Summing It Up: From One Plus One to Modern Number Theory
By Avner Ash and Robert Gross
5/5
()
About this ebook
The power and properties of numbers, from basic addition and sums of squares to cutting-edge theory
We use addition on a daily basis—yet how many of us stop to truly consider the enormous and remarkable ramifications of this mathematical activity? Summing It Up uses addition as a springboard to present a fascinating and accessible look at numbers and number theory, and how we apply beautiful numerical properties to answer math problems. Mathematicians Avner Ash and Robert Gross explore addition's most basic characteristics as well as the addition of squares and other powers before moving onward to infinite series, modular forms, and issues at the forefront of current mathematical research.
Ash and Gross tailor their succinct and engaging investigations for math enthusiasts of all backgrounds. Employing college algebra, the first part of the book examines such questions as, can all positive numbers be written as a sum of four perfect squares? The second section of the book incorporates calculus and examines infinite series—long sums that can only be defined by the concept of limit, as in the example of 1+1/2+1/4+. . .=? With the help of some group theory and geometry, the third section ties together the first two parts of the book through a discussion of modular forms—the analytic functions on the upper half-plane of the complex numbers that have growth and transformation properties. Ash and Gross show how modular forms are indispensable in modern number theory, for example in the proof of Fermat's Last Theorem.
Appropriate for numbers novices as well as college math majors, Summing It Up delves into mathematics that will enlighten anyone fascinated by numbers.
Read more from Avner Ash
Fearless Symmetry: Exposing the Hidden Patterns of Numbers - New Edition Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Elliptic Tales: Curves, Counting, and Number Theory Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5
Related to Summing It Up
Related ebooks
Gamma: Exploring Euler's Constant Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Dr. Euler's Fabulous Formula: Cures Many Mathematical Ills Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5e: The Story of a Number Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Skeleton Key of Mathematics: A Simple Account of Complex Algebraic Theories Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsNumber Theory Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Nonplussed!: Mathematical Proof of Implausible Ideas Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Fascinating World of Graph Theory Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Geometry of Complex Numbers Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Set Theory: The Structure of Arithmetic Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Elementary Theory of Numbers Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Elementary Mathematics from an Advanced Standpoint: Geometry Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Gentle Art of Mathematics Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Calculus Gallery: Masterpieces from Newton to Lebesgue Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsIn Pursuit of Zeta-3: The World's Most Mysterious Unsolved Math Problem Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Euler's Gem: The Polyhedron Formula and the Birth of Topology Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Introduction to Graph Theory Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5History of the Theory of Numbers, Volume II: Diophantine Analysis Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsIntroduction to Mathematical Thinking: The Formation of Concepts in Modern Mathematics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Axiomatic Set Theory Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Introduction to Topology: Second Edition Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Number Theory Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsBeautiful, Simple, Exact, Crazy: Mathematics in the Real World Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Fundamentals of Number Theory Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Analytic Functions Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsWhat Is Mathematical Logic? Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Fundamental Concepts of Abstract Algebra Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Heavenly Mathematics: The Forgotten Art of Spherical Trigonometry Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Proof Theory: Second Edition Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsJourney into Mathematics: An Introduction to Proofs Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Elements of Number Theory Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratings
Mathematics For You
Quantum Physics for Beginners Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5What If?: Serious Scientific Answers to Absurd Hypothetical Questions Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Algebra II For Dummies Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Alan Turing: The Enigma: The Book That Inspired the Film The Imitation Game - Updated Edition Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Calculus Made Easy Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Standard Deviations: Flawed Assumptions, Tortured Data, and Other Ways to Lie with Statistics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5My Best Mathematical and Logic Puzzles Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Intermediate Algebra Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsMath Magic: How To Master Everyday Math Problems Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Little Book of Mathematical Principles, Theories & Things Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Real Estate by the Numbers: A Complete Reference Guide to Deal Analysis Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsRelativity: The special and the general theory Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Algebra - The Very Basics Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Mental Math: Tricks To Become A Human Calculator Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Basic Math & Pre-Algebra For Dummies Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Golden Ratio: The Divine Beauty of Mathematics Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5GED® Math Test Tutor, 2nd Edition Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe New York Times Book of Mathematics: More Than 100 Years of Writing by the Numbers Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsBasic Math & Pre-Algebra Workbook For Dummies with Online Practice Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Mental Math Secrets - How To Be a Human Calculator Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Sneaky Math: A Graphic Primer with Projects Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsHow Math Explains the World: A Guide to the Power of Numbers, from Car Repair to Modern Physics Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Everything Everyday Math Book: From Tipping to Taxes, All the Real-World, Everyday Math Skills You Need Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Limitless Mind: Learn, Lead, and Live Without Barriers Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Precalculus: A Self-Teaching Guide Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Algebra I Workbook For Dummies Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5
Reviews for Summing It Up
2 ratings0 reviews
Book preview
Summing It Up - Avner Ash
UP
Introduction
WHAT THIS BOOK IS ABOUT
1. Plus
Counting—one, two, three, four or uno, dos, tres, cuatro (or in whatever language); or I, II, III, IV or 1, 2, 3, 4, or in whatever symbols—is probably the first theoretical mathematical activity of human beings. It is theoretical because it is detached from the objects, whatever they might be, that are being counted. The shepherd who first piled up pebbles, one for each sheep let out to graze, and then tossed them one by one as the sheep came back to the fold, was performing a practical mathematical act—creating a one-to-one correspondence. But this act was merely practical, without any theory to go with it.
