Deals With Microparticles, Its Significance Is by No Means Limited Microphenomena
Deals With Microparticles, Its Significance Is by No Means Limited Microphenomena
Deals With Microparticles, Its Significance Is by No Means Limited Microphenomena
Mechanics
L.v. Tarasov
,
Basic
Concepts
of
Although quantum mechanics
deals with microparticles, its
significance is by no means
limited to microphenomena.
In our endless quest
for undersfanding and per-
fe ing our knowledge of
the laws of nature quantum
mechanics represents an
important qualitative leap.
-MlR-Pubiishers Moscow
------ --r-
7hi-s bOOK 5 to EX U 13 RI5 '.
Amit- J)haKulk01i{ ])t IB/J./J2K
\
II
.
, I
I
)
1
d
11. B. TapaCOB
OCHOBbl
';bA9.Ta llbCTBO
BblCWafi WKOJla
MOCKBa
-.1T
" ...
, \.
,
L.V. Tarasov Basic Concepts of .
Quantum Mechanics
Translated from the Russian
by Ram S. Wadhwa
MIR Publishers Moscow
First published 1980
Revised from the 1978 Russian edition
H3AaTeJIbCTBo BblCmaJi mKOJIa&, 197R
English translation. Mir Publishers, 1980
.,
Contents
Preface 1
Prelude. Can the System of Classical Physics Con-
cepts Be Considered Logically Perfect? 12
Chapter I.
Chapter II.
Chapter Ill.
Physics of the Microparticles
Physical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics
Linear Operators in Quantum Mechanics
17
67
161
On the History of Origin and Growth of Quantum
Mechanics (A Brief Historical Survey) 239
Appendices 249
References 258
Subject Index 262
.,
Preface
Research in physics, conducted at the end of the 19th Some Preliminary Remarks
century and in the first half of the 20th century, revealed
exceptionally peculiar nature of the laws governing the
behaviour of microparticles-atoms, electrons, and so on.
On the basis of this research a new physical theory called
quantum mechanics was founded.
The growth of quantum mechanics turned out to be quite
complicated' and prolonged. The mathematical part of
the theory, and the rules linking the theory with experi-
ment, were constructed relatively quickly (by the begin-
ning of the thirties). However, the understanding of the
physical and philosophical substance of the mathematical
symbols used in the theory was unresolved for decades.
In Fock's words [il, The mathematical apparatus of non-
relativistic quantum mechanics worked well and was free
of contradictions; but in spite of many successful applica-
tions to different problems of atomic physics the physical
representation of the mathematical scheme still remained
a problem to be solved.
Many difficulties are involved in a mathematical inter-
pretation of the quantum-mechanical apparatus. These
are associated with the dialectics of the new laws, the
radical revision of the very nature of the questions which
a physicist "is entitled to put to nature", the reinterpreta-
tion of the role of the observer vis avis his surroundings,
the new approach to the question of the relation between
chance and necessity in physical phenomena, and the
rejection of many accepted notions and concepts. Quan-
tum mechanics was born in an atmosphere of discussions
and heated clashes between contradictory arguments.
The names of many leading scientists are linked with
its development, including N. Bohr, A. Einstein,
M. Planck, E. Schrodinger, M. Born, W. Pauli, A. Som-
merfeld, L. de Broglie, P. Ehrenfest, E. Fermi, W. Hei-
senberg, P. Dirac, R. Feynman, and others.
It is also not surprising that even today anyone who
starts studying quantum mechanics encounters some
sort of psychological barrier. This is not because of the
mathematical complexity. The difficulty arises from
the fact that it is difficult to break away from accepted
concepts and to reorganize one's l'attern of thinking
which are based on everyday experience.
Preface 7
; OIC7Tiillill-IIIiIE"lIln __..-..
k
.J&:"
Before starting a study of quantum mechanics, it is
worthwhile getting an idea about its place and role in
physics. We shall consider (naturally in the most general
terms) the following three questions: What is quantum
mechanics? What is the relation between classical physics
and quantum mechanics? What specialists need quantum
mechanics? So, what is quantum mechanics?
The question can be answered in different ways. First
and foremost, quantum mechanics is a theory describing
the properties of matter at the level of microphenomena-
it considers the laws of motion of microparticles. Micro-
particles (molecules, atoms, elementary particles) are
the main "characters" in the drama of quantum me-
chanics.
From a broader point of view quantum mechanics should
be treated as the theoretical foundation of the modern
theory of the structure and properties of matter. In com-
parison with classical physics, quantum mechanics consi-
ders the properties of matter on a deeper and more funda-
mental level. It provides answers to many questions which
remained unsolved in classical physics. For example,
why is diamond hard? Why does the electrical conductivi-
ty of a semiconductor increase with temperature? Why
does a magnet lose its properties upon heating? Unable
to get answers from classical physics to these questions,
we turn to quantum mechanics. Finally, it must be em-
phasized that quantum mechanics allows one to calculate
many physical parameters of substances. Answering the
question "What is quantum mechanics?", Lamb [2] re-
marked: The only easy one (answer) is that quantum mecha-
nics is a discipline that provides a wonderful set of rules
for calculating physical properties of matter.
What is the relation of quantum mechanics to classical
physics? First of all quantum mechanics includes classical
mechanics as a limiting (extreme) case. Upon a transition
from microparticles to macroscopic bodies, quantum-
mechanical laws are converted into the laws of classical
mechanics. Because of this it is often stated, though not
very accurately, that quantum mechanics "works" in the
microworld and the classical mechanics, in the macro-
world. This statement assumes the existence of an isolated
"microworld" and an isolated "macroworld". In actual
practice We can only speak" of microparticles (micro-
phenomena) and macroscopic bodies (macrophenomena).
It is also significant that microphenomena form the basis
of macrophenomena and that macroscopic bodies are
made up of micI'oparticles. Consequently, the transition
from classical physics to quantum mechanics is a transi-
8
tion not from one "world" to another, but from a shallower
to a deeper level of studying matter. This means that
in studying the behaviour of microparticles, quantum
mechanics considers in fact the same macroparticles,
but on a more fundamental level. Besides, it must be
remembered that the boundary between micro- and macro-
phenomena in general is quite conditional and flexible.
Classical concepts are frequently found useful when consid-
ering microphenomena, while quantum-mechanical ideas
hel p in the understanding of macrophenomena. There is
even a special term "quantum macrophysics" which is
applied, in particular, to quantum electronics, to the
phenomena of superfluidity and superconductivity and
to a number of other cases.
In answering the question as to what specialists need
quantum mechanics, we mention beforehand that we
have in mind specialists training in engineering colleges.
There are at least three branches of engineering for which
a study of quantum mechanics is absolutely essential.
Firstly, there is the field of nuclear power and the appli-
cation of radioactive isotopes to industry. Secondly, the
field of materials sciences (improvement of properties
of materials, preparation of new materials with preas-
signed properties). Thirdly, the field of electronics and
first of all the field of semiconductors and laser technology.
If we consider that today almost any branch of industry
uses new materials as well as electronics on a large scale,
it will become clear that a comprehensive training in
engineering is impossible without a serious study of
quantum mechanics.
The aim of this book is to acquaint the reader with The Structure of the Book
the concepts and ideas of quantum mechanics and the
physical properties of matter; to reveal the logic of its
new ideas, to show how these ideas are embodied in the
mathematical apparatus of linear operators and to de-
monstrate the working of this apparatus using a number
of examples and problems of interest to engineering
students.
The book consists of three chapters. By way of an intro-
duction to quantum mechanics, the first chapter includes
I a study of the physics of microparticles. Special attention
I has been paid to the fundamental ideas of quantization
and duality as well as to the uncertainty relations. The
first chapter aims at "introducing" the main "character",
s Le. the microparticle, and at showing the necessity of
rejecting a number of concepts of classical physics.
1 The second chapter deals with the physical concepts of
quantum mechanics. The chapter starts with an analysis
Preface
9
1
!
10
of a set of basic experiments which form a foundation
for a system of quantum-mechanical ideas. This system
is based on the concept of the amplitude of transition
probability. The rules for working with amplitudes are
demonstrated on the basis of a number of examples, the
interference of amplitudes being the most important.
The principle of superposition and the measurement
process are considered. This concludes the first stage in
the discussion of the physical foundation of the theory.
In the second stage an analysis is given based on ampli-
tude concepts of the problems of causality in quantum
mechanics. The Hamiltonian matrix is introduced while
considering causality and its role is illustrated using
examples involving microparticles with two basic states,
with emphasis on the an electron in a magnet-
ic field. The chapter concludes with a section of a general
physical and philosophical nature.
The third chapter deals with the application of linear
operators in the apparatus of quantum mechanics. At the
beginning of the chapter the required mathematical
concepts from the theory of Hermitian and unitary linear
operators are introduced. It is then shown how the physi-
cal ideas can be "knitted" to the mathematical symbols,
thus changing the apparatus of operator theory into the
apparatus of quantum theory. The main features of this
apparatus are further considered in a concrete form in the
framework of the coordinate representation. The transi-
tion from the coordinate to the momentum representation
is illustrated. Three ways of describing the evolution of
microsystems in time, corresponding to the Schrodinger,
Heisenberg and Dirac representation, have been discussed.
A number of typical problems are considered to demon-
strate the working of the apparatus; particular attention
is paid to the problems of the motion of an electron
in a periodic field and to the calculation of the probability
of a quantum transition. "
The book contains a number of interludes. These are
dialogues in which the author has allowed himself free
and easy style of considering certain questions. The
author was motivated to include interludes in the book
by the view that one need not take too serious an attitude
when studying serious subjects. And yet the reader
should take the interludes fairly seriously. They are
intended not so much for mental relaxation, as for help-
ing the reader with fairly delicate questions, which can
be understood best through a flexible dialogue treatment.
Finally, the book contains many quotations. The author
is sure that the "original words" of the founders of quan-
tum mechanics will offer the reader useful additional
information.
The author wishes to express his deep gratitude to Personal Remarks
Prof. I.I. Gurevich, Corresponding Member of the USSR
Academy of Sciences, for the stimulating discussions
which formed the basis of this book. Prof. Gurevich
discussed the plan of the book and its preliminary drafts,
and was kind enough to go through the manuscript. His
advice not only helped mould the structure of the book,
but also helped in the nature of exposition of the material.
The subsection "The Essence of Quantum Mechanics"
in Sec. 16 is a direct consequence of Prof. Gurevich's
ideas. .
The author would like to record the deep impression
left on him by the works on quantum mechanics by the
leading American physicist R. Feynman [3-51. While
reading the sections in this book dealing with the appli-
cations of the idea of probability amplitude, superposi-
tion principle, microparticles with two basic states, the
reader can easily detect a definite similarity in approach
with the corresponding parts in Feynman's "Lectures in
Physics". The author was also considerably influenced
by N. Bohr (in particular by his wonderful essays Atomic
Physics and Human Knowledge [6]), V. A. Fock [1, 7],
W. Pauli [8], P. Dirac [9], and also by the comprehensive
works of L. D. Landau and E. M. Lifshitz [10], D. I. Blo-
khintsev [11], E. Fermi [12], L. Schiff [131.
The author is especially indebted to Prof. M. I. Podgo-
retsky, D.Sc., for a thorough and extremely useful
analysis of the manuscript. He is also grateful to Prof.
Yu. A. Vdovin, Prof. E. E. Lovetsky, Prof. G. F. Druka-
rev, Prof. V. A. Dyakov, Prof. Yu. N. Pchelnikov, and
Dr. A. M. Polyakov, all of whom took the trouble of
going through the manuscript and made a number of
valuable comments. Lastly, the author is indebted to
his wife Aldina Tarasova for her constant interest in the
writing of the book and her help in the preparation of
the manuscript. But for her efforts, it would have been
impossible to bring the book to its present form.
Prelude. Can the System
of Classical Physics
Concepts Be Considered
Logically Perfect?
Participants: the Author and the
Classical Physicist (Physicist of
the older generation, whose
views have been formed on the
basis of classical physics alone).
Author:
Classical Physicist:
Author:
Classical Physicist:
Author:
Classical Physicist:
12
He who would study organic existence,
First drives out the soul with rigid
persistence,
Then the parts in his hands he may
hold and class
But the spiritual link is lost, alas!
Goethe (Faust)
It is well known that the basic contents of a physical theory
are formed by a system of concepts which reflect the objecti va
laws of nature within the framework of the given theory. Let us
take the system of concepts lying at the root of classical physics.
Can this system be considered logically perfect?
It is quite perfect. The concepts of classical physics were formed
on the basis of prolonged human experience; they have stood the
test of time.
What are the main concepts of classical physics?
I would indicate three main points: (a) continuous variation
of physical quantities; (b) the principle of classical determinism;
(c) the analytical method of studying objects and phenomena.
While talking about continuity, let us remember that the state of
an object at every instant of time is completely determined by
describing its coordinates and velocities, which are continuous func-
tions of time. This is what forms the basis of the concept of motion
of objects along trajectories. The change in the state of an object
may in principle be made as small as possible by reducing the time
of observation.
Classical determinism assumes that if the state of an object as
well as all the forces applied to it are known at some instant of
time, we can precisely predict the state of the object at any sub-
sequent instant. Thus, if we know the position and velocity of
a freely falling stone at a certain instant, we can precisely tell its
position and velocity at any other instant, for example, at the
instant when it hits the ground.
In other words, classical physics assumes an unambiguous and
inflexible link between present and future, in the same way as
between past and present.
The possibility of such a link is in close agreement with the
continuous nature of the change of physical quantities: for every
instant of time we always have an answer to two questions: "What
are the coordinates of an object"? and, "How fast do they change?"
Finally, let us discuss the analytical method of studying objects
and phenomena. Here we come to a very important point in the
system of concepts of classical physics. The latter treats matter
as made up of different parts which, although they interact with
one another, may be investigated individually. This means that
Prelude
Author:
Classical Physicist:
Author:
Classical Physicist:
Author:
Classical Physicist:
Author:
Classical Physicist:
Author:
firstly, the object may be isolated from its environments and treated
as an independent entity, and secondly, the object may be broken
up, if necessary, into its constituents whose analysis could lead
to an understanding of the nature of the object.
It means that classical physics reduces the question "what
is an object like?" to "what is it made of?"
Yes, indeed. In order to understand any apparatus we must
"dismantle" it, at least in one's imagination, into its constituents.
By the way, everyone tries to do this in his childhood. The same
is applicable to phenomena: in order to understand the idea behind
some phenomenon, we have to express it as a function of time,
Le. to find out what follows what.
But surely such a step will destroy the notion of the object
or phenomenon as a single unit.
To some extent. However, the extent of this "destruction"
can be evaluated each time by taking into account the interactions
between different parts and relation between the time stages of
a phenomenon. It may so happen that the initially isolated object
(a part of it) may considerably change with time as a result of its
interaction with the surroundings (or interaction between parts
of the object). However, since these changes are continuous, the
individuality of the isolated object can always be returned over
any period of time. It is worthwhile to stress here the internal
logical connections among the three fundamental notions of clas-
sical physics.
I would like to add that one special consequence of the "prin-
ciple of analysis" is the notion, characteristic of classical physics,
of the mutual independence of the object of observation and the
measuring instrument (or observer). We have an instrument and
an object of measurement. They can and should be considered
separately. independently from one another.
Not quite independently. The inclusion of an ammeter in
an electric circuit naturally changes the magnitude of the current
to be measured. However, this change can always be calculated
if we know the resistance of the ammeter.
When speaking of the independence of the instrument and the
object of measurement, I just meant that their interaction may be
simply "ignored".
In that case I fully agree with you.
Born has considered this point in [14]. Characterizing the philos-
ophy of science which influenced "people of older generation", he
referred to the tendency to consider that the object of investiga-
tion and the investigator are completely isolated from each other,
that one can study physical phenomena without interfering with
their passage. Born called such style of thinking "Newtonian",
since he felt that this was I"Jflected in "Newton's celestial me-
chanics."
13
[I
,
I
,I
I
; :
, I
14
Classical Physicist: Yes, these are the notions of classical physics in general terms.
They are based on everyday commonplace experience and it may
be confidently stated that they are acceptable to our common sense,
Le. are taken as quite natural. I rather believe that the "principle
of analysis" is not only a natural but the only effective method of
studying matter. It is incomprehensible how one can gain a deeper
insight into any object or phenomenon without studying its com-
ponents. As regards the principle of classical determinism, it re-
flects the causality of phenomena in nature and is in full accordance
with the idea of physics as an exact science.
A uthor: And yet there are grounds to doubt the "flawlessness" of clas-
sical concepts even from very general considerations.
Let us try to extend the principle of classical determinism to the
universe as a whole. We must conclude that the positions and
velocities of all "atoms" in the universe at any instant are precisely
determined by the positions and velocities of these "atoms" at the
preceding instant. Thus everything that takes place in the world
is predetermined beforehand, all the events can be fatalistically
predicted. According to Laplace, we could imagine some "super-
being" completely aware of the future and the past. In his Theorie
analytique des probabilites, published in 1820, Laplace wrote [15]:
A n intelligence knowing at a given instant of time all forces acting
in nature as well as the momentary positions of all things of which
the universe consists, would be able to comprehend the motions of the
largest bodies of the world and those of the lightest atoms in one single
formula, provided his intellect were sufficiently powerful to subject
all data to analysis, to him nothing would be uncertain, both past
and future would be present to his eyes. It can be seen that an imagi-
nary attempt to extend the principle of classical determinism to
nature in its entity leads to the emergence of the idea of fatalism,
which obviously cannot be accepted by common sense.
Next, let us try to apply the "principle of analysis" to an investi-
gation of the structure of matter. We shall, in an imaginary way,
break the object into smaller and smaller fractions, thus arriving
finally at the molecules constituting the object. i\J further "breaking-
up" leads us to the conclusion that molecules are made up of atoms.
We then find out that atoms are made up of a nucleus and electrons.
Accustomed to the tendency of splitting, we would like to know
what an electron is made of. Even if we were able to get an answer
to this question, we would have obviously asked next: What are
the constituents, which form an electron, made of? And so on.
We tend to accept the fact that such a "chain" of questions is end-
less. The same common sense will revolt against such a chain
even though it is a direct consequence of classical thinking. .
Attempts were made at different times to solve the problem of
this chain. We shall give two examples here. The first one is based
on Plato's views on the structure of matter. He assumed that
matter is made up of four "elements"-earth, water, air and fire.
'"
I
Preluoe
Each of these elements is in turn made of atoms having definite
geometrical forms. The atoms of earth are cubic, those of water
are icosahedral" while the atoms of air and fire are octahedral and
tetrahedral, respectively. Finally, each atom was reduced to tri-
angles. To Plato, a triangle appeared as the simplest and most per-
fect mathematical form, hence it cannot be made up of any con-
stituents. In this way, Plato reduced the chain to the purely mathe-
matical concept of a triangle and terminated it at this point.
The other example is characteristic for the beginning of the 20th
century. It makes use of the external similarity of form between
the planetary model of the atom and the solar system. It is assumed
that our solar system is nothing but an isolated atom of some
other, gigantic world, and an ordinary atom is a sort of "solar
system" for some third dwarfish world for which "our electron"
is like a planet. In this case we admit the existence of an infinite
row of more and more dwarfish worlds, just like more and more
gigantic worlds. In such a system the structure of matter is de-
scribed in accordance with the primitive "chinese box" principle.
The "chinese box" principle of hollow tubes, according to which
nature has a more or less similar structure, was not accepted by
all the physicists of older generations. However, this principle
is quite characteristic of classical physics, it conforms to classical
concepts, and follows directly from the classical principle of anal-
ysis. In this connection, criticizing Pascal's views that the smallest
and the largest objects have the same structure, Langevin pointed
out that this would lead to the same aspects of reality being revealed
at all levels. The universe should then be reflected in an absolutely
identical fashion in all objects, though on a much smaller scale.
Fortunately, reality turns out to be much more diverse and in-
teresting.
