Eat Like You Care - Gary L
Eat Like You Care - Gary L
Eat Like You Care - Gary L
An Examination of the Morality of Eating Animals Gary L. Francione Anna Charlton EXEMPLA PRESS
Table of Contents
Copyright Acknowledgments Introduction Two Things Before We Begin I. We're All Michael Vick: Our Moral Schizophrenia Remember Michael Vick? The Problem: Were All Michael Vick Paying Someone Else to Do the Dirty Work There is No Moral Distinction Between Meat and Other Animal Products Remember Mary Bale? Beyond Dogs and Cats II: But The Excuses We Use and Why They Dont Work ButWhere do you get your protein from? ButWill I get enough iron if I dont eat meat? ButWill I get enough calcium if I dont consume milk and other dairy products? ButWill my children get enough iodine? ButI heard about someone who became ill after eating no animal foods. ButDoesnt God want us to eat animals? ButIsnt eating animal products natural? ButWhat if everyone ate just plant foods? There would not be enough land to grow food! ButWhat if I were on a desert island starving to death? ButWhat would happen to all of those animals if we did not eat them? ButWe brought food animals into existence to be eaten; that is what they are here for. ButAnimals used for food dont suffer as much as dogs used in fighting. ButDo animals feel pain in the same way that humans do? ButDo fish really feel pain? ButArent there laws that require the humane treatment of animals? ButWhat if we improved the treatment of animals we use for food? ButWhat if we treated food animals just as we treat our pets? ButDont we have to solve human rights issues first? ButWhat about Hitler? He was a vegetarian. ButWhat about plants? ButEating animal products is a tradition. ButWere at the top of the food chain. ButI know people who consume a vegan diet who are preachy (or hypocritical). ButIsnt what I eat a matter of my choice? ButIm busy and grabbing a quick burger is just more convenient. ButAnimals eat other animals. ButI could never give up [my favorite food]. ButMy family and friends will be upset if I stop consuming animal foods. ButMy partner wont go along with it even though I want to. ButIsnt it difficult and expensive to eat a vegan diet? ButIm too old to change.
ButIm too young to change. ButWhat if I cant give up all animal foods right away? ButIsnt eating more humanely produced animal foods a good first step? ButIsnt going vegetarian a good first step? ButIf I accept that I cant continue to eat meat and other animal products, am I committed to rejecting all animal use for any purpose? III: Conclusion For Further Reading About the Authors
Copyright
2013 by Gary L. Francione & Anna Charlton. All rights reserved. First Edition ISBN: 978-0-9896167-0-6 Published by Exempla Press Exempla is the plural of exemplum, or a story, which could be real or fictitious, used to make a moral point. Exemplary literature was a genre that was popular in classical, medieval, and Renaissance literature.
Dedicated to the approximately 57 billion land animals and one trillion aquatic animals we will consume in the next year. So much suffering. So much death. All so unnecessary. All so wrong.
Acknowledgments
Thanks so much to Sarah K.Woodcock for her excellent editorial and production assistance. Her contributions were considerable and her dedication to the project from beginning to end never wavered. Thanks also to Aruna Lopez and Melissa Resnick for their assistance and editorial suggestions.
Introduction
The number of animals used for food is overwhelming. According to the United Nations Food and Agricultural Organization, humans kill more than 57 billion animals a year for food. One billion is a thousand million. This number does not include the number of fish and other aquatic animals we consume. That number is estimated to be at the very least another one trillion. One trillion is a million million. Thats an absolutely staggering amount of suffering and death. If you are like most people, you like animals. In fact, you may even think of yourself as an animal lover. But you also probably eat meat, dairy, eggs, and other animal products. Youve thought about this and it has troubled you. You suspect that the process of raising and slaughtering animals is pretty brutal and you arent sure about how you should respond. Most of us, when we were children, were horrified to learn that we were eating animalsbeings who, at least in an abstract sense, we loved. In order to assure us, our parents told us one story or another, such as that God wanted us to eat animals or that we would be weak and ill if we did not consume animal products and so we grew comfortable with eating them. As we got older, we kept our moral quiescence on the matter by convincing ourselves of the many excuses that are explored in this book. The prevalence of these excuses, together with the fact that they dont really satisfy us, establishes very clearly that we know something is not right here. And now there is a move afoot to address our concerns by offering us free-range this, cage-free that, and a whole range of other happy meat and animal products. Is this the answer? Is the answer to continue consuming animal products that are supposedly humanely produced? Or is our childhood reaction to this whole enterprise the right reaction? Should we stop consuming animal products altogether? What are we to think about the issue of consuming animals and animal products? Its all so perplexing. The purpose of this book is to try to make this matter less perplexing. We are going to defend a simple proposition: If animals matter morally at all, we cannot consume them or products made from them and we are committed to a vegan diet, or a diet of vegetables, fruits, grains, beans, nuts, and seeds, and excluding all meat, fish, milk, cheese, other dairy products, and eggs. We are not going to present a general argument for animal rights. We are not going to defend the notion that animals and humans have equal moral value. We are going to focus on two principles that you and everyone else already accept and we hope to demonstrate that, based simply and solely on these two principles, we cannot justify consuming animal products. These principles commit us to a vegan diet. These principles, which are widely-shared moral intuitions and constitute our conventional wisdom about animal ethics, are as follows: The first principle is that we have a moral obligation not to impose unnecessary suffering on animals. No one doubts that. We could, of course, have an interesting and lengthy discussion about what necessity means and when suffering or harm is necessary. But determining what necessity means as an absolute matter isnt necessary for our purposes. All that is necessary is that we all agree on what is not necessary: we all agree that it is not necessary to inflict suffering on animals for reasons of pleasure, amusement, or convenience. So although we might disagree about whether particular instances of animal suffering are necessary, we would all agree that suffering imposed on animals solely because it brings us pleasure, or because we
find it amusing or convenient, is not necessary. The second principle is that although animals matter morally, humans matter more. Some of us think that humans matter more because they are made in the image of God and have souls. Some of us may not believe in God at all, but still think that humans matter more generally or because they have certain abilitiesthey can write symphonies or poetry, paint pictures, or design buildings or bombs. It really doesnt matter why most of us think that humans matter more and it doesnt matter whether that idea can be defended. Although we think that there are compelling reasons to challenge and reject this notion--and we have done so in our other writing setting out and defending a comprehensive theory of animal rights--we will, for present purposes, just assume that it is true. A corollary of this second principle is that if there is a conflict that necessitates deciding between a human and a nonhuman, we must favor the interests of the human. For example, if we are on a lifeboat with another human and a dog, and we are confronted with some emergency that compels us to throw one overboard, the dog loses. The dog matters but the human matters more. We would submit that there is virtually no one who would disagree with these two principles or doubt that they are widely-shared moral intuitions. Yes, there are some people who have no moral concern for animals. But so what? There are some people who have no moral concern for other humans. Just as that fact does not negate our moral concern for other humans, the fact that some people have no moral concern for animals does not negate the fact that most people do and those who have no concern represent a minority view. Nearly everyone regards animals as having some moral value and does not regard them merely as things. So lets recap. We maintain that our conventional wisdom about animals is: 1. We have a moral obligation not to impose unnecessary suffering on animals; suffering imposed for mere pleasure, amusement, or convenience is, by definition, unnecessary. 2 . Animals have some moral value but humans matter more than nonhumans; in a situation of conflict between a human and an animal, the animal loses. We will not challenge these widely-shared moral intuitions. Well leave them in place and well show you that if you agree with them, they compel you to stop consuming animal products without even thinking about animal rights, much less embracing that notion. In sum, we hope to persuade you that what you already believe commits you to a plants onlyor vegandiet.
cure for some illnessthere was no conflict between humans and animals that required us to sacrifice the interests of the dogs. The only conflict Vick had involved his desire to use them for his pleasure, which was inconsistent with their well-being. And that is not the sort of conflict that counts. The suffering that Vick imposed was wholly unnecessary.
