Foundations of Physics
https://doi.org/10.1007/s10701-019-00264-0
Quantum Reality, Perspectivalism and Covariance
Dennis Dieks1
Received: 23 March 2019 / Accepted: 13 May 2019
© The Author(s) 2019
Abstract
Paul Busch has emphasized on various occasions the importance for physics of going
beyond a merely instrumentalist view of quantum mechanics. Even if we cannot be
sure that any particular realist interpretation describes the world as it actually is, the
investigation of possible realist interpretations helps us to develop new physical ideas
and better intuitions about the nature of physical objects at the micro level. In this spirit,
Paul Busch himself pioneered the concept of “unsharp quantum reality”, according
to which there is an objective non-classical indeterminacy—a lack of sharpness—in
the properties of individual quantum systems. We concur with Busch’s motivation for
investigating realist interpretations of quantum mechanics and with his willingness to
move away from classical intuitions. In this article we try to take some further steps
on this road. In particular, we pay attention to a number of prima facie implausible
and counter-intuitive aspects of realist interpretations of unitary quantum mechanics.
We shall argue that from a realist viewpoint, quantum contextuality naturally leads to
“perspectivalism” with respect to properties of spatially extended quantum systems,
and that this perspectivalism is important for making relativistic covariance possible.
Keywords Unitary quantum mechanics · Perspectivalism · Relativistic covariance
1 Introduction
I met Paul Busch for the first time during the 1985 Symposium on the Foundations of
Modern Physics in Joensuu, Finland. On that occasion Paul gave a talk on “Elements of
unsharp reality in the EPR experiment” [1], in which he explained ideas of a research
program on which he had embarked not long before [2] and to which he would keep
returning in his later work.
B
1
Dennis Dieks
d.dieks@uu.nl
History and Philosophy of Science, Utrecht University, Princetonplein 5, 3584CC Utrecht, The
Netherlands
123
Foundations of Physics
The Joensuu paper starts from the observation that in any measurement, no matter
how carefully designed, there is a non-vanishing residue of uncertainty. In the case
of spin measurements, it is thus impossible to construct a spin measuring device that
determines spin in exactly one spatial direction. This means that the standard formal
treatment of quantum measurements using projection operators should be seen as an
idealization, and that actual laboratory measurements are better described with the
help of “smeared out” projections. In the case of spin measurements this leads to the
n) by positive
replacement of projection operators Pn (for spin in the exact direction
operators E that are weighted means of projections: E(n) = Ω dµ(n′ )Pn ′ , with µ
some measure (probability) centered around the direction n. More generally, taking
into account the approximate nature of measurements results in a variation on the
standard quantum mechanical measurement formalism in which positive operators E,
effects, take the place of projection operators.
The novel interpretative step taken by Paul Busch is to view these effects E not
merely as mathematical tools for taking into account the imprecision of measurements
on a quantum system, but also as a representation of unsharp properties of this quantum
system itself. As he comments [1, p. 351] “It is important to note that ‘unsharpness’
admits not only an interpretation as (subjective) measurement uncertainty but also as
proper quantum mechanical uncertainty.”
As it turns out, if the unsharpness of the quantum spin effects E(n) and E(n′ )
increases, at a certain point these two unsharp properties will start to admit a joint
probability distribution (in spite of the fact that the projection operators Pn and Pn′
do not commute). It is therefore to be expected that unsharp quantum properties play
a role in making the classical limit of quantum mechanics intuitively understandable: unsharpness washes out the consequences of complementarity. Unsharpness of
quantum properties also plays an explanatory role in other contexts. For example, the
unsharp position of quantum particles makes their behavior in a double-slit experiment
fathomable.
Paul Busch fleshed out his realist interpretation of quantum indeterminacy in various later publications [3–6]. In the Introduction of his review paper with G. Jaeger,
“Unsharp Quantum Reality” [7], the interesting motivation of the authors for pursuing
any realist research program at all is made explicit:
[In physical practice] there is still a strong presence of the view that Quantum
Mechanics is nothing more than a formalism for the calculation of measurement
statistics...
It seems to us that a more coherent and productive approach would be to investigate systematically all possible variants of realist interpretations of Quantum
Mechanics, including those in which probabilities are not essentially epistemic.
On a realist interpretation of Quantum Mechanics as a complete theory, the referent of quantum mechanical propositions is the individual system. This would not
only recognize the possibility that such a philosophically realist interpretation
could in the end enable the best description of the physical world; it also has the
potential benefit of providing us with guidance in developing new, appropriately
adapted intuitions about microphysical objects... A primary role of any realist
interpretation is to provide a rule that determines, for every state, which physical
123
Foundations of Physics
quantities have definite values in that state, thus representing “elements of reality” or actual properties pertaining to the quantum system under investigation.
In the present paper we put forth an interpretational point of view that has not yet
been much considered but that seems to us worthy of further exploration—the
concept of unsharp quantum reality.
We fully agree with the motivation for investigating realist interpretations expressed
in this quotation. Even though it may be unlikely that we will ever be able to single out
one such interpretation as uniquely and faithfully describing physical reality as it is in
itself, each consistent and empirically viable realist interpretation will provide us with
a picture of what the physical world could be like and will thus enrich our conceptual
repertoire and broaden our intuitions. As stated by Busch and Jaeger, in order to go
beyond mere measurement statistics such interpretations of quantum mechanics have
to be about physical systems and their properties.
The essential question that arises for each realist interpretation is how the states
ascribed to physical systems by quantum mechanics relate to properties possessed by
these systems; different interpretations give different answers to this question. Busch
and Jaeger also comment on this issue, and argue that in the case of sharp properties
the most plausible answer is provided by the eigenvalue-eigenstate link.1 They reason
as follows:
If a property is absent, the system’s action or behavior will be different from
that when it is present. Applied to the context of a measurement, in which an
observer induces an interaction between the system and part of its environment
(a measurement apparatus), this means that if a property is actual—that is, an
observable has a definite value—then its measurement exhibits this value or
property unambiguously and (hence) with certainty.
This condition—which, incidentally, is routinely being used as a calibration
condition for measuring instruments—is taken as the defining requirement for
a measurement scheme to qualify as a measurement of a given observable.