Thus, we are convinced that a successive application of the prin-
ciples of classical physics may, in some cases, lead to results which
appear doubtful. This indicates the existence of situations for
which classical principles are not applicable. Thus it is to be
expected that for a sufficiently strong "breaking-up" of matter, the
principle of analysis must become redundant (thus the idea of the
independence of the object of measurement from the measuring
instrument must also become obsolete). In this context the question
"what is an electron made of?" would simply appear to have lost
its meaning.
If this is so, we must accept the relatiVity of the classical concepts
which are so convenient and dear to us, and replace them with some
qualitatively new ideas on the motion of matter. The classical
attempts to obtain an endless detailization of objects and phenom-
ena mean that the desire inculcated in us over centuries "to study
organic existence" leads at a certain stage to a "driving out of the
soul" and a situation arises, where, according to Goethe, "the spiri-
tual link is lost".
15
I'
I; I
Section 1.
Section 2.
Section 3.
Section 4.
Section 5.
Section 6.
Certain Characteristics and Properties of Micro-
particles 18
Two Fundamental Ideas of Quantum Mechanics 25
Uncertainty Relations 34
Some Results Ensuing from the Uncertainty Relations 42
Impossibility of Classical Representation of a Micro-
particle 49
Rejection of Ideas of Classical Physics 55
Interlude. Is a "Physically Intuitive" Model of a
Microparticle Possible? 63
-- f
I
Chapter 1
Physics
of the Microparticles
9
5
3
rl
Section I
I'
, :
!
Microparticles
Spin of a Microparticle
18
Certain Characteristics and
Properties of Microparticles
Molecules, atoms, atomic nuclei and elementary particles
belong to the category of microparticles. The list of
elementary particles is at present fairly extensive and
includes quanta of electromagnetic field (photons) as well
as two groups of particles, the hadrons and the leptons.
Hadrons are characterized by a strong (nuclear) inter-
action, while leptons never take part in strong interac-
tions. The electron
t
the muon and the two neutrinos (the
electronic and muonic) are leptons. The group of hadrons
is numerically much larger. It includes nucleons (pro-
ton and neutron), mesons (a group of particles lighter
than the proton) and hyperons (a group of particles
heavier than the neutron). With the exception of pho-
tons and some neutral mesons, all elementary particles
have corresponding anti-particles.,
Among properties of microparticles, let us first mention
the rest mass and electric charge. As an example, we note
that the mass m of an electron is equal to 9.1 X 10-
28
g;
a proton has mass equal to 1836m, a neutron, 1839m
and a muon, 207m. Pions (n-mesons) have a mass of
about 270m and kaons (K-mesons) , about 970m. The
rest mass of a photon and of both neutrinos is assumed
to be equal to zero.
The mass of a molecule, atom or atomic nucleus is equal
to the sum of the masses of the particles constituting the
given microparticle, less a certain amount known as the
mass defect. The mass defect is equal to the ratio of the
energy that must be expended to break up the micropar-
ticle into its constituent particles (this energy is usually
called the binding energy) to the square of velocity of
light. The stronger the binding between particles, the
greater is the mass defect. Nucleons in atomic nuclei
have the strongest binding-the r s ~ defect for one
nucleon exceeds 10m.
The magnitude of the electric charge of a microparticle
is a multiple of the magnitude of the charge of an elec-
tron, which is equal to 1.6 X 10-
19
C (4.8 X 10-
10
CGSE
units). Apart from charged microparticles, there also
exist neutral microparticles (for example, photon, neutri-
no, neutron). The electric charge of a complex micro-
particle is equal to the algebraic sum of the charges of
its constituent particles.
Spin is one of the most important specific character-
istics of a microparticle. It may be interpreted as the
angular momentum of the microparticle not related to
its motion as a whole (it is frequently known as the
internal angular momentum of the microparticle). The
square of this angular momentum is equal to ;,,zs (s + 1),
where -s for the given microparticle is a definite integral
or semi-integral number (it is this number which is
usually referred to as the spin), Ii is a universal physical
constant which plays an exceptionally important role
in quantum mechanics. It is called Planck's constant
and is equal to 1.05 X 10-
34
J.s Spin s of a photon is
equal to 1, that of an electron (or any other lepton) is
equal, to , while pions and kaons don't have any
spin. * Spin is a specific property of a microparticle. It
does not have a classical analogue and certainly points
to the complex internal structure of the microparticle.
True, it is sometimes attempted to explain the concept
of spin on the 'model of an object rotating around its
axis (the very word "spin" means "rotate"). Such a mode
is descriptive but not true. In any case, it cannot be
literally accepted. The term "rotating microparticle"
that one comes across in the literature does not by any
means indicate the rotation of the microparticle, but
merely the existence of a specific internal angular mo-
mentum in it. In order that this momentum be trans-
formed into "classical" angular momentum (and the object
thereby actually rotate) it is necessary to satisfy the
conditions s 1. Such a condition, however, is usually
not satisfied.
The peculiarity of the angular momentum of a micro-
.. particle is manifested, in particular, in the fact that its
projection in any fixed direction assumes discrete values
lis, Ii (s -1), ..., -lis, thus in total 2s + 1 values.
It means that the microparticle may exist in 28 + 1 spin
states. Consequently, the existence of spin in a micro-
particle leads to the appearance of additional (internal)
degrees of freedom.
If we know the spin of a microparticle, we can predict Bosons and Fermions
its behaviour in the collective of microparticles similar
to it (in other words, to predict the statistical properties
of the microparticle). It turns out that all the micropar-
ticles in nature can be divided into two groups, according
The definition of spin of a microparticle assumes that spin is
independent of external conditions. This is true for elementary
particles. However, the spin of an atom, for example, may change
with a change in the state of the latter. In other words, the spin
of an atom may change as a result of influences on the atom which
lead to a change in its state.
Sec. 1
19
I'
I
\
,
I
I
t
<'
Instability of Microparticles
20
to their statistical properties: a group with integral values
of spin or with zero spin, and another with half-integral
spin.
Microparticles of the first group are capable of populating
one and the same state in unlimited numbers. * Moreover,
the more populated is a given state, the higher is the
probability that a microparticle appears in this state.
Such microparticles are known to obey the Bose-Einstein
statistics, in short they are simply called bosons. Micro-
particles of the second group may inhabit the states only
one at a time, if the state under consideration is already
occupied, no other microparticle of the given type can
be accommodated there. Such microparticles obey Fermi-
Dirac statistics and are called fermions.
Among elementary particles, photons and mesons are
bosons while the leptons (in particular, electrons), nu-
cleons and hyperons are fermions. The fact that electrons
are fermions is reflected in the well-known Pauli exclusion
principle.
All elementary particles except the photon, the elec-
tron, the proton and both neutrinos are unstable. This
means that they decay spontaneously, without any exter-
nal influence, and are transformed into other particles.
For example, a neutron spontaneously decays into a pro-
ton, an electron and an electronic antineutrino (n -+ p +
+ e- + v
e
). It is impossible to predict precisely at what
time a particular neutron will decay since each individ-
ual act of disintegration occurs randomly. However, by
following a large number of acts, we find a regularity
in decay. Suppose there are No neutrons (N0 1) at
time t = O. Then at the moment t we are left with
N (t) = No exp (-tiT:) neutrons, where T is a certain
constant characteristic of neutrons. It is called the life-
time of a neutron and is equal to 10
3
s. The quantity
exp (-tIT) determines the probability that a given
neutron will not decay in time t.
Every unstable elementary particle is characterized by
its lifetime. The smaller the lifetime of a particle, the
greater the probability that it will decay. For example,
the lifetime of a muon is 2.2 X 10-
6
s, that of a positively
charged Jt-meson is 2.6 X 10-
8
s, while for a neutral
Jt-meson the lifetime is 10-
16
s and for hyperons, 10-
10
s.
In recent years, a large number of particles (about 100)
have been observed to have an anomalously small lifetime
of about 10-
22
-10-
23
s. These are called resonances.
* The concept of the state of a microparticle is discussed in Sec. 3
below.
1
e
S
"l
s
,-
t
t
l
n
y
n
y
e
,
"
Y
1
I)
e
3
It is worthnoting that hyperons and mesons may decay
in different ways. For example, the positively charged
n-meson may decay into a muon and a muonic neutrino
It (n+ -+ f.-t + + "It), into a positron (antielectron) and elec-
tronic neutrino (:n: + -+ e+ + "e), into a neutral :n:-meson,
positron and electronic neutrino (n + --+ :n:o + e+ + "e).
For any particular :n:-meson, it is impossible to predict
not only the time of its decay, but also the mode of decay
it might "choose". Instability is inherent not only in
elementary particles, but also in other microparticles.
The phenomenon of radioactivity (spontaneous conver-
sion of isotopes of one chemical element into isotopes of
another, accompanied by emission of particles) shows
that the atomic nuclei can also be unstable. Atoms and
molecules in excited states are also unstable; they spon-
taneously returp to their ground state or to a less excited
state.
Instability determined hy the probability laws is, apart
from spin, the second special specific property inherent
in microparticles. This may also be considered as an
indication of a certain "internal complexity" in the
microparticles.
In conclusion, we may note that instability is a specific,
but by no means essential, property of microparticles.
Apart from the unstable ones, there are many stable
microparticles: the photon, the electron, the proton,
the neutrino, the stable atomic nuclei, as well as atoms
and molecules in their ground states.
Looking at the decay scheme of a neutron (n -+ p + Interconversion of Microparticles
+ e- + v:,), an inexperienced reader might presume
that a neutron is made up of mutually bound proton,
electron and electronic antineutrino. Such an assumption
is wrong. The decay of elementary particles is by no
means a disintegration in the literal sense of the word;
it is just an act of conversion of the original particle
into a certain aggregate of new particles; the original
particle is annihilated while new particles are created.
The unfoundedness of the literal interpretation of the
term "decay of particles" becomes apparent when one
considers that many particles can decay in several dif-
ferent ways.
The interconversion of elementary particles turns out
to be much more diverse and complicated if we consider
particles not only in a free,' but also in a bound state.
A free proton is stable, and a free neutron decays accord-
ing to the equation mentioned above. If, however, the
neutron and the proton are not free but bound in an
atomic nucleus, the situation radically changes. Now
Sec. 1 21
.,
22
the following equations of interconversion are operative:
n.- p + ~ P -+- n + n+ (here, n- is a negatively
charged n-meson, the antiparticle of the n +-meson).
These equations very well illustrate that an attempt to
find out whether the proton is a "constituent" of the
neutron, or vice versa is pointless.
Everyday experience teaches us that to break up an
object into parts means to reveal its structure. The idea
of analysis (or splitting) reflects the characteristic feature
of classical methods. When we go over to the micropar-
ticles, this idea still holds to a certain extent: the mole-
cules are made up of atoms, the atoms consist of nuclei
and electrons, the nuclei are made up of protons and
neutrons. However, the idea exhausts itself at this point:
for example, "splitting up" of a neutron or a proton does
not reveal the structure of these particles. As regards
elementary particles, when we say that a particle decays
into parts, it does not mean that these particles constitute
the given particle. This condition itself might serve as
a definition of an elementary particle.
Decay of elementary particles is not the only kind of
interconversion of particles. Equally important is the
case of interconversion of particles when they collide
with one another. As an example, we shall consider some
equations of interconversion during collision of photons
(V) with protons and neutrons:
V+ p.-n+n+, l'+n.-p+n-,
1'+ p.- p+no, ,\,+n.-n+no,
'\' +p.- p +n+ +n-,
l'+n .-n+n
O
+nO,
1'+p.- p+p+PCD-denotes an antiproton)
It should be mentioned here that in ,all the above equa-
tions, the sum of the rest masses of the end particles is
greater than the rest mass of the initial ones. In other
words, the energy of the colliding particles is converted
into mass (according to the well-known relation E = mc
2
).
These equations demonstrate, in particular, the fruitless-
ness of efforts to break up elementary particles (in this
case, nucleons) by "bombarding" them with other par-
ticles (in this case, photons): in fact, it does not lead to
a breaking-up of the particles being bombarded at, but
to the creation of new particles, to some extent at the
expense of the energy of the colliding particles.
A study of the interconversion of elementary particles
permits us to determine certain regularities. These regu-
I
I
S
l'
Ii
I.
i-
.s
-
0
It
Ie
)s
1-
T:.es.are e x p ? ~ e d inthe form of law, of con,erva'i?n
I
', of certalll quantities which play the role of some defimte
; characteristics of certain particles. As a simple example,
~ we take the electric charge of a particle. For any inter-
i conversion of particles, the algebraic sum of electric
charges of the initial and end particles remains the same.
The law of conservation of the electric charge refers to
a definite regularity in the interconversion of particles:
it permits one to summarily reject equations where the
total electric charge is not conserved.
As a more complicated example, we mention the so-called barionic
charge of a particle. It has been observed that the number of nu-
leons during an interconversion of particles is conserved. With the
discovery of antinucleons, it was observed that additional nu-
cleons may be created, but they must be created in pairs with
these antinucleons. So a new characteristic of particles, the barion-
ic charge, was introduced. It is equal to zero for photons, leptons
and mesons, +1 for nucleons, and -1 for antinucleons. This per-
mits us to consider the above-mentioned regularity as a law of
conservation of the total barionic charge of the particles. The law
was also confirmed by the discoveries that followed: the hyperons
were assigned a barionic charge equal to 1 (as for nucleons) and the
antihyperons were given a barionic charge equal to -1 (as for
antinucleons).
While going over from macroparticles to microparticles, Universal Dynamic Variables
one would expect qualitatively di fferent answers to
questions like: Which dynamic variables should be used
to describe the state of the object? How should its motion
be depicted? Answers to these questions reveal to a con-
siderable extent the specific nature of microparticles.
In classical physics, we make use of the laws of conserva-
-tion of energy, momentum and angular momentum. It is
woll known that these laws are consequences of certain
properties of the symmetry of space and time. Thus, the
law of conservation of energy is a consequence of homoge-
neity oj time (independence of the course of a physical
process of the moment chosen as the starting point of
the process); the law of conservation of momentum is
a consequence of the unijormity of space (all points in
space are physically equivalent); the law of conservation
of angular momentum is a consequence of the_ isotropy
of space (all directions in space are physically equivalent).
To elucidate the properties of symmetry of space and
time, we note, for example, that thanks to these pro-
perties, Kepler's laws describing the motion of the plan-
ets around the sun are independent of the position of
the sun in the galaxy, of the orientation in space of the
I
Sec. 1
23
rl
plane of motion of the planets and also of the century in
which these laws were discovered. The connection between
the properties of symmetry of space and time and the
corresponding conservation laws means that the energy,
momentum and angular momentum can be considered
as integrals of motion, whose conservation is a consequence
of the corresponding homogeneity of time and the homo-
geneity and isotropy of space.
The absence of any experimental evidence indicating
violation of the above-mentioned properties of symmetry
of space and time for microphenomena reveals that such
dynamic parameters as energy, momentum and angular
momentum should retain their meaning when applied
to microparticles. In other words, the connection of these
dynamic variables with the fundamental properties of
symmetry in space and time makes them universal
variables, Le. variables which are "used" while consider-
ing the kind of phenomena occurring in different branches
of physics.
When transferring the concepts of energy, momentum
and angular momentum from classical physics to quan-
tum mechanics, however, the specific nature of the micro-
particles must be taken into account. In this connection
we recall the well-known expressions for energy (E),
momentum (p) and angular momentum (M) of a classical
object, having mass m, coordinate -;, velocity ;;
I,
I
,
,!
mv2 -* -+ ---+ -+ -+-+
E= -2-+U (r),p=mv, M =m(r X V).
(1.1)
Eliminating the velocity, we get from here the relations
connecting energy, momentum and angular momentllm
of a classical ohject:
If we turn to a microparticle, we can go a bit farther,
(see Sec. 3) and conclude that relations (1.2) and (1.3)
are no longer valid. In other words, the classical connec-
tions between the integrals of motion become useless as
we go over to microparticles (as regards relations (1.1),
they cannot be mentioned at all since the very concept of
the velocity of a microparticle, as we shall see below, is
meaningless). This is the first qualitatively new cir-
cumstance.
(1.2)
(1.3)
p2 -+
E=2:m+
U
(r),
24
In order to consider the other qualitatively new circum-
stances, we must turn to the fundamental ideas of quan-
tum mechanics, i. e. the idea of quantization of physical
quantities and the idea of wave-particle duality.
The essence of the idea of quantization lies in the
fact that certain physical quantities related to the micro-
particles may assume, under relevant circumstances,
only certain discrete values. These quantities are said
to be quantized.
Thus the energy of any microparticle in a bound state,
like that of an ~ l t r o n in an atom, is quantized. The
energy of a freely moving microparticle, however is
not quantized.
Let us consider the energy of an electron in an atom.
The system of so-ealled energy levels corresponds to a
discrete set of values of electron energy. We consider
two energy levels E
1
and E
2
as shown in Fig. 2.1 (the
values of electron energy are plotted along the vertical
axis). The electron may possess energy E
1
or E
2
and
cannot possess any intermediate energy-all values of
energy E satisfying the condition E
1
< E < E
2
are
forbidden for it*. It should be noted that the discreteness
of energy does not mean in any case that the electron is
"doomed" to remain forever in the initial energy state (for
example on level E
1
). The electron may go over to another
energy state (level E
2
or any other) by acquiring or
releasing the corresponding amount of energy. Such
a transition is called a quantum transition.
The quantum-mechanical idea of discreteness has a fairly
long history. By the end of 19th century, it was established
that the radiation spectra of free atoms are line spectra
(i.e. they consist of sets of lines) and contain, for every
element, definite lines which form ordered groups (series).
In 1885, it was discovered that atomic hydrogen emits
radiation of frequencies (iln (henceforth we use the cyclic
frequencies (il, related to the normal frequencies v through
the equation (il = 2nv) which may be described by the
formula
(iln = 2ncR ( 1- :2 ), (2.1)
The Idea of Quantization
(Discreteness)
Section 2 Two Fundamental Ideas of
Quantum Mechanics
Fig. 2.1
E.,
e
'i * A specific situation in quantum mechanics is possible in which
one must assume that an electron occupies level 1 as well as level
2 (see Sec. 10).
Sec. 2
25
t
)
26
where n are integral numbers 3, 4, 5, ... , c is the
velocity of light, R is the so-called Rydberg constant
(R = 1.097 X 10
7
m-
1
). Formula (2.1) was derived by
Balmer, hence the set of frequencies described by this
formula is called the Balmer series. The frequencies of
the Balmer series fall in the visible region of spectrum.
Later (in the beginning of 20th century), additional series
of radiation from atomic hydrogen falling in the ultra-
violet and infrared regions were discovered. The regulari-
ties in the structure of these spectra were identical to the
regularities in the structure of the Balmer series, which
enabled a generalization of formula (2.1) in the following
form:
CJ)n = 2ncR ( ;. - ) . (2.2)
The number k fixes the series (in each series n > k);
k = 2 gives the Balmer series, k = 1, the Lyman series
(ultraviolet frequencies), k = 3, the Paschen series (infra-
red frequencies), and so on.
Regularity in the structure of series was observed not
only in the spectrum of atomic hydrogen, but also in the
spectra of other atoms. It definitely indicated the possibil-
ity of some generalizations. One such generalization
was proposed by Ritz in 1908 in his combination principle,
which states that if the formulae of series are given and
the constants occurring in them are known, any newly
discovered line in the spectrum may be obtained from
the lines already known by means of combinations in the
form of sums and differences. This principle may be
applied to hydrogen in the following way: we write the
so-called spectral terms for different numbers n:
T(n) = 2ncRln
2
34
a wave packet. By considering U) and k
x
in (3.1) as wave
characteristics of a microparticle and making use of
relations (2.13), it is easy to go over to an analogous
expression for the corpuscular characteristics of a micro-
particle (for its energy and momentum):
ti, (>\.2)
n. (.3.;3)
These relations were first introduced by Heisenbefg in
1927 and are called uncertainty relations.
