The Geography of Good and Evil: Philosophical Investigations
4/5
()
About this ebook
In this bracing book, the eminent Dutch philosopher Andreas Kinneging turns fashionable thinking on its head, revealing how good and evil are objective, universal, and unchanging—and how they must be rediscovered in our age.
In mapping the geography of good and evil, Kinneging reclaims, and reintroduces us to, the great tradition of ancient and Christian thought. Traditional wisdom enables us to address the eternal questions of good and evil that confront us in both public and private life. Though it is common to accept uncritically the blessings of modernity and its intellectual sources, the Enlightenment and Romanticism, Kinneging shows that traditional thinking is richer and more realistic. Indeed, we see how, in more than a few respects, the Enlightenment and Romanticism brought not progress but deterioration. Kinneging skillfully reformulates and defends the insights of traditional thinking for today's readers, demonstrating how an objective morality is to be understood and how we can know what morality demands of us.
At a time when the traditional virtues have practically disappeared from our language (that is, all but one—"tolerance"), he lays out the foundations of virtue and vice. Ultimately, Kinneging reveals the lasting significance of these seemingly archaic notions—to our own lives, to our families, to our culture, and to civilization.
This profound, award-winning work establishes Andreas Kinneging as one of our wisest moral philosophers.
Andreas Kinneging
Andreas Kinneging, a professor of legal philosophy at the University of Leiden (Netherlands), was awarded the Socrates prize in 2006 for the best Dutch book in the field of philosophy.
Related to The Geography of Good and Evil
Related ebooks
A Critical History of Greek Philosophy Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Will to Power Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Proposed Roads to Freedom Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Ethics Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Aristotle: The Complete Works Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Antichrist Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsBeyond Good and Evil Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Black Rabbit: A Novel About the Trial and Hanging of Saddam Hussein Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Greek Philosophy - Simple Guides Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5In Praise of Doubt: How to Have Convictions Without Becoming a Fanatic Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Human, All Too Human Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsFrom Plato to NATO: The Idea of the West and Its Opponents Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Adventures of Huckleberry Finn (Centaur Classics) [The 100 greatest novels of all time - #15] Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsA History of Religious Ideas Volume 1: From the Stone Age to the Eleusinian Mysteries Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Tao Te Ching Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Conscious Capitalism and Moral Compass Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Metaphysics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Gettysburg Address Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5History of Philosophy Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Meditations on First Philosophy Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Socratic Method: A Practitioner's Handbook Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Understanding Kant: Concepts and Intuitions Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsSocrates and the State Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Just So: Money, Materialism, and the Ineffable, Intelligent Universe Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsGreat Philosophers Volume One: The Road to Inner Freedom, The Art of Philosophizing, and Pilgrimage to Humanity Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Philosophy of History Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Age of Reason Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Republic Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Great American Disconnect: Seven Fundamental Threats To Our Democracy Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Tyranny of Silence Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5
Philosophy For You
The Source: The Secrets of the Universe, the Science of the Brain Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Art of War Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Four Loves Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Sun Tzu's The Art of War: Bilingual Edition Complete Chinese and English Text Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Republic by Plato Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Boy, the Mole, the Fox and the Horse Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Inward Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Beyond Good and Evil Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Dictionary of Obscure Sorrows Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Meditations of Marcus Aurelius Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Laws of Connection: The Scientific Secrets of Building a Strong Social Network Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Little Book of Hygge: Danish Secrets to Happy Living Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Courage to Be Happy: Discover the Power of Positive Psychology and Choose Happiness Every Day Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Meditations: Complete and Unabridged Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Sapiens: A Brief History of Humankind Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Art of Loving Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Plato and a Platypus Walk Into a Bar...: Understanding Philosophy Through Jokes Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Be Here Now Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Art of Communicating Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5How to Pray: Reflections and Essays Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Experiencing God (2021 Edition): Knowing and Doing the Will of God Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Plato's Republic Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Tao Te Ching: A New English Version Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Egyptian Book of the Dead: The Complete Papyrus of Ani Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Bhagavad Gita Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Antidote: Happiness for People Who Can't Stand Positive Thinking Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Reviews for The Geography of Good and Evil
10 ratings0 reviews
Book preview
The Geography of Good and Evil - Andreas Kinneging
The Geography of Good and Evil
Philosophical Investigations
Andreas Kinneging
Translated by Ineke Hardy
The Geography of Good and Evil, by Andreas Kinneging, Regnery GatewayPREFACE TO THE ENGLISH EDITION
This book is the work of a convert who once firmly believed in the blessings of modernity and its intellectual sources, the Enlightenment and Romanticism, but at some point suddenly grasped that what the Enlightenment and Romanticism brought us constitutes in more than a few respects a decline and a deterioration, instead of progress and improvement. The author who converted me was Cicero. I was studying him with the intention of showing that the political and moral thought of the Romans was primitive and inadequate, as compared to modern political and moral thought. At a certain moment, I perceived that it was not their thinking but ours that is primitive and inadequate. A complete about-face. What I had set out to describe as an outmoded worldview was far superior to the new worldview, or views, that had replaced it. I had to completely rewrite the book I had been working on. What eventually emerged was a work titled Aristocracy, Antiquity, and History: Classicism in Political Thought.
