity have entered the process with
their own moral economy and cultural outlook. Entailed in this morality and
culture are values and as these people see “virtues’ which are not considered as
assets for a civil society. In fact these values ostensibly negate the very requirements
of what goes to constitute a civil society. Communal solidarity, helping castecommunity brethren out of turn, breaking the queue for community advancement,
scant regard for civility or politeness towards those who are not with you, lack of
decorum in public utterances are all features which have become pronouncedly
visible and prominent in the public life (or, the public sphere) of the country.
Such a situation has its source in the nature of communities active in the political
life. These people do not enter the public-political as individuals but as people
embedded in their community ties. In addition, most of these are communities,
which demand uncritical affirmation of affiliation with community life as a price
to lean on for help and succor. Moreover as single persons they are ill equipped
to act in the public- diffidence and inadequacy with verbal skills, so important as
assets to enter a public contestation with civility. Lacking in this, they enter
together in large number to makeup for the lack of verbal skills. This pattern of
participation of also helps them to overcome the sense of shame at their own
perceived inadequacy. The spectacle of the contest of communities in the public
sphere is then a political culture at variance with our received notions of civil
society. A Culture, which transcends such strong primordial bonds into same
38
Journal of Social and Political Studies
common denominators and acquires certain universal features, is necessarily
supposed to provide the site for the civil society.
Such being the sense of civil society in its real moorings, it remains a restricted
presence in Indian society. Those with education, culture, capable of carrying the
baggage of rights, etc. are the core members of civil society; they carry the cross
for the other assuming others to be capable of acting like them. The decline in
the importance of the assumptions of their world in social life and the consequent
erosion from the political process is quite pronounced. This is the reason for those
of us strongly subscribing to the values enshrined in the civil society to have
become alienated from the processes which sustains democracy in India on the
ground. Democracy in India is surviving and functioning with all its untidiness
and infirmities without the backing of a very large part of the civil society. The
present conjuncture in India therefore is rather unusual, unlike in much of the
western world from where we still draw our notions of what sustains democracy.
Civil society as a necessary facilitative presence for the working of democracy has
either gone indifferent to its actual processes here or has in certain ways ranged
itself against it. I do not know in which other way to read the alienation of the
elite- the established middle classes- those of the educated with traditions of
learning and the well-off strata—from the democratic process. The only possible
exceptions to this alienation are sizeable sections of the critical intelligentsia active
in academics, social movements, and other radical activities.
It is precisely in these sections of society in a third world country with a thin
spread of modern culture that something called civil society takes shape and from
where it spreads outward. However, it is also not necessary for a civil society to
thrive that the entire society become educated and culturally accomplished in a
modern way. But what however is quite necessary in a third world society where
the gulf in the values and well-being of elite and the ordinary people is very wide
that a kind of a covenant exist. Such was the case during the Freedom Movement
and the making of the Constitution.
The elite held out a promise, one of a desire future for the ordinary people.
It may be that the promise made out may not be authentic as can be seen now
with the advantage of hindsight. At the time it was made, it was seen to be so. In
terms of this, agreements about goals to pursue and frame-works of action grew
and become wide spread in society. It was due to this covenant that is acting
together the differences between the world outlook of the elite and the ordinary
people did not come to the fore. In other words, cultures of difference as exists
within and across the communities as such remained dormant and did not
influence the political process. In contrast, this culture of difference has now
flooded the public sphere. A unity of purpose informed the public sphere at the
time in terms of which contestation and debate among the intelligentsia, with
some kind of a tacit participation from the people, took place. We could therefore
see that something akin to civil society, however restricted in range and limited
Civil Society, Democracy and Public Sphere in India
39
in scope functioned quite well in India.
Things are no longer the same. The expansion and deepening of democracy
in India is taking place, as shown above, in a rather untidy way. Whether we can
consider this development as radical is a moot question. Disputation can arise
depending on the ideological position and perspective from which this is seen.
The expansion of democracy is the result of the quest for bourgeois equality which
is what has sustained are given it a wider legitimacy than ever before. However
untidy the micro processes in the expansion of democracy, these have a fact allowed
at the macro level to maintain some of the secular character of the polity and
thus a minimal assurance to the minorities in the face of their growing vulnerability
in face of the Hindutva onslaught, murderous in many instances when it comes
to religious minorities. The increasing power of Hindutva also represents from
the other side a direct attack on the essence of civil society. What however is
different in the case of Hindutva is that while it disables the functioning of
democracy, it ostensibly respects the form.
Respecting the form is quite central to the Hindutva is disguising an important
aspect of its drive towards Hinduising Indian politics. I want to refer in passing
to the political of inclusion which is more invidious then that of exclusions.
Inclusion with dressing down denudes people of their identity. The Christians or
Muslims may have social features or ideas which are, Sangh Parivar insists inimical
to the Indian cultural ethos. If they do not shed these, there is the lurking threat
of disenfranchisements, in the sense of silencing their voice in the public sphere.
The disguising act by fore grounding form is important in attracting large number
of people who would not otherwise subscribe to its core ideological beliefs. It is
therefore not unsurprising that a sizeable part of the core of civil society still feels
at home with Hindutva. In the same way as an aside, that it feels no discomfort
with the antics and incivility of Mamta Bannerjee but gets repelled in the case of
Lallu Yadav. The rise of Hindutva also coincides with another development of
quite some importance.
With the decline in the transformative agenda of Nehruvian era, so too has
gone the supportive role of the state in favour of the poor. This too has been a
welcome feature of the state for the elite. However, what is equally important is
that the state is no less interventionist. It has become interventionist in a different
form, non-transformative interventionism in favour of the global capital. This runs
counter not only to the emancipatory urges of the masses but is also against their
quest for bourgeois equality and exercise of civil liberties because it takes out more
and more areas out of the domain of affirmative action and reservation. The
question whether the earlier agenda of chance was at all emanciptory or not central
in understanding the mutual relations between the civil society and democracy.
it was the basis of hope. It failed is another matter. Therefore, in addition, in the
question whether the quest for bourgeois equality will lead to an improvement
in the well being of the people is also not significant to the understanding of this
40
Journal of Social and Political Studies
issue. It is the battleground of present day struggles.
The elite is therefore in no position to help civil society become coterminous
with the society, as has been the case in western democracies. The elite therefore
cannot create the climate of a civil society that can furnish a supportive
surrounding atmosphere to the working of democracy on the ground. It is a
double-bind. On the one hand, there is the rupture between the elite and the
ordinary people taking the shape of the main conflict in today’s politics. The two
can hardly come together for common goals and shared exertions in day to day
life of society. In fact there is no nesting between the two and in the public debates
that go on the two are often talking at cross-purposes. It is here that an important
feature of the public sphere in India gets greatly enfeebled.
The public sphere, a place for intercommunication which itself is its
justification, is deeply fragmented given the way the communities face each other
in the organized political and their rupture with the elite. Communication and
messages do not have an unhindered flow but get obstructed or alter their meaning
when they cross the community boundaries. Such a process has been evident in
the way questions of “merit” or “efficiency” or “competence”, and above all what
it means to be “rational” has been talked in the public arenas as issues of debate
since the anit-Mandal agitation. These terms have now become weapons of the
educated upper castes to run down the claims of the deprived. On the other hand
terms like equity or (politics of ) social justice have come to be the weapons of
backward castes. The meanings associated with the key terms of debate have
become properties of community interest, to thwart rather than facilitate
intercommunications. A similar tendency is also discernible in the way Hindutva
manipulates many a key terms of debate, for instance democracy to create
confusion. Rather than majority in democracy be something contingent and
constantly contested, made and unmade, it is imbued with permanence by
associating it with the Hindu population; an ascriptive, denominational majority
presence in India. Further by legitimizing the actions of mobs on behalf of the
majority, as during the entire campaign leading to the demolition of Babri Masjid
and in the subsequent phase of illegal exertions for building the Ram Temple, it
empties the sense of democracy of all its procedural requirements and fills it with
unwarranted meanings.
The rupture between the elite and masses, on the other hand, extends beyond
the world of meanings and communications. The elite has chosen to go all hog
for narrow self-interest of maximising only their material wellbeing. In this era
of globalization, they have made the state shed more and more of its welfare
functions leaving people to fend for themselves. In a society with widespread
poverty and unmet daily needs and no supportive civil institutions to lean on,
people themselves are left without the presence of benign institutions in society.
In this situation, people are forced to lean for support available with the kin groups
of their communities. Communities thus become the sanctuary, rather than social
Civil Society, Democracy and Public Sphere in India
41
institutions, where people can recompose their lives. This may have many
consequences but let us look at one of these.
Communities in India often play very contradictory roles in the life of
individuals. We all know how the struggle for equality and consequently for
recognition can have liberating influence on the functioning of the persons. They
can stand up and insist on being counted. The significance of this in a society
where silent acceptance was their fate cannot be minimised. On the other side,
forced dependence on the communities for things that they should be able to do
for themselves viz. fulfilling their daily needs can have very deleterious effects on
their personal autonomy and self-respect. Dependence on communities of a forced
kind induced on the people tends to unduly enhance the importance of the
communities. Non-modern communities in India unlike the trade unions or
business associations or hobby groups demand uncritical affirmation of affiliation
to the community. Absorption of the persons into the normative reasoning of
the community is an insistent demand made on the individuals, often there can
be retaliation for non-compliance; “intractable” persons are unwelcome for other
community members.
Let us see this is relation to the internal constitution of the communities.
They make strong claims to the importance of their “way of life” and claim a
right to culture while they deny the same right to the individuals to choose a
way of life, an important aspect of civil society. In the context of these strong
claims, the absence of any sustained dialogue across the communities to arrive at
common notions of good life, the demands on the individual members to wholly
subscribe to these notions of good of respective communities, some unwholesome
features of community life in India become prominent. All these also have deep
repercussions on the evolving nature and working of civil society. Civil society
after all is specific kind of society. Unlike society, which is as old as human life,
civil society has its origin, as we saw above, along the emergence of capitalism
and liberal ways of thinking about life. Although it has evolved and changed
drastically, it had not entirely outgrown its origins. Exploration of one facet of
this will perhaps be useful for understanding democracy in India in relation to
the civil society.
With deepening of the bourgeois conditions, which surrounds our life from
all sides, aspirations also, taken on a different hue. Communities as collective
personalities are also out to maximise the economic well being of the collectivity.
They fight for the right and well being not just in the name of the needy members,
which also they might do, but much more so as a necessity for communal benefits.
The well being of the community is very often being measured in terms of the
aggregate presence of the indices of welfare or prosperity vis-à-vis another
community. If the numbers of well off and well placed people say from the Thevers
is comparable to that of any other well placed community say the Mudaliars, then
it would matter little if there is also the presence of large number of needy people
42
Journal of Social and Political Studies
within that community. In other words, these communities, whatever the internal
alternations under way, act as the equivalent of the egoistic individuals in the
competitive world of bourgeois possessiveness; it is kind of “possessive” communal
orientation which regulates public competitiveness and the maximization of
interests through this. We have the unhealthy sight of any civil society being the
site for fighting of self-maximization but absence of the inter-community exertions
for common good, which is the presentable face of the public sphere, We can see
from all this that the conceptual baggage received from Habermas comes apart
when we look at societies like India.
Such a political context, without the underlying minimal unification, to the
extend which will promote intra-society communication, characteristic of public
sphere, introduces an element of radical uncertainty of democracy. A win or lose
situation between two who become contenders when they ought to be supportive,
end in a no win situation. India thus is in unenviable situation. The core of the
civil society stands in combat with the process by which democracy in India is
getting transcribed, a universal imprinting itself within the particularities of a
society. Most of those who stand for the universal seem to be aghast at the
particularities, noisily articulating their concerns in the face of the universal. The
point is not whether one ought to like it. The issue is to be able to take a position
one has to start from an understanding of this.
The Question of Justice in the Contemporary Global Order
43
The Question of Justice in the
Contemporary Global Order—
Some Guiding Considerations
Anand P. Mavalankar
In the contemporary global order, the question of justice has acquired greater
prominence in the wake of growing ‘economic globalisation’ across the planet
earth, and cultural and other diversities prevailing in different national societies
within the contemporary world.1 Why has the justice question figured as the
dominant concern in the present times, remains a matter of reflection for a student
of contemporary global order. The Latin root of the word ‘Justice’ is “suum cuique
tribuere” means “to allocate to each his own”. The quest for restoring and
reaffirming the value of justice is indeed quite relevant and extraordinarily
significant in the contemporary social discourse. Both corrective justice and
distributive justice are posited as the essential endeavours on the part of sovereign
states as well as the international community as a whole. The idea of corrective
justice due to a person as punishment has been refined and reformulated in past
few decades, although there is disagreement about the justification of the
punishment. Similarly, the idea of distributive justice as due by way of benefits
and burdens other than punishments has occupied centre-stage in policy debates
across the political spectrum in contemporary democratic societies. At the same
time, there is no agreement about the content of just principles for the distribution
of benefits and (non-punitive) burdens.
The main objective of this essay is to explore the question of justice in the
contemporary global order. How do we approach the problem of justice from
the analytical level of the global order itself? Where does justice figure in the
hierarchy of values that shape the contemporary global order? How do we
differentiate different kinds of justice, and what are the implications of coming
to terms with the changing contemporary global order? We shall address these
questions by referring to certain guiding considerations that should shape our
exploration into the question of justice in the contemporary global order. In the
subsequent sections of this essay, we shall discuss them at some length.
I
At the outset, it is important to recognize that the value of justice in contemporary
international relations is not acknowledged as overriding one by certain scholars
working in the domain of international or global studies. According to them, given
the absence of a global sovereign authority, conditions for bringing about justice
in the contemporary global order do not exist at the present juncture. The implicit
suggestion here is that the state constitutes the maximal moral authority.2
44
Journal of Social and Political Studies
This line of thinking is, however, contested by those who advance the idea
of fundamental human equality, the belief that in some sense human beings are
of equal value. As Andrew Link later, one of the leading scholars wedded to this
idea, contends that the idea of humanity needs to be ‘reconstituted within a theory
of history which is able to avoid the inadequacies that were endemic in traditional
and modern theories of natural law’.3
At the level of the sovereign nation-state, the emphasis on social justice has
been historically acknowledged, since it relates to the basic condition of inequality
among communities, groups and individuals within the territorial confines of the
state. The idea of the welfare state was meant to reduce disparities in income and
wealth among its citizens. In a sense, it was meant to ensure credibility of the
government of the day, in terms of meeting certain basic requirements of its people
by fulfilling their minimum living standards.4
At the level of the sovereign state-system, however, some scholars wedded to
an enlightened state-centric view of the international community prioritise the
value of order over the value of justice. Hedley Bull’s argument in the Anarchical
Society was based on his contention that order is considered to be more
fundamental than justice. According to him, “order is a condition for the
realization of other values”.5 clearly, order is recognized here as prior to justice.
While this was articulated as such by way of a general statement, Bull did qualify
it by saying that in any particular case, justice may come first. In this connection,
Bull gave the example of international justice of self-determination and state
sovereignty for colonized people in Asia and Africa. It was widely regarded as
morally prior to the international order of Western colonialism in the colonized
societies of Asia and Africa.
Bull’s argument, however, does not squarely address the political economy
context of the contemporary global order as it evolved since the late nineteenth
century. The divide between the ‘North’ (advanced industrial states of the Western
world) and the ‘South’ (less-developed, erstwhile colonized countries of Asia, Africa
and Latin America) in the contemporary international economic order,
fundamentally challenges the political conception of Bull which establishes the
overriding salience of order vis-à-vis justice in the contemporary international
society of states.
The nature of the contemporary international economic order remains highly
inequitable, as certain elements of the relationship between the developing and
the developed countries are particularly irksome. In his perceptive appraisal of
the contemporary order, W. Arthur Lewis outlined those elements in the following
manner:
“First, the division of the world into exporters of primary products and
exporters of manufactures.
Second, the adverse factorial terms of trade for the products of the
developing countries.
Third, the dependence of the developing countries on the developed
The Question of Justice in the Contemporary Global Order
45
countries for finance.
Fourth, the dependence of the developing countries on the developed for
their engine of growth”.6
Although these underlying elements have undergone change in the past two
decades, the thrust of his argument does point towards an inherently restrictive
political conception of Bull on justice, to the extent that if fails to take into account
the injustice-producing structural make-up of the contemporary global order.
By way of conclusion, Lewis had pointed towards domestic change in the
prevailing international economic order. As Lewis put it, “The engine of growth
should be technological change, with international trade serving as lubricating
oil and not as fuel. The gateway to technical change is through agricultural and
industrial revolutions, which are mutually dependent.”7 He went on to say that
“The most important item on the agenda of development is to transform the food
sector, create agricultural surpluses to feed the urban population, and thereby create
the domestic basis for industry and modern services.”8
These ideas of Lewis enable us to focus on the underlying economic variables
that produce conditions of injustice in the developing countries. They sensitize
us to the sources of inequitable international economic order that give rise to the
unjust economic environment for the countries of the ‘South’.
Be as it may, the question of justice in the contemporary global order from
the standpoint of the sovereign state-system has to be considered in detail from
Bull’s perspective, as it focuses upon international justice. We may now briefly
turn to Hedley Bull’s conception of justice. Bull makes a distinction between
‘commutative justice’ and ‘distributive justice’ in the realm of sovereign states.
Cumulative justice refers to procedures and reciprocity in the international
community of sovereign states. According to him, it is a process of claim and
counter-claim among states. Accordingly, justice is fairness of the rules of the gamethe same rules are applied in the same way to every state. Such rules of the game
are expressed by international law and diplomatic practices.9
Bull’s notion of commutative justice posits that states are socially responsible
actors and they have a common interest in promoting international justice.
Although complying with certain rules and norms create basic framework for
society of states, it does not necessarily lead to justice among states.
As regards ‘distributive justice’, Bull examines the issue of how goods should
be distributed among states, as exemplified by the idea that justice requires a
transfer of economic resources from rich countries to poor ones.10 The suggestion
here is that the poor and weak states deserve special treatment, such as
development aid. The notion of distributive justice does indicate what the
developing countries are legitimately entitled to in the first place, both positively
and negatively, the appropriate distribution of benefits and (non-punitive) burdens
within a political order.
In the latter half of 20th century and early 21st century, issues of distributive
46
Journal of Social and Political Studies
justice have been vociferously presented by a whole range of groups and
organizations from international civil society. The call for establishing a “New
International Economic Order (NIEO)” in 1974 was a clear expression for
realizing distributive justice on part of the developing countries as a united bloc
to influence the workings of the prevailing global economic order.
Bull’s framework on justice differentiates three distinct levels of justice in
world politics. The first level refers to ‘international or inter-state justice’ which
basically involves the notion of sovereign equality of states and removing unfair
and unjust barriers to their economic growth. The second level refers to ‘individual
or human justice’, which basically involves justice pertaining to human rights.
The third level refers to ‘cosmopolitan or world justice’, which basically involves
‘what is right or good for the world as a whole’. Applying global environmental
standards across the board among all nations of the world would be a case in
point here.
II
Considering the question of justice from the standpoint of the wider planet earth
or globe enables us to look at it in a holistic manner. There are principally two
broad ways to examine the question of justice in the contemporary global order,
which would capture the range and complexity of the justice problematic itself.
The distinction between ‘international justice’ and ‘global justice’ remains
vital to the discourse of justice in the contemporary global order. In the present
age of economic globalization, the globe itself has become the reference point to
assess the workings of the globalize world. Hence, with regard to global justice,
the guiding consideration must be humanity as s whole as the referent object of
justice. Clearly, it is conceptually quite distinct from the so-called ‘international
justice’. Bull’s proposition that states are bound by various norms and practices
is instructive in this regard. It also indicates the extent to which violence and
conflict are not prevalent in the international society. In the Westphalian order,
international justice rests on a ethic of co-existence of sovereign states. This being
a procedural view of justice, it does not address the substantive issues relating to
the nature and implications of justice in the contemporary world. In this
connection, it is worthwhile to recall Terry Nardin’s11 propositions that the society
of states is analogous to an association of citizens (cives) as opposed to an
“enterprise association”, which is devoted to the pursuit of some substantive
common goal of nations.
The main difficulty with the notion of international justice is that it
overestimates the degree of order in the Westphalian system. In the 21st century,
this notion is ineffective due to several reasons. First of all, in a predominantly
non-European contemporary global order, state will impose its own culture and
provide its own support for a legal system based on coexistence among nations.
Secondly, the growing trend towards democratization of the present order has
undermined old diplomatic culture.
The Question of Justice in the Contemporary Global Order
47
On the other hand, ‘global justice’ focuses on humanity as a whole. In such
conceptualization, interests of the entire humanity are best served by the normative
principles that underlie inter-state relations. Broadly speaking, there are three
distinct sets of arguments for the notion of global justice. First of all, Charles
Beitz took the view that under contemporary conditions of interdependence,
national societies are not sufficiently discrete to justify their being treated as
separate, self-contained entities.12 In other words, the world has to be seen as, in
certain respects, a single society and therefore the Rawlsian idea that differences
in outcome vis-à-vis the distribution of social and economic goods must be
justified, applies. Rawls’ “difference principle” can be applied to the effect that
such inequalities must work to the benefit of the least advantaged should be
applied internationally which would, of course, require wholesale distribution of
wealth and income among different national societies.13 Its implications for the
contemporary global order are quite clear cut. As Beitz put it, a Rawlsian society
is to be understood as a cooperative scheme based on mutual advantage and it is
by no means clear that the current world economic order could be seen in this
light.14 As Beitz states that the principle that states own the raw materials found
on their territory is indefensible, since they have done nothing to deserve this
wealth and thus resource-poor countries should be compensated by the equivalent
of a global wealth tax. The implicit assertion is that existing international economic
inequalities are actually created by, rather than reflected in, the contemporary
international economic order.
The second set of arguments for the notion of global social justice refers to
the basic assertion that rich countries of the contemporary global order are
responsible for the poverty of poor countries. The argument says that rich countries
have extensive obligations to the poor and weak countries. This broad line of
argumentation is echoed in post-Leninist theories of imperialism, dependency
theory and centre-periphery analysis.15
Another variant of the approach is that of Thomas Pogge.16 His work
highlights the problems of environmental degradation, mass poverty, malnutrition
and starvation, are the price paid by the poor to support the life-style of all the
inhabitants of the advanced industrial world. He advocates global redistribution
via a tax on the use of natural resources, which is a requirement of global social
justice. This line of inquiry is, however, contested by certain economists who
contend that genuine free trade would do more to help the poor.17
Both of these arguments referred to above, are challenged on the ground that
they contain incorrect empirical propositions about the state of affairs in the actual
global order that prevails in the contemporary times.
The third set of arguments favoring social justice is based on the Kantian
principle that a wrong done anywhere within the contemporary global order is
felt everywhere in it. The Kantian view entails a priori moral principles which
envisage all individuals as deserving of equal respect independent of boundaries
of nation-state. Kant’s formulation of categorical imperative forms the basis of
48
Journal of Social and Political Studies
Beitz’s (1983) account of Cosmopolitanism, and Onora O’Neill’s account of our
obligations to distant strangers.18 Peter Singer’s utilitarian framework regarding
obligation of the rich to the poor is another attempt to conceptualize the question
of global justice.19
Brian Barry’s espousal of the principle that the basic needs of all should be
met before the non-basic needs of anyone are satisfied is essentially a cosmopolitan
one, which derives from the idea of justice as impartiality (Barry, 1994, 1998).
In the third set of arguments, there is recognition of the prevailing social reality
that such extremes of wealth and poverty in itself (that are found in the
contemporary global order) create obligations on the part of the rich to help the
poor.
Here the debate has revolved around certain key considerations. To begin with,
it is important to determine the extent of such obligations on the part of the
“haves” towards the “have-nots”. Secondly, it is vital to figure out whether these
obligations are necessarily fulfilled by full-blooded state intervention to redistribute
resources in an inequitable contemporary global order.
John Rawls, in his work , The Law of Peoples20 advances the proposition that
our obligation extends only to helping societies that are not capable of sustaining
internal schemes of social justice to reach the point at which they would be so
capable. Rawls was of the view that the transfer of actual wealth is not necessary
to put burdened societies on the road to social justice. According to him, what
such societies require is the right kind of civil society and socio-political values.
The real assistance, though, of a different order was suggested by economists in
the form of free trade and access for less-developed countries to developed world
markets.21
Rawls invokes the idea of public reason that “specifies at the deepest level of
the the basic moral and political values that are to determine a constitutional
democratic government’s relation to its citizens and their relation to one another.
In short, it concerns how the political relation is to be understood.”22 This should
serve as the basis for initiating systematic efforts to address the problem of justice
in the given national society. According to Rawls,…“such reason is public in three
ways: as the reason of free and equal citizens, it is the reason of the pubic; its
subject is the public good concerning questions of fundamental political justice,
which questions are of two kinds, constitutional essentials and matters of basic
justice; and its nature and content are public, being expressed in public reasoning
by a family of reasonable conceptions of political justice reasonably thought to
satisfy the criterion of reciprocity.” 23
Rawls relies upon the effectiveness of deliberative democracy, as the best way
to address the question of justice. He goes on to say that there are “three essentials
of deliberative democracy. One is an idea of public reason;…a second is a
framework of constitutional democratic institutions that specifies the setting for
deliberative legislative bodies. The third is the knowledge and desire on the part
The Question of Justice in the Contemporary Global Order
49
of citizens generally to follow public reason and to realize its ideal in their political
conduct.”24
The arguments in favor of global justice are, however, subject to certain
criticisms regarding the status of global justice as a feasible and desirable line of
argumentation in the contemporary global order. First of all, social democracy
and a strong welfare state in Western Europe have come under sustained scrutiny
as a sound political economy option in the past few decades. Commitment to
one’s fellow citizens and high taxes are being questioned as credible propositions.
Secondly, the Westphalian assumption that power would be divided amongst a
plurality of national actors no longer holds true. Thirdly, anti- global capitalist
movements such as ‘Occupy Wall Street’ agitation have fundamentally critiqued
the bases and motivations of global justice framework. Thirdly, changes of policy
in national units in response to the demands of global justice are visible, rather
than the development of effective global institutions of governance. Fourth, the
Westphalian states have not been able to cope with problems thrown up by
environmental degradation or the management of the global economy.
III
While addressing the question of justice in the contemporary global order, the
above sets of guiding considerations impinge upon the problem of justice at the
present juncture. The idea of global justice emerges as the most credible way of
inquiring and acting upon the sources and nature of injustice in the contemporary
global order. Since the globe remains the reference point for conceptualizing the
nature and dynamics of the contemporary global order, the question of justice
has to be addressed from the vantage point of the globe itself and its necessary
implications will have to be taken into account for forging an effective strategy
of countering injustice across the global spectrum.
As regards human rights violations and its impact on world politics, former
or even sitting heads of states are brought before various national and international
courts or tribunals. In 1998, General Augusto Pinochet, the former ruler of Chile,
was arrested in London on an extradition request by a Spanish Court seeking to
try him for crimes committed during his military dictatorship. Later, Slobodan
Milosevic of Yugoslavia and Charles Taylor of Liberia were indicted for war crimes.
Due to shifts in international legal standards and practices, human rights
prosecutions have taken place. Sikkink has called the rise and spread of a set of
ideas and norms as “justice cascade”.25
The question of justice in contemporary global order is indeed multidimensional. Under present political conditions in the contemporary world the
obligations derived under conceptions of international and global justice are so
stringent that compliance cannot be ensured in the foreseeable future.
NOTES
1.
Globalization essentially refers to the shrinking of geographical distance. It means compression
of both time and place in that events in one location can be visually and aurally experienced,
50
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
23.
24.
25.
Journal of Social and Political Studies
through the grace of modern technology, virtually instantly around the globe. See Anthony
Giddens, “The Director’s Lectures: Runaway World, The Ruth Lectures Revisited, Lecture
1: 10, November 1999.
Economic globalization indicates convergence in regard to income levels, social structure
and behavior across the planet earth. But its critics point towards sections of society, which
is not benefited by economic globalization. As regards cultural diversities, the point is
that their differences must be so acknowledged, and protecting their cultural diversity means
ensuring justice to them.
This remains the essence of the realist thought in international relations.
See Andrew Linklater, Critical Theory and World Politics. London: Routledge, 2007, p.29
On the question of welfare state, see Clause Offe, Contradictions of the Welfare State. Edited
by John Keane. London: Huchinson, 1984.
See Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics. London: Macmillan,
1977, p.93.
See W. Arthur Lewis, The Evolution of the International Economic Order. New Jersey, Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1978, p.3.
See Lewis, p.74.
Lewis, p.75.
See Bull, 1977.
See Bull, 1977.
See Terry Nardin, Law, Morality and the Relations of States. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton
University Press, 1983.
See Beitz, 1983.
See Rawls, A Theory of Justice. 1971.
See Charles Beitz, “Cosmopolitan Ideas and National Sovereignty,” in Journal of Philosophy,
80, pp.591-600, 1983.
See A.G.Frank, Capitalism and Underdevelopment in Latin America. Hrmondsworth: Penguin,
1971; See Johan Galtung, “A Structural Theory of Imperialism”, Journal of Peace Research,
13: pp. 81-94; See Iammanuel Wallerstein, The Modern World System, Vols. I, II and III,.
London: Academic Press, 1974/19890, 1989; See Bill Warren, Imperialism: Pioneer of
Capitalism. London: New Left Books, 1980; See Anthony Brewer, Marxist Theories of
Imperialism: A Critical Survey. London: Routledge, 1990.
See Thomas Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2002.
See M. Desai, Marx’s Revenge: The Resurgence of Capitalism and the Death of Statist Socialism.
London: Verso, 2002; Also see J. Bhagwati, In Defense of Globalization. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2004.
See O. O’Neill, Faces of Hunger. London: Allen and Unwin, 1986; and also see O. O’Neill,
“Transnational Justice”, in Political Theory Today. Ed., David Held. Cambridge: Polity Press,
1991.
See Peter Singer, “Famine, affluence and morality “, In International Ethics, Ed., C.R. Beitz,
et al. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1985.
See John Rawls, The Law of Peoples. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999
See R. Cassen, Does Aid Work?. 2nd Edition. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994.
See Rawls, 1999, p.132.
Ibid., p.133
Op.cit.
See Kathryn Sikkink, The Justice Cascade: How Human Rights Prosecutions are Changing
World Politics. New York: Norton, 2011.
Social Inclusion through Exclusive Provisions in India
51
Social Inclusion through Exclusive
Provisions in India: The Glass is Half Full
P.K. Chaubey·
ABSTRACT
India, that is Bharatvarsha, was perhaps a cultural identity once upon a time. India, that is
Bharat, is now a modern State. India is perhaps unique where within the historically given
boundary there is so much diversity and plurality that some scholars choose to call it most
complex nation. Yet, except very small countries and Bangladesh, all large countries in the
South Asia have patterns of social diversity.
Plurality and diversity are considered positive attributes of a society while disparities are
considered negative attributes. But all attributes coexist. Modern State of India has tried,
particularly through its constitutional provisions, to preserve diversity while mitigating
disparities. It is not easy to distinguish between diversities and disparities in certain
situations, and ideas of disparities are therefore often imposed on the matters of diversities.
Attempts of the modern State, like various reformists earlier, may be characterized as
fostering harmony without imposing homogenization and promoting unity without
imposing uniformity. The goal has been to reduce disparities in various spheres of secular
domain. It is considered a worth pursuing goal though difficult to achieve.
The Constitution of India has duly recognized group identities of people along with
individual citizenship. It has therefore inserted various provisos concerning the interests of
groups, not necessarily always weaker, while providing for fundamental rights to the
individuals vis-à-vis State. It makes provisions for preserving cultural rights of various groups
and weaker sections in the Indian society. There is also a Part in the Constitution dealing
with special provisions relating to certain classes. These provisions relate to Scheduled Castes,
Scheduled Tribes, Anglo-Indians, and Other Backward Classes as well as for people living
in the Scheduled Areas. But general provisions are spread throughout the Constitution like
Art 275 which generally deals with grants in aid from the Union Government to certain
States but reference is made about Scheduled Tribes/Areas or Parts IX and IXA which deal
with matters of panchayats and municipalities but make reservation of seats for Scheduled
Castes and Scheduled Tribes.
My approach in the present paper is to view the Indian social scenario as the ‘glass is half
filled’ rather than the ‘glass is half empty’ for the audience of Nepal which is undertaking
exercise of Constitution making to take lessons from working of Indian Constitution.
On the relationship between a society and its State, as far as democratic dispensation is
concerned, there are two, somewhat contrasting, views. One is that society creates the
instrument of State as its executive wing for managing public affairs and guides the State
to move in a certain direction. Society is the principal and State is its agent. The other is
that the State holds the society together and is autonomous of the society it governs. In a
dynamic context, both actually inform each other. It is under the general will of the people
that State enacts the law and acts in accordance with it. But the law has to evolve itself
with evolving empirical social reality in order to aligning its activities with the values, and
at times in inculcating the values, generally held among the members who are not
individually very conscious about them or hold a contrary view. There may be times where
the State itself has to learn. For example, there has emerged a view that Art 44 of the
Constitution of India calling for uniform civil code for the citizens throughout the country
may not be pursued at all.
Journal of Social and Political Studies
52
There arose several occasions in India when the view of the judiciary was not found
synchronous with the ethos of the people as represented in the Parliament, which necessitated
amendment of the Constitution. Clauses and provisions were added in Art 15 for securing
the right to the State for taking affirmation action. Or take the example of reservation of
seats for Scheduled Castes and Scheduled Tribes in the Parliament and State Assemblies.
To begin with the provision in Art 334 was only for 10 years but it has been extended
time and again through Constitutional Amendments and is likely to be extended indefinitely.
Several schemes for inclusion of ‘excluded’ and marginalized or vulnerable sections and
disadvantaged regions through differential treatment have been devised and a partial success
has also been achieved. There are people having reservations on the variety of reservations
extended to certain sections yet the mainstream thinking is to do much more than has been
done so far.
It may be noted that Indians are faced with two thought streams—one of Gandhi who would
like the society to reform itself and call for people to be magnanimous to accommodate every
group irrespective of the traits of distinction, and the other of Ambedkar who would like to use
the State power and discretion, if not coercion, to bring in results through positive discrimination
or affirmative action. While the former may be enduring and very smooth but would be damn
slow, the latter would be expedient, though not smooth, and may invite reactions. India has
chosen the other course and weathered some troubles and reactions.
Introduction
Social inclusion of excluded groups and communities in societal processes of
political and economic significance is a very good idea expressive of modern ethos
across the globe, yet not without ambiguities. However, I do not set out here to
carry out a scholastic discourse on what its nuances could be, but propose to
discuss how it has been attempted and being attempted in India as it is broadly
understood.
Social inclusion for this paper does not mean mainstreaming the excluded,
partially excluded, and secluded sections of the people in any narrow sense but
does mean bringing in some kind of integration among diverse social groups and
some kind of fusion between them by addressing the perceived causes of divisive,
fissiparous and fissionary tendencies. Two things we need to keep constantly in
mind. One, the notion of inclusion presupposes a societal core to which diverse
groups may wish to be included in certain senses and yet not in many others.
Two, inclusion should not mean intrusion in areas which the sections (to be
included) wish to preserve simply because the latter is uninvited. Broad
understanding is that in most secular matters they wish to be included and in
most religious matters they may not wish to be included. For example,
communities not professing Hindu religion may not like to have common civil
code and may seek seclusion.
India, that is Bharatvarsha, was perhaps for pretty long stretch of time a
cultural identity without well-defined geographical boundaries or with shifting
political boundaries. India, that is Bharat, is now a modern political State with
more or less well-defined boundaries. India is unique where within the historically
given boundary there is so much diversity and plurality that some scholars have
chosen to call it most complex nation in the world. Yet, except very small countries
Social Inclusion through Exclusive Provisions in India
53
and Bangladesh, all countries in the South Asia have a good measure of diversity,
even within the majority religions which people in different countries happen to
practice. But I shall however dwell on India with which I am more familiar much
like in the fashion of a well-known litterateur late Rahi Masoom Raza who wrote
in his celebrated novel Adha Gaon that he is speaking of that half of the village
which he understood better.
The modern State of India is home to people of many religious faiths and
castes and classes, within several of them, but they have a broad cultural affinity
too. It has therefore been possible for the people to hold together despite lack of
justice in certain spheres to certain sections. Even before Independence several
reforms were carried out by various social reformers, generally within a given
religion and particularly within Hindu fold, and at times with the State support.
After Independence, many of the social grudges and grievances were addressed in
the making of the Constitution. In a dynamic society like India with evolving
aspirations and ethos, there could be no single permanent optimum mix; but
cohesive forces were tried to be so built as to contain divisive tendencies in the
society.