liters; tomatoes 214 liters; potatoes 287 liters; and rice 2,497 liters. Most estimates vary between 1000 to 2000 gallons of water to produce a gallon of milk. The Food and Agriculture Organization of the United Nations states that animal agriculture contributes more greenhouse gases, which are linked directly to global warming, to the atmosphere than does burning fossil fuel for transportation.[4] According to Worldwatch Institute, animal agriculture produces an estimated 51% of the worldwide total of greenhouse gas emissions from human activity. Moreover, a significant amount of fossil energy is required to yield an animal-based product. The average fossil energy input for all animal protein sources is 25 kcal of fossil energy input to 1 kcal of animal protein produced, which is more than 11 times greater than for grain protein production.[5] Modern intensive animal agriculture techniques, known as factory farming, have evolved to produce a large number of animals for market at a faster rate, at a lower cost, and by using far less land. This, of course, does not take into account the land that must be used to grow the grains and soy that must be fed to these animals so factory farming represents anything but an efficient use of land. An acre of land can provide food for many more people who consume a vegan diet than for those who consume animal products. While these practices produce cheaper food, factory farms, or concentrated animal feeding operations (CAFOs), as the United States Environmental Protection Agency (EPA) refers to them, have serious environmental implications. For example, the United States Department of Agriculture reports that 1.37 billion tons of solid animal waste is produced annually in the United States (130 times greater than the human waste produced in the country). The excess quantities of nitrogen found in this manure can easily convert into nitrates, which, according to EPA, contaminate the drinking water of approximately 4.5 million people. When nitrates exist in the groundwater, they can be fatal to infants.[6] The runoff into water and soil from factory farms is also responsible for the pollution of ground water and the widespread dissemination of hormones. Antibiotics are routinely added to the feed and water of poultry, cattle, and pigs to promote growth and prevent infection caused by unsanitary, intensive confinement; approximately 80% of the antibiotics that are produced are fed to animals used for food.[7] The use of antibiotics in animal agriculture and the resulting dissemination of antibiotics can contribute to antibiotic resistance in humans. Animal agriculture is also responsible for water pollution, deforestation, soil erosion, and all sorts of unhappy environmental consequences. Again, you may dispute some of the details, but no one can credibly maintain that animal agriculture is not a net negative as far as the environment is concerned. So, in the end, whats the best justification that we have for imposing suffering and death on 57 billion land animals and at least a trillion aquatic animals, whom we do not need to consume for nutritional purposes and where the result of that consumption is ecological devastation? Animal foods taste good. We enjoy the taste of animal flesh and animal products. We find eating animal foods to be convenient. Its a habit. So how exactly is our consumption of animal products any different from Michael Vicks dog fighting? The answer: it isnt. We no more have a conflict with the animals we want to eat or whose products we want to eat, than Michael Vick had a conflict with the animals he wanted to use in fighting. Vick liked sitting around a pit watching animals fight. The rest of us like sitting around a barbecue pit roasting the corpses of animals who have been treated as badly if not worse than Vicks dogs. There is no difference between getting pleasure from dog fighting and the palate pleasure we get from eating animal products. In both cases, there is great suffering. In both cases, there is no necessity. Were all Michael Vick.
[1]. American Academy of Nutrition and Dietetics, Vegetarian Diets: Abstract, at http://www.eatright.org/About/Content.aspx?id=8357. [2]. David Pimentel and Marcia Pimentel, Sustainability of meat-based and plant-based diets and the environment, American Journal of Clinical Nutrition 2003; 78 (suppl): 660S-3S, available at http://ajcn.nutrition.org/content/78/3/660S.full.pdf. [3]. Institution of Mechanical Engineers, Global Food: Waste Not, Want Not (2013), at 12, available at: http://www.imeche.org/docs/default-source/reports/Global_Food_Report.pdf?sfvrsn=0. [4]. FAO Newsroom, http://www.fao.org/newsroom/en/news/2006/1000448/. [5]. See Pimentel study. [6]. Pew Commission on Industrial Farm Animal Production, at http://www.ncifap.org/issues/environment/. [7]. See Natural Resources Defense Council, at http://www.nrdc.org/food/saving-antibiotics.asp.
animal who is raised and killed to make the hamburger probably had, on balance, a much worse life than the animal killed by the hunter. So, although killing the animal in both situations is not necessary, if there is any difference between these two situations, it is that the former is actually worse because it involves more suffering.
[8]. Patrick Barkham, Cat bin woman Mary Bale fined 250, The Guardian , Oct. 19, 2010, at http://www.guardian.co.uk/world/2010/oct/19/cat-bin-woman-mary-bale.
Most of us agree that although animals do not have the same moral value that humans do, they do have moral value, and that we have a moral obligation not to impose unnecessary suffering on them. Most of us agree that the imposition of suffering on animals for reasons of pleasure, amusement, or convenience does not constitute necessity. We look at people like Michael Vick and Mary Bale, or to practices like bullfighting, and we condemn them all because animals were made to suffer for no good reason. The problem is that every time we consume animal products, we are participating in inflicting suffering on animals for no good reason. When it comes to animals, we are all Michael Vick. We are all Mary Bale. We all engage in conduct that is indistinguishable from bullfighting. When it comes to animals, we suffer from moral schizophrenia. Clinical schizophrenia involves delusional thinking. Our moral thinking about animals is literally delusional. We think of animals as having moral value; we think of ourselves as having an obligation not to impose unnecessary suffering on animals. We object to the imposition of suffering on animals when there is no compelling reason. We then proceed to impose horrible suffering on billions of animals without any reason that is more compelling than pleasure, amusement, or convenience. At this point, we have only three options. The first option is to decide that although we say that its morally wrong to inflict suffering on animals without a sufficient justification, we dont really mean it. Its perfectly fine to inflict suffering on animals for any reason, including pleasure, amusement, or convenience. Our getting upset about Vick, Bale, and bullfighting is really nothing more than hypocrisy that we now acknowledge and accept. The second option is that we have convinced you to stop consuming animal products or, at least, to resolve to do so. If that is the case, then you can stop reading now and just start searching for quick, easy, inexpensive, and healthful vegan recipes, of which there are many thousands readily available on the Internet. The third option is that you are troubled and think that there is something to our argument but you are saying But and then thinking about other reasons that would cause you to retain the belief that animals really do matter but that its acceptable for you to continue to consume them. We examine those Buts in the following section.
[9]. See Nicholas Graham, Julio Aparicio GORED IN THROAT During Bullfight, in Huffington Post, May 22, 2010, at http://www.huffingtonpost.com/2010/05/22/julio-aparicio-gored-in-t_n_585941.html.
II: But The Excuses We Use and Why They Dont Work
Yes, you think that inflicting suffering on animals requires a good reasonsome sort of necessity. No, pleasure isnt a good reason. Yes, you think that what Michael Vick did was terrible. No doubt. But you say But So in this section, we will explore the Buts that we use to try to distinguish our consumption of animal foods from dog fighting and other forms of animal abuse. These Buts are the excuses that we use to pretend that what most of us do every daywithout even giving it a second thoughtis different from what Michael Vick did. A preview: none of them works.
[10]. Joel Fuhrman, M.D., Eat to Live (Little Brown and Company 2011), at 184.
ButWill I get enough calcium if I dont consume milk and other dairy products?
Yes. In fact, if you dont consume dairy, and are conscientious about getting calcium from plant foods, you may well reduce your chances of getting osteoporosis. What? you ask. But we are told that we need milk and other dairy products in order to have strong bones. Yes, we are told thatby the dairy industry. But that does not mean that it is true. We dont need to drink the milk produced by another species; indeed, we are the only species that does so. In order to perpetuate the profitable notion that we need cows milk, we are subjected to nutritional disinformation. We need calcium for strong bones. The dairy industry tells us that cows milk is the sole or primary source of calcium. But cows milk is not the only, or the best source of calcium. Many plant foods are excellent sources of calcium: molasses; almonds; figs; sprouted sunflower seeds; sesame seeds; tofu processed with calcium sulfate; calcium-set tofu; bok choy; broccoli; Chinese cabbage; kale; mustard greens; okra; beans; and fortified soy, almond, coconut, hemp, and rice milks. Moreover, not only is cows milk not by any means the only source of calcium, its not the best. The body needs magnesium to absorb calcium and cows milk does not have sufficient magnesium to support its level of calcium. This results in the accumulation of excessive calcium in the body and that can lead to the development of calcium deposits in our joints and kidneys. The consumption of animal protein, including the protein found in dairy products, causes our blood to acidify, which results in the leaching of calcium from our bones and our eventually excreting it from our bodies. So the consumption of dairy products not only does not prevent osteoporosis but it can actually cause it! In The China Study, Dr. T. Colin Campbell found that a protein found in cows milkcasein promoted cancer. Dr. Joel Fuhrman also notes in Eat to Live that there is a strong correlation between dairy lactose and heart disease. Do vegans have to be sure to eat enough calcium-rich plant foods to ensure that they have sufficient calcium? Yes. But given that more than 60% of Americans who consume milk are deficient in calcium, diligence is not only a matter for vegans. Indeed, given the other issues involved with cows milk and the proteins contained in it, the vegan, once again, has the nutritional advantage.