Roman thought—and Cicero in particular—was heavily dependent on the Greeks. My existential opening up to Cicero hence made it possible for me to read the Greeks, particularly Plato, existentially as well. I became able to read them as authors from whom we can actually learn much—something that I had not previously managed to do. Christianity did not interest me at that point, although it was not a subject I was unfamiliar with. As a child of Roman Catholic parents, I had absorbed a certain amount of knowledge of Christianity in my early youth, but as an adolescent, unhampered by any real insight, I had rejected it altogether. After that, Christianity ceased to exist for me. I still remember bursting into laughter when I came across the notion of sin while leafing through the Catholic catechism. It seemed idiotic to me. Christianity, as I saw it, was, compared to antiquity, a regression, a spiritual barbarism that remained unconquered until the Renaissance brought a rebirth of true wisdom.
But I once again had to reconsider my point of view: studying Augustine, Thomas Aquinas, and the other giants of Christian thought of late antiquity and the Middle Ages in order to understand the impact of classical thought on Christian ideas, I was once more forced to change my mind. I now came to believe that Christianity possessed an understanding of certain essential moral and existential truths that had eluded the Greeks and Romans—even Plato—and that these truths cannot be forgotten without doing great harm to ourselves and to the world. Hence, I came to admire Christianity as an indispensable source of wisdom that can benefit anyone—even the most inveterate atheist—as long as one does not, like Luther, demand an exclusively literal interpretation of the Bible but reads it metaphorically and philosophically as well. Thinkers no less than Augustine and Aquinas did that. Why shouldn’t we?
The essays collected in this book have a few things in common. They are all the fruit of my rediscovery of the great tradition of ancient and Christian thought as a tradition that is of direct existential interest to us. They all deal with the eternal questions of good and evil that men and women of every historical age are confronted with both in public and in private life. And they aim to show that traditional thinking on these matters is in many ways superior—richer and more realistic—than modern thinking.
Two defining characteristics of traditional thinking should be mentioned in this preface. First, such thinking holds that good and evil are objective and universal, that they are not subjective judgments which are culturally determined or personal idiosyncrasies. The view that they are subjective is a typically modern one, a product of the Enlightenment and Romanticism, although it was foreshadowed by some of the Greek sophists in the fifth century B.C. If, as the tradition maintains, good and evil are objective and universal, they are part of the world outside of us. They cannot be posited but have to be discovered, just like the various parts of the world had to be discovered. And just as a geographer has the task of mapping the material world—as the Vermeer painting on the cover depicts—to write about good and evil is to map the geography of good and evil. Hence the title of this book.
The second characteristic of traditional thinking is that it revolves around a notion that has practically fallen into oblivion in our time: virtue. It is true that since the appearance of Alasdair MacIntyre’s After Virtue in 1981 there has been something of a renaissance of virtue ethics in academia. But this has had very little influence on the discourse about good and evil in society at large. One reason, certainly, is the nature of academic writing on virtue ethics, which by and large has been in the analytical mold and focused on foundational questions.
Far as I am from being a categorical opponent of analytical philosophy, I do not believe it sufficient. The word analytical
derives from the Greek verb analuein, meaning to unloose,
to undo,
to dissolve.
That is exactly what analytical philosophy does: it unwinds, it takes apart. That approach frequently makes things clearer. But at the same time, if it is not combined with a different, complementary approach, analytical philosophy often dissolves a meaningful whole into more or less meaningless parts. For instance, looking at what analytical philosophers do with Plato, one gets the uneasy feeling that—though clever and precise—something essential is lost in their presentation of his views. To counterbalance the analytic approach, we need what one might call a synaptic
approach, from the Greek verb synhaptein, meaning to connect.