In this paper my general approach is to view the Indian social scenario as the
‘glass is half filled’ rather than that of the ‘glass is half empty’ and my judgement
is that the ‘glass will never be full up to the brim’ given the contradictions that
exist between, say, notions of caste justice and gender justice, as is exemplified by
the recent controversy over the bill for reservation of parliamentary and legislative
seats for women or between gender justice and freedom to profess religion, as
came to the fore a quarter century ago in the famous Shah Bano case.
Despite the fact that we Indians (which may be true of all the people in the
South Asia) are quite argumentative, it goes to our credit that we have a great
capability to develop broad consensus over many issues and move ahead in a
positive direction. Both of these, argumentative tendency and capability to
building consensus, are healthy signs—for a democracy to thrive and not only to
survive.
In post-Independence India, we seem to have been broadly pursuing a course
of harmony without imposition of homogenization, unity without imposition of
uniformity and diversity while mitigating disparities. To paraphrase: harmony sans
homogenization, unity sans uniformity and diversity sans disparity. Jawaharlal
Nehru had articulated the idea long ago and characterized Indian social fabric as
‘unity in diversity’. Though at times mainstreaming was thought to be the best
form of inclusion, the idea was shelved for good and preserving diversity and
plurality rather than tolerating it became the dominant thinking. Some scholars
have preferred to call this ethos as ‘union’ rather than ‘unity’. I would prefer to
articulate it as union of minds, unity of purpose and harmony of relations.
Yet justice demands doing away with disparities. It is quite a difficult task to
live with diversities and pluralities, while trying to do away with disparities. Quite
often it is not even easy to distinguish between diversity and disparity. Preserving
54
Journal of Social and Political Studies
cultural diversity yet doing away with social disparity, preserving religious diversity
yet doing away with political disparity, and preserving local traditions and doing
away with economic disparity, could not be an easy task. It is rendered difficult
because in most of the religions, matters ecclesiastic have not been clearly separated
from matters secular, with the exception of Christianity. In fact, it is a bit surprising
that almost all people(s) in India have accepted the separation of secular domain
from ecclesiastic domain even while the two major religions and, of course, many
minor religions (minor-major division in numerical sense) had never articulated,
let alone concluded, the separation of the two domains.
India chose to be a sovereign, socialist, secular, democratic, republic in 1949,
though the words secular and socialist were added in the preamble of the
Constitution of India through an amendment in 1976 only. The Preamble
pronounced to all Indian citizens the liberty of thought, expression, belief, faith
and worship and also aimed to secure to all of them justice—social, economic
and political. A fine balance has thus been attempted between preservation of
traditional cultural values and promotion of modern secular values. In fact, the
Preamble does not only aim at the liberty of belief and faith, it provides to secure
it to the citizens. The state is in a pro-active mode in both the domains even
though it is professedly secular.
Before we proceed further, it would be appropriate to bring forth the two
steams of thoughts that prevailed in pre-Independence India. Gandhi wanted to
achieve social harmony through a course of social reformation without State
intervention and thus promote unity, especially among Hindus and between
Hindus and Muslims where he could see some discord; at the same time,
Ambedkar on the other hand wanted a political solution through State
intervention to bring justice to disadvantaged groups, particularly within Hindu
fold, and thus preserve the union. Gandhi thought achieving social harmony
through social movement and change of heart would be a permanent solution to
attain social justice without unwanted repercussions, while Ambedkar thought
State affirmative action would be not only expedient but the only possible course
in the given circumstances. In a sense, they believed in two different theories of
relationship between State and society. It was Ambedkar line that we finally chose
to pursue in the making of the Constitution of India, although original Ambedkar
line was itself modified as a compromise that was evolved in the Poona Pact
between Gandhi and Ambedkar in 1932 and was incorporated in Government
of India Act 1935 passed in the British Parliament for political dispensation in
the Dominion of India.
It is true that Ambedkar line proved expedient but it occasionally gives rise
to dissonance in certain quarters and disruption in social and economic life people,
leading to backlashes and clashes at times. The domain of reservation, the most
visible form of positive discrimination, went on expanding its coverage and
dimensions from Scheduled Castes/ Scheduled Tribes to Other Backward Classes
to Minorities and from political representation to employment/jobs (also within
Social Inclusion through Exclusive Provisions in India
55
that from initial recruitment to promotion and accumulation of vacancies) to
admission in educational institutions. If some people have reservations on these
reservations, it is because, they feel, the game is being played in a zero-sum fashion,
particularly in the economic domain. In a zero-sum game, inclusion of one implies
exclusion of another and this is what people are against, though opposition is
often articulated in terms of efficiency and merit. Present policy of inclusive growth
in some way addresses to this issue by emphasizing on participation of people,
better distribution of growth and eradication of poverty instead of redistributing
existing stocks, containing concentration and removing inequality. Converting
policies into positive-sum games is the real issue, but some games cannot be easily
turned into positive-sum games.
What Constitutes India
In most of the countries with capitalistic economic framework, which the
Constitution declares India to be one through its Art 39(b) and 39(c), theoretical
backdrop of the Constitution revolves around the relationships between State and
individual and market. State’s duty to individuals remain a major goal of a modern
democratic Constitution. The State shall generally be required to oversee the
conduct of a citizen vis-à-vis another citizen or entity or even the State itself. But
reality is much more complex because many other institutions have to be reckoned
with and regional aspirations have to be respected. More importantly, in countries
like India, group identities have generally been accepted and have also been
constitutionally recognized. These groups are in terms of races, religions, castes,
classes, regional affiliations and gender. While we have inherited many practices
which are considered bad today, we have also inherited a positive trait for
appreciation for variety and traditions.
India with a population of more than 1210 million is more than three times
larger than the rest of the SAARC countries and therefore more diverse and plural.
It has the geographical area of about 3.3 million square-kilometers, which is twice
as large as that of the remaining of the SAARC countries. With an area of onethird of the US or China, it is quite dense in terms of population density, more
dense than any other SAARC country, except Bangladesh. It is also home to seven
major religions viz. Hinduism, Islam, Christianity, Sikhism, Buddhism, Jainism
and Zoroastrianism and 200 minor religions/sects There are estimated 3500 castes,
of which about 500 castes excluding duplication across states, are scheduled for
special treatment and another 1000 castes for differential treatment. With 114
languages, of which 22 are recognized as ‘national’ languages (including the official
languages of her three neighbours—Bangladesh, Nepal and Pakistan), India has
around 1600 officially accepted spoken languages though mother tongues returned
in the census of 2001 were around 10,000. There are several culturally different
tribes in India (about 550), again with some duplication across States, which are
scheduled for special treatment. There are also several primitive, de-notified, seminomadic and nomadic tribes in India, 75 of them have been identified. Criminal
56
Journal of Social and Political Studies
Tribes Acts of 1871 and 1924, under which some of the castes and tribes were
considered ‘criminal tribes’ were repealed in 1952 though for a while they were
considered as habitual offenders. De-notified tribes exist in all categories of
classification. We had had stories of thugs and pindaries committing theft and
robberies. Now, no castes are considered outcastes and no tribes are considered
criminal.
Hindus constitute the majority, whose percentage has come down from
around 85 in 1951 to 81.5 in 2001. Muslims constitute the major minority whose
percentage has increased from 10.4 in 1951 to 13.4 in 2001. The two religious
groups put together constitute more than 95 percent of the population. Christians
and Sikhs constitute 2.3 percent and 2.0 percent respectively. Buddhists and Jains
are around 0.8 percent and 0.5 percent respectively. While Buddhism, Jainism
and Sikhism are considered as having been originated in India, Islam and
Christianity are not considered likewise. Growth rate of Hindu population is the
smallest, after Sikhs, and that of Muslims is the highest among the major religions.
An overwhelming majority of people in any religion are converts from Hindus
and as a result, scheduled castes are accepted to exist in every major religion in
India. Officially scheduled castes are accepted to exist only among Hindus, Sikhs,
and Buddhists. It may be noted that the original Constitutional Orders issued by
the President on 10th August 1950 and 20th September 1951 restricted these castes
to exist among Hindus only. It was only after amendments that people professing
Sikhs and Buddhists were accepted to be belonging to Scheduled Castes if they
originally came from such castes, races or tribes as were scheduled. Highest
incidence of Scheduled Castes is found among Sikhs. Some scholars feel that
freedom of religion should permit the converts (to Christianity and Islam) to be
accepted as belonging to Scheduled Castes, if by origin they were from such castes,
races or tribes.
Scheduled tribes people are in all religions except among Muslims though
there are such converts (numerically not very large) among Muslims as well. The
Constitutional Orders issued by the President on 6th September 1950 and 20th
September 1951 do not restrict their existence to any religion.
It may reiterated that Muslims, Buddhists, Sikhs and Christians are treated
as religious minorities, but only followers of Buddhists and Sikhs could belong
to scheduled castes while scheduled tribes people could profess any religion.
However, they are found empirically almost absent, but not nil, among Muslims.
However, there are also socially and educationally backward classes, often
called ‘other backward classes’, which exist in all religions in India, including Islam
and they account for a huge majority. As the Census of India is not conducted
on caste basis, and there is some difference between castes and classes, estimates
of their numbers are controversial. Their numbers vary from well below 30 percent
to well over 50 percent.
Social Inclusion through Exclusive Provisions in India
57
Castes and Exclusion
History is replete with cases of ostracism, isolation, segregation and apartheid—
some of which is racial in nature. People have often been suppressed and oppressed
in many civilizations. Slavery, widely extant in Greece in the ancient period, reemerged in recent past centuries. America and South Africa both practiced
apartheid till late in the passing centuries. Institution of private property and
market forces, much useful as they are, have been analysed as causing exploitation
and deprivation as well. Jajmani system, where institution of private property was
well entrenched but money mediation was not the dominant mode of exchange,
is now being increasingly defended because activities of production and
distribution were taken care of simultaneously in that system.
Occupational castes exist everywhere in all societies, exception being non-State
societies, with certain degree of division of labour. So is the case with
discrimination. But exclusion from accessing certain amenities and privileges,
performing certain functions and carrying out certain occupational activities has
been an exclusive specialty in the caste system of Hindu society. Apart from this,
there prevailed the curse of untouchabiity of certain castes doing cleaning jobs.
The other characteristic of the casteism, as it is called, had been forbiddance of
marriage and dining across castes. Even when occupational rigidity has melted
away to a great extent, the other social practices still continue, particularly in the
rural areas. Exclusion from accessing amenities, an extension of untouchability,
is still prevalent in some parts of the country and in the neighbourhood though
in a diluted form. Some scholars have therefore chosen to call it Indian Caste
System. The system is so well ingrained and entrenched in the society that
members belonging to certain low castes continue to be in the same low social
status, in the eyes of others, even though they have converted to such religions
which do not permit social hierarchy based on castes. In other words, they could
not lose their castes even after conversion. And vocal sections have now started
asserting castes, even after conversion, if their ancestors came from low castes.
Almost all religions in India are found practicing casteism in marriage, if not in
dining. Not to accept the existence of Scheduled Castes (and Scheduled Tribes)
among Muslims, some scholars and leaders argue, is the discrimination practiced
by the State.
While the State is supposed to intervene generally in the market processes
for securing economic justice to the poor and labour, it has to do some extra
efforts for ending exclusion of people belonging to certain castes and tribes from
participation in the societal processes by ensuring their inclusion in those
processes—accessing amenities, performing rituals, amd carrying out activities.
There had been traditionally excluded castes—some of which were
untouchable and in some parts of the country even unapproachable and unseeable.
Obviously, these were the castes engaged in unpleasant lowest level occupations
or cleaning occupations. There has been a sort of hierarchy within the groups as
well as between the groups. Some of the groups can easily be identified with the
58
Journal of Social and Political Studies
varnas, but for others it is not easy. To these varnas were assimilated certain tribes,
as they became part of the larger society, which can be taken seen as a process of
inclusion. These tribes were not considered untouchable even while followers of
other religions were called mlechhas and treated so. Tribal people were however
considered low in skills, which they actually were as they came in contact with
the larger society much later and were expected to take time to learn skills already
developed. Low castes were considered quite adept in their various occupations
as they have been a part of society always and had been naturally learning their
skills and innovating for a long time. They actually made what is called as the
exterior of civilization!
But there are also areas within the territory of India, which have been called
scheduled areas. There are also exclusive tribal areas. Some areas got politically
assertive and special arrangement has been made for them, for example, in the
shape of Darjeeling Gorkha Hill Council. Then, there are marginalized sections
like women, minorities—religious and linguistic, nomadic and migratory tribes,
and physically handicapped persons as also ex-servicemen for whom some
differential treatment has been provided.
The Constitution of India does take care of what it calls Scheduled Areas
and Tribal Areas. Scheduled Areas, as provided for in the Fifth Schedule of the
Constitution, were originally declared through Constitutional Orders issued on
26th January and 7th December of 1950. They are the areas/regions/pockets with
tribal concentration that exist within the States/Union Territories except four States
in the North East viz. Assam, Meghalaya, Mizoram and Tripura. There is provision
in the Fifth Schedule [under Art 244(1)] for a Tribes Advisory Council, mostly
consisting of Scheduled Tribes representatives in the Legislative Assembly of the
State, to advise the Governor on matters pertaining to the welfare and advancement
of the Scheduled Tribes in the State. The Governor is empowered to disallow
application of, or modify, any particular Act of Parliament or of Legislature of
the State and may prohibit, restrict and regulate market transactions particularly
with reference to transfer/allotment of land.
The Sixth Schedule [under Art 224 (2) and 275 (1)], applicable to Tribal
Areas in the States of Assam, Meghalaya, Mizoram and Tripura, makes provision
for autonomous districts, and within them autonomous regions if there are
different Scheduled Tribes, and District Councils (and Regional Councils) with
powers to make laws, rules and regulations with respect to certain matters related
with land, forest, water courses, taxes (including land revenue), social customs
(including marriage and divorce), etc. The District and Regional Councils are
largely bodies with members elected for a term of five years on the basis of adult
suffrage. They are endowed with powers, subject to certain limitations, to
constitute village councils and courts and to establish/construct/manage primary
schools, dispensaries, markets, cattle ponds, ferries, fisheries, roads, waterways.
They may prescribe the language of instructions and the manner in which primary
schools would be run. They have been empowered to collect land revenue and
Social Inclusion through Exclusive Provisions in India
59
impose taxes on land and buildings as well as tolls on persons resident in their
jurisdictions. District Councils have powers to levy and collect taxes on professions,
trades, callings and employments; on animals, vehicles and boats; on entry of goods
for sale; and for maintenance of schools, dispensaries and roads. As of now there
are nine such districts—two in Assam, three in Meghalaya, one in Tripura, and
three in Mizoram.
One can notice that the provisions in respect of Scheduled Areas and Tribal
areas as well as Art 371A through 371C and Art 371F through 371H, pertaining
to the States in the North East, are reflective of inclusion in one sense, exclusion
in another and seclusion in still another sense. However, in a broad sense, these
dispensations have been accepted as part of inclusion policy, because these
interventions are intended to take care of those groups in the secular realm without
intruding into their personal and cultural spheres where they prefer a kind of
‘seclusion’ or ‘self-exclusion’.
Constitution: Framework and Working
In the Constitution of India, particular and specific provisions for furtherance of
welfare of the weaker sections besides general provisions have been made in the
Parts dealing with Fundamental Rights (of the citizens vis a vis the State), Directive
Principles of State Policy (about intervention in economic and social life), Fiscal
Matters (Finance, Property, Contracts and Suits), and Special Provisions Relating
to Certain Classes. It needs to be mentioned that the State has been defined in
Art 12 of the Constitution to include ‘the Government and Parliament of India
and the Government and the Legislature of each of the States and all local or
other authorities within the territory of India or under the control of the
Government of India’. The word State has been used in the Constitution of India
in several senses and we shall be using it in this paper in three senses viz., for the
Republic of India, the Union of India and each of the states and UTs.
There are two kinds of measures adopted. One set is preventive and protective
in nature and the other is that of promoting the interest and welfare of the weaker,
marginalized and disadvantaged sections of the citizenry. Both types of these
measures are provided in the Constitution.
Enshrining great principles in the Constitution is one thing but making them
work is another. Howsoever anti-discriminatory, anti-exploitation, anti-oppressive
and anti-exclusionary the Constitution is in its formulation, the issue is how much
progress we could make in that direction. Making a good Constitution is the
necessary condition but it is only the first step. Acts have to be legislated, rules
have to be framed, institutions have to be established, and mechanisms have to
be put in place. It has to be seen that dilution is not brought in the steps following
the Constitution mandate. Also programmes/schemes/ missions/projects have to
be planned, implemented, and monitored.
We shall first deal with the provisions in the Constitution, then on the steps
taken to execute them and thereafter on the outcomes. Yet, it is difficult to know
60
Journal of Social and Political Studies
clearly about how much change is autonomous and how much is on account of
State interventions, more so when State interventions trigger societal change, which
is what it ought to do, and when State intervenes because of societal and sectional
pressure.
Constitutional Provisions for Positive Disrimination
Constitutional provisions could be grouped in certain broad areas like civil,
political, economic, educational, cultural, employment and administrative. In the
section dealing with Right to Equality (Article 14 to Article 18) in the Part III
called Fundamental Rights, it has been made clear that, on the grounds of religion,
race, caste, sex and place of birth, neither the State shall discriminate against any
citizen in any sphere nor shall it permit others to impose any restriction on access
to public amenities and facilities. Abolition of untouchability is specifically
mentioned and its practice is declared as an offence in the Constitution itself.
But it seeks exemption for the State to make special provisions for women and
children as well as for advancement of any socially and educationally backward
classes of citizens, in addition to the Scheduled Castes, the Scheduled Tribes. This
affirmative exemption has been termed as positive discrimination. It further
declares equality of opportunity in matters of public employment and makes it
clear that nobody shall be discriminated on the grounds of religion, race, caste,
sex, or place of birth. But it again seeks exemption for the State to make laws in
favour of any backward class, which is under-represented in the services of the
State. The Constitution also permits the State to make laws regarding domicile
situation in certain classes of employment.
In fact, the Constitution was tested soon after its promulgation. While Art
16 (4) had made provision of reservation by the State in the employment under
the State, there was no exception for the State to make provision of reservation
of seats in admission in educational institutions. The State of Madras (then
comprising present four Southern States of Andhra Pradesh, Karnataka, Kerala
and Tamil Nadu) had reserved seats for certain communities based on certain
religions and castes in state medical and engineering colleges, which the Supreme
Court of India had found violative of Article 15. Article 15 asserts nondiscrimination but seeks exemption for making special provision only for women
and children, not for castes, classes or communities. In the very first amendment
of the Constitution a clause (4) was added to the Article 15, making room for
the State to make special provisions for the Scheduled Castes, the Scheduled Tribes,
and what came to be known as the OBCs later on through clause (5) added in
2005.
Civil
In order to operate the Constitutional provisions, laws were enacted quite early
like Protection of Civil Rights Act, 1955 and Untouchability Offences Act, 1955.
However, when they did not prove enough, some further protective provisions
Social Inclusion through Exclusive Provisions in India
61
were made like Scheduled Castes and Scheduled Tribes (Prevention of Atrocities)
Act in 1989, Employment of Manual Scavengers and Construction of Dry Latrines
(Prohibition) Act in 1993, and Scheduled Tribes and Other Traditional Forest
Dwellers (Recognition of Forest Rights) Act in 2006. In recent years there has
been made amendment in the Hindu Succession Act 1955, where word Hindu
has been defined to consist of Hindus, Sikhs, Biddhists and Jains. There has also
been enacted the Indecent Representation of Women (Prohibition) Act in 1987
and the Protection of Women from Domestic Violence Act in 2005. There already
existed Dowry Prohibition Act, 1961 and Pre-Conceptual and Pre-Natal
Diagnostic Techniques (Prohibition of Sex Selection) Act, 1994. Recently there
has been enactment of the Sexual Harassment of Women at Workplace
(Prohibition and Redressal) Act (2007). There is also an Act to take care of
physically handicapped persons, namely, The Persons with Disabilities (Equal
Opportunities, Protection of Rights and Full Participation) Act, 1995.
The Constitution has also provided for appointing Special Officers, or
Commissions for undertaking studies and recommending remedial measures to
the State for protecting the interests of the SCs, and the STs, and later on for the
OBCs and the Minorities, etc.
It is important to note that Uniform Civil Code, a central provision in the
Directive Principles of State Policy (Art 44), impinging upon women’s status in
civil matters, has been kept in abeyance for indefinite period, despite positive nod
from the Supreme Court. It is because such an enactment, thought a section of
intelligentsia, might militate against religious rights of certain minorities. An Act
professing uniform civil code could of course be enacted yet making certain
exceptions and exemptions. No enactment is ever made without a proviso or two
and certain practices for example, among the tribal communities could always be
accommodated in the Act. But, even the mere mention of enacting any legislation
in the matter itself creates a psychosis in the mind of protagonists as well as in
that of antagonists and thus the operation of the provision has been postponed
for an indefinite period.
Political
With regard to political inclusion, there is a Part (XVI) in the Constitution wholly
devoted to Special Provisions relating to certain classes (Art 330 to Art 342). India
is said to be unique to make political reservation for representation even in its
legislative bodies. Seats are proportionally reserved for Scheduled Castes and
Scheduled Tribes in the House of the People, in the Parliament, and in the
Legislative Assembly of every State, with some distinction in the case of Scheduled
Tribes in the Tribal Areas in the States of Assam, Nagaland, Meghalaya, Mizoram
and Tripura. They are however not to be represented in the Council of States, in
the Parliament, or Legislative Councils of States, wherever constituted. Special
representation is ensured through nominations for Anglo-Indians in the House
of People, as also in State Legislatures, if not adequately represented through
62
Journal of Social and Political Studies
election.
The provision of reservation of the seats in the House of People and the
Legislative Assemblies was originally intended to end after ten years but the relevant
Article has been continually amended every tenth year to extend the limit and by
an Amendment in 2009 the limit has been extended till 25 January 2020. Presently
79 seats for Scheduled Castes and 42 seats for Scheduled Tribes out of total 543
seats are reserved in the House of People of the Parliament. In the Legislative
Assemblies of the States, out of total 3961 seats, 543 and 527 seats would be
reserved for Scheduled Castes and Scheduled Tribes respectively. Given the
circumstances, the provision is likely to be extended again and again.
It is important to note that there is only one general electoral roll for each of
the territorial constituencies and there are no special constituencies on the basis
of religion, race, caste, or sex. But in certain constituencies only candidates
belonging to Scheduled Castes or Scheduled Tribes, as the case may be, can contest
for being elected to the House of People, Legislative Assemblies or local bodies.
Here, candidacy is qualified but electorate is not. In autonomous districts, all
constituencies are to be represented by a member of Scheduled Tribes.
According to original provisions, after each census, the allocation of seats in
the House of People to the States has to be readjusted to keep them in proportion
to their populations in relation to national population, and also the number of
seats to be reserved for candidates belonging to Scheduled Castes/Scheduled Tribes
depending upon their populations in relation to the population of the State in
question. A Delimitation Commission has to be constituted to decide the above
matter but also to determine the territorial constituencies within States and as to
which constituencies will go to Scheduled Castes/ Scheduled Tribes candidates.
A similar provision exists for Legislative Agencies of the States. However, after
three such Commissions were constituted in 1952, 1962 and 1973 and which
completed their exercises as per Constitutional provision of proportionality, an
amendment was brought in 1976 freezing the number of seats (as well as their
territorial divisions) till the first census after 2000 so that the States do not
incentive to go slow on family planning measures. Reference population
composition thus remained as returned by 1971 census. However, by the time
census was taken in 2001, it was discovered that even within States there was a
wide variation in the size of constituencies. It was pointed out that in the National
Capital Territory of Delhi, while Chandni Chowk constituency had a population
of barely 0.35 million while Outer Delhi constituency had a population of over
3.0 million. An amendment was brought in 2001 to freeze the number till the
census after 2026. But by an Act a Delimitation Commission was also constituted
in 2002 to rationalize the territorial constituencies within each of the States. Here
the word State includes Union Territory.
A little history would be of some importance here. Under Government of
India Act of 1919, there were created separate electorates for representation for
Muslims and Sikhs (and later on also for Indian Christians and Anglo-Indians
Social Inclusion through Exclusive Provisions in India
63
under Government of India Act, 1935). The British rulers decided to review, under
political compulsions at home, the working of the Government of India Act, 1919,
and constituted Indian Statutory Commission of British MPs in 1927 under John
Simon to make an assessment and propose changes in the governance of the
country. The next five years were tumultuous in a sense. During this period,
Ambedkar demanded a separate electorate for Depressed Classes (as the Scheduled
Castes communities were known in those days) on the pattern of Muslims and
Sikhs. The Indian National Congress, the most important political party of the
day, would not agree to the proposal but Ramsay Macdonald, the then Prime
Minister of Britain, announced separate electorate for them in 1932. Ambedkar
and Gandhi took two different and divergent positions. Gandhi undertook fast
unto death. Finally, a compromise was brokered into what is popularly known as
‘Poona Pact’ between Gandhi and Ambedkar, which decided for single (joint)
electorate for Hindus but doubling the number of the seats for Depressed Classes
within the quota of the seats for Hindus.
It is significant to note that there was constituted an Advisory Committee
on Minority Rights which, in order to safeguard the political interest of the
minorities, proposed to recommend to Constituent Assembly reservation for
minorities in the legislatures on the basis of population. It was a little before
Independence. But it came for debate in the Constituent Assembly a fortnight
after Independence, the sense of the house was against such a move. In fact when
the Advisory Committee met again in mid-1949, a Christian member H.C.
Mukherjee moved a resolution saying that ‘the system of reservation for minorities
other than SC in legislatures be abolished’. It was supported by all forty members,
irrespective religions they belonged to, barring one Muslim member. Majority of
Muslim members held that ‘all these reservations must disappear and that it was
in the interests of the minorities themselves that such reservations (as proposed
on 8th August 1947) in the Legislatures must go’. Tajamul Hussain, a vocal
member in the Constituent Assembly, even said:
The term minority is a British creation. The British created the
minorities. The British have gone and the minorities have gone with them.
Remove the term minority from your dictionary. There is no minority
in India....I would like to tell you that in no civilized country where there
is parliamentary system on democratic lines; there is any reservation of
seats….We want to merge in the nation.
It appears that to begin with, political representation for Scheduled Castes
and Scheduled Tribes was 12.5 percent and 5.0 percent respectively as was in the
case of jobs. Subsequently it was raised to 15.0 and 7.5 percent for national
representation, roughly in proportion to their population, with varying degrees
across the States and UTs, depending upon their numerical strengths. Though
their share in population has increased, the number remains frozen as part of
embargo imposed on the number of seats in 1976. This was with regard to
representation in the House of People and the Legislative Assemblies in the States.
64
Journal of Social and Political Studies
In the Constitutional provisions made in 1993 for panchayats and
municipalities, seats have been reserved for membership and chairpersonship for
Scheduled Castes and Scheduled Tribes in proportion to their population in each
constituency. It is here that political reservation has been started for women in
the Indian democracy and the Constitution mandates at least one-third positions
for them (Art 243D and Art 243T). Following Bihar, many a State has raised it
to the mark of 50 percent, a little over-representation than their proportion in
the population. Recently, the Union Cabinet has also decided to propose for an
amendment in the Constitution to raise the reservation of seats to 50 percent in
panchayats and municipalities. These reservations have a further complication.
No single constituency can perpetually be represented exclusively by a woman
candidate and likewise no particular chairpersonship can be assigned to a woman
representative on a permanent basis. So, a rotational basis is evolved to carry out
the provision of reservation, not based on residential dominance of the section.
Government of India under different party coalitions made several attempts
to make reservation of women in the Parliament and State Legislatures, but has
failed so far. An articulation is now being attempted to show that it is not the
removal of disabilities through Constitutional provisions, but creation of abilities
through sensible affirmative action that intended results can be obtained even
without invoking reservations which often provoke people against reservations.
At the same time, it has to be noted, the same political parties which have favoured
a higher representation of women in panchayats and municipalities are opposing
this reservation in the House of People and Legislative Assemblies. Day will not
be far away when there would be reservation for women in the Parliament and
the Legislative Assemblies.
However, with reservations in local governments, India has around one million
women as panchayat members, more than the population of several countries.
However, women are occupying only around 11 per cent seats in the present
House of People, which has been steadily rising at least from the mid-eighties of
the past century from 5.5 percent and before that the number fluctuated between
3.5 percent and 7.7 percent. The situation compares well with the same percentage
in Japan, around 14 percent in France, Ireland and Russian Federation, 16 per
cent in Italy as well as the US, and around 19 per cent in the UK and Switzerland.
In our Council of States also women parliamentarians are around 10 percent. In
many other countries where they have two houses, women representation is quite
good as high as 40 percent. India is far below in the ranking of the countries in
terms of percentage of women representatives. It is below 100! All our neighbours
have done better, except Sri Lanka and Bhutan.
To begin with it was in the Scandinavia that reservation/quota for women
came up in the political parties as pressure from within. Their quota crosses the
mark of one-third and reaches two-fifths in Sweden, Norway and Demark. In
many modern States, some quota has been reserved for women in their national
legislature. They vary from Argentina to South Africa, from Uganda to Tanzania
Social Inclusion through Exclusive Provisions in India
65
and Bangladesh, in some countries only notionally. Though there has been
expressed some reservations in certain quarters by holding that ‘in some ways,
quotas are a remedy to a disease, but in some ways they can lead to another disease’,
but by and large such a move is considered progressive and inclusive and
empowering.
It appears that we will be able to make a law, in near future, for reservations
for women, with quota for SC and ST women within it, in the House of People
and the Legislative Assemblies.
Cultural
The Constitution of India has provided, in its Part III belonging to Fundamental
Rights under section ‘Cultural and Educational Rights’ (Art 29 and Art 30), for
protection of cultural and educational rights of the minorities and nondiscrimination in granting aid to educational institutions on the ground that its
management is in the hands of a religious or linguistic minority. Also nobody
shall be denied admission in the institutions run or aided by the State.
There is also a provision in Part IV relating to Directive Principles of State
Policy under Art 46 for the State to promote the educational and economic
interests of the Scheduled Castes, the Scheduled Tribes and other weaker sections
of people.
Under Fundamental Rights dealing with non-discrimination on grounds of
religion, race, caste, sex, descent and place of birth and residence, Art 16 (5)
guarantees that the affairs of a religious or denominational institution can be
administrated by a person professing a particular religion or belonging to a
particular denomination.
There are permanent Commissions to look after interest of the Linguistic
Minorities, Women, the Scheduled Castes, the Scheduled Tribes and Religious
Minorities. Recently, in pursuance of entry 15 mentioning ‘vagrancy, nomadic
and migratory tribes’ in the Union List of the Seventh Schedule of the
Constitution, there has been constituted a National Commission for De-notified,
Nomadic and Semi-Nomadic Tribes.
Economic
Directive Principles of State Policy, the Part IV of the Constitution, though not
enforceable by any court of law, are said to be ‘fundamental in the governance of
the country and it is the duty of the State to apply them in making laws’ (Art
37). They are said to be forerunner of the UN Convention on Right to
Development as an inalienable human right. These are the principles which make
India a welfare State as is suggested in Art 38 that the State shall strive to secure
a social order for the promotion of welfare of the people, echoing the Preamble,
through ensuring that justice—social, economic and political—informs all the
institutions of national life. In 1978 it was added that the State shall strive to
minimize the inequalities in income, and endeavour to eliminate inequalities in
66
Journal of Social and Political Studies
status, facilities and opportunities, not only among individuals but amongst groups
of people residing in different areas or engaged in different vocations.
Without using the modern phrase inclusion, it says a lot. Art 39, which
accepts the primacy of private property and market forces, indicates the conditions
for the State intervention. It specifically mentions equality among men and women
about their right for adequate means to livelihood and equal pay for equal work.
Art 39A, brought in as an amendment in 1976, provides for equal justice and
free legal aid so that justice is not denied to anybody on account of economic or
other disabilities. There are general indications for inclusion of men, women,
children and workers, who are in need, in the matter of education, employment
and public assistance, and there is a specific mention in Art 46 for promotion of
the educational and economic interests of the weaker sections of the people,
particularly of the Scheduled Castes and the Scheduled Tribes.
Under Art 275, the Union can provide each year from the Consolidated Fund
of India such sums as grant-in-aid of the revenues of such States as may be in
need of assistance to enable them to meet the costs of such schemes of development
as are carried out to promote welfare of the Scheduled Tribes or to improve the
level of administration of the Scheduled Areas.
In pursuance of these provisions, one notices that there has been created in
the Five Year Plans special component plan for Scheduled Castes since 1978 and
Tribal Sub-Plan since 1976, wherein is placed 15 per cent and 7.5 per cent of
total plan budget respectively for the purposes. They are at the disposal of National
and State authorities created for development of SCs and STs. There have been
established the National Scheduled Castes Finance and Development Corporation
in 1989 and (State) Scheduled Caste Corporations much before in 1978 as a
Centrally Sponsored Scheme with 49:51 equity shares. In 1997 National Safai
Karmachari Finance and Development Corporation was also established. For
Scheduled Tribes there are again two bodies, viz., National Scheduled Tribes
Finance and Development Corporation and Tribal Cooperative Marketing
Development Federation of India. The National Backward Classes Finance and
Development Corporation was also created in 1992 with an authorized capital
of Rs 200 crore, further raised to Rs 700 crore and the National Minorities
Development and Finance Corporation was constituted in 1994 with an
authorized capital of Rs 500 crore.
There are several schemes such as Post Matric Scholarship Scheme for
Scheduled Castes (since 1944), Mahila Samriddhi Yojana (Women Prosperity
Scheme), Adivasi Mahila Sashaktikaran Yojana (Tribal Women Empowerment
Scheme), etc. There are exclusive Girls Schools, Girls Colleges and Women
Polytechnics. There are several Gandhi, Ambedkar and Valmiki yojanas as well.
Employment
Employment and opportunity for employment is a crucial parameter in any society
trying to transit from a feudal order to a capitalist order in the emerging
Social Inclusion through Exclusive Provisions in India
67
technological scenario. People are dispossessed of means of production and wage
employment is scanty and whatever wage employment is available is in the
informal sector where wages are quite low because the demand for the goods and
services produced in that sector is generally low, and elastic. Most people are still
in ‘forced’ self-employment, somehow making out their living, barring few
professionals who by definition are part of informal sector.
The State cannot normally force private employers for employment and wages
at the same time in any economy, let alone in an economy where self-employment
is the order and wage employment is at best intermittent and casual. Private
organised sector is too small from the angle of employment as it employs barely
two percent of the total labour force. Therefore, the State stipulates employment
of people under its wings, where it is at most 5 to 6 percent. Accommodating
huge number of aspirants in such a small opening is not possible and
complications also arise because of competencies required for the jobs available.
Therefore, there has occasionally been raised demand for reservation for weaker
sections in private sector also, which is least likely to be finally conceded.
Since there exists a general shortage of jobs, one talks of equalization of
opportunity, which is supposed to be just enough. Under Fundamental Rights,
Art 16 guarantees equality of opportunity to all citizens in matters relating to
employment or appointment to any office under the State and holds that no
discrimination can be made on grounds of religion, race, caste, sex, descent, birthplace or residence for any employment or office under the State. The provision
implies that if there is one vacancy and a hundred applicants, every applicant
should stand equal chance of getting selected in the process of recruitment.
However, in the same article, it is stipulated that nothing shall prevent the
Parliament from making any law prescribing, in regard to a class or classes of
employment or appointment to an office under the Government of, or any local
or other authority within, a State or Union Territory, any requirement as to
residence within that State or Union Territory prior to such employment or
appointment. So, discrimination can be built between two or more categories of
employment (say class IV) and of people (say, domicile). Not only this, it further
makes exception for the State to make provisions for the reservation of
appointments or posts of any backward class of citizens, which in its opinion is
not adequately represented in the services under the State. That is, jobs are reserved
for Scheduled Castes, Scheduled Tribes and Other Backward classes. Then, the
principle of equality of opportunity of employment would be applicable within
each class but not between classes.
However, the facts of under-representation and backwardness of the castes/
classes did not prove adequate for promotion of SCs and STs in jobs and it had
to be specifically provided for by insertion of Art 16 (4A) in 1995, which says,
after amendment in 2001, ‘Nothing shall prevent the State from making provision
for the reservation in matters of promotion of any class or classes of posts in the
services under the State in favour of Scheduled Castes and Schedules Tribes which,
68
Journal of Social and Political Studies
in the opinion of the State, is not adequately represented in the services under
the State’. A further clause (4B) in Art 16 was subsequently added in 2000 to
cumulate un-filled posts in any year and carrying them forward in subsequent
years.
The Supreme Court of India had suggested a ceiling of 50 per cent for
reservations of all categories and has indicated income criterion for creamy layer
in the case of members of other backward classes. Art 16 (4B) makes it clear that
50 per cent ceiling will apply only for fresh vacancies caused, not to unfilled SC/
ST vacancies in the past.