Its implementation within the quantum theory of measurement is possible if
a property’s being actual is associated with the system being in a corresponding
eigenstate.
In summary, the structure of the quantum theory of measurement ... suggests the
adoption of the eigenvalue–eigenstate link as a necessary and sufficient criterion
of empirical reality in quantum mechanics.2
The core idea of this argument is that if a perfect measurement of an observable
is made on a system possessing a sharp value of that observable, an outcome revealing this value must be found with certainty, that is with probability 1. According to
quantum mechanics this is only possible if the system is in an eigenstate of the measured observable. This leads to the conclusion that a system can only possess a sharp
1 It should be noted that Busch’s and Jaeger’s defense of the eigenvalue-eigenstate link is independent of
their unsharp quantum reality proposal, as emphasized by an anonymous reviewer.
2 Busch and Jaeger immediately add: “However, the application of quantum mechanics to the description
of measurement processes also leads directly into the quantum measurement problem... This problem is
one of the main reasons for the continued debate about the interpretation of quantum mechanics.”
123
Foundations of Physics
property (corresponding to an eigenvalue of an observable) if its state is the associated
eigenstate—this is the eigenvalue-eigenstate link.3
However, there is room for alternative views concerning this issue: as shown by
non-collapse interpretations (e.g., relative-states/many-worlds interpretations [8,9],
modal interpretations [10,11], including the Bohm interpretation [12]) it is possible
to consistently interpret quantum mechanics in terms of physical properties of individual systems even without subscribing to the eigenvalue-eigenstate link. The key
idea here is that it is a conceptual possibility that the quantum state specifies epistemic
probabilities for the presence of a range of possible values of a physical quantity, even
though only one value is actually realized in any individual case (in the many-worlds
interpretation this description applies to the epistemic situation as seen from one single
branch). In spite of such a range of non-vanishing epistemic probabilities, a perfect
measurement may still unambiguously and faithfully reveal the actually present property with (conditional) probability 1. In other words, even if the quantum state is not
an eigenstate of an observable, so that it specifies non-vanishing probabilities for several eigenvalues, it is not a priori inconsistent to assume that an individual system
is associated with only one of these values and that this value will be revealed with
certainty in a perfect measurement. Of course, if the quantum state assigned to the
object is not an eigenstate of the measured observable, this state only allows us to
predict probabilities for a range of possible measurement outcomes, and in repetitions
of the measurement in this same state these probabilities will materialize as approximate relative frequencies. But nevertheless the principle that a preexisting property
of a system must be faithfully and certainly reproduced by an ideal measurement can
be upheld if the conditional probability for the measuring device to indicate value a,
if a represents a property of the object system, is 1. This shows that the “calibration
condition” by itself does not prove that a property can only be actual if the system is
described by the corresponding eigenstate.
Moreover, as Busch and Jaeger note in their review paper, adopting the eigenvalueeigenstate link has the unpleasant consequence that we have to accept the occurrence
of collapses of the wave function during measurements. Indeed, once a measurement
result has become definite, the eigenvalue-eigenstate link tells us that the system on
which the measurement has taken place must have ended up in an eigenstate of the
measured observable, even if it was in a superposition of such eigenstates before.
This leads to the infamous measurement problem: taking collapses seriously entails
recognizing restrictions on the validity of unitary Schrödinger evolution, which raises
a plethora of well-known problems.
We shall therefore in the following explore an alternate route, namely acknowledging the universality of unitary evolution and rejecting the eigenvalue-eigenstate link
as a necessary condition for the attribution of (sharp) properties.4 As we shall see,
attributing properties to systems in the context of unitary quantum mechanics leads to
an unexpected, intuitively peculiar non-classical picture.
3 The degree of sharpness (or lack thereof) of unsharp properties can then be characterized via the distance
between a system’s state and the eigenstate corresponding to the sharp property.
4 The eigenvalue-eigenstate link as a sufficient condition for property attribution is unproblematic. Which
properties are to be ascribed to a system when the eigenvalue-eigenstate link is abandoned, depends on the
specific unitary interpretation that is considered.
123
Foundations of Physics
2 Unitary Quantum Mechanics
There are several interpretational schemes only admitting unitary evolution and excluding collapses: the Bohm theory, consistent histories, Everett/many worlds, and modal
interpretations are examples. These schemes all start from the basic view that the same
physical principles should apply regardless of whether we are dealing with elemental
physical interactions or complicated measurements. Measurements are accordingly
treated as ordinary physical interactions, between object systems and measuring
devices. Given the huge amount of evidence that outside the measurement context
physical interactions between quantum systems are governed by unitary evolution
(which leads to superpositions and entanglement), the assumption that unitary evolution applies universally becomes natural once one does not assign an independent
status to measurement interactions.
Unitary schemes not only unify ordinary physical interactions and measurements,
but also the theoretical treatment of the micro and macro levels. Macroscopic properties like the position of a pointer on the dial of a measuring device should accordingly
fall under the same rules of quantum property ascription as microscopic properties.
Even human observers should in principle be seen as very complicated quantum systems, analyzable in terms of the physical properties they possess (including memory
contents). This general programmatic viewpoint is of course not unique to quantum
physics: it generalizes physicalist ideas well known from classical physics. We mention the point here because it will play a role in our later discussion of measurements
(and their reversal) in unitary quantum mechanics.
As discussed in the previous section, the argument that a system can only possess
a determinate value of a physical quantity when it is in the appropriate eigenstate
of the associated observable can be circumvented by a probabilistic interpretation
of the quantum state, according to which this state provides us with probabilities
for individual eigenvalues to be present. Unitary schemes employ the usual Born
probability rule for these probabilities.5
A point that will play an important role later on is that the assumption of universal
validity of unitary Schrödinger evolution entails that all quantum processes can in
principle be reversed. Just as in classical physics any process that goes from initial
state A to final state B can be undone by a physical interaction in the reverse direction,
leading back to the initial state, the final state in a quantum process governed by
unitary interaction can also be brought back to its initial state by applying appropriate
interactions. In particular, it is possible (in principle!) to undo a measurement: after
a record of the measurement result has been formed, an appropriate reversal of the
interactions between the elementary constituents involved in the process will be able
to restore the situation that was present before the measurement—the record of the
outcome will of course be erased during this process.