Likewise, a philosophy that focuses mainly on foundational issues is insufficient. Such a focus can easily be overvalued. As Aristotle taught us, the truth of first principles is impossible to prove or disprove. Principles are literally beginnings—the meaning of the Latin principium. With them we prove other propositions. To want to prove principles with these other propositions is to get caught in a petitio principii. Hence, foundational philosophy is in a sense sterile. It can tell us what the foundations of a system of thought are, but not what the merits of that system are. What these merits are, what makes a system interesting and fertile as a window on the world, becomes clear not by studying its foundations but by studying the edifice constructed on top of them. Think, for instance, of Euclidian geometry. This whole system is based upon ten first principles that cannot be proved or disproved—e.g., that a straight line can be drawn from any point to any other point, and that if equals are added to equals, the sums are equal. As such, none of these principles is either interesting or enlightening. It is only when one studies the whole Euclidian system based on them and applies its various propositions to the real world that one begins to grasp the marvelous richness and fruitfulness of Euclid’s geometrical thought.
That is no different with regard to the study of virtue ethics, the interesting part of which is the edifice built upon its foundations: the whole gamut of virtues and their interrelations. Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics is less concerned with the foundations of virtue ethics than with giving the reader an excellent phenomenological description of a number of key virtues. It is through this description and not through Aristotle’s foundational remarks that the meaning and significance of the virtues becomes clear. Sadly, because foundations tend to be regarded as most important, the contemporary renaissance of virtue ethics has brought us very little in terms of a phenomenological description of the various virtues. Aristotle’s example has few imitators in our time. That must change if virtue ethics is ever to have social influence.
The virtues—and the vices—are central to the traditional conception of good and evil, and hence to this book. The approach is both analytic and synaptic. Sometimes virtues are taken apart
analytically, for instance tolerance
in chapter 7 and loyalty
in chapter 8. But often the virtues are connected synaptically
to other virtues—as in chapter 12, where justice and love are discussed—or to related concepts, such as honor, value, duties, and rights—as in chapters 5, 6, and 13. The foundations are examined in various chapters, especially in chapters 4 and 14. Both the ontological question of how an objective morality is to be understood, and the epistemological question of how we can come to know what morality demands of us, are discussed there. Most chapters, however, are of a phenomenological rather than foundational character. They describe, in the manner of Aristotle, what is there, factually. They are not primarily concerned with the principles underlying the phenomena.
The first two and the last three chapters are of a slightly different nature than the rest. Chapter 1 discusses something vital to civilization but often overlooked: the need for leisure—especially the leisure to read good books and to reflect. Chapter 2 is an extended criticism of Enlightenment thinking. It is placed at the beginning of the book in imitation of the Socratic elenchus: one needs first to get rid of one’s prejudices if the mind is to be opened to the truth. The last three chapters apply the insights of the previous chapters to subjects that have received far too little serious attention from moral philosophers in the last several decades. Chapters 15 and 16 deal with the family, and chapter 17 with the moral education of society’s future leaders.
Like all prefaces, this preface cannot end without a word of thanks to the people who have contributed to the English version of this book. First of all, I should mention the translator, Ineke Hardy, who did a superb job rendering my baroque Dutch into real English. Jonathan Price, my editor, also deserves the highest praise for the many idiomatic improvements and edits he suggested, most of which I adopted. Jeremy Beer, until recently editor in chief of ISI Books, managed the whole process like the true professional he is, beyond the call of duty. The Faculty of Law of the University of Leiden, my employer, was kind enough to pay most of the expenses associated with the translation. Finally, I would like to express my gratitude to all the people who have shaped my mind and kindled my love for the true and the beautiful over the years. If they are not mentioned here by name, it is only because they number so many, and I don’t want to run the risk of forgetting anyone. In a sense, they are the coauthors of this book. Hence, errors and inanities are due to them as well. But I gladly take the blame.
CHAPTER 1
LEISURE AND CIVILIZATION
1
In the modern Western world superficiality marks public discourse on various momentous topics. Think of the debate on values, which does not rise above the level of clichés. The same applies to the recent discussions in Europe about the European constitution. Pondering the question of why this is so, I began to realize that superficiality itself is one of the vices that constitutes the moral crisis of the West. No wonder then that discussion fails to break the surface.