It is a duty of the State, under Art 46 of ‘Directive Principles of State Policy’,
to promote the educational and economic interests of the weaker sections of the
citizens and in particular of the Scheduled Castes and Scheduled Tribes. The same
article also asks the State to protect them from social injustice and all forms of
exploitation. In the Part XVI dealing with Special Provisions Relating to Certain
Classes, Art 335 maintains that the claims of the members of the Scheduled Castes
and Scheduled Tribes shall be taken into consideration, consistently with
maintenance of efficiency of administration, in the making of appointments to
services and posts in connection with the affairs of the Union or of a State. There
is thus an issue of efficiency versus reservation. A recently introduced bill in the
Council of States (on 23rd December, 2008), known as the Scheduled Castes and
Scheduled Tribes (Reservation in Posts and Services) Bill restricts the reservation
in 47 institutes of national importance to the lowest level of grade ‘A’ posts only.
This has been seen by some quarters as a case of ‘apartheid’. There is a genuine
concern that reservation in employment in the category A at all levels (Lecturer,
Reader and Professor; Scientist at levels A, B, C, D, E, F, etc.) would compromise
the quality of work that is expected of the organization.
As of now there is reservation in the case of employment under the
Government of India, generally speaking at entry level in all categories, 15.0
percent for the Scheduled Castes and 7.5 percent for the Scheduled Tribes, and
27.0 percent for the Other Backward Classes, thus totaling to 49.5 percent, over
which there is supernumerary reservation of 3.0 percent for physically handicapped
persons in all categories. The States are free to determine their own quota for the
Other Backward Classes. Creamy layer’ of the OBC, defined by an income limit,
is debarred from enjoying opportunities under reservation. Income is not a
criterion for non-discrimination.
Education
The most significant ethos of the day and an important factor for equalizing
opportunities in employment is understood to be education. Under Art 46, in
Directive Principles of the State Policy, the State undertakes to promote with
special care the educational and economic interests of the weaker sections of the
citizens, and in particular, of the Scheduled Castes and Scheduled Tribes. There
are scholarships, hostels, special coaching institutions, etc. for these sections, but
Social Inclusion through Exclusive Provisions in India
69
for a long time, there was no reservation in admission. Post-matric scholarship
existed from 1944, pre-matric scholarship was introduced in 1977, remedial and
special coaching to remove deficiencies in school subjects so as to help them enter
professional and technical courses started in 1987 and Rajiv Gandhi Fellowship
to help them pursue higher studies and research degrees was provided in 2005.
They are given help to prepare for competitive examinations conducted by the
Union Public Service Commission through coaching and hostel facilities. All this
which is available to Scheduled Castes is also available to Scheduled Tribes. But
in addition, for Scheduled Tribe students, there is a special focus for providing
textbooks and uniforms and free tuition etc.
Reservation in admission in most courses in all States is now available to the
Scheduled Castes, the Scheduled Tribes, and physically handicapped and to the
Other Backward Classes in the institutions funded by the Union Government.
Some differential treatment is also meted out to girls and women in the matter
of education.
In the wake of passage of Right to Education Bill in 2009, a good fillip is
likely to be given to the provisions for scheduled and backward sections.
Administrative
In some way even administrative mechanism of ensuring inclusion has been
provided for in the Constitution. It provides for, especially in the State of Bihar,
Madhya Pradesh and Orissa, a Minister in charge of tribal welfare who may also
be simultaneously in charge of the welfare of Scheduled Castes and backward
classes. And there is specific provision for administration of Scheduled Areas and
Tribal Areas and formation of autonomous State within Assam with full legislative
and executive functions.
Though there is no specific direction for the Union to create such ministries
yet it has been over time creating several ministries to look after interests of
vulnerable sections. To begin with there existed several divisions in the Ministry
of Home Affairs to look after interests of excluded sections, like Scheduled Castes
Development Division, Tribal Development Division and the Minorities and
Backward Classes Welfare Division. The Ministry of Law had a Wakf Division.
All these divisions were moved to form a Ministry of Welfare. Department of
Woman and Child Development, which was a part of the Ministry of Human
Resource Development created in 1985, with main constituent as the Department
of Education, was made part of the Ministry of Welfare. The Ministry of Welfare
had two main Departments: Department of Welfare and Department of Woman
and Child Development. Department of Welfare was upgraded to the level of
Ministry and renamed as Ministry of Social Justice and Empowerment in 1998
while the Division of Tribal Development was taken out in 1999 and made the
Ministry of Tribal Affairs. Minorities and Backward Classes Welfare Division/
Department was again divided in 2007. While there was created a Ministry of
Minority Affairs in 2007, Backward Classes Welfare Division was retained in the
70
Journal of Social and Political Studies
Ministry of Social Justice and Empowerment. Department of Woman and Child
Development was also upgraded to the level of Ministry in 2006.
Ministry of Social Justice & Empowerment as the name suggests is to ensure
equitable treatment to such sections of society who have suffered social inequalities,
exploitation, discrimination and injustice. The Social Defence Bureau of the
Ministry caters to the requirements of neglected and marginalized people,
abandoned destitute, neglected and delinquent juveniles who need care and
protection for want of support or are in conflict with the society or the law. The
Disability Division is supposed to empower the physically handicapped.
Current State of Affairs in Terms of Inclusion
Finally, the taste of pudding is in eating. How were provisions in the Constitution
implemented and how much resources—financial and administrative—were
actually committed, and how well were they utilized? How were other sections
of the society taken along? How was the morale of the people, excluded and
marginalized, boosted? What was the end result in terms of outcomes?
Political
As far as political representation is concerned, we know that the Constitutional
provision of reservation of seats exists for the Scheduled Castes and the Scheduled
Tribes at all levels—national, state and local, including autonomous district/
regional councils and tribes advisory councils wherever they exist, are followed in
toto. However, for women, constitutional provision is only at local level and it is
strictly followed. There exists no reservation for other backward classes and their
number is not exactly known as there is no constitutional order declaring castes/
classes in various States or parts thereof as is the case for Scheduled Castes and
Scheduled Tribes. Various States have declared certain castes, including those
among Muslims, as OBC but their number cannot be ascertained as the census
does not enumerate people by caste. A variety of caste census is being attempted.
There is no political reservation for them though they have emerged politically
strong across the spectrum.
The reservation for SC and ST was made to begin with for ten years only,
but it has been extended time and again and currently it exists upto 2020, and
before its expiry it is certain that it will be further extended. Their seats are reserved
in proportion to their population at national, state and local level, as the case
may be. There has been no deviation, and the provision was implemented in toto.
The Constitution has made provision of reservation of at least 33 percent of the
seats for women in each type and level of local government. The State of Bihar
reserved 50 per cent seats for women and following Bihar, many other States have
also enhanced the reservation quota. The Government of India is also
contemplating an amendment for raising the quota from one-third to half of the
seats at local level. The most important fact in this context is that political
Social Inclusion through Exclusive Provisions in India
71
reservation at local level is permanent, as against at other levels. It has also been
implemented in toto.
Women are increasingly coming to the legislatures, thanks to societal
understanding. Their number has increased from 5.5 per cent in Ninth Lok Sabha
to 11.0 percent in Fifteenth Lok Sabha, which is one-third (or less) of what
Scandinavian countries have for women but about two-thirds of what other
developed countries may have but more than what many other countries have
fixed for women.
We have at the moment a woman President and a woman Speaker in the
House of People. We did have a woman Prime Minister earlier. We have been
having woman Chief Ministers, Governors, Ministers and Legislators at all levels
across the country.
Other Backward Classes have politically done quite well. They have come
on their own. They may be even over-represented in terms of their numerical
strength, as legislators, if not as ministers.
Practically every religion and caste/tribe group had at some point of time
occupied one or the other top constitutional/political position. Even today the
President is a Hindu, the Vice- President is a Muslim and the Prime Minister is a
Sikh. And they are there often by their merit. No negative discrimination has
been done to them on the grounds of race, religion, caste or gender.
Education
What is there in terms of education? Literacy is the simplest case to reckon with,
which has been attempted through formal and non-formal institutions. We find
from the following Table 1 that literacy level has increased from mere one-sixth
in 1951 to about two-thirds in 2001, while the number of illiterates exceeded
that of literates till 1990 or so. The SCs and STs still do not fare that well though
increase in their proportion is somewhat better due to the efforts made by the
State. It is true that the differences between overall literacy rate and those of
Scheduled Castes and Scheduled Tribes have increasingly come down. But, it is a
sorry state of affairs that literacy rate, with so much modern value attached, was
not still 2/3rds by 2001. It has improved to 74 by the census in 2011 for the
country as a whole and that for weaker sections to cross the mark of 65 percent
and 60 percent respectively.
But when we study literacy by religion across gender in Table 2, we observe
that Muslims are the least literate and Christians are the most literate, followed
by Buddhists and Sikhs. The disparity between male and female is the least among
Christians followed by Sikhs while it is the worst among Hindus followed by
Muslims. It is, in general, a reflection of prosperity and poverty and, of course,
of culture and exposure. It seems that situation would have been far worse had
the promotional measures not been undertaken.
Journal of Social and Political Studies
72
Table 1: Literacy Rates of SC and ST and Changes Over Time (in percent)*
1951
1961
1971
1981
1991
2001
All
SC
ST
Difference
SC
Difference
ST
Ratio
SC
Ratio
ST
16.7
24.0
29.5
36.2
52.2
64.8
10.2
14.7
21.4
37.4
54.7
08.5
11.3
16.4
29.6
47.1
13.8
14.8
14.9
14.8
10.1
15.5
18.2
19.9
22.6
17.7
42.7
49.5
59.0
71.7
84.4
35.5
38.4
45.1
56.7
72.7
SC=Scheduled Castes; ST=Scheduled Tribes * Difference in Percent Points
Table 2: Literacy Rates Across Religion in 2001 (in percent)
Religion
Male
Female
Persons
Male-Female
All
Hindu
Muslim
Christian
Sikh
Buddhist
75.4
77.8
67.6
84.4
75.2
83.1
53.7
54.7
50.1
76.2
63.1
61.7
64.8
66.2
59.1
80.3
69.4
72.7
21.7
23.1
17.5
08.2
12.1
21.4
Female/Male
71.2
70.3
74.1
90.3
83.9
74.2
M-F = Percent point difference between male and female literacy rates; F/M= Ratio of female literacy
rate to male literacy rate, in percent.
Economic
People’s life depends a lot on how they are employed. Despite the fact that India
is presently growing fast and contribution of its agriculture has fallen below 17
per cent, a preponderant majority, close to two-thirds, of labour force is still
working in the agriculture sector either as self-employed cultivators or as
agricultural wage labour insofar as its rural scene is concerned. More than 76
percent of SC labour force and 85 percent of ST labour force is still on farms.
The major difference between the three categories is the division between
cultivators and agriculture wage labour though, given the fact that more than
three-fourth holdings are small and marginal, they are all labourers. For
appreciating the division, we may peruse the following Table 3.
Table 3: Participation Rate of Population and Distribution of Workers in 2001
(in percent)
Participation Rate of Population
Workers as Cultivators
Workers as Agr Labour
All
SC
ST
All
SC
ST
All
SC
ST
India
39.10
40.41
49.06
31.65
19.99
44.71
26.55
45.61
36.85
Rural
41.75
42.50
50.37
40.24
23.47
47.07
33.05
52.23
38.37
Urban
32.75
33.14
34.56
02.81
01.76
06.55
04.71
11.03
12.38
While all workers are divided in the ratio of 5:4 as cultivators and agricultural
labour in rural areas, where all workers include all religions and all forward and
backward classes/castes, the Scheduled Caste workers are divided in the ratio of
Social Inclusion through Exclusive Provisions in India
73
5:11 and the Scheduled Tribes workers are in the ratio of 5:4 again. Scheduled
Caste people are most dispossessed of land. This is the rural scene. Urban scene
is different: the ST in the ratio of 1:2, the SC in 1:6, and all in 3:5. But again,
Scheduled Castes people are most dispossessed of land though land may not be
the most important possession in the cities.
But does ownership mean much? Not, much. Let us look at the poverty
incidence by social division for which data is readily available. When compared
to all population, the STs are worse off than the SCs in rural areas though they
are better off in terms of land possession. The order of poverty incidence is just
reverse in urban areas. When we concentrate on change between 2004-05 and
1993-94 (that is, during the years of so-called liberalization) reduction in poverty
rate is better in the case of the Scheduled Castes irrespective of the area of residence
(rural: 11 percent points, and urban: 10 percent points), while the Scheduled
Tribes do not do better whether in rural areas (less than 8 percent points) or in
urban areas (less than 8 percent points). If the STs fare better in urban areas (7.8
percent points) than the aggregate (6.7 percent points) their number is not large.
Further, the gap between ‘all’ and ‘STs’ has increased between 1993-94 and 200405. See the following Table 4.
Table 4: Poverty Head Count Ratios (in percent) and Differences and Reduction
(in percent points)
All
Scheduled Castes
Scheduled Tribes
Difference: All-SC
Difference: All-ST
1993-94
Rural
1993-94
Urban
2004-05
Rural
2004-05
Urban
37.2
48.1
51.9
10.9
14.6
32.4
49.5
41.1
17.1
09.8
28.3
36.8
47.3
08.5
19.0
25.7
39.9
33.3
14.2
07.6
Reduction
Rural
Urban
09.0
11.3
04.6
02.3
- 04.4
06.7
09.6
07.8
02.8
01.1
Employment
For economic well-being, but more importantly for status, in India, government
jobs matter a lot, particularly for those who are very well-off. The Constitution
provided, to begin with, two things: political representation in legislative bodies
without exceptions and job reservation in government employment with some
riders. Other things were added later. It is worth having a look at the job position
in the government. Our database supports information about the employment
in the Government of India. But similar and a better position exists in the case
of employment under the State Governments including their parastatal bodies, if
we cannot say the same about local governments. For 2004, we also have
information on the other backward classes as well. First, let us see how the
composition is across groups in Tables 5, 6 and 7.
Journal of Social and Political Studies
74
Table 5: Employment of Scheduled Castes and Scheduled Tribes in
Government of India
Group
A
B
1994
1999
All
SC
ST
59016
6046
1727
103198
12442
All
2004
SC
93520 10558
2902 104963 13306
ST
All
OBC*
SC
ST
3172
80011
3088
9744
3311
3512 135409
3127
19602
6274
C
2381613 374758 128228 239426 378115 145482 2040970 106334 344865 136630
D
1023285 209423 62945 949353 189761 66487 802116
26149 147212 53776
Total 3567112 602670 195802 3544262 591740 218653 3058506 138698 521423 199991
*Backward calculations.
We observe from Table 6 that proportion of the Scheduled Caste and the
Scheduled Tribe employees in each category of service under the Government of
India is improving except in the D category where the Scheduled Castes are a bit
over-represented while the Scheduled Tribes are under-represented. There is some
moderation in D group in the proportion of Scheduled Castes in last ten years
and Scheduled Tribes in last five years. In the government jobs as a whole, their
proportions have reached or are reaching their share in population despite lag in
literacy/education. Other backward classes are dismally represented in
bureaucracy—the best they do is in the C category followed by that in the A
category. We can note that in politics they seem to be doing quite well on their
own without reservation.
Table 6: Share of Scheduled Castes and Scheduled Tribes and Other Backward
Classes in the Employment in Government of India (in per cent)
Group
1994
1999
2004
OBC
SC
ST
OBC
SC
ST
OBC
SC
ST
A
B
C
D
-
10.24
12.06
15.74
20.47
2.93
2.81
5.38
6.15
-
11.29
12.68
15.78
19.99
3.39
3.35
6.07
7.00
3.86
2.31
5.21
3.26
12.18
14.48
16.90
18.35
4.14
4.63
6.69
6.70
Total
-
16.90
5.49
-
16.70
6.17
4.53
17.05
6.54
How is each group (Scheduled Castes, Scheduled Tribes and Other Backward
Classes) distributed across categories? Most of the employees are in C group and
their proportion is staying put and more than three-quarters of OBC employees
are in this group while in the case of Scheduled Castes and Scheduled Tribes
employees are in the vicinity of two-thirds as is the overall composition. It implies
that general category is little less represented. Group D is coming down across
the social categories while shares of groups A and B is improving. OBC is less
represented in group B than SC/ST while they are doing better in group A,
suggesting a little better representation of general category. It may be noted that
though OBC are numerically fewer in government jobs their own composition
on the better side. See Table 7.
Social Inclusion through Exclusive Provisions in India
75
Table7: Share of SC, ST and All in Government Employment (in percent)
Group
1994
1999
2004
All
SC
ST
All
SC
ST
All
OBC
SC
ST
A
1.65
1.00
0.88
2.64
1.78
1.45
2.62
2.22
1.87
1.66
B
2.89
2.06
1.48
2.96
2.25
1.61
4.43
2.25
3.67
3.14
C
66.77
62.18
65.49
67.61
63.90
66.54
66.73
76.66
66.14
68.32
D
28.69
34.75
32.15
26.79
32.07
30.41
26.23
18.85
28.23
26.89
One side window we can afford to open here is that share of employees in A
plus B categories is improving largely at the cost of D category employees while
that of the C categories remains almost constant at 2/3rds. Calculations can be
made from Table 4 where one can observe that the number of employees in groups
A and B is on increase whereas that of those in groups C and D is on decrease.
However, all euphoria evaporates when one notices in Table 5 stagnancy in
number of all employees between 1994 and 1999 and attrition in absolute
numbers in 2004 over 1999. Five lakh less people, from 35 lakh to 30 lakh, are
in the Union government jobs. That is a reduction of around 15 percent in
number of employees in the employ of Government of India. That is the impact
of downsizing and rightsizing policies given effect to during this period. Had there
been increase in private sector, we might have ignored the attrition. But the fact
is in terms of employment, organized/corporate sector is not performing well.
There is a tremendous work load and pressure on young generation in certain
sectors of the corporate world. If we move down from job-less to job-loss scenario,
inclusion policies will suffer a great blow. Reservation has much meaning when
there is accretion in jobs but it loses significance when there is absolute attrition
in the face of increase in the size of labour force. Sphere of wage employment,
which frees one from a variety of bondage, has to increase in the present
circumstances.
This scenario is expected to be reflective of the government employment in
general though our database is limited to Union Government, except in the North
East States where major employment is in the government sector.
We can recall when Dadabhai Naoroji studied poverty, he did not blame the
distribution but the lack of growth due to British drain policy. Likewise, talk of
inclusion loses significance if opportunities are shrinking. Ensuring equality of
opportunity is not enough, growth of opportunities is even more important. If
recruitment is zero, 100 percent reservation is useless. If, on the other hand,
recruitment increases by 10 per cent instead of 5 percent, a little more than half
the stipulated reservation will work better.
Conclusion
Social inclusion of excluded, partially excluded and secluded communities and
groups in secular domain of societal processes of political and economic
76
Journal of Social and Political Studies
significance has been attempted in India without intrusion in the privacy domain.
Given the diversity and plurality that makes India, it was not an easy task to carry
out inclusion agenda because removing disparity at times bumps into some notion
of diversity and plurality. There has been a broad consensus about pursuing a
course of harmony without imposition of homogenization and unity without
imposition of uniformity of any kind, rather preserving diversity and plurality,
yet doing away with or at least moderating the magnitude of disparities. However,
it should be noted that in economic field we have done away with, along with
the rest of the world, the idea of reducing disparity (often called inequality) and
concentrated on poverty and in political and social arena we are stuck with
reducing disparities. It means we shall not make attempt to do away with economic
disparities but shall make attempt to do away with social disparities. In a way
that is what existence of capitalist economic order and political democratic
dispensation calls for! However, we are also witnessing interest, in countries like
India, in reducing what has come to be known as horizontal disparity but losing
interest in vertical inequality. Reduction in vertical inequality was no guarantee
of reduction in horizontal inequality but overly emphasis on reducing horizontal
inequality sans vertical inequality will not go a long way. Yet, on balance, social
inclusion has improved—partly by autonomous movement of society and partly
by State activism.
India as a State pursued Ambedkar line and perpetuated by practice political
reservation for Scheduled Castes and Scheduled Tribes in the Lower House of
the Parliament and Legislative assemblies, which was a temporary arrangement
in Ambedkar formulation. When it came to reservation in local government, it
was made permanent in the same Constitution. Reservation for women in local
government is at least one third of the total seats of members in each local
government and of total number of chairpersonships in the State. But there is no
reservation for women in the Parliament or State Legislature. Political success in
what was proposed in the Constitution is total. In the civil matters success is more
than half of the completed journey. In educational and economic matters the
success is far from satisfactory. But it is not only in the case of excluded groups
alone, but even in the case of so-called included. The State of India does face
backlashes and clashes on reservation count.
For long growth of the economy and employment was very sluggish, but good
enough not to badly impact on population growth. Now, when rate of growth of
the economy has picked up fast and population growth is stabilizing, employment
elasticity is on a declining curve. Neither employment growth is picking up nor
is the quality of employment, in terms of productivity improvement. Reduction
of poverty though a bit higher for excluded sections, is not big enough to give a feeling
of inclusion to those who were traditionally excluded, yet causing a feeling of exclusion
in those who are supposedly included.
In economic sphere, India seems to have been playing a zero-sum game leaving
people on both the side of inclusion-exclusion line dissatisfied. The real challenge
Social Inclusion through Exclusive Provisions in India
77
for India is to turn economic games into positive-sum ones so that fruits in terms of
job and livelihood reach everyone. Jobs just do not entitle an individual for
livelihood, but also empower him/her socially and psychologically. Equality of
opportunity which reservation policy seems to be promoting at best should be
construed as an assignment problem of who gets what rather than an allocation
problem in which some get and some do not. Unfortunately, that is not happening
as employment is formulated as a derivative of growth strategy which looks for
acceleration per se. Of late, realizing the failure of growth process to translate into
employment of the socially excluded and exclusion of the socially included we
have attempted strategy of inclusive growth in the recent past. Preliminary results
are not very encouraging.
(Acknowledgement: Revised version of a paper read in a SAARC Regional
Workshop on Social Inclusion Policies of the State: Experience and Challenges
organized by Centre for Nepalese and Asian Studies, Tribhuban University,
Kathmandu. The author would like to thank the organizers, particularly Nirmal
Man Tuladhar and Mrigendra Bahadur Karki, who invited him to participate in
the workshop and fellow participants who made fruitful observations and
comments, some of which could be incorporated in the revision of the draft. The
author was also benefited from the general discussion that took place in the
workshop. The author would also like to thank Dr. Geeta Chaubey, Dr. D.P.
Sharma and Dr. Sushma Yadav who went through the draft for revision and offered
critical suggestions for improvement. However, the author alone is responsible
for lacunae, gaps and weaknesses that the paper might inhere.)
REFERENCES
Ministry of Law and Justice, Government of India, The Constitution of India, various editions.
Planning Commission, Government of India, Eleventh Five Year Plan 2007-2012 Volume I: Inclusive
Growth, Oxford University Press, New Delhi, India, 2008.
Publication Division, Government of India, India: A Reference Annual, various issues.
Internet websites.
APPENDIX
Scheduled Castes and Scheduled Tribes
The word ‘scheduled’ in the context of the Scheduled Castes, Scheduled Tribes
and Scheduled Areas is little confusing to many scholars. Therefore, the following
explanation is offered.
There are twelve schedules in the Constitution of India, two of which viz.,
the Fifth and Sixth Schedules refer to similar matter. While the Fifth Schedule
provides for a Tribal Advisory Council in a State with Scheduled Areas and also
in a State with Scheduled Tribes but not Scheduled Areas, the Sixth Schedule
provides for administration of the Tribal Areas, each with autonomous District
Council and Regional Councils if there are different Scheduled Tribes, with powers
to make laws in respect of certain matters, in certain States like Assam, Meghalaya,
Mizoram and Tripura. In the latter schedule, there is a Table with parts showing
78
Journal of Social and Political Studies
certain Districts as Tribal Areas. However, the word ‘scheduled’ in the above three
expressions has nothing to do with these twelve schedules except that matters
related to ‘Scheduled’ Areas are dealt with in the Fifth Schedule. In short, word
‘scheduled’ is different than a ‘schedule’ of the Constitution. Some of the
Constitutional schedules are not in a strictly scheduler form. Some scholars have
unfortunately attributed existence of scheduled castes and scheduled tribes to
schedules appended to the main Constitution.
The President is supposed to issue an order, under the Fifth Schedule of the
Constitution dealing with Part X, to declare the certain areas as Scheduled Areas.
By the Constitutional Order No. 9 issued on 26th January 1950, the President
actually declared four areas in Bihar, now in Jharkhand; ten areas in Bombay,
now in Gujarat; eleven areas in Madhya Pradesh, now in Chhattisgarh except one
that is in Maharashtra; and two in Madras, now one in Andhra Pradesh and one
is Lakshadweep; two in Orissa; and one in Punjab, which is now in Himachal
Pradesh. They were all listed under the relevant State.
Article 366 of the Constitution gives definitions of certain terms, which
include Scheduled Castes and Scheduled Tribes. Scheduled Castes are defined as
castes, races, tribes or parts of, or groups within, such castes, races, tribes as are
deemed under Article 341 which empowers the President to specify with respect
to a State (in consultation with the Governor) or a Union Territory by public
notification. Likewise Scheduled Tribes are defined as tribes or tribal communities
or parts of, or groups within, such tribes or tribal communities as are deemed
under Art 342 which empowers the President to specify with respect to a State
(in consultation with the Governor) or a Union Territory by public notification.
These notifications are called Constitutional Orders. The Constitutional
(Scheduled Castes) Order 1950, numbering 19 was issued on 10th August 1950
and the Constitutional (Scheduled Tribes) Order 1950, numbering 22, was issued
on 6th September 1950, supplemented by the Constitutional (Scheduled Castes)
(Union Territories) Order 1951, numbering 32, issued on 20th September 1951
and the Constitutional (Scheduled Castes) (Union Territories) Order 1951,
numbering 33, issued on 20th September 1951. Of course, the words Union
Territories were substituted for other words as certain category of States were redesignated as Union territories in 1956 only. Both of the sets of orders were
modified and amended several times only to include more castes and tribes or
enumerate them under the newly formed/carved out States.
The word ‘scheduled’ has origin in Government of India Act of 1935, in
which Depressed Classes were given these ‘neutral’ expressions. Gandhi used to
call the people belonging to lower castes as Harijan, a term earlier used for
Brahmins say writers like saint Tulsidas. Since most of tribal people used to live
on the hills, they were given a term of Girijan by certain scholars. Word ‘depressed’
was the translation of Hindi/Marathi word ‘Dalit’, which is emerging in recent
years in literature and is subsuming both Scheduled Castes and Scheduled Tribes;
but the adjective is getting attached with Muslims and Christians as well.
Exploring the Dynamics of Talent and Significance in the State System
79
State and Talent: Exploring the Dynamics of
Talent and Significance in the State System
I.D. Mishra
This is a modest attempt to understand the relations between state and talent.
Talent as determinant of state capacity is of the highest significance both for the
individuals and the state itself. It is the intrinsic worth of a person and the potential
strength of a state. Talent, if misconstrued and manipulated, weakens the state
and deprives its individuals from their due. Cunningness, tricking, dishonesty,
intolerance, hatred, violence are alien to talent and therefore can not formulate
the contours of talent. Any policy or behaviour which encourage the above one
are the worst of animality to enter in to the arena of humanity. Individuals, society
and state can never be safe if either of the above makes any space for itself in
talent search scheme at any levels, i.e. from formative stage to competitive stage
and finally at the stage of governance. We have viewed this problem in India’s
context and have drawn the line of framework to explore the notion of talent
and its relations with state.
Statement of the Problem1
India as a state is the background in which the talent search scheme has to be
functional. This involves two basic problems. First, searching the talent of the
candidate in person, and second, searching the talent of the person in relation to
the state. Since India as a state consists of citizens living there in, every candidate
whether a citizen or prospective citizen, has the right to be searched out the talent
he/she possesses. This hidden but vital background appears to be missing through
out the national curriculum. Therefore, the scheme is to be desired to be evolved
where the talent of every prospective candidate, as far as possible, be searched
and recognized in the field he/ she is comparatively more potential of, and the
state in the background of the talents deserving its due must be reckoned with
its share in the process of contributions from talent. In view of this probability,
the National institutions like NCERT can endeavour in evolving such system
which could effectively enlarge and decentralize its area so as to extend the benefit
of the curriculum to the people living in the backward rural and remote areas. In
fact the ideal situation is where every learner must know one’s own talent and
the opportunities to develop it. But one can find a different situations where scope
remains narrowed, and opportunities remain limited to comparatively a small
number. It has been observed on an average that the beneficiaries under the present
scheme are those who come from elite schools. The students in majority from
rural areas and low income groups can not afford to study in such schools.
Therefore, these students in general lag behind in competitive race than those
80
Journal of Social and Political Studies
who have been educated in elite schools and have acquired technical efficiency
through training and coaching systems. Consequently students who are more
trained and know more tricks remain in advantageous position than those who
are less trained and are unaware of the tricks. Hence, necessity is to devise such
modalities to improve the existing schemes and practices which could help search
out the natural/potential talents of the maximum number as far as possible. The
fallacies lie in our co-relation to talent and its core components. We bring to our
notice some of these problems for exploration and exposition to the core areas of
talent.
Talent- Merit Relationships: Paradigm Shift
Talent and merit are sometimes used interchangeably. Talent measured and
recognized is known as merit. Indeed, these are the two different words with two
different meanings. Merit is a comparative concept—one’s merit in comparison
to the other. It is a ranking system. Ranks are provided to the individual
competitors. It means merit is hierarchy of ranks and talent is evaluated as ranked
merit. It acknowledges, therefore, the incompleteness of the person in the merit
which is sandwiched between superiority and inferiority paradigm. One is superior
to the other within the formula evolved. Moreover, it also creates frustrations
among those who are ranked below and those who are excluded from the merit.
This is good neither for state nor for democracy. It leads us to say that talent as
merit is shift of paradigm which requires reconsideration to mark a difference.
We propose here some paradigms to explore the notion of talent and its
significance. The purpose is to hint about the short comings the talent search
schemes at different levels have.
Q-R Paradigm of Talent
In this formula questions are the monopoly of evaluators where as ‘response’ is
the candidates’ exclusive opportunities. Although this is a way to test/evaluate the
context, this cannot claim to be comprehensive one. First, questions are the
mechanized pattern to which the respondents have to interact. This means talent
is = Q (Question) + R (Response). In this system Q(Question) remains always Q
and R (Response- Respondents) always ‘R.’ This means ‘Q’ excludes from itself
the opportunities of ‘R’ and ‘R’ excludes from itself the opportunities of ‘Q’.
Therefore, at least ‘R’ which is in the process of evaluation, is partly evaluated as
‘R’ and not as ‘Q’. An argument in this reference is that ‘Q’ involves ‘R’ and ‘R’
involves ‘Q’ otherwise ‘Q’ will cease its merit as ‘Q’ and ‘R’ will also cease its
merit as ‘R’. ‘R’ becomes functional only when it interacts with ‘Q’ and reaches
its centre. Similarly ‘Q’ becomes functional only when it attracts the ‘R’ to interact
with it and finally dissolves in to ’R’ when properly interacted. In this process
the space between ‘Q’ and ‘R’ is reduced to be merged with each-other. Here ‘Q’
as ‘R’ should be formulated/ detailed or explained as such that ‘R’ as ‘Q’ may be
able to formulate it as question. In this process answer is given as description of
the problem from which the questions are required to be raised.
Exploring the Dynamics of Talent and Significance in the State System
81
But in the existing system, we find that ‘Q’ is deprived of the ‘R’’s right, as
well as ‘R’ is deprived of ‘Q’’s right. Unless at least ‘R’ has also the right to ‘Q’,
one of the basic properties of talent remains veiled. This property is inquisitiveness,
a quality of the mind which has been discussed later on at appropriate places.
Second, evaluation of talent, based on question-response formula is indeed
the evaluation of question-response and not the evaluation of respondent. In
system of evaluation of subject as respondent, it is for the candidate to demonstrate
himself/herself as potential doer as well as capable of introspecting his/her
potentialities. Since candidate as a subject is not static being, but potential
prospective doer, it is necessary for the person concerned, that he/she should
introspect himself/herself and his/her introspection-ability must be tested or
searched. We have discussed it at appropriate place.
Thirdly, questions under the Mental Ability Test (MAT) category are asked
generally of puzzles type. But ‘puzzle’ is one of the modes and not the total modes.
In puzzle, a situation in complication (or complicated situation) is presented to
which mind is to interact and find the expected solution. Complication is a
negative situation in which the candidate is placed. The argument is that the
application of mind to respond to negative situations may demonstrate one version
of its talent, the next version i.e. application of mind in the positive situation
remains neglected and thus, out of the scope for testing. Hence, the functioning
of mind in positive (stressless) situations also requires to be tested in order to
compare the capacity of mind both in negative and positive situations.
Scholastic Aptitude Test (SAT) is based on information based test of the
aptitude and application of the mind. In this test, the items used ‘aim at measuring
the knowledge of the subject area besides assessing the ability to apply that
knowledge to solve new problems.’2 According to this guideline the evaluator (test)
can use/ exercise as many options as it be thought fit to fulfill the above target of
the National Talent Search ( NTS) curriculum. Since, the evaluator does not
include cognitive test, test of analytical and comparative capability, use of
inductive-deductive method, it is suggested that these aspects are required inclusion
in scholastic test. We have observed, especially, in interview that the candidates
doing well theoretically are unable to cognize the problems (including the things/
objects) they are speaking about. Besides, knowledge as an usable perspective .i.e.
applicability of knowledge to solving the problem may also constitute the theme
for formulation of questions for evaluation.
F-I paradigms of Talent
We now shift over the another important paradigms of talent. It may be named
as the ‘F-I paradigm of talent’. Two questions are involved here. First, what is
talent? Second, what is ‘F-I’ paradigm. These are the basic question to understand.
To begin with the first, it has already been mentioned above that talent is the
intrinsic worth of a person. It is potential capability to respond to the situations
in right direction.3 This capacity is determined by four ‘I’s which need three ‘F’s
82
Journal of Social and Political Studies
for their reflections. Thus we can say it as ‘F-I’ paradigm to evaluate the level of
talent in a person. ‘F’ is the state of conditions of mind where ‘I’ as talent can
function. This state of condition of mind is ‘fearlessness’, ‘freshness’ and ‘fertility’.
In other words this can be explained as ‘fearless mind, ‘fresh mind’ and ‘ fertile
mind’. ‘I’ stands for four intrinsic and inherent qualities of mind, viz.
inquisitiveness and intuitive, informative one, intelligence and introspection
ability.4
These four areas of mind may be used to describe as inquisitive and intuitive
mind, informative mind, intelligent mind and introspective mind. These core areas
of mind along with its three prior state of conditions constitute the datum of
talent. We would come to explain it later on. First of all, we must elaborate the
notion of talent from another angle as this would help outlining the basic elements
involved in it. Since candidate’s response is object of evaluation, the candidate is
the subject as well object in the whole process of evaluation.
S-R paradigm of Talent
Response to what means response to situations. Thus situation is stimuli to which
candidate responds. Prior to response is required to explore the structure of
situations. Hence, person’s response to the situation is subject of evaluation. If
the response is not in the right direction, then question for evaluation is the
methods, technique/skill being used by the person.
From the above four things emerge, First, potentiality or capability of person
in evaluation; second, situation in which the candidate is placed; third, the response
or behaviour of the person; and fourth, appropriateness of candidate’s response
or behaviour in right direction. These four segments define the contours of talent
which are to be searched.
Among the four, the first one .i.e. person in evaluation is in the centre, and
the rest three are meant for evaluating the person. In fact, the last three are the
objects which reflect the subject in proportion to its relationship and the nature
there of. This subjectification of object and vice-versa presents itself as an index
of talent. Objectification of subject places the candidate in the whole situation as
a conscious object which can adjust, readjust or explore itself, subject to the
performance of the talent. This subject-object unification can be evaluated in talent
search scheme. Any problem as such is an object to which a subject is attracted
for response. What does and how does the candidate respond, are the basic
guidelines to search out the talent. This is one dimension of searching out the
talent. Since the candidate in the evaluation process may be of different age groups,
the evaluators are required to handle the persons and process in a way to protect
them from any harm.
Situation is another important factor in the process of evaluation. Thus, one
can prepare the situations index for searching and evaluating the talent. Situation
is a background in which one is placed. It is, therefore, indispensable to one’s
existence. How to interact with situation is thus one paradigm to be put before
Exploring the Dynamics of Talent and Significance in the State System
83
the person whose talent is to be searched. This may be big or bigger situation as
well as small or smaller situation. Evaluation process prepares situations with
questions representing problems for responses.
Talent is to explore the situation and respond to it in right direction. If
situations are problematic, talent is required to respond to them so as they could
be converged in to meaningful situations and usages. If situations are to be
promoted/improved for better usages, talent is required to be applied for exploring
the best out of them. The searching out of inherent qualities or intrinsic worth
of situation as an object depends on the talent of the searcher. It is this content
of enquiry, the NTS needs to be reviewed and assessed.