[11]. James Gallagher, Iodine deficiency may lower UK childrens IQ, BBC News, May 22, 2013, at http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/health-22607161.
ButI heard about someone who became ill after eating no animal foods.
And what about all of the people you know who ate animal products and have developed cancer, heart disease, etc.? This But is yet another attempt to characterize consuming animal products not as a matter of pleasure but one of physical necessity. As we mentioned earlier, even traditionally conservative organizations, such as the Academy of Nutrition and Dietetics, formerly the American Dietetic Association, agree that an appropriately planned vegan diet can be completely healthy. And there is no evidence to the contrary. It is, of course, possible to get ill eating only plants just as its possible (and more likely, actually) to get ill eating animal products. Although some vitamin B-12 is made by bacteria in the human body, not enough is reliably made for our needs and the unhealthy habits that humans have prevent maximum production and absorption of the endogenous B-12. Therefore, it is necessary to supplement B-12 from external sources whether you consume a vegan diet or a diet of animal foods. So all humans need to get their B-12 from somewhere outside their bodies. We get our vitamin B-12 from yeast; omnivores get theirs from meat. But all B-12 comes from bacteriawhether it is found in the gut of ruminating animals who get it from fermenting plant material in their hindgut, or in certain strains of nutritional yeast. So if you adopt a vegan diet but dont consume an alternative source of B-12, such as yeast, yes, you may get ill. But there are plenty of people who have B-12 deficiencies despite their consumption of animal foods. How about DHA and EPA, the long-chain fatty acids that arent found in plant foods and that people eat fish to get? Most people can convert the short-chain fatty acids found in chia seeds, walnuts, dark leafy greens, and canola oil into long-chain fatty acids. Or you can get long-chain DHA and EPA directly from the source that fish get italgae. There are now many DHA/EPA supplements that are algae derived. Occasionally, one hears about a parent prosecuted for manslaughter because their child died on a vegan diet. But when the facts are revealed, we learn that the parents had fed the child only iceberg lettuce (or something similar) and nothing else for some extended period of time. If the parents fed the child nothing but steak three times a day for an extended period, the child would also become ill. But no one would say that the child died or became ill from eating meat. They would say that the parents engaged in abuse by feeding the child an inadequate diet. The same is true of a diet consisting only of lettuce. Thats not a vegan diet; its a ridiculously inadequate diet. In the 30 years that we have been vegans, we have heard of a number of people who supposedly became ill while on a vegan diet. An inadequate vegan diet will make you ill because it is inadequate and not because it is plant-based. Eat nothing but celery and soy yogurt and you will not feel very energetic. Surprise, surprise. We have also encountered people who say that their bodies tell them that they must eat meat or fish or chicken or dairy or whatever. But such assertions are really no different than saying, I like the taste of meat (or whatever). In other words, they are assertions about palate pleasure and nothing more. A related issue is the need to eat meat or other animal products based on blood type. The so-called blood type diet has been debunked as junk science.
The Bible prohibits all sorts of things, such as rounding off the side-growth of your heads (sideburns) or cutting the edges of beards,[18] tattoos,[19] wearing blended fabrics of linen and wool,[20] contact with a woman who is menstruating,[21] women speaking in church,[22] and men whose testicles or penis are not intact from attending church.[23] If two men are fighting and a wife of one of the men should try to help her husband by grabbing the testicles or penis of the man beating her husband, her hand is to be cut off.[24] And the death penalty is prescribed not only for killing another but for other offenses, such as cursing your parents.[25] The bottom line is that even the most fundamentalist person does not follow the scripture of her or his religion to the precise letter. So its clear that these texts cannot be relied upon exclusively to resolve every particular moral problem. It would seem that the most that one could argue is that humans matter more because they are made in Gods image and have souls, or have special souls. Such a view is, of course, just an aspect of conventional wisdom. That is, most people think that animals matter morally but that humans matter more than animals. Religious people may believe that humans matter more because God created animals as spiritual inferiors. But many people who are not religious and, indeed, who may be atheist, think that humans matter more because they are cognitively more sophisticated. Even if you believe that you have a soul and animals dont, and that we ought to prefer the interests of a human in any situation in which we must choosethat is, in any situation of legitimate conflictthat gets us right back to the fact that when you are deciding what to eat tonight, there is no conflict. There is only a choice. If you choose the animal product, you are participating in suffering and death in the absence of any sort of conflict or compulsion. You r only justification is that you enjoy consuming animal products or that it is more convenient for you to do so. Think about it this way. Imagine that Michael Vick were to say that dog fighting was okay because dogs dont have souls. Would you buy that? Imagine that Vick says God wants us to fight dogs because they dont have souls. Would you buy that? You would respond to Vick that Gods creating us in Gods image means that in situations of conflict between human and nonhumans, we ought to protect the human interest over the animal interest. So in the situation in which a person is in a true emergency situation, such as being in a situation where she is starving to death with no plant foods to eat, it would make sense for a religious person to say that God wants her to kill and eat an animal and that she ought to do so. But saying that God wants us to eat animal foods when we are not in that sort of emergency situation is no different from saying that God wants us to fight dogs. If you would find the latter to be objectionable outrageous perhapsyou should find the former so as well.
[12]. Genesis 1:29 (all references are to King James Bible). [13]. Genesis 1:30. [14]. Genesis 9:3. [15]. Isaiah 2:4. [16]. Isaiah 65:25. [17]. See Genesis 19:1-8. [18]. See Leviticus 19:27. [19]. See Leviticus 19:28. [20]. See Leviticus 19:19. [21]. See Leviticus 15:18-24.
[22]. See I Corinthians 14:34-35. [23]. See Deuteronomy 23:1. [24]. See Deuteronomy 25:11-12. [25]. See Exodus 21:17.
[26]. Rob Dunn, Human Ancestors Were Nearly All Vegetarians, Scientific American Guest Blog , July 23, 2012, at http://blogs.scientificamerican.com/guest-blog/2012/07/23/human-ancestors-were-nearly-all-vegetarians/.
ButWhat if everyone ate just plant foods? There would not be enough land to grow food!
