Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

From $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

100 Great Philosophers Who Changed the World
100 Great Philosophers Who Changed the World
100 Great Philosophers Who Changed the World
Ebook381 pages5 hours

100 Great Philosophers Who Changed the World

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Who am I? What is justice? What does it mean to live a good life?

Fully illustrated throughout, this engaging and accessible hardback book invites readers to contemplate the ideas of 100 key philosophers within the Western intellectual tradition. Covering philosophical, scientific, political and religious thought over a period of 2500 years, 100 Great Philosophers Who Changed the World serves as an excellent guide to this history of philosophy and the progress that has been made in interpreting the world around us.

These figures include:
• Aristotle
• Jean-Jacques Rousseau
• Karl Marx
• Simone de Beauvoir
• Noam Chomsky
• W.V.O Quine

By presenting details of their lives and the concerns and circumstances that motivated them, this book makes philosophy come to life as a relevant and meaningful approach to thinking about the contemporary world.

LanguageEnglish
Release dateApr 15, 2021
ISBN9781398806160
100 Great Philosophers Who Changed the World
Author

Philip Stokes

Philip Stokes graduated with a BA(Hons) in Philosophy from the University of Reading in 1993, and gained his Masters degree from Bristol University in 1995. His Masters dissertation was a critique of Quine from a Wittgensteinian perspective. After working for several years in academic publishing, Philip returned to academia proper, beginning his PhD at the University of Reading, where he was Course tutor within the Department of Continuing Education at Reading. In 2005 he took up a post at Chulalongkom University in Thailand, where he is a member of the Language Faculty.

Read more from Philip Stokes

Related to 100 Great Philosophers Who Changed the World

Related ebooks

Philosophy For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for 100 Great Philosophers Who Changed the World

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    100 Great Philosophers Who Changed the World - Philip Stokes