Direction of response is another component of evaluation. The nature of
response and its direction may tell about the talent one possesses. Response is a
behaviour of person. It is a link between the subject and object .i.e. between
respondent and the situation. It is reflective of talent of personality as well as the
rate of its success. In one way response determines the intelligence, and skill both.
It also includes the communicative skill.
Minds and Talent: Exploring the Core Areas
Within the above contours of talent, the core areas of mind may include the
following:
1. Inquisitive and intuitive mind
2. Informative mind
3. Intelligent and imaginative mind
4. Introspective mind
There is no harm if we treat these areas as functions of mind. In evaluating
the talent of one’s mind, the functions of mind in these paradigms may
be evaluated. But before casting one’s judgment one must know what
mind and its core areas mean.
The western classical philosophy prioritizes mind and its realm***. Plato,
Aristotle, Descartes, Leibnitz, Kant, Martin Heidegger, and many other
well known philosophers have considered mind as the abode of thought
developed through the process of reasoning-imaginatively, intuitively,
speculatively, empirically and practically either way or as a whole.
The six Indian Philosophy, known as Khad darshan,is a wonderful
exposition to understand the notion of mind- both as eternal and
temporal. It is neither possible nor appropriate in this modest attempt
to ponder in to this high level exposition and illumination. However, we
refer here in substance the functions of mind as follows:
i Manas—it is the sensory, processing mind;
ii. Chitta—Storage of impression
iii. Ahamkar—‘I’-maker of ego
iv. Buddhi—knows, decides, judges, and discrimination
84
Journal of Social and Political Studies
Human mind, in nut shell, ‘is the complex of cognitive faculties that
enables consciousness, thinking, reasoning, perception and judgment.’ We
can understand the mind by observing its functioning, first, ‘by observing
mind through actions and speech’, and second, ‘by observing thinking
process within at the moment operating, independently and as they
interact.’
Inquisitive and Intuitive Mind: Testing and Learning Method
The first criterion of searching and evaluating the talent is to see whether the
person’s mind is inquisitive one. Inquisitiveness is known by one’s quest for
knowledge. It means ‘eager to know’/‘apt to ask questions.’ It is ‘curious ‘mind.5
It could be observed whether the person in the process of evaluation is capable
of raising the basic questions. It could be applied both in MAT and SAT. The
inquisitiveness may be tested both in the written and interview modes of
examination. For example, a situation described in piece of writing as paragraph
may be included in the questions-booklet and the examinee should be asked to
raise as many questions as possible within the stipulated time. In the process of
evaluation, the evaluator could see whether those questions were basic, reflecting
to the quest of mind or were superficial one. In interview schedule also the
inquisitiveness of mind could be tested by allowing the person to raise question
related to the situations provided to the examinee. The examinee should raise
situations based questions and the answer or counter questions be produced by
the members of the Board. This would help the examinees two ways. First, the
candidates’ inquisitive mind would be evaluated, and second, he/she would also
learn the contents and size of answer as well as skill to response. In short, this
method would provide opportunities both for testing inquisitiveness and learning
answers. Of course, this would need more rigorous effort from the interviewers
than the interviewee. The interviewer should be well read and trained in the use
of this methodology.
Another aspect of inquisitive mind is its contemplative nature. The candidate’s
ability to contemplate on the basic question/problem is the concern of evaluation.
But how to know whether one’s mind is contemplative one. For this sort of
exploring the contemplative nature of mind, for example, the evaluator can ask
questions, ‘Does he/she have any query in mind? Do these queries have any further
queries’? Do these queries constitute the fundamental problem/question? One may
also raise such questions as what does press his/her mind to think about? The
basic questions to explore the contemplation ability may be formulated on the
basis of response/interaction with the candidate. This however, is possible in the
interview schedule only.
It is also possible to explore contemplative mind through some other modes.
Such modes may include essay writing, paragraph writing, precise writing through
which it may be possible to explore what the candidate thinks. Whether mind is
argumentative in contemplative process is then the point to be searched. Although
Exploring the Dynamics of Talent and Significance in the State System
85
contemplation and imagination are sometimes interchangeably used, the meaning
and context of these two words differ. Contemplation is reasoning process
involving logic. In other words, it is argumentative process of mind which may
use its imaginative power as well to advance its argument. However, imagination
is the flight of mind .i.e. forming image out of the situations with or without
concrete reality. In other words the imagined being does not exist in concrete reality
when one is in the process of imagination.
Informative Mind
Another important aspect of exploring the talent is to see whether the mind is
informative one. Its purpose is to know whether the examinee has adequate and
proper information about anything raised before the candidate. One of the major
points to be covered in the system is to know about candidates’ power of
understanding, explanation, interpretation, examination and application,
orientation and aptitude. Besides testing the applicability of acquired information
based knowledge to solving the problems and other purposes as mentioned in
the NTS brochure, the following may be added to improve the evaluation process.
1. Testing the range of information and interest areas,
2. Testing the authenticity of information and its sources,
3. Retention capability and memory,
4. Testing the communicative skill and,
5. Testing the capability of analysis, comparison, criticism, judgment and
application.
Test of Intelligence
One of the above core areas of functioning of mind is intelligence. Intelligence is
the genetic response to the situations and problems. However,it reflects an over
all state of conditions of mind and, therefore, covers the test of the following major
areas:
i. Intuitive, imaginative and speculative mind,
ii. Receptive capability of mind,
iii. Quickness in receiving the problem and response to the problem,
iv. Testing the capability of judgment and its relevance and significance, and
v. Testing the ability to reduce the gap (space) between the problems and
their solutions in terms of times and methods.
Intelligence as an over all state of conditions of talent needs evaluated
within the above major points. Since we have given the resumed
perceptions of imagination and speculation in the preceding pages, it is
not desirable to repeat them. However, reflection on the content of
intuition requires a bit explanation. ‘Intuition is the power of the mind
by which it immediately perceives the truth of things without reason or
analysis. It is immediate knowledge in contrast with the mediate.’6 The
86
Journal of Social and Political Studies
intuitive mind is the ability of introspection and direct apprehension. In
fact, spirituality7 is the ground on which intuitive mind functions.
Test of Introspection—Ability
Searching the talent and its evaluation must consist of testing the introspection
ability. It is act of observing directly the process of one’s own mind; a view of the
inside or interior’8 self-Introspection ability consists of self cognition (i.e. cognition
of self capability), self awareness, self criticism and self evaluation. It implies the
test of inner vigilance and introspection of the self and its performance. It includes
the introspection of the goal, capability, performance, errors and mistakes as well
as will to correct and search the probability to improve.
In short, the National Talent Search Scheme should be designed to test the
aforesaid core areas of mind. Since, talent is total personality of a person, the test
scheme should be at least designed to examine, evaluate and measure the total
areas of mind and its perform ability.
Significance of Talent for the State
We assume that talent is the potential quality of a state. It is the fixture of statehood
and its quality. It may appear strange and unconventional to relate state with talent
and vice-versa. The relationship is, however, inherent and potent, and thus natural.
Since state is ‘writ large’ of individual, it possesses the same qualities the
individual possesses. From this perspective talent is the inherent qualities of
individuals and their social groups which compose state and make it strengthful
or fragile, in accordance with the placement of talent in the state system. We may
hold the assumptions of relationships otherwise as well. Aristotle’s perception of
state as prior to individual is of much relevance in the present context. State which
provides opportunities to individuals to magnify their ‘selves’ imply two things.
First, state, as supreme moral institution posseses all infrastructures to help
individuals grow and develop their potentials. State as such is supposed to be the
most talented institution, above individuals, their groups, society and all other
institutions, as it helps grow individuals their intrinsic talent and worth,
appropriate for themselves and the state as a whole. ‘State as collective talent’ is
superior to individuals and their groups, at least in the sense it understands the
basic questions and their solutions. This is how state and individuals are
interrelated by talents. Second, it is all impossible for individuals to develop
themselves without state. Individuals explore their potentialities and use them in
the state itself. One’s individuality is marked by the talent, one possesses and
explores within the state .i.e. ‘collective talent’. Consequently, individual in relation
to state explores and individualises potentiality and utilizes it within the state’s
collective purpose, albeit the talent personified individually remains inclusive for
itself.
Since, worth of a system is determined by the talent being used, it holds the
supreme significance for its worth while functioning. Thus, talent is supreme
Exploring the Dynamics of Talent and Significance in the State System
87
capability of state which can be used for the full expression of its ‘beings’ in the
process of ‘becoming’.
We can evaluate a system by talent—merit approach. If the approach is
adopted and followed properly, it may make a system qualitatively better. For
example in India’s case the systemic ideals mirrored in the constitution could be
achieved successfully. Sovereignty, democracy, socialism, secularism etc. may be
virtually functional in expression of their substantial and vital notions, provided
the notion of talent is well defined in its inherent, natural and inclusive meaning,
without any inhibitions in the process of policy framing, adopted and followed
accordingly. This depends on the placement of excellence in all sectors, viz, social,
economic and political. If we frame and adopt policies otherwise, it may create
division and degradation, unsuitable to healthy systemic rhythms. Problems that
have sprung in our system owe to inappropriate framing of talent concept and
its implementation at different levels. Reference in this is not a state other than
those which express themselves through democratic modes. Talent is not one
dimensional, but multi-dimensional. It is neither proto type, nor expresses in one
way but different ways. All people have talents in different forms required for
different situations. If talents of individuals by requirement of situations are
identified and used, the system may excel in performance. But the experiences
narrate otherwise. Democracy is malfunctioning, governance is at risk, socialism
is mortgaged, secularism is sacrificed and sovereignty is dechannelised, and state
as a whole is unable to identify and use its supreme capability. In short, talent is
par excellence, and its ignorance or abuse is the root cause of decay or decline of
the system and its governance. Perceptions that make policies victim to lust for
power upset the whole constitutional curriculum, to rule by mediocrity /mediocre
than by meritocracy. Right from school stage to higher education, and at all
competitive examinations, we find anomalies in the measurement and evaluation
system. The system is unable to identify and recognise the talent. Talent is
comprised of moral virtue, truthfulness, honesty, sociability, dutifulness,
contributory, respect to constitutionality, obedience to rule of law and above all,
humanity-endowed with love and spirituality which allow the mind to function
in excellence within its core areas, to know oneself, social self and total self .i.e.
including the state, environment/nature and the whole cosmos.
NOTES
1.
2.
3.
4.
This is a modified version of an article entitled “Selection of Talent at Secondary Stage :
Exploring the Probabilities for Improvement”, presented in a National Seminar-CumWorkshop for the Review of National Talent Search Scheme organized by the Department of
Educational Measurement and Evaluation, National Council of Educational Research and
Training, New Delhi.(from November 16 to 19, 2005).
See Brochure for National Talent Search Scheme, DEME, NCERT, New Delhi
The meaning of talent defined in the Chamber’s Dictionary is “any natural or special gift;
special aptitude; eminent ability’ etc. pp.1376. The present attempt endorses these.
For understanding the state of conditions of mind, Shree MADA BHAGAWAT GEETA
PROVIDES the deep rooted context for exploration. The Four VEDAS, contain the super
88
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
Journal of Social and Political Studies
consciousness contents, to relate them with consciousness with purity intact for a world to
live in, with happy and healthy life. In fact, the ancient Indian Super Classics, viz., VEDAS,
SHASHTRAS, and PURANAS are unparallel treasure of Knowledge and wisdoms ever
written in the history of mankind-the greatest sources of knowledge and truth useful in the
present context.
We suggest here at least two major classics to study with philosophical approach to derive the
meaning of mind within the broad frame work. These are Plato’s Republic and Kant’s
Critique of Pure Reason ; and Critique of Practical Reason.Besides, Decatese’ The Meditation
on First Philosophy, Heidegger’s Existence and being are also worthwhile reading and
illuminating.
see Chamber’s Dictionary,p.689
See chambers Dictionary pp.689-90
Spirituality is a combination of qualities, viz. simplicity, honesty, truthfulness, non-violence
which includes humanity, brotherhood, sociability, tolerance, respect to all religions,
constitutionality and rule of law embodied and promoted by state in the present context.
Unity of Mind, Peace and Harmony, Love and kindness to all beings etc. are the reflections
of spirituality .For, proper understanding of spirituality, we suggest to ponder in to VEDAS,
and GEETA, nevertheless the scriptures like PURANAS. To refer BUDDHA is of special
significance in the above context. Besides, the history of western philosophy in general and
Greek Philosophy in particular also contain the rich contents of spiritual discourse.
Chamber’s Dictionary, p. 689.
The Fifth and Sixth Schedule and Tribal Autonomy
89
The Fifth and Sixth Schedule and
Tribal Autonomy
Dr. Nisheeth Rai
ABSTRACT
The Tribes of India are one of the earliest populations in the land. India can proudly be
called the largest “tribal” population in the world. Today there are as many as 704 Tribes
(A.R. 2010, Tribal Ministry) across the country. The Tribals are considered the “sons of
the soil” and make for 8.2 per cent of the total population of India according to 2001
census. This interprets into 84 million people. In order to handle this large population
British government followed a policy of maintaining tribal culture and their distinct
identities. This policy resulted in the isolation of the tribals from the mainstream of Indian
life. After independence many approaches were proposed to face the question of the tribals.
These approaches may be broadly classified into Isolation, Assimilation, Planned assimilation
and Integration .Undoubtedly the Constituent Assembly chose the integration theory.
The term Scheduled Areas denotes the tribal regions to which either the Fifth Schedule
or the Sixth Schedule applies. The two Schedules have very different mechanisms for
governing their jurisdictional areas. However, the Fifth and Sixth Schedule has not helped
the tribal communities acquire the status and dignity of viable and responsive people’s bodies
.The tribes feel as much culturally deprived and economically robbed as under colonial
rule. The powers wield by the tribal communities are subject to a number of “exceptions
and modifications” ranging from general guidelines to specific demarcation of tribal
administrative authority. Tribal local governments are often ignored in development plans
and the benefits of any actual development rarely percolate down to the local tribes which
are subordinated to outsiders, both economically and culturally.
The Fifth and Sixth Schedule only marginally altered the power balance between state
governments and the tribes because of ineffectual participation by the former, and the general
tendency at the state level to monopolize power rather than share power with people at
large. It has debased the tribal traditions of self-governance. The abrupt shift from traditional
institutions to alien concepts of elected representatives and Panchayats has resulted in “very
low” tribal participation and an underutilization of the institutions.
Despite the increase in tribal violence, there has never been a serious debate about
alternative schemes for governing the tribal regions in India. Almost everybody presumes
that the fault lies not with the substantive content of the law, but with its implementation.
However, as I prove in this research paper, a major cause for the failure of governance in
the tribal areas is the top down approach of decentralization adopted in the Indian
Constitution. I therefore advocate a range of constitutional and statutory reforms that would
institutionalize tribal autonomy (the term that I employ to refer to a bottom-up approach)
and permit the tribes to maintain their individual identity while participating in national
development.
Introduction
The Tribes of India are one of the earliest populations in the land.1 India can
proudly be called as the largest “tribal” population in the world. Today there are
as many as 704 Tribes (A.R. 2010, Ministry of Tribal Affairs ) across the country.
The Tribals are considered as the “sons of the soil” and make for 8.2 per cent of
90
Journal of Social and Political Studies
the total population of India according to 2001 census. India’s population includes
nearly one hundred million tribal people.2 In order to handle this large population
two major approaches protection and development were followed.
During the colonial period the British government favoured isolation of the
tribal areas from the mainstream. The British set in motion a series of moves in
order to establish a degree of political and administrative dominance over the plains
as well as the hill people. The British policies and the activities of Christian
missionaries who came into the region contributed significantly in creating a freeze
effect on the communities and social formations. The impact of British
administration became manifest through various means and measures such as the
introduction of Inner Line Regulation in 1873 and the declaration of most of
the hill areas as “Excluded Areas” under the provision of Government of India
Act of 1935. Most tribal communities of the hills thus remained cut off from
social and political developments taking place elsewhere. Mention must also be
made of impressive population movements into the region during the British
period unleashed by the imperatives of colonial administration and economy. In
the context of an organised colonial economy with fairly strict monitoring of
exploitable resources, coupled with immigration of diverse groups in a short period
of time, the earlier resilience of the regional social system was lost forever. Each
community tended to become a rigid social formation and this was to the utmost
advantage of the colonial rulers. The accentuation of tribal-non-tribal differences
and the formation of rigid social blocks out of indigenous castes and communities
as well as recent migrants were important developments in the colonial period.
After independence many approaches were proposed to face the question of
the tribals. V. Elwin3 wanted a revivalist isolation policy to be adopted. His scheme
of “National parks” pleaded for the complete non-interference of the British rule
and its withdrawal from the tribal areas. In reaction to these conservative or
revivalist views, G.S. Ghurye,4 a senior sociologist, made a case for the complete
assimilation of tribals with the rest of the people in India. He said that it was
misleading to call the tribes aborigines as they were actually only backward Hindus
and the solution of all their problems cultural as well as economic and social, lay
in their complete assimilation into the Hindu society. In fact, the tribal folks have
distinct cultures and their complete assimilation with Hindus may not be possible
without disruption to their culture, customs, traditions etc. Tribal culture has many
happy and useful facets and the same must be preserved.
D.N. Majumdar5 opines that the best policy for tribes would be for their
controlled (planned) and limited assimilation. By limited assimilation he implied;
the need and desirability of preserving their useful institutions, customs, practices
etc. though these are to be tribal in origin and character. The transcultural
borrowing should be encouraged.The integrationist approach towards development
was laid down by Jawaharlal Nehru,6 the first Prime Minister of independent India
as follows: “We cannot allow matters to drift in the tribal areas or just not take interest
in them .... At the same time, we should avoid over-administering the areas and in
The Fifth and Sixth Schedule and Tribal Autonomy
91
particular, sending too many outsiders into their territory. It is in between the two
extreme positions we have to function.”7 In conformity with this thinking, the tribal
development policy in the country was formulated. The task of tribal development
has been defined as social and economic development of the tribal people.
According to L.P. Vidyarthi,8 historically tribal development in India was
viewed as (i) a movement emphasizing upon building up organizational structures,
(ii) a programme emphasizing on activities, (iii) a method emphasising on certain
achievable ends (iv) a process emphasising upon what happens to people not only
economically and socially but also, psychologically, and (v) institutionalization
of newly discovered skills and procedures leading to social change without
completely breaking away from the past.
The Constituent Assembly chose the integration theory. Accordingly, two
constitutional arrangements were made. Firstly, a state-wise list of tribes was drawn
and it was left to the Parliament to officially determine the list of the Scheduled
Tribes (STs) from time to time. Secondly, the provisions for the administration
and control of Scheduled Areas and Scheduled Tribes were made and were
incorporated in the Fifth and Sixth Schedules of the Constitution.
The Fifth and Sixth Schedules of the Constitution
The legal regime laid out in the 5th and 6th schedules has its origins in the Act of
1935, which created, excluded and partially excluded areas where a different set
of laws will govern the life of tribal people. Section 52 and 92 of the Act provided
for the reservation of certain predominantly aboriginal areas (to be known as
Excluded or Partially excluded areas) from operation of Provincial legislature. The
executive of authority of provinces extends to ‘excluded’ and partially excluded
areas therein’, but the administration of excluded areas is under the governor at
his discretion and partially excluded areas are administered by the ministers subject
to the special responsibility for their peace and good government imposed on the
governor by the section 52(e) of the Art. Thus the governor is given the power to
control the application of legislation whether of the Federal or Provincial
Legislature, and make regulations in both these areas.9
The term Scheduled Areas denotes the tribal regions to which either the Fifth
Schedule or the Sixth Schedule applies. The two Schedules have very different
mechanisms for governing their jurisdictional areas.
The Fifth Schedule10 is an entirely centralized system where the communities
the majority being tribal were directed in their affairs by provincial governors.
Scheduled Areas have certain distinct provisions meant to protect and benefit
tribals:
(a) The Governor of a State, which has Scheduled Areas, is empowered to
make regulations in respect of the following: i. Prohibit or restrict transfer
of land from tribals; ii. Regulate the business of money lending to the
members of Scheduled Tribes. In making any such regulation, the
92
Journal of Social and Political Studies
Governor may repeal or amend any Act of Parliament or of the Legislature
of the State, which is applicable to the area in question.
(b) The Governor may by public notification direct that any particular Act
of Parliament or of the Legislature of the State shall not apply to a
Scheduled Area or any part thereof in the State or shall apply to such
area subject to such exceptions and modifications as he may specify;
(c) The Governor of a State having Scheduled Areas therein, shall annually,
or whenever so required by the President of India, make a report to the
President regarding the administration of the Scheduled Areas in that State
and the executive power of the Union shall extend to the giving of
directions to the State as to the administration of the said area;
(d) Tribes Advisory Councils [TAC] shall be established in States having
Scheduled Areas. A TAC may also be established in any State having
Scheduled Tribes, but not Scheduled Areas, on the direction of the
President of India. The TAC should consist of not more than twenty
members of whom, as nearly as may be, three fourth should be from the
representatives of Scheduled Tribes in the Legislative Assembly of the
State. The role of TAC is to advise the State Government on matters
pertaining to the welfare and advancement of the Scheduled Tribes in
the State, as may be referred to it by the Governor;
(e) The Panchayat (Extension to Scheduled Areas) Act, 1996 (PESA), (as
per the recommendation of Bhuria Commission) the provisions of
Panchayats, contained in Part IX of the Constitution, were extended to
Scheduled Areas, also contains special provisions for the benefit of
Scheduled Tribes.11 The states were to ensure that (i) their laws comported
“with the customary law, social and religious practices and traditional
management practices of community resources,” and (ii) the Gram Sabhas
(bodies “consisting of persons whose names are included in the electoral
rolls for the Panchayat at the village level”) were “competent to safeguard
and preserve the traditions and customs of the people, their cultural
identity, community resources and the customary mode of dispute
resolution.”
In contrast, the Sixth Schedule12 of the Constitution of India under Article
244 makes provisions for the administration of tribal areas through Autonomous
District/ Regional Councils in the States of Assam, Meghalaya, Mizoram and
Tripura. The term “tribal areas” generally means areas with a preponderance of
tribal population. In other words, areas where provisions of Sixth Schedule are
applicable are known as “tribal areas”. In relation to these areas, Autonomous
District Councils, each having not more than thirty members, have been set up.
These Councils are elected bodies and have powers of legislation, administration
of justice apart from executive, developmental and financial responsibilities. The
District or Regional Councils are empowered to make rules with the approval of
the Governor with regard to matters like establishment, construction or
The Fifth and Sixth Schedule and Tribal Autonomy
93
management of primary schools, dispensaries, markets, cattle ponds, ferries,
fisheries, roads, road transport and water-ways in the district. The Autonomous
Councils of the North Cachar Hills and Karbi Anglong have been granted
additional powers to make laws with respect to other matters like secondary
education, agriculture, social security and social insurance, public health and
sanitation, minor irrigation etc. The Councils have also been conferred powers
under the Civil Procedure Code and Criminal Procedure Code for trial of certain
suits and offences, as also the powers of a revenue authority for their area for
collection of revenue and taxes and other powers for the regulation and
management of natural resources.
The Fifth and Sixth schedule, the Bhuria Committee Report and the PESA
Act of 1996 is an important step towards the realization of self-rule for tribal
people in India. These concerns resonate the demand for Tribal autonomy in the
sixth schedule areas in the Northeastern frontier regions of India. The Act of 1996
emphasized that “Traditional tribal conventions and laws should continue to hold
validity. Harmonisation with modern systems should be consistent herewith. The
committee felt that while shaping the new Panchayati Raj structure in tribal areas
it is desirable to blend the traditional with the modern by treating the traditional
institutions as the foundation on which the modern supra structure should be
built.”13
To what extent does this legal regime equip the tribal people to move towards
self-rule? What does self-rule mean when there are only few tribal people who
have not become what they are not, that is have not adopted non-tribal religions
and cultures? What part of their tradition remains that can harmonize with
modern systems? These are some of the questions which constitute the demerits
of the schedules.
Demerits of the Fifth and Sixth Schedule
To begin, The Fifth and Sixth Schedule only marginally altered the power balance
between state governments and the tribes because of ineffectual participation by
the former, and the general tendency at the state level to monopolize power rather
than share power with people at large. This apathetic attitude has manifested itself
in two forms. First, the majority of the states with tribal populations procrastinated
in their decentralization programs. Although all states with Scheduled Areas have
now enforced the Fifth and Sixth Schedule, their past slow performance has led
to the risk of delays in future amendments necessary to reflect changed
circumstances. Second, when they did legislate, the states either ignored tribal
customary law, social and religious practices and traditional management practices
of community resources or enacted incomplete laws. One such example is from
the Orissa Gram Panchayat (Amendment) Act of 1997 which conferred authority
on the larger Gram Sabha comprising all communities in a demarcated territory.14
As a result, the Orissa legislation disregarded the distinct socio-cultural practices
and different interests of the individual communities within that territory.
94
Journal of Social and Political Studies
Contrary to the Fifth and Sixth Schedule which guarantees that state laws
would respect tribal customs and traditions, they have debased the tribal traditions
of self-governance. The tendency to violate tribal norms is not only a product of
sub national apathy, but also the outcome of a statutory scheme that compels
the tribes to adopt non-tribal concepts. By promoting the system of local
government prescribed for non-tribal communities in Part IX of the Constitution,
the Indian Parliament has instantly abolished centuries-old systems of Indigenous
governance.
The abrupt shift from traditional institutions to alien concepts of elected
representatives and Panchayats has resulted in very low tribal participation and
an underutilization of the institutions. Thus, for example, the Lanjia Saoras, a
tribe in the state of Orissa, have been unable to adopt the electoral system of
government mandated by Part IX of the Constitution,15 as have the Santals.16
Similarly, the tribes in Madhya Pradesh that were asked to adopt the Panchayat
form of government have not seen “the importance of panchayat … for their own
welfare or societal development,”17 while in Gond and Bhil societies the Panchayat
system eroded the significance of traditional councils and strained ties within the
community.
A more understated reason for the tension between the customary and the
received is the entrenched perception in India that the tribes are primitive
communities with little or no order in society. Of course, such a view can only
be seen as a product of the dominant culture’s prejudice against, and ignorance
of, the culture of both settled and nomadic tribal peoples, particularly those
deemed ‘primitive’, since each of these groups, of course, has its own customs,
traditions and laws. The Manki-Munda system in the state of Jharkhand, for
instance, competes with state laws enacted to enforce PESA because the tribes
prefer their traditional law’s emphasis on collective and consensual decisionmaking.18
The Fifth and Sixth Schedule drafters mistakenly believed that an ambiguous
directive to the states to design their laws in consonance with such customary
law, social and religious practices and traditional management practices of
community resources would resolve the dichotomy. What they overlooked was
the inevitable displacement of indigenous laws and institutions that accompanies
the imposition of a non-native system of governance. The convergence of the
opinions of politicians, bureaucrats and federal and state administrations in a
decentralized paradigm has been shown to almost always result in high-discretion
laws which allow the executing agencies (the states) considerable freedom to decide
the fate of the target population (the tribes).
In India, decentralized governance in the tribal regions follows the traditional,
top-down approach of defining the political, administrative and fiscal powers of
a self-contained community, such as a tribe, with the expectation that the
empowered entity would function within the parameters (and towards the
objectives) envisioned by the retreating State. Therefore, the Indian model of tribal
The Fifth and Sixth Schedule and Tribal Autonomy
95
governance can hardly be considered devolved authority because even though there
has been a transfer of some degree of responsibility for governing, the activities
of the tribal governments are not substantially outside the direct control of central
government. These acts and schedule progressively denied tribal communities selfgovernment and rights to their community natural resources which is discussed
below.
The Tribal Rights in a Decentralized Government
Neither PESA in the last two decades, nor the Fifth and Sixth Schedule before it,
has helped the tribal communities acquire the status and dignity of viable and
responsive people’s bodies. The tribes feel as much culturally deprived and
economically robbed as under colonial rule. The powers wield by the tribal
communities are subject to a number of exceptions and modifications ranging
from general guidelines to specific demarcation of tribal administrative authority.
Tribal local governments are often ignored in development plans and the benefits
of any actual development rarely percolate down to the local tribes which are
“subordinated to outsiders, both economically and culturally.”19
The Fifth and Sixth Schedule have also not prevented large corporations from
gaining “control over the natural resources which constituted the life-support systems
of the tribal communities;”20 neither have they made the tribes prosperous from
the mineral-rich land on which they live. In fact, the tribes have “gradually lost
control over community resources such as forests to both settlers and the State”21 and
some scholar would go so far as to equate non-tribal acquisitions with tribal
displacement. Dishonesty and the active involvement of state employees with nontribal communities is another weakening factor reversing, in this case, the benefits
of land reform legislation. There are numerous cases of tribal lands in the northern
state of Uttar Pradesh which revealed a nexus between traditionally influential
non tribal landowners and corrupt government officials. The latter exercised their
discretionary powers to favour non-tribals by transferring lands over which tribal
communities may have had a valid claim.22 Even in a tribal majority state like
Jharkhand in the north, the tribes are the worst affected in the population since
the state government’s mining operations and hydroelectric power projects exploit
natural resources in the resource-rich tribal areas, thus making the tribes “outsiders
in their own land.”23
Faced with this onslaught, many tribes have resisted settlers, the government
and private enterprises, and sought to reassert their identity. For instance, in the
Bengal region the Kamatapur tribal movement has cited neglect, exploitation, and
discrimination, and demanded a separate state.24 Tribes in the neighbouring state
of Orissa have demanded a prohibition on private consortiums that intend to
mine bauxite from one of the most richly endowed regions in India.25 Similarly,
in the south, Kerala’s tribal population has recently begun to defend its rights by
banding together in various political groups at the state and local community levels
in order to compel the administration to review land alienation, poverty, and
96
Journal of Social and Political Studies
exploitation by private enterprises.26
It is far too easy to dismiss these incidents as mere consequences of misplaced
development strategies and lack of interest among state administrations. The critics
of tribal governance in India see the dangers in an extremely narrow compass,
criticizing provisions in the Fifth and Sixth Schedule as impracticable or the states
as legislatively ignorant.27 In sum, they believe that good civil administration alone
will lessen tribal woes and they have completely forgotten that in order to make
tribal local governments a true institutions of self-government, autonomous powers
should be exercised rather than devolved authority.
Tribal Autonomy: The Bottom-up Approach
The best way to help the tribal communities is to enhance their autonomy because
it will be an equity-facilitating step where the State accepts that its definition and
vision of what a community can (or should) achieve does not necessarily reflect
the aspirations of the tribal community. Hence, the State would encourage the
tribal community to develop indigenous political, administrative and fiscal
structures, with the conventional bureaucracy playing a support function. This is
a bottom-up approach where governance evolves from the members of the
community. An autonomous government is therefore anchored in a new deal
between the State and the tribes (with civil society as a mediator) to design
government according to tribal culture and tradition “Because of this legal character,
the life of an autonomous entity is not subject to simple administrative measures or
decisions made by a higher authority. It is in this sense that autonomy is more than
mere decentralization.” 28
Autonomy also ensures “a dramatic increase in tribes representation in the
political system and their participation in decision-making processes that affect their
own development.”29 The extant policies of decentralization should accordingly be
perceived only as the initial steps towards that ideal, offering avenues for
participation that can be cultivated into independent decision-making. In other
words, “autonomy lies at the end of a progression of rights that can be demanded
by “Indigenous communities to exercise meaningful internal self-determination and
control over their own affairs in a manner that is not inconsistent with the ultimate
sovereignty of the State.”30
A compelling reason for Indian government to embrace autonomous local
governments is the international acceptance of the tribes’ inherent right to
autonomy as a people. The International Labour Organization (ILO) Convention
169,31 which is the only binding international treaty dealing with Indigenous
peoples and land rights, replaced the ILO Convention 107 that had focused “on
the goal of integration and assimilation rather than on the protection of Indigenous
peoples lands, culture, and distinctiveness.”32 The ILO Convention 169 takes a
different approach by requiring State parties to the convention to respect the
cultures and institutions of Indigenous and tribal peoples, their right to continued
existence within their national societies, their right to establish their own
The Fifth and Sixth Schedule and Tribal Autonomy
97
institutions and to determine the path of their own development. ILO Convention
169 was therefore designed to reverse the integrationist policy.
The irony is that the values of tribal autonomy cherished in ILO Convention
169 were also initially the principles guiding independent India’s tribal policy.
Six decades ago, India’s first Prime Minister, Jawaharlal Nehru, espoused the
Panchasheel doctrine that the tribes could flourish and develop only if the State
interfered minimally and functioned chiefly as a support system.33 Some were
down the years, those values were lost and the very same bureaucratic stranglehold
that Nehru warned against.
In September 2007, India voted in favour of the United Nations Declaration
on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples (UN Declaration)34 which affirms various
rights to autonomy that are inherent in the tribal peoples of the world. The UN
Declaration, although not binding, has been variously described as an international
norm-building document that reflects the widespread agreement with respect to
Indigenous rights among many nations, and which, along with other
developments, can be seen as giving rise to a body of customary international
law on the subject. By supporting the UN Declaration India agreed that nations
must respect some form of autonomy for Indigenous people, but the vote was
conditioned on the fact that the UN Declaration recognizes “the right to internal
autonomy for tribal people and not the right to impair the territorial integrity of
sovereign and independent nations that India has so vigorously opposed”.35
Even so, the government’s acceptance of the right to internal autonomy for
the tribes under international law greatly strengthens the case for enhancing tribal
autonomy proposed in this paper. Securing property rights has been a key part
of modern Indigenous peoples’ movements around the world; yet the tribes in
India are regularly deprived of these rights. Also noted was the root of the problem
that the tribes have a legal rather than fundamental right to property under Indian
law, which has made it possible for the State to acquire tribal lands if it meets the
low threshold of having consulted or sought recommendations before doing so.
The most straightforward way of substituting ‘consent’ for ‘consultation’ is
to alter the balance of power between the states and the tribal local governments
by making property a fundamental right for the tribes as well. Even though states
can still acquire tribal community property by qualifying this right (as almost all
other fundamental rights are) and paying just compensation, the extent of police
powers would be significantly curtailed, since any state action interfering with
fundamental rights will be judicially reviewable for its effects and consequences
under the well established principles of the Indian Supreme Court. The mandate
for such a provision has been constitutionally given to Parliament, which can make
“any special provision for the advancement of … the Scheduled Tribes.” 36 If
recognized, the fundamental right would be one of many provisions securing tribal
interests: the Fifth and Sixth Schedules are examples, and so is Parliament’s ability
to legislatively restrict a citizen’s right to travel or reside in any part of India if
such law was for the protection of the interests of any Scheduled Tribe. Once
Journal of Social and Political Studies
98
property rights are secured, they must be sustained by a legal paradigm that
strengthens tribal autonomy. Tribal autonomy is not a challenge to India’s
sovereignty. Rather, in claiming the right to self-determination the Indigenous
communities are “seeking new ways of being recognized by national laws and systems
of decision making without losing their autonomy and their own values.”37
The basic unit of administration in an alternative structure should continue
to be a community that manages its affairs in accordance with shared traditions
and customs. There has never been an objection to the community as the
foundation for governance in tribal areas. On the contrary, the community is the
fundamental institution of all tribes whether settled or nomadic. At the grassroots,
the tribal community should be empowered to constitute a local government that,
for reasons given elsewhere, is based on traditional systems of government. The
revised Fifth and Sixth Schedule should also prescribe the method of determining
the hierarchically superior levels of tribal administration which may in many cases
lie entirely within a homogeneous tribe settled over a vast area. For example, the
Biar and Bhinjhal tribes of central India split their traditional governing bodies
into two tiers —one at the village level, and the other at the regional level.38 It is
also extremely important that the Fifth Schedule allow sufficient flexibility to
accommodate traditional governments that may not closely follow the
conventional division of authority between the legislative, executive and judicial
branches. Many tribes in peninsular India appoint traditional councils that act
both as executive and legislative bodies.
Conclusion
The introduction of the Fifth and Sixth schedule definitively signaled the Indian
Parliament’s intention to abandon command-and-control for “new governance”
in the tribal areas. However, by choosing decentralization the law-makers made
the mistake of matching the right idea with the wrong solution. Although
decentralization has proven vital whenever national or provincial governments have
desired local solutions for local problems, the system is obviously unsuitable for
tribal governance. Instead, the right solution is some form of autonomous tribal
government grounded in the Indian Constitution and supported by the
conventional administration and civil society. In this paper, I provided one such
arrangement. Autonomy is preferable to decentralization because while the
decisions of the decentralized organs may be replaced by the state; the decisions
of autonomous organs may be canceled but not definitively replaced.” In other
words, what I have proposed is “freedom within the law” for almost one hundred
million tribal people. This is certainly achievable, and the legal change would be
a highly effective way of transforming ideology to create a sense of entitlement
amongst the tribes.