Of course, a restoration of the initial situation is also possible in schemes in which
collapses occur: after a projection that takes |Ψ = Σi ci |ψi to |ψk , there will in
principle always be a unitary evolution that transforms |ψk into |Ψ again, since
5 Often these Born probabilities are simply posited; some authors attempt to derive them from more basic
principles, e.g. [9]. For our purposes this difference is not important.
123
Foundations of Physics
unitary transformations are rotations in Hilbert space and any vector can be rotated
into any other. The essential difference with the unitary case becomes clear when
we consider states of several systems that are correlated, as in the EPR situation. For
example, after a collapse Σi ci |ψi1 ⊗|ϕi2 ⇒ |ψ1k ⊗|ϕ2k , as a result of a measurement
on system 1, the initial entangled state can only be reproduced via a transformation
that affects the total system, comprising both 1 and 2. By contrast, when we assume
only unitary evolution an ideal measurement on system 1 alone is represented by a
transition of the form
Σi ci |ψi1 ⊗ |ϕi2 ⊗ |E0 ⇒ Σi ci |ψi1 ⊗ |ϕi2 ⊗ |Ei ,
in which |Ei and |E0 are states of a measuring device interacting solely with system
1. This transition can be reversed by locally acting on system 1 and its measuring
device; no interaction with system 2 is needed. For the case of EPR experiments on
space-like separated systems this implies that the effects of a local measurement on
system 1 can also be undone locally, by interactions with 1: the total state, including
system 2, can be brought back to what it initially was without touching system 2
(something that is impossible in the case of collapses).
3 Unitarity and Relativity
Unitary interpretations as defined in the preceding section are known to face problems
with Lorentz invariance (e.g., [13–15]). The nature of the difficulty has recently been
illustrated in a simple way by Gao [16]. In Gao’s thought experiment two observers,
Alice and Bob, are located at space-like separation from each other and perform spin
measurements on an EPR pair of electrons in the singlet state (the usual Bohm-EPR
setup). Let us assume that Alice and Bob both measure spin in the same direction, so
that quantum mechanics predicts that their outcomes will be anti-correlated.
As we have seen a moment ago, unitary quantum mechanics permits the local
reversal of such measurements, which restores the original two-particle singlet state.
This can be used to construct a paradoxical variation on the usual Bohm-EPR thought
experiment.
Let Alice measure the spin of her particle and let her record (or memorize) the
outcome—we may think of Alice as fulfilling the role of the measuring device in
the discussion at the end of Sect. 2. After Alice’s measurement a unitary restoration
process takes place that locally undoes the measurement and returns Alice and Bob
plus the two particles to their original total state (so that Alice loses all her information
about the outcome). Finally, Bob measures the spin of his particle in the same direction
in which Alice had measured before.
Let us call the inertial frame in which the just-given description of the experiment
applies the laboratory frame. When we apply the standard quantum mechanical rules in
this frame, we predict that Alice records either +1 or −1 as her result, both possibilities
having probability 1/2. Alice’s record is erased in the subsequent anti-measurement,
after which Bob performs his measurement in the original singlet state so that he also
finds either +1 or −1, again with probability 1/2 for each possible result.
123
Foundations of Physics
However, because Alice and Bob are space-like separated, there exists another
inertial frame of reference with a simultaneity relation such that in this frame Alice
measures her electron first, then Bob measures his electron, and finally Alice’s measurement is undone only after both measurements have taken place.
This leads to the following problem. In the second frame, in which Alice’s experiment is undone as the final step, Bob’s measurement must yield −1 if Alice’s result
was +1, because of the anti-correlation in the singlet state: the conditional probability
of Bob’s outcome being −1 is 1, given Alice’s result. As we have seen, however,
in the laboratory frame Alice’s result no longer exists when Bob performs his measurement, since Alice’s measurement has been undone at that instant and the original
Bohm-EPR state has been restored. Consequently, according to the usual quantum
mechanical rules applied in the laboratory frame Bob’s result does not need to be −1
even if Alice’s result was +1; Bob may alternatively find −1, with probability 1/2.
The consequence is that in a long series of repetitions of this “EPR plus restoration”
experiment, after selection6 of all cases in which Alice’s experiment yields +1, we
have to expect that Bob finds −1 and +1 in approximately half of the cases according
to quantum mechanics applied in the laboratory frame, but always −1 according to
quantum mechanics in the other frame.
We may construct a variation on this thought experiment in which we do not need
a series of repetitions with new EPR pairs, but use the same electrons over and over
again. Suppose that when Alice’s experiment has been undone (as seen from the laboratory frame), and Bob has completed his measurement, Bob’s measurement is undone
as well, after which he performs a second measurement. This second measurement
can be reversed in its turn, after which a third measurement can be done; and so on. If
the space-time distance between Alice and Bob and the time scales of Bob’s measurements are judiciously chosen the experiment can be arranged in such a way that all
Bob’s measurement take place before Alice’s measurement is undone, according to the
simultaneity in some other inertial frame. In this way we arrive at the same paradox as
before: In the lab frame quantum mechanics tells us that approximately half of Bob’s
results will be −1 if Alice’s result was +1, in the other frame the quantum prediction
is that all of Bob’s outcomes must be the same, namely −1.
In both cases we arrive at a contradiction, which suggests that the unitary formalism
of quantum mechanics cannot be used for making predictions in the same way in all
inertial frames.
One way of responding to this is to posit that there exists a preferred inertial frame,
whose simultaneity is the only one to be used when predicting outcomes and their
frequencies with the standard formalism of quantum mechanics. This is the route taken
by the Bohm theory—that the Bohm theory faces problems with special relativity and
cannot accept the equivalence of all inertial reference frames has long been recognized
because of the occurrence of instantaneous interactions in that theory. It is interesting
to discuss in some more detail how the Bohm theory deals with the new thought
experiment, and to compare it with other unitary schemes.