    100 Great Philosophers Who Changed the World, by Philip Stokes

    Contents

    Introduction

    The Presocratics

    Thales of Miletus

    Pythagoras of Samos

    Xenophanes of Colophon

    Heraclitus

    The Eleatics

    Parmenides of Elea

    Zeno of Elea

    The Academics

    Socrates

    Plato

    Aristotle

    The Atomists

    Democritus

    Epicurus

    The Cynics

    Diogenes of Sinope

    The Stoics

    Marcus Tullius Cicero

    Philo of Alexandria

    Lucius Annaeus Seneca

    Marcus Aurelius

    The Sceptics

    Sextus Empiricus

    The Neoplatonists

    Plotinus

    The Christians

    St Augustine of Hippo

    Boethius

    The Scholastics

    St Anselm

    St Thomas Aquinas

    John Duns Scotus

    William of Occam

    The Age of Science

    Nicolaus Copernicus

    Niccolò Machiavelli

    Desiderus Erasmus

    Thomas More

    Francis Bacon

    Galileo Galilei

    Thomas Hobbes

    Sir Isaac Newton

    The Rationalists

    René Descartes

    Antoine Arnauld

    Nicolas Malebranche

    Benedict de Spinoza

    Gottfried von Leibniz

    The Empiricists

    John Locke

    David Hume

    Thomas Reid

    Voltaire

    Jean-Jacques Rousseau

    Denis Diderot

    The Idealists

    George Berkeley

    Immanuel Kant

    Johann Schiller

    Frederick Schelling

    Georg Hegel

    Arthur Schopenhauer

    The Liberals

    Adam Smith

    Mary Wollstonecraft

    Thomas Paine

    Jeremy Bentham

    John Stuart Mill

    Auguste Comte

    The Evolutionists

    Charles Darwin

    Henri Louis Bergson

    A.N. Whitehead

    The Pragmatists

    Ernst Mach

    Charles Peirce

    William James

    John Dewey

    The Materialists

    Karl Marx

    Friedrich Engels

    Vladimir Lenin

    Sigmund Freud

    Carl Jung

    John Maynard Keynes

    The Existentialists

    Søren Kierkegaard

    Friedrich Nietzsche

    Edmund Husserl

    Martin Heidegger

    Jean-Paul Sartre

    Albert Camus

    Simone de Beauvoir

    The Linguistic Turn

    Gottlob Frege

    Bertrand Russell

    Ludwig Wittgenstein

    Ferdinand de Saussure

    George Edward Moore

    Moritz Schlick

    Lev Vygotsky

    Rudolph Carnap

    A.J. Ayer

    Alfred Tarski

    J.L. Austin

    Gilbert Ryle

    Noam Chomsky

    The Postmodernists

    Claude Levi-Strauss

    Michel Foucault

    Jacques Derrida

    The New Scientists

    Emile Durkheim

    Albert Einstein

    Karl Popper

    Kurt Gödel

    Alan Turing

    B.F. Skinner

    Thomas Kuhn

    Paul Feyerabend

    W.V.O. Quine

    Introduction

    There are more things in heaven and earth, Horatio, than are dreamt of in your philosophy

    Hamlet, I.v.

    When Shakespeare’s Hamlet utters those memorable lines, he is worrying about the spirit of his dead father haunting both the battlements of the castle and his own troubled mind. Shakespeare was writing in the time of Bacon and Galileo, in a world already shaped by the ideas of Machiavelli and Copernicus. Ever the social commentator, he was more than likely using Hamlet to offer a riposte to the pronouncements of the new ‘age of science’, the philosophy of his time, which was moving away from the spiritual and ever-closer to a wholly materialist conception of the world.

    Hamlet’s pronouncement nevertheless provides a useful characterization of the aim of the philosophers in this book. Exactly what more is there to ‘heaven and earth’ that is not represented in the knowledge we already possess? There is little unity to the answers provided by the thinkers you will find here, but that is only to be expected. On the one hand philosophy is like any other human endeavour, situated within and confined by the context of its day and yet on the other hand, it tries to wrestle with and expand the boundaries of current thought. It is neither a science, interested in the collection and organization of new information, nor an art, representing a reaction to the world as perceived. Philosophy, then, is an altogether unique activity. With this in mind, the thoughts of the great philosophers explored in the following pages will be all the clearer if we approach them with some understanding of the nature and value of their enterprise.

    If there is one thing that characterizes both the method and the results of philosophical inquiry, it must be the general lack of consensus that precedes the whole process, and often remains even after the work is complete. The reason for this lies in the kinds of questions philosophers are interested in. Many questions outside of philosophy seem to have answers that command widespread agreement; this is typical, for instance, of science subjects. In the sciences, many answers enjoy a general consensus because people agree both on the assumptions upon which the questions are based and on the application of certain concepts within that discipline. Nonetheless, there are some questions that arise, both in science and elsewhere, where none of the suggested answers command widespread acceptance, even given shared assumptions and an agreement about concepts. These are the sorts of questions in which philosophers are typically interested.

    The reason philosophers have trouble agreeing, then, is partly because that is the nature of the subject (philosophy deals in questions that people in general don’t agree on) and partly because philosophers go about their business by challenging assumptions and concepts in order to generate new perspectives on recalcitrant problems.

    Despite the inherent difficulty of philosophy its value should not be underestimated. As recent discoveries in genetics and biotechnology have shown, it is impossible to know what to do with scientific discoveries without reflecting on what sort of a society we want to live in and what duties we owe each other, our descendants and the environment. Answers to all these questions depend on what conception we have of ourselves as human beings and what we think that means for the best way to live. None of these issues are questions for science or for art, but for philosophy.