NOTES
1.
Kumar S, Padmanabham PB, Ravuri RR, Uttaravalli K, Koneru P, Mukherjee PA, Das B,
Kotal M, Xaviour D, Saheb SY, Rao VR. 2008, The earliest settlers’ antiquity and
The Fifth and Sixth Schedule and Tribal Autonomy
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
23.
24.
25.
99
evolutionary history of Indian populations: evidence from M2 mtDNA lineage. BMC Evol
Biol, 8.
The 2001 Government of India Census recorded 8.2 per cent of India’s population as tribal.
Elwin, Verrier. The Baiga. Gyan Publishing House (Indian Edition): Delhi. 1938.
Ghurye G S. 1943.The Aborgines so called and their Future. Popular Press, Bombay 1943.
Majumdar, D.N. Races and Cultures of India. Asian Publishing House:Bombay. 1958.
Foreword to the second edition of Elwin, Verrier. Myths of the North-East Frontier of India.
North-East Frontier Agency: Shillong. 1968.
Foreword to the second edition of Elwin, Verrier. Myths of the North-East Frontier of India.
North-East Frontier Agency: Shillong. 1968.
Vidyarthi L.P., Tribal Development and its Administration, Concept publishing Company,
New Delhi, 1981.
http://www.legislation.gov.uk/ukpga/Geo5and1Edw8/26/2/enacted.10/10/2011
Schedule V in The Constitution of India, 1950.
Constitution of India, 1950, Art. 243-M(3A)(b), allows “Parliament ... [to] extend the
provisions of this Part [IX] to the Scheduled Areas subject to such exceptions and
modifications as may be specified in such law.”
See Schedule VI in The Constitution of India, 1950.
http://www.odi.org.uk/work/projects/00-03-livelihood
options/forum/schedareas/about/
bhuria_report.htm 10/10/2011
Avinash Samal, “Institutional Reforms for Decentralized Governance and the Politics of
Control and Management of Local Natural Resources: A Study in the Scheduled Areas of
India” (paper presented to the RCSD Conference, Chiang Mai, Thailand, 11–14 July 2003)
[unpublished], online: Digital Library of the Commons <http://dlc.dlib.indiana.edu/archive/
00001084/00/Avinish_Samal.pdf>
Nityananda Das, “The Tribal Situation in Orissa” in K. Suresh Singh, ed., The Tribal
Situation in India (Shimla: Indian Institute of Advanced Study, 2002).
Ibid.
S.N. Chaudhary, “Tribal Leadership in Panchayats: A Study of their Profile, Performance and
Plan”in D.C. Sah and Yatindra Singh Sisodia, eds., Tribal Issues in India (New Delhi: Rawat
Publications, 2004) at 117.
Bhubneshwar Sawaiyan, An Overview of the Fifth Schedule and the Provisions of the Panchayat
(Extension to the Scheduled Areas) Act, 1996 (Commonwealth Policy Studies Unit, 2002) at 45, online: Commonwealth Policy Studies Unit <http://www.cpsu.org.uk/downloads/
Bhubnesh.pdf>.
Govinda Chandra Rath, Introduction in Govinda Chandra Rath, ed., Tribal Development in
India: The Contemporary Debate (New Delhi: Sage Publications, 2006).
Ibid.
R.K. Barik, “Faulty Planning in a Tribal Region: The Dandakaranya Development
Authority” in Govinda Chandra Rath, ed., Tribal Development in India—The Contemporary
Debate (New Delhi: Sage Publications, 2006).
Kripa Shankar, “Land Alienation among Tribals in Uttar Pradesh” in Govinda Chandra Rath,
ed., Tribal Development in India—The Contemporary Debate (New Delhi: Sage
Publications, 2006).
Sajal Basu, “Ethno-regionalism and Tribal Development: Problems and Challenges in
Jharkhand” in Govinda Chandra Rath, ed., Tribal Development in India—The Contemporary
Debate (New Delhi: Sage Publications, 2006).
I. Sarkar, “The Kamatapur Movement: Towards a Separate State in North Bengal” in
Govinda Chandra Rat, ed., Tribal Development in India—The Contemporary Debate (New
Delhi: Sage Publications, 2006).
Orissa’s Kashipur Alumina Project Rekindles Tribal Wrath” Down to Earth (25 February
100
Journal of Social and Political Studies
2007), online: Down to Earth <http://www.downtoearth.org.in/full6.asp.10/10/2011
26. Jos Chathukulam and M.S. John, “Issues in Tribal Development: The Recent Experience of
Kerala” in Govinda Chandra Rath, ed., Tribal Development in India—The Contemporary
Debate (New Delhi: Sage Publications, 2006).
27. Impracticality of provisions is asserted even by the Draft National Tribal Policy. See
India,Ministry of Tribal Affairs, Draft National Tribal Policy (New Delhi: Government of
India, 2006).
28. Deborah J. Yashar, “Democracy, Indigenous Movements, and the Postliberal Challenge in
Latin America” (1999) 52 World Pol. 76.
29. Hector Diaz Polanco, Indigenous Peoples in Latin America: The Quest for Self-Determination,
trans. by Lucia Rayas (Colorado: Westview Press, 1997).
30. Tomasz Branka, “Autonomy—Old Concept, New Tasks” in Current Issues of the International
Politics through the Eyes of Young Europeans (Prague: University of Economics, 2005) .
31. Convention Concerning Indigenous and Tribal Peoples in Independent Countries, 27 June
1989, 28 I.L.M. 1384 (entered into force 5 September 1991) (ILO Convention 169).
32. Marcos A. Orellana, Mining, Minerals & Sustainable Dev., Indigenous Peoples, Mining, and
International Law (International Institute for Environment and Development, 2002) ,online:
International Institute for Environment and Development <http://www.iied.org/mmsd/
mmsd_pdfs/002_orellana_eng.pdf>.10/10/11
33. Jose George and S.S. Sreekumar, Tribal Development Legislation and Enforcement (New Delhi:
Commonwealth Publishers, 1994).
34. Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples, GA Res. 61/295, UNGAOR, 61st Sess.,
UNDoc. A/RES/47/1 (2007).
35. http://www.un.org/News/Press/docs/2007/ga10612.doc.htm.10/10/2011
36. Constitution of India, Art. 15(4) 1950.
37. http://www.forestpeoples.org/documents/law_hr/fpic_ips_text_only_aug04_eng.pdf>.10/10/
2011
38. K.S. Singh, The Scheduled Tribes (New Delhi: The Anthropological Survey of India, 1994).
Constitutional Structure, Mechanism and Working of Federalism in India 101
Constitutional Structure, Mechanism and
Working of Federalism in India
H.M. Jain
India is a Union of States. At present there are 28 States and 7 Territories forming
part of the Union. The States and the territories thereof are as specified in the
First Schedule.
Parliament may by law admit into the union, or establish, new states on such
terms and conditions as it thinks fit.1
This necessarily involves changes in the First Schedule requiring a
constitutional amendment. However, the Constitution Clarifies that any such law
can be passed by the ordinary process of law making and will not attract the
provision of Art. 368.
Historically, it was the Government of India Act. 1935 which first conceived
of a federal polity for India. It envisaged a federation of provinces and princely
states the former under direct British rule and the latter under British Suzerainty
then.
After the transfer of power in 1947, the Constitution Assembly resolved to
constitute India into a federation of provinces and princely States joining the
Indian Union.
It is noteworthy that the Indian Union is not the creation of any voluntary
compact among any pre- existing States. In the USA, Switzerland, Australia the
federation rose from below; the federating entities met and decided to form a
federal Union.
In the case of India it was the opposite. The Government of India Act, 1935
decided upon a federal system “by creating autonomous units and combining them
into a federation by one and the same Act”.
In the same way the Constitution Assembly of India set up a federal system
by placing the provinces in a federal union and associating the princely States
with them, placing them all on the same footing.
The States did not exist prior to the Constitution except as administrative
divisions of unitary state. They did not have any rights of their own part from
those delegated to them by the Central Authority.
Therefore the states cannot any in violability as regards their territory,
boundary, area or even name. Parliament is empowered by ordinary legislative
process to—
(a) Form a new State by separation of territory from any States or by uniting
two or more states or part of states or by uniting any territory to part of
any State:
102
Journal of Social and Political Studies
(b) Increase or diminish the area of any State:
(c) Alter the boundaries or name of my State.
The states have no say in the matter except that if the proposed Bill affects
the area, boundaries or name of any State, the bill is referred to the legislature or
that State for expressing its opinion thereon within specified period.
Whatever be the mode of formation of the Union and regardless of its plenary
power in respect of reorganization of States, structurally India is a Union of States.
It was argued in the Constituent Assembly that the word Union denotes that
the States will have no power to secede from the Union. It is doubtful if the word
Union has any such connotation. The former USSR granted the right of secession
to the constituent Republics even though they formed Union. Ultimately secession
is not a matter legal of right but of popular will. In the same way the union
depends on political will and popular support.
The position of the States under the Indian Constitution can be summed up
as follows:
(1) The Constitution does not grant to any State the right of secession. The
insurgency in Kashmir should be seen in this light. No pledge or promise
on plebiscite made by Prime Minister Nehru or his Government can stand
if it is not supported or sanctioned by the Constitution.
(2) The States do not have any a priori rights, but only such rights as have
been expressly granted to them by the constitution. Even the residuary
rights vest in the Union Government. In the concurrent field of powers
it is the union law which prevails over a state law in the event of a conflict
between the two.
(3) There is a single Constitution both for the Union and the States. The
States do not have the right to have a separate constitution of their own,
with the single exception of the State of Jammu & Kashmir. Part VI of
the Constitution provides a framework for the Government of the States.
(4) There is a single unified judiciary for the whole country and an integrated
Civil Service under the supervision and control of the All India Services.
(5) There is single Citizenship for the people of the country and no separate
Citizenship for the people of any State, not even for those living in Jammu
& Kashmir.
(6) The Governor of States are appointed by the Union Government and
besides being the constitutional head of the States, are also the agent of
the Centre in the State.
(7) The Constitution guarantees individual rights of certain groups, such as
scheduled castes, scheduled tribes and minorities, but not of States as such.
It does not concede even the right of equal representation to the States
in the Upper House of the Federal Parliament. The Constitution requires
the union:—
(i) To protect every State against external aggression and internal
disturbance and
Constitutional Structure, Mechanism and Working of Federalism in India 103
(ii) To ensure that the government of every State is carried on in
accordance with the provision of the Constitution.
The Constitution is in the nature of a covenant among the people as such
and the States are the creation of this Constitution. The Constitution therefore
guarantee individual rights and freedoms and singles out the minorities for double
protection, first under provisions of general rights and freedoms (Arts. 14, 19,
20-23) and again under special provisions relating to freedom of religion and
cultural and educational rights. In this way the Indian Constitution still adheres
in respect of the minorities to the long discredited principle of equal but separate.3
It is questionable whether recognition of minorities as separate entities and subjects
of rights and freedoms will serve and advance the objective of national integration
and secularism.
Growth of the Union
The constitution as it emerged in 1949 from the Constituent Assembly made
India a Union in which there were to be four categories of States, named simply
as A, B, C and D with 9, 8 and 10 States in the first three categories and one in
the last, a total of 27 States and territories.
There has been a constant process of reorganization, bifurcation and creation
of States making the Union more compact and its divisions more rational.
The first case of creation of a new States was that of Andhra Pradesh which
was carved out of the States of Madras by separating the Telugu speaking areas
to form the new State in 1953. Madras was re-named Tamil Nadu in 1968.
A major recognition of States on linguistic basis took place in 1956. As result,
the first three categories of State were grouped in to one so that there remained
only States and Union Territories, 15 of the former and 9 of the latter.
Subsequent changes have been taken place as result of—
(a) Bifurcation or even multiple division of the existing States to form new
ones.4
(b) Liberation of former Portuguese and French Possessions and their
Admission to the Union of India.5
(c) Accession of Sikkim to the Indian Union.6
(d) Raising some of the union Territories to full Statehood.7
(e) Re-naming some of the States in deference to local sentiments and usage.8
The territorial evolution of the Indian Union since the inception of the
Constitution has been shown in the following tables:
States of the Indian Union as originally stipulated in the Constitution in 1949.
Part A State
Part B States
Part C States
Part D Territories
Assam
Bihar
Bombay
Madhya Pradesh
Madras
Hyderabad
Jammu & Kashmir
Madhya Bharat
Mysore
Ajmer
Bhopal
Bilaspur
Andaman & Nicobar
Islands
Pepsu
Coorg
Journal of Social and Political Studies
104
Part A State
Orissa
Punjab
Uttar Pradesh
West Bengal
Part B States
Part C States
Rajasthan
Saurastra
Cochin
Manipur
Travancore
Part D Territories
Delhi
Himanchal Pradesh
Kutch
Tripura
Vindhya Pradesh
After the States Reorganization in 1956
States
Union Territories
Assam
Andhra Pradesh
Bihar
Bombay
Kerala
Madhya Pradesh
Madras
Mysore
Orissa
Punjab
Rajasthan
Uttar Pradesh
West Bengal
Jammu & Kashmir
Andaman & Nicobar Islands
Delhi
Himachal Pradesh
Laccadive, Minicoy &
Andmindivi Islands
Manipur
Tripura
Changes after 1956
Year
State divided
State/UT
Created
UT raised to
Statehood
Acquire Territory
incorporated in to the
Union
1960
Gujarat
Himachal
Pradesh (1970)
Goa, Daman Diu,
1961
1962
Bombay
(Renamed
Maharashtra)
Assam
Nagaland
Meghalaya
(1971)
Dadra & Nagar
Haveli, 1961
1966
Punjab
1969
Assam
Manipur (1971)
Pondicherry, 1962
1971
Assam
Tripura (1971)
Sikkim, 1975
2000
2000
2000
Madhya Pradesh
Uttar Pradesh
Bihar
Haryana
Chandigarh (UT)
Meghalaya
Sub-State
Mizoram (UT)
Arunachal
Pradesh (UT)
Chhattisgarh
Uttaranchal
Jharkhand
Mizoram (1986)
Arunachal Pradesh (1986)
Goa (1987)
States Participation in Constitutional Amendment
The Indian Constitution is not covenant among the states. Rather the States are
the creation of the Constitution and subsequently of the parliament. The States
therefore do not have the right to share in the process of the amendment of the
Constitution, except that a constitutional amendment requires ratification by one
Constitutional Structure, Mechanism and Working of Federalism in India 105
half of the state legislatures if the amendment affects the powers and jurisdiction
of the states, such as the scale of representation in the Electoral College or in the
parliament or the Items of the three List in the VII Schedule, or the provisions
relating to the Supreme Court and the High Court, or the extent of executive
power of the Union and the States:
In any case, the states cannot initiate the move for any constitutional
amendment.
Of the 78 Amendments adopted till 1995, only thirty required ratification
by state legislature in accordance with the proviso to Art. 368.9
Art. 368 requires a Constitutional amendment bill to be passed by both the
Houses of Parliament by the requisite majority. The defeat of the measure in either
house means that it can make no further headway and must be dropped.
The requirement of ratification by one half of the state legislatures in respect
of amendment of specified parts of the constitution is an additional meaningful
check on the parliament’s constitutive authority.
There is however one item of constitutional amendment which the
Constitution leaves to the initiative of the State legislatures, ands that is the creation
or abolition of second chamber in the state legislatures.
The legislative Council in Andhra Pradesh, Tamil Nadu, West Bengal and
Punjab was abolished by acts of Parliament following the adoption of a Resolution
by the legislature of the state.
In Andhra Pradesh the legislative Council was first created in 1957 and then
abolished in1985 by this process.
In the Golaknath case (1967) the Supreme Court by a strange logic reached
the conclusion that Parliament by way of constitutional amendment could take
away or abridge a fundamental rights conferred by Part III of constitution. This
decision was later set aside twenty fourth amendments but in the Keshvanand
Bhatrti case (1973) the Supreme Court hit back with more sweeping more
limitations on parliament’s Constitutive Authority as to impair its basic structure
or any essential feature thereof. It reserved the right to determine the validity of a
constitutional amendment on this touchstone from case to case, without specifying
in advance the basic structure or its essential features.
With the invention of the Basic Structure theory the Supreme Court moved
towards what an American writer has said in the American context, Imperial
Judiciary.10
‘The basic structure theory has the effect of freezing the status quo and
converting the Constitution into a prison house for both the Union and the States
from which there can be no escape.’
This is strikingly reminiscent of Hobbesian social Contract wherein people
having surrendered their powers to an all powerful Leviathan are not free to change
the terms of the Contract (the Constitution) or withdraw from it except by means
of civil revolution.
106
Journal of Social and Political Studies
Dual Polity
Introducing the Draft Constitution in the Constituent Assembly Dr. Ambedkar
said that in as much as the draft establishes dual polity it may be called federal.
The 73rd and the 74th Amendments which have introduced Part IX and IXA
respectively in the constitution have given constitutional status to local bodies,
both urban and rural, but character of the polity remains unaltered.
Local Government Panchayats & Municipalities:
Part IX of the Constitution outlines the framework of institutions of
rural self government, part IXA gives the framework of urban local
government.
Part IX envisages a three tier system of panchayat for rural areas: namely,
(a) the village Panchyats, (b) the District Panchayant, and (c) the
Intermediate Panchayat standing between the village and district
panchayats.
Three types of institutions of local self government have been provided for
the urban areas namely,
(a) Nagar Panchayat, for a transitional area i.e. an area which is being
transformed from a rural area to an urban area.
(b) Municipal Council, for a smaller urban area;
(c) Municipal Corporation for a larger urban area
It is obligatory for every State to constitute such units.
The local Government remains an exclusive State subject. The 73rd and the
74th Amendments have outlined the scheme which would be implemented by
the several States by making laws or by amending their own existing laws to bring
them in conformity with these Amendments.
The Constitution provides for direct election of local bodies every five years.
The other notable provisions are:
(i) Reservation of seats for women and for scheduled castes and tribes.
(ii) A State Election Commission to conduct election.
(iii) A state Finance Commission to ensure financial viability of these
institutions.
(iv) Devolution of powers and responsibilities to the local with respect to:
(a) Preparation of plans and implementation of schemes for economic
development and social justice.
(b) Subjects listed in the XIth schedule for the Panchayat in the XIIth
schedule for the Municipalties.13
(c) Devolution of financial powers to the local bodies.14
Prime Minister Vajpayee had promised to bring a constitutional amendment
in the winter session of Parliament to give more administrative and financial
powers to the pachaayat.15
It should not be supposed that these constitutional measures have attempted
anything like division of powers and financial resources between the states and
Constitutional Structure, Mechanism and Working of Federalism in India 107
the local bodies.16 Their impact is only devolution of powers and responsibilities
from the States to the local bodies, not their division between the two.
Therefore the two-tier federal polity remains intact unaffected.
Division of Powers
In his speech to the Constituent Assembly during the third meeting Dr Ambedkar
said “The chief mark of federalism…. Lies in the partition of the legislative and
executive authority between the Centre and the Units by the Constitution. This
is the principle embodied in our costitution.17
The States derive their powers, including fiscal powers, directly from the
Constitution. They are not dependent on the Centre for their legislative or
executive authority.
The result is that:—
(1) It will not be possible for the Union or a State to assume powers which
are assigned by the Constitution to the other Government, unless such
assumption is sanctioned by some provision of the Constitution itself.
(2) Nor would such usurpation or encroachment be valid by consent of the
other party, for the Constitution itself provides the cases in which this is
permissible consent (e.g. Arts.252, 258).
(3) Nor would this be possible by delegation of powers by one legislature in
favor of another.
“Hence the Constitution would not permit any of the units of the federation
to subvert the federal structure set up by the Constitution, even by consent.18
The Constitution elaborates in detail the legislative and administrative
relations of the Union and States, and the distribution of Revenues between
them.19 It has been noted by the most writers that the constitution tiites in favour
of the Centre in the matter of distribution of powers and resources.
The reason is that constitution making in India (1947-49) was preceded by
a phase of violent communal politics which succeeded in partitioning the country.
The partition and the influx of millions of refugees from Pakistan created problems
of relief and rehabilitation. Besides, there were colossal problems of social and
economic planning and development to be tackled if the tryst with destiny was
to be kept. The historical background of disunity inviting foreign invasions and
fissiparous tendencies inherent in Indian history, sociology and politics alike urged
the need for a strong Centre.20
The outcome was that the Union was invested with “too large a field for the
operation of its legislative and executive authority than is to be found in any other
federal constitution.21 This would be evident from the following facts and features.
(1) Of the three Lists of powers the Union has the exclusive powers to legislate
on 97 subjects of the union List, and concurrent power to legislate on
the 47 concurrent Lists.
108
Journal of Social and Political Studies
(2) It shares with the States the power to legislate on subjects of concurrent
List but it is provided that the Union law will have priority over any State
law in the event of a conflict between the two.
Santhanam expressed the view that “As there is continuous pressure on
parliament to legislate on almost every item in the Concurrent List, it is
not unlikely that , before long, the Concurrent List will , in Practice,
become a continuation of the Federal List.22
(3) The Residuary powers as in Canada and unlike USA and Switzerland
have been vested in the Union. K. Santaanam comments inter alia, “the
residuary powers are vested in the Centre. Though this may be deemed
to be proof of the dominant role of the centre in the Indian Federal
system, the fact that all the important matters have been brought into
three lists makes it more or less a nominal provision.23
(4) The Union Parliament may make laws on subjects contained in the State
List.
(i) if the Rajya Sabha by a Resolution passed by not less than two thirds
of members present and voting declares that it is expedient or
necessary in the national interest to do so (Art.249).
(ii) If a proclamation of national Emergency is in operation (Art.250)
(iii) Parliament may legislate for two or more States on subjects of State
list. If the legislatures of those States pass resolutions to that effect
(Art.252)
(iv) To give effect to any treaty, arrangement or convention with any other
country or any decision made at international conference association
or other body, (Art253).
In this way the Union may encroach upon legislative field of the States in
the specified circumstances.
Dr. Ambedkar justified these cases of central encroachment “as a new way to
overcome rigidity and legalism inherent in federalism.”24
The powers of union are such as to enable the Indian State to fulfill its basic
obligation of (a) safeguarding the unity and integrity of nation, (b) ensuring
economic development and growth, (c) adoption of measures of social reform
(d) promotion of higher education, Science and Technology, (e) fostering social
security and welfare of labour, and (f) advancement of trade, commerce industries,
agriculture, banking etc.
This is why all subjects of national importance or subjects requiring
uniformity of the treatment throughout the country are included in the Union
List. These include; Defence, Foreign Affairs; Citizens, Railways, Posts and
telegraphs; telephones, wireless and other like means of communication, currency,
coinage and foreign exchange. Inter State Trade & Commerce, Banking, Insurance,
Patents & Inventions, standard of weights & Measures, Industries; oilfield and
mines, census; the higher judiciary.
The Concurrent List contains items which enables the Union to undertake
Constitutional Structure, Mechanism and Working of Federalism in India 109
measures of social reform and economic planning and growth:
These include:
Criminal law and procedure and Civil procedure, Marriage & Divorce,
Adoption, succession, Forests, protection of wild animals and birds: Adulteration
of foodstuffs and other goods, Economic and social planning: Trade Unions; Social
security; Employment and unemployment; Welfare of Labour, Education Weights
and measures ; price control, factories Electricity, Acquisition and Requisitioning
of property.
The general principle behind these items is that parliament can initiate on
matters in which central initiative considered necessary to secure nation wide
uniformity or to guide and encourage State efforts.25
The subjects which by their very nature require variation in treatment so as
to suit local conditions and circumstances have been placed in the State List.
The State legislature has the exclusive power to make laws for any subject
contained in the State List. This is however subject to two limitations.
The State law must not be repugnant to any provision of law made by
parliament which Parliament is competent to make.
In the event of a repugnancy between the two, the law made by Parliament
shall prevail and the State law, to the extent of repugnancy, shall be void.
In means that the State legislation is put in a subordinate position in its own
or in the Concurrent field.
Sir Ivor Jennings pointed out that Art. 254 which provides for the supremacy
of the union law, cannot be restricted in its application to subjects in the
concurrent list alone.26
In fact not such restriction can be inferred from the plain language of Art.
254.
(2) Every bill passed by the Legislature has to be sent to the Governor for
his assent and the Governor, among the various courses open to him opt to reserve
it for the consideration of the President.
It is not clear whether he can do so on his own or on the advice of the Chief
Minister.
Bam Kishore Vyas former Speaker of Rajasthan Legislative Assembly, disclosed
that “it is not unusual for State Government to advise the Governors to reserve
State Bills for the assent of the President as a precaution against possible conflict
with central legislation.27
The Administrative Reforms Commission Study Team on Centre- State
Relations was of opinion that “the Governor could exercise his own judgment, in
case he feels and his cabinet does not, that unconstitutional or serious impropriety
is involved.”28
It is notable that besides leaving it to the Governor to reserve to any bill passed
by the State legislature for consideration by the President, the constitution specifies
110
Journal of Social and Political Studies
that the Governor has not choice but to reserve the bill for President’s
consideration.
(i) If in his opinion the Bill is derogatory to the powers and position of High
Court.
(ii) Where the bill provides for the acquisition by the State of any State or
of any rights or for therein or the extinguishment or modification of any
such rights or for taking over of the management of any property by the
state, or for the amalgamation of two or more corporations, or affects
corporate rights mentioned in Art. 31 A.
(iii) Where a State law provides for imposition of tax in respect of water or
electricity generated, distribute, or sold by any authority established by
any law made by parliament for regulating or developing any inter State
or river valley.
The wide powers given the Union under List I and III and limited powers
given to the States in List II must not be seen in terms of ‘either-or-federalism’29
of the past, which rested on a dichotomy between the Centre and the States. The
two should no longer be seen as competing centres of power but as co-partners
in the task of nation building.
This may be illustrated by reference to Item 24 of the State List. It reads:
Industries subject to the provisions of entries 7 and 52 of the Union List.
Entry 7 of the Union List reads: Industries declared by Parliament by law to
be necessary for the purpose of defence or for the prosecution of war.
Entry 52 reads: Industries, the control of which by the Union is declared by
Parliament by law to be expedient in the Public interest.
The Union Power to legislate in respect of industries, the control of which is
deemed to be in the public interest, has been an avenue for increasing Central
control over industrial development. The Union Government had by 1974
extended its control over all industries with a fixed capital of Rs. 25 lakhs and
over.
Administrative Relations
The primacy of the Union over the States in legislative fields is seen in the
administrative relations as well. The basic premise is that the executive power is
co-extensive with legislative power. Therefore the executive powers of the Union
extend to matters contained in the Union List while the executive power of the
States applies to matters contained in the State list and the Concurrent List.
The Constitution directs that the executive power of every State will be so
exercised as to ensure compliance with, and, not to impede or prejudice, the
exercise of executive power of the Union, and the Union Shall have the power to
give such directions to State as may appear to it to be necessary for the purpose.30
The Union will have the power to issue directions to a State as to:
(i) The construction and maintenance of means of communication declared
in the direction to be of national or military importance.
Constitutional Structure, Mechanism and Working of Federalism in India 111
(ii) The measures to be taken for the protection of the railway within the
State.
The president, with the consent of the State Government, may entrust to
the Government or its officers functions in relation to may matter falling within
the domain of federal Executive.
A law made by Parliament which applies in any State, may confer powers
and impose duties upon the State or its officers and authorities, for instance, the
power of subordinate legislation.
The Governor of a State may also, with the consent of the Government of
India, entrust to it functions in relation to any matter within the executive power
of the State.
When a proclamation of Emergency is in operation, then the Union Executive
is empowered to give directions to any State as to the manner in which the
executive power there of is to be exercised.
There are two other institutional arrangements whereby the Union may
exercise superintendance, direction and control over the State administration:
(1) The head of the State Executive is the Governor who is appointed by
the President.
The Governor holds office during the pleasure of the President, though,
ordinarly, for five years.31
The governor acts not merely as the constitutional head of State but also as
the agent of he Centre, as the eyes and ears of the Centre in the State.
The Union Government may bring a State under the President rule
(pseudonym for Centre) under Art. 356, if it is satisfied on its own or on receipt
of a Report from the Governor of the State that the government of the State
“cannot be carried on in accordance with the provisions of the Constitution”.
In such a situation powers and functions of Government of the State are
assumed by the Union Government.
Art. 356 is the reserve power of the Centre to dismiss any State Government
which is politically unacceptable to it, besides providing a way out where no
political party or coalition of parties is able to command majority support in the
Legislature.
Most of the cases of imposition of President’s rule in the States relate to solving
the impasse created by a lack of a party or party coalition in the Assembly to
support and sustain government.
There have however been cases where:
(1) the ruling party has resorted to a temporary spell of President’s rule in
order to regroup its supporters and return to power (Rajasthan 1967)
(2) the ruling party at the Centre has abused its power to get ride of its
political opponents ruling in the states. (Kerala 1959), U.P. Madhya
Pradesh, Himachal Pradesh, Rajasthan, (1992).
112
Journal of Social and Political Studies
(3) the ruling party at the Centre riding on the wave of popular support has
sought to wipe out the opposition ruled states en masse (1977, 1980)
the party in power having failed to win a single seat in the Lok Sabha
polls.
(4) the President’s rule has been imposed a stop-gap arrangement to enable
a fresh election of the Assembly, which has not taken place before the
expiry of its term. (Tripura, 1993).
(5) the law and order situation in the state was not conducive to the holding
elections (Punjab 1983) due to internal disturbances.
(6) to stall the opposition from staking a claim to power where the party
favoured by the Centre:
(i) had not been returned with a majority in the elections.
(ii) had been reduced to a minority due to floor crossings.
(iii) had no chance of forming the government on the collapse of the
existing one. (Orissa, 1973, Nagaland Aug. 1988 U.P. Oct. 1995,
Gujarat Sep. 1996).
For these reasons the regional parties, and the several Janata brand parties
seem Art. 356 a negation of the federal principle but they can not bring themselves
upto demanding its deletion from the Constitution for they see in it a potential
weapon for a possible use against use a BJP Government or a BJP led formation.
Another institutional device to secure the superintendence, direction and
control of the State administrative apparatus by the Union is the superimposition
of the All India Services, the IAS and IPS on the corresponding State Services,
the Provincial Civil Services and the provincial Police Service.
Dr. Ambedkar claimed that a special feature of the Indian Federation is the
conscious arrangement made to avoid diversity in the civil and criminal laws, in
judicial administration and in civil administration. This will ensure that Indian
federal system will have uniformity in all matters which are essential to maintain
the unity of the country. The means adopted to secure this objective are:
(1) a single hierarchical, unified judiciary.
(2) Uniform civil and criminal laws and codes of procedure.
(3) All India Services at the head of strategic posts in the State administration.
He said, “The Constitution provides that without depriving the States of their
right to form their own Civil Services, there shall be an All India service recruited
on an All India basis with common qualifications, uniform scales of pay and the
members of which alone would be appointed to the strategic posts throughout
the Union.32
Financial Relations
There is clear demarcation of the revenue resources of both the Union and the
States so as to secure them financial autonomy.
The sources of revenue of the Union are listed in entries 82 to 92A of the
Union List, while those of the States in Entries 45 to 63 of the State List.
Constitutional Structure, Mechanism and Working of Federalism in India 113
An important feature of the financial relations between Union and States is
the provision for revenue sharing between the Union and States. The following
provisions of the Constitution are noteworthy in this connection.
(1) There are duties levied by the Union but collected and appropriated by
the States, such as stamp duties and excise duties on medical and toiled
preparations.
(2) There are taxes levied and collected by the Union but assigned wholly to
the States, for example, succession duties, estate duty, terminal taxes, taxes
on railway fares and freights etc.
(3) There are taxes levied and collected by the Union and distributed between
the Union and the States. This is the position of taxes on income other
than agricultural income.
(4) There are taxes and duties which are levied and collected by the Union
and may be distributed between the Union and the States if Parliament
by law so provides. This is the position of excise duties other than duties
on medicinal and toiled preparations.
(5) Parliament is empowered to make such grants as it may deem necessary
to give financial assistance to any State which is in need of such assistance.
Such grants may either be block grants or specific grants.
The Constitution provides for grants—
(a) to States of Assam, Bihar, Orissa and West Bengal in lieu of expert duty
on jute and products.
(b) to State of Assam for the development of tribal Areas in the State.
(c) for schemes of development for welfare of Scheduled Tribes, and for
raising the level of administration of Scheduled Areas as may have been
undertaken by a State with the approval of the Union.
The Constitution provides that the distribution between the Union and the
States of the net proceeds of taxes which are to be divided between them and the
allocation between States of the respective shares of such proceeds shall be done
on the recommendations of finance Commission which shall be appointed by
the President every five years.
The Commission will also recommend the principles which should govern
the grants in aid of the revenue of the States.
The grants are a means to assist development schemes in States lacking in
adequate financial resources and an instrument to exercise control and
coordination over the welfare schemes of the States.
As the Supreme court said “Realising the limitations on the financial resources
of the States and the growing needs of the community in a welfare States, the
Constitution has made… specific provisions empowering Parliament to set aside
a portion of its revenue… for the benefit of the States not in Stated proportions
but according to their needs… The resources of the Union are not meant
exclusively for the benefit of the Union activities… In the words, the Union and
114
Journal of Social and Political Studies
the States together form one organic whole for the purposes of utilisation of the
resources of India as a whole:33
Emergency Provisions
The Constitution provides that while a proclamation of Emergency is in operation,
the President may by an order modify or suspend the provisions relating to
distribution of revenues between the Centre and the States as may be specified in
the order.
While a proclamation of financial Emergency under Art. 360 is in operation,
the Union is empowered to give directions to any State to observe such canons
of financial propriety as may be specified in the directions. Such direction may
include (a) a provision requiring the reduction of salaries and allowances of State
officials and (b) a provision requiring all Money Bills to the reserved for the
consideration of the President after they are passed by the Legislature of the State.
The Union is also empowered to reduce the salaries and allowances of its
officials including the judges of the Supreme Court and High Courts during the
period of financial emergency.
While a State is under President’s rule under Art. 356, the powers of the State
Legislature are exercisable by the Parliament including the power to adopt the
State Budget and pass the money bills.
In this way, during an Emergency the constitutional barriers between the
Union and the States are scaled down and the Indian State can function more or
less like a unitary mechanism.34
Inter State water Disputes
The Constitution provides that Parliament may be law provide for the adjudication
of any dispute with respect to use, distribution or control of the waters of any
inter-State river or river valley and also provide for the exclusion of the jurisdiction
of the Supreme Court in any such dispute.
In exercise of this power, Parliament has enacted the inter-State Water Disputes
Act, 1956, providing for the constitution of an ad hoc Tribunal for the
adjudication of any dispute arising between two or more States with regards to
the waters of any inter State river (such as Cauvery) or river valley.
Inter-State Council
The Constitution provides that for coordination among States on subjects of
common interest and for inquiring into and advising upon inter-State disputes
there may be constituted an Inter State Council.
It was in 1990 that an Inter State Council comprising of 6 Union Cabinet
Ministers and all the State Chief Ministers was first constituted. However subject
wise Councils have been established from time to time by the Central Government
to secure coordination of policy and action in the relevant field, such as Central
Council of Health, Central Council of Local Self Government, a Transport
Constitutional Structure, Mechanism and Working of Federalism in India 115
Development Council, Central Council of Indian Medicine, Central Family
Welfare Council, Central Council of Homeopathy. These Councils have been set
up to investigate and discuss subjects of common interest between the union and
the States or between two or more States, and to make recommendations for
coordination of policy and action relating to such subject.
Federation at Work
It follows from the above narrative that the Constitution has provided for a strong
dominating Centre conceding uncertain internal autonomy to the constituent
States within carefully defined limits.
The proof of the pudding is the eating thereof and it is notable that the
equation of powers between the Centre and States has not been static but has
been fluctuating with circumstances so that several patterns are discernible in the
actual working of the Constitution during the past fifty years.
One Dominant Party and Charismatic Leadership
The long stretch of Congress rule (1950-77), (1980-89) was characterised by the
dominating position of the Congress both in the Centre and the States (with the
exception of Kerala) though there was a set back for the Congress in several of
the States after the fourth General Election but it was short lived and after 1971,
the Congress continued to recover its lost ground except for the State of Tamil
Nadu, and after 1977, the State of West Bengal.
The Central command and control mechanism located in the Congress
President who was invariably the Prime Minister too, and the Congress Working
committee or the High Command, were the unifying thread for the political
system in operation in both the Union and the States. The decisions on the
selection of the Chief Minister, replacement of the incumbent any time,
composition of the Ministry, dissolution of the ministry or imposition of
President’s rule, and similar vital issues relating to the State government slipped
into the domain of the central leadership.