Take the press as a representative example. We all know that a free press is one of the pillars of our free society, since it monitors and thereby restrains the ruling power. This role of the press is so important that one can say that if the ruling power curtails the freedom of the press, that power is almost certainly autocratic. In time, autocratic power goes hand in hand with arbitrariness, abuses of power, repression, legal insecurity, and violations of human rights. A free press is clearly imperative, but it would be superficial to suppose that its intended purpose has been achieved once we find ourselves with a diverse array of newspapers, news magazines, journals, and Web sites that gather news without interference by the authorities. When the press fails to exercise critical judgment and drifts along on the waves of current events, when it concentrates on sensational scoops and human interest
stories about the love children of movie stars and the like, it does not well serve its constitutional function. Or worse, it does not serve it at all. It can only fulfill that role by practicing honest, critical, and, above all, searching journalism—in other words: investigative journalism.
Today, except in a few stalwart publications, investigative journalism is as good as dead. There simply is not enough time. The deadlines are murderous—articles have to be completed within days, often within hours. Time for reflection falls short, and granting a writer the freedom to spend more time on research is also out of the question. No money for that. What we are left with is the quick, the simple, and the juicy, which is also usually the sexy. We have infotainment. The European constitution? Genocide in Africa? Global warming? A quick interview with one or two people, a bit of typing, and that’s that. Next topic please—we don’t have all day.
2
The same haste, the same deadlines, the same pressures plague all levels of society, but especially politics and the civil service, schools and universities, the bar and the judiciary. In short, all intellectual professions in the public domain. You have a meeting every day (often several) on a wide range of subjects. You are expected to have an opinion on everything that comes up for discussion. Each day you receive a stream of policy notes in preparation for the meetings—or just for your information
—all of which must be carefully read while the normal work never stops for a second. The telephone rings incessantly, and every five minutes the computer displays a new e-mail message. If one’s secretary or a colleague calls in sick for the day, a temporary worker cannot be brought in, for lack of funds. Those who are left in the office must pick up the slack. They were already in the habit of working three nights a week anyway. So now it is four. And let us not forget the weekend, certainly Sunday, from noon onwards.
This is not merely the author, a professor, complaining about his workload. It has practical costs for us all. In the spring of 2004, I crossed swords with a Dutch politician who had been a member of the European convention that concocted a European constitution. It soon became apparent that my opponent had never given any real thought to the constitution phenomenon. The existence of a profound tradition of constitutional theory dating back to antiquity and culminating in Montesquieu, the Federalist Papers, and Tocqueville came as a complete surprise to him. That in 1787 and ’88, the Americans also held a convention—the Philadelphia Convention—which constructed a constitution so outstanding that today, more than two hundred years after its inception and with only a few amendments, it still forms the judicial and moral foundation of that country, in spite of the fact that qua population size, affluence, power, and culture, the United States of that era bears little likeness to the United States of today: all this was news to our politician. He failed to see why the participants of the European convention should have consulted the wisdom of their American predecessors.
This politician is no exception. On the contrary: the entire European convention consisted of shallow pragmatists of his ilk. That is a serious state of affairs, because the founding of a European constitutional state, the Rechtsstaat, will never happen this way. Those who are unaware of and unfamiliar with the basic principles of limited government, the separation of powers, checks and balances, and representative democracy, who are unaware of the momentous questions these doctrines address and resolve, will make a mess of constitutional law and create an abominable constitution that, if left to its devices, will produce chaos or repression or both.
Can we blame the politicians for lacking even a basic knowledge of these matters, and hence for having not even the faintest idea of what they are doing? No, because they never have time to immerse themselves in anything but the practical. They have not the time to read books, let alone to make a thorough study of the classic authors of constitutional theory. This is the most essential difference with the Philadelphia Convention. At least some of the participants in that convention—and quite a few hovering around them—did engage in lengthy studies, did reflect deeply on the subject matter, and thanks to these careful deliberations, developed a mature vision. The American constitution bears witness to that.
What about the civil service? Does it not counterbalance the unbearable lightness of the politicians? I fear not. To stay with the example of the European constitution, during a meeting on that topic, a senior civil servant of the Dutch Ministry of the Interior division in charge of constitutional issues complained to me that both he and his staff were completely occupied with topical matters, such as the municipal elections. There was no time to study the basic principles of the rule of law and contribute to the discussion on the European constitution from that perspective. And this from the head of a government division that is the official watchdog of the rule of law in the Netherlands!