This But maintains that if we all ate just plant foods, there would not be enough room to grow all the necessary crops. Therefore, eating meat and other animal products is, contrary to what has been said, necessary. This distinguishes eating animals from dog fighting. This But is not only wrong; it is very wrong. According to the EPA, approximately 80 percent of all corn grown in the U.S. is consumed by livestock, poultry and fish and [o]ver 30 million tons of soybean meal is consumed as livestock feed in a year.[27] Moreover, according to the U.S. Department of Commerce, [w]hile 56 million acres of U.S. land are producing hay for livestock, only 4 million acres are producing vegetables for human consumption.[28] These statistics clearly illustrate how we are using our planets resources, including land, water, and energy, inefficiently by consuming meat and other animal products. Nonetheless, meat and dairy production continues to be on the rise across the globe. The demand across the United States and Europe is so high that it cannot be met within national borders. These meat industries have taken to Latin America to meet this demand, and 70 percent of the Amazons forests have been converted into pastures and feed crops. These practices inefficiently and cheaply feed the United States and Europe, while taking away the efficient and natural agriculture of these developing nations. Opponents of plant-based agriculture argue that the expansion of crop production would result in the complete destruction of arable land because the soil depletion will become so severe that the land will be incapable of maintaining our current methods of monoculture, or repeatedly harvesting the same crop. However, this argument completely ignores the effects of todays practices. In the United States, livestock accounts for more than half of soil erosion. Researchers in the United Kingdom have noted that the arable land in the United Kingdom is incapable of providing adequate amounts of some meat substitute crops, such as soy, lentils, and chickpeas. But they also noted that the cultivation of different pulses, such as various other dry beans and peas, would eliminate such concerns. Regardless of whether or not feasible crop alternatives would exist for the United Kingdom, this would not be a new concern faced by European countries. Currently, the continent as a whole has the arable land capacity to feed its entire population with plant protein, but it does not have even close to the land capacity to feed all of its farm animals. The European Union found that only 20 percent of what Europes farm animals eat comes from the continent, while the remainder must be imported. Because most of these imports use up the land in developing countries, this animal-based method of feeding Europe contributes directly to the depletion of the resources of developing nations, thus contributing to their continued impoverishment. What it essentially boils down to is that our production of food, regardless of what it is, has a large ecological impact. As our population continues to grow, if we persist in eating the amount of animal products we do, that impact will continue to take an exponentially larger toll on our planet than would the production of only plant foods. And what about the field mice, snakes, birds, and other creatures who are killed when crops are planted and harvested? Would we kill more animals if we had a vegan diet than if we ate animals and animal products? The answer is clearly no. It takes more land to grow plants that we feed to animals we eat than it would take if we consumed the plants directly. And the production of meat has the largest impact on the
destruction of the worlds biodiversity due to its role in pollution, deforestation, soil erosion, land degradation, greenhouse gas emissions, and so on. There are some people who argue that even if we have fewer acres under cultivation, whatever crops we eat will result in more animal deaths because more wild animals are killed in crop production than in raising animals on pastures. But this position ignores that the land used for crop production can provide up to 10 times the amount of protein than can be produced from animals raised on pastures. So even if more wild animals are killed in crop production than in raising animals on pasture, the number of wild animals killed per consumer in crop production will be a fraction of the number of animals killed in raising animals on pasture because one acre of crops can produce protein for so many more people than one acre of pasture used to raise animals.
[27]. See Major Crops Grown in the United States, at http://www.epa.gov/oecaagct/ag101/cropmajor.html. [28]. Worldwatch Institute, Is Meat Sustainable?, at http://www.worldwatch.org/node/549, (quoting U.S. Department of Commerce, Census of Agriculture).
heroism, you head home to eat dinner. What does your choice of saving the human tell you about the morality of eating chicken for dinner? Nothing. Absolutely nothing. Our moral intuitions may tell us that in situations of genuine conflict between humans and animals, humans win. But our intuitions also tell us that in situations in which there is no conflict, we cannot inflict suffering on animals simply because we get enjoyment from doing so. Again, to see this clearly, all we need to do is consider what we would think if the burning house contained two humans. You dont know either human but one is a great deal older than the other and your moral intuitions tell you that you ought to save the younger person simply because she is younger. Would you conclude from this that it would be acceptable morally to torture older people, start farming them or start using them in biomedical research? Of course not. Your moral intuitions might lead you to save the younger person precisely because you could only choose one to save and, in that unhappy situation, you chose to save the younger person. But that choice leaves completely unaffected your other intuition that hurting someoneanyonerequires a moral justification. There is a tendency to use these desert island/lifeboat/burning house scenarios to demonstrate that, because our moral intuition is that animals have moral value but less moral value than do humans, and because we would choose the human over the animal in a genuine conflict situation, animals have no moral value and we can inflict suffering on them even when there is no conflict. But that simply does not follow, and it explains why many of us feel deeply uneasy about continuing to consume animal products in the absence of any necessity. Even if we think that animals have less moral value than humans do, the point of this book is that if they have any moral value whatsoever, we cannot justify imposing any suffering on them just because we get enjoyment from it. Similarly, just because we would choose one human over another in an emergency situation does not mean we would support the view that it is acceptable to subject some humans to any suffering just because we enjoy it. If animals matter morally at all, if they are not just things, imposing any suffering on them because we enjoy it or the results of it cannot be morally acceptable. So the fact that you would eat the rabbit on the desert island, or throw the cow out of the lifeboat, does not in any way affect the moral principle that imposing unnecessary suffering is morally wrong and suffering for the sake of palate pleasure is, by definition, unnecessary. A variation on this But involves people who live in places where they dont have a choice of what to eat. There are a few examples of indigenous people in remote parts of Canada, or on the African continent (Kenya), who consume a diet of meat where there are few or no non-animal foods. The idea is that such situations are similar to the desert island scenario where one can choose to eat animals or die. We dont need to get into a factual inquiry about people in Canada or in Africa and whether they really have no choice and must eat animal foods or perish. The position that we are arguing for here is in any situation in which there is really no choice, animal use could be considered morally acceptable under the conventional rule that we should not impose unnecessary suffering. In situations in which there really is no choice, there is a sort of necessity that removes the conduct from the proscription of the general moral rule. But our guess is that just as there is no one reading this who is stranded on a desert island, or adrift in a lifeboat, there is no one reading this who lives somewhere where they really have no ability to get nonanimal foods. The point remains: for anyone who does have a choiceand that includes just about everyone reading this right nowa choice to impose suffering in the absence of necessity violates what we claim to be the moral principle that we all accept.
ButWhat would happen to all of those animals if we did not eat them?
This is an easy one: If we stop consuming animal foods, we would stop bringing domesticated animals into existence. Period. What would we do with the animals we have here now? Well, that depends on what you think are our moral obligations to those animals. It is not an option to just release these animals into the wild. The cows, pigs, chickens, turkeys, etc. that we see today are not wild animals. They were domesticated by us to be food animals. If you regard animals as having greater moral value than conventional wisdom allows, you may think that we should take care of the animals who are here now until they die a natural death and just not bring more into existence. Alternatively, you may think that we should just eat the animals and animal products we have now but stop bringing any more animals into existence. The ultimate answer is, however, the same under either (or any) scenario: if we think that we should stop consuming animals, we should stop bringing domesticated animals into existence. There are three responsive Buts. ButWhat about natural diversity? A responsive But is to point out that if we did not have domesticated animals, we would somehow lose a piece of natural diversity. Its as if having a vegan world would be one big violation of the Endangered Species Act. It is, on at least two levels, beyond absurd to use the word natural in any context that involves domesticated animals. First, animals have been so manipulated genetically that many do not even resemble the animals we had 100 years ago. Cows have enormous udders; pigs and turkeys develop such massive body weight that they cannot walk. Domesticated animals are anything but natural in any sense. Second, domesticated animals, whether a long while back or now, are just that: theyre beings who have been domesticated. They are not part of the natural world. They are part of the world that we have created. They are beings we caused to be developed and produced for our purposes. The natural world will be much more natural without domesticated animals. There is no extinction when it comes to domesticated animals. ButWhat about their right to live? Another responsive But is that by eliminating domestication, we actually make animals worse off than if they lived and died in unpleasant circumstances. This response assumes that it is better for an animal to have even an unpleasant life and death than never to have lived at all. So by having a vegan diet, we harm animals generally because they would not exist if we were all vegans. We are doing animals some sort of favor by consuming them. Indeed, we would be harming animals if we didnt consume them. In addition to requiring that we make a completely speculative and ultimately baseless guess about whether animals would, if they could, choose not to live at all rather than live a horrible life and suffer a horrible death, this position completely negates our intuition that animals matter morally and we ought not
to make them suffer unless it is necessary to do so. This position says, in effect, using animals for food is unnecessary and results in a great deal of pain, suffering, and death but it is better to have that unnecessary suffering and death than not to have it. So if we adopt this position, we, in effect, discard our moral intuition that animals matter and that causing them suffering for frivolous reasons is immoral. To put the problem another way: if this works for the animals we eat, it works for Michael Vicks dogs. Sure they suffered and many died. Sure dog fighting is a completely frivolous use of animals. But Vicks dogs were better off living and suffering than not living at all and so dog fighting is just fine. Indeed, this position would allow us to engage in a wide range of animal torture on the view that a life with some tortureeven a significant amount of tortureis better than no life at all. Do we really need to explain what horrendous results come from this way of thinking? So, in addition to any other problems that this position has, we cannot maintain it at the same time we maintain that we need a good reason to inflict suffering and death on animals and that pleasure, amusement, or convenience cannot suffice as a good reason. If we take this position, we, in effect, endorse the notion that animals are just things that we can use, make suffer, and kill just because we enjoy doing so. ButWhat about their right to reproduce? A third responsive But is that if we dont have any more domesticated animals, we will violate the rights of animals to reproduce. This But, in essence, seeks to make the point that if we dont continue to eat animals, we are somehow going to violate their rights, thus providing an extraordinary example of how desperate we get when we want to justify eating animal foods. Putting aside that, for the majority of domesticated animals, sex and procreation are unpleasant and frightening experiences, it is nothing short of bizarre for people who dont believe in animal rights and who consume meat and other animal products to be concerned about the right of animals to reproduce.