6 That is, selection in abstracto, with the mind’s eye. Any real physical selection would involve an interaction
that would spoil the perfect reversal of Alice’s measurement.
123
Foundations of Physics
According to the Bohm theory the complete state of a system of two spin- 21 particles
is given by its wave function plus the individual positions of the two particles. We
consider here the standard version of the theory according to which the particles
do not possess an intrinsic spin—their only physical property is position. However,
the wave function is taken to be the usual spinor-valued one (in our case with the
singlet state as its spin part) and the Hamiltonian governing the evolution of the wave
function contains the usual coupling between spin variables and magnetic fields. In
the interaction with a Stern–Gerlach device the spatial wave function will therefore
be split into two parts, an upper and a lower wave packet. The initial positions of the
particles, in their initial wave packets, determine whether they will end up in the upper
or the lower wave packet on their wing of the experiment. In this way the final position
of a particle, after the interaction with a Stern–Gerlach device, represents the result of
a “spin measurement” even though the Bohm theory does not operate with an intrinsic
spin property. The result of the spin measurement is either “up” or “down”. Because
of the non-local interaction between the particles (due to the entanglement of the total
state), particle 2 will be driven down when particle 1 is the first to interact with the
magnetic field of the Stern–Gerlach device and goes up; and vice versa when particle
2 is the first to interact (see [17] for a detailed discussion).
In the initial stage of our thought experiment there is one spatial wave packet near
Alice and one near Bob. Let us suppose that both Alice’s and Bob’s particle find
themselves in initial positions such that they will emerge “up” (spin result +1) when
they are the first to interact with their respective Stern–Gerlach devices (the particle
that is second to interact will go opposite to the other one, so that its spin outcome
will be −1 and the anti-correlation between the spin results predicted by quantum
mechanics is reproduced). In repetitions of the experiment with new pairs of electrons
there will be a probability of 1/2 for each electron to be in an initial position, in its
own wave packet, that leads to the result “up”.7
Suppose that as judged from the laboratory frame Alice makes her measurement
first and finds +1, after which a reverse local evolution takes place that restores the
initial wave function, returns Alice’s particle to its original position, and erases Alice’s
result. Then Bob measures the spin of his particle and also finds +1, the outcome deterministically determined by his particle’s initial position. In a long series of repetitions
of the experiment, each time with a new pair of electrons, and collecting (in thought!)
all runs in which Alice’s outcome is +1, the Bohm prediction is that Bob will find
both instances of +1 and of −1, each of these outcomes in approximately 50% of
the cases—in the Bohm theory it is supposed that in repetitions of the experiment the
initial particle positions will be distributed according to the Born rule. By contrast, if
Bob’s measurement is repeated many times with the same particle, each time undoing
the measurement and restarting from the same initial situation, the Bohm prediction
is that the same result (+1) will be found in each run of the experiment.
When we now consider these three versions of the experiment from the other inertial
frame, in which Bob’s measurements take place before Alice’s measurement is undone,
7 From this description one already sees why the notion of a preferred frame imposes itself in the Bohm
theory: if Alice and Bob are at space-like separation from each other, the time order of their spin measurements will generally be frame-dependent. In this case, application of quantum mechanics in the same way
in all frames leads to contradictory predictions for the measurement outcomes.
123
Foundations of Physics
we find the following. In the single-run experiment Alice finds +1 and Bob −1,
because the non-local influence of Alice’s result sends Bob’s particle “down”. When
the experiment is repeated many times with new particle pairs, and Alice’s +1 cases
are collected, Bob will in all cases measure −1. If the experiment is done repeatedly
with one particle pair, as described before, Bob will also find −1 each time.
Clearly, the predictions from the two frames of reference contradict each other in
all three versions of the experiment. This further supports the necessity of a privileged
frame in Bohm’s theory.
Let us now consider the same experiments from the perspective of non-Bohmian
unitary quantum mechanics (i.e., unitary schemes that do not assume that position is
a preferred observable [12]). According to the standard quantum rules applied in the
lab frame, Alice will find either +1 or −1, both with probability 1/2. Let us again
focus on the case with outcome 1, in order to compare with the predictions of the
Bohm theory. After the reversal of Alice’s measurement Bob finds either +1 or −1,
with equal probabilities. In a long series of experiments, with many pairs of particles,
we find that Bob’s results are 50% up and 50% down. If Bob’s experiment is repeated
by means of reversals we also find a 50–50% distribution.
There is therefore a difference with the Bohm prediction for the third version of the
experiment. Because of its determinism, the Bohm scheme predicts that repetitions of
an experiment with exactly the same initial conditions will lead to exactly the same
outcomes. But since the initial conditions in non-Bohmian quantum mechanics do
not involve particle positions, this Bohm result cannot be carried over to the standard
theory. So it might seem that we have a situation where we could, in principle, empirically distinguish between the Bohm theory and standard quantum mechanics. This is
deceptive, however: because Bob’s measurements are each time undone, no records
of them can exist and no empirical comparison of their outcomes is possible. Whether
or not there is a correlation between the results of repeated measurements on the same
system, with reversals between the measurements, is something that as a matter of
principle cannot be verified or refuted empirically.
When the second frame of reference is used to describe the three versions of the
EPR-plus-reversal experiment with non-Bohmian unitary quantum mechanics, we find
that Bob measures −1 if Alice’s result is +1. In repetitions with new particle pairs
Bob will also always find −1 in the cases in which Alice measured +1. Finally, when
Bob’s measurements are repeated on the same particle he will still find −1 in all cases.
Non-Bohmian quantum mechanics, applied in the second frame, thus yields the
same predictions as Bohm’s theory: the +1 result of Alice fixes Bob’s outcome as −1
in all cases. Again, the predictions from frame 2 run counter to what is predicted from
the laboratory frame. In the first version of the experiment (one single measurement
by both Alice and Bob) the probability of Bob finding −1 is 1/2 in the lab frame
instead of 1 (the latter probability value is predicted in the other frame). Although this
is not an direct contradiction in terms of measurement results, it becomes so in the
second and third versions of the experiment in which the probability is made into an
approximate frequency.
