What do you think?
Rate this book
236 pages, Paperback
First published January 1, 1989
”If the inner truth of gender is a fabrication and if a true gender is a fantasy instituted and inscribed on the surface of bodies, then it seems that genders can neither be true or false, but are only produced as the truth effects of a discourse of a primary and stable identity.”
The radical dependency of the masculine subject on the female “Other” suddenly exposes his autonomy as illusory. That particular dialectical reversal of power, however, couldn’t quite hold my attention… (p. xxx)
...there is the political problem that feminism encounters in the assumption that the term women denotes a common identity. (p. 4)
If the immutable character of sex is contested, perhaps this construct called “sex” is as culturally constructed as gender; indeed, perhaps it was always already gender… (p. 9)
Perhaps, paradoxically, “representation” will be shown to make sense for feminism only when the subject of “women” is nowhere presumed. (p. 8)
But it struck me repeatedly as I read the chapter that there’s a serious argument to be made that many of the harms described by genderists seem to be discursively constituted. Couldn’t the supposed harm of using the “wrong” pronouns be reduced if people stopped referring to misgendering as violence? Doesn’t talking about “victims of transphobia” deny trans people agency? These sorts of conclusions ought to follow from a coherent philosophy of discursive construction of harm. Or have I completely misunderstood something?
In effect, the relations among patrilineal clans are based in homosocial desire (what Irigary punningly calls “hommo-sexuality”), a repressed and, hence disparaged sexuality, a relationship between men which is finally, about the bonds of men, but which takes place through the heterosexual exchange and distribution of women. (p. 55)
Further, there are other power/discourse centers that construct and structure both gay and straight sexuality; heterosexuality is not the only compulsory display of power that informs sexuality. (p. 165)
If homosexuality produces sexual nonidentity, when homosexuality itself no longer relies on identities being like one another; indeed, homosexuality could no longer be described as such… perhaps we can ask whether this is, instead, a love that either cannot or dare not speak its name? (p. 138)
The masculine “subject” is a fictive construction produced by the law that prohibits incest and forces an infinite displacement of a heterosexualizing desire. (p. 38)
The taboo generates exogamic heterosexuality which Levi-Strauss understands as the artificial accomplishment of a non-incestuous heterosexuality extracted through prohibition from a more natural and unconstrained sexuality (an assumption shared by Freud in Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality. (p. 55)
Learning the rules that govern intelligible speech is an inculcation into normalized language, where the price of not conforming is the loss of intelligibility itself… there is nothing radical about common sense. It would be a mistake to think that received grammar is the best vehicle for expressing radical views… (p. xiv)
Is there a “physical” body prior to the perceptually perceived body? An impossible question to decide. (p. 155)
The power relations that infuse the biological sciences are not easily reduced, and the medico-legal alliance emerging in nineteenth-century Europe has spawned categorial fictions that could not be anticipated in advance. (p. 44)
What a tragic mistake, then to construct a gay/lesbian identity through the same exclusionary means, as if the excluded were not, precisely through its exclusion, always presupposed and, indeed, required for the construction of that identity… Lesbianism would then require heterosexuality. (p. 174)
Originally intended to dispute the biology-is-destiny formulation, the distinction between sex and gender serves the argument that whatever biological intractability sex appears to have, gender is culturally constructed: hence, gender is neither the causal result of sex nor as seemingly fixed as sex. (6)Thence: “If the immutable character of sex is contested, perhaps this construct called ‘sex’ is as culturally constructed as gender; indeed, perhaps it was always already gender, with the consequence that the distinction between sex and gender turns out to be no distinction at all” (7)—which is not a rigorous argument for the implosion of the binary, but rather a hypothetical, a thought experiment, upon which the remainder of the argument proceeds. I propose to make true the thought experiment herein.
There is nothing in her account that guarantees that the ‘one’ who becomes a woman is necessarily female. If ‘the body is a situation,’ as she claims, there is no recourse to a body that has not always already been interpreted by cultural meanings; hence, sex could not qualify as a prediscursive anatomical facticity. Indeed, sex, by definition, will have been shown to have been gender all along. (8)This is, again, not rigorous argumentation for the implosion, but rather an immanent critique of basic feminist theory on the principle of sex/gender differentiation—what we might designate as primary differentiation, as opposed to secondary differentiation radiating thereunder, between the feminine/masculine (purported indicia of ‘gender’), on the one hand, and the female/male (alleged indicia of ‘sex’ so-called), on the other.