The charisma associated with the Nehru family and the myth surrounding
the leading figures of the National freedom movement were the unifying force
for the party and magnet for mass support.
This is why the congress emerged as the single dominant party in the Indian
political system and ensured a stable and strong government not only at the Centre
but also in the States.
Under Nehru and subsequently under Indira Gandhi and Rajiv Gandhi
Centre State disputes were invariably treated as subjects of domestic jurisdiction
for the party rather than matters of constitutional concern.
In this way the federal scheme was supplanted and supplemented by party
discipline.
116
Journal of Social and Political Studies
Planning and Federalism
To the political hegemony of one dominant party under leaders of mass appeal
in their respective States and beyond, Nehru added one ideological input namely,
Economic planning for a socialistic pattern of society, and later on for building
Democratic Socialism.
This was the goal which transcended party lines and cut across State
boundaries.
Therefore planning soon came to be looked upon as an anathema to federal
polity.
The reason is that Planning process necessarily meant central initiative and
leadership in plan formulation and centralized superintendence, direction and
control in plan execution and performance evaluation.
In 1950, in pursuance of a Resolution of the Union Cabinet, a Planning
Commission was set up with the Prime Minister as its Chairman ex officio, to
prepare five Year Plans for social and economic development and secure the “most
effective and balanced utilization of the country’s resources” which would “initiate
a process of development which will raise living standards and open out to the
people new opportunities for richer and more varied life”. Besides the Prime
Minister, the Ministers of home, Finance and Defence are the members of the
Planning Commission. Its Dy. Chairman once the Minister for Planning is not a
Minister but enjoys the status of a Cabinet Minister.
Besides, there are several full time members, who are experts in Finance,
Agriculture, Economics and the like.
In deference to the federal nature of the polity, in 1952 a National
Development Council was set up to associate the States in the formulation of
the Plans and “to strengthen and mobilize the efforts and resources of the nation
in support of the plans.
In particular, the specific functions of the NDC are—
(a) to review the working of the National Plan from time to time
(b) to recommend measures for the achievement of the aims and targets set
out in the National Plan.
The prime Minister is the chairman of the NDC ex officials, while the
members of the Planning Commission and the Chief Ministers of all the States,
numbering 28 at present, are its ex officio members.
The draft of the Plan is prepared by the Planning Commission in consultation
with Union Ministers and State Governments and after approval by the Union
Cabinet it is placed before the NDC for its approval.
In this way the Plan formulation is a cooperative exercise but many critics
see in it t erosion of State autonomy. The Planning Commission has been described
as a “super Cabined” or a “parallel cabinet’ and as ‘the Economic Cabinet not
only for the Union but also for the States.”35
Constitutional Structure, Mechanism and Working of Federalism in India 117
K. Santhanam laments that “planning has profoundly altered the relations
between the Union and the States while maintaining intact the legal framework.36
In the context of Centre-State Relations in India the criticism of Planning
rests on the following grounds:
(1) The Planning Commission and the National Development Council are
both extra-constitutional and non statutory bodies and have superseded the
constitutional organs of power in the field of social welfare and economic planning.
Even Appleby observes that “Membership of the Commission is a small
edition of the Government itself. As a result of these things the development of a
Plan is the development of the Government’s policy and program.37
In theory, the NDC is superior to the Planning Commission as “It is a policy
making body and its recommendations cannot but be regarded as policy decisions
and not merely as advisory suggestions”.38
According the Michael Brecher the NDC “lays down policy directives
invariably approved by the Cabinet… the NDC and its Standing Committee have
virtually relegated the Planning Commission to the Status of a research arm.”39
Santhanam cites the decision to surrender by State Governments of their sales
taxes on textiles, sugar and tobacco in lieu of additional excise duties, to illustrate
how the NDC is making policy decisions on behalf of the States. He writes “ the
decision… was taken at a single sitting of the National Development Council at
which many of the Chief Ministers had not even fully consulted their own
Cabinets.”40
(2) Through Planning the Union has been able to encroach into the State
sphere such as land reforms, forestry, agriculture, irrigation, power, cottage
industries, primary education, health. The first Five Year Plan Stated
that”…without complete coordination of policies and timely concerted action,
there is danger of waste and misdirection of effort….”
It is notable that 70 percent of the total expense of Planning in the First Plan
and 65 percent in the Second Plan pertained to subjects of the State List.41
According to Tarlok Singh, an ex-Member of the Planning Commission,
Planning widens the scope of Central responsibilities as—
(i) Planning determines the directions in which central as well as State
resources are to be used.
(ii) In joining with the States to prepare a national Plan the Centre accepts
some obligation for its implementation.
(iii) the Centre inspires the States with new ideas and impulse for national
development programme.
During the period 1957-64 the Central expenditure on social services (which
is mostly State responsibility) was nearly doubled (from 172.6 crores to 513.7
crores).42
(3) The financial dependence of the States on the power of the Union to levy
118
Journal of Social and Political Studies
certain taxes for them, to levy and collect certain others, and to levy, collect and
share with them the proceeds of income tax and excise duties is further accentuated
by the compulsions of Plan financing.
K. Santhanam was of opinion that Plan financing had become so centralized
as to convert India almost into a unitary State for this purpose, He noted that
75% of capital investment of each State and about 50 percent of its revenue
expenditure are derived from the Centre. The whole of the former and nearly
half of the latter are at the discretion of the Union Governmen.”43
The following Table44 shows the central assistance in aid of revenue and capital
expenditure of the States.
Central Assistance
Ist Plan
41.4%
IInd Plan
48.5%
IIIrd Plan
52.2%
IVth Plan
56.7%
The resource transfers that take place under Art. 275 on the recommendations
of the Finance Commission are known as statutory grants while those under Art.
282, on the recommendations of the Planning Commission, are known as
discretionary grants.
It is the latter which are criticised as causing the States’ abject dependence
on the Centre, also enabling it to discriminate between States.
However with the Fourth Plan allocations the Statutory grants allocations
began to exceed the discretionary grants.45
Transfers under Commission
A. Finance Commission
recommendations
B. Planning Commission
Recommendations
C. Other transfers
Total
Ist
Plan
IInd
Plan
IIIrd
Plan
Three
Annual
Plans
IVth
Plan
Vth
Plan
VIth
Plan
429
918
1590
1782
5420
13079
20845
880
104
1344
606
2738
1272
1917
1648
4900
4992
10595
4054
13245
-
1413
2868
3600
5347
15312
27728
34090
Plan grants given under Art. 282 are matching grants which means that the
state has to match the central grant with an equal sum from its own resources.
It means that states have to fall in line with Central policies, priorities and
preferences for securing matching grant and also dovetail their own funds to central
allocations.
Vertical Federalism
The central grants are routed through central Ministries o their counterparts in
the States. The result is that the Central Ministry is in a position to superintend,
Constitutional Structure, Mechanism and Working of Federalism in India 119
direct and control the corresponding State ministry. In this way besides the
territorial or horizontal federation set up by the Constitution a sort of vertical
federation has come into being. The Central Ministries and corresponding State
Departments each constitute a separate single unit for planning, programming,
and funding plan projects.
(4) Besides the project sanctioned for the States in the national Plan, there
are some known as “Centrally sponsored schemes” which have to be necessarily
located in one or the other State. These are wholly financed by the Centre but
executed by the State concerned under technical guidance and supervision of the
related Union Ministry.
The location of public sector undertakings of the Central Government which
encompass most of the infrastructure industries such as steel, heavy electrical, heavy
engineering, fertilizers, becomes the subject of inter-State rivalry in view of its
multiple impact on local economy and employment potential. The choice of one
site in preference to the other is an exercise of patronage in the discretionary bag
of the Union. As most of these schemes relate to State subjects, the Centre is able
to transform them into central or concurrent subjects.
New Trends in Federal Theory
These grounds of criticism are no doubt factually correct but they derive from a
theory of federalism which is wholly out of tune with modern times.
Henry Steel Commager observed that the doctrine of state autonomy or State
rights had generally been invoked by those who wanted to weaken the government
and imperil the citizen’s freedom. It smacks of “narrowness, selfishness and
vindictiveness.”46
When the doctrine of State autonomy becomes either a “cover for ideological
strategies against the Union Government,47 (as in the hands of the CPI (M)
government of West Bengal) or an “expression of aggressive cultural separatism”
(as in the hands of the Akali Dal in Punjab48 or DMK in Tamilnadu in the early
days49 it ceases to be a device of “Unity in diversity” which is the raison d’etre of
federalism.
In modern federal theory the focus in not on functional jurisdictions but on
goal attainment. The concept of dual polity have been substituted by what may
be called a commonwealth, or, in the words of Granville Austin, co-operative
federalism, in which both the centre and the States are seen as two levels from
which the tasks of economic and political development should be carried out.
Under the impact of science and technology and pressure of globalisation and
threats of terrorism, the tasks of development and internal security have assumed
a dimension and scale which can no longer be divided into lists but require vertical
allocation of responsibility between the Union and the States.50 According to one
writer “both the Union and the States are parts of a single, indivisible political
system. Neither level of government should be administratively weak or
incompetent, Ultimately, the goals of the system are more important than the
120
Journal of Social and Political Studies
specific constitutional arrangement for it is a means and no more. It is significant
that the preamble of the India constitution gives us no hint regarding the federal
character of the system…. But it winds up with the phrase unity and integrity of
the nation.”51
Interpreted in the light of this shift in federal theory, the Indian Constitution
would seem to create a “co-operative union” of States rather then a dual polity.
Planning for mobilisation of national resources and their utilization most
effective and balanced utilisation for the social and economic development of the
country as a whole would appear to be an integral part of this concept.
This mutual cooperation is institutionalised in the National Development
Council which Tarlok Singh, an Ex-Member of Planning Commission calls “the
highest national forum for planning”. He writes that it has “in practice embodied
and given informal sanction to the underlying concept of partnership and
cooperation between the Centre and the States over the whole range of
development” and “which brings State governments into an organic relationship
with the organization of planning at the national level.”52
Growing Role of States in National Politics
The unitarian federalism as the Union State relations came to be described during
the long years of Congress rule at the Centre was consequence of the dominance
of the one party both at the Centre and in States.
The one party dominance continued until the defeat of the Congress in the
General Election of 1989, with brief spells of set-back as during 1967-70 and
again from 1977 to 1979.
Since 1989 there has been a minority coalition or a minority Congress
Government at the Centre,53 sustained by outside support and, therefore, instable,
and, in most of the States, there were governments at variance with the Centre
politically.
Therefore the one-dominent party system which fostered and sustained the
unitarian federalism was replaced by competitive party politics. What Morris Jones
calls competition in India’s bargaining federalism actually emerged after the loss
of monopoly of political power by the Congress.
In the formation of he National Front Governments (1989-91) and the
United Front Government (1996-1998) and the NDA governments in 1998 the
regional parties and the State Chief Ministers played the decisive role. The
Narsimha Rao government (1991-96) was a minority government to begin with
and even when it changed into a majority government by inducing defections to
its side it was so rocked by scandals and scams as to be unable to exercise any
leadership role over the States.
The United Front Government (1996-98) was a coalition of some 14 parties
depending on the outside support of the Cong (I). It was to retain support of
the Con (I) that Deve Gowda was replaced by I.K. Gujral as Prime Minister in
Constitutional Structure, Mechanism and Working of Federalism in India 121
the mid-stream (April 1997). Similarly the National Democratic Alliance is
conglomeration of more than a dozen regional parties joined in an alliance with
the BJP, in power since March 1998, but depending on the outside support of
several other regional parties like the Telegu Desam, Trinmul Congress, AIADMK
and the BSP.
The leadership role of the Centre also waned because of the “end of Ideology”
from political agenda. The Congress was able to rally wide support and consensus
across parties around its socialistic political programmes but after the drive for
liberalization and “economic reforms” politics has become a pure struggle for power
in which divisive issues have gained primacy and regional political forces have
come to the fore in national politics.
The regional parties became share holders in power at the Centre though most
of them were not in power in their own State. The State Governments politically
incompatible with the Centre arrogated near autonomy to themselves, while the
Union Government became a mere “federation of regional interests”.
The Laloo/Rabri apparatus in Bihar, the DMK/AIADMK alternative in Tamil
Nadu, the TDP supremacy in Andhra Pradesh, the CPI(M) monopoly of power
in West Bengal are instances in point.
In this way the Union and the States under the impact of competitive party
politics and rising regionalism have become coordinate centres of power.
The one party hegemony subsumed regional politics and regional political
forces are bound to come on the surface with the end of this hegemony.
Speaking in March 1959, K. Santhanam had expressed the view that the
reorganization of States on the linguistic basis has cemented the base of State
autonomy, and since then there have been added tribal States and hill States to
the linguistic States. In the same lecture he had forewarned that “If at any time
in the future, a considerable number of State Governments should belong to
parties different from that which control the Union Government….. there may
have to be reversion to the State autonomy to the full extent provided by the
Constitution.54
Added to these changes in the federal equation since the break up of the
Congress monopoly of political power is the consideration which was underlined
by Paul H. Apple by early as 1953. Appelby had warned that howsoever strong
the position of the Union in planning, programming and financing the execution
of plans and projects rests in the hands of the State Governments. Appelby notes
with surprise that “No other large and important national government.. is so
dependent as India on theoretically subordinate but actually rather distinct units
responsible to a different political control, for so much of the administration of
what are recognised as national programmes…
The power that is exercised organically in Delhi is influence rather than power.
The method is making plans, issuing pronouncements, holding conferences…
Any real power in most of the development field is the personal power of
122
Journal of Social and Political Studies
particular leaders and the informal, extra constitutional, extra-administrative power
of a dominant party, coherent and strongly led by the same leaders….55
Two instances are cited to illustrate how politically willful States may frustrate
central plans and political implementation on the ground. While the Union
Government was able to enact POTA State leaders in and outside Parliament
openly declared that they know how (not) to implement it.
The second instance is related to the implementation of the National
Curriculum Framework issued by the NCERT. The Left, the Congress and the
Janata brand parties have declared that the States ruled by them would not in
any case adopt the NCERT text books. They would, go further and launch a
nation-wide agitation against the Education policy of the Central Government.56
These factors in Indian federalism show that while diversity in Indian
conditions is invulnerable, unity is constantly at stake. The restraining thought is
that if the Union is weakened the States will be losers too. This should be guiding
rule for maintaining the federal equilibrium in the days to come.
REFERENCES
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
Art. 2 of the Constitution. The following cases are illustrative of the differential treatment.
(a) the special status accord to the Jammu and Kasmir under Art. 370.
(b) the admission of Sikkim as “an associate State” of the Union, 1974.
(c) the differential treatment among the Union Territories.
(d) the special provisions governing the administration of Tribal Areas as provided in Vth
and Vth Scheduled of the Constitution
As per the Advisory Opinion of the Supreme Court in Re Berubari Union (1960) 3 SCR
250, Parliament may not cede any portion of the national territory in favour of a foreign
state. In view of this, both the Tashket declaration (1966) and Simla Agreement (1972)
involving the return of portions of Kashmir territory recovered from Pakistan’s illegal
Occupation back to it were politically ridiculous and constitutionally void.
Reading the Court’s opinion in the Brown case (1954) Chief Justice Warren said: “We
conclude that in the field of public education the doctrine ‘separate but equal’ has no place.
Separate educational facilities are inherently unequal…. Any language in Plessy V. Ferguson
contrary to these findings is rejected.” See Brown V Topeka Board of Education, 374 U.S.
483 (1954).
In 1960 Bombay State was bifurcated to form the two States of Maharashtra and Gujarat; in
1962 Nagaland was separated from Assam and Meghalaya in 1969. In 1966 Punjab was
bifurcated to form the States of Punjab and Haryana. The North East Areas Reorganization
Act, 1971 brought up Manipur, Meghalaya and Tripura into the category of States and added
and Mizoram and Arunachal Pradesh to the list of UTs.
Goa first admitted to India as a Union Territory in 1961, was raised to full Statehood in
1987. Dadra and Nagar Haveli, former Portuguese colonies were admitted as Union Territory
in 1961. Pondicherry former French colony was admitted as Union Territory in 1963.
Sikkim was first admitted as an “associate State” of the Union but later given full-fledged
Statehood by the Constitution (36th) Amendment Act, 1975.
The other cases of upgradation were Hmanchal (1970) Manipur and Tripura (1971)
Mizoram and Arunachal Pradesh (1986).
The renamed States are Tamilnadu (formerly Madras), Karnatak (Mysore), Maharashtra
(Bombay), Lakshadwitp (Laccadiv, Minicoy, Amindivi).
Art. 368 goes on to say that if the amendment seeks to make any change in: (a) article 54,
Constitutional Structure, Mechanism and Working of Federalism in India 123
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
article 55, article 73, article 162, or article 241;or; (b) Chapter 4 of Part V, Chapter 5 of Part
VI or Chapter I of Part XI; or (c) any of the Lists in the Seventh Schedule, or (d) the
provisions of this article the amendment shall also require to be ratified by the Legislature of
not less than on half of the State by resolutions to that effect passed by these legislatures.
Nathan, Glazer “Towards and Imperial Judiciary” in the American Commonwealth, 1976
(eds) Nathan Glazer and Irving Kristol, Basic Books, New York p. 104.
CAD, VII, p.33. Dr. Ambedkar said, “This dual polity under the proposed Constitution will
consists of the Union at the Centre and the States at the Periphery each endowed with
sovereign powers to be excercised in the field assigned to them respectively by the
Constitution… The Union is not a league of State nor are the States administrative units or
agencies of the Union Governments.”
The Constitution (73rd Amendment) Act, 1992, and the Constition (74 th Amendment) Act,
1992 went into force form 20 April, 1993 and introduced part IX and Part IXA in the
Constitution. While Pt IX relates to the Panchayats, containing Articles 243 to 243 0, part
IX A relates 0 the municipalities, containing Articles 243 P to 243 ZG. The provisions in the
two Parts are more or less parallel or analogues.
11th Schedule contains 29 Items such as Land improvement, Minor irrigation, animal
husbandry, fisheries, education, women and child development, 12th Schedule contains 18
items such as Urban Planning. Regulation of Land use, Roads and Bridges, Water Supply,
Public Health, Fire Services, Urban Forestry, Slums.
Art 243X stipulates “The legislature of a State may by law (a) authorise a Municipality to
levy, collect and appropriate such taxes, duties, tolls and fees. (b) assign to a Municipality
such taxes, duties tolls and fees levied and collected by the State Government for such
purposes. (c) provide for making such grants in aid to the Municipality from the
consolidated Fund of the State. as may be specified in the law. There is analogous provision
for the Panchayats.
In a Resolution passed by the All India Panchyat Adhyakshas Sammelan it was urged that the
Union Government introduce a new constitutional Amendment to empower the panchayati
raj institutions with more administrative and financial powers. Prime Minister Vajpayee
inaugurating a conference of project directors of district level rural development agencies
(DRDA’s) at New Delhi on Oct. 5 2002 responded by declaring that a Constitution
amendment bill would be introduced in the winter session of Parliament to give more
financial and administrative powers to the panchayati raj institutions after evolving a
consensus among political parties on this issue. The pioneer, Lucknow, 5 Oct. 2002.
Cf. Durga Das Basu, Introduction to the Constitution of India, 1999, p. 270. Basu believes
that “The 11th Schedule distributes powers between the State Legislature and the Panchayats
just as the 7th Schedule distributes powers between the Union and the State Legislature” Such
a view in unwarranted.
CAD, XI, p. 976.
D.D. Basu, A Commentary on the Constitution of India, Vol. I. 3rd Ed. p.18
Part XI, Ch, I Legislative Relations: Ch. II. Administration Relations, Part XII, Arts. 268 to
281: Distribution of Revenues between the Union and States.
“In the Context of India, so large and varied with so many religions, languages and
traditions, all contending for recognition, it was imperative to invest the Centre with
authority unusual in a fedration”. Ram Kishore Vyas, “Centre State Relations in the
Legislative Field”, in Rajsthan Vidhan Sabha Silver Jubilee Commemoration Volume (19521975), Jaipur, 1977, p. 249.
Dr. Ambedkar in his concluding speech during the Third Reading debate on the Draft
Constitution, CAD, IX, p. 976.
K. Santhanam, “Federal Relations”, in M.G. Gupta (ed) Aspect of Indian Constitution,
Central Book Depot, Allahabad, 1964, p. 443.
124
Journal of Social and Political Studies
23. Ibid, p. 442.
24. Dr. Ambedkar defended these cases of Central encroachment upon the State Legislative
sphere as a “new way to overcome rigidity and legalism inherent in federalism”. CAD, VII,
P.36.
25. Ram Kishore Vyas, “Centre-State Relations in the Legislative Field”, Rajasthan Vidhan Sabha
Silver Jubilee Volume, 1977, p. 250-51 Also see S.P. Aiyar, “Thoughts on a More Perfect
Union”, in the Constitution and the Parliament in India, (Ed.). S.L. Shakdher, Lok Sabha
Secretariat, New Delhi, pp. 35-36. According to Aiyar, “The Functions of government are
acquiring a broader significance and deeper complexity under the impact of science and
technology. Many activities which in an earlier period could be left to the States have now a
federal Aspect as well. This is particularly true of fields like education, health and agriculture.
This is he logic of the concurrent list”
26. Sir lver Jennings, Some Characteristics of the Indian Constitution, Oxford, Univ. Press,
1953, p. 61.
27. “Centre State Relations in the Legislative Field”. in Rajasthan Vidhan Shbha, Silver Jubilee
Commemoration Volume, (1952-77), Jaipur P. 253. He writes, “Normally the President gave
his assent on all the bills sent to him. He, however, withheld his assent of the following State
laws and no reasons were given for withholding the assent: (i) Rajasthan Urban Property
(ceiling) bill, 1972) (ii) The Indian Electricity (Rajasthan Amemdment) bill, 1975.
28. Ibid, p-254. The president returned for reconsideration the Madhya Pradesh SC and OBC
Reservation bill on 11 April 2002 on the ground that the Reservation quota envisaged in it
exceeded the 50% outer limit.
29. S.P. Aiyar “Thoughts on a More Perfect Union”, in the Constitution and the Parliament of
India, (ed) S.L. Shakdher, Lok Sabh Secretariant, New Delhi, 1976. Aiyar writes, “It is now
widely accepted that the neatness of dual federalism is unsuited to modern needs. Items of
government responsibilities can no longer be regarded as falling in either the Union of the
State list. The either of federalism of the past has become obsolescent in the modern world.”
p.35
30. In 1967 the Home Ministry issued a communication drawing the attention of the State
Governments to growing menance of gheraos and bandhs and frequent suspension of rail
and air services and the stoppage of work in Central Government offices and industrial
undertakings due to inaction on the part of State authorities and warning them that if they
failed to protect Centre’s property and installations and to ensure proper functioning of its
agencies, it will have to take action to ensure that Government is carried on in accordance
with the Constitution. The Hindustan Times, New Delhi 12.11.1967.
31. The dismissals of Governors Prabhudatt Patwari ( Tamilnadu 1980) Raghukul Tilak
(Rajsthan 1980), Sheila kaul (Himanchal Pradesh) 1996, Fathima Bibi (Tamilnaud, sep.
2011) before expiry of five year term are some of the examples.
32. CAD VII, p.37
33. Coffee Board v. CTO AIR 1971 SC 870
34. Cf. D.D. Basu, Introduction to the Constitution of India, Wadhwa and Co. 1999, Basu
writes, “In emergencies the government under the Indian Constitution will as if it ware a
unitary government” (p. 26). Again, “the Emergency provision of our Constitution enable
the federal Government to ecquire the strength of a unitary system whenever the exigencies
of the situation so demand”. p.339.
35. Asoka Chanda, “Institutional Base of Centre, State Relations” in B.L. Maheshwari, (ed)
Centre-State Relations in the Seventies, Calcutta, 1973, p. 138. Also see K.M. Munshi “The
Super Cabinet” in The Radical Humanist, 6 Dec. 1959 p.571, and, Administrative Reforms
Commission, Interim Report on the Machinery of Planning, New Delhi, 1967, para 15.
36. K. Santhanam, “Federal Relations”, in M.G. Gupta (ed) Aspects of Indian Constitution,
Allahabad. 1964, p. 447.
Constitutional Structure, Mechanism and Working of Federalism in India 125
37. Paul H. Applebby, “The Civil Services”, in M.G. Gupta, Aspects of Indian Constitution,
p.323.
38. H.M. Patel, The Indian Journal of Public Administration, Oct.-Dec.1959, p.461.
39. Michael Bracher, Nehru- A Political Biography, Landon, 1959, p.521.
40. K. Santhanam, Union State relation in India, Bombay, 1963, p. 46.
41. B.L. Fadia, State Politics in India, Vol.I, Radiant, New Delhi, 1984, p.125, 131
42. Ibid, p.136.
43. K. Santhanam, Federal Relations in Aspect of Indian Constitution. opcit., p.447.
44. Fadia, Babulal, State Politics in India, op. cit. pp. 183-84.
45. Ibid, p. 187.
46. Henry Steel Commager, “To, Form a Much Less Perfect Union”. The New York Times
Magazine, 14 July 1963.
47. See the West Bengal Government’s Memorandum on Centre State Relations, 1979.
48. See the Anandpur Saheb Resolution of the Akali Dal. There are, in fact, several versions of
the “Resolution”, in circulation. The “original” Resolution was adopted by the Akali Dal
Working Committed at Anandpur Sabeb on 16th October 1973. Another version was
adopted at the all Indian Akali Conference in Ludhiana in 1978. A third version was adopted
by the World Sikh Convention organized by the Akali Dal faction led by Jagdev Singh
Talwadi at Anandpur Saheb in April 1981. The Anandpur Saheb resolution assumes the
concept of a “Sikh Nation’ and on this basis demands the creation of an autonomous “Sikh
State” where the supremacy of the Khalsa Panth is recognised. See Harkishan Singh Surjeet,
“what Anandpur Sahib Resolution Really aimed at”, in Northern India Patrika, Allahabad,
July 31, 1985, p. 4.
49. Tamilnadu, Centre-State Relations Inquiry also known as Rajmannar Committee Report,
Madras, 1971.
50. Saradar K.M. Pannikar observed that “No State in India, singly, even if it were dreaming of
its greatness in a mythical golden age, can undertake a multi-purpose project like that at
Hirakud, or contemplate an iron and steel factory like the Hindustan Steel. The costs
involved, the technical skill required, the sustained planning and execution, are beyond the
resources of single State”. See Fadia, op cit., p.139.
51. S.P. Aiyar, “Thoughts on a More Perfect Union”, in the Constitution and Parliament in
India, Ed, S.L,Shakdher, 1976, p. 36.
52. Government of India, Planning Commission, Th Planning Process, New Delhi, 1963, pp 5354. In her address to the meeting of the National Development Council on 20 January 1973,
Mrs. Gandhi said, “It would be useful if the meetings of the National Development Council
are held not only for discussing the plan but also for other major problems and broad matters
of national policy” The Statesman, New Delhi. Dated 21 January 1973.
53. The National Front Government headed by V.P. Singh (1989-90) was a minority coalition
depending on outside support of the BJP and the CPI(M); It was followed by the
“Miniscule” Government headed by the Breakaway Chandra Shekhar group having a
following of some sixty members in the Lok Sabha but assured of the outside support of the
Cong. (I). Cong (I) Government headed by PV Narsimha Rao was in June 1991 a minority
government but gradually attained majority status when on 30 December 1993 the 10 Janata
Dal (Ajit) MPs crossed over to its side. The United Front Government (1996-98) was a
coalition of some 14 parties depending on the outside support of Cong (I).
54. M.G. Gupta (ed), Aspects of Indian Constitution, op.cit, p.448.
55. Paul H. Appleby, Public Administration in India, New Delhi, 1953, p.22
56. The pioneer, Lucknow, 18 October 2002, p.3.
126
Journal of Social and Political Studies
Antony and Cleopatra:
Shakespeare’s Epic in Drama
Lakshmi Raj Sharma
Some basic questions about Shakespeare’s art have been raised time and again,
and several attempts have been made to tackle these questions. This monograph
may be considered one such attempt. The questions raised in this monograph
and the answers attempted herein are connected with Shakespeare’s art and beliefs
as reflected in Antony and Cleopatra. They relate to the play’s form as well as to
its content (the philosophy it seems to support)—both of which have remained
enigmatic. But the questions raised here also extend beyond the play, to perplexing
attributes of the poet and dramatist as a whole.
The questions:
1. Why had it become necessary for Shakespeare to write Antony and Cleopatra
at the time he wrote it?
2. Does the play say anything? If it does, what does it say?
3. How does Shakespeare say whatever he wants to, in Antony and Cleopatra?
How does he overcome the limitations imposed by the existing genres?
(Each of the above questions is tackled in the different sections of this monograph)
I
Shakespeare’s extensive experimentation with literary form is no secret. He may
have settled for the literary genres of that period —genres such as the sonnet, the
narrative poem, comedy, tragedy, history-play, and romance—but he always put
new life into the existing genres. Even a sub-genre, like revenge-tragedy or
domestic-tragedy was transformed in Shakespeare’s hands. Domestic-tragedy, for
instance, was first seen in the anonymous Elizabethan dramas: Arden of Feversham
(1591), A Warning for Fair Women (1599), and The Yorkshire Tragedy (1606).
Besides, there was Thomas Heywood’s Woman Killed with Kindness. But when
Shakespeare used domestic-tragedy in Othello, and Hamlet, the result was very
different. His domestic-tragedies became substantially more than what they had
been earlier.
Shakespeare dwelt on “generic boundaries”, as G.K.Hunter put it,1 rather
than on the conventional genre itself. Due to this quality in his make-up, he was
constantly trying to find newer ways of expressing his observations and experiences.
To a certain extent, all great literature is a result of this saying something new in
a new way. This idea has found support from critics, Coleridge down to Eliot.
But with Shakespeare, the newness of the form of expression seems to have been
an obsession. He was critical of poets and playwrights who wrote in blind
imitation. Hamlet’s instructions to the company of players is indicative of the
Antony and Cleopatra: Shakespeare’s Epic in Drama
127
fact that Shakespeare did not find contemporary theatre expressive enough.
Besides, Shakespeare pointed out repeatedly that the state of contemporary
poetry was deplorable.2 A number of characters figuring in the plays between 1595
and 1599 ridicule soneteers and mere rhymers.3 Ballads are ridiculed in Henry
IV.4 Shakespeare had indeed become dissatisfied with verse itself in the years 15951600.5 Poets were easily bracketed with lovers and lunatics and were often
disparaged. Incidentally, Shakespeare seems to have favoured the spontaneous
variety of poetry,6 the variety which he later used abundantly in Antony and
Cleopatra, and in his other works as well. Though dissatisfied with verse,
Shakespeare was still using it in his plays as well as his poems. So he had to be
original in the handling of verse as well as the literary genre he was using in order
to be sufficiently expressive. But originality tends to be a problem for literary
history,7 particularly if the originality crosses the bounds laid down by literary
genres and/or social morality. By the latter I refer to an author who chooses to
use ideas which are ahead of his times. Since Antony and Cleopatra was original
on both levels, it was likely to create problems (and it actually has) for its audiences
and readers. It must therefore remain one of Shakespeare’s problem plays.
Shakespeare’s originality seems to have been at its highest in Antony and
Cleopatra. He was indeed saying something very new in a very new way. He seems
to have come to the kind of spiritual discovery that needed an almost new medium
to contain it. This included a new kind of literary form and required an impressive
machinery of myth, image, symbol and metaphor. What he wanted to convey
was beyond the limits of social permissibility as it violated existing codes of morality
in its permissiveness. Furthermore, what he had come to believe was definitely
not something which was easy to grasp. I will deal with this point in the next
section. For the present, suffice it to say that Shakespeare was trying to say, in a
more successful way, what he had merely hinted at in “Venus and Adonis”:
How love is wise in folly, foolish witty. (838)
This of course is only one strand of thought from the poem which he would
recast in the play; and this is not all that he says in Antony and Cleopatra.
Several nineteenth century critics have considered “Venus and Adonis” a
“quasi-biographical document”.8 To Shakespeare the poem had its obvious
limitations, particularly because it was not expressive enough. It must have seemed
“too sensual moralistically and too cold artistically”.9 In other words, Shakespeare
seems to have been unsuccessful in finding appropriate symbols for expressing a
thought dear to him. He was probably saddled with a fine vision that did not
find an appropriate voice. Hence his desire to say in “Venus and Adonis”
something which went beyond the merely social met with a failure of sorts. He
was, after all, saying something new in not such a new way. The desire to put his
experience into a different artistic mould seems to have resulted in Antony and
Cleopatra. This can be deduced on the premise that the two texts share much in
thematic terms and Cleopatra is largely Venus.10 Ovid, who was the “amorous
128
Journal of Social and Political Studies
schoolmaster” of several Renaissance poets, had definitely influenced Shakespeare
in “Venus and Adonis”, where the amorous element was distinctly physical and
yet more than the merely physical. Similar was to be the case in Antony and
Cleopatra. Even artistically there is some similarity between the two pieces. Both
works use myth and create vivid pictorial presentations of a similar content.
J.W. Lever’s assessment of Shakespeare’s narrative poetry is very significant
for this article.11 He points to the pictorial qualities of “Venus and Adonis”
describing it as “verbal painting” and linking it with “Florentine pictorial treatment
of classical myth.”12 Lever says that in both “Venus and Adonis” as well as “The
Rape of Lucrece”, Shakespeare’s narrative art was greatly flawed.13 Perhaps this
was so because Shakespeare’s aptitude was more suited to comic art than to the
tragic, at that time, and he had chosen the wrong subject.14 Now, years later,
Shakespeare probably decided to say the same thing more successfully by blending
the epic with that form which he had perfected—poetic-drama. He was critic
enough to assess that his narrative poems lacked the finesse of his dramas. He
seems to have been driven towards inventing a genre to facilitate his expressiveness
in Antony and Cleopatra.
Further, Shakespeare could have been impressed by the idea of writing an
epic because (a) the sixteenth century regarded Virgil, and his hero, the very
epitome of human perfection,15 (b) he was impressed by the Aeneid, (the Trojan
episode in “The Rape of Lucrece” came from the first two books of the Aeneid).16
If Shakespeare had to write an epic as grand as the Aeneid, he had to make it
different to it. The difference, he seems to have decided, would be achieved by
changing narrative art to dramatic art.
II
A significant question that must be answered at this stage is, whether Shakespeare
was actually interested in saying something in Antony and Cleopatra. Was he trying
to convey a thought through this play? Morris Weitz believes that Shakespeare
has said nothing at all in Antony and Cleopatra and that,
. . . in the case of Antony and Cleopatra we have a great tragedy which
contains a number of philosophical themes but no implied or elicitable
philosophical thesis or universal claim. . . . it neither makes nor includes
any general claim about man and his world. Rather it is a tragedy of two
particulars, who instance no universal applicable to all.17
This seems to be the opinion of one who has learned to accept that Shakespeare
was that unique author who never voiced a personal belief or philosophy. An
erroneous theory, is applied by Weitz to Antony and Cleopatra. But to my mind
Shakespeare had evolved certain beliefs about life which, being unconventional,
could not have been stated in unambiguous terms. He had perhaps struck upon
a theory which, had he been a philosopher, he might have put more explicitly.
He had probably come to realise something about life and human experience
which went against social norms and beliefs. And what he had realised was by no
Antony and Cleopatra: Shakespeare’s Epic in Drama
129
means simple. It was a complex world-view. Perhaps Shakespeare was anticipating
axiological intuitionism (or some other shade of objective idealism). This early
twentieth century philosophy seems to support the asocial attitude of Shakespeare
in Antony and Cleopatra. Axiological intuitionism, particularly that of G.E. Moore,
questions the very basis of what constitutes the good or goodness. Moore believed
that goodness is a simple, indefinable property, which can be arrived at by intuition
rather than any other moralistic value-system. Similarly H.A. Prichard has
maintained that moral judgements about what one ought to do cannot be analysed
or proved in terms of any other consideration including self-interest or general
utility. Besides, according to Axiology, values are considered extra-social
phenomena. Further, objective idealist theories like neo-Kantianism, followers of
Husserlian phenomenology, and neo-Thomism also share in such a value system.
For them value is absolute essence outside space and time.
Shakespeare had a romantic disposition and the romantic is seldom content
with what is traditional and socially valid. Hence, it may not have been the
legitimate or socially rational philosophy to have possessed. This philosophy may
not have tallied with the world-view reflected in his other texts because he may
not have been writing with the same audiences, or aims, in mind each time. In
Antony and Cleopatra it appears he was neither justifying the Tudor myth nor
writing to please a particular monarch, lord, or patron. This play, more than any
other, seems to be Shakespeare in soliloquy. Shakespeare’s world-view, as expressed
in this play, included a redefinition of what was ideal for individuals; what is the
right equation between law and impulse; what constitutes the nature of true love;
who is the ideal man and who the ideal woman; how far is it justified to sacrifice
one’s desires for the sake of society or even one’s country. It is also possible that
Shakespeare’s world-view did not fall in line with traditional ways of thinking
because his imagination was not exactly hetrosexual,18 and he saw things with a
different degree of sensitivity. What Shakespeare wanted to convey in this play
through image, symbol, and metaphor is roughly summarised below:
The ideal man is not he who is either too powerful or wealthy, too patriotic
or worldly, too masculine or moral (in social terms). The ideal woman likewise,
is not one who has any of these extreme traits in her personality. On the contrary,
the ideal man or woman is one who has the capacity to partake of these extreme
qualities, yet, at the same time, be able to remain happy in the reverse situations.