Given that the Bohm theory has already developed a tool to protect itself against
relativistic inconsistencies, namely the postulation of a privileged reference frame with
respect to which the non-local quantum interactions are defined, it seems only natural
123
Foundations of Physics
to take over this recipe for unitary interpretations in general. It is true that assuming the
existence of such a frame is at odds with Einstein’s first special relativistic postulate; but
it has often been argued that this objection is not decisive because quantum mechanics
contains an element of non-locality and therefore is at odds with special relativity
anyway.
However, it is possible to interpret this non-locality of quantum mechanics in a
way that does not involve superluminal causation or action-at-a-distance, and does
not conflict with relativity. A key to this alternative viewpoint is the observation that
physical systems as described by quantum mechanics are generally not space-time
objects in the way classical systems are. As we shall argue, this observation may be
used as a starting point for the construction of a new scheme for reconciling quantum mechanics, and the above thought experiments, with relativity—even though the
ensuing alternative solution of the inconsistency problems will require a break with a
number of classical intuitions.
4 Perspectives and Non-locality
According to classical physics physical systems can be analyzed as built up from local
parts, each part possessing its own locally defined properties. Specification of all these
local parts and their properties provides us with the complete instantaneous state of a
classical system as a whole. For example, a measuring rod is described as a collection
of very many particles whose instantaneous local properties together determine the
properties of the composite system. A classical field in a spatial region is likewise
completely specified by the local field strengths at all points in that region.
The formalism of quantum mechanics suggests a different picture, though. This
is because in general many-particle states are entangled, and such entangled states
are not combinations of one-particle states that specify complete sets of one-particle
properties. The Bohm-EPR two-electron singlet state furnishes a typical example. This
state is the product of a symmetric spatial part and an anti-symmetric spin part
1
|Φ = √ {|L1 |R2 + |R1 |L2 } ⊗ {| ↑1 | ↓2 − | ↓1 | ↑2 },
2
(1)
where |L and |R correspond to narrow wave packets localized on the left and right
wing of the EPR experiment, respectively. If one were to think of the EPR experiment
as pertaining to two particles, each one with its own complete set of spatial and spin
properties, one would expect the total state to be built up from the one-electron states
|L1 | ↑1 , |L1 | ↓1 , |R2 | ↑2 and |R2 | ↓2 , in each of which a full set of particle
properties is specified (namely a definite spin plus a localization property). Instead,
however, we find that in Eq. (1) the global spatial features of the two-particle system
and its global spin properties are independently combined, i.e. without a correlation
between individual particle localization and individual spin.
In fact, the indices 1 and 2, usually taken to be particle labels, are not correlated to
either |L or |R so that in state (1) we cannot even speak about particle 1 as being
at the left-hand side and particle 2 at the right-hand side, or vice versa. As argued in
123
Foundations of Physics
[18–20] this shows that the standard interpretation of state (1) in physical practice,
namely as representing two particles at a large distance from each other, one on the
left and one on the right, implicitly renounces the doctrine that the indices 1 and 2
label these particles. Rather, in physical practice the individual constituents of the
total system are taken to correspond directly to the two spatial one-particle states |L
and |R (L referring to the left particle and R to the right one). However, even with
this understanding there is no correlation between spatial properties and definite spin
directions, so that we still cannot think in terms of a particle on the left possessing
its own definite spin and a similar particle on the right. Instead, Eq. (1) represents a
system with a global spin property that is uncorrelated to its localization properties.
In other words, the classical paradigm according to which a system consists of
independently defined local parts does not fit in in a natural way with how quantum
mechanics generally describes physical systems. As argued in [20,21], violations of
Bell inequalities can accordingly be viewed as evidence that a classical “local parts picture” does not apply—instead of the more common interpretation that such violations
are manifestations of non-local interactions or influences between distant parts.
In order to fix the properties of a two-particle system in an entangled quantum state
like (1) we therefore need to specify its total, global state, which cannot be written as
a concatenation of local states or as the combination of two one-particle states. In the
case of a spatially extended system as in (1) the specification of the total state must
involve the identification of a hyperplane of simultaneity, or more generally a spacelike hypersurface, on which the state is defined. Different choices of such hyperplanes
will generally lead to different property attributions (cf. [22]). The thought experiment
of Sect. 3 provides us with an example: the laboratory frame and the other inertial frame
considered there define alternative hyperplanes of simultaneity on which the global
states of the system are different. On one hyperplane the total state is correlated to a
state of Alice’s measuring device corresponding to a definite outcome, whereas there
is no such correlation on other hyperplanes. It cannot be excluded a priori that this
leads to differences in the description even locally at points where the two hyperplanes
intersect, in particular at Bob’s position.
What we accordingly propose as an interpretative option is that the physical characteristics of what happens in Bob’s measurements not only depend on the local
circumstances near Bob, but also on the total state that determines the properties of
the system that is being measured and thus on the hyperplane on which that state is
defined. If the global state is different on different hyperplanes, the properties of the
global system will generally be different as well so that Bob as described on different
hyperplanes will be involved in measurements of different properties.
What we are suggesting here is the attribution of hyperplane dependent, and in
this sense perspectival properties. The idea of perspectivalism is not new: see for
example [23–26]. These earlier proposals discuss property attributions to a system
from different perspectives connected to different observers (who stand in different
relations to the system depending on whether or not they have interacted with it).
The present proposal is even more radical because it contemplates the possibility
that the same observer measures different outcomes depending on the hyperplane on
which the measurement is described (see, however, [27] for arguments that hyperplane
dependence is not as radical as it seems).
123
Foundations of Physics
A comment that may come to mind is that hyperplane dependence is something
already well known from special relativity. However, although it is true that in special
relativity different frames of reference are associated with different descriptions of
physical processes, these descriptions relate to each other via Lorentz transformations
that translate between states of affairs defined point by point. These Lorentz transformations will never translate an outcome +1 (the event of a pointer indicating +1 on a
dial) in one frame of reference into the outcome −1 in another frame. The hyperplane
dependence that we are discussing here goes further than this special relativistic frame
dependence. The non-quantum special relativistic picture is still based on the principle
that physical systems and processes are built up from independently existing locally
defined events. But in the quantum mechanical formalism of many-particle systems
physical properties are not specified per point. The resulting hyperplane dependence
is different from what is at issue in special relativity with its point-by-point Lorentz
transformations.8
5 Uniqueness of Outcomes
According to this perspectivalist proposal there may be a difference between Bob’s
outcome in relation to Alice having made a not yet undone measurement and with
respect to Alice after her measurement has been undone. Evidently, this conflicts
with the intuition that it cannot make any difference for Bob’s local situation what
happens far away—the locality notion that underlies relativity and the EPR argument.