    Since philosophers are engaged in exploring every avenue of thought, it should cause no surprise that many of their conclusions strike us as unacceptable in some way or another. At least one of the merits of such work is that it can indicate what we should not believe. But it should be equally appreciated that the conclusions of philosophers have also had profound effects. The two great superpowers of the twentieth century, the USA and the USSR, were born of the philosophical writings of Tom Paine and Karl Marx respectively. The modern information age would never have been possible without the work of the great logician Frege. Female suffrage was taken seriously only after Wollstonecraft. The Enlightenment stood in need of a Voltaire, Einstein needed Newton and Newton, in turn, relied on Aristotle. The history of social, political and technological change is inextricably bound to the history of thought.

    To some it has often seemed that modern philosophy is both undervalued and overlooked. They should not be so concerned. In the wider sense philosophical reflection is a natural enterprise concomitant with our inquiries on any level. It is not solely the province of specialists, but an intrinsic and indispensable part of a person’s navigation through life. If Hamlet is right, Horatio’s only response is to continue to expand the limits of his thought, in other words, to continue to dream.

    100

    Essential Thinkers

    Thales of Miletus

    c.620–540BC

    The first natural scientist and analytical philosopher in Western intellectual history

    Credited as the first philosopher of Ancient Greece, and therefore the founder of Western philosophy, Thales hailed from the Ionian seaport of Miletus, now in modern Turkey. Miletus was a major centre of development for both science and philosophy in Ancient Greece. Thales, probably born somewhere around 620 BC is mainly remembered as the presocratic philosopher who claimed that the fundamental nature of the world is water. Aristotle mentions him, as does Herodotus, and these are really our only accounts of Thales’ background. However, his significance as a philosopher is not so much what he said, but his method. Thales was the first thinker to try to account for the nature of the world without appealing to the wills and whims of anthropomorphic, Homerian gods. Rather, he sought to explain the many diverse phenomena he observed by appealing to a common, underlying principle, an idea that is still germane to modern scientific method. He is also credited by Herodotus with correctly predicting that there would be a solar eclipse in 585 BC during a battle between the Medes and the Lydians. As such, Thales can with some justification be thought of as the first natural scientist and analytical philosopher in Western intellectual history.

    Thales had other modern traits, for it also seems that he was something of an entrepreneur. According to one story, Thales made a fortune investing in oil-presses before a heavy olive crop – certainly he would have had to be wealthy in order to devote time and thought to philosophy and science in seventh century BC Ancient Greece.

    According to his metaphysics, water was the first principle of life and the material world. Seeing that water could turn into both vapour by evaporation and a solid by freezing, that all life required and was supported by moisture, he postulated that it was the single causal principle behind the natural world. In a crude anticipation of modern plate tectonics, Thales professed that the flat earth floated on water. Aristotle tells us that Thales thought the earth had a buoyancy much like wood, and that the earth floated on water much like a log or a ship. Indeed, many floating islands were said to be known to the sea-farers of Miletus, which may have served as either models or evidence for Thales’ theory. He even accounted for earthquakes as being due to the rocking of the earth by subterranean waves, just as a ship may be rocked at sea. From the port of Miletus he would have been familiar with the phenomenon of sedimentation, possibly believing it to be the spontaneous generation of earth from water, an idea held as recently as the eighteenth century.

    Having sought to give a naturalistic explanation of observable phenomena, rather than appealing to the wills of gods, Thales claimed that god is in all things. According to Aetius, Thales said the mind of the world is god, that god is intermingled in all things, a view that would shortly appear contemporaneously in a number of world religions, most notably Buddhism in India. Despite his metaphysical speculations being clearly mistaken, it seems that Thales was a modern thinker in more ways than one, pre-empting many ideas in religion, philosophy and science.

    Pythagoras of Samos

    c.570–480BC

    The ultimate nature of reality is number

    Probably born around the mid-sixth century BC no exact date is known as to when Pythagoras lived. Despite his name being familiar to every schoolchild for Pythagoras’ Theorem, which states that the square of the hypotenuse of a right-angled triangle is equal to the sum of the squares of the remaining two sides, it is likely that this was known both to the Babylonians – where Pythagoras is thought to have travelled in his youth – and the Egyptians.