The ideal person in Shakespeare possesses what he calls a “heavenly mingle” and
is one who finds the role of queen or milkmaid, statesman or warrior (or “doting
mallard”) equally acceptable. Note the description of Antony in the dialogue
between Alexas and Cleopatra,
Cleo: What, was he sad, or merry?
Alex.: Like to the time of the year between the extremes
Of hot and cold, he was nor sad nor merry.
Cleo.: O well divided disposition! . . . .
130
Journal of Social and Political Studies
He was not sad, for he would shine on those
That make their looks by his; he was not merry,
Which seem’d to tell them his remembrance lay
In Egypt with his joy; but between both
O heavenly mingle! Be’st thou sad, or merry,
The violence of either thee becomes,
So does it no man else.
(I.v.50-61)
It seems that Shakespeare’s association with stage-acting led him toward a
disposition that helped him to fit into any role without being uncomfortable.
One significant feature of his ideal man and ideal woman seems to be the capacity
for true love. Love is the one essential human virtue; the rest is mere role-playing.
Cleopatra’s character must be seen in this light if it is to be seen sympathetically.
Shakespeare has stated more than once that the world is a stage and that we are
merely players. Playing roles successfully would imply not the mere understanding
of one’s own part but an involvement with the parts of others as well. On stage,
every character must understand every other character’s part and respect it. To
understand one’s own part and the parts of others is to be able to accept others
with sympathy. Actors must do this in order to allow the play to proceed without
confusion on stage; and in life also the same performance must go on. If we can
play our roles successfully, as Cleopatra does ( but as Cordelia, Lady Macbeth,
Desdemona and some others do not) then all is well. Cordelia, Lady Macbeth
and Desdemona have each failed to understand the true psychology/nature of the
tragic hero in question. They have not really entered that area where there is a
blending of minds in the true sense. They therefore end up contributing to the
hero’s suffering.
Developing these ideas further, it may be possible to suggest that Shakespeare
was not entirely in sympathy with a man like Othello. Othello may have been a
fine general and public figure, but he seems to have been too much of the male.
He is devoid of feminine experience and is unable to enter imaginatively into
female experience. When brought into contact with a noble woman he is unable
to understand her. The same is partly true of Lear and Macbeth. But Mark Antony
has the kind of flexibility which Shakespeare seems to have approved of. As a
result, Antony is unlike the ideal Roman patriot and can find his heaven in love
alone. He can be, without getting frustrated, the “doting mallard” following a
woman whom the Roman would consider a strumpet.
Cleopatra, similarly, is not too much of woman. She is perhaps less feminine
than the other tragic heroines of Shakespeare even though she has more charm.
She can at times be almost like a man without losing her femininity. Lady Macbeth
fails when she tries to play the male role. Cleopatra is not like the traditional
woman who would allow her man to think for her. She has a mind of her own.
She would not be satisfied in accepting the submissive role of the weaker sex.
Antony and Cleopatra: Shakespeare’s Epic in Drama
131
She successfully carries out the other role. This is what Enobarbus and Agrippa
say of her:
Eno.: Upon her landing, Antony sent to her,
I invited her to supper: she replied,
It would be better he became her guest,
Which she entreated: our courteous Antony,
Whom ne’er the word of ‘No’ woman heard speak
Being barber’d ten times o’er, goes to the feast;
....
Agri.: Royal wench!
She made great Caesar lay his sword to bed;
He plough’d her, and she cropp’d. [Emphasis mine.]
(II.ii.219-27)
She too, like Antony, has the capacity for accepting contradictory situations
without being disturbed. She in fact possesses the “heavenly mingle” and seems
to remain unaffected by what ordinary mortals would be troubled or even defeated.
She has the ability, as Enobarbus says, of making “defect perfection” (II.ii.231).
She remains unaffected even by age and custom:
Age cannot wither her, nor custom stale
Her infinite variety: Other women cloy
The appetites they feed, but she makes hungry,
Where most she satisfies. For vilest things
Become themselves in her, that the holy priests
Bless her, when she is riggish.
(II.ii.235-40)
This does not mean that Cleopatra is unconscious of the problems of other women
or is unsympathetic towards them. She can be indeed as mild a woman as any,
when the need arises:
Ah women, women! Come; we have no friend
But resolution and the briefest end.
(IV.xv.90-91)
Compared to Desdemona and Cordelia, Cleopatra is much more flexible. She is
also much closer to Modern Woman. She can be in the commanding position,
like a man, and then revert back to a woman’s role with ease. Perhaps Shakespeare
felt that one who has experienced this world only through one’s own gender has
seen but half of it. It is probably for this reason that we have in Shakespeare what
M.C. Bradbrook describes as “transvestite games.”19 Unfortunately, Bradbrook does
not say enough on the subject. Similarly, even a critic of G.Wilson Knight’s stature
stops short of explicating this point. He merely says that there is in this play a
132
Journal of Social and Political Studies
blending of the sexes.20 Shakespeare’s favourite, symbolic way of suggesting this
trans-gender experience can be seen in several comedies where the heroines dress
in men’s attire and enact the roles of men. To Shakespeare, experiencing the other
gender seems to have been one of the highest points of achievement. Bradbrook
refers to the great Renaissance dream of an exchange and union of the masculine
and feminine principle.21 But to me, the exchange and union is not merely an
exchange or a blending of the two sexes. The entire exercise involves a certain
depth—a reaching out to the soul, as it were. Going beyond the self (caged in a
gender)—to the soul—is what seems to be desirable. It is not only the love of
man for woman that seems the necessary ideal. Love should transcend gender.
The Brihadäranyaka Upanishad says something similar:
It is not for the love of a husband that a husband is dear; but for the
love of the Soul in the husband that a husband is dear.
It is not for the love of a wife that a wife is dear; but for the love of the
Soul of a wife that a wife is dear.22
This trans-gender movement is in line with that quality of Shakespeare’s mind
which has been described as “negative-capability”.
Antony and Cleopatra are perhaps Shakespeare’s greatest lovers as well as his
ideal human beings because they have this extreme flexibility and this capacity to
transcend gender. There are, undoubtedly, some references in the text which make
Antony and Cleopatra slaves of lust. On the surface, they appear to be sensual
and physical but even from the first scene there are references to their higher love.
The end of the play shows them to be lovers of a unique kind. Other characters
in the play, who are unable to see their soul-union, belittle them. But being
spiritual (as opposed to being merely physical), the love of Antony and Cleopatra
transcends gender. They would have loved each other as much even if they
belonged to the same sex. Each is able to empathise with the other. There are
several references to this trans-gender movement in Antony and Cleopatra.
Significantly, Octavius says that Antony
. . . is not more manlike
Than Cleopatra; nor the queen of Ptolemy
More womanly than he.
(I.iv.5-7)
Cleopatra says:
. . . now I have nothing
Of woman in me.
(V.ii.236-37)
When Enobarbus says, “Hush, here comes Antony” (I.ii.76), it is Cleopatra who
actually enters. There is a reference to Antony violating manhood (III.x.23), and
Enobarbus says to Antony: “Transform us not to women” (IV.iii.36). And Antony
remorses: “I . . . condemn myself, to lack/ The courage of a woman” (IV.xiv.56-
Antony and Cleopatra: Shakespeare’s Epic in Drama
133
60). Some effect of this filters down to others. Canidius says, “our leader’s led/
And we are women’s men” (III.vii.68-69). And again, “. . . young boys and girls/
Are level now with men (IV.xv.65-66).
Shakespeare achieves much by this fluidity of gendered experience. It is as if
nobility is not to love the other for what he has (in material, political or sexual
terms), but for what one is spiritually. The world of Antony and Cleopatra is
perplexing if seen in social terms. What may be the cherished ideal in society
(particularly the feudalistic) may be of no value in the world of the lovers. Thus
worldly success, political power, patriotic leaning, love of spouse, mean little to
them. This attitude is like Keats’ belief that what the imagination seizes as beauty
must be truth. Thus social approval becomes less desirable than what is deeply
felt in the heart and soul.
Octavius Caesar, who symbolises the worldly man (materialistic, political,
powerful, i.e. socially successful) says this of Antony:
. . . he fishes, drinks, and wastes
The lamps of night in revel; is not more manlike
Than Cleopatra; nor the queen of Ptolemy
More womanly than he. . . . You should find there
A man who is the abstract of all faults
That all men follow.
(I.iv.4-9)
The faults of Antony are faults in the social sense only. Lepidus says to Octavius
very aptly, almost as if he were Shakespeare’s mouthpiece:
I must not think there are
Evils enow to darken all his goodness;
His faults, in him, seem as the spots of heaven,
More fiery by night’s blackness, hereditary,
Rather than purchas’d; what he cannot change,
Than what he chooses.
(I.iv.10-15)
Antony may be wanting by social standards, but seen independently of society,
Antony’s faults seem “as the spots of heaven”. In this sense Antony and Cleopatra
may be considered an apotheosis of the spirit of man. It can be considered a poem
on the supremacy of spirit over body, impulse over social law, and intuition over
intellect. One of the key messages of the play is conveyed through Antony,
“Kingdoms are clay: our dungy earth alike/ Feeds beast as man;” (I.i.35-36).
Shakespeare is taking an antimaterialistic position, as he has often done. In King
Lear, for instance, the Fool tells the shattered Lear about the worthlessness of the
crown: “Nuncle, give me an egg, and I’ll give thee two crowns” (I.iv.152-53). The
human world (social, moral, political) can lead to a state in which man and beast
134
Journal of Social and Political Studies
are quite alike. The “dungy earth” feeds both in the same way. The earth is a baser
element. Cleopatra says she is fire and air and hence above earth. Antony uses
the adjective “dungy” to show his dissatisfaction with the earth. He, after all, has
the “heavenly mingle” in him. If man is to be different to beast, he must exist at
the spiritual level where worldly considerations melt into insignificance. The
manner in which Antony dies is evidence of this attitude. This Antony has
advanced far beyond the one we saw in Julius Caesar. In the earlier play, Antony
possessed the courtier’s art just as he did a calculating worldliness. In the later
play he has clearly become spiritual. In Antony and Cleopatra he gives up the world,
of which he had become a “triple pillar” by hard means. He has also advanced to
a consciousness where there is little difference between life and death. He embraces
death as a lover going to his beloved’s bed.
Little wonder then, that Antony does not think it necessary to be with either
Fulvia or Octavia, both of whom he has wedded in the social sense. It is not that
he does not sympathise with them. It is just that they are not his soul-mates.
Cleopatra, similarly, cannot be judged as a member of society, playing a social
role and enjoying a corresponding social status. She is queen-milkmaid, strumpetgoddess, mistress-wife, all in one. But there is one role—not social—which she
seems most keen to play: that of Antony’s soul-mate. She too, like Antony happily
gives up the material world and embraces death. For her the mighty Octavius
has never been more than “the scarce-bearded Caesar”. She throws him out of
her life as one would a rotten apple.
The problem for Shakespeare was how to justify his Antony and his Cleopatra
to an audience which was clearly not as progressive and advanced as he was. It
must have been a teasing problem to validate socially a man and a woman who
must appear like social deviants.
III
Shakespeare seems to have invented a method of justifying his hero and heroine.
He probably found a double-edged strategy in his use of the following formula:
(a) Elevating Antony and Cleopatra to the stature of gods every now and
again by presenting them through an imagery of magnitude and grandeur.
(b) Blending epic and drama into a new literary form, let us call it the
“dramatic epic”, and thus being able to inflate the stature of his
protagonists. If he had written in the form of the traditional epic, he may
not have felt as confident since he had been dissatisfied with his handling
of narrative verse. If he had written just another drama, he may not have
been able to deify his protagonists because they would seem awkward
and unconvincing in the company of the other characters. It may be
pointed out here that Shakespeare was trying out a similar experiment
in Troilus and Cressida but had not quite succeeded in that play. In Troilus,
Shakespeare had the additional burden of looking after a double plot.
Troilus remained rather contrived and artificial but the time gap of four
years seems to have brought about artistic maturity. In Antony and
Antony and Cleopatra: Shakespeare’s Epic in Drama
135
Cleopatra, Shakespeare managed to do the virtually impossible: making
his protagonists remain human and godlike simultaneously. This was
achieved by a skilful blending of the dramatic and epic forms.
Much criticism on Antony and Cleopatra has addressed itself to the apotheosis of
Antony and Cleopatra but strangely none treats of the real reason for the
apotheosis. G. Wilson Knight, who has always been outstanding in his explication
of Shakespeare, has said merely this of the apotheosis:
Here finite and infinite are to be blended. Throughout we have a new
vital complexity surpassing other plays; a wider horizon, a richer content.23
But this observation hardly takes us further in understanding the process of
character-magnification which the poet so successfully weaves into the play. Others
like Michael Payne24 and Richard Hillman25 talk at length about the apotheosis
but their reasons for doing so are very different. They don’t get to the root of the
apotheosis.
From the very opening dialogue of Antony and Cleopatra, Shakespeare’s chief
concern seems to be to put forward the central problem and then to tide over
the hurdles that present themselves in the way of its solution. Both Antony and
Cleopatra are introduced with their faults, as they would appear to society. Philo
is virtually a nobody in the play, but he is like any member of a society which is
critical of the licentiousness described below:
Philo: Nay, but this dotage of our general’s
O’erflows the measure . . .
. . . his captain’s heart,
. . . reneges all temper,
And is become the bellows and the fan
To cool a gipsy’s lust . . .
. . . and you shall see in him
The triple pillar of the world transform’d
Into a strumpet’s fool.
(I.i.1-13)
The very first word, “Nay” opens a debate about the respectability of Antony and
Cleopatra. Philo is disagreeing with Demetrius’s (unmentioned though implicit)
response to their behaviour. Antony’s dotage is overflowing the “measure”. The
measure relates to social custom and expectation. Whereas Antony is Fulvia’s
husband, and should ideally be with Octavius, helping Rome in its onward march
towards aggrandisement and prosperity, all he is doing is to foolishly spend his
time lusting after a strumpet. Whether it is actually lust or love it will take the
entire play to decide, though even in the first scene we do get a glimpse of its
spirituality. From the play it would appear that Shakespeare is questioning the
very basis of society. The reasons for which society came into existence—the
general preservation of man’s interests and his larger happiness—seem to have been
136
Journal of Social and Political Studies
rendered meaningless. The demands of the social world need not always be in
agreement with the world of individual pleasure and gratification. The individual
is often sacrificed for the general welfare of a system. Social life has a definite
rationale and yet is only what may be called a necessary evil. These lines of Byron
would support such a view:
Society is now one polished horde,
Formed of two mighty tribes, the Bores and Bored.
(Don Juan XIII.xcv)
The mind has been behind the creation of society—but there are the heart and
the soul—which do not always tread the mind’s path. Antony and Cleopatra brings
up some very basic conflicts that arise in society. Should a married man revel in
the company of a woman other than his wife? Can a man doing so still be
considered respectable, especially when he is guilty of neglecting his duty towards
his country?
In order to justify his hero and heroine, Shakespeare has tried to distinguish
them from other people. Over and again they are raised to the level of the gods.
Gods are not hampered by social morality: they can choose their own values and
modes of living. Shakespeare raises the protagonists’ stature by projecting them
through an imagery that suggests immensity and magnitude:
Eternity was in our lips, and eyes,
Bliss in our brows’ bent; none our part so poor,
But was a race of heaven.
(I.iii.35-37)
He takes pains to keep up this imagery of magnification from beginning to end,
a job which in a lesser poet would result in tedium. There are, however, moments
in the play when Antony and Cleopatra are allowed to appear like ordinary
mortals. But these moments are few and short-lived. Given below are instances
of how the two characters are often shown as gods, or larger than life at least:
The general’s dotage overflows the measure of ordinary people. His eyes have
“glow’d like plated Mars”; his heart “in the scuffles of great fights hath burst the
buckles on his breast”; and he is “a triple pillar of the world”. By line seventeen
of the first scene we have already been told by one of the characters that Antony’s
love (not lust) for Cleopatra needs a new heaven and a new earth to fit into. The
biblical connotation of the line takes the man closer to spiritual, rather than
sensual, love. Soon after these hyperbolic descriptions of Antony, we are introduced
to Octavius who (though another triple pillar of the world, and who had a virtually
godlike stature in history) is yet presented very differently, in a somewhat paltry
fashion. He is called “the scarce bearded Caesar” and later described as “the boy
Caesar” (III.xiii.18 and IV.i.1). Fulvia, similarly, is merely described as “shrilled
tongued”. These descriptions of Octavius and Fulvia make them both rather
common figures. Later in the text Octavia will be described as “low voiced”, “dull
of tongue and dwarfish” (III.iii.12-16). Shakespeare is using the method of
Antony and Cleopatra: Shakespeare’s Epic in Drama
137
contrast—human-gods as opposed to common men and women.
Having presented Octavius and Fulvia through an imagery bereft of grandeur,
in the first scene, Shakespeare returns to the spiritual qualities of Antony and
Cleopatra thus highlighting the difference between them and the common
materialistic lot.
Let Rome in Tiber melt, and the wide arch
Of the rang’d empire fall! Here is my space,
Kingdoms are clay: our dungy earth alike
Feeds beast as man; the nobleness of life
Is to do thus: when such a mutual pair,
And such a twain can do’t, in which I bind,
On pain of punishment, the world to weet
We stand up peerless.
(I.i. 33-39)
Antony’s spirituality and nobility are reflected in the choice he has made. He has
not opted for a life of material gratification. Instead he has asked for a life of
quality; with Cleopatra. With her he achieves the true godlike state; the true
nobility. The wide arches of the ranged empire are not more attractive to him
than the little space beside her. His existence with her is like a nirvana before
which every other consideration is insignificant. He achieves his higher self in
her company. Having failed as a social, political, and worldly person Antony can
still draw this praise from Agrippa: “A rarer spirit never/ Did steer humanity”
(V.i.30-31). The coming together of the lovers is no ordinary meeting. It is a soulunion which puts them towering above the rest of the world:
We stand up peerless.
(I.i.39)
Significantly, whereas others cannot understand the true nature of this world (“the
world to weet”), the lovers do understand it when they stand up above the rest.
Reason and intelligence seem to be limited, but instinct and impulse are without
such boundaries.
In the first scene we see Antony putting aside the social problem, related to
marriage, without any vexation. When Cleopatra asks him why he married Fulvia
if he did not love her, he merely says:
Now for the love of Love, and her soft hours,
Let’s not confound the time with conference harsh.
(I.i.44-45)
The love of Love is the love of goddess Venus. How can human considerations
interfere with divine bliss?
In the second scene of Act One, we similarly learn of Cleopatra’s superhuman
traits:
138
Journal of Social and Political Studies
Ant.: She is cunning past man’s thought.
Eno.: Alack, sir, no her passions are made of
nothing but the finest part of pure love.
We cannot call her winds and waters sighs
and tears; they are greater storms and tempests
than almanacs can report. This cannot be
cunning in her, if it be, she makes a
shower of rain as well as Jove
(I.ii.143-149)
Cleopatra will later be called Venus, Isis, witch, fairy, spell, serpent of old Nile,
and “thou grave charm”. She is often referred to as Egypt itself. Age cannot wither
her and custom cannot stale her. Besides, she has “immortal longings” in her. The
famous barge scene stands out in the reader’s mind and she remains there as Venus,
enthroned, rather than an ordinary human. Of course she is, once or twice,
brought to the lowest level to confuse the reader who would cling hard to his
social conscience. Even a critic as sane as Edward Dowden tends to see her as an
enigma:
And of Cleopatra what shall be said? Is she a creature of the same breed
as Cato’s daughter, Portia? Does the one word woman include natures
so diverse? Or is Cleopatra . . . no mortal woman, but Lilith who ensnared
Adam before the making of Eve?26
Between the first two scenes of the play, in which the protagonists are presented
through images of immensity, and the last where the same impression is conveyed
with a sense of finality, there are several references to the two towering above the
rest. For the sake of convenience, I turn to the last scene first, where Antony’s
superhuman size is communicated through a plethora of visual and auditory
images:
His legs bestrid the ocean, his rear’d arm
Crested the world: his voice was propertied
As all the tuned spheres, and that to friends:
But when he meant to quail, and shake the orb,
He was as rattling thunder. For his bounty,
There was no winter in’t: an autumn ’twas,
That grew the more by reaping: his delights
Were dolphin-like they show’d his back above
The element they lived in: in his livery
Walk’d crowns and crownets: realms and islands were
As plates dropp’d from his pocket.
(V.ii.82-92)
In addition to Antony’s physical description given at the beginning, there are more
descriptions of his larger-than-life stature—his legs bestriding the ocean, his arm
cresting the world, his voice having the music of the spheres as well as the volume
Antony and Cleopatra: Shakespeare’s Epic in Drama
139
of rattling thunder. Besides, we are introduced to his immense generosity which
can give in charity vast islands and kingdoms.
Between the introductory and concluding scenes of the play, the same
process—the enlargement of the hero and heroine—goes on.
Cleo.: Lord of lords
O infinite virtue, com’st thou smiling from
The world’s great snare uncaught?
(IV.viii.16-18)
Antony says to Cleopatra:
Make mingle with our rattling tabourines,
That heaven and earth may strike their sounds together,
Applauding our approach.
(IV.viii.37-39)
Of the above lines, Joseph Summers has this to say: “As the scene ends with the
beginning of a triumphal march, Antony’s voice creates the military music of an
almost supernatural Coriolanus . . .”27 The process goes on; Antony says:
. . . when I cried ‘Ho!’
Like boys unto a muss, kings would start forth.
And cry ‘Your will?’
(III.xiii.90-92)
Again he says:
I, that with my sword
Quarter’d the world, and o’er green Neptune’s back
With ships made cities, . . .
(IV.xiv.57-59)
Yet again he is described as “The demi-Atlas of this earth, the arm/ And
burgonet of men” (I.v.23-24). He can say for himself,
The shirt of Nessus is upon me: teach me
Alcides, thou mine ancestor, thy rage
Let me lodge Lichas on the horns o’ th’ moon.
(IV.xii.43-45)
Antony can even “outstare lightning”.
Harold Fisch, in an illuminating article, suggests how Antony and Cleopatra
“lay claim to mythological status and who at every turn adopt the posture of figures
in a fertility ritual.”28 Fisch links Antony with Mars, Hercules, Bacchus, Osiris,
and the Sun. Cleopatra is similarly linked with Venus, Isis (who “is no ordinary
goddess. She is in fact the ultimate matrix of nature”), goddess Proserpine, and
Eve. Besides, he points out that she has a changeless,
timeless character, which is also clearly marked in her own
140
Journal of Social and Political Studies
speech where she asserts her antiquity, her immortal, fixed
and absolute quality:
‘Think on me
That I am with Pheobus’ amorous pinches black,
And wrinkled deep in time.’29
Fisch does see the inflated, mythological status of the lovers but does not quite
see the consequences of such an inflation. He merely discovers an irony in the
inflation.30
The reason for enlarging the stature of Antony and Cleopatra seems to be
rather plain. Shakespeare is elevating the two characters so that they may appear
different to the others. They are placed on a higher plane, on a colossal scale,
making others look ordinary in comparison. A.C.Bradley has observed that Antony
and Cleopatra sit “in their paradise like gods.”31 They can say proudly, as the others
in the play cannot, “We have kissed away/ Kingdoms and provinces”. The result
is that we tend to consider them exceptional people. It is not we alone who do
that, other characters frequently do the same, and through them our responses
are monitored. Note for instance, the reaction of priests to Cleopatra’s charm.
Other women would not get the same response from priests:
For vilest things
Become themselves in her, that the holy priests
Bless her, when she is riggish.
(II.ii.238-40)
However, the grand scale on which Shakespeare would like his hero and heroine
to be seen needs more than enlargement of imagery. It is here that Shakespeare’s
innovative expertise comes into play. Shakespeare writes a play which encompasses
several characteristics of an epic. Antony and Cleopatra should not be judged merely
as a play. Its purpose is to touch epic heights; and a simple play would not achieve
such an effect. In another play, people would be judged by the moral standards
of their society. But here the social dimension snaps without appearing to do so.
Shakespeare seems to have created a new kind of genre, the dramatic-epic. Dr
Johnson had complained that in Antony and Cleopatra events proceed “without
any art of connection or care of disposition.”32 The criticism may be justified in
one who would insist on the purity of literary forms in the classicist sense. But if
the play is seen as a combination of two literary forms, then the criticism does
not seem quite valid. It should be kept in mind that a pure epic has never been
written33 and when Shakespeare uses this form he changes it to some extent. For
example instead of one epical hero Shakespeare introduces two protagonists in
Antony and Cleopatra.
M.H.Abrams defines an epic in the following manner:
Antony and Cleopatra: Shakespeare’s Epic in Drama
141
It is a long narrative poem on a great and serious subject related in an
elevated style, and centres on a heroic or quasi-divine figure on whose
actions depends the fate of a tribe, a nation, or the human race.34
This definition would be quite befitting for Antony and Cleopatra but for the fact
that the play is not a “long narrative poem”. This is where Shakespeare has
innovated upon the form of the epic. He has created the epic in dramatic form.
Further, the play can be seen as a long poem rather than a drama because there is
very little action in it. Little happens in the play. Harley Granville Barker says
that Shakespeare “reduces the actual story to simplicity itself.35 Much of the
dramatic interest is transferred to the poetry of the work. The poetry of this play
outdoes the poetry of the other plays of Shakespeare. What is lost in dramatic
terms is regained in the poetic. Given below is a list of epic features which have
entered this play.36
(a) The subject of the play is indeed great, complex, and heroic. Much of
the second section of this monograph deals with it. It may be said that
the play opens a debate on certain social issues, like public versus private
interests, individual versus state, law versus impulse, etc. The hero is torn
between these opposing forces.
(b) The hero of an epic is a figure of national or cosmic importance. Antony
is such a man.
(c) The setting of the epic is always on an ample scale—world-wide or even
larger. We can think of Antony’s wanting “a new heaven and a new earth”
to accommodate his love. Epic imagination is expansive. It proceeds in
ever widening circles. Shakespeare’s world grows in this play until there
is a meeting point between this world and the other.
(d) The action of an epic involves superhuman deeds. To give up the world
for love is itself in a sense, a superhuman act. But Antony, in the role of
a Hercules-figure is certainly superhuman. He can make a statement like,
“Let me lodge Lichas on the horns o’th’ moon” in a casual manner as
though this was like picking up a feather. He is a “demi-Atlas”, the Sun,
Mars, and Osiris. He can “outstare lightning”, and bestride the ocean.
Similarly the goddess-image of Cleopatra, her “immortal longings”, her
relationships with Mars and Phoebus and her timeless personality make
her superhuman indeed.
(e) Gods, or other supernatural beings play an active role in an epic. Hercules
leaves Antony in Act IV. Shakespeare devotes a scene to this event even
though the incident does not affect the plot structurally. Cleopatra talks
of her communion with the sun: “Think on me/ That I am with Phoebus’
amorous pinches black,/ And wrinkled deep in Time” (I.v.27-29). Besides,
as Arthur Bell informs, Shakespeare uses the heroic convention to describe
Antony’s relation to Time.37 Time has been pictured as goddess Fortune
in the play. Antony leaves and returns to the world of Time. However,
Journal of Social and Political Studies
142
(f )
(g)
(h)
(i)
(j)
(k)
in this play the hero and heroine are themselves presented as gods. Hence
other gods and goddesses seem to fade out in their presence.
Northrop Frye sees the epic as a post-mythical genre. “The hero of a myth
is a god, the hero of an epic has authority, passion and powers of
expression far greater than ours, but what he does is subject both to social
criticism and the order of nature.”38 Antony and Cleopatra are very much
in this position.
In Antony and Cleopatra, as in epics, divine worship is replaced by human
awe, an awe which is prodigious but still remains human. “Epic awe as
distinguished from religious or mythical awe, springs from the
circumstance that a man can commit an extraordinary act while still
remaining limited. The hero is understood to be subject to ignorance,
foolhardiness and above all death.”39 Antony and Cleopatra inspire this
awe and remain human (as they do come back to the human level now
and then). Similarly, they share with the epic hero in remaining subject
to ignorance, foolhardiness and death.
A man’s name is very significant in heroic poetry—it becomes
synonymous with the sum of his achievements. His “action is knowable
and is known, and is known to be his”.40 The names of Antony and
Cleopatra are important in the heroic sense. Shakespeare even says clearly,
“Antony will be Antony,” and “But since my lord/ Is Antony again, I
will be Cleopatra” (III.xiii.186-87).
Epic narrative is a series of adjustments between the hero’s capacities and
his limitations. Antony’s frequent movement towards Egypt and then back
to Rome is indicative of these adjustments.
That Antony and Cleopatra contains the soul of an epic can be best
demonstrated by the following primary quality of epics: “The subject of
all epic poetry might be said to be politics not limited to society, a politics
embracing the natural and fabulous worlds, embracing the moral or
spiritual worlds involving ultimately the divine.”41 The world of Antony
and Cleopatra is made up of this politics which transcends the social order
and co-exists at the spritual as well as this-worldly planes.
The language and dialogue of this play are also those that resemble the
language and dialogue of epic-verse. Speech in epics “is ampler and more
formal than common speech; it is the vehicle by which the political and
symbolic associations of an action or image are commonly revealed, and
by which they are situated in the historical context”.42 At the same time
the language of an epic being grand, and in a higher style, must yet have
a living impulse which imparts energy to men and things. The actions
of the lovers are described through such symbolic and living associations:
This dotage of our general’s/O’erflows the measure,
The triple pillar of the world transform’d/ Into a strumpet’s fool,
Antony, that blood of thine/ Is Caesar’s homager,
Antony and Cleopatra: Shakespeare’s Epic in Drama
143
Let Rome in Tiber melt, and the wide arch/ Of the rang’d empire fall,
The nobleness of life/ Is to do thus,
Sir, sometimes, when he is not Antony/ He comes too short of that
great property/ Which still should go with Antony,
By the fire/ That quickens Nilus’s slime, I go from hence/ Thy soldier,
servant, making peace or war,/ As thou affects,
Look . . . / How this Herculean Roman does become/ The carriage of
this chafe,
Get me ink and paper,/ He shall have every day a several greeting,/ Or
I’ll unpeople Egypt,
. . . from edge to edge/ Of the world, I would pursue it,
For her own person,/ It beggar’d all description: She did lie/ In her
pavilion—cloth of gold, of tissue —/ O’er-picturing that Venus where
we see/ That fancy outwork nature,
The world and my great office, will sometimes/ Divide me from my
bosom,
He will to his Egyptian dish again: then shall the sighs of Octavia blow
the fire up in Caesar,
Good majesty,/ Herod of Jewry dare not look upon you,/ But when
you are well pleas’d,
Antony,/ Claps on his sea-wing, and (like a doting-mallard)/ . . . flies
after her,
When my good stars, that were my former guides,/ Have empty left
their orbs, and shot their fires/ Into the abysm of hell,
The three-nook’d world/ Shall bear the olive freely,
Make mingle with our rattling tambourines,/ That heaven and earth
may strike their sounds together/ Applauding our approach,
. . . comest thou smiling from/ The world’s great snare uncaught?
But I will be/ A bridegroom in my death, and run into ’t/ as to a lover’s
bed,
. . . but you gods will give us/ Some faults to make us men,
I am fire, and air; my other elements/ I give to baser life,
The stroke of death is as a lover’s pinch,/ Which hurts; and is desir’d,
Dissolve, thick cloud, and rain, that I may say,/ The gods themselves
do weep.
The above list is not exhaustive. The play is full of a “high-style” which impresses
the reader both by its extraordinary symbolic order as well as by its living quality.
The surprising thing is that here, as perhaps nowhere else, a poet writes in a
language which can be said to be heroic and spontaneous, romantic and classicist,
of speech and of the spirit, as it were, simultaneously.
Returning to the crucial third question, which this monograph attempts to
answer, I need say that Shakespeare was trying to convey something that could
144
Journal of Social and Political Studies
not have been conveyed directly. He was trying to show what he considered ideal
in human action. His ideal man and woman may not have coincided with the
ideal of a narrow-minded social-system. With this new compounded genre,
Shakespeare was conveying his nonconformist vision of the best in human beings.
He is thus able to present the protagonists in a way so as to justify their ways to
men. Milton too had a similar kind of problem when he wrote of Satan, in the
first two books of Paradise Lost. He too had to treat with respect and seriousness,
a character that earlier tradition had cast into the mould of the villain-comedian.
Milton has been misunderstood as one who was unconsciously taking the side of
the Devil. He too presented Satan in the same, larger than life, form. Milton could
not have allowed Satan to appear as an ordinary villain-cum-comedian. The epic
form required that the contest between the forces of good and evil be not too
unequal. For the contest to be effective, it was necessary to make Satan impressive.
Hence Satan was presented on an ample scale—with huge shield and spear.
Shakespeare, for different reasons, raised his protagonists to the level of gods by
introducing the epic dimension into his play.
The form of Antony and Cleopatra has troubled several critics. It does not fit
clearly into any of the traditional moulds. Coleridge called the play, the most
wonderful of the historical plays.43 (emphasis mine) Harold H. Fisch too felt that
tragedy has given way to history in this play.44 A.C. Bradley has not clubbed his
play with the four “pure-tragedies” of Shakespeare.45 G.K.Hunter does not quite
accept this view of Bradley’s46 because for him this play is as much a tragedy as
any other. Bradley had found it a unique play because it was the only play in
which Shakespeare had reserved an entire last act for his heroine.47 Besides, Bradley
does not find it dramatic enough as compared to Shakespeare’s pure-tragedies.48
It is a rarely acted play, and is not painful enough to be a tragedy. To Bradley, the
subject matter of the play too lacks something which one finds in the other pure
tragedies.49
More recently, Richard Hillman has suggested that in writing Antony and
Cleopatra Shakespeare has changed the typical tragic form.50 To Hillman the play
has decisively moved beyond tragedy into a world like that of Shakespearean
romance—a world whose essential quality is a “sense of the participation of the
mythic in human life”.51
It may be said, then, that the play is tragic yet not a tragedy and that it is at
the same time a history play as well as a romance. E.M.W. Tillyard, however, does
not give it the status of a pure history play (nor do other critics for that matter)
because it does not cover English history, nor does it voice the Tudor myth, nor
again does it foster patriotism as the other history plays of Shakespeare do.52 In
fact it seems to go against Octavius, the patriot. To call the play a romance would
also limit and misrepresent it. At the heart of each of Shakespeare’s romances lies
an “organic unity built up of breakdown and reconstruction.”53 This is clearly
not present in Antony and Cleopatra.
Antony and Cleopatra can loosely be classed with the plays which are grounded
Antony and Cleopatra: Shakespeare’s Epic in Drama
145
in Roman history. But even there the play is the odd one out. Roman heroes
tend to be patriotic, showing a preference for public duty over private sentiment.
Since Antony has chosen to give up public interest in favour of his personal
involvement, the play does not quite belong to the category to which Julius Caesar
and Coriolanus do. It is, on the contrary, their antithesis.
It can definitely be seen as Shakespeare’s final definition of love, a definition
which runs through Romeo and Juliet and Othello and culminates in this play.
But to see the three plays as a group under the label of love-tragedies is not free
from fault. Romeo and Juliet are “star crossed” lovers, the other two pairs cannot
be similarly described. Othello, it is sometimes argued, is more in love with himself
than with Desdemona, and is the only tragedic hero who kills his beloved. Antony
and Cleopatra have the freedom of choice. They choose their lives as well as their
deaths. Fate, or jealousy, or self-centredness plays little or no role in their lives.
Antony and Cleopatra defies categorisation. If at all, it can be grouped with
any plays of Shakespeare it is the problem plays. Ernest Schanzer has classified
the play under this category.54 But unfortunately for Schanzer, Antony and
Cleopatra is a problem play only because of its structural pattern. To me this play
is not a problem play on the basis of its structure alone, but more so because of
its problematic content. What Shakespeare says here is not traditional by any
means. The way he says it, therefore, is also untraditional; it involves the breaking
down of traditional genres and the creation of a new one—a dramatic epic.
NOTES
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
See Stanley Wells (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Shakespeare Studies (Cambridge, 1986),
128.
Kenneth Muir, “Shakespeare’s Poets”, Shakespeare Survey (Cambridge, 1970) Vol. 23, 95.
Ibid.
Ibid.
Ibid.