Relations (3.2) and (3.3) should be supplemented by the
following uncertainty relation:
dt n, (3.4)
where is the uncertainty in the angular coordinates
of the microparticle (we consider rotation around the
x-axis) and x is the uncertainty in the projection of
the momentum on the x-axis. *
By analogy with (3.3) and (3.4), one may write down
relations for other projections of momentum and angular
(J momentum:
e-
o
e-
o
'.
)
;.
:s
X
Y
II
!1P
y
!1y n, ti, (3.:3<1)
dt ti, n. (3.4a)
Let us consider relation (3.3). Here is the uncertainty The Meaning of the Uncertainty
in the x-coordinate of the microparticle and the Relations
uncertainty in the x-projection of its momentum. The
smaller is, the greater is, and vice versa. If the
microparticle is localized at a certain definite point x,
then the x-projection of its momentum must have arbi-
trarily large uncertainty. If, on the contrary, the micro-
particle is in a state with a definite value of Px' then it
cannot be localized exactly on the x-axis.
Sometimes the uncertainty relation (3.3) is interpreted
in the following way: it is impossible to measure simulta-
neously the coordinate and momentum of a microparticle
with an arbitrarily high precision; the more accurately
,ve measure the coordinate, the less accurately can the
momentum be determined. Such an interpretation is not
very good since it might lead to the erroneous conclusion
that the essense of the uncertainty relation (3.3) is respon-
sible for limitations associated with the process of measurr-
* Notice that relations (3.4) and (3.4a) are valid only for small
values of the uncertainty in angular coordinate 2n) or, in
othpr words, for large values of uncertainty in the projection of
the momentum.
I
1..
Sec. 3
35
t
36
ment. One might be led to assume that a microparticle
itself possesses a definite coordinate as well as a definite
momentum, but the uncertainty relation does not permit
us to measure them simultaneously.
Actually the situation is quite different. The microparticle
itself simply cannot have simultaneously a definite coor-
dinate and a corresponding definite projection of the
momentum. If, for example, it is in a state with a more
definite value of the coordinate, then in this state the
corresponding projection of its momentum is less definite.
From this the actual impossibility of simultaneous mea-
surements of coordinates and momenta of a microparticle
follows naturally. This is a result of the specific character
of the microparticle and is by no means a whim of nature
which makes it impossible for us to perceive all that
exists. Consequently, the sense ot relation (3.3) is not
that it creates certain obstacles to the understanding of
microphenomena, but that itreflects certain peculiarities
of the objective properties ofallicroparticle. The last
remark is, of course, of a general nature: it refers not only
to relation (3.3), but also to other uncertainty relations.
Now let us look at relation (3.2). Let us consider two
different, though mutually supporting interpretations,
of this relation. Suppose that the microparticle is unstable
and that M is its lifetime in the state under consideration.
The energy of the microparticle in this state must have
an uncertainty I1E which is related to the lifetime I1t
through inequality (3.2). In particular, if the state is
stationary (M is arbitrarily large), the energy of the
microparticle will be precisely determined (I1E = 0).
The other interpretation of relation (3.2) is connected
with the measurements carried out to ascertain whether
the microparticle is located at the level E
1
or E
z
. Such
a measurement requires a finite time T which depends on
the distance between the levels (EZ'I- E]):
(E
2
- E
1
) T Ii. (3.2a)
It is not difficult to see the connection between these
two interpretations. In order to distinguish the levels E
1
and E
2
, it is necessary that the uncertainty I1E in the
energy of the microparticle should not be greater than
the distance between the levels: I1E (E
z
- E]). At
the same time the duration of measurement T should
obviously not exceed the lifetime M of the microparticle
in the given state: T M. Consequently, the limiting
conditions, under which measurement is still possible,
are given by
I1E E
2
- Ej1 T I1t.
'If,
Ie
le
it
Ie
r-
le
re
1e
e.
a-
le
er
re
'lt
ot
of
es
st
Iy
s.
m
s,
Ie
n.
ve
~
is
lie
~
er
3h
m
a)
se
"fE
1
lie
m
'\t
ld
Ie
19
e,
By using (3.2), we can arrive at (3.2a) from these rela-
tions.
The uncertainty relations (3.2)-(3.4) show how the con-
cepts of energy, momentum and angular momentum
should be applied in the case of microparticles. Here,
a very important peculiarity of the physics of micro-
particles is revealed: the energy, momentum and the
angular momentum of a microparticle have meaning
only within the limitations imposed by the uncertainty
relations. Heisenberg [20] writes that we cannot inter-
pret processes on an atomic scale in the same way as
processes on a large scale. If we make use of the usual
concepts, their applicability is limited by the uncertainty
relations.
It should, however, be pointed out that the uncertainty
relations do not in any way lead to the above-mentioned
restrictions OD the applicability of classical concepts of
coordinates, momentum, energy, etc. for microparticles.
It would be unfair not to mention the considerable "posi-
tive aspects" of uncertainty relations after having talked
about their "negative aspects". They serve as a working
instrument of the quantum theory. By reflecting the spe-
cific character of the physics of microparticles, the uncer-
tainty relations allow us to obtain fairly important results
through fairly simple means. Some examples are given
in Sec. 4 below.
The method of deriving the uncertainty relations consid-
ered in the beginning of this section might appear too
formal and unconvincing to some readers. There are
various means of deriving uncertainty relations (see, for
example [21]). One such method [which is specifically
applied to relations (3.3)] is based on a consideration of
the phenomena of diffraction of microparticles.
Suppose (Fig. 3.2) a screen with a narrow slit is placed
in the path of a strictly parallel beam of certain micro-
particles with momentum p. Let d be the width of the
slit along the x-axis (the x-axis is perpendicular to the
direction of the beam). Diffraction takes place during
the passage of microparticles through the slit. Let ebe the
angle between the initial direction and the direction
of the first (principal) diffraction peak. The classical
wave theory gives the following well-known relation for
this angle sin e = 'f.ld. Assuming angle e to be sufficient-
ly small, we can rewrite this relation in the following form:
e ~ 'A/d (3.5)
If by A we now mean not the classical wavelength, but
the length of the de Broglie wave (i.e. the wave character-
From Diffraction in Microparticles
to Uncertainty Relations
Fig. 3.2
_J_.s.ec..3
37
__
1
Uncertainty Relations and the
State of Microparticles.
The Concept of a Complete Set
of Physical Quantities
38
istic of the microparticle), we may rewrite relation (3.5)
in "corpuscular language" by using the expression (2.11):
8 nlpd. (3.5a)
But how we are to understand the existence of the angle
8 in "corpuscular language"? Obviously, it means that
while passing through the slit, the microparticle acquires
a certain momentum !1p", in the direction of the x-axis.
It is easy to see that I1px p8. Substituting (3.5a)
into this, we get I1px Md. By considering the quantity
d as the uncertainty !1x in the x-coordinate of the micro-
particle passing through the slit, we get !1px!1x 11"
i.e. we arrive at the uncertainty relation (3.3). Thus the
attempt to determine in some way the coordinate of
a microparticle in a direction perpendicular to the di-
rection of its motion leads to an uncertainty in the mo-
mentum of the microparticle in that direction, which also
explains the phenomenon of diffraction observed in the
experiment.
In order to describe the state of a classical object it is
necessary to give a definite set of numbers-the coordinates
and the velocity components. In doing this other
quantities, in particular, energy, momentum and angular
momentum of the object will also be determined [see (1.1)1.
The uncertainty relations show that this method of
defining a state is not applicable to microparticles.
Thus, for example, the existence of a definite projection
of momentum in a given direction for a microparticle
means that the position of the microparticle in this
direction cannot be determined unambiguously: according
to (3.3), the corresponding spatial coordinate is character-
ized by an infinitely large uncertainty. The electron
in an atom has a definite energy; moreover its coordinates
are characterized by an uncertainty of t,he order of the
linear dimensions of the atom. This [according to (3.3)]
leads to an uncertainty in the projection of the momentum
of the elect.ron equal to the ratio of Planck's constant
to the linear dimension of the atom.
We now indicate the following situations, fundamental
in quantum mechanics, which arise from the uncertainty
relation: (a) various dynamic variables of a microparticle
are combined in sets of lJimultaneoulJly determined (simul-
taneously measurable) quantities, the so-called complete
sets of quantities; (b) various states of a microparticle
are combined in groups of states corresponding to differ-
ent complete sets of quantities. Each group contains
the states of the microparticle in which the values of
the corresponding complete sets are known (it is custom-
1!
5)
):
a)
Ie
it
es
s.
a)
;y
0-
~
le
:>f
i-
:>-
;0
Le
is
3S
lr
tr
I.
If
5.
n
e
ls
g
~ -
n
~ s
e
~ 1
n
.t
11
Y
.e
l-
~ e
.e
'-
.s
If
t-
J
ary to say that every complete set has its own method of
defining its states).
We shall give examples of the complete sets employed
for determining the states of, say, an electron and a pho-
ton. Each of the sets includes four quantities (because
of this we say that a microparticle like an electron or
a photon has four degrees of freedom). To describe the
states of an electron, the following sets are employed:
x, y, Z, (J (3.6a)
p ~ . PIi' pz> (J (3.6b)
E, 7, m, (J (3.6c)
(remember that l, m, and (J are orbital, magnetic and
spin quantum numbers, respectively). We emphasize
that the coordinates and the momentum components
of a microparUcle (in this case an electron) fall in differ-
ent complete sets of quantities; these two physical
quantities cannot be measured simultaneously. Hence
the classical relations (1.2) and (1.3) are not valid when
going over to microparticles, since each of these relations
contains the coordinates as well as the momentum.
The set (3.6b) is used, in particular, for a describing the
states of a freely moving electron. Moreover, the energy
of the electron also turns out to be definable: E =
= p ~ + p ~ + p;)/2m*. The set (3.6c) is usually employed
for describing the states of an electron in the atom.
To describe the states of a photon, the following sets
are most commonly employed:
k" "y, kz> ex, (3.7a)
E, 211
2
, Mz> P. (3.7b)
Here "x, kif' k z are the projections of the wave vector of
the radiation; ex is the polarization of the photon; M2
and M z are the square of the momentum and the pro-
jection of the momentum of the photon, respectively; P is
a quantum number called the spatial parity. We notice
that as soon as the projections of the wave vector of
radiation are determined, the projections of the photon
momentum are also known (recall that p= nk). The
polarization of a photon may take two values correspond-
ing completely to the two independent polarizations of
a classical wave (thus, for example, one might talk
about a photon having right elliptical polarization).
... In contrast to relation (1.2), the classical relation E = p2/2m
remains valid for a freely moving particle when going over to
microparticles.
Sec. 3
d
Uncertainty Relations and
Quantum Transitions
40
The spatial parity is a characteristic property of a micro-
particle; it may be considered as an integral of motion
whose conservation is a result of symmetry with respect
to the operation of reflection by a mirror. At a later stage
(see Sec. 20) we shall discuss it in greater detail. Here.
we only mention that parity can assume one of the two
values: +1 and -1.
The set (3.7a) is used for describing the states of photons
corresponding to plane classical waves, in this case the
energy of the photon is also defined (recall that E = nw =
= nck). The states described by the set (3.7a) are called
kcx-statos. The set (3. 7b) is employed for describing
the states of photons belonging to spherical classical
waves. We note that just as a spherical wave may be
represented as a superposition of plane waves, the states
of a photon described by the set (3. 7b) may be represented
as a "superposition" of states described by the set (3.7a).
The converse statement regarding the representation of
plane waves as a superposition of spherical waves is also
true. Here we have touched upon (for the present just
touched upon) one of the most important and delicate
aspects of the quantum-mechanical description of mat-
ter-the specific character of the "interrelations" between
states of a microparticle described by different complete
sets. This specific character is reflected in the most
constructive principle of quantum mechanics-the prin-
ciple of superposition of states. The superposition of states
will be considered in detail in the second chapter; here
we shall just restrict ourselves to the above-mentioned
remarks.
The main contradiction regarding quantum transitions
indicated in Sec. 2 is essentially overcome by making
use of the idea of duality or, more precisely, the uncer-
tainty relation (3.2). Let us consider transition of an
electron in an atom from level E
1
to level E
2
by absorbing
a photon of energy nw = E
2
- E
1
We recall that the
contradiction in transition was connected with the
question whether the absorption of the photon precedes
the transition of the electron or vice versa. It is easy
to see that this question simply loses its meaning now.
In fact, if we have a bound electron with energies E}
and E2 before and after interaction with radiation, respec-
tively, then during the interaction we have one quantum-
mechanical system including both the electron and the
radiation. This system exists for a definite time (while
the interaction with the radiation takes place) and, accord-
ing to (3.2), cannot have any definite energy. Hence
it is meaningless to find out precisely what takes place
ro- in such a system. Strictly speaking, during the interac-
on tion of the electron with the photon there is no electron
lct and no photon, but a single entity which must be treated
,ge as such, without going into details. This example shows
ret that in quantum mechanics a physical process cannot be
VilO infinitely detailed in time. The question ''what follows
what"? cannot always be posed in the case of microphe-
us nomena.*
he
The uncertainty relation (3.2) allows us to introduce and employ
ed a very important concept in quantum theory, the so-called virtual
ng transitions, for explaining quantum transitions. \Ve shall give
:al here a simplified treatment of virtual transitions, but we shall
be give a detailed explanation later in Sec. 6. According to relation
,es (3.2), an electron may go over from level E
l
to E
2
without getting
ed any energy from outside; what is important is that it should quick-
I). ly return to its initial level E
l
Such a "journey" (El -+ E 2 -+ E l )
of is possible if its duration /:,t is such that the inequality nI /:,t >
so > (E
2
- E
l
) is satisfied, because in this case the uncertainty in
st the energy of the electron is greater than the difference in the ener-
te gies of the levels under consideration. Hence it is clear that the
t- statement "the electron occupies level Et may be understood quite
ln specifically-as incessant "transition" of the electron from the
te given state to others with an inevitable return every time to the
st starting level E
l
. Such transitions cannot be observed experimen-
n- tally, and are called virtual transitions in contrast to the normal
es (real) transitions. During interaction of an electron undergoing
re virtual transitions with radiation, the electron is liable to change-
its "residence". For example, it might now occupy level E 2 and will
in future perform virtual transitions not from level E
l
, but from
1S level E 2' If such a thing happens, the electron is said to have ab-
19 sorbed a photon of energy fw) = E
2
- E
l
, and undergone a tran-
r- sition from level E
l
to E
2
Virtual transitions don't require any
.n expenditure of energy from outside while a real transition cannot
19 occur without expenditure of energy-the energy of the photons-
Le absorbed (or emitted) by electrons during interaction with radia-
le tion.
lS To explain the difference between real and virtual transitions, we-
y note that a real transition from a level E
l
to another level E
2
r. and back may be broken up into two successive events in time'
'1 (in between, the electron may be experimentally registered in the-
intermediate state E
2
). However, the virtual transition from level
:- E
l
to E 2 and back cannot be broken up into two events in time-
e both parts of the transition must be considered as a single, indi-
e visible process in time.
e * The anomaly of quantum transition is completely removed by
e considering the principle of superposition of states (see Sec. 10).
Sec. 3
4t
_ 1
Section 4
l
1
"
Ii,
II
i'
il
"
Ii
Uncertainty Relation "Number of
Photons-Phase"
Evaluation of Energy of Ground
State of Hydrogen Atom
42
The uncertainty relations used in quantum theory are
by no means exhausted by relations (3.2)-(3.4). As an
example of one more such relation we consider the uncer-
tainty relations for the number of photons and the phase
of the wave.
Let there be a monochromatic radiation of frequency ffi.
On one hand, it may be considered as a collective of
photons each having energy nffi; on the other hand, we
might treat it as a classical electromagnetic wave. Let N
be the number of photons in the volume under considera-
tion and let cI> = ffit be the phase of the classical wave.
The corpuscular characteristic of the radiation (number
of photons N) and its wave characteristic (phase cI
cannot have definite values simultaneously; there exists
the uncertainty relation
dNdcI> d- 1. (3.8)
In order to arrive at relation (3.8), we start from the
uncertainty relation for energy and time. We recall
that for measuring the energy of a quantum object with
an accuracy dE we must spend time M til dE. If we
take the collective of photons as the quantum object,
we get
dE = nffidN,
where dN is the uncertainty in the number of photons.
During the time dt necessary for measurement of the
energy of the object with an accuracy nffidN, the phase cI>
changes by dcI> = ffiM. Substituting into this the rela-
tion dt d- tilnffidN, we find dcI> d- 11dN, Q.E.D.
Relation (3.8) reflects the dialectically contradictory
unity of corpuscular and wave properties of radiation.
The uncertainty dcI> is small when the wave properties
of radiation are clearly exhibited; in this case the density
of photons is high (N is large) and sq, is the uncertainty
dN. On the other hand, the uncertainty dN is small
when there are a few photons in the aggregate. In this
case the corpuscular properties of radiation are clearly
exhibited and therefore the uncertainty dcI> is large.
Some Results Ensuing from
the Uncertainty Relations
The uncertainty relations serve as very useful working
tools of quantum theory since they permit one to obtain
important results, by fairly simple means.
As an example, we consider the hydrogen atom in its
ground state. We make use of the well-known classical
'I
j'
~
n
r-
;e
xpression for energy of a charged particle moving in
<I Coulomb field:
(4.1 )
(4.4)
(4.3)
(4.2)
I' from (4.1) by using (4.2),
The values given by (4.4) fully coincide with the results
of the rigorous theory*. Of course such a complete coinci-
dence must be considered to some extent as an accidental
success. Only the order of the quantities should be taken
seriously here. We emphasize that this order can be
evaluated quite simply as follows: it is sufficient first
to simply replace the precise values of the dynamic vari-
ables in expression (4.1) by quantities which characterize
the degree of "blurring" of these variables, Le. by their
uncertainties, and then use the quantum-mechanical
relations connecting the said uncertainties.
where m and e are the mass and charge of the electron,
respectively. In order to use the classical expression (4.1)
in the quantum theory, we consider the quantities p
and I' occurring in it as uncertainties in momentum and
coordinates of the electron, respectively. According to
relation (3.3), these quantities are connected with each
other. We assume pI' ~ Ii, or, simply,
pI' = h.
Eliminating the quantity
we get
[12 t'e
2
p
E(p)=---.
2m h
It is easy to see that the function E (p) has a minimum
for a certain value P = Pl' We denote it as E
l
. The quan-
tity E
l
may be considered as the energy of the ground
state of the hydrogen atom while the quantity 1'1 = !!...
P1
is the estimate of the linear dimensions of the atom
(in Bohr's theory this is the radius of the first orbit).
By equating the derivative dd E (p) to zero, we find
z P
Pl - ~ This at once gives the required evaluations
Icf. (2.6) and (2.7)]:
m
~ y
11.
es
;y
;y
11
is
.y
e.
s.
1e
rt>
a-
1e
11
;h
v-e
t,
3)
).
)f
re
7V
1-
e.
er
)
ts
ts
11
<I< In the rigorous theory the quantity r1 is a characteristic for
the ground state of the hydrogen atom and denotes the distance
from the nucleus at which an electron is most likely to be observed
(see expression (5.4)].
Sec. 4 43
__ 1
Estimate of the Energy of
Zero-point Oscillations of an
Oscillator
We shall proceed exactly in the same way as in the
preceding example. The energy of a classical one-dimen-
sional harmonic oscillator is given by the expression
(4.5)
Treating Px and x as uncertainties in the momentum and
coordinate of the oscillating microparticle and using the
equality Px'X = Ii as the uncertainty relation, we get
from (4.5)
(4.6)
Evaluation of the "Blurring" of
the Optical Absorption Band
Edge in the Franz-Keldysh Effect
44
By equating the derivative 3:..- E (PJ to zero we find
dpx
the value of Po = + V mliffi for which the function E (Px)
assumes its minimum value. It is easy to see that this
value is
(4.7)
This result is quite interesting. It shows that in quantum
mechanics the energy of an oscillator cannot vanish;
its minimum value is of the order of liffi. This is the
energy of what is called the zero-point oscillation. We
note that the estimate (4.7) differs from the exact expres-
sion for the energy of the zero-point oscillation just by
1
a factor of 1/2 (exact value Eo = 2" liffi).