ButWe brought food animals into existence to be eaten; that is what they are here for.
And? First of all, if this is relevant, what is wrong with dog fighting? After all, all domesticated animals, whether dogs, cats, cows, sheep, pigs, chickens, turkeys, or even farm-raised fish were brought into existence by us. So if this justifies our eating animals, it justifies our using animals for dog fighting, bullfighting, and everything else. That is, to accept this But is, in effect, to say that animals do not matter morally at all; that they are just things and that we dont need a good reason to inflict suffering on any domesticated animal. To accept this is to say that we dont accept the conventional morality we claim to accept. Second, if we do have moral obligations to animals but our having some responsibility in bringing them into existence lets us off the moral hook, then where does that leave our children? They would not exist but for us. Does that mean we can justify harming them for pleasure, amusement, or convenience?
ButAnimals used for food dont suffer as much as dogs used in fighting.
This But seeks to distinguish the Michael Vick situation from our eating animals by suggesting that animals used for food suffer less than dogs used to fight. As a factual matter, animals used for food are, under the most humane circumstances, treated horribly; they are literally tortured. Do they suffer less than did Michael Vicks dogs? Animals used for food, whether for meat, dairy, or eggs, are, as a matter of routine industry practice, subjected to pain, suffering, and distress throughout their lives. And their deaths in slaughterhouses are always terribly frightening and horribly violent. Therefore, its probably the case that animals used for food suffer more than dogs used for fighting. But thats not the point. The point is that our conventional wisdom would say that any suffering cant be justified without a good reasonsome necessityand pleasure cant suffice as an acceptable justification. The issue is not whether dogs used for fighting suffer more than cows, chickens, turkeys, pigs, fish, or other animals used for food. They all suffer and they all suffer significantly. We are not talking about suffering a light slap. That is clear. Animal agriculture, particularly on the scale required to feed billions of people, necessarily results in horrible suffering under the most humane conditions. And, as we have discussed, there is no justification for eating animals any more than there is a justification for fighting dogs. Both behaviors serve one primary interest: our pleasure. There is nothing necessary about either use of animals. So even if, as a general matter, animals used for food suffered less than dogs used for fighting, what would that mean? Nothing. Our conventional wisdom is that we cannot justify inflicting any level of suffering on animals without a good reason and pleasure is not a good reason. To say that animals used for food suffer a great deal but may suffer less than dogs used in fighting does not address the fact that animals used for food suffer a great deal under the very best circumstances and most humane conditions. If we determined that Michael Vicks fighting dogs suffered less than the animals we eat, would any of us think that dog fighting is morally alright? No. We should also say that we reject the notion that we can say with any confidence who suffers more in any particular circumstance. Do cows suffer more than fish? We dont even know what that question means when we are talking about individuals from the same species. If two humans were afflicted with an illness, what would it mean to ask whether one was suffering more than the other? Would any of us find that question meaningful? We cant even make meaningful assessments about physical pain or suffering, or emotional distress, where members of our own species are involved. Trying to ask this question when it comes to different species makes an impossible situation even more impossible. We may be able to recognize cow suffering more because cows, like us, are mammals. We can more easily understand suffering in a mammal than we can, say, in a bird or a fish. But that does not mean that the bird or the fish suffers less. It means that the bird or fish suffers differently. But again, that is irrelevant. The idea behind the notion that we ought not to subject animals to unnecessary suffering is not that only suffering like ours is relevant. The point is to acknowledge a moral rule that animals are not things; that they have some moral value, and that we have to justify harming them. And to say that one animal is harmed less than another animal does not mean that it is acceptable to harm the former. Yes, it is worse to impose 10 units of suffering than 5 units of suffering. But we have to justify both. Indeed, we have to justify imposing even one unit of suffering. And we agree that pleasure
cannot be a sufficient justification for imposing pain and suffering on animals. There must be a compulsion; a necessity.
ButDo animals feel pain in the same way that humans do?
Maybe yes; maybe no. But it doesnt matter whether they do or not. The only issue is whether they can feel pain; any being who can feel pain has an interesta preference or desirenot to feel pain. It does not matter whether an animal feels pain in the same way that a human does or even in the same way that other members of the same species feel pain. Part of our conventional wisdom is that nonhuman animals, like us, feel pain and that we all have an interest in not suffering pain. Although there are some people who will say things like, animals dont feel pain, or animals dont have feelings, no one really believes that. After all, we have had laws requiring that we treat animals humanely for hundreds of years now. Those laws may be pretty ineffective but we have them on the books because we all recognize that animals feel pain, that they can suffer, and that they have feelings. After all, we dont have laws requiring the humane treatment of rocks or trees. There are, however, people who will say that although animals feel pain, they dont feel it in the same way that humans do. So what? We dont know whether humans all feel pain in the same way. You may not feel pain in the same way that your friend feels pain but you both have an interest in not experiencing pain irrespective of how each of you experiences that pain. And thats what matters: that you are capable of having an experience that you dont want to have. It does not matter whether another human experiences pain differently from the way that you do. What matters is that she, too, is capable of having an experience that she does not want to have. You and she are similarhowever differently you experience painin that you can both experience something that neither of you wants to experience. You have the same interest even if the experience itself is different. The same is true of animals. Indeed, humans and all of the animals we routinely exploit for food, with the possible exception of mollusks such as clams and oysters, are all sentient. That is, they have subjective perceptual awareness; they have the capacity for feeling or sensation. Humans and nonhumans are all similar in this respect: they are all capable of experiencing pain; they are all beings who have an interest in not experiencing pain. That interest is the same even if the experiences are themselves different. We should add that there is a tendency to think that humans suffer more because they are more sophisticated intellectually. Maybe yes; maybe no. It may well be the case that animals suffer more because of cognitive differences with humans. A visit to the dentist, although painful, may present a great deal less suffering and distress than a dogs visit to the veterinarian. The human knows that the pain will end shortly and understands the reason that the pain is being inflicted; the dog does not, and this may make the dogs suffering worse. Finally, consider that when we object to what Michael Vick did, we dont do so because we think that the dogs felt pain in the exact same way that humans do. We know that dogs feel pain and our moral outrage about what Vick did is not contingent on our thinking that dogs and humans experience pain in the same way. All that matters is that dogs can feel pain, not how they feel pain. Our conventional wisdom says that such pain cannot be morally justified unless we have a good reason to inflict that pain. Our moral obligation is not linked to a similarity of experience; it is only linked to a similarity of interest. And all sentient beings have the same interest in not wanting to experience pain and suffering, however different that experience may be. And the obligation not to impose pain and suffering without a good reason is not in any way linked to the actual experience of a particular being; it is a moral obligation to respect an interest that all sentient beings have.