    Pythagoras was a somewhat shadowy figure and like Socrates after him wrote nothing himself, preferring to leave his students to document his thoughts. Reputed to be a mystic as well as a thinker, the school he founded would nowadays be thought of as a religious cult that taught many unusual and strange doctrines including, notoriously, the veneration for – and abstinence from the eating of – beans. Pythagoras also preached reincarnation and the transmigration of souls and is largely responsible for the modern belief in numerology, later popularized by Nostradamus.

    According to Pythagoras, the ultimate nature of reality is number. This idea developed out of his theory of music, in which he proved that the intervals between musical tones could be expressed as ratios between the first four integers (the numbers one to four). Since part of Pythagoras’ religious teaching consisted in the claim that music has a special power over the soul, infused as it is into the very fabric of the universe, the belief that number is the ultimate nature of reality quickly followed.

    The Pythagoreans went on to venerate certain numerical patterns, especially the so-called ‘tetractys of the decad’. The tetractys is a diagram that represents the first four numbers in a triangle of ten dots:

    Both the triangle and the number 10 – the decad – became objects of worship for the Pythagoreans. In Pythagorean thought, the number 10 is the perfect number because it is made up of the sum of the first four integers, as shown in the tetractys. The integers themselves were thought to represent fundamental ideas – the number one representing the point, two the line, three the surface and four the solid. Further, it was thought that there were ten heavenly bodies – five planets, the sun, the moon, the earth and a mysterious and invisible ‘counter-earth’ (probably invented to make the celestial number up to ten) all revolving around a central fire.

    After Pythagoras’ death, his school splintered into two camps. One maintained his religious and mystical teachings, while the other concentrated on his mathematical and scientific insights. The latter continued to believe the nature of the universe must be essentially arithmetical. Units of number, points, were somehow thought to possess spatial dimensions and be the ultimate constituents of objects. An idea later criticized by both Parmenides and Zeno. The Pythagorean cosmogony also encountered grave problems due to one of Pythagoras’ own discoveries. For Pythagoras had shown how the ratio of the diagonal through a square to its sides could not be expressed as a whole number. The problem of ‘the incommensurability of the diagonal’ led to the discovery – or invention, depending on your philosophical point of view – of irrational numbers. Though a major problem for the Pythagorean cosmogony, irrational numbers have proven a major and lasting development in mathematical thinking.

    Xenophanes of Colophon

    c.570–?475BC

    ‘If horses could draw, they would draw their gods like horses’

    Like many of the presocratic philosophers whom we know of mainly through mention by later authors, exact dates for Xenophanes are uncertain. What is known is that Heraclitus mentions him as a contemporary and critic of Pythagoras, and we can thus date him as living roughly at around the same time.

    Exiled by the Persian wars in Ionia to southern Italy, Xenophanes wandered the polities of Ancient Greece as a poet and freethinker. Following Thales, he criticized the Homerian concept of anthropomorphic gods. Homer’s gods, Xenophanes complained, had all the immoral and disgraceful traits of flawed human beings and should hardly be the object of veneration. In one of the earliest known expressions of cultural relativism, Xenophanes remarked that Homer’s gods were simply a reflection of Homerian culture. As he proclaimed, ‘the Ethiopians make their Gods black and snub-nosed; the Thracians say theirs have blue eyes and red hair’. If oxen and horses had hands and could paint, Xenophanes said, oxen would no doubt paint the forms of gods like oxen and horses would paint them like horses. Likewise, he criticized Pythagoras’ doctrine of the transmigration of souls, making fun of the idea that a human soul could inhabit another animal. Xenophanes held some vague concept of a single deity that was ‘in no way like men in shape or in thought’ but rather ‘causing all things by the thought of his mind’.