By taking the zero-point oscillations into account, one
may arrive at the following interesting conclusion: the
energy of the oscillatory motion of atoms in a crystal
does not vanish even at absolute zero.
The zero-point oscillations illustrate a basically general
circumstance: it is impossible to find a microparticle at
the "bottom of the potential well", or, in other words
"a microparticle cannot fall to the bottom of the poten-
tial well". This conclusion does not depend on the form
of the potential well, since it is a direct consequence of
the uncertainty relation: "falling to the bottom of the
well" is connected with the vanishing of momentum and
hence the uncertainty in the momentum of the micro-
particle. In this case, the uncertainty in the coordinate
becomes so large that there is a direct contradiction with
the very fact that the microparticle is in a potential well.
The essence of the effect, investigated in 1958 by Kel-
dysh, and independently by Franz, lies in the following:
in a uniform external electric field, the minimum of the
electron energy in the Conduction band of semiconduc--
(4.9)
'I
I
e
l-
n
I)
d
e
it
I)
d
,)
is
')
n
l;
e
e
;-
y
I
e
e
II
11
t
s
11
If
e
d
I-
e
II
e
I
J
tors shifts downwards on the energy scale, leading to
a "blurring" of the edge of the fundamental optical absorp-
tion band (as a result the absorption of the photons with
energies lower than the forbidden band width becomes
possible) [22]. The value of the shift of electronic states
characterizing the indicated "blurring" may be obtained
in the same way as the preceding evaluations were made.
We make use of the classical expression for the energy
of a charged particle in the electric field of intensity G :
(4.8)
Here m is the effective mass of the electron in the conduc-
tion band. Treating Px and x as uncertainties in the
momentum and coordinate of the electron and using
the equality pxx = n as the uncertainty relation, we
get from (4.8)
E ( ) = pi _ ~
Px 2m Px'
Next, as usual we equate the derivative -f- E (Px)
Px
to zero and obtain the value Po = - (Y'0enm for which
the function E (Px) assumes its minimum value:
(4.10)
Expression (4.10) gives an estimate of the extent of the
"blurring" of the edge of the fundamental optical absorp-
tion band in the Franz-Keldysh effect.
While postulating the stationary states, Bohr's theory Why does not the Electron Fall
did not explain why, after all, the electron, moving into the Nucleus?
under acceleration, does not radiate and fall into the
nucleus as a result of this. Relation (3.3) explains this
fact. The falling of an electron into a nucleus would
obviously mean a considerable reduction in the uncer-
tainty of its coordinate. Before the hypothetical falling
into the nucleus, the electron is localized within the
limits of the atom, i.e. in a region of space with linear
dimensions n
2
/me
2
~ 10-
8
em [see (4.4)], whereas after
falling into the nucleus it would be localized in a region
with linear dimensions less than 10-
12
em. According
to (3.3) a stronger localization of a microparticle in space
is linked with a "blurring" of its momentum. Hence upon
falling into the nucleus, the mean value of the momentum
of the electron must increase, which requires an expendi-
ture of energy. Thus it turns out that effort has to be
made not to "hold" the electron from falling into the
Sec. 4 45
d
nucleus, but on the contrary to "force" the electron to be
localized within the nucleus.
In the example of the zero-point oscillations it was
pointed out that the microparticle in a potential well
always possesses a non-zero minimum energy Eo. The
magnitude of Eo depends, in particular, on the spatial
dimensions of the well (or on its width a, which determines
the extent of localization of the microparticle in
space). By taking into account the uncertainty relation,
it is easy to see that
(4.11)
On the "Trajecfory" of
Microparticles
46
If a decreases, Eo increases. For sufficiently small a, the
energy Eo may become greater than the depth of the
potential well. It is obvious that such a well will not
hold the microparticle at all.
The falling of an electron into the nucleus corresponds to
a decrease in the width of the potential well from 10-
8
cm
to 10-
12
cm (and even lower). According to (4.11) the
minimum energy Eo should increase in this case from
10 to 10
9
eV (and higher). As a result the minimum energy
of the electron turns out to be a few orders higher than
the binding energy of a nucleon in the atomic nucleus
(the latter being not greater than 10
7
eV). This means
that the electron cannot ever be present in the nuclear
potential well and hence it can by any means be compelled
to be localized within the nucleus, not even by force.
This not only eliminates the problem of "an electroll
falling into the nucleus" but also solves another funda-
mental question: the electron is not one of the constituents
of the atomic nucleus.
In order to draw the trajectory of a particle, it is neces-
sary, strictly speaking, to know the coordinate and mo-
mentum of the particle at every moment of time (in fact,
in order to depict the dependence x (t), it is necessary to
know, for every t, the values x and ~ ~ Since, according
to the uncertainty relation (3.3), a microparticle canllot
simultaneously possess a defmite coordinate and a definite
projection of the momentum, one can draw the conclusion
that the concept of trajectory in case of microparticle,
strictly speaking, is not applicable.
The rejection of the trajectory concept is connected with
the existence of wave properties in microparticles, which
do not permit one to consider microparticles as classical
corpUScles. The movement of a microparticle along the
x-axis cannot be associated with the differentiable func-
47
tion x (t) which is so widely used when considering
the mechanics of classical objects. From a known value
, of x of the microparticle at a certain time t, it is impossible
to predict the value of its coordinate at the time t +
+ dt.
As applied to Bohr's theory, this means a rejection of
the very concept of "the orbit of an electron in an atom".
One may speak about the localization of the electron
within the atom as a whole; the orbit requires a much
greater spatial localization. Turning to the problem of
"the electron falling into the nucleus" discussed above,
we can understand the consequence to which such a local-
ization leads. The planetary model of the atom thus
turns out to be just an intermediate step in development
of our concept of the atom. Much later, in the fifties,
Bohr himself amusingly recalled how after one of his
lectures a student came up and asked him "Were there
really idiots who thought that the electron revolves
in an orbit?"
We note that with the rejection of the idea of orbits of the electron
in an atom the contradiction regarding the problems of the in-
stantaneous jump of the electron from one orbit into another, dis--
cussed in Sec. 2, is automatically eliminated.
There are situations, however, in which one can make
use of the idea of "the trajectory of a microparticle". As an
example we consider the motion of electrons in the kine-
scope of a television set. The momentum of the electron
along the axis of the tube is p = V2meU, where U is
the accelerating voltage. The formation of the electron
beam means a definite localization of the coordinate in
the transverse direction. The degree of this localization
is characterized by the diameter d of the beam. According
to (3.3), there must be an uncertainty in the electron
momentum in a direction perpendicular to the axis of
the beam: !'J.p Md. As a result of this uncertainty, the
electron may deviate from the axis of the beam within
an angle !'J.8 !'J.p/p h/pd. Let L be the path length
of the electron in the kinescope. Then the uncertainty
in the position of the point of impingement of an electron
on the screen will be characterized by the quantity
!'J.x L!'J.8 Lli/pd. Assuming U = 20 kV, d = 10-
3
em,
L = 10
2
em, we get !'J.x 10-
5
cm. In this way, the
blurring of the point of impingement due to the uncertain-
ty relation is considerably less than the diameter of the
beam. It is clear that in such cases the motion of the
electron may be treated classically.
I Sec. 4
i l
I I
..J, .... "
The Possibility of a Microparticie
Sub-Barrier Passage (Tunneling
Effect)
48
I
I
I
I
I
: I
1......1--
Fig. 4.1
Suppose we have a potential barrier whose height U is
greater than the energy of the particle (Fig. 4.1). We
ask the question: can a particle, situated somewhere
to the left of the barrier, appear after some time to the
right of it, without getting any energy from outside?
Classical mechanics gives a negative answer-a classical
corpuscle cannot pass through the barrier. If this were
to happen, then the total energy of the particle, say,
at the point A in Fig. 4.1 would be less than its potential
energy, which is physically absurd.
Does this ban apply to microparticles as well? It can be
shown that it does not-it is removed by relation (3.2).
Let the microparticle move from infinity to the right
and encounter the potential barrier. Until this encounter
it was in a state of free motion for an infinitely long
time and hence its energy had a definite value. But now
the microparticle interacts with the barrier, or, more
precisely, with the objects which caused the appearance
of the barrier. Suppose the interaction lasts for a time M.
According to (3.2), the energy of the microparticle in
a state of interaction with the barrier is no longer definite
but is characterized by the uncertainty i1E:p Ii/ M.
If this uncertainty is of the order of the height U of the
barrier, the latter stops being an unsurmountable obstacle
for the microparticle. Thus the microparticle may pass
through the potential barrier. This specific quantum effect
is called the tunneling effect. It explains, in particular,
the a-decay of atomic nuclei. It should be noted that
when considering the tunneling effect, the motion of
the microparticle cannot be represented by the dotted
line in Fig. 4.1. The dotted line corresponds to the classic-
al trajectory, while a microparticle does not have a
trajectory. Hence there is no point in trying to
"accuse" the microparticle of having been "under the
potential barrier" at some moment of time.
It has been noted above that the energy of a freely moving micro-
particle is not quantized. This may be easily shown by making
use of the tunneling effect. Suppose a microparticle is located in
a potential well shown in Fig. 4.2. On account of the tunneling
,effect the microparticle may of its own accord leave the potential
well. Consequently, the time for which it stays in the well is not
infinite. If we denote this time as !':.t, it follows from (3.2) that
the energy of the microparticle must have an uncertainty of the
-order tz/ ""t. We reduce the width b of the potential barrier (dotted
line in Fig. 4.2). It is clear that as a result the magnitude of f':..t
will decrease, since the probability of the microparticle leaving
the well will increase. With a decrease in f'>.t, the uncertainty in
the energy of the microparticle, tz/!':.t, will increase. This may be
:Fig. 4.2
s
e
e
e
?
I
,
,
considered as a larger blurring (further broadening) of the energy
levels of the microparticle in the well. In the limiting case of zero
thickness of the barrier, the value of f.,t vanishes, the microparticle
becomes a freely moving particle, and the energy levels broaden up
indefinitely, actually transforming into a continuous energy
spectrum.
Section 5
r
Impossibility of Classical
Representation of a
Microparticle
The process of "breaking up" of objects surrounding us
into smaller and smaller "fractions" leads to micropar-
ticles. Therefore it is but natural to associate micro-
particles first of all with corpuscles. This is also support-
ed by the fact that a microparticle is characterized by
a definite rest mass and a definite charge. For instance,
it is meaningless to speak of a half-electron having half
the mass and half the electric charge of a whole electron.
The very terms "microparticle" and "elementary particle"
reflect the notion of the microparticle as being some
particle (corpuscle).
However, as follows from the preceding discussion, a
microparticle is considerably different from a classical
corpuscle. Firstly it does not have a trajectory which is
an essential attribute of a classical corpuscle. The use of
such corpuscular characteristics as coordinate, momentum,
angular momentum, energy when considering micropar-
ticles is restricted to the framework of the uncertainty
relations. Interconversion of microparticles, spontaneous
decays, the existence of an indestructible intrinsic mo-
ment (spin) and the ability to pass through potential
barriers indicate that microparticles are quite dissimilar
to classical corpuscles.
Wave concepts are radically different from corpuscular
concepts. Hence it is not surprising that the striking
contrast between classical corpuscles and microparticle
is explained by the existence of wave properties in the
latter. Moreover, it is the wave properties which account
for the uncertainty relations and all the consequences
resulting from them. In this respect, the following re-
mark by de Broglie [23] is worth noting: "for a century,
the corpuscular method of analysis in optics was too
much neglected in comparison with the wave method.
Hasn't the converse been the case in the theory of matter?
Haven't we thought too much of the "particle" picture
and neglected the wave aspect far too much?" The question
raised by de Broglie is fully justified. However, an excessive
Sec. .;
A Microparticle Is not a Classical
Corpuscle
49
I
~ _ . . I
A Microparticle Is not II
Classical Wave
Example 1
Example 2
exaggeration of the wave aspect while considering
microparticles should be avoided. We must remember
that while on one hand a microparticle is not a classical
corpuscle, it is similarly, on the other hand, not a classi-
cal wave.
The analysis of one mistake which is committed quite
often even these days when considering a simplified
account of quantum mechanics is quite instructive.
We shall demonstrate this mistake through two examples.
It is contended that the wave properties of an electron
permit one to derive the conditions for the quantization
of momentum which are postulated in Bohr's theory.
The "derivation" is done in the following way. Let 2:n:r
n
be the perimeter of the n-th Bohr's orbit. In this orbit,
an electron moves with de Broglie's wavelength An =
= 2:n:1i/Pn' The basic assumption lies in the fact that
the perimeter of the orbit should contain n wavelengths
An of the electron. Consequently, 2:n:r
n
= nAn' This
at once gives the desired condition for quantization
of momentum:
(5.1)
It is stated that the wave properties of an electron
permit a very simple derivation of the formula for the
energy levels in a potential well, if we assume that a
definite number of de Broglie half-waves are confined
in the potential well (in analogy with the number of
half-waves contained in the length of a string fixed at
both ends) corresponding to different stationary states.
Designating the width of the one-dimensional poten-
tial well by a, we write a = n
An
l2, from which we get
the desired result:
(5.2)
50
Both these final results [(5.1) as well as (5.2)] are
correct; they are the same as the result deduced from
strict theory. However, the "derivation" of these formulas
must be considered to be unsound. In both cases in
fact the same fundamental mistake has been committed:
they are based on the wrong assumption that the electron
in a potential well has a definite de Broglie wavelength,
or, in other words, a definite momentum. However,
according to (3.3), the momentum of a microparticle
in a bound state is characterized by the uncertainty
!1p ;:r Ma. Since in the above examples p li/').. Ma,
it follows that the momentum is of the same order of
magnitude as the uncertainty in momentum given by
AHempts to Represent a
Microparlicle as a Symbiosis of a
Corpuscle and a Wave
I'
I relation (3.3). It is clear that in such cases one cannot
speak about any value of the electron momentum (and
correspondingly of its de Broglie wavelength) even ap-
proximately. * These examples demonstrate an obvious
exaggeration of the wave aspect. The identification of
an electron in a potential well with a classical wave
inside a "resonator" is incorrect. The picture of an electron
wave in a "resonator" is the same kind of simplification
as the picture of an electron-ball moving in a classical
orbit. We shall return again to the question of waves
in quantum mechanics; however, it is useful to emphasize
at this stage that by the term "de Broglie wave" we
do not conceal any sort of classical wave. It is just a
reflection in our imagination of the fact that microparti-
cles possess wave properties.
If a microparticle is neither a corpuscle nor a wave,
then may be it is some kind of a symbiosis of a corpuscle
and a wave? Several attempts were made to model such
a symbiosis and thus also to visually demonstrate the
wave-particle duality. One such attempt represents a
microparticle as a formation, limited in space and in
time. This may be the wave packet mentioned in Sec 3.
This may also be just a "scarp" of a wave, often called
a wave train. Another attempt uses a model of a pilot-
wave, according to which a microparticle is some sort
of a "compound" of a corpuscular "core" with a certain
wave which controls the motion of the core.
One of the versions of the pilot wave model is considered by
D. Baum in his book [25]: We first postulate that connected with
each of the "fundamental" particles of physics (e.g. an electron) is a body
existing in a small region of space.... in most applications at the
atomic level the body can be approximated as a mathematical point..
The next step is to assume that associated with this body there is a
wave without which the body is never found. This wave will be assumed
to be an oscillation in a new kind of field, which is represented mathe-
matically by the ,p-field of Schrodinger ... somewhat like the gravita-
tional and the electromagnetic, but having some new characteristics
of its own....
We now assume that the ,p-field and the "body" are interconnected in
the sense that the ,p-jield exerts a new kind of "quantum-mechanical"
force on the body, ... the force is such as to produce a tendency to pull
the body into regions where I ,p I is largest.
If the above tendency were all that were present, the body would even-
tually find itself at the place where the ,p-field had the highest intensity.
We now further assume that this tendency is resisted by random motions
... This question is considered in greater detail in Sec. 23 of this
book. See also [24].
i!
i
i':'
Sec. 5
51
undergone by the body, motions which are analogous to the Brownian
movement ... They could, for example, come from random fluctuations
in the itself. .. ,
Once admitting the existence of these fluctuations, we then see that
they will produce a tendency for the body to wander in a more or less
random way over the whole space accessible to it. But this tendency is
opposed by the "quantum force" which pulls the body into the places
where the is most intense. The net result will be to produce a
mean distribution in a statistical ensemble of bodies, which favours
the regions, where the 1,jJ-field is most intense ....
Figure 5.1 illustrates We given model as applied to the passage
of a microparticle through the screen with slits: the is diff-
racted on bothithe slits, while the "body" passes through one slit
and is registered on the screen in accordance with the result of the
interference of
l:
It
Fig. 5.1
How to Understand the
Wave-Particle DUlIlityl
It is not denied that such models could appear attrac-
tive at first glance if only because of their intuitive
appeal. It must be emphasized at once, however, that
all these models are baseless. We shall not explain at
this stage the reasons for. worthlessness of the pilot-
wave model considered above, but shall just mention
that it is cumbersome since it uses artificial notions
such as the 'llJ-field which is "to some extent similar
to gravitational end electromagnetic fields", or the
"quantum force" which reflects the interaction of certain
"object" with the 'IjJ-field. The reader will later realize
that the worthlessness of such models is not because
of some specific feature, but because of deep fundamental
reasons. He will understand that any attempt at a literal
interpretation of the wave-particle duality, any attempt
to model a symbiosis of corpuscle and a wave, should
be considered fruitless from the very start. A
particle is not a symbiosis of a corpuscle anda-wave.
At present the wave-particle duality is considered as
the potential ability of a microparilcle to exhibit its
different properties depending on external conditions,
in particular, on the conditions of observation. As Fock
[1] wrote, Thus under certain an atomic object
may exhibit wave properties and under other conditions
corpuscular properties; conditions are when
both kinds of appear but not
sharply. We can state that it is potentially for
an atomic object to either ail a wave or as
. a particle or in an intermediate fashion, according to the
external condition prevailing. It is this potential
of exhibiting various properties inherent in an
dtomic object that constitutes the wave-corpuilcular duality.
Any other, more literal meaning attached to this duality,
ac-
lve
lat
at
ot-
:on
ms
lar
;he
lin
ize
Ise
tal
ral
lpt
lId
ro-
ve.
as
its
ns,
lck
ect
~
zen
not
for
as
the
'08-
an
ty.
ty,
'T
I
such as a wave-particle model of any kind, is incorrect.
Let us consider a simple example. Let a beam of electrons
pass through a screen with slits and then hit a detector
screen. While passing through the slits, the electrons
realize their wave properties which leads to a distribution
for electrons beyond the slit characteristic of interference.
When impinging on the detector screen, the electrons
exhibit their corpuscular properties-each of them is
registered at a certain point on the screen. It m.ay be
said that the electron passes through the slit as a "wave",
and is registered on the detector screen as a "particle".
In this connection, it is sometimes said that a micro-
particle is a wave under some circumstances, and a micro-
particle is a particle under other circumstances. Such
a treatment of wave-particle duality is incorrect.0Vhat-
ever the conditions, a microparticle is neither a wave,
nor a particle, "not even a symbiosis of a wave and a
particle. It is a quite specific object, capable of exhibiting
corpuscular or wave properties to some extent or other
depending on the circumstances. The understanding of
wave-particle duality as the potential capability of the
microparticle to exhibit different properties in different
external conditions is the only correct one. Hence, in
particular, follows an important conclusion: it is impos-
sible to give a definite visual model of a microparticle.