[29]. See Alex Kirby, Fish do feel pain, scientists say, BBC News, April 30, 2003, at http://news.bbc.co.uk/1/hi/sci/tech/2983045.stm.
cars, computers, machinery, or other commodities, are sentient and have interests. All sentient beings have interests in not suffering pain or other deprivations and in satisfying those interests that are particular to their species. But it costs money to protect animal interests. As a general matter, we spend money to protect animal interests only when it is justified as an economic matteronly when humans derive an economic benefit from doing so. That is, the law generally prohibits imposing suffering on animals only when we get an economic benefit from doing so. Consider the Humane Slaughter Act in the United States, enacted originally in 1958, which requires that large animals slaughtered for food be stunned and not conscious when they are shackled, hoisted, and taken to the killing floor. This law protects the interests that animals have at the moment of slaughter, but does so only because it is economically beneficial to do so. Large animals who are conscious and hanging upside down and thrashing as they are slaughtered will cause injuries to slaughterhouse workers and will incur expensive carcass damage. Therefore, stunning, or rendering large animals immobile, makes good economic sense. To do so will reduce injury to workers and carcass damage that results in lower market prices. Of course, these animals have many other interests throughout their lives, not just including an interest in avoiding suffering at the moment of slaughter, but these interests are not protected because it is not economically efficient to do so. Interestingly, the Humane Slaughter Act does not apply to chickens, who are slaughtered by the billions annually and comprise about 95% of the animals we slaughter. Why not? Because in 1958, it was not thought that covering chickens under the Act would provide any economic benefit. Many animal advocates are arguing that poultry should be covered under the Act and their argument is based, in part, on the notion that the supposedly humane way of killing chickens, which involves gassing them before they are decapitated and defeathered, is economically efficient and will reduce production costs. Employees are often injured during the present slaughtering process and, because the chickens struggle before they die, there is a fair amount of carcass damage. Animal welfare laws generally either explicitly exempt what are considered the normal or customary practices of institutionalized animal use, and, in particular, exempt the animals we raise and kill for food, or courts interpret pain and suffering imposed pursuant to those practices as necessary and humane. That is, the law defers to industry to set the standard of humane care. This deference is based on the assumption that those who produce animal productsfrom the breeders to the farmers to the slaughterhouse operatorswill not impose more harm on animals than is required to produce the particular product just as the rational owner of a car would not take a hammer to her car and dent it for no reason. In any event, the effect of most animal welfare laws is to make the production process more efficient. Beyond the economics of production efficiency, animal welfare laws that require humane treatment are really not about animals; theyre about humans and making humans feel better about using animals. We can comfort ourselves with the idea that we are acting in a humane way. Lets be clear: the laws requiring humane treatment allow for the tortureand we are using that term literally and deliberatelyof the animals we raise and kill for meat and other animal products. Most of the meat, dairy, and eggs we eat are produced from animals kept in intensive confinement on the factory farms that we discussed earlier. And factory farms are nothing but large torture chambers.
might all be willing to pay a great deal more for animal products and that standards could improve in significant ways. But thats just theory. Very few people could afford animal products that were produced in a way that provided significantly more protection to animal interests. And lets be perfectly clear: even if we completely eliminated every vestige of factory farming, which is an economic impossibility, and went back to a system of what we think of as the idyllic family farm, there would still be a great deal of animal suffering. The storybook image of farming is a fantasy, designed to make children comfortable with eating creatures who look just like the stuffed animals that they love. Moreover, anyone who would care enough to pay the significantly higher cost of such production would probably care enough so as not to eat animal products at all. Additionally, given economic realities and free-trade rules, even if welfare standards were raised significantly in one place, demand for lower-priced, lower-welfare products would force the higher-welfare producers out of business except, perhaps, to serve a very small and affluent niche market.
To say that any sentient being is not harmed by death is most peculiar. Sentience is not a characteristic that has evolved to serve as an end in itself. Rather, it is a trait that allows beings to identify situations that are harmful and that threaten survival. Sentience is a means to the end of continued existence. Sentient beings, by virtue of their being sentient, have an interest in remaining alive; that is, they prefer, want, or desire to remain alive. To say that a sentient being is not harmed by death denies that the being has the very interest that sentience serves to perpetuate. It would be analogous to saying that a being with eyes does not have an interest in continuing to see or is not harmed by being made blind. The Jains of India expressed it well long ago: All beings are fond of life, like pleasure, hate pain, shun destruction, like life, long to live. To all life is dear.[30] The notion that animals are not self-aware is based on nothing more than a stipulation that the only way to be self-aware is to have the self-awareness of a normal adult human. That is certainly one way to be self-aware. Its not the only way. A s biologist Donald Griffin, one of the most important cognitive ethologists of the twentieth century, noted in his book, Animal Minds, if animals are conscious of anything, the animals own body and its own actions must fall within the scope of its perceptual consciousness. We nevertheless deny animals self-awareness because we maintain that they cannot think such thoughts as It is I who am running, or climbing this tree, or chasing that moth. Griffin maintains that when an animal consciously perceives the running, climbing, or moth-chasing of another animal, it must also be aware of who is doing these things. And if the animal is perceptually conscious of its own body, it is difficult to rule out similar recognition that it, itself, is doing the running, climbing, or chasing. He concludes that [i]f animals are capable of perceptual awareness, denying them some level of self-awareness would seem to be an arbitrary and unjustified restriction. It would seem that any sentient being must be self-aware in that to be sentient means to be the sort of being who recognizes that it is that being, and not some other, who is aware. When a sentient being is in pain or distress, that being necessarily recognizes that it is she or he, and not some other, who is in pain or distress; there is someone who is conscious of being in pain and who has a preference not to have that experience. Even if animals live in some sort of eternal present, which we doubt to be the case, that still does not mean that they are not self-aware, that they have no interest in continued existence, or that death does not harm them. It just means that their self-awareness is different. Animals would still have a sense of themselves in each particular moment. They would still want to get to the next moment of the present. Their sense of self-awareness may be different from that of a normal adult human, but it would not be accurate to say that they are not self-aware or that they are indifferent to death. We see this where humans are involved. If a human is mentally disabled and is not self-aware in the same way that a normal human is, we do not think that such a human is without an interest in life or that death is not a harm to her or him. She or he may be self-aware in a different way than others but is still self-aware in a morally relevant way so that we would regard treating her or him exclusively as a resource, which is how we treat nonhuman animals we use for food, as morally wrong. In sum, if a being is sentientthat is, if she is perceptually awarethen she has an interest in continuing to live, and death harms her. It is not necessary to have the autobiographical sense of self that we associate with normal adult humans in order to be self-aware. And a humanlike sense of selfawareness is not necessary to have an interest in continuing to live. Fourth, lets get back to practicality. Even if everything we just said is completely wrong and it were possible to have animal agriculture with the animals being treated like dogs and cats and not suffering at all, and being allowed to die of old age, the reality is that products made from such animals are simply not available now in the world in which we live, so what difference does it make to your choice about what to eat tonight?
The answer is clear: None. There are some people who, when they find out we dont consume milk (or anything from anyone who had eyes or a mother), will tell us a story about their great grandparents cow who was treated as a member of the family. Although we do not accept as an empirical matter that the cow in the family farm situation did not suffer, our usual follow up is not to argue that point but to ask what happened to the baby cows who were born as the result of having this cow be pregnant regularly so she would continue to produce milk. The reason we ask that question is that we know the answer: the males are sold as veal calves as are some of the females. The rest of the females become dairy cows. This undercuts the argument that there is no suffering in the family farm situation in a way that most people can understand. But there is always the person who comes back with, All of the babies were allowed to live on the farm and were never sent to slaughter. I am telling you, these cows never suffered. Again, there are many things that could be said in response to this wildly fantastical characterization but among the most efficient time wise is to ask: Do you have any access to milk made in that way now? The answer is always no. Our reply is always, So even if thats all true, what relevance does it have to your decision now to consume milk? The response is always either an acknowledgment that the hypothetical situation is meaningless in terms of our actual moral behavior or a remark expressing irritationindicative of the fact that we have asked a question that cannot be answered in a satisfactory way. A related responsive But we get at this point is: ButWhat if I rescued and adopted a chicken and treated her as I would my dog or cat. Would it be alright to eat her eggs? Putting aside that such a system could not supply eggs to many people (unless we all adopted chickens), the reality is that because chickens have been bred to lay such an unnatural number of eggs, their bodies are depleted of nutrients and the chickens will often and usually eat their own eggs once they realize that they are not fertilized. And hens often become very distressed when their eggs are taken. So in the very best case scenario, which certainly could not supply any quantity of eggs as a commercial matter, we end up taking eggs that the hens need for themselves and putting them in situations in which they suffer distress. And unless we are going to keep them until they die of natural causes, which can be 10 years or more after egg production wanes, we will end up killing them. The bottom line is clear: there is no way to produce animal productswhether meat, dairy, or eggs without suffering under the best of circumstances, and death. It just cant be done. And if it is not necessary for us to consume animal products, then we cannot justify even a greatly reduced level of suffering, and more humane death on the non-existent Old MacDonalds Farm, just as we agree that a more humane dog fighting operation would not make Michael Vicks conduct justifiable.