As pointed out before, this intuition depends on the idea that any global system consists
of spatial parts, each with its independently defined properties—a notion of which
we have seen that it does not sit well with the mathematical structure of quantum
mechanics.
But, it may be objected, perhaps Bob is not aware that Alice is performing measurements far away, or does not even know that the system on which he is making
his measurement has a distant counterpart. Surely, Bob will find one definite result
completely independently of such considerations? All our experience indicates that
any successful experiment has only one definite result. Can this be reconciled with the
idea that Bob’s results are perspectival?
The uniqueness of direct experience is not in conflict with perspectivalism, because
in each perspective there is only one unique and definite measurement result. But it is
true that there is a multiplicity of outcomes corresponding to different perspectives.
This is reminiscent of the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics, in which
there are many branches, each with its own unique state of affairs. But although there
is this similarity with the many-worlds account, there are also important differences.
In relativistic many-worlds branching [28], Bob’s local measurement induces a local
splitting of worlds so that each possible spin plus position outcome is instantiated in
one of the resulting branches. This splitting then propagates through the universe, with
a velocity less than or equal to the velocity of light. This account retains the classical
8 That many-component systems are defined globally rather than point by point is also important for the
covariance properties of wave function collapse construed as an effective description within unitary quantum
mechanics [22].
123
Foundations of Physics
notion of locality: the branching events arising from Alice’s and Bob’s measurements
are localized at Alice’s and Bob’s positions and the branching propagates like a wave
through space-time.
By contrast, in the perspectival account discussed here there is no local propagation
of different possibilities (branches) but two different states of affairs as defined on two
different global hyperplanes. Moreover, in our account not all possible results need
to be instantiated. After one pair of measurements by Alice and Bob, Alice’s spin
outcome may be +1 and Bob’s outcome −1, from all perspectives; this is a globally
consistent possibility. It is true that in repetitions of Bob’s measurement the outcome
+1 will also occur, namely with respect to hyperplanes on which Alice’s measurement
has been undone. This is not the consequence of a splitting of the world, however. It
takes place in the same world as before, although along a different hyperplane from
the one on which the outcome −1 is instantiated.
So there is a multiplicity of outcomes in a quite specific and limited sense, namely
relating to different perspectives defined by different hyperplanes, all occurring in
one single world. This restricted multiplicity is sufficient to avoid a number of no-go
results that may seem to show that quantum experiments cannot have unique outcomes
in a stronger sense, and that even the objectivity and consistency of quantum theory
are under threat [29–31].
6 Perspectives and Contextuality
A recent example of such no-go arguments was recently discussed by Healey, who
credits its idea to Masanes [31]. As in the thought experiment discussed in Sect. 3, Alice
and Bob (who find themselves at space-like separation from each other) share a BohmEPR pair of spin- 21 particles and each of them is set to perform a spin measurement, in
directions a and b, respectively. In the new experiment there are also two colleagues
of Alice and Bob, Carol and Dan, with their own measuring devices; Carol finds
herself close to Alice, Dan is located near to Bob. Carol and Dan are set to make
spin measurements in the respective directions c and d. As in the earlier experiment,
it is supposed that measurements can be undone by local operations, as permitted
by unitary quantum mechanics; Alice and Bob are assumed to possess the means to
locally reverse the measurements made by Carol and Dan, respectively.
Measurement are now made in the following way and order. First Dan measures the
spin of the particle near to him in the d direction, then Carol performs a measurement
on her particle, in the c direction. Subsequently, Alice undoes Carol’s measurement
and performs her own measurement in the a direction. Because Carol’s measurement
has been undone, the state of the particle system plus Dan is the same for Alice, when
she does her measurement, as it was for Carol when she did hers. Finally, Bob undoes
Dan’s measurement and measures in the b direction himself.
So in the final situation measurements have been made in the four directions a, b, c
and d on one and the same Bohm-EPR pair. This distinguishes the present thought
experiment from standard EPR-type experiments: in the standard cases Alice measures
in her direction and Bob in his, and the experiment has to be repeated with other particle
pairs in order to make measurements in other directions.
123
Foundations of Physics
In the lab frame in which the four experimenters are at rest the correlations between
the outcomes found by Dan and Carol, Alice and Dan, and by Alice and Bob, respectively, can be directly calculated from the standard formula − cos(θ ), with θ standing
for the angle between the directions in which the two parties involved have measured
their spin values. The correlation between the results of Bob and Carol cannot be calculated this way in the laboratory frame, because Carol’s result has already been erased
when Bob performs his measurement. But this complication can be circumvented by
a maneuver that is reminiscent of the earlier thought experiment: there exists another
inertial frame in which Bob, who is at space-like separation from Alice and Carol,
makes his measurement before Alice reverses Carol’s measurement and performs her
own. In this frame, the correlation between the outcomes found by Carol and by Bob
can again be calculated by means of the standard formula − cos(θ ).
Now, if we assume that all four measurements have outcomes that are perspectiveindependent, we have in a single run of the experiment the four jointly existing results
a, b, c and d. In repetitions of the experiment there will in this case be a probability
distribution over these values. This is exactly the familiar situation in which a Bell
inequality can be derived: the values a, b, c and d play the role of the local hidden
variables that are assumed to exist in the standard Bell derivation. But the correlations
between the measurement outcomes, as predicted by quantum mechanics in the way
just explained, violate that Bell inequality if the directions a, b, c and d are appropriately chosen.