This book is concerned with what may have been the next mathematical activity to be discovered (or invented): addition. We may think that addition is primitive or easy, because we teach it to young children. A moment’s reflection will convince you that it must have taken an enormous intellectual effort to conceive of an abstract theory of addition. There cannot be addition of two numbers before there are numbers, and the formation of pure numbers is sophisticated because it involves abstraction.
You may want to plunge into the mathematics of addition and skip the rest of this section. Or you may want to muse a little on philosophical problems connected with the concepts and practice of mathematics, as exemplified in the subject matter of this book. Those who have a taste for these philosophical questions may enjoy the following extremely brief survey.
Perhaps this abstraction of pure numbers was formed through the experience of counting. Once you had a series of number words, you could count axes one day, sheep the next, and apples the third day. After a while, you might just recite those words without any particular thing being counted, and then you might stumble onto the concept of a pure number. It is more probable that arithmetic and the abstract concept of number were developed together.¹
One way to see the difficulty of the concepts of number, counting, and addition is to look at the philosophy of mathematics, which to this day has not been able to decide on a universally acceptable definition of number.
The ancient Greek philosophers didn’t even consider that the number one was a number, since in their opinion numbers were what we counted, and no one would bother to count one, period.
We won’t say more about the very difficult philosophy of mathematics, except to mention one type of issue. Immanuel Kant and his followers were very concerned with addition and how its operations could be justified philosophically. Kant claimed that there were "synthetic truths a priori. These were statements that were true, and could be known by us to be true prior to any possible experience, but whose truth was not dependent on the mere meaning of words. For example, the statement
A bachelor doesn’t have a wife is true without needing any experience to vouch for its truth, because it is part of the definition of
bachelor that he doesn’t have a wife. Such a truth was called
analytic a priori. Kant claimed that
five plus seven equals twelve was indubitably true, not needing any experience to validate its truth, but it was
synthetic because (Kant claimed) the concept of
twelve was not logically bound up and implied by the concepts of
five,
seven, and
plus." In this way, Kant could point to arithmetic to show that synthetic truths a priori existed, and then could go on to consider other such truths that came up later in his philosophy.
In contrast, other philosophers, such as Bertrand Russell, have thought that mathematical truths are all analytic. These philosophers often think logic is prior to mathematics. And then there is the view that mathematical truths are "a posteriori," meaning they are dependent on experience. This seems to have been Ludwig Wittgenstein’s opinion. It was also apparently the opinion of the rulers in George Orwell’s novel 1984, who were able to get the hero, in defeat, to believe firmly that two plus two equals five.
The philosophy of mathematics is exceedingly complicated, technical, and difficult. During the twentieth century, things grew ever more vexed. W.V.O. Quine questioned the analytic–synthetic distinction entirely. The concept of truth (which has always been a hard one to corner) became more and more problematic. Today, philosophers do not agree on much, if anything, concerning the philosophical foundations of numbers and their properties. Luckily, we do not need to decide on these philosophical matters to enjoy some of the beautiful theories about numbers that have been developed by mathematicians. We all have some intuitive grasp of what a number is, and that grasp seems to be enough to develop concepts that are both free from contradictions and yield significant theorems about numbers. We can test these theorems doing arithmetic by hand or by computer. By verifying particular number facts, we have the satisfaction of seeing that the theorems work.
2. Sums of Interest
This book is divided into three parts. The first part will require you to know college algebra and Cartesian coordinates but, except in a few places, nothing substantially beyond that. In this part, we will ask such questions as:
• Is there a short formula for the sum 1 + 2 + 3 + · · · + k?
• How about the sum 1² + 2² + 3² + · · · + k²?
• We can be even more ambitious. Let n be an arbitrary integer, and ask for a short formula for 1n + 2n + 3n + · · · + kn.
• How about the sum 1 + a + a² + · · · + ak?
• Can a given integer N be written as a sum of perfect squares? Cubes? nth powers? Triangular numbers? Pentagonal numbers?