in a nonconscious way; isnt consciousness necessary for intention? Do plants engage in activities that achieve certain states of affairs? Yes. But it begs the question to talk about intentionality in this context. At this very moment, there are all sorts of biological processes going on in our bodies. We hope that these processes are conducted toward certain ends, such as cellular repair, and not toward other ends, such as tumor formation. But can we talk about the intentionality of cancer cells? Only if we beg the question and assume that cellular reactions have a cognitive component. We could say that the electrically charged particles that travel down the wire are nonconsciously intending to make the bell sound. That would be silly but no more silly than saying that a Venus flytrap nonconsciously intends to close its jaws on a fly. Advocates of plant ethics often argue that we simply cannot say whether plants are sentient. They may be sentient in a way that we cannot yet recognize. We just dont know. For example, although Chamovitz acknowledges that plants cant think, he adds, but maybe thats where Im still limited in my own thinking! There are three simple responses here. First, you could say the same thing about anything. You could, for instance, claim that we cannot really know whether a particular blade of grass is Einstein reincarnated. It may very well be Einstein; we just do not have the tools yet to recognize that it is. Making absurd claims and saying that they may not be absurd because its possible that they may not be absurd is an absurd endeavor. Second, unless you want to ignore the principle of evolution, you would need to explain why plants would evolve a characteristic that would be entirely useless to them. If plants could feel pain, there is nothing that they could do about it except to suffer that pain. Plants cant run away. Third, even if, contrary to everything we know, plants were sentient, we still kill more plants when we eat animals than when we consume those plants directly. So when someone who is eating a one-pound steak asks you about the plants you are eating, you can remind him or her that the cow from whom the steak was taken was once a sentient mammal who had a nervous system very similar to our own and who was unquestionably sentient. In order to produce that one-pound steak, about 16 pounds of plant protein were needed. So we have a sentient mammal who died, along with 16 pounds of supposedly sentient plants. So even if plants are sentient, the person eating the steak and the person eating the plant foods directly are engaged in different acts and the formers act is a lot worse. But then, if the person eating the steak really had a moral concern about plants, or about the suffering of sentient beings generally, she or he would be consuming the plants directly. Although the concern about the sentience of plants is silly, this But, like But Hitler, is an indication that the person youre talking with recognizes that there is something wrong, or at least questionable, about eating animal foods. Just as no one really thinks that Hitlers dietary regime is relevant to anything, no one really thinks that your broccoli suffered when it was cut or boiled. And, like But Hitler, But Plants is a But that, despite its silliness, is often used by otherwise intelligent people. In any event, the fact that someone is offering a But, particularly a very silly But like this, may be a strong indication that she or he is provoked and troubled about eating animal foods.
[31]. Gareth Cook, Do Plants Think?, Scientific American , June 5, 2012, at http://www.scientificamerican.com/article.cfm?id=doplants-think-daniel-chamovitz. [32]. Michael Marder and Gary Francione Debate Plant Ethics, Columbia University Press Website, at http://www.cup.columbia.edu/static/marder-francione-debate.
Europe, which do not have a great track record when it comes to Africa, criticize Africans for this practice. Or indigenous people who live in northern Canada will bristle when non-indigenous Canadians or those from the United States criticize their killing of seals or whales. We should, of course, be sensitive to these concerns and to the effects of other unjustifiable practices, such as colonization. But that does not mean that people get a free pass to do other morally unjustifiable practices. Two wrongs dont make a right. Finally, the use of tradition to justify eating animals is particularly absurd. Everyone, including people from every ethnic group can claim that animal foods are part of their cultural tradition. One of the reasons that But Tradition resonates in other contexts is that it is usually made to defend a practice that a fairly small number of people regard as sacrosanct, such as female genital mutilation or bullfighting. When we use tradition to justify something like the consumption of animal foods, which everyone does, it is like using tradition to justify sexism, or racism, or something else that everyone does. In this instance, the use of tradition is particularly absurd and amounts to nothing more than saying that the practice is a longstanding one. There is no valid claim that eating animals, as an activity, is something that is part of the identity of the particular group in any special way. Yes, people may claim that their particular ethnic animal foods are part of their group identity, but that is like saying that a particular sort of pornography is part of the identity of a group that practices sexism. When we are talking about pervasive, ubiquitous behaviors, such as consuming animal foods or sexism, using tradition is nothing more than saying that something being criticized has been going on for a long time, and instead of regretting that something morally wrong has been going on for far too long, the tradition argument says weve done it for a long time so we can do it some more.
ButI know people who consume a vegan diet who are preachy (or hypocritical).
So do we. On both scores. So what? There are people who are advocates for all sorts of moral issues who are preachythat is, they preach rather than teach. There are also people who advocate for a moral issue, whatever it is, and then engage in what they advise you not to. Does either attribute negate the validity of the moral position for which they advocate?
[33]. Gary L. Francione, Thinking About Mitt Romney and Seamus, Michael Vick and Dog Fighting, and Eating Animals, April 18, 2012, at http://truth-out.org/news/item/8459-thinking-about-mitt-romney-and-seamus-michael-vick-and-dog-fighting-and-eating-animals.
ButMy family and friends will be upset if I stop consuming animal foods.
There are two reactions to this But: the moral one and the practical one. The moral response is: why do you care? Are you going to let the opinion of others prevent you from living in a way that you see as morally right? Think about it. If you now see that eating animal foods is wrong for the same reason that what Michael Vick did was wrong, why should you care whether others have a negative reaction to your moral thinking? If anything, given that your family members and friends are probably nice people, you might want to discuss with them why they should see the situation in the exact same way. Presumably you would not compromise your other moral beliefs for others, so you should not consume animal products in order to make them happy now that youve concluded that our conventional moral thinking rules it out. Think about this in the context of Michael Vick. You express to your friend that you are horrified about what Vick did and your friend says that she disagrees and really wants you to attend a dog fight together. Assume that she says that it is really important to her. Shes going to get hostile if you dont go. Would you go to make her happy? The same analysis applies in the context of eating animal foods or any other activity that youve concluded is morally wrong. You should never do something you think is morally wrong simply because someone else wants you to do so. The practical response: most people are not going to ask you to go to a dog fight but many of them will react negatively if you dont consume animal products. Why is this? The answer is complicated in at least two respects. First, much of our social life revolves around food and many of our interactions with family and friends have occurred in the context of eating. And, as we mentioned earlier, it is the case that, as a result of habit and absolutely no necessity whatsoever, many people still think that eating means eating animal products; that you havent had a proper meal if there is no dead animal or animal products on the table. When you announce that you do not consume animal products, you, in effect, excise a primary way in which you have related to that person in the past and you may be worried about how you will relate to that person in the future. To put the matter another way, you have been eating a dead bird at your grandmothers house for Thanksgiving for the past however many years. You now tell grandma that you arent eating the bird anymore and will just eat the non-animal foods that she has prepared. Youll be just fine with Brussels sprouts, baked potatoes, salad, etc. She gets upset because she interprets you as saying that even though youre going to be sitting at the table with everyone else, youre not really eating the meal. Youre not really having Thanksgiving dinner together. The symbolic function of the meal has been frustrated. Second, when you inform family and friends that you no longer eat animal foods and that you are doing so because you think that its morally wrong, what they hear is that youre saying that they are immoral people. They take offense. Their reaction is understandable because, even though the whole issue of eating animals should be as clear as the issue of Michael Vicks dog fighting, it isnt. Eating animal products is culturally pervasive. Most people do it. Most people think its normal, which, if normalcy is determined by what most people, at least in rich Western societies, do, it is. You are perceived as announcing an idiosyncratic
opinion that is understood as equivalent to saying that you dont eat red apples because you think its immoral and, whats worse, that you think that anyone who eats red apples is also immoral. Its not just that youre not having Thanksgiving dinner with grandma when you eat only the sprouts, potatoes, and salad; you are telling grandma shes a bad person. For these two practical reasons, it is important to understand that although once you see the immorality of animal use for food because it causes unnecessary suffering, and you see this clearly, the same does not hold true for people who have not yet had that moral perception. It is imperative that you remember this in your interactions with them and help them to have that moral perception by explaining the reasons that have caused you to stop consuming animal products and pointing out they are in agreement with the same conventional moral principles that have led you to your decision. In other words, you start with Michael Vick. The idea is not to make judgments about people; the idea is to educate people about how something that they already believe points them in your direction and that it is their inconsistency and not your conduct that is the problem. But again, the focus is the conduct and discussion about why we do something that most of us think is wrong. The focus is not the moral flaws of the person. In other words, you dont tell grandma that shes evil. You explain that youre not eating the turkey for the same reason that grandma thinks that dog fighting is wrong. She may not agree with you (at least from the outset) so that shes joining you in a Thanksgiving dinner of sprouts, potatoes, and salad but shell understand why youre doing it and shell understand that you are not rejecting or judging her. Youre just acting on what we all (including grandma) say we believe: that causing unnecessary suffering is morally wrong. If you do a gentle but persuasive job educating people, you can deal with negative and even hostile reactions. But, in the end, you have to ask yourself two simple questions: (1) do I take morality seriously?; and (2) am I willing to act on what I claim to take seriously? Caring about others means that you take the time to explain why you think the way you do and why your conduct is related to moral principles that you share. But caring is not doing something you regard as wrong because someone else wants you to. So you educate and you explain. If someone gets hostile and says their happiness is contingent on your doing something that violates your moral beliefs, you need to ask yourself why you would react to that in any way other than sadness.