The assumption that the outcomes of the four measurements in a single run of the
above experiment can be represented by unique numbers a, b, c and d that possess a
joint probability distribution thus leads to a contradiction.9
The inconsistency disappears if we introduce context-dependence: in that case the
outcome of Carol’s measurement in the context of Dan’s result may be different from
Carol’s outcome in the context of Bob’s result. This solution accords with our proposal
in Sect. 4: hyperplanes connecting Bob’s and Carol’s measurements are different from
hyperplanes connecting the measurements by Dan and Carol, and the perspectivalism
explained earlier tells us that in this case Carol’s result need not be the same on these
two hyperplanes.
The just-discussed thought experiment, in which there is a conflict with Bell inequalities, sheds additional light on the status of quantum perspectivalism. An often-heard
comment on violations of Bell inequalities is that they signal the presence of a nonlocal influence between distant events: different choices of the direction in which to
measure a spin value at one position apparently make a difference for values of quantities far-away. But in the variation on the EPR setup with four experimenters and
reversals of measurements, there are no choices to be made: all measurement directions are instantiated together and fixed in each run of the experiment. Consequently,
an interpretation in terms of superluminal influences due to distant choices is ruled
out. The role of such non-local influences in avoiding violations of Bell inequalities is
9 This contradiction is confirmed in an interesting way by a calculation of Gao’s [32], who notes that if
a joint distribution of a, b, c and d exists, the joint distribution of b and c is completely fixed by the joint
distributions of c and d, a and d, and a and b, respectively. Direct calculation, using the quantum predictions
for the latter three joint distributions, demonstrates that the thus found joint distribution of b and c does not
agree with what quantum mechanics predicts for it.
123
Foundations of Physics
taken over by the perspectival nature of the measurement outcomes: it is not the case
that different choices of directions at Bob’s and Dan’s locations change something
at Carol’s position. Rather, Carol’s physical quantities are differently defined with
respect to Bob’s and Dan’s results.
This is basically a case of contextuality: the physical quantity measured by Alice is
different in the context of Bob’s measurement from what it is in the context of Dan’s
measurement. It is well known that contextuality of this sort is an essential feature
of quantum mechanics, as proved by the Kochen and Specker theorem. This same
contextuality can be identified as the basis of the violation of Bell inequalities (cf.,
e.g., [33]). Indeed, the incompatibility in the Bohm-EPR experiment between quantum
mechanics and the joint existence of values of the four possible measurement results
does not depend at all on the mutual distance between the parts of the system: it
persists in exactly the same way when there is no appreciable distance between them.
The consideration of great distances between the partial systems only serves to bring
out the strange consequences of a “classical” interpretation of this contextuality in
terms of causal influences: if separations become space-like, such influences have to
be superluminal or even instantaneous. What the perspectivalism proposal does is to
replace all such talk about influences, causality and propagation speeds by the idea
that a context—or perspective—is needed to define the value of a physical quantity,
in accordance with the core of the Kochen and Specker results (and, one might add,
of certain old Bohrian ideas).
In some more technical detail, the Kochen and Specker theorem demonstrates that
if we want to assign a value to a physical quantity of a part of a composite system
represented by an operator A, we have to take into account the rest of the total system,
in the following sense. It makes a difference whether A is considered as a function
of A ⊗ B or of A ⊗ C, where B and C are observables of the rest of the system that
do not commute with each other. The Kochen and Specker theorem shows that the
assumption that A can be assigned one and the same value in all such combinations with
observables of the remainder of the system leads to a contradiction. This result is based
on the structure of the algebra of observables in Hilbert space, and holds independently
of any consideration of the distance between the systems to which A, and B, C, pertain.
The perspectivalism that we have discussed is in line with this: physical quantities are
generally defined with respect to quantities in other systems, which in the specific case
of spatially extended systems may be expressed as hyperplane dependence.10
7 Conclusion: Unitary Quantum Mechanics and Covariance
Unitary quantum mechanics faces a difficulty with relativistic covariance if it is interpreted in terms of space-time events that are characterized by locally defined properties:
it can be rigorously proved that no unitary scheme that provides such a local account
10 Of course, this perspectivalism or hyperplane dependence becomes significant only in the case of entangled states. If the total state is a product state, or if the effects of entanglement are washed out by a
decohering environment, monadic, non-perspectival properties can be ascribed to the two partial systems
without contradiction.
123
Foundations of Physics
can satisfy the requirement that the same probability rules apply equally to all hyperplanes in Minkowski space-time [13–15].
The core premise in these proofs is that intersecting hyperplanes should carry local
properties in a coherent way, so that they provide agreeing descriptions of the physical
conditions at the space-time points where they intersect. The proofs demonstrate that
this local meshing of hyperplanes is impossible, if the Born probability rule is to be
valid on all hyperplanes.
One way of responding to this situation is to introduce a privileged inertial frame of
reference. This is the course taken by the Bohm theory, according to which the Born
rule only holds in the preferred frame. This is a consistent and empirically viable way
out of the problem; but still, there is a tension with the spirit of special relativity. Indeed,
Einstein in 1905 made the equivalence of inertial frames a fundamental principle of his
theory in order to theoretically express the empirical fact that measurement results do
not provide evidence for a privileged role of any particular frame. This motivation for
the first postulate keeps its force also in quantum mechanics: the empirical predictions
of quantum mechanics, even in the Bohm interpretation, are such that they make any
assumed preferred frame undetectable.
It is therefore worth-while to ask whether there exist other options for escaping the
no-go theorems. The answer is affirmative: such a possibility has in fact been outlined
in the foregoing sections. Indeed, as we have seen, the crucial assumption in the no-go
theorems is that properties of physical systems are monadic, in the sense of independent
of the presence of other systems and locally defined independently of the hyperplane on
which they are considered. This assumption is rejected in interpretations that work with
perspectival and hyperplane dependent properties. In these interpretations physical
properties are defined per hyperplane, in a way that is relativistically covariant.
Unlike the proposal to accept the existence of a privileged inertial system, the idea
to accept that physical properties are perspectival is not ad hoc, because it addresses
more questions than merely the lack of Lorentz invariance and fits in naturally with
the mathematical structure of quantum mechanics. In particular, as argued in Sect. 6,
it may be seen as an expression of the contextuality that the Bell, and Kochen and
Specker, results have shown to be central to quantum theory.