3
Fortunately, it seems we still have scholarship—the university—to come to the rescue. Academia, at least, still looks beyond the surface, still engages in critical thinking, still produces in-depth articles. Or does it? No longer are universities temples of the spirit, secular monasteries sheltered from the hustle and bustle of everyday life, exempt from market pressures, devoted to contemplation. There is not time for contemplation. The large numbers of students and the even larger financial cutbacks in the universities have led to a precipitous increase in the teaching burden. That alone leaves little time to do research. Add to that the administrative chores. It is interesting to note that the arrival of all sorts of support
staff has only increased the administrative burden. The fundamental feature of university administration is nonstop change. Every rule and every agreement is permanently up for discussion.
The little time that remains must be spent on doing research. Add to that the obligation to publish three articles or so a year on penalty of eventual dismissal. It goes without saying that those articles are unlikely to plumb any depths or make an essential contribution to our knowledge. Thus, when it comes to the European constitution, the European universities have advanced precious little writing of any significance. This should come as no surprise when everything has to be written with great haste. There is not time for quiet reflection on a subject as complex and wide-ranging as the European constitution, a project of unifying almost thirty nation-states under one federal government. Fortunately, the quality of these articles, or the lack thereof, matters little, because nobody reads them. No one who matters to the discussion has time to read, least of all journalists, politicians, and civil servants.
4
Taking stock of the above discussion leaves us with only one possible conclusion: what we lack, and what we need above all, is leisure. Leisure to reflect, leisure to investigate issues in detail, leisure to regain a clear image of both the big picture and the basics. In short, leisure to ponder the question of what we are actually doing.
This no doubt applies to everyone, but it applies most especially to the aforementioned intellectual professions that serve the public interest: journalism, politics and the civil service, schools and universities, the bar and the judiciary. Since these professions are the purveyors of culture that, in the long term, influence the weal and woe of society, they bear a special responsibility for the commonweal. If they do not function properly, society as a whole is endangered.
The intellectual professions can perform their duties to society well only if they have the leisure to break through the daily deluge of facts and ask themselves the fundamental questions about the human condition, human nature, and history. They must also have the leisure to make a careful study of the best arguments that have been offered over the course of time in answer to these questions. The European politician, for example, who drafts a constitution and thereby lays down the basic conditions of the future European state should, more than anything else, have knowledge of these fundamental issues. For, as the Federalist Papers put it, what is government itself, but the greatest of all reflections on human nature?
¹
If he is completely ignorant of these matters, if he is a shallow technocrat, he is bound to create a monstrosity of a constitution that is more likely to bring chaos and repression than order and liberty.
Where can this intellectual habit and this knowledge be found? What sources should be consulted? The best sources we have are the works of the greatest thinkers and poets who ever lived. From Homer, Thucydides, and the Gospels to Dostoyevsky, Nietzsche, and T. S. Eliot. Only those who have been cast in their mold are entitled to call themselves cultivated, educated, gebildet. Which means no more than that the cultivated have a certain understanding of reality in general, and knowledge of man in particular. Most others merely grope along in the dark, however much specialized knowledge they may possess.²
Studying these sources requires leisure; they must be pondered, not merely read. They sink in slowly. It takes time and the intellectual space that comes with being unencumbered by practical concerns. Society clearly has a vital interest in creating and guaranteeing this leisure time. It is a prerequisite for the proper functioning of the intellectual professions, which are, in turn, of crucial importance to society.
This insight is one of the pillars of Western civilization, going back to antiquity, and until recently it has been largely undisputed. It manifested itself in the ethos of those practicing the intellectual professions—Bildung was a must—and in various religious and cultural institutions such as Sunday rest, retreats, the grammar school and university curriculum, but also in limits on the working hours and workload of people such as politicians, lawyers, and judges; in university libraries that were maintained even if they received few visitors; in academic freedom for the researcher on whom few demands were made, etc. All this was based on the idea that those who practice the intellectual professions need the opportunity to reflect on fundamental issues.
All these institutions, all these enclaves of leisure time, have perished in recent years. In the words of theologian and philosopher Josef Pieper—who has discussed this theme with great eloquence—the intellectual professions have all been harnessed to the total world of work.