‘Intelligible’ genders are those which in some sense institute and maintain relations of coherence and continuity among sex, gender, sexual practice, and desire. In other words, the spectres of discontinuity and incoherence, themselves thinkable only in relation to existing norms of continuity and coherence, are constantly prohibited and produced by the very laws that seek to establish causal or expressive lines of connection among biological sex, culturally constituted gender, and the ‘expression’ or ‘effect’ of both in the manifestation of sexual desire through sexual practice. (17)I’d go however a step further by including coherence/continuity in the indicia of so-called biological sex—internal genitalia, external genitalia, gametes, hormones, chromosomes—all of which take on their purported binary character solely through reference to the gender ideology that they are alleged otherwise to constitute. That is, there is nothing inherent to these anatomical markers to render them male or female individually, and we have instances of their not ‘matching up,’ as detailed in the long head-scratching over so-called ‘hermaphroditism,’ what we might designate now more sagely as intersex, the existence of which should trouble not only primary differentiation, but should rather solicit the secondary differentiation of binary sex, male/female. Butler does not get into these debates very much (though we can always reference Fine’s Delusions of Gender and Fausto-Sterling’s Sexing the Body for some of the raw data).
essay remains committed to a distinction between sex and gender which assumes the discrete and prior ontological reality of a ‘sex’ which is done over in the name of the law, that is, transformed subsequently into ‘gender.’ This narrative of gender acquisition requires a certain temporal ordering of events which assumes that the narrator is in some position to ‘know’ both what is before and after the law. And yet the narration takes places within a language which, strictly speaking, is after the law, the consequence of the law. (74)All good times. Similarly, “insofar as Kristeva conceptualizes this maternal instinct as having an ontological status prior to the paternal law, she fails to consider the way in which that very law might well be the cause of the very desire it is said to repress” (90).
The task of distinguishing sex from gender becomes all the more difficult once we understand that gendered meanings frame the hypothesis and the reasoning of those biomedical inquiries that seek to establish ‘sex’ for us as it is prior to those cultural meanings that it acquires. Indeed, the task is even more complicated when we realize that the language of biology participates in other kinds of languages and reproduces that cultural sedimentation in the objects it purports to discover and neutrally describe. (109)In her analysis of Wittig, author notes quite irresistibly that “‘sex’ imposes an artificial unity on an otherwise discontinuous set of attributes” (114), a “historically contingent epistemic regime” (id.). That last is salient, and suggests the appropriate frame of analysis: Althusser’s theory of the ideological state apparatus--
What are ideological state apparatuses (ISAs)? They must not be confused with the (repressive) state apparatus. Remember that in Marxist theory, the state apparatus contains: the government, the administration, the army, the police, the courts, the prisons, etc., which constitute what I shall in the future call the repressive state apparatuses. Repressive suggests that the state apparatus in question ‘functions by violence’ – at least ultimately […] I shall call ideological state apparatuses a certain number of realities which present themselves to the immediate observer in the form of distinct and specialized institutions. I propose an empirical list of these which will obviously have to be examined in detail. (Lenin & Philosophy, “Ideology & Ideological State Apparatuses at 142-43)He then lists out various institutions, such as the religious ISA, the educational, the family, the legal, and so on. These institutions “function massively and predominantly by ideology, but they also function secondarily by repression, even if ultimately, but only ultimately, this is very attenuated and concealed, even symbolic” (loc. cit. at 145). The School and the Church accordingly “use suitable methods of punishment, expulsion, selection, etc., to ‘discipline’ not only their shepherds, but also their flocks” (id.). The “ideology by which they function is always in fact united, despite its diversity and contradictions, beneath the ruling ideology, which is the ideology of the ‘ruling class’” (loc. cit. at 146). These institutions “may not only be the stake, but also the site of class struggle” (147). The ruling class “cannot lay down the law in the ISAs as easily as it can in the [RSA], not only because the former ruling classes are able to retain strong positions there for a long time, but also because the resistance of the exploited classes is able to find means and occasions to express itself” (id.). The ultimate aim of ideology: “Ideology represents the imaginary relationship of individuals [sic] to their real conditions of existence” (162). Ideology functions by means of both illusion of the Imaginary but also allusion to the Real (id.). That is, “What is represented in ideology is therefore not the system of real relations which govern the existence of individuals [sic], but the imaginary relation of those individuals to the real relations in which they live” (165).
‘Gender is the repeated stylisation of the body, a set of repeated acts within a highly rigid regulatory frame that congeal over time to produce the appearance of substance, of a natural sort of being’