• Obviously, an integer larger than 1 can be written as a sum of smaller positive integers. We can ask: In how many different ways can this be done?
• If a number can be written as a sum of k squares, in how many different ways can this be done?
Why do we ask these questions? Because it is fun and historically motivated, and the answers lead to beautiful methods of inquiry and amazing proofs.
In the second part of this book, you will need to know some calculus. We will look at infinite series.
These are infinitely long sums that can only be defined using the concept of limit. For example,
Here the dots mean that we intend the summing to go on forever.
It seems pretty clear that there can’t be any answer to this sum, because the partial totals just keep getting bigger and bigger. If we want, we can define the sum to be infinity,
but this is just a shorter way of saying what we said in the previous sentence.
This, too, is clearly infinity.
How should we evaluate
Now you might hesitate. Euler.
We will see that this problem has a nice answer if a is a real number strictly between –1 and 1. You may have learned this answer when you studied geometric series.
We will expand our algebra so that we can use a complex number for a.
Then we can ask about
where n is any complex number. This answer (for some values of n) gives a function of n called the ζ-function.
Going back one step, we can add in coefficients:
This is the setting in which we introduce the concept of generating function, where a itself is a variable.
We can also add coefficients to the ζ-function series and ask about series like
which are called Dirichlet series.
These questions and their answers put us in position in the third part of this book to define and discuss modular forms. The surprising thing will be how the modular forms tie together the subject matter of the first two parts. This third part will require a little bit of group theory and some geometry, and will be on a somewhat higher level of sophistication than the preceding parts.
One motivation for this book is to explain modular forms, which have become indispensable in modern number theory. In both of our previous two books, modular forms appeared briefly but critically toward the end. In this book, we want to take our time and explain some things about them, although we will only be scratching the surface of a very broad and deep subject. At the end of the book, we will review how modular forms were used in Ash and Gross (2006) to tie up Galois representations and prove Fermat’s Last Theorem, and in Ash and Gross (2012) to be able to phrase the fascinating Birch–Swinnerton-Dyer Conjecture about solutions to cubic equations.
As a leitmotif for this book, we will take the problem of sums of squares,
because it is a very old and very pretty problem whose solution is best understood through the theory of modular forms. We can describe the problem a little now.
Consider a whole number n. We say n is a square if it equals m², where m is also a whole number. For example, 64 is a square, because it is 8 times 8, but 63 is not a square. Notice that we define 0 = 0² as a square, and similarly 1 = 1². We easily list all squares by starting with the list 0, 1, 2,… and squaring each number in turn. (Because a negative number squared is the same as its absolute value squared, we only have to use the nonnegative integers.) We obtain the list of squares
in which, as you can see, the squares get farther and farther apart as you go along. (PROOF: The distance between successive squares is (m + 1)² – m² = m² + 2m + 1 – m² = 2m + 1, so the distance gets larger as m gets larger. Notice that this argument gives us more precise information: The list of differences between successive squares is in fact the list of positive odd numbers in increasing order.) We can be very pedantic, if a bit ungrammatical, and say that the list of squares is the list of numbers that are the sum of one square.
This raises a more interesting question: What is the list of numbers that are the sum of two squares? You could write a computer program that would output this list up to some limit N, and your computer program could generate the list in at least two different ways. First, list all the squares up to N. Then:
NOTE: We have defined 0 as a square, so any square number is also a sum of two squares. For example, 81 = 0² + 9². Also, we allow a square to be reused, so twice any square number is a sum of two squares. For example, 162 = 9² + 9².
Run your program, or add squares by hand. Either way, you get a list of the sums of two squares that starts out like this:
As you can see, not every number is on the list, and it is not immediately clear how to predict if a given number will be a sum of two squares or not. For instance, is there a way to tell if 12345678987654321 is on the list without simply running your computer program? Nowadays, your program would probably only take a fraction of a second to add up all squares up to 12345678987654321, but we can easily write down a number large enough to slow down the computer. More importantly, we would like a theoretical answer to our question, whose proof would give us some insight into which numbers are on the list and which ones are not.
Pierre de Fermat asked this question in the seventeenth century³ and must have made such a list. There were no computers in the seventeenth century, so his list could not have been all that long, but he was able to guess the correct answer as to which numbers are sums of two squares.⁴ In chapter 2, we will supply the answer and discuss the proof in a sketchy way. Because this book is not a textbook, we don’t want to give complete proofs. We prefer to tell a story that may be more easily read. If you wish, you can refer to our references and find the complete proof.