The absence of a visual model of a microparticle does
not in any way prevent us from using tentative models
quite suitable for representing a microparticle under
different conditions. As an example, let us consider an
electron in an atom.
We recall that the state of an electron in an
atom is described by a set of quantum numbers
n, l, m, cr. A given state is characterized by a definite
energy, while in the particular case of the hydrogen
atom, it depends only on the number n [see (2.7)), and
in a more general case on the numbers nand l. An electron
in an atom isdelocalized in space-its coordinates have
an uncertainty of the order of the size of the atom. Usual-
ly, when considering an electron in an atom, it is custom-
ary to introduce the concept of an electron cloud which
may be interpreted in this case as a tentative image
of the electron. The form and the effective size of an
electron cloud depend on the quantum numbers n, l,
m and, consequently, vary from one state of the electron
in the atom to another.
In order to describe the dimensions and the form of
the electron cloud, we introduce a certain function
u
n1m
(r, 8, Ip) = Unl (r) Zlm (8, Ip), (5.3)
Electron in an Atom
,
I
''f
I
:j
J.se.
c
,.5
5
3
....
1
(I;
Fig. 5.2
where r, e, cp are the spherical coordinates of the electron.
The function Unl
m
is interpreted in the following way:
Unl
m
(r, e, cp) dV is the probability of finding an electron
in a state with quantum numbers n, l, m in an element
of volume dV in the vicinity of point (r, e, cp). In other
f) 1
54
/"""
I \
l ~ o
\
\
\
words, Un 1m (r, e, cp) is the corre;ponding probability
density of finding the electron. Remember that dV =
= r
2
drdQ, where dQ = sin ededcp is the element of solid
ngle. The function
Wnl (r) dr = Unl (r) r
2
dr (5.3a)
is thus the probability of finding the electron with quan-
tum numbers n, l at a distance between rand r + dr
from the nucleus.
In Fig. 5.2a are shown forms of functions Wnl (r) for
different states of the electron in a hydrogen atom.
Notice that the functions WIO, W21' W
32
have maxima
corresponding to the radii of first, second and third
orbits in Bohr's theory. Figure 5.2b shows forms of
Section 6
m.
ly:
'on
mt
ler
:ity
lid
3a)
an-
dr
for
1m.
ma
ird
of
, function Zim fo, some states of the electron. Fo' I 0
., (for the so-called s-electron) we have a spherical electron
cloud. For l = 1 (for p-electron) the electron cloud
has a form of either a spindle or a toroid depending on
the quantum number m. Thus in order to imagine an
electron in atom, one may use conventional forms like
the models of a sphere, spindle, toroid, etc. ,
The ground state of the hydrogen atom is characterized
by a spherical electron cloud. Theory shows (see, for
example, [11]) that in this case
(5.4)
r
1
r
1
The parameter r
1
characterizing the effective radius
of the cloud is determined by relation (4.4); in Bohr's
theory it occurs as the radius of the first orbit.
In conclusion w/iJ note that during quantumtransitions in an
atom, there occurs not only a change in energy, but
also a "redistribution" of electron clouds-a change of
their shape and size.
Rejection of Ideas of
Classical Physics
As has been asserted, a transition from macrophenom-
ena to microphenomena presupposes a rejection of the
basic ideas of classical physics. The notion of a strict
continuity in the spectrum of values of physical quanti-
ties is no longer valid, the classical concept of a tra-
jectory is rejected, the principle of classical determinism
is in question. At the root of this viewpoint lie ideas of
quantization (discreteness) and wave-particle duality
which are alien to classical physics.
On the basis of a number of examples that we have consid-
ered, we could see the need to reject the classical principle
of unlimited detailing of objects in space, and of phenom-
ena in time. Thus the question of the internal structure of
elementary particles turns out to be groundless. Like-
wise the efforts towards a detailed development in time
of the process of the quantum jump (quantum transition)
have no meaning.
The concepts of energy. momentum, angular momentum
which are widely used in classical physics are carried over
to quantum mechanics as well. However, these concepts are
nowseen differently with a reconsideration of the previous
interconnections, takinginto account the possibilityof quan-
tization, and the limitations imposed by the uncertainty
Sec. 6
General Remarks
55
,
J
relations. In particular, there arises the question, unknown
to classical physics, of the simultaneous measurement of
physical quantities, and questions about the state and the
methods of describing a state are put in a new light.
In conclusion we stress the impossibility of the classical
interpretation of a microparticle, and the loss of the
clarity of classical physics.
Identity of Microparticles The rejection of the classical individualization of an
object is quite fundamental. In classical mechanics ob-
jects are known to have individuality since it is always
possible in principle to enumerate them and observe
the behaviour of anyone of them. In this case, how-
ever alike two classical objects may be, they are never
identical and can always be distinguished. But in quantum
mechanics two microparticles of the same type should
be treated as absolutely identical. Thus, all electrons
are identical and so are all unexcited hydrogen atoms,
helium nuclei, etc.
Suppose we have several electrons, one of which is "assigned" the
number 1 at the moment of time t = O. Can this electron be identi-
fied after a certain time t? Such an identification could have been
easily done if we could put some "label" on this isolated object.
We could get by without "labelling" this electron if we could sim-
ply keep a watch over the isolated object, i.e. if we could "mentally"
follow it (in our imagination) along its trajectory. This is precisely
what we would have done in the case of isolated classical objects.
However, none of this holds in the case of an electron; it is in
principle impossible to "label" it. Strictly speaking, it has no
trajectory. The electron "isolated" by us at the instant t = 0, cannot
be isolated in actual practice: it does not have the individuality
which would allow it to be identified in the assembly of electrons
after a certain time t. Two electrons are much more "like each
other" than the proverbial "two peas in a poll"; sinctl the latter
are classical objects, they could differ in size or in chemic'll com-
position in some way.
Chance and Necessity in the
Behaviour of a Microparticle
56
It is understood that the identity of microparticles does
not exclude the possibility of their differentiation on
the basis of different states in which these particles
may be found. Two electrons belonging to two different
atoms are, of course, identical but at the same time
distinguishable. The affiliation of an electron to one
atom or another permits its "isolation". However, nothing
changes physically if the electrons interchange places.
It is clear that if such an exchange is possible, for example,
by combining the atoms under consideration into a
molecule, the distinguishability of the electrons vanishes.
LaplaCian determinism excludes the element of chance
from the behaviour of an isolated object; in classical
lS
n
lS
It
e
e
g
;,
.
"
J
a
;.
e
I
n
)-
is
'e
r-
lr
n
d
IS
3,
mechanics, necessity completely dominates. Because of
this, the laws of classical mechanics are dynamic and
not statistical. The element of chance (and, consequently,
statistical laws also) appear in classical physics only
when considering aggregates of objects or assemblies of
particles.
From this point of view, it is important to stress that
in quantum mechanics we are dealing with a qualita-
tively different situation concerning the behaviour of
individual microparticles: here, elements of necessity,
as well as chance, are present. An excited atom spon-
taneously returns to the ground state without any ex-
ternal influence. This is associated with the spontaneous
transitions of electrons in the atom from one set of energy
levels to another. It is impossible in principle to indicate
precisely when a particular excited atom will return
to its ground state; such a return is a random act.
Precisely in the same way, it is impossihle to predict exactly
when a given elementary particle, for example, a neutron,
will decay spontaneously. In this case also an element
I 0If chance is present.
1,',1,. n addition to elements of chance, there are also pres-
t ent the elements of necessity in the behaviour of a
i( microparticle. As has already been indicated in Sec. 1,
if we have No neutrons at the instant t = 0, No:?> 1,
we can confidently state that at the time t we will be
left with only No exp (-th:) neutrons, being a constant
called the lifetime of the neutron. Here, the necessity
is obvious. In the case of an individual neutron this
necessity is replaced by a definite probability of keeping
the neutron intact until time t, once it has managed
to survive to time t = O. This probability is equal
to exp (-tl.). It should be noted that this probability
is independent of the time for which the given neutron
has survived up to the time t = O. Necessity is also
manifested in the conservation laws which govern decay
processes as well as the processes of interconversion of
microparticles in general. We may also mention the fact
that there are definite modes of decay; for example,
a free neutron may decay into a proton, an electron and
an electronic neutrino.
The existence of chance as well as necessity in the be-
haviour of an individual microparticle has very im-
portant consequences. It leads to the fact that quantum
mechanics turns out to be in principle a statistical theory
with probability as one of its basic attributes. As Fock
[1] has remarked, in quantum physics the concept of prob-
ability is a primary concept and plays a fundamental
J.s.ec.'.6 .57__
1,1
~
f
r
I,
t
Virtual Transitions and Virtual
Microparticles
'S8
role. It could be said that the behaviour of an individual
microparticle is random, but the probability of this
behaviour is necessary*. The electronic cloud considered
in Sec. 5 may serve as a good example of this. The oc-
currence of an electron at some point near the nucleus
is a random event, but the probability of its being found
at a given point (r, e, <p) is definite-it is described by
a function of the type (5.3) or, in other words, is deter-
mined by the shape and size of the corresponding electron
cloud.
In the end, we note that the element of chance in the
behaviour of an individual microparticle is due to the
uncertainty relations. In Sec. 4, we concluded on the
basis of relation (3.3) that it is impossible to "aim a
microparticle to hit a given point". In other words, the
registration of a particular electron at some point of
a detector screen is random; we can only speak of the
probability of such a fact. In Sec. 3, we introduced
on the basis of relation (3.2) the concept of the virtual
transitions of a microparticle. It is easy to see that such
transitions also point, towards the existence of randomness
in the behaviour of a microparticle. When discussing
the specific nature of the physics of microparticles, it
is necessary to discuss in greater detail the idea of virtual
transitions and of virtual microparticles associated with
them.
Perhaps there is nothing more alien to classical physics
than the idea of virtual transitions and virtual micro-
particles. The virtual transition of an electron from level
E
2
to level E
1
and back (the transition E
2
-+ E
1
+ E
2
)
may be considered as a process in which the electron
emits and absorbs a photon of energy (E
2
- E
1
). Such
a photon is called virtual. In contrast to the photons
participating in real transitions, virtual photons cannot
be observed experimentally. The creatioh of a virtual
photon is not connected with an absorption of energy
from outside, and its annihilation is not connected with
a release of energy. The law of conservation of energy
is not violated since a virtual photon exists for a very
short time I'J.t and, according to uncertainty relation
(3.2), the energy of an electron emitting the virtual
photon is characterized by the uncertainty I'J.E > iiI I'J.t,
which may be of the order of, or greater than, the energy
of the photon (E
2
- E
t
). The emission or absorption
by an electron of virtual photons corresponds, from a
* Here, it is quite appropriate to recall the words of F. Engels:
Necessity emerges from within the framework of randomness.
1
t..... :. [1
~
~
~
M1------<
Fig. 6.1
I
".
z
.1
rei)
((;
physical point of view, to the process in which an electron
undergoes virtual transitions.
Taking into consideration the emission and absorption
of virtual photons by an electron, one may imagine
that each electron is surrounded by a photon cloud.
This "cloud" should be compared with the electron's
own electromagnetic field. Two electrons may exchange
virtual photons. In quantum field theory, the interaction
of electrons is seen as a result of the exchange of virtual
photons between electrons. For this we frequently make
use of Feynman's diagrams, which enable us to consider
the various processes of photon exchange.
Figure 6.1 shows four Feynman's diagrams demonstrating
the scattering of one electron by another. The solid
lines "show" electrons and the dotted one-photons.
The intersections of solid and dotted lines are called
the vertices Qf the diagram. Let us consider the diagram
(a). Here 1 and 2 are the electrons before interaction
with each other (before scattering), AB is a virtual
photon which is exchanged by the electrons during the
process of interaction (note that all the particles indicated
in the diagram by lines connecting two vertices are
virtual); 3 and 4 are the electrons after scattering. Let
us turn to the diagram (b). Here 1 and 2 are electrons
before scattering, AB and CD are virtual photons ex-
changed by the electrons, 3 and 4 are virtual electrons,
5 and 6 are electrons after scattering. The diagram
(c) is of the same type as diagram (b); here the electrons
exchange two photons. The diagram (d) shows one of
the processes in which the electrons exchange three
photons. It is obvious that there is an infinite number
of such diagrams which become more and more complicated
(with the participation of more and more photons).
In order to calculate the probability of scattering of
an electron by an electron, one must consider in principle
the contribution of the various processes indicated by
the various diagrams. Fortunately, the contribution of
different processes is different: it is less if the number
of vertices is greater (Le. if more virtual photons take
part in a process). Theory shows that this contribution
is quantitatively determined by the dimensionless quanti-
ty (e
2
/tw)n/
2
, where e is the charge of the electron, c is
the velocity of light, Ii is Planck's constant and n is
the number of vertices in the diagram. Since e
2
/nc =
= 1/137, it followS that the main contribution to the
scattering of one electron by another must come from
the diagram (a) with two vertices (exchange of one pho-
ton). The four vertices diagrams (b) and (c) (exchange
Ii
)'
I'
I
,I
't
"
I
I
Sec. 6
S9
Fig. 6.2
~
The Microparticle and Its
Surroundings
60
of two photons) should provide the next approximation;
their contribution will be two orders of magnitude lower.
Thus, in actual practice there is no need to consider
a very large number of diagrams, it is sufficient to limit
ourselves to diagrams with a relatively small number
of vertices.
Of course, a systematic study of Feynman's diagrams and
calculations based on them is beyond the scope of this
book. These questions are related not to quantum mechan-
ics, but to quantumfield theory (quantum electrodynamics)*.
However, a general introduction to the ideas forming
the bases of Feynman's diagrams is quite appropriate
at this point, since they permit us to emphasize the
specific nature of the physics of microparticles and also
demonstrate some fundamental quantum-mechanical prin-
ciples (the latter will be considered below, in particular,
in Sec. 25).
Before ending this discussion on Feynman's diagrams,
we consider the so-called effect of polarization of a vacuum.
Figure 6.2 shows a diagram describing one of the proces-
ses responsible for this effect. A photon is transformed
into a virtual electron-positron pair, which is annihilat-
ed and transformed again into a photon (one of the
solid lines between the vertices of the diagram "shows"
a virtual electron, and the other, a virtual positron).
The members of this pair during their lifetime may
obviously generate virtual photons and, consequently,
new virtual electron-positron pairs, and so on. As a
result of this, the vaeuum turns out to be not "empty"
but "fIlled" with virtual electric charges which must
exercise a screening effect on external (real) charges.
Experimental confirmation of this effect is the best
evidence of the usefulness of our concept of virtual
particles.
As we have already mentioned, the existence of the
element of chance in the behaviour of a microparticle
is one of its most specific properties. As a result of this,
quantum mechanics turns out in principle to be a sta-
tistical theory operating with probabilities. But what
is the reason for the existence of an element of chance
in the behaviour of a microparticle?
This question can be answered as follows: The existence
of chance in microphenomena is explained by the fact
that a microparticle, figuratively speaking, interacts
with all its surroundings. The specific nature of quantum
* A simple and detailed account of Feynman's diagrams is given,
for example, in [26].
mechanics is such that, strictly speaking, not a single
object in it can be considered to be fully isolated, com-
pletely independent of its surroundings. It has been
remarked [27] that the cause of the statistical nature
of quantum mechanics is the same as in classical statis-
tical mechanics, i.e. the existence of a large number
of bonds affecting the motion of the object. A particle
treated as free in quantum mechanics is in fact free
only from influences of a dynamic nature. But it remains
under the influence of random forces which cause quantum
fluctuations in its behaviour, as reflected by the uncertain-
ty relation.
What is the nature of the random influences on a micro-
particle? In quantum fIeld theory, it manifests itself
in an explicit form as the interaction of a microparticle
with a vacuum (recall that a vacuum is not "empty";
it is "filled" ,with virtual charges). It may be said that
a microparticle interacts with its surroundings through
virtual microparticles.
The reader should now find it quite natural to inter-
pret wave-particle duality as the potential ability of
a microparticle to exhibit one kind of property or another,
depending on the external conditions, i.e. on the micro-
particle's surroundings. This envisages a close connection
between the microparticle and its surroundings-in fact,
the very nature of a microparticle is displayed in one
form or another depending on specific conditions and
circumstances.
The impossibility of an unlimited detailization of ob-
jects and phenomena being displayed in quantum me-
chanics should also be explained by the interaction
of a microparticle with its surroundings. This means
that after a certain stage of investigation, physical
objects cannot be considered as being isolated. Here
it is appropriate to recall the statement given in Sec. 3
regarding the discussion on quantum transition: "During
the interaction of an electron with photons there is,
strictly speaking, no electron and no photon but a single
entity which must be considered as such without going
into details."
Quantum mechanics re-establishes the idea acquired
through everyday experience regarding the unity of the
universe and general connections among phenomena.
This idea received a setback in the classical theory.
The sharp boundaries that existed between waves and
particles, particles and fields, object under investigation
and the medium are all obliterated and the concept
of the interconversion of matter is introduced. We fwd
Sec. 6 61
I!
\ I
I!
ourselves in full agreement with the following appro-
priate remark made by Bohm [281: It seems necessary
to give up the idea that the world can correctly be analysed
into distinct parts, and to replace it with the assumption
that the entire universe is basically a single, indivisible
unit. Only in the classical limit can the description in
terms of component parts be correctly applied without
reservations. Wherever quantum phenomena play a signifi-
cant role, we shall find that the apparent parts can change
in a fundamental way with the passage of time, because
of the underlying indivisible connections between them.
Thus, we are led to picture the world as an indivisible,
but flexible and everchanging, unit.
Interlude. Is a "Physically
Intuitive" Model of a
Microparticle Possible?
Participants: (same as in
Prelude).
It may well be that these electrons
Are worlds just like our very own,
With kings and scholars, arts and armies,
A nd memories of ages flown.
And atoms-cosmic systems, spinning
Around a central spinning sphere.
Where things are just like ours, but smaller,
Or nothing like what we have here.
Bryusov (The World of the Electron)
Interlude
A uthor: The impossibility of the classical interpretation of a micro-
particle predetermines a negative answer to the question "Is it
possible to have a "physically intuitive" model for a microparticle?"
Classical Physicist: It is still not clear why a "physically intuitive" model[ of a
particle explaining its various properties including spin, insta-
bility, wave properties, etc. cannot be created. Such a model may
turn out to be complicated. Or, it may be possible that we still
do not know enough about a microparticle to create such a model.
But why can't we believe in the very possibility ~ this model?
A uthor: There are very sound reasons for this. I shall indicate just
two of them. Firstly, any modelling envisages in the long run a
detailization irrespective of whether it is a model of an object
or a process. However, the impossibility of an unlimited detailiza-
tion is characteristic of microparticles and microphenomena, as
we have already mentioned. This important situation was persis-
tently stressed by Bohr. He wrote, in particular (see his article
Quantum Physics and Philosophy-[6]): A new epoch in physical
science was inaugurated, however, by Planck's discovery of the ele-
mentary quantum of action, which revealed a feature of wholeness
inherent in atomic divisibility of mdtter. Indeed, it became clear that
the pictorial description of classical physical theories represents an
idealization valid only for phenomena in the analysis of which all
actions involved are sufficiently large to permit the neglect of the
quantum.... It is appropriate to mention here that this feature
of wholeness indicated by Bohr is closely linked with the identity
of a microparticle. Secondly, as we have already indicated, a char-
acteristic property of microparticles is their inavoidable inter-
action with surroundings leading, in particular, to a dependence
of some of the properties of microparticle on definite external
circumstances. These properties should be treated as certain pos-
sibilities which can be realized depending on the external circum-
stances. One may ask, in what way can these possibilities be re-
flected in the framework of a definite "physically intuitive" model?