Accepting that physical properties are not monadic and locally defined, but rather
perspectival, relational and hyperplane dependent is a huge step away from everyday experience and from the intuitions that served us well in non-quantum physics.
But it constitutes a broadening of our conceptual repertoire of exactly the kind that
Paul Busch envisaged as a benefit of investigating realist interpretations of quantum
mechanics.
Open Access This article is distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted use, distribution,
and reproduction in any medium, provided you give appropriate credit to the original author(s) and the
source, provide a link to the Creative Commons license, and indicate if changes were made.
123
Foundations of Physics
References
1. Busch, P.: Elements of unsharp reality in the EPR experiment. In: Lahti, P., Mittelstaedt, P.
(eds.) Symposium on the Foundations of Modern Physics–50 years of the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen
Gedankenexperiment, pp. 343–367. World Scientific, Singapore (1985)
2. Busch, P.: Can quantum theoretical reality be considered sharp? In: Mittelstaedt, P., Stachow, E.W.
(eds.) Recent Developments in Quantum Logic, pp. 81–101. Bibliographisches Institut, Mannheim
(1985)
3. Busch, P.: Unsharp reality and joint measurements for spin observables. Phys. Rev. D 33, 2253–2261
(1986)
4. Busch, P.: Remarks on unsharp quantum observables, objectification, and modal interpretations. In:
Dieks, D., Vermaas, P. (eds.) The Modal Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, pp. 279–288. Kluwer,
Dordrecht (1998)
5. Busch, P.: Unsharp localization and causality in relativistic quantum theory. J. Phys. A 32, 6535–6546
(1999)
6. Busch, P.: EPR-Bell tests with unsharp observables and relativistic quantum measurement. In: Placek,
T., Butterfield, J. (eds.) Non-locality and Modality. NATO Science Series (Series II: Mathematics,
Physics and Chemistry), vol. 64, pp. 175–193. Springer, Dordrecht (2002)
7. Busch, P., Jaeger, G.: Unsharp quantum reality. Found. Phys. 40, 1341–1367 (2010)
8. Everett, H.: “Relative state” formulation of quantum mechanics. Rev. Mod. Phys. 29, 454–462 (1957)
9. Wallace, D.: The Emergent Multiverse: Quantum Theory According to the Everett Interpretation.
Oxford University Press, Oxford (2012)
10. Dieks, D., Vermaas, P.: The Modal Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Kluwer Academic Publishers,
Dordrecht (1998)
11. Lombardi, O., Dieks, D.: Modal interpretations of quantum mechanics. In: Zalta E.N. (ed.) The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Spring 2017 Edition (2017). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/
entries/qm-modal/
12. Bub, J.: Interpreting the Quantum World. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1997)
13. Berndl, K., Dür, D., Goldstein, S., Zanghi, N.: Nonlocality, Lorentz invariance, and Bohmian quantum
theory. Phys. Rev. A 53, 2062–2073 (1996)
14. Dickson, M., Clifton, R.: Lorentz invariance in modal interpretations. In: Dieks, D., Vermaas, P. (eds.)
The Modal Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics, pp. 9–47. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht
(1998)
15. Myrvold, W.: Modal interpretations and relativity. Found. Phys. 32, 1773–1784 (2002)
16. Gao, S.: Unitary quantum theories are incompatible with special relativity. http://philsci-archive.pitt.
edu/15357/ (2018)
17. Norsen, T.: The pilot-wave perspective on spin. Am. J. Phys. 82, 337–348 (2014)
18. Dieks, D., Lubberdink, A.: How classical particles emerge from the quantum world. Found. Phys. 41,
1051–1064 (2011)
19. Dieks, D.: Quantum information and locality. In: Lombardi, O., et al. (eds.) What is Quantum Information?, pp. 93–112. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2017)
20. Dieks, D., Lubberdink, A.: Identical quantum particles as distinguishable objects. arXiv:1902.09280
[quant-ph] (2019)
21. Dieks, D.: Quantum mechanics and perspectivalism. arXiv:1801.09307 [physics.hist-ph]. To appear.
In: Lombardi, O., et al. (eds.) Quantum Worlds. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2019)
22. Dieks, D.: On the covariant description of wavefunction collapse. Phys. Lett. 108A, 379–383 (1985)
23. Rovelli, C.: Relational quantum mechanics. Int. J. Theor. Phys. 35, 1637–1678 (1996)
24. Bene, G., Dieks, D.: A perspectival version of the modal interpretation of quantum mechanics and the
origin of macroscopic behavior. Found. Phys. 32, 645–671 (2002)
25. Dieks, D.: Objectivity in perspective: relationism in the interpretation of quantum mechanics. Found.
Phys. 39, 760–775 (2009)
26. Laudisa, F., Rovelli, C.: Relational quantum mechanics. In: Zalta, E.N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2013 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/qmrelational/ (2013)
27. Fleming, G.: Just how radical is hyperplane dependence? In: Clifton, R. (ed.) Perspectives on Quantum
Reality, pp. 11–28. Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht (1996)
123
Foundations of Physics
28. Bacciagaluppi, G.: Remarks on space-time and locality in Everett’s interpretation. In: Placek, T.,
Butterfield, J. (eds.) Non-locality and Modality. NATO Science Series (Series II: Mathematics, Physics
and Chemistry), vol. 64. Springer, Dordrecht (2002)
29. Frauchiger, D., Renner, R.: Single-world interpretations of quantum theory cannot be self-consistent.
arXiv:1604.07422v1 [quant-ph] (2016)
30. Bub, J.: Why Bohr was (mostly) right. arXiv:1711.01604v1 [quant-ph] (2017)
31. Healey, R.: Quantum theory and the limits of objectivity. Found. Phys. 48, 1568–1589 (2018)
32. Gao, S.: Are there limits of objectivity in the quantum world? http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/15373/
(2018)
33. Mermin, N.D.: Hidden variables and the two theorems of John Bell. Rev. Mod. Phys. 65, 803–815
(1993)
Publisher’s Note Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps
and institutional affiliations.
123