Once you get interested in this kind of problem (as did Fermat, who gave a huge impulse to the study of number theory), then it is easy to create more of them. Which numbers are sums of three squares? Of four squares? Of five squares? This particular list of puzzles will stop because, 0 being a square, any sum of four squares will also be a sum of five, six, or any larger amount of squares, and we will see that in fact every positive integer is a sum of four squares.
You could also ask: Which numbers are sums of two cubes, three cubes, four cubes, and so on? You could then substitute higher powers for cubes.
You could ask, as did Euler: Any number is a sum of four squares. A geometrical square has four sides. Is every number a sum of three triangular numbers, five pentagonal numbers, and so on? Cauchy proved that the answer is yes.
At some point in mathematical history, something very creative happened. Mathematicians started to ask an apparently harder question. Rather than wonder if n can be written as a sum of 24 squares (for example), we ask: In how many different ways can n be written as the sum of 24 squares? If the number of ways is 0, then n is not a sum of 24 squares. But if n is a sum of 24 squares, we get more information than just a yes/no answer. It turned out that this harder question led to the discovery of powerful tools that have a beauty and importance that transcends the puzzle of sums of powers, namely tools in the theory of generating functions and modular forms. And that’s another thing that this book is about.
¹ Of course, in practice, two apples are easily added to two apples to give four apples. But a theoretical approach that could lead to the development of number theory is more difficult. There was a period in the mathematical thought of the ancient Greek world when pure
numbers were not clearly distinguished from object
numbers. For an account of the early history of arithmetic and algebra, we recommend Klein (1992).
² One way to justify Euler’s answer is to use the formula for the sum of an infinite geometric series. In chapter 7, section 5, we have the formula
valid as long as |z| < 1. If we dare to go outside the region of validity and substitute z = –1, we see why Euler interpreted the sum as he did.
³ Apparently, another mathematician, Albert Girard, had asked the question and guessed the answer before Fermat, but Fermat publicized the problem.
⁴ Fermat announced the answer in a letter to another mathematician, Marin Mersenne, without giving a proof. The first printed proof was written by Leonhard Euler.
PART ONE
Finite Sums
Chapter 1
PROEM
In the interest of allowing the reader to enjoy our book without constantly referring to many other references, we collect in this chapter many standard facts that we will often use in the remainder of the book. A reader familiar with elementary number theory can skip this chapter and refer back to it when necessary. We covered most of these topics in Ash and Gross (2006).
1. Greatest Common Divisors
If a is a positive integer and b is any integer, then long division tells us that we can always divide a into b and get an integer quotient q and integer remainder r. This means that b = qa + r, and the remainder r always satisfies the inequality 0 ≤ r < a. For example, if we take a = 3 and b = 14, then 14 = 4 · 3 + 2; the quotient q = 4 and the remainder r = 2. You may not be used to thinking about it, but you can do this with b < 0 also. Take b = –14 and a = 3, and –14 = (–5) · 3 + 1; the quotient is q = – 5, and the remainder is r = 1. Notice that if we divide by 2, the remainder will always be 0 or 1; if we divide by 3, the remainder will always be 0, 1, or 2; and so on.
If the result of the long division has r = 0, then we say that "a divides b." We write this sentence symbolically as a | b. Of course, one requirement for long division is that a cannot be 0, so whenever we write a | b, we implicitly assert that a ≠ 0. If the remainder r is not zero, we say that "a does not divide b." We write that assertion symbolically as a∤b. For example, 3 | 6, 3∤14, and 3∤(–14). Notice that if n is any integer (even 0), then 1 | n. Also, if a is any positive integer, then a | 0. At the risk of giving too many examples, we also point out that 2 | n means that n is even, and 2∤n means that n is odd.
Suppose now that m and n are integers that are not both 0. We can then define the greatest common divisor:
DEFINITION: The greatest common divisor of m and n, symbolically written (m, n), is the largest integer d such that d | m and d | n. If the greatest common divisor of m and n is 1, we say that m and n are relatively prime.
Because all divisors of m are at most as big as m (if m > 0) or –m (if m < 0), we can theoretically list all divisors of m and all divisors of n, and then pick the largest number that is on both lists. We know that the number 1 is on both lists, and there may or may not be any larger number simultaneously on both lists. For example, (3, 6) = 3, (4, 7) = 1, (6, 16) = 2, and (31, 31) = 31. This process would be tedious, though, if we wanted to compute (1234567, 87654321). There is a process called the Euclidean algorithm, which allows one to compute greatest common divisors without listing all of the divisors of both m and n. We will not describe that process here, but we will state and prove one consequence, often called Bézout’s identity.
THEOREM 1.1: Suppose that m and n are not both 0, and suppose that d is the greatest common divisor of m and n. Then there are integers λ and μ such that d = λm + μn.