Classical Physicist: It must be admitted that these ideas serve as strong arguments
against a "physically intuitive" model of a microparticle. However,
I don't like the very spirit of quantum mechanics which rejects
graphic representations. In my view it introduces subjectiveness
in describing real world. Take, for example, the statement: "The
63
,
I
II'
64
electron may present itself as a wave or as a particle, depending
on circumstances". Now, everything depends on circumstances,
especially on the circumstances of observation. Involuntarily, one
gets the idea that the electron is not something objective, but
rather something subjective depending on how we "look" at it.
A uthor: Of course, this is not true. First of all, you overlook the fact
that the electron has quite definite characteristics like rest mass,
electric charge, spin, etc. It is stable and is a fermion. As regards
a "physically intuitive" model of an electron, well, it simply does
not exist. However, in rejecting a "physically intuitive" model
of a microparticle, quantum mechanics in no way sacrifices objec-
tivity in favour of subjectivity. It is just that the electron is a
very complicated physical object, and depending on the external
circumstances, including circumstances of observation, it exhibits
its different aspects, which objectively existed in potential form
(I stress this) even before the observer was born. A sober assessment
of this complex situation is that a "physically intuitive" model
of the electron is not possible.
Classical Physicist: Can one seriously speak about an object without having an
idea of what it looks like? Isn't it strange that we study, for example,
the behaviour of an electron in a crystal while we don't even know
what an electron actually is?
Author: I don't agree that we don't even know what an electron is.
I have just indicated a number of precisely determined characteris-
tics and properties of an electron. More detailed properties of micro-
particles in general and electrons in particular were considered in
the preceding sections of the book (and will be considered in the
following sections). In fact, we know quite a lot about the electron
and know, in particular, about its behaviour in a crystal. This is
evidenced by the large number of semiconducting devices fabricated
and used by us in practice. As you will see, the absence of a "physi-
cally intuitive" model of the electron has in no way turned out
to be a serious obstacle. We may even go a step further and state
that an understanding of natural phenomena in which Planck's
constant plays an important role is possible ~ y through a signif-
icant rejection of a graphic description. By the way, this idea
was given by Heisenberg, in whose works much attention was given
to questions of the use of physically intuitive methods.
Classical Physicist: But by rejecting models, isn't quantum mechanics running
the risk of losing its material basis? Won't we be finally left
with only equations and abstract mathematical symbols?
A uthor: I can understand your doubts. For you, apparently, only the
extremes matter: either graphic models, or mathematical abstrac-
tion. To you, either a model should reflect everything or almost
everything, otherwise it is quite useless. The doubts arising in
your mind' are a consequence of precisely this type of viewpoint.
However, the quantum-mechanical approach to such questions is
mOTe flexible, or rather, dialectical.
19
s,
le
lt
ct
s,
js
es
el
c-
a
al
ts
m
rlt
el
III
e,
IW
s.
s-
o-
in
ile
m
is
Old
;i-
ut
te
it
: s
[f-
ea
,I
en
rlg
II
lft
II
ile
c-
,st
in
It.
is
Classical Physicist:
Author:
Classical Physicist:
Author:
Classical Physicist:
Author:
Classical Physicist:
Author:
I don't understand what exactly you mean by that.
I want to stress two points. Firstly, although there is no "phys-
ically intuitive" model for a microparticle, this does not stand
in the way of the "model representations" in quantum mechanics.
That means I was right after all?
This is something different. Quantum mechanics believes that
even the most refined model cannot reflect the specific characteris-
tics of a microparticle. Hence quantum mechanics makes use of
tentative models (tentative images)-sometimes one, sometimes
another, admitting the relativity of every model. The only thing
that is important is that each of the models employed should reflect
some side of the nature of the object or phenomenon. Thus, when
considering electronic transitions through the forbidden band
in a semiconductor, we unhesitatingly imagine electrons as some
kind of corpuscles, which "jump" on the energy scale. When con-
sidering the propagation of electrons through an ideal crystal
lattice we use wave concepts. It is convenient to study the scattering
of electron waves by the elastic waves of a crystal in a "corpuscular
language", using the picture of collisions of corpuscles of two
types-electrons and phonons. Similarly, the image of the electron
cloud used for describing electrons in an atom also serves as a
good example of ~ t n t t i v modelling. As you see, modelling in
quantum mechanics is used quite extensively and flexibly. More-
over, all models are not interpreted literally but tentatively.
All right. And what is your second point?
The second point is as follows: Quantum mechanics makes use
of both tentative models and mathematical abstractions on an
equal footing. Just on equal footingI At this point modern physics
breaks off quite radically from classical concepts. Stressing the
great heuristic (and leading) significance acquired by mathematics
in the new physics, which was not the case earlier in the epoch of
the domination of "physically intuitive" concepts, Vavilov [29]
writes: we don't have enough accepted ideas and concepts for a physi-
cally intuitive model interpretation, but logic with its immense per-
spectives represented in mathematical form continues to be valid,
thereby creating order in the new, unexplored world and opening pos-
sibilities for physical predictions.
As a matter of fact, there is nothing definite in all this.;'
To be more precise, there is nothing predetermined beforehand.
The new physics turns to a study of theT objective world, if one
may say so, "without classical prejudices". It flexibly makes use
of different media: models and mathematical abstractions. Figu-
ratively speaking, it is not "alien to anything that is human".
Summing up, we may say that firstly, when studying microphe-
nomena, we do make use of visual models quite extensively. Se-
condly, models are by no means taken literally in quantum
mechanics; their relativeness and arbitrariness are considered.
Thirdly, getting acquainted with microphenomena is based on
the dialectic unity of model conceptI and TTUlthemattcal abstractions.
'.
I
I
.,.
~ "'1
Section 7.
Section 8.
Section 9.
Section 10.
Section 11.
Some Basic Experiments
Amplitudes of Transition Probabilities (Formulation
of Basic Principles)
Amplitudes of Transition Probabilities (Demonstra-
tion of Basic Principles)
Superposition of States
Measurement in Quantum Mechanics
! I
68 I
79 I
84
96
106
Interlude. Are These the Same Waves? Or, Again
on Waves in Quantum Mechanics 115
Section 12.
Section 13.
Section 14.
Section 15.
Section 16.
Causality in Quantum Mechanics
Microparticles with Two Basic States
The Electron in a Magnetic Field
The Wave Function
Quantum Mechanics as a Qualitative Leap in Man's
Knowledge of the Laws of Nature
Interlude. Do Quantum-Mechanical Concepts Con-
tradict Our Common Sense?
117
123
131
138
J
:i1
143
I'
f'
156 r I
i
Ohapter 2
68
Physical Foundations
of Quantum Mechanics
79 \
84
96
106
115
117
123
131 I'
\
138
143 I
156
Section 7
Some Basic Experiments
,.
Actual Experiments and the
System of Basic Experiments
The concepts of quantum mechanics are based on
a vast collection of experimental data gathered over
a period of more than fifty years at the end of the 19th
century and in the first half of the 20th century. Among
the large number of experiments, a few stand out as
being definite "milestones" and can hence be called deci-
sive. They include the experiments of Lummer and
Pringsheim on black body radiation coupled with Planck's
theoretical works (1900), the experiments of Frank and
Hertz (1914) on inelastic collision of electrons with
atoms, Millikan's experiments (1914) on the photoelectric
effect, confirming the laws predicted ealier by Einstein,
the experiments conducted by Stern and Gerlach (1921)
on the splitting of atomic beams in non-uniform mag-
netic fields, the measurements of wavelengths of X-rays
scattered by matter carried out by Compton (1923),
and the experiments of Davisson and Germer, and Tarta-
kovsky (1927) on electron diffraction*. These experiments
(and many others which did not become so famous)
constitute the foundation on which, over a number of
decades, quantum theory was built, perfected, freed
from various paradoxes, and finally brought to its
present harmonious structure.
Looking now from the position of the existing quantum
theory at the experimental quest which led to it, it
is worth generalizing the actual experimental picture
by omitting the details that do not play a significant
role and trying to conceive the simplest system of basic
experiments which describe the fundamental aspects of
the quantum-mechanical viewpoint. In this section an
attempt has been made to consider such a system of
experiments. This system is built on ,the basis of actual
experiments but one should not look for a one-to-one
correspondence between the basic experiments and actual
experiments conducted at a certain time in a certain
laboratory. Basic experiments must be seen as a sort
of generalization of several actual experiments. Hence,
the experimental details concerning a certain apparatus
or various details of a historical nature do not play
a significant role here.
In our view, resorting to the system of basic experiments
is motivated by two circumstances. Firstly, being free
* A description of these experiments may he found, for example.
in [30].
,
'f
Fig. 7.1
Experiment 1 (Microparticles in
an Interferometer)
t
. .: from the detail, of actual experimental re,earche' and
. their unavoidable "zigzags" and "deadends", such a
system of experiments permits one to isolate the main
events prominently, and clearly show the experimental
foundations of the theory. Secondly, quantum-mechani-
cal ideas have so radically changed our views on the
structure and properties of matter that it would not
be proper to draw final conclusions on the basis of par-
ticular individual experiments (even on "decisive" ex-
periments) but only on their totality. It is essential
to (onsider the totality of experiments as a whole, and
for this purpose it is useful to conceive a system of basic
experiments.
Let us begin by considering the well-known experiment
on the interference of light waves. Figure 7.1 schematically
the simplest interferometer. Here, 1 is a point
source of monochromatic light, 2 is a screen with two
small slits A and B, and 3 is a detector screen registering
the intensity of light impinging it. This intensity is
indicated on the diagram by the curve I(x). The inter-
ference character of the curve I (x) is fairly simply
explained within the framework of classical wave theory
of light: the light wave from source 1 upon reaching
the screen 2 converts the slits A and B into sources
of new light waves, which add up to give on screen 3
characteristic interference pattern of intensity distri-
bution.
We recall that the interference of light was observed
the middle of the 17th century by Grimaldi, and its
explanation on the basis of wave concepts was given
in the beginning of the 19th century by Young. Since
then, the experiment shown in Fig. 7.1 is called Young's
experiment.
One might ask what relation can the phenomenon of
the interference of light, discovered and explained long
ago, have with quantum mechanics? It turns out that
the two are directly related.
Let us gradually reduce the intensity of light from source
1. The illumination of screen 3 as a result will naturally
decrease. However, the interference character of the
curve I(x) will be retained. By increasing the time of
exposure, it is possible in principle to obtain the inter-
ference curve I(x) for even the smallest light intensities.
This is not trivial since with decreasing intensity of
the light beam the number of photons in it will decrease
I ,and so, obviously, a situation should arise when individ-
ual photons will have to be considered in place of
light waves. However, as has been shown experimentally,
e,
IS
ly
m
it
re
It
ic
of
Lll
of
al
1e
al
In
rt
yS
),
a-
ts
s)
of
ld
GS
0'-
:>
;h
Lg
lS
1-
ld
's
ld
;h
ic
1,
1)
sr
In
e.
69
-(
I
p
I
70
2
the natu'" 01 the interlerenee eueve lex) obvion'ly re-'lI:
mains unchanged no matter how much the light inten- ~ of 1
sity is decreased. The distribution of the individual scre
photons falling on the detector screen gives the same' dist
interference pattern on the screen as is produced by by
light waves. slit
Moreover, the interference is observed even if at point 1 By
(Fig. 7.1) we place a source of monochromatic electrons but
(all having the same energy). In this case also the in- the
tensity of the electron beam may be reduced indefinitely. was
We can even perform an experiment in which the electrons abll
pass through the interferometer one by one. By studying any
the distribution of the electrons falling on the detector dis1
screen over a sufficiently long exposul'e time we get in
in this case also the characteristic interference pattern doe
[curve I(x)l. Experiments repeated with other micro- slit
particles (protons, neutrons, etc.) lead to similar results. thu
From an observation of the behaviour of microparticles mu:
in the interferometer it should be concluded that, first- by
ly, the phenomenon of interference is inherent in all pas
microparticles and, secondly, it should be explained I1(J
by the properties not of en5embles of microparticles the
but of individual microparticles. reg
We shall try to "follow" the motion of an individual ing
microparticle (say, electron) in the interferometer shown to ;
in Fig. 7.1. The electron emerges from point 1, passes wit
through the slits in screen 2 and is finally registered sag
at a certain point x on screen 3. By repeating the ex- the
periment for a large number of single electrons we notice Ho
two fairly interesting facts. s n ~
The first fact is the impossibility of predicting pre- can
cisely at what point x a particular electron will be regis- we
teredo The experimental conditions are the same for each one
electron (remember that the electrons pass through the I all(
interferometer one by one) and yet each electron "behaves of
in its own way"; moreover, one cannot predict the way ass
in which it will behave. This remark applies to every (de
single electron. However, by following a large number slit
of electrons, we observe a pattern in the distribution on
of their incidence on the screen 3, shown by a kind of (WI
the interference curve I(x). Moreover it is immaterial "hE
whether we observe the distribution of the incidences thE
of a large number of single electrons or the distribution thI
of the incidences of electrons from a beam. Thus, the ob'
unpredictability concerning the behaviour of an indiv- Th
idual microparticle is associated with the predictability "hl
concerning the behaviour of a large number of micro- ow
objects. otl
5e
re-
ten-
iual
arne
by
rJ.t 1
rons
in-
ely.
rons
ying
ctor
get
tern
cro-
Ilts.
des
lrst-
all
lned
cles
iual
own
lsses
ered
ex-
ltice
pre-
19is-
the
aves
way
very
[lber
tion
d of
lrial
ficeS
tion
the
div-
ility
cro-
'The second lact is connected with the specilic nat",e
of the passage of an electron through the slits in the
screen. Let us close slit B; in this case we observe the
distribution of incidences on the screen, as described
by curve /l(X) (Fig. 7.2). Let us open slit B but close
slit A; in this case the distribution /2(X) is observed.
By opening both slits, we do not get the additive distri-
bution /l(X) + /2(X) described by the curve /3(X) in
the diagram but the interference distribution /(x) which
was noted earlier. It is this fact that is especially remark-
able. If we suppose that each electron passes through
anyone of the slits, the appearance of the interference
distribution /(x) forces us to admit that the electron
in some way "perceives" the other slit, otherwise, it
does not matter for an electron passing through one
slit whether the neighbouring slit is open or closed and
thus the distribution of incidences with both slits open
must be described not by the interference curve but
by the additive curve /3(X) = /l(X) + /2(X). The electrons
passing through slit A should give the distribution
1
1
(x), while those passing through slit B should give
distribution 12(x). The detector screen should then
the sum of these distributions. Since it is mean-
'Iingless to talk about the electron "perceiving" we have
admit that the interference distribution /(x) observed
both the slits open is associated with the pas-
; sage of the electron somehow simultaneously through
f the two slits.
ti However, this admission does not simplify matters
il since it is not clear exactly in what way a single electron
can pass simultaneously through two slits. Of course,
xwe may assume that the electron at first passes through
one slit, then it somehow returns through the other slit
and again passes through the first slit (we get a sort
of loop encompassing both the slits). Finally, we may
assume that near the slits the electron is "spread out"
(delocalized) in space, partially passing through one
slit and partially through the other, and while impinging
on the detector screen, it is again localized in space
(we get a temporary splitting of the electron into two
"halves"). There is no special need to prove that both
the attempts made above to model the passage of electron
through two holes are artificial. This becomes quite
obvious if we turn to more complicated interferometers.
Thus, in Michelson's interferometer, for example, one
"half" of the microparticle will have to move towards
one reflecting mirror and the other "half", towards the
other (in completely the opposite direction).
Sec. 7
Fig. 7.2
[(xl
\1\/
- --2
,4 13
71
Experiment 2 ("Observing" a
Microparticle in the
Interferometer)
Fig. 7.3
11
,f
"
, ,
\:1 72
Hf
Thus, the interference curve lex) greatly complicates
the problem about the nature of the passage of a micro-
particle through a screen with two slits. If the micro-
particle passes through one slit, then either there should
be no interference, or we must admit that the micro-
particle has a hidden ability to "perceive" the neigh-
bouring slit. The only logical conclusion arising from
the existence of interference is that the microparticle
passes simultaneously through two slits, though the
mechanism of such an unusual passage is not clear.
In such a situation, obviously, a direct experiment
could be helpful. Why shouldn't we try to "spy" on
the electron to see exactly in what wayan electron passes
through the slits in the screen? Such experiments were
actually conducted. Let us see what they led to.
Let us imagine that near the slits A and B of screen 2
we have light sources 4 and photodetectors 5 (Fig. 7.3),
designed for "observing" the passage of electron through
the screen with slits (the photodetectors register light
scattered by the electron). If the electron simultaneously
passes through both the slits both the photodetectors
are activated simultaneously. But if the electron passes
through either one of the slits, only one detector is activat-
ed; in this case we shall also know through which slit I
the given electron passes. '
So, we place an electron source at point 1, switch on
the light sources 4 and watch the photodetectors 5.
We shall assume that the electrons pass through the
apparatus one by one: the source emits an electron only
after the preceding one has reached the detector screen.
What does the experiment show? It always turns out
that only one photodetector (either left or right) is acti-
vated and both photodetectors are never activated
simultaneously. It means that the electron passes not
through two slits but only through .one. Moreover, we
can always indicate the slit through which any electron
passes.
The reader may surmise that to explain interference
we again have to start talking about an electron "per-
ceiving" the neighbouring slit by some secret means,
while passing through a slit. We shall not jump to con-
clusions but shall first carry out the experiment to the
end; we obtain a sufficiently large number of events
of electron incidence on the detector screen 3 and see
how they are distributed. Here, we get a surprise. On
screen 3 we get not the interference curve lex) but the
additive curve I sex).
We repeat the experiment after switching off the light
,
es
0-
O-
ld
0-
b.-
ill
I
Ie-
le-
I,
r.
It
m f
es
k
,
re-
l
2
),
~
It
ly
rs
~
t-
it
ill
) .
le-
y
1.
It
l-
d
.t
'e-
n
:e
r-
l,
l-
e'
.s
e-
n
e-
t
sources (thus depriving ourselves of the possibility of
"observing" the passage of the electrons through the
slits). In this case we again observe the interference
curve I(x).
The situation is such that interference occurs when light
sources are switched off and is absent when they are
switched on. As soon as we try to control the process
of passage of electrons through two open slits, the
interference disappears. In other words, our observation
of the behaviour of electrons near the slits destroys the
interference!
A change in the nature of the motion of electrons upon
the switching on of the light sources has a simple physical
explanation: this change is the result of collision of
photons with the electrons "being controlled". In the
process of measurement some influence on the object
under investigation is inevitable. Here only one thing
is important-can this influence be made sufficiently
small? Maybe the experiment considered above was
too crude? Maybe we should somehow try to observe
the electrons more delicately, so that the interference
picture is not destroyed by this.
But how to reduce the influence of a photon on an electron?
It is obvious that a reduction in the light intensity of
the sources would not yield anything-light intensity
is associated with the number of photons in a beam,
thus a reduction in the intensity will simply result
in an increase in the number of "unregistered" electrons.
We must reduce the energy of a single photon. But
for this we shall have to increase the wavelength of
the radiation and this will lead to an increase in the
spatial delocalization of the photon (a photon is local-
ized in space with an accuracy not exceedingffiwaveIength)
and thus for a wavelength exceeding the distance between
the slits the photon will no longer be in a position to
register a particular slit.
But, may be, we could think of some other experiment-
without resorting to the scattering of photons by elec-
trons? For example, isn't it possible to try to construct
an extremely light screen with slits in such away, that
it could move to the left or right upon being struck by
individual electrons? The screen deflects to the left if
an electron passes through the left slit and to the right
if it passes through the right slit (Fig. 7.4). But if the
electron passes through two slits simultaneously, the
screen will not move at all. Thus, we just have to follow
the movement of the screen. It would appear that at least
in principle the aim has been achieved-the required
Sec. 7
Fig. 7.4
I
,
\
73
1
I
I
. I
, I
,1,1.