    Like Thales before him, Xenophanes speculated about the underlying principles of natural phenomena. Whereas Thales had conceived the first principle to be water, Xenophanes proposed the rather less glamorous possibility of mud. The speculation was not entirely unreasonable at the time, having the virtue of at least being based on observation. For Xenophanes had noticed the fossil remains of sea-creatures embedded in the earth, and guessed that perhaps the world periodically dried up, returning to its original muddy state, trapping and preserving the earth’s creatures as it did so before reversal of the process.

    Xenophanes was also the first known thinker to anticipate Socrates’ caution regarding claims of certain knowledge. Philosophical certainties could not be had, according to Xenophanes, for even if we chance to hit upon the truth, there is no way of knowing for certain that things are as we think they are. Nevertheless, this does not make philosophical inquiry useless, for exposing errors in our thinking can at least tell us what is certainly not the case, even if it cannot tell us what certainly is the case. This idea has a modern counterpart in the falsificationist methodology of Karl Popper.

    There is little coherent or underlying structure to Xenophanes’ thought, or at least not that we can tell from the fragments that have come down through history. This is perhaps unsurprising for someone who was essentially a refugee of the political turbulence in Asia Minor and who propagated his thoughts and speculations mostly in the form of oral poems and stories. Nonetheless, Xenophanes clearly had enough influence to be remembered and mentioned by those that followed him. Quite probably it is his criticism of the Homeric gods, still revered throughout the Hellenistic world during and long after Xenophanes’ time, that attracted a great deal of attention to him.

    Heraclitus

    c.?600 –?540BC

    War and strife between opposites is the eternal condition of the universe

    Everything is in a state of flux, or change, and war and strife between opposites is the eternal condition of the universe. So claimed Heraclitus, whilst famously condemning his fellow citizens of Ephesus as so witless they should hang themselves and leave the city to the rule of children. An antagonist of the first order, Heraclitus ridiculed Homer, claiming he should have been turned out and whipped, and further poured scorn on the ideas and intellectual integrity of both Pythagoras and Xenophanes, amongst others.

    Seeking to understand the basic structure of the universe, Heraclitus thought the three principal elements of nature were Fire, Earth and Water. However, Fire is the primary element, controlling and modifying the other two. ‘All things are an exchange for Fire, and Fire for all things...the transformations of Fire are, first of all, sea; and half of the sea is earth, half whirlwind’.

    The cosmic fire has its counterpart in the human soul, which in weak men is tainted by the ‘watery’ elements of sleep, stupidity and vice. The virtuous soul can survive the death of its physical body and eventually rejoin the cosmic fire. However, the process of separation and unity is continual. Mirroring the Oriental concepts of yin and yang, Heraclitus believed the dynamism between opposites was the driving force and eternal condition of the universe. ‘Men do not understand that being at variance it also agrees with itself, there is a harmony, as with the bow and the lyre’. Heraclitus continues to tell us that ‘God is day and night, winter and summer, war and peace, fullness and hunger’. Strife and opposition are both necessary and good, for the concept of universal tension ensures that whilst opposites may enjoy periods of alternating dominance, none shall ever completely extinguish or vanquish the other: ‘The sun may not overstep his measure; for the Erinyes, the handmaids of Justice, shall find him out’.

    This universal tension ensures that change is continual, that everything is in a state of flux. Permanence does not exist in the universe, only the permanent condition of change as a result of the transformations of Fire. This implies that whilst nothing remains changeless within the universe, the universe itself is eternal. The universe ‘was ever, is now, and ever shall be, an ever-living Fire’.

    Heraclitus, unlike the emerging rationalist philosophers of his period, chose not to explain the reasons behind his thinking in very great detail. Indeed, the fragments of his works that survive are so obscure that even those who followed in his footsteps, principally the Stoics, nicknamed him ‘the riddler’. His works are written in aphoristic and prophetic style, with a clear contempt for those that cannot see what is clearly before them. Heraclitus is undoubtedly a mystic and there are strong affinities between his writings and the Chinese classic Tao Te Ching supposedly written by Lao Tzu (‘Old Master’)

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1