Ibid., 98.
See René Wellek and Austin Warren, Theory of Literature (New York, 1968), 258, and
Edward Said, The World, the Text and the Critic (London, 1991), 126.
J. W. Lever, “The Poems”, Shakespeare Survey (Cambridge, 1962), Vol. 15, 19.
Ibid.
This point has been made by Enobarbus in the text (II.ii.205-6) and by several scholars like
Adrien Bonjour, “From Shakespeare’s Venus to Cleopatra’s Cupids”, Shakespeare Survey, Vol,
74-9, and Joseph H. Summers, Dreams of Love and Power: On Shakespeare (Oxford, 1984),
117.
J.W. Lever suggests that Shakespeare wanted to write narrative poetry but never quite wrote
the best kind of narrative poetry. Compared to his other art-forms his narrative-art remained
inferior. See 19-25.
Ibid., 19.
Ibid., 19-25.
Ibid., 24-25.
See D. C. Allen, “Some Observations on The Rape of Lucrece”, Shakespeare Survey, Vol. 15, 95.
Ibid., 94-95.
Morris Weitz, “Literature Without Philosophy”, Shakespeare Survey (Cambridge: 1975) Vol.
146
Journal of Social and Political Studies
28, 31.
18. Edward Jayne, “Comments on the Homosexual Imagination”, College English (1975), Vol.
37, No.1, 62-67 suggests that Shakespeare’s homosexual imagination tormented him and led
to the creation of several of his characters and situations.
19. M.C. Bradbrook, Shakespeare: The Poet in his World (New York, 1978), 214.
20. G. Wilson Knight, The Imperial Theme (London, 1931, This ed. 1972), 302.
21. M.C. Bradbrook, Shakespeare: The poet in his world, 214.
22. See Juan Mascaro, translated, The Bhagavad Gita (New Delhi, 1962), 31.
23. G. Wilsom Knight, The Imperial Theme, 197.
24. Michael Payne, “The Polarity Pattern in Antony and Cleopatra”, Shakespeare Quarterly (Vol.
xxiii, Summer 1972, No.3), 271-294.
25. Richard Hillman, “Antony, Hercules, and Cleopatra: ‘the bidding of the gods’ and ‘the
subtlest maze of all’,” Shakespeare Quarterly (Vol. xxiii, Summer 1972, No. 3), 295-306.
26. See Shakespeare: Antony and Cleopatra, ed. John Russell Brown (London, 1968), 39.
27. Joseph Summers, Dreams of Love and Power, 127.
28. Harold Fisch, “Antony and Cleopatra: The limits of Mythology”, Shakespeare Survey (1970)
No. 23, 59.
29. Ibid., 60.
30. Ibid., 59-67.
31. A.C. Bradley, “Shakespeare’s Antony and Cleopatra”, Shakespeare: Antony and Cleopatra, ed.
John Russell Brown, 75.
32. Samuel Johnson, Ibid., 27.
33. See Thomas Greene, “The Norms of Epic”, Perspectives on Poetry, ed. James L. Calderwood
and Harold E. Toliver, (New York, 1968), 194.
34. M.H. Abrams, A Glossary of Literary Terms (Madras, 1986), 49.
35. Harley Grenville-Barker, Shakespeare: ‘Antony and Cleopatra’ ed. John Russell Brown, 88.
36. I must acknowledge, here, the debt I owe to Thomas Greene’s views on the norms of epics.
Much of what follows relies heavily on Greene’s article. To me, this is one of the best pieces
on the subject.
37. Arthur Bell, “Time and Convention in Antony and Cleopatra” Shakespeare Quarterly (Vol.
Xxiv, Summer 1973, No.3), 260.
38. See Thomas Greene, 198.
39. Ibid., 199.
40. Ibid., 199-200.
41. Ibid., 201.
42. Ibid., 203.
43. See Shakespeare: ‘Antony and Cleopatra’, ed. John Russell Brown, 63.
44. Harold Fisch, 65.
45. See A.C. Bradley, Shakespearean Tragedy (London, 1904).
46. See The Cambridge Companion to Shakespeare Studies, ed. Stanley Wells, 123-124.
47. A.C. Bradley, “Shakespeare’s Antony and Cleopatra”, 79.
48. Ibid., 66.
49. Ibid.
50. Richard Hillman, 449.
51. Ibid., 443.
52. See E.M.W. Tillyard, Shakespeare’s History Plays (1944) revised edition (Harmondsworth,
1969) and R.L. Smallwood, “Shakespeare’s Use of History”, The Cambridge Companion to
Shakespeare Studies, 143-62.
53. See D.A. Traversi, “The Last Plays of Shakespeare”, The Age of Shakespeare, ed. Boris Ford
(Harmondsworth, 1955), 257.
54. Ernest Schanzer, The Problem Plays of Shakespeare (London, 1963).
Indo-Persian Historiography up to the Thirteenth Century
147
Book Review
Indo-Persian Historiography up to the
Thirteenth Century
Iqtidar Husain Siddiqui
Primus Books, Delhi, 2010, pp 199, Rs. 795, ISBN: 978-81-908918-0-6
Historiography, it is said, is the science of committing past events and their causes
to writing. This seemingly simple task is fraught with numerous constraints and
pitfalls. It requires among other things a thorough knowledge of the sources, a
sense of critical enquiry and judgment and a command over language. Writing
about the history of historiography and that too of Medieval India is even more
onerous task and scholars claiming to be expert in this field in India are few and
far between. Professor I.H. Siddiqui belongs to that rare group of historians who
have undertaken to take a plunge in a practically unchartered field and use his
skill and expertise as a historian to study Indo-Persian historiography of the
thirteenth century. It is common knowledge that by the time the Delhi Sultanate
was established in India at the turn of the thirteenth century, Muslim
historiography had reached a take off stage. Arab and Persian historians had already
produced a number of first rate histories and had created a distinct tradition of
history writing of their own. The Indo-Persian historians naturally looked towards
these two traditions for inspiration and it is not at all surprising that the Arab
and Persian traditions of historiography influenced the historians writing in the
Indian environment.
Professor Siddiqui also begins his narrative with a chapter on Arabic
historiography and its impact on Persian historians. This is followed by six
chapters, each devoted to an in-depth study of one prominent historian of the
thirteenth century. All of these six historians, Fakhr-i-Mudabbir, ‘Ali Kufi, Hasan
Nizami, Sadiduddin Muhammad ‘Awfi, Minhaj-i-Siraj Juzjani and Amir Khusrau
wrote after the foundation of the Delhi Sultanate. With the exception of ‘Ali Kufi
who translated an obscure Arabic history of the Arab conquest of Sindh into
Persian, which came to be known as Chachnama, the other five historians focused
on the rise of Muslim power in North India and provide valuable information
about the early Sultans of Delhi. They not only wrote about the political problems
facing the Sultanate and the individual Sultans but also shed light on the social,
cultural and administrative milieu of their time. Their style was innovative and
their approach to history writing was marked by freshness and originality. Professor
Siddiqui has taken note of these unique features of the early Sultanate
historiography. His method of analyzing these historical works is as innovative as
that of the early protagonists of Indo-Persian historiography. He begins every
chapter with a note on the early life and career of the historian before his arrival
148
Journal of Social and Political Studies
in India, follows it up with a succinct summary of the contents of his works and
concludes the chapter with incisive remarks about the author’s approach to history
and his contribution to Indo-Persian historiography.
Every chapter of this important book furnishes some vital piece of information
regarding the early history and historiography of Muslim rule in India. We are
told for instance that contrary to popular belief Hasan Nizami’s Tajul- Ma’sir
contains an account of the Delhi Sultanate till 1217 only and that Sir Henry
Elliot’s translation of the book bringing the account to 1229 is based on a
manuscript of dubious nature and hence it is not worthy of trust (pp 13, 15-16).
From chapter two we come to know that Tarikh-i Fakhruddin Mubarak Shah
Marvar-rudi (edited by Sir E. Denison Ross in 1927) containing an account of
Qutbuddin Aibak’s career in India between 1192 and 1206 is not a separate work
of Fakhr-i-Mudabbir but it is actually the preface of the historian’s first major
work Shajra-i-Ansab which he had composed in the year 1206. The same chapter
likewise reveals that Fakhr-i-Mudabbir’s famous work Adabul-Harb wa-ash-Shuja
is also not a separate work of the author but is a part of his larger work Adab ulMuluk wa-Kifayat ul-Muluk (pp 18, 23). The fifth chapter, giving an account of
Sadiduddin Muhammad ‘Awfi’s Jawami’ul Hikayat wa-Lavami’ul- Rivaayat, is
perhaps the most important component of the book in terms of providing new
information about the events related to the career of Muizuddin Muhammad bin
Sam, his lieutenants in India Qutbuddin Aibak and Nasiruddin Qabacaha as well
as some major episodes of Iltutmish’s reign. We also get to know that ‘Awfi had
compiled the Jawami’ul Hikayat at the instance of Nasiruddin Qabacha and that
Sultan Alauddin Khalji’s famous market control regulations were perhaps inspired
by ‘Awfi’s narration of a similar measure undertaken by the Qarakhanid monarch
Tamgoch Khan Ibrahim in Samarqand (pp 57- 58). The following chapter which
covers almost one third of the book’s 199 pages gives a succinct summary of the
twenty- three tabaqat of Minhaj-i-Siraj Juzjani’s famous history Tabaqat-i-Nasiri.
Minhaj, we are told, migrated to India in 1227 and before shifting his loyalty to
Iltutmish served for some time under Nasiruddin Qabacha in Sindh. He utilized
a variety of sources but wrote primarily on the basis of his vast knowledge and
experience of politics in Central Asia and India. He was not only the first scholar
to write history in the tabaqat genre but also invented a novel methodology to
criticize men in power either by communicating his views about them in a discreet
manner through hints or by praising their adversaries (pp 94, 101, 117). In the
same vein in the chapter on the historical writings of Amir Khusrau, the author
informs us that Khusrau was the first Indian born historian and his writings reflect
a strong sense of identity with India. He admired India and India’s (Hindu’s)
contribution to philosophy and astrology. He held that the Hindus were better
than the atheists or dualists as they believed in the unity of God and therefore
deserve full religious freedom. He was also the first historian who recognized the
significance of cultural and geographical factors in the making of history and
always took care to describe the topography of the routes and places that he cites
Indo-Persian Historiography up to the Thirteenth Century
149
in his works (pp 170-174).
On these and related issues the present reviewer is in agreement with the
learned author. Some arguments and methods of the book are however
problematic. Direct and indirect references to Shamsuddin Iltutmish’s
achievements in India, first as a slave officer of Qutbuddin Aibak and subsequently
as Sultan of Delhi (1211-36), in the book are unduly harsh. Professor Siddiqui’s
summary dismissal of Iltutmish as treacherous and usurper (pp 50, 131, 133, 135137) as well as his ready acceptance of ‘Awfi’s statements attributing all the political,
military, administrative and cultural attainments of Iltutmish’s reign to his Wazir
Nizam-ul-Mulk Junaidi (pp 83-87) is surprising to say the least. ‘Awfi had
dedicated his book to the Wazir and hence his exaggerated eulogization of his
patron should not be taken at its face value. In the same vein the author’s
contention that Medieval India Muslims did not distinguish one regional dialect
from the other and that they loosely used the term Hindvi for every regional dialect
spoken in India at that time (p 90, n 33) is only partially correct. There is no
doubt that in the medieval period ‘Hindi’ or ‘Hindvi’ was used as a generic term
for any Indian language. However there were scholars who clearly distinguished
between languages spoken in different parts of India. In Nuh Sipihir (1317-18),
for instance, Amir Khusrau has mentioned that in India a specific language is
spoken in every territory. He identifies these languages as Sindhi, Lahori, Kashmiri,
Kibar, Dhaur Samanadari, Tilangi, Gujar, Ma’bari, Gauri etc. and names these
languages as Hindvi or belonging to India (Amir Khusrau, Nuh Sipihir, ed. Vahid
Mirza, OUP, Calcutta, 1948, pp 179-180, quoted by S.R. Faruqi, Early Urdu
Literary Culture and History, OUP, New Delhi, 2001, pp 65-68). Likewise, spelling
of certain words in the book leaves much to be desired. Spelling the holy book
of Islam as Koran (pp 1-2, 24, 77, 146 etc.) seems inappropriate to say the least.
F. Steingass has spelled the word as Qur’an (A Comprehensive Persian-English
Dictionary, second Indian edition, New Delhi, 1981, p 962) which should be
preferred over Koran. The last name of Muhammad Ghauri’s famous slave and,
after his death, the ruler of Multan and Sindh, Nasiruddin Qabacha has also been
misspelled as Qubacha. Both Steingass (p 950) and James W. Redhouse (A Turkish
and English Lexicon, Istanbul, first published 1890, reprint, 1978, p 1430) have
spelled it as Qabacha (A short jacket, cloak or tunic). There are some typographical
errors as well. For instance Bahram Shah has been printed as Bahrain Shah (p
101) and the sentence ‘Take this Maulana, that it may be a good omen’ has been
printed as ‘Take this Maulana, that it may be a good man’ (p 98).
These are only minor blemishes and do not mar the literary or academic merit
of the book. Professor Siddiqui has produced as usual a book that amply
demonstrates his command over diverse dimensions of Medieval Indian history
as well as the Persian sources of this history. Overall this book will be a valuable
addition to many university and scholarly libraries.
150
Journal of Social and Political Studies
Women’s Rights as Human Rights
Mahendra Prasad Singh*
I
Men and women equally partake in humanity by birth, notwithstanding the
biological difference between them in terms of anatomy. Hence it is axiomatic
that women’s rights are human rights, rights that are naturally enjoyed by every
human being by virtue of being human. The supposed vulnerability of women
arising in the anatomical difference and procreative function cannot be construed
to deduce the proposition that anatomy is destiny. Differences and disparities
between men and women are, in fact, based on differential upbringing and
conditioning among the genders, and are therefore socially constructed.
Nevertheless, with the possible exception of matrilineal societies, patriarchy
has been an oppressive fact of history in practically all civilizations the world over.
Moreover, among the variety of disparities such as the ones based on race, ethnicity,
class, etc., gender disparities have been the most persistent and pernicious. With
the rise of liberalism and democracy in modern times, other disparities came to
be questioned earlier than those based on gender. This was for the reason that
the distinction between the private and the public spheres in liberalism as also
religion-based family laws of marriage and property generally kept the state out
of bounds in these matters. This is an irony and a paradox in view of glaringly
iniquitous conditions of women both nationally and internationally. In the world
today women notionally form half of the population, but perform nearly twothirds of its work hours, receive one-tenth of world‘s income, and own less than
one-hundreths of world‘s property. They are also fewer than 5 percent of the heads
of governments and lower than 10 percent of parliamentarians (popularly elected
House). Their greater vulnerability to social, cultural, and economic discrimination, and to domestic and social violence and crime in normal as well as riotous
and war situations are patent facts of life all over the world with variations only
of degrees across countries and cultures and climes (Gale Binion 1995: 511).
Even in regard to political suffrage, women happened to be the last section
of the population to be enfranchised. The problem of their social and economic
empowerment has, in fact, proved to be much more complex and intractable.
Even in terms of their political empowerment, they have still a long way to go.
But what is notable is that the present is the most propitious time for the idea of
gender equality. And no one can hold back an idea for too long whose time has
come.
II
* The Keynote Address to the National Seminar on Women’s Rights are Human Rights : Role of
Non-State Actors, Patna Women’s College / Patna University, 28-29, February, 2012.
Women’s Rights as Human Rights
151
For reasons outlined above, when human rights are stated all is not stated; it needs
to be supplemented by women’s rights as a special variant of human rights. Ideally,
a time may come when the difference between human rights and women’s rights
may dissolve or become obsolescent. In that eventuality, feminism and humanism
may become merged into one indistinguishable ideology or theory. That it has
not happened in the past cannot be taken as an improbability in the future. For
a basic lesson that philosophy of science teaches us is that the past cannot foreclose
the future. There is a certain degree of fixity in the past, but the future is wide
open. Indeed, entirely unanticipated developments in the future give us new ways
of looking back at and reinterpreting the past.
Feminist theory made its appearance earlier at the level of individual social
or political thinkers than at the level of collective political action by the peoples
or nations. There have been at least three waves of feminism in the thought of
individual political thinkers, in terms of my somewhat parsimonious version of a
review of feminist writings by Rosemarie Tong (2003). Prominent voices in the
first stage of feminist thought argued that the women must emulate the same
traits and qualities as men in order to be their equal. Mary Wollstonecraft in the
eighteenth century and John Stuart Mill in the nineteenth century illustrate this
line of thinking. Wollstonecraft in her monograph A Vindication of the Rights of
Women (1792) observed that the society expected men to be educated in “morals”
whereas women were taught ‘manners’. Men were supposed to be rational and
abstract in their thinking, and strong, whereas women were thought to be
sentimental, contingent, self-indulgent, and weak. The remedial equality with men
could be attained, according to Wollstonecraft, if women cultivated the same
virtues as men. John Stuart Mill, too, in his On the Subjection of Women (1869)
lamented their subjugation and advocated that the society must provide the same
rights and privileges as are enjoyed by men. This feminist perspective may be called
the “sameness” theorem of the feminist theory.
The second stage of the feminist thought may be called the “difference”
theorem of feminism as it stressed on the differences rather than the importance
of being the same as men. This phase also came to be marked by some degree of
cleavage between liberal feminists like Betty Friedan (1974) and radical feminists
like Sulasmith Firestone (1970) and Mary Vetterling-Braggin (1982). In fact,
liberal feminists largely continued the point of view of the British feminist thought
of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries mentioned above. As the first President
of the National Organization for Women (NOW) in the USA, Friedan took the
leading role in formulating a Bill of Rights for Women in 1967. Radical feminists
asserted their sexuality androgynously and sought sexual pleasures of all types—
heterosexual, lesbian, and autoerotic, celebrating the new developments in
reproductive, contraceptive, and genetic technology as a factor reducing the
vulnerability of women due to the biological difference with men (Firestone 1970).
152
Journal of Social and Political Studies
Some other radical feminists, on the other hand, refuted androgyny and
masculinity and advocated the ideal of essential femaleness, predicated on
“gentleness, modesty, humility, supportiveness, empathy, compassionateness,
nurturance, intuitiveness, sensitivity, unselfishness” (Vetterling-Braggin 1982 : 6).
Some yet other radical feminists emphasized the dangers of heterosexual sex
as the prime cause of male domination, macho sadism and female masochism.
Lesbianism to them appeared as a way to escape these dangers. Yet other feminists
wished to discard artificial reproductive or unproductive techniques and rely on
their natural capacity to procreate or refuse to procreate in order to enhance their
utility and respect in male estimation (Corea 1985).
The third stage of the feminist thought is marked by what may be called the
“diversity” theorem of feminism. According to this view, the women condition is
not simply defined in terms of the female gender. It is significantly determined
by the variables of race, religion, ethnicity, class, and age. Thus the question of
gender equality is confounded in a complex web of causation, almost a vicious
circle. This diversity view of feminist thought finds its most acute expression in
postmodern feminism that rejects any uniform foundational value of gender
equality and allows a radical relativism of values contingent on variety of identities
and subcultures. Thus gender emerges neither as a resultant of biology nor as an
overarching social construction but as a conceptual grid through which radically
different values can be interpreted or deconstructed and reconstructed (Lauretis
1994).
III
At the level of collective political action by the peoples and nations, the earliest
declaration of rights are human rights in general without any special or separate
concern with the rights of women. The American Declaration of Independence
made by the second Continental Congress attended by the delegates from the 13
rebellious English colonies on July 4, 1776, for example, simply stated : “We hold
these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed
by their creator with certain inalienable rights, that among these are Life, Liberty
and the pursuit of Happiness.” The Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen
made by the National Assembly of France in the wake of the French Revolution
on August 26, 1789, “resolved to set forth a solemn declaration of the natural,
inalienable and sacred rights of man...” The Declaration of the Rights of the People
of Russia and of the Working and Exploited Peoples of the world made by the
All Russian Congress of Soviets made in January 1918 set “as its fundamental
task the destruction of any exploitation of man by man, the complete abolition
of the division of society into classes, the merciless suppression of the exploiters,
the establishment of a socialist organization of society and the victory of socialism
in all countries....”
Among these early declarations of rights, the Karachi Resolution of the Indian
Women’s Rights as Human Rights
153
National Congress (29-31 March, 1931) was perhaps the first that proclaimed
“equal rights and obligations of all citizens, without any bar on account of sex.”
This resolution presaged all the fundamental rights and directive principles of state
policy that came to be guaranteed by the constitution of independent India in
1950. However, the makers of the Indian constitution stopped short of
guaranteeing some special rights of women comparable to those provisionally
guaranteed to the “socially and educationally backward classes of citizens or for
the Scheduled Castes and the Scheduled Tribes” (article 15, clause 5; the latter
added by the first constitutional amendment 1951). Representational reservation
for women to the tune of 33 percent of the local government councils in rural
and urban areas had to wait until the seventy-third and seventy-fourth
constitutional amendments in 1992/93 and the conforming laws enacted by the
state legislatures subsequently. A proposed representational reservation for women
in State Legislatures and Parliament has been debated for a decade but not yet
enacted due to lack of consensus in the political class and political parties.
IV
Now, we come to some select international declarations of human rights and scan
them from, the feminist perspective. The Universal Declaration of Human Rights
(UDHR) adopted by the General Assembly of the United Nations on December
10, 1948, provide a common standard of human rights worthy of “achievement
for all peoples and all nations” “without distinction of any kind, such as race,
colour, sex, language, religion political or other opinion, national or social origin,
property, birth or other status” (article 2). Here again we find a general prohibition
against gender-related discrimination but no special rights or reverse discrimination
in favour of women in view of their acute or abnormal backwardness.
The UDHR (1948) was subsequently supplemented by two additional
declarations by the UN General Assembly : (a) the International Covenant on
Civil and Political Rights (1966), and (b) the International Covenant on
Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966). Both came into force in 1976
following ratification by the member-states. Both the covenants guarantee the
human rights to every person, child or adult, regardless of any socio-economicpolitical differences, including those based on gender. The one and the only one
age or gender-specific human rights promised under the civil and political rights
covenant is that a death sentence shall not be imposed for crimes committed by
a person below eighteen years of age and a pregnant woman (article 5).
Feminists argue that given the grossly unequal status of women in the
prevailing laws in most countries, a gender-blind law in reality works in favour
of patriarchy. The ends of justice would not be served by anything less than an
affirmative action or reverse discrimination.
From among the myriad of other international covenants and conventions, I
intend to briefly refer the three such documents : (a) Convention on the
154
Journal of Social and Political Studies
Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women adopted by the UN
General Assembly in 1979 that came into force in 1981, (b) Declaration on the
Right of Development adopted by the UN General Assembly in 1986, and (c)
Convention on the Rights of the Child adopted by the UN General Assembly in
1989 and enforced in 1990. The convention on women’s rights seeks to ensure
complete equality with men before the law in all respects. It specifically also
declares that the adoption by states of “temporary special measures aimed at
accelerating de facto equality between men and women shall not be considered
discrimination as defined in the present convention” (article 4, clause 1). This
international sanction for affirmative action in favour of women is not evidently
matched in the national laws, however.
The Declaration on the Right to Development declares development as “an
inalienable human right by virtue of which every human person and all peoples
are entitled to participate in, contribute to and enjoy economic, social, cultural
and political development, in which all human rights and fundamental freedoms
can be fully realized” (article 1, clause 1). The convention on the child rights in
a very comprehensive charter ensuring protection against exploitation and
conditions for proper development under parental care and material assistance
and support by the state.
An analytical retrospective view on the evolution of human rights is suggestive
of different stages through which they have developed. My teacher, political
theorist Professor Christian Bay at the University of Alberta in Canada used to
talk about the growth of three packages of rights, namely, the Blue Rights or the
rights against the state engendered by the bourgeois revolutions in the UK, USA,
and France; the Red Rights or the rights against hunger produced by the socialist
revolutions in the Soviet Union, Eastern Europe, and the People‘s Republic of
China; and the Green Rights or the rights to clean environment and healthy life
created by the movements for ecological protection and sustainable development.
Similarly, others have talked about three generations of rights. The first generation
rights are primarily concerned with civil and political rights born out of the liberal
and democratic movements since the nineteenth century. These are the ‘negative’
rights against the arbitrary action by the state. The second generation rights are
primarily related to social, economic, and cultural equality and social security
typical of welfare and socialist states. The third generation rights include the more
recent concern with environmental and developmental rights including special
rights of women and children (Arjun Dev et. al. 1996: xi-xv).
The Vienna Declaration of Human Rights, proclaimed at a world conference
to review the progress of UDHR (1948) and subsequently endorsed by the UN
General Assembly, aptly remarks: “All human rights are universal, indivisible and
interdependent and interrelated” (article 5). The Millennium Development Goals
of the United Nations believe that we can end poverty by 2015. They reiterate :
Women’s Rights as Human Rights
155
“We are committed to making the right to development a reality for everyone
and to freeing the entire human race from want” (para 11). These goals need to
be made part of the constitutions of the member-states for their entrenched and
determined pursuit. For minorities and women, “rights, equality, and development
may not be achieved simply by putting them in the constitution and even in
government policies. For them, the issue is not recognition of cultural
distinctiveness. In fact, it may be recognition of different needs or meeting similar
needs in appropriate ways.” (Ghai & Cottrell 2011: 147-148).
In addition to the foregoing universal or global human rights systems, there
are three regional human rights systems in Europe, Americas, and Africa. The
European human rights system comprises two major treaties: the European
Convention of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms (1950) and the
European Social Charter (1961). As monitoring and enforcement mechanisms
the European Commission of Human Rights and the European Court of Human
Rights were instituted. Now the former has become obsolete and replaced by the
court itself, which accepts applications complaining violations from individuals
as well as states. The Inter-American human rights system emerged with the
adoption of the Americas‘ Declaration of Rights and Duties of Man in April 1948,
being the first regional human rights instrument of a general nature, predating
the UDHR (1948) by more than six months. Alongside were also set up the InterAmerican Commission on Human Rights and the Inter-American Court of
Human Rights. The third and most recent of the regional systems of human rights
is the African Charter of Human and Peoples‘ Rights (1981). It was first adopted
under the aegis of the Organization of African Unity, which aws subsequently
replaced by the African Union. It is monitored and interpreted by the African
Commission on Human and Peoples‘ Rights set up in 1987. An African Court
on Human and Peoples‘ Rights is also mooted under a protocol to the Charter
adopted in 1998 under which the foregoing Commission is proposed to be
incorporated into the Court. The operationalisation is still in process at this
writing.
V
In view of all-pervasive patriarchy and the diversity theorem of postmodern
feminism discussed above, the full realization of women’s human rights would
not be a cakewalk. It will require a concerted strategy of action by the state, civil
society, market, and national and international organizations to actualize the goals
of gender equality and justice advocated in the feminist thought and national and
international declarations of human rights surveyed above. To my mind,
constitutional entrenchment of these rights, conforming laws and public policies,
including affirmative action by way of special rights such as reservations on the
part of nation-states , hold the key to the achievement of women’s rights as human
rights in India and the world at large.
156
Journal of Social and Political Studies
The human rights texts that we have rapidly reviewed above are distinguishable
into at least the following categories: political thought/theory, national declarations,
national constitutional or legal bill of rights, regional human rights instruments,
and UN-UDHR and other universal international declarations and conventions.
If we assess these texts in terms degrees of freedom as to their formulation, if not
implementation, the free will and imagination enjoyed by a political thinker is
unparalleled, followed by an empirical political theorist working under the double
binds of rational imagination and normative justification, on the one hand, and
the constraints of factual evidence, on the other. If formulation and
implementation are jointly considered, a national human rights charter emerges
as the most efficacious proposition for the simple reason that a sovereign nationstate produces it is not dependent on any other power to beg for its
implementation. The case of regional and universal declarations is different. Their
formulation, declaration, ratification, and implementation are all in stages
dependent on the sovereign will of the high contracting parties, mostly or all
members of the United Nations.
Nevertheless, as we have argued above, women‘s rights even within the domain
of domestic jurisdiction of nation-states still leave much to be desired, and they
need instruments of special rights in the form of protective reservation or
affirmative action. In the international domain, both globally and regionally, a
lot still depends on the sovereign will of the state, though women‘s rights may be
undertaken as a political mission animated by new ideas in national government,
international relations, and organisations such as “governance” and “cosmopolitan
democracy”. Governance goes beyond the structure of government and brings in
administration in collaboration with the institutions of civil society like
nongovernmental organizations (NGOs) and the market (World Bank 1991;
Rosenau 1999). Cosmopolitan democracy refers to new developments allowing
civil and economic relations among communities across international boundaries
in international law without negating state sovereignty, rather jointly facilitated
by the neighbouring states in the supranational region ( David Held 1994; Daniele
Archibugi 2008).
REFERENCES AND A SELECT BIBLIOGRAPHY
Agarwal, Bina, A Field of One’s Own : Gender and Land Rights in South Asia (New Delhi :
Cambridge University Press, 1996).
Archibugi, Daniele, The Global Commonwealth of Citizens: Towards Cosmopolitan Democracy
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008).
Bakshi, P.M., The Constitution of India (Delhi : Universial Law Publishing Co., 2011, eleventh
edn.)
Baxi, Upendra, The Future of Human Rights (New Delhi : Oxford University Press, 2008, 3rd edn.
with a new Preface).
Binion, Gale, “Human Rights: A Feminist Perspective”, Human Rights Quarterly, vol. 17, no. 3,
August 1995.
Women’s Rights as Human Rights
157
Corea, Gena. The Mother Machine : Reproductive Technologies from Artificial Insemination to
Artificial Wombs (New York : Harper & Row, 1985).
Dev, Arjun and Indira and Supta Das, Human Rights : A Source Book, (New Delhi : Indian
Council of Educational Research and Training, 1996).
Firestone, Sulasmith, The Dialectic of Sex (New York : Bantam Books, 1970).
Friedan, Betty, The Feminine Mystique (New York : Dell, 1974).
Ghai, Yash and Jill Cottrell, The Millennium Declaration, Rights, and Constitutions (New Delhi :
Oxford University Press for UNDP, 2011).
Held, David, “Democracy: From City-States to a Cosmopolitan Order?” in The Polity Reader in
Social Theory (Cambridge: Polity Press, 1994), chapter 29.
Lauretis, Terrecy de, “The Essence of the Triangle, or Taking the Risks of Essentialism Seriously”,
in N. Schor and E. Weed, eds., The Essential Difference (Bloomington : Indiana University
Press, 1994).
Mill, John Stuart, On the Subjection of Women (New York : Fredrick A. Stokes Company, 1911,
first published 1869).
Rosenau, James N. “Towards an Ontology for Global Governance” in Martin Hewson and
Thomas Sinclair, eds. Approaches to Global Governance Theory (Albany: State University of
New York Press, 1999.
Singh, Ujjwal Kumar, ed. Human Rights and Peace : Ideas, Laws, Institutions and Movements (New
Delhi : Sage Publications, 2009).
Tong, Rosemarie, “Gender and Sexual Discrimination”, chapter 9, in Hugh LaFollette, ed. The
Oxford Handbook of Practical Ethics (New York: Oxford University Press, 2003), pp. 219-244.
Vetterling-Braggin, Mary, “Feminity”, “Masculinity” and “Androgyny” : A Modern Philosophical
Discussion (Totowa : Rowan & Littlefield, 1982).
Wollstonecraft, Mary, A Vindication of the Rights of Women (London : Penguin, 1988, first
published 1792).
158
Journal of Social and Political Studies
An Outsider Everywhere
M.K. Kaw
New Delhi: Konark Publishers, 2012, 210 pp Rs 570
ISBN 978 -93-220-0804-8
Written in a lucid language, the author gives us peep into his family genealogy
and then covers his own life journey from early education to the superannuation
from his active civil services in close of 2001, an event full career of forty two
years.
The early education of the author shows how Kashmiri Pandit homes were
like established unnoticed universities. He had no formal schooling, yet in his
home from grand father to his uncles, he was groomed in specialities’ of different
disciplines,” over the years, I learnt English and mathematics from my father, Hindi
from Baitathya(my eldest uncle), science from Saibiji(my second uncle) Urdu from
Tathyaji and geometry from Bablal”(p.24). It reveals Kashmiri community until
independent India and there after till the latest seventh exodus in 1989, had
remained a monolithic Brahminic community. The family title’ Kaw’ has come
to mark the distinctness over time and space, nothing to do with the gotra.
Shifting to Delhi was not easy choice for his father but he had no option,
like other Kashmiri Pandits too. Kashmir for them was a diminishing realm after
independence,“ the rude awakening came….when he saw the list of the selected
candidates and found his own name missing”. Affected by sixth exodus, kaw family
grew out of the crisis like other Kashmiri families, Nehrus, Kathjus and saprus in
the past had grown and found their niche. It was perhaps despite being outsiders;
their anchorage was firm in joint family traditions and genealogical purity that
gave them a huge advantage of intrinsic social, cultural capital. Kaw too was
enriched with this legacy.
He enters civil service career at young age and services at different challenging
assignments, both in Himachal Pradesh and Delhi for more than four decades. It
is this conversion of cultural capital that blends power and glamour with
spirituality and poetry to make Kaw a holistic personality, unlike a
compartmentalized civil servant. Many interesting incidents and anecdotes fill the
book depicting Kaw’s distinct interplay between choice and range, free will and
destiny and poet and administrator in a country, where it becomes extremely
difficult to’reforge social issues into effective collective action’ and live as an honest
actor with ramifications on social structures. He lives honestly side by side with
his family life as well with his professional duties.
So I told madam frankly that I would most probably have an arranged marriage
with girl of my community” (P.63).
“I can say that in many ways Indraprastha represented a watershed in my life. I
grew up. I lost my ego. I got interested in my spirituality. I wrote poetry. I started on
An Outsider Everywhere
159
my satirical pieces on the bureaucracy. I lost my illusion,” (p.90).
Kaw succinctly shows how actors can make the difference despite rigid
structures, the rational action with the sense of duty and altruism always give you
space to stretch, which is a transformation within, as well as, makes difference to
public sphere, despite all odds, “Now there were officers to note down their
outstanding issues…Resultantly, the number of their pending cases came down
drastically” (p.124).
The last three chapters reveal unfolding of an insider, perceived to be ‘outsider’
that leaves reader with wonder in Bauman’s aphorism, ‘that there is more to what
you see and hear than meets the eye., that most important part is hidden from
view’. Kaw faces that schism, while encountering with the degenerative politics,
‘shameless exploitation and ruthless corruption’ (p.189). His personal ethics, polity
and power are in conjunction to promote the cherished institutional means to
attain the cultural and social goals, where structure and actor are existential
dualities, but he defies dualism with grace and dignity. He did not bend when
testing moments struck in, ”the President refereed to the high safety standards
that required the latest aircraft to be provided to him, at which kaw blurted out,
‘sir is the safety and security of 350 passengers not equally important’…I was never
invited to any Rashtripati Bhawan function. I did not check with Kaw if he ever
was” (p.186). That self reflectivity is not one day born; it is accumulative cultural
capital of generations, which produces that inner strength.”Believe it or not, at11.30
pm we got positive message from the Singaporeans and at midnight we signed the
agreement” (p.187).
Kaw does not hesitate to scribble about ethics of justice and rebuttal of
detection that he masterly shows in two cases one about his own trip to Rome
and another about minster’s fascination to visit Gulf countries. It was his power
of intellectual surplus that fetched him trip to Rome to write a book on china,
which he completed before stipulated time. But, not only its authorship was
deprived to him, even his name in the acknowledgement was not accredited, “I
was also surprised not see my name as the author of the book; my contribution was
not even acknowledged in the preface” (p.135). On the other hand, “…., he had
spent the entire month in a hotel room watching the TV and drinking free beer”
(p.189)
Over all, it is an insightful story of a civil servant, whose intellectual acumen
and family grooming unfolds a reflective life world of a poet patriot, who in his
own way places some of the most insistent themes that he pursues through details
and compels you to gloss over the gross. There might have been missed
opportunities and neglected chances, But he has saved himself ‘from triviality,
cowardice and inner shame’, when it was bending in pattern variables of system
management in elite power structure for material referent and self empowerment.
The cherished common collective good and institutional ideology how sealed and
160
Journal of Social and Political Studies
impenetrable to each other it might appear, the author has revelation about it.
The book assumes historical significance, for its continuity and linkages of world
view of a person that is a reflection to his past anchorage genealogy and identity.
There is a threat to that kernel ‘world view’ of cerebral, cultural and genealogical
continuity, which the book conceitedly is letting known. The new social cultural
dynamics is melting down it fast, with paradigm shift in the ‘collective world view’.
An enjoyable reading with insightful details, the book is a must read for a
critical engagement of self to the public sphere.
Ashok Kaul
PhD, Professor of Sociology,
Banaras Hindu University.