expensive, than a comparable quantity of meat. And, as we mentioned above, processed foods, whether vegan or animal-based, are not particularly healthy things to consume. Some people will point out that organic vegetables and fruits are often more expensive than animal foods. That may be true in some cases, but organic plant foods are certainly no more expensive, and, indeed, are far less expensive, than organic animal foodsand that is the proper standard of comparison. Finally, some people claim that it is elitist to eat a vegan diet. Were not sure what they mean by this. As weve said, a diet of plant foods is invariably cheaper than a diet that includes animal foods. And many people in the world who are anything but affluent consume a diet of all or substantially all plant foods. In any event, whatever is meant by characterizing a vegan diet as elitist, we would suggest that there is nothing more elitist than the idea that our palate pleasure can justify imposing suffering and death on a sentient being who values her or his life as much as we do ours.
ButIsnt eating more humanely produced animal foods a good first step?
No. What we strongly dont recommend is that, if you decide that you are troubled by eating animal foods, you adopt as an interim measure that you are going to eat happy meat from animals supposedly raised or killed humanely, or happy milk from cows who were supposedly treated with compassion or eggs from hens who are in larger enriched cages or in one large cage called a cage-free barn. Our opposition to happy animal products is not only that we think that these improvements arent really improvements at all and are, as we discussed earlier, really similar to putting padding on a water board at Guantanamo Bay. Our opposition is that this solution makes no sense given the conventional wisdom we claim to accept. That is, although we think these improvements do very little if anything, what if they did do something? What if they reduced overall animal suffering by 50% or 80%? It would be beyond absurd to claim anything like that but lets assume for argument sake that it was accurate. So what? Lets consider an example involving humans. We all agree that it is wrong to inflict unnecessary suffering on children. We all agree that it would be morally horrible to inflict suffering on children for reasons of pleasure because that would be completely unnecessary under anyones views about what constitutes appropriate discipline for children. That is, even if you think its okay to spank a child under some circumstances, no one thinks its acceptable to spank a child for pleasure. Assume that John and Mary spank their child severely for pleasure. You are horrified at this. Assume that either because the authorities dont care, which, despite what wed like to believe, is often the case in many places, or because John and Mary will lie convincingly to the authorities and claim that the child misbehaved and merited the spanking, you decide to intervene and talk with John and Mary. They agree with you but their solution is to use a softer belt or to reduce the number of blows by half or more. Is that better? Yes, sure it is. Is it right? Absolutely not. As a matter of economic reality, the idea that we will ever reduce the suffering of the billions of animals used for food by 50% or even 20% or 30% isand we mean this very literallyon a par with belief in Santa Claus. Its fantasy. Period. But even if we could reduce it by 50% or more, would it be right given that weyoubelieve that its wrong to inflict unnecessary suffering on animals? Absolutely not. Therefore, if you really believe what you say you believe -- that animals matter morally but humans matter more and that animals lose in any real conflict, as long as you are not on the desert island or lifeboat -- your obligation is crystal clear: you cannot justify any suffering imposed on animals used for food and you are obligated to adopt a vegan diet.
ButIf I accept that I cant continue to eat meat and other animal products, am I committed to rejecting all animal use for any purpose?
Now you have been confronted with the argument that given what you say you believe, youre committed to not eat animals or animal products because their production invariably involves suffering and our best justification for imposing that suffering or causing it to be imposed is that animal flesh and animal products taste good. The argument troubled you so you started thinking about all of those But points that youve relied on over the years to avoid coming to this conclusion sooner. But then you read the foregoing and you now have to acknowledge something else youve known all alongthat the Buts are, for the most, pretty silly. So now youre really considering that the whole vegan thing isnt as extreme as you once thought. But wait. If you take this stepif you stop eating animal productswhere is this going to lead you? Can you still wear leather or wool or fur? Are you now obligated to stop attending circuses? Are you obligated to oppose the use of animals in experiments or in product testing? That is a discussion for another day. In this discussion, we are focusing on one and only one thing: if you think that Michael Vick did wrong when he engaged in animal fighting, you cant justify eating animal foods. If you think that animals matter at all morally, you cannot, without being a hypocrite, continue to support suffering and death that is every bit as frivolous as what Michael Vick did. Period. Thats all were talking about here. We can, however, assure you that if you accept the argument we are making, and you stop eating animal products, we think it will be clear to you as to where you go from there as it concerns other issues. If you want to explore the ethical dimension of animal use more, we invite you to visit our website, www.AbolitionistApproach.com.
In sum, weve examined all of the major Buts that we use to keep ourselves from seeing that there is no difference between what Michael Vick did and what the rest of us do. None of these Buts works. All buts are off the table, so to speak. We just need to get the animals and animal products off the table as well.
III: Conclusion
Having read this far, you either agree with us, and you acknowledge that you are obligated to adopt a vegan diet, or you dont agree with us either because you have concluded that you dont really think that animals matter morally, or because you think that they matter morally but that you still arent going to change your behavior because you are willing to live with what is a serious moral inconsistency. In any event, you dont need us to draw any conclusions for you. If, however, you have decided that you are going to put your morality where your mouth is and adopt a vegan diet, we want to offer some advice: In a society in which most people consume animal products and where conformity is valued, and in which non-conforming behavior is often dismissed as extreme, you will inevitably find others labeling you as extreme. Dont let that bother you. Consider: What is extreme is eating decomposing flesh, milk produced for the young of another species, and the unfertilized eggs of birds. What is extreme is that we regard some animals as members of our family while, at the same time, we stick forks into the corpses of other animals. What is extreme is thinking that it is morally acceptable to inflict suffering and death on other sentient creatures simply because we enjoy the taste of animal products. What is extreme is that we say that we recognize that unnecessary suffering and death cannot be morally justified and then we proceed to engage in exploitation on a daily basis that is completely unnecessary. What is extreme is that we excoriate people like Michael Vick while we continue to eat animal products. What is extreme is pretending to embrace peace while we make violence, suffering, torture and death a daily part of our lives. What is extreme is that we say we care about animals and we believe that they are members of the moral community, but we sponsor, support, encourage and promote happy meat/dairy labeling schemes. What is extreme is not eating flesh but continuing to consume dairy when there is absolutely no rational distinction between meat and dairy (or other animal products). There is as much suffering and death in dairy, eggs, etc., as there is in meat. What is extreme is that we are consuming a diet that is causing disease and resulting in ecological disaster. What is extreme is that we encourage our children to love animals at the same time that we teach them those whom they love can also be those whom they harm. We teach our children that lov ing others is consistent with hurting them. That is truly extremeand very sad. What is extreme is the fantasy that we will ever find our moral compass with respect to animals as long as they are on our tables. What is extreme is that we say we care about animals but we continue to eat animals and animal products. Good luck on your journey.