II ~
'\
I.
I
delicate experiment has been conceived. But it is mean-
ingless to set up such an experiment. To make sure that
this is so, we recall the uncertainty relation for momen-
tum and coordinate. It follows from this relation that
if the experimental conditions really permit us to register-
the momentum of the screen due to a recoil from the elec-
tron impingement, the same condition must lead to an "-
uncertainty in the position of the screen on the line 00
(Fig. 7.4). Consequently, the shift in such a screen does
not permit one to draw any conclusion on the nature of
passage of an electron through the slits. If, on the other
hand, we fix the position of the screen on the line 00,
then it is easy to see that a measurement of the momen-
tum of its recoil will become impossible.
Several attempts were made to devise such an experiment
in which the passage of electrons through a screen with
slits could be "controlled" without seriously influencing
the electrons themselves (so that the interference is not
destroyed). But all these attempts proved futile. As a
result, we must admit that the above conclusion regarding
the destruction of interference caused by observing the
behaviour of electrons near the slit, is of a fundamental
nature. In other words, the effect of observation (measure-
ment) destroying interference cannot be eliminated in
principle.
Author:
Reader:
Reader:
Reader:
Author:
Author:
Author:
Reader:
He was going into one room
And by mistake entered another...
Griboiedoff (Gore ot Ouma)
This means we were not able to determine exactly how an
electron passes through a screen with slits-through one slit or
simultaneously through both the slits?
Indeed, we couldn't.
But then experiment 2 did not attain its goal. Was it necessary
to consider it?
Yes, it was. The experiment did not answer the question posed
by us. So what? It just means that the question was not formulated
properly. We see that we cannot question all the phenomena of
nature.
Does the whole idea of the experiment lie in its negative result?
This is not to be ignored. However, as we shall see later, it
also contains a positive result of utmost importance. In fact, we
were looking for one thing, but we found another.
And what is that?
Let us not make haste. We shall first consider our system 8
fundamental experiments to the end.
'jLet us pass a beam of light through a polarizer, say, Experiment 3 (Passage of Photons
a tourmaline crystal. A linearly polarized light beam Through Polarizers)
emerges from the crystal. The direction of polarization of
the beam is determined by the orientation of the polarizer
with respect to the beam (the direction of polarization
coincides with the direction of the axis of the polarizer).
Let us denote the intensity of the linearly polarized light
beam through f.
Further, we place a second polarizer in the path of the
linearly polarized light beam and consider the following
three cases: (a) the axis of the second polarizer is parallel
to the axis of the first; (b) the axis of the second polarizer
is perpendicular to the axis of the first; (c) the axis of
the second polarizer makes an angle a with the axis of the
first. We shall measure the intensity of light emerging
from the second polarizer. In case (a) we get intensity f,
in case (b) we do not get anything, while in case (c) we
get a light beam of intensity f cos
2
a, polarized along the
axis of the second polarizer. These cases are shown in
Fig. 7.5, where AA and BB are the directions of the axis of
the first and the second polarizers, respectively.
The above experiment is well known in classical optics.
However, like the Young experiment on interference, it
has a direct relation to quantum mechanics. As in the
case of interference we shall reduce the intensity of the
light beam till the photons pass one by one through our
A Brief Interlude
I
,
Sec. 7
7S
Fig. 7.5
fa)
(I;
Fig. 7.6
~ 76
~
set-up. We shall consider the cases illustrated in Pig. 7.5
as applied to single photons.
First of all, we recall that a photon is characterized by
a definite polarization. Moreover, this polarization cor-
responds to the polarization of the classical light wave
from which the photon under consideration has been
"taken". In particular, this means that after the first polar-
izer we shall have linearly polarized (polarized in the
direction of the axis of the polarizer) photons. In the
following we shall "deal" only with these photons and
shall call them "initial photons".
In case (a) the initial photon always passes through the
second polarizer; in case:(b), on the contrary, it never pas-
ses the second polarizer. These results are not unexpected.
But what happens in case (c)? It turns out that in this
case the photon may pass through the second polarizer
or it may not. Moreover, it is absolutely impossible to
predict which of the two alternatives (passing or not pas-
sing) will be realized for a given initial photon. If it so
happens that the photon passes through the second polar-
izer, its polarization will change-it will be polarized
in the direction of the axis of the second polarizer. Thus,
the fate of any particular individual photon is, in prin-
ciple, unpredictable!
Let us assume further that there are N initial photons.
We observe their passage through the second polarizer in
the case (c) and see what happens. We find that if N is
sufficiently large, the number of photons passed can be
predicted fairly accurately; it will be about N cos
2
ex.
In this connection, we recall our earlier remark that the
unpredictability in the behaviour of an individual mi-
croparticle is related to the predictability in the behaviour
of a large number of microparticles (see Experiment 1).
We can say that there is a definite prohaboility of the ini-
tial photon passing through the second polarizer. This
probability is equal to cos
2
ex.
Let us now complicate the experiment. We use the situa-
tion shown in Fig. 7.5 (c) and add yet another (i.e. a
third) polarizer, whose axis is perpendicular to the axis
of the first polarizer. The three-polarizer system under
consideration is shown in Fig. 7.6. Let N be the number
of initial photons (i.e. photons passing through the
first polarizer). After the second polarizer, as we already
know, we shall have N cos
2
ex photons, the polarization of
these photons coinciding with the axis of the second polar-
izer. Analysing further in the same way, we conclude
that after the third polarizer, we must have N cos
2
ex sin
2
ex
photons; moreover, the polarization of these photons must
co
P
Tl
is
e:l
ill
tt
Cf
W
fa
a]
Pi
fi
If
"1
ti
F
n
a
u
1
r
I
f
I
I
t
~
I
I
t
t
1
I
t
coincide with the axis of the third polarizer. The ex-
periment certainly confirms this conclusion.
There is nothing that appears astonishing in this (that
is, of course, if we assume that our astonishment over the
existence of two unpredictable possible behaviours of an
individual photon has somewhat diminished). And yet
there is something here which contradicts our usual con-
cepts. Let us remove the second polarizer. Then no photons
will be observed after the third polarizer. This creates a
fairly interesting situation. Photons pass through this
apparatus, as if they are "filtered" first through the second
polarizer and then through the third. As a result, we at
first have N photons, then N cos
2
a, and we are finally
left with N cos
2
a sin
2
a photons. We remove one of the
filters" and thus, it would appear, improve the condi-
tions for passage of photons through the given apparatus.
However, in actufll practice it turns out quite differently-
now the photons do not pass through the apparatus at
all!
We shall consider elastic collisions of microparticles and
use for convenience the centre of mass system for the col-
liding particles. Figure 7.7 shows experimental diagram
related to the system of the centre of mass of the particles.
Here, A and B are particle beams, 1 and 2 are the counters
for scattered particles, deployed on the line perpendicu-
lar to the direction of motion of the particles before col-
lision. Thus, we consider here the scattering of particles
through an angle of 90 in the centre of mass system.
We note that the picture of the process in the centre of
mass system may considerably differ from the analogous
picture in the laboratory system. Thus, for example, in
the laboratory system the counters 1 and 2 may not be on
the same line. Besides, in actual practice only one beam of
particles (for example, particles of type A) may be used
while the particles of the other type (type B) constitute
the stationary target. It is assumed that every time the
experiment in the laboratory system is conducted in such
a way that the diagram shown in Fig. 7.7 is applicable for
the centre of mass system of the particles.
We shall consider different examples as applied to the
above diagram, measuring each time the probability of
scattering of particles by the number of simultaneous acti-
vations of counters 1 and 2.
First example. Particles of type A are a-particles (4He
nuclei), particles of type Bare 3He nuclei; counter 1
registers only a-particles, counter 2, only 3He nuclei.
Let 1IJ be the probability of scattering measured in this
case.
Sec. 7
Experiment 4 (Scattering of
Microparticles by Microparticles)
Fig. 7.7
1j1"
(
I
I
,+. I '. /3
~ - - ~ - - - ~
I
I
I
I
L!.Jt.
77
:11'"
II.'
~ I
',.11'
I
i
,I
;
Conclusion
78
Second example. The particles are the same, but now
each counter can register both a-particles and 3He nuclei.
In this case the measured probability of scattering turns
out to be 2w. This result appears quite natural-the doubl-
ing of the probability w is associated with the realization
of the two alternatives shown in Fig. 7.8.
Third example. We replace 3He nuclei by a-particles.
Let the a-particles be scattered now by a-particles. It
would appear that in this case the scattering probability
must be the same (or nearly the same) as in the previous
case, i.e. 2w. The experiment, however, yields quite a
different result, 4w. A "mere" replacement of 3He nuclei
by 4He nuclei has doubled the scattering probability!
Still more unexpected results are observed by taking into
account the spin states of the colliding particles (in the
case of a-particles the question of taking spin into account
did not arise since a-particles do not have spin). In this
connection let us consider scattering of electrons by elec-
trons. We recall that an electron may exist in two spin
states (a = 1/2, -1/2). Electrons Jcreated as a result of
photoelectric emission, for example, appear in one spin
state or the other with same probability. Such electron
beams are termed nonpolarized; half the electrons in
them have a = 1/2 and the other half, a = -1/2. If we
take special measures, we may obtain a polarized electron
beam in which all electrons are in the same spin state.
Having made these remarks, let us now return to the dia-
gram in Fig. 7.7 and continue the list bf examples under
consideration. Moreover, we shall assume that the energies
of the colliding particles are considerably small, hence,
the possibility of an electron ~ h n i n its spin state upon
collision need not be taken into consideration.
Fourth example. The two electron beams are nonpolarized.
Let the scattering probability measured in this case be We.
Fifth example. The electron beams are pblarized but in
both directions. For example, A-electrons have spin
a = 1/2 and B-electrons, a = -1/2. In this case the
scattering probability turns out to be 2w
e
i
If we further assume that the amplitude (Fi I S) is the
same for all i (which is often the case in practice), then,
denoting this amplitude by a for brevity, we rewrite
(8.13) in the form
IU I s)1
2
= I a /2 LJ IU I Vi) (Vi I s)I
2
i
{
s
e
e
'Y
t
Thus while result (8.8) is obtained in the absence of S-
particles (in the absence of "control"), we now have the
result (8.14). It is easy to see that it corresponds to (8.6)-
Sec. 8
83
;1\
I
I':
Behaviour of a Microparticle in
the Interferometer and
Interference of Amplitudes
84
we destroy the interference of amplitudes by establishing
a "control" over the intermediate states, i.e. by turning
the physically indistinguishable alternatives into distin-
guishable ones.
S . 9 Amplitudes of Transition
ectlon Probabilities
(Demonstration of Basic
Principles)
Using the concept of the transition amplitude and the
rules relating to the amplitudes, let us turn to experiment 1
discussed in Sec. 7. An electron emerges from the initial
s-state, passes through a screen with slits A and B, each
of which corresponds to its intermediate state (A -state
and B-state, respectively) and is finally registered in
its final x-state, i.e. at the point with coordinate x on
the detector screen.
Suppose that slit A is open and slit B is closed. In this
case (x I S) A = (x I A) (A Is). The probability of tran-
sition s -x, i.e. the probability of the electron being
registered at point x of the detector screen, is of the form
I(x I S)A /2= I(x I A) (A I S)/2. (9.1)
We denote this probability by II (x), and recall that this
is how we denoted the distribution of electron incidences
on the detector screen in experiment 1 (Sec. 7) under the
conditions that slit A is open and slit B is closed. For the
probability of an electron being registered at point x
in the case when slit B is open and slit A is closed, we
may write the analogous expression
(9.2)
Now let us open both the slits. Since it is impossible to
indicate through which slit any electron passes (the alter-
natives are indistinguishable), we have,; consequently,
(x I s) = (x I A )(A I s) + (x I B)(B , s). (9.3)
Denoting the transition probability I (x I s) 1
2
by I (x)
(we denoted the interference curve observed on the detector
screen with both slits open in the same way in Sec. 7),
and taking into account (9.1) and (9.2) we get from this
I(x)= /(x I A) (A / s)+(x I B) (B I s)/%
= Ii (x) +12 (x) +(x I S)A (x I s)1 +(x I s)l (x Ish. (9.4)
It is easy to see that the resulting probability of transi-
tion is not equal to the sum of probabilities of the transi-
tions through slits A and B [I (x) =1= II (x) + 1
2
(x)l.
(9.6)
In addition to the components I I (x) and 1
2
(x), the right-
hand side of expression (9.4) contains two additional terms
caused by the i n t r r n ~ of amplitudes. It is these
terms that account for the difference of the interference
curve I (x) from the add itive cmve 1
3
(x) = I I (x) +
+1
2
(x).
Thus, the interference distribution of the electron inci-
dences on the detector screen observed with both the
slits open in experiment 1 in Sec. 7 is a consequence of
the result (9.4), i.e. a consequence of the interference of
the amplitudes of two possible transitions of the electron
from the given initial state to the given final state.
Figure 9.1 depicts schematically the fundamental exper-
iment 2 considered in Sec. 7. Here s is the electron source,
S is the photon source, PI and P2 are photoelectric coun-
ters which fix the two final states of photons scattered by
electrons in th'e vicinity of slits A and B. To begin with,
we shall assume that the photons scattered in the vicinity
of either of the slits may be registered in the Fl-state as
well as the P
2
-state (which corresponds to the use of ra-
diation with a sufficiently large wavelength). In this
case, obviously, the photons don't "control" the passage
of electrons through the screen with slits. We denote the
transition amplitudes thus:
for electrons
(x I A)(A Is) = CPI, (x I B)(B Is) = CP2' (9.5)
for photons (taking into account the symmetry of the
photon transition which can be clearly seen from Fig. 9.1)
(Fi I A) (A I S) = (F2 I B) (B I S) = "'1'
(F21 A)(A 1 S)=(F
i
/ B)(B /,S)="'2'
Using these notations and result (8.11), we write the
following expression for the probability amplitude of
simultaneously registering an electron at point x and
a photon in the Fl-state
(xF
I
IsS> = CPlll\ + CP21\J2' (9.7)
Correspondingly, for the probability amplitude of simul-
taneously registering the electron at point x and the
photon in the P2-st3te, we write
(xF2 1 sS) = CPIlP2 + CP2
l
P!. (9.8)
The probability of an electron being registered at point x,
independent of where the photon is registered, is of the
form (according to second rule from Sec. 8)
I(x I s)1
2
= l(xF
1
1sS))2+ l(xF
2
/ sS)1
2
(9.9)
Sec. 9
Destruction of Interference of
Amplitudes upon "Controlling"
the Behaviour of a Microparticle
in the Interferometer
Fig. 9.1
"
ji
I
:1
II
, !
8S
I
Thus the resulting probability of the electronic transition
s --+ x is made up of two components. The first is the sum
of the probabilities of transitions through slits A and B
(considered separately) multiplied by (I 'ljJ1 [2 + ['ljJ2 1
2
).
The second component has an interference character; it is
due to the interference of amplitudes. Because of the
existence of this component, we observe the interference
distribution of the impingements of electrons on the detec-
tor screen.
Thus, when the photons don't "control" the passage of
electrons through a screen with slits, we observe the inter-
ference effect described by the expression (9.10).
Remember that in the example considered here we as-
sumed a sufficiently long wavelength for the radiation.
Let us now reduce the wavelength. This will lead to a
reduction in the probability of a photon scattered by an
electron falling in the "alien" counter (for example, the
probability of a photon scattered near slit A being detect-
ed by counter F
2
). This means that with a decrease in
the radiation wavelength, the amplitude 1/12 must decrease.
A decrease in the amplitude 1/12 will also decrease the
relative contribution of the interference component as
is seen clearly from (9.10). As a result, the interference
pattern observed on the detector screen gets blurred.
For a sufficiently small radiation wavelength, it is pos-
sible to accurately "control" the passage of electrons
through a screen with slits. In this extreme case a photon
scattered near either of the slits arrives only at its "own"
detector. This means that 1P2 = O. Substituting this
result in (9.10) we get
I(x I s)1
2
= /1VtI
2
(lcpt 1
2
+ I CP21
2
). (9.11)
Thus, "control" of the passage of electrons through a
screen with slits leads to a destruction of the interference
amplitudes, and consequently to a disappearance of the
interference distribution of the electrons impingements on
the detector screen. The result (9.11) is in complete accord
with (8.14). "Control" makes the alternatives correspond-
ing to the passage of an electron through different slits
distingUishable.
From this example we see that there is a subtle point
involved in the question of the distinguishability of
alternatives: in addition to the complete indistinguish-
86
Substituting (9.7) and (9.8) into this, we find
I(x I s)1
2
=(/ qJ11
2
+I qJ21
2
) (I 'ljJt/
2
+I 'ljJ21
2
)
+ +qJlqJ2) +
(9.10)
"
3
t
1
(
g
(
ability and complete distinguishability, there is a con-
tinuous spectrum of intermediate situations which should
be identified with partial distinguishability. The result
(9.11) describes the limiting case of complete indistin-
guishability of the alternatives under consideration
N2 = 0). The opposite extreme case of the complete in-
distinguishability of alternatives envisages equal pro-
babilities for a photon falling on its "own" or the "other"
detector: 1J'1 = 1J'2' In this case it is easy to see that expres-
sion (9.10) assumes the form
I(x I s)1
2
=21 'lJJ1/
2
1cr1 +cr2 1
2
(9.12)
Results (9.11) (the squares of the moduli of electron ampli-
tudes are added) and (9.12) (the electron amplitudes them-
selves are added up) are obtained from (9.10) as particular
(limiting) c s ~ s The general expression (9.10) describes
the intermediate situation corresponding to partial dis-
tinguishability of the alternatives under consideration,
differing from one another by the magnitude of the inter-
ference component. The less the interference component
is the greater is the degree of distinguishability of alter-
native3.
Thus, distinguishability and indistinguishability are
by no means discrete. Complete indistinguishability is
continuously transformed into complete distinguishability
through intermediate situations corresponding to partial
distinguishability. In Sec. 10 we shall return to the ques-
tion of partial distinguishability from the point of
view of the principle of superposition. *
We turn to experiment 4 of Sec. 7. Let Sl and 8
2
be the
initial states of the colliding microparticles and 11 and 12
be the final states registered by the corresponding counters.
In Sec. 7 we considered the scattering through an angle
of 90 in the centre of mass system of the colliding par-
ticles. For a more general approach, we shall consider
scattering through an angle e. In this case the counters
are arranged along a straight line at an angle e with the
initial direction of the colliding particles-see Fig. 9.2(a)
(the analysis is carried out, as before, in the centre of
mass system of particles).
If upon scattering one microparticle undergoes a transi-
tions
1
-11' and theotheratransitions2 -/2 (Fig. 9.2(b)),
the scattering amplitude has the form
Scatfering of Microparticles and
Interference of Amplitudes
~ i
, '
i
(9.13)
* Partial distinguishability of alternatives is described in detail
in [31].
Sec. 9
87
; ~ .
(9.14)
Suppose that the microparticles are completely distinguish-
able. This may mean, for example, that different kinds of
microparticles, or the same kind of microparticles with
different spin states are colliding. We fIrst consider a situa-
tion when counter 11 registers microparticles from SI only
and counter 12 from S2 only. In this case the probability
of a simultaneous activation of both counters is
Another alternative is also possible: one microparticle
undergoes a transition SI -+ 12 and the other, S2 -+ 11
(Fig. 9.2(c. In this case the scattering amplitude has
the form
1q> (8)1
2
= W1 1
8
1) (/21 S2)/2. (9.15)
Second situation: each counter registers any of the micro-
particles participating in the collision (the situation cor-
responds to the second example in experiment 4 of Sec. 7).
We should now consider two possible alternatives. Since
these alternatives are also completely distinguishable
fOF completely distinguishable microparticles, the proba-
bility of simultaneous activation of both counters will
be given in this case by the expression
I q> (8)1
2
+ I q> (n-8)1
2
= 1<11 1
8
1) (121
5
2)1
2
+ 1(14181) (/1182)12. (9.16)
For 8 = n/2, we get the probability 21 q> (:rr/2) 1
2
-it is
this doubling of probability which we mentioned in the
second example in experiment 4 of Sec. 7.
Further, we assume that the microparticles are completely
indistinguishablJe. This means that microparticles of the
same type and in the same identical state are considered.
Note that the identity of micropartiq]es mentioned in
Sec. 6 is a necessary condition for complete indistinguish-
ability.
If the microparticles are completely indistinguishable,
so are the alternatives shown in Fig. 9.2(b), (c). In this
case we should sum not the probabilities of the alterna-
tives, but their amplitudes. The probability of simultaneous
activation of the counters should be determined by the ex-
pression
W= / rp (8) +cp (n- 8)/2. (9.17)
When applied to the third example in experiment 4 of
Sec. 7 (when we considered the scattering of a-particles i ~
by a-particles), the result assumes the form
W= / cp(:rr/2)+cp(:rr/2)1
2
=41 cp(:rr/2)/2. (9.18)
(I;
(f)
CD
,
~ -.
- --,+'-"-l(0
,
,
,
(tI) CD
Fig. 9.2
88
,. ..
~ ~
It is this four-fold increase in the probability I cp (:11/2) 1
2
which was observed in the experiment.
Interference of scattering amplitudes is just one of the
consequences of the complete indistinguishability of mic-
roparticles. Another consequence is that the probability
of the simultaneous activation of counters should not
change if we interchange Sl and S2' or, in other words, if
we interchange the scattering amplitudes cp (8) and
cp (n - 8). If we proceed from these consequences, the
probability may be formally written in the form
W = I cp (8) + qJ (n - 8)12.
(9.19)
The alternative with the "+" sign (interfering amplitudes
have the same sign) is already familiar to us-it is the
expression (9.17). The other alternative, when the ampli-
tude with opposite signs interfere, is alE:O formally pos-
sible. It is remarkable that nature "employs" this alter-
native as well; this can be verified by studying the results
of experiments on scattering of electrons by electrons.
Thus, we assume that amplitudes with opposite signs in-
terfere:
W
e
= I qJ (8)-cp (:n-8)1
2
(9.20)
\
and turn to the results of the indicated experiments. For
8 = :n/2, the probability (9.20) vanishes. This corres-
ponds to the sixth example in experiment 4 of Sec. 7.
We recall that th is example concerned the collision of
electrons in the same spin state. It is in this case that we
have two completely indistinguishable alternatives for
the electrons*.
If the colliding electrons are in different spin states (the
fifth example in experiment 4), the alternatives are distin-
guishable. In this case the probability of the activation
of the counters is given (as for distinguishable particles)
by expression ~ l . 1 7 , which for 8 = :n/2 leads to the famil-
iar result 2 I (P (:n/2) 1
2
In the case of non-polarized
electron beams (the fourth example in experiment 4),
it should be remembered that the probability of collision
between two electrons in similar spin states is 1/2. From
this, taking (9.20) and (9.16) into account, we get the
following expression for the probability of activation of
* We shall henceforth omit the word "completely", but shall ahays
mean it while speaking of distinguishable and indistinguishable
alternatives. Partial distinguishability will be specially mentioned.
Sec. 9
~ I
I
il
e
!
89
:1
..
the counters
1
We =2
1
cp (8)-cp (n-8)1:>.
+ [j cp(8)12+ I cp(n-8)1
2
1.
(9.21)
,I
I,H,
'It
,j
II,
,
Interference of Amplitudes and
Division of Microparticles into
Bosons and Fermions
90
Result (9.21) includes the summing of amplitudes (for
cases characterized by indistinguishable alternatives)
as well as the summing of probabilities (for cases charac-
terized by distinguishable alternatives). For 8 = n/2,
(9.21) gives the probability We = I cp (n/2) /2. This is
half the "classical probability" (i.e. the probability taking
place in the case of indistinguishable alternatives) in
complete agreement with the results of the experiments
considered in Sec. 7.
Thus, we have found that the experiments on the scat-
tering of microparticlesdescribed in Sec. 7 provide a good
experimental background for the concept of the interfer-
ence of amplitudes. Moreover, these experiments indi-
cate the necessity for using not one but two different laws
of interference, (9.17) and (9.20). We shall discuss the
meaning of these two laws, assuming that 8 = n/2.
According to (9.17), we have for a-particles
W = 4 I cp (n/2) 1
2
, (9.22)
and from (9.20) we have for the electrons in the same spin
state
we = O. (9.23) '*
The use of angle 8 = n/2 makes the scattering diagram
symmetrical. If in addition we also take into account
that the electrons are in similar spin states (a-particles
do not have spin), we may conclude that expressions (9.22) ,
and (9.23) describe the probabilities of pairs
and electron pairs, respectively, appearing in the same 1
state. Comparing this expression with the "classical pro- (
bability" 2 Icp (nIQ) 1
2
, we can come to the conclusion that
one kind of microparticles (a-particles in this case) exhib-
its a tendency to "populate" a given state densely, while
other microparticles (electrons in this case), on the con-
trary, may "populate" states only one at a time.
The fact that all microparticles in nature are divided,
according to their behaviour in assemblies of similar
particles, into two groups-bosons (with a tendency to
densely "populate" the same state) and fermions ("popu-
lating" the states only one at a time) has already been
mentioned in Sec. 1. Now we see that this fundamental
fact is associated with the existence of two different laws
"
for the interference of amplitudes. In the case of bosons,
the amplitudes with like signs interfere; in the case of
fermions, it is the amplitudes with opposite signs that
interfere.
Let us consider an example: there are three atoms emit-
ting photons (8
1
, 8
2
, 8
3
) and three photon counters (f1'
f2' 13)' The amplitude of probability that three transitions
8
1
~ . j 1 8
2
-+/2' 8
3
-+/3 take place simultaneously is
<11 18
1
) (f2 18
2
) (f3 18
3
), We assume that the photons
are registered in the same state. We then have 3! = 6
indistinguishable alternatives. Besides the one indicated
above, the remaining fivp amplitudes are given by
<t1 1
8
2) <12 I 81) <t31 83),
</1 I 8
1
) <t31 82) <12 1 83),
<fa I 8
1
) (f21 82) <1
1
1 8a),
</1 I 82) (/2 I 83) (f3/ 81),
</1 I 83) (/21
8
1
) <t31 82 ),
Assuming that the amplitude of each transition 8i -+ Ik
is the same (we denote it by a), and taking into account the
indistinguishability of alternatives, we get, for the ampli-
tude of a transition with the emission of three photons,
the expression 3 !aa, and for the probability of the tran-
sition (3! )21 a
3
1
2
. If the alternatives were distinguishable
(if distinguishable microparticles were emitted), the
probability would be expressed by 3! I a
3
1
2
Generalizing
these results for the case of n microparticles, we get for
emission probabilities the expressions (n!)21 an 1
2
and
n! 1 an 1
2
, respectively.
Let w" be the probability of the emission of n bosons (pho-
tons in this case) in the same state, and W
n
the probabil-
ity of the emission of n distinguishable microparticles
in the same state. It is easy to see that
W
n
= nl W", (9.24)
Consequently, the probability of the combined detection
of n bosons is nl times greater than the probability of the
combined detection of n distinguishable microparticles.
We rewrite the result (9.24), replacing n by n + 1:
w
n
+1=(n+1)!W
n
+t. (9.25)
Dividing (9.25) by (9.24) we get
wn+1Iwn=(n+l) Wn+iIWn' (9.26)
This means that the probability of getting one more boson
in a state where there are already n bosons is (n + 1) times
Bosonic Nature of Photons and
Processes of Spontaneous and
Induced Emission of Light
II
' I
'I'
I,
Sec. ., 91 I II
~ _ .... ~
Here we consider a particular state, and (1 I 0) is the
amplitude of the transition:
(unoccupied state) --+ (state with one boson), (n + 1 In>
is the amplitude of the transition:
(state with n bosons) --+ (state with n + 1 bosons). When
applied to amplitudes and not probabilities, result (9.27)
means
greater than the probability of getting one more distinguish-
able microparticle in a state where there are already n.
such microparticles. We note further t bat for distinguish-
able microparticles the degree of prior "population"
of the state is not important. When applied to hOSOIlS, it
is analogous to the situation when a boson appears in
a state which was not occupied earlier. Hence result (9.26)
may also be interpreted in a different way. The probability
of getting another boson in a state having n bosons is
n + 1 times greater than the probability of a boson appear-
ing in a state which was hitherto unoccupied. In accord-
ance with this interpretation we can rewrite result
(9.26) in the form
1(n + 1 In) 1
2
= (n + 1) 1(1 10) 1
2
(9.27)
Let us analyse the result (9.27) by considering photon
emission (emission of light). It is easy to see that the
probability of emission is split into two components:
The component (9.29) describes the probability of spon-
taneous emission of light and the compol).eut (9.30) that
of induced emission of light. In the case of sp'ontaneous emis-
sion, the transitions in a substance (to be more precise,
in the radiating atoms) are spontaneous. They are mutu-
ally unrelated and are independent of external rad iation.
In contrast to spontaneous emission, induced emission
depends on the existence of photons near the rad iating
atom-the more photons there are, the greater is the pro-
bability of induced emission. It turns out that on account
of their hosonic nature, the photons "extract", as it were,
new photons from the substance. To be more prccise,
they stimulate transitions in a substance which lead to
the emission of new photons. We stress that a "stimulated"
photon is created in the same state in which the "stimulat-
ing" photon was.
,
(I
,I
:I!
i ~ !
:1
~
~
92
(n + 1 / n) = Vn + 1 (1 / 0).
/(n+1/ s I ~ = /(1/ 0)/2,
l(n+11 n I ~ = n/(11 0)1
2
(9.28)
(9.29)
(9.30)
~ 1
,',
,
,
:\
<
1
t
~
c
1
q
a
~
a
o
d
i
s
t
s
S
I'
C
t
(
\
h
"
Experiment shows that the probability of the absorp-
tion of light by a substance depends upon the number of
photons in tlie radiation. In this respect the process of
absorption of light is an induced process. By using the
analogy with (\3.30) we can write the following expression
for the probability of the annihilation of a photon in a
state having n photons: I (n - 1 I n) I 2 = n 1(0 11) 1
2
i
N N
(f I S)= 2J (f I S)i= 2J (f I i) qJ(i Is).
i i
94
il
II'
(
Atomic beam in inhomogeneous fields. Let us assume that
a beam of atoms occupying a certain initial s-state (this
is a definite spin state) passes first through one region of
non-uniform magnetic field (B
1
), then through another
(B
2
) and is fmally registered in its final spin state j.
Non-uniform magnetic fields are used here as factors ca-
pable of changing the spin state of the atoms in the beam.
Experiment shows that the probability of the s -+ j tran-
sition is different in the cases when (a) observations are
carried out to find the state of the atoms in the beam be-
tween fields B} and B
2
, and when (b) such observations are
not carried out. The difference in probabilities I <t I s) 1
2
in these two cases is easily explained if we take into ac-
count that in case (a) the intermediate i-spin states are
fixed each time and, consequently, the alternatives cor-
responding to them are distinguishable; hence:
I (f I s) 1
2
= 2J,,1 (f I i}(i I s) 1
2
(9.38)
i
In case (b) the intermediate i-states are not fixed and,
consequently, the alternatives corresponding to them are
indistinguishable. Hence
I (f J s) 1
2
= 12J (/ I i) (i I s) r (9.39)
i
'I
Fig. 9.4
~
(I)
FEYNMAN'S PATH INTEGRALS. In conclusion we shall
indicate the possibility of a somewhat unusual formulation
of quantum mechanics, based on amplitude concepts. In the
beginning of this section, we considered an interferometer in
the form of a screen with two slits. There were two indistin-
guishable alternatives corresponding to the two interference
amplitudes. Let us now assume that instead of a screen with
two slits, we have a screen with n slits. The number of alter-
natives (and, correspondingly, amplitudes) will be equal to n.
Further, we place another screen with n slits parallel to the first
screen; the number of alternatives (amplitudes) will rise to n2.
We shall continue this process by placing more and more screens
in the space between the source of microparticles and the detector
screen; moreover, we shall simultaneously keep on increasing the
number of slits in each screen. In the limiting case of an infinitely
large number of screens and an infinitely large number of slits,
we arrive at a situation when the entire space between the source
and detector screen will turn out to be "filled" by different 'paths'
of the microparticle, each corresponding to a definite alternative
and a corresponding definite amplitude (one such path is indicated
in Fig. 9.4(a). The total amplitude of s ...... x transition is the sum
(more exactly, the integral) over all the possible amplitudes.
Finally, we assume that the system of screens with slits was intro-
duced only fictitiously; in fact there are no screens and the entire
ji
1
95
Sec. 9
I
if
I
sM
....._-------------
Superposition of States
In the previous section, while studying the problem of
the probability of the transition of a microparticle from
one state to another, we introduced and discussed the con-
cepts of the transition probability amplitude, distinguish-
able and indistinguishable alternatives of transition,
the interference of amplitudes corresponding to indistin-
guishable alternatives, all of which are specifically quan-
tum-mechanical concepts. on the basis of a number of
examples the reader should convince himself of the im-
portance of the concept of interfering amplitudes, which
gives an explanation of the results of various experiments
with microparticles.
The interference of transition amplitudes is inseparably
linked with one of the most fundamental principles of
quantum mechanics-the principle of superposition of
states, which reflects the specific nature ;.of the "interre-
lations" among the states of a microparticle. We shall
now consider this principle.
Earlier, in Sec. 3, we studied the uncertainty relations.
In this connection it was remarked, in particular, that
the states of a microparticle were combined in groups
each of which contained the definite values of anyone
complete set of physical quantities. We also gave exam-
ples of complete sets of values for an electron and a pho-
ton.
Continuing the discussion commenced in Sec. 3, we shall
introduce notations for the various complete sets: the
a-set, the the y-set, etc. In this context we shall
speak of the group of a-states, the group of etc.
Section 10
Principle of Superposition of
States
96
space between points s and x il "filled" by all the possible paths.
If we can writethe transition amplitude for each such trajectory,
then the probability of the s -+ x transition may be found as the
square of the modulus of the integral summing up all the given
amplitudes (called the path integrals), In this sense, the quantum-
mechanical motion from s to x is nothing but the superposition of
a set of classical motions (classical trajectories) almost in the
ii same way as indicated in Fig, 9.4(b). The transition from quantum
to mechanics corresponds to the reduction of the given
Ii superposItion of paths to a certain individual trajectory.
The concept of the motion of a microparticle along classical path
integrals (in other words, through interference of amplitudes cor-
responding to the classical trajectories) is discussed in detail in
Sec. 5.
We suppose that the microparticle is in one of the a-
states. It means that the quantities in the a-set have
definite values. But what can we say about the values of
the quantities in any other complete set, for example, the
According to the uncertainty relations, the quan-
tities in the 13-set do not have definite values in the state
under consideration. The reader is justified in taking this
as a negative fact. But, fortunately, this is fully "com-
pensated" by a positive circumstance-the principle of
the superposition of states.
According to the principle of 5uperposition, there exists
a link between the states of the microparticle, corre-
sponding to different complete sets: any state from one set
may be represented in the form of a superposition of states
from another set. Thus, for example, a given a-state may
be represented in the form of a superposition of
If we arbitrar,,ily adopt the symbol ( I to indicate the
state of a microparticle, the principle of superposition may
be written in the form
(10.1)
II
The expression (10.1) appears as an "expansion" of the
given state (a I into the sum of the numbers cD
a
/3
playing the role of coefficients in the expansion. More
concretely, the number <D
a
/3 is the amplitude of the prob-
ability that we shall obtain values corresponding to
the state (P I while measuring the quantities from the
p-set in the state (a I. In other words, it is the amplitude
of the probability that a microparticle in state (a I may
also be found in the state (P I. If we denote this amplitude
by the usual symbol (a I expression (10.1) assumes
the following form:
(a I = LJ (a I P> I (10.2)
13
In the preceding sections we considered the amplitudes of
the transition probability (in short, transition ampli-
tudes). At first glance, the principle of superposition "brings
into play" a new type of amplitudes of probability. Ac-
tually, the above-mentioned expression "(a IP> is the
amplitude of the probability that a microparticle in
state (a I may also be found in state (P I" allows another
obvious interpretation: "(a I P> is the amplitude of the
probability of a microparticle arriving in state (P I,
if it is known that the particle actually exists in
state (a I". In short, the latter statement means that
(a I is the amplitude of the probability with which
any is "represented" in a given a-state. This pro-
'1
,
i
:
t Sec. 10
jp--------------
P
b
(J
M
Ie
m
OJ
pI
ti
01
iu
st
w
ci
ql
si
m
p<
Ti
WI
M
tb
m
or
I
th
I
r
.!
T:
duces the impression that the amplitudes (a I ~ don't ..1 or
have anything to do with any transitions or processes. .'. : to,
Considering this impression, we introduce a new term (rl
for (a I ~ - t h e amplitude of probability of state (in brief, pr
the amplitude of state). he
The reader must be warned at once that the above impres- It
sion is erroneous. However, in order to be convinced of th
this, we must analyse the process of measurement. Mea- nG
surement in quantum mechanics will be discussed in bJj
Sec. 11. This discussion will necessitate some correction I in
in the above definition of the amplitudes (a I ~ > and ". SI
will enable us to actually reduce the amplitudes of states sil
to the already familiar amplitudes of transitions. tv!
But everything has its own time, and so, for the time being, hf
we shall operate with the concept of "amplitude of state" pc
as an independent concept, without ascertaining the th
practical meaning of, say, the phrase "a particle in state ~ -
(a I can also be found in state ~ I". of
As has been noted earlier, the principle of superposition of
"supplements", as it were, the uncertainty relations; its :,. (c
positive content "compensates" the well-known negative
aspect of these relations. Figuratively speaking, the uncer-
tainty relations indicate the "old" concept which must
be rejected while we go over from macrophenomena to
microphenomena. In particular, they require a rejection
of the simultaneous meai'lurability of all physical quan-
tities characterizing a given object. At the same time,
the principle of superposition indicates the "new" con-
cept which is applicable when considering microparticles;
superposition (10.2) means that if a microparticle is in
a state in which the quantities of the a-set are measurable,
then the value of the quantities in the ~ - s e t may be pre-
dicted with a probability equal to I (a I P>/2.
In classical physics one comes across superposition quite
frequently, the foremost example being ihe well-known
superposition of classical waves. From a mathematical
point of view, the classical superposition and superpo-
sition in quantum mechanics are analogous. This circum-
stance greatly stimulated the development of quantum
theory. At the same time, it certainly complicated the
interpretation of the physical content of theoretically
obtained results since it tempted one to draw erroneous
analogies with classical waves. In the words of Dirac [9]
the assumption of superposition relationships between the
states leads to a mathematical theory in which the equations
that define a state are linear in the unknowns. In conse-
quence of this, people have tried to establish analogies with
systems in classical mechanics, such as Vibrating strings
Superposition in Classical Physics
and Quantum Mechanics
f
s.
t
n
;-
,f
[l
n
:l
s
,
"
e
e
1
S
e
t
)
1
or membranes, which are governed by linear equations ana
for which, therefore, a superposition principle holds....
(remember the criticism in Sec. 5 of the attempts to re-
present the motion of a bound microparticle with the
help of classical waves in a resonator-author's remarks).
It is important to remember, however, that the superposition
that occurs in quantum mechanics is of an essentially different
nature from any occurring in the classical theory, as is shown
by the fact that the quantum superposition principle demands
indeterminacy in the results of observations.
Speaking of the difference between quantum and clas-
sical superpositions, remember that a superposition of
two classical waves leads to the generation of a new wave
having, of course, new characteristics. However, a super-
position of two states I and I, characterized by
the values and respectively, of quantities in the