³
They have been proletarianized.
They have been gleichgeschaltet—forced into line—and, like every other profession, they have become part of the market economy. This clearly shows in the quality of journalism and politics, in the administration of justice, and in the products
of the other intellectual professions. The quality, in a word, often makes one weep. If that does not change, the consequences are bound to be disastrous in the long run. The text of the professed European constitution is a clear indication.
5
This book is about the big picture, about the basics. It has been written in (often hard-won) moments of leisure. And it should be read at leisure and in peace, ruminatively, so that the mind opens up and the basics may be explored. Basics that are so familiar to us and, precisely for that reason, so difficult to understand. Is there anyone left who has time for that? Is there anyone left who still has the skill, in spite of the pressures of daily life? It is for those who still retain that ability that this book has been written.
The central issue, although not always stated in so many words, is the classical question of the good life—for the individual but also for society. In other words, we will be dealing with good and bad in the widest sense, with personal as well as public ethics—exactly what used to be the focus of Bildung. Not how something should be done or accomplished, but what should be done or accomplished, was its focus. Not the method, the means, the blueprint to follow, the technique, but the purpose, the reason, the wherefore, and the why. In recent decades, this focus has increasingly disappeared. Nearly all we talk about these days is the how. We no longer discuss the what. With the result that our thoughts about the what have, to a large extent, become simplistic and shallow. The base thought, for instance, that the meaning of life lies in earning a great deal of money or in having constant fun has never received as much support as it does today. This explains, among many other things, the sancta simplicitas that is so characteristic of the members of the European convention. They simply never gave proper thought to the one crucial question: to what purpose?
Those who give little thought to what they ought to do just muddle along. They stumble through life, blundering from one endeavor to the next. Life does not amount to much, that way. Some succeed, but most fail. As long as this does not involve more than a few, little harm is done. They can be corrected and supported by others who know better. But what if an entire society has lost its way? If almost everyone stumbles along, including the government, then the harm will be incalculable. One ill-considered reform after another, one rash decision after another, will roll over the nation. No need to give examples; we can all name plenty of them.
Ultimately, such is the downfall of civilizations. It may be reassuring to know that this is a slow process, but therein lies the danger. Precisely because of the slow pace of decline, it is often difficult to perceive. It is seen only by those who possess Bildung, and they are becoming fewer and fewer in number.
6
What was the substantive core of Bildung?⁴
What was the subject matter around which everything revolved? It was, on the one hand, Greek and Roman thought—their philosophy, epic poetry, drama, rhetoric, historiography, visual arts, and so forth. On the other hand, it was the Christian tradition. The latter’s focus, naturally, was on the Bible, but it also produced a rich array of theological, philosophical, and literary writings, not to mention the visual arts. These have been the two pillars of Bildung over the past two millennia and more.
The sixty-four-thousand-dollar question is: was this Bildung worth the effort? Did it give us what we need and cannot do without? Many—perhaps most—think not. Their perception is that what we have been handed through the centuries in terms of insight into the human condition is nothing more than an accumulation of prejudices and fictions. It is good riddance that finally, after two millennia, we have jettisoned the rubbish.
I believe this view to be both incorrect and dangerous. Incorrect, because it is based on a lack of appreciation of the richness and versatility of this heritage. Dangerous, because apart from the fact that we cannot do without the Greco-Roman and Christian heritage, what replaced it, in the name of the Enlightenment and Romanticism, is a serious threat to civilization. Leisure is just one of its victims. This, more than anything, is the thesis that links the following chapters. If you want to call it conservative, that is fine with me.
CHAPTER 2
THE SOLID DARKNESS OF THE ENLIGHTENMENT
1
The first half of the nineteenth century gave birth to three philosophies that have played a decisive role in shaping the political debate of the past centuries: socialism, liberalism, and conservatism. The primary reference point for all three was the French Revolution and the Enlightenment philosophy that preceded it and was one of its causes. In essence, the three philosophies embodied the whole extent of the three possible interpretations of the Enlightenment and the Revolution.
To the socialists, they were the dawn of a new day. To the liberals, they were the noonday sun breaking through clouds. And to the conservatives, they were the fall of night.¹
For socialists the Enlightenment and the Revolution did not go far enough. The battle was not over yet. To the liberals, they were the discovery and first implementation of the only valid principles of political and social order. What remained to be done was to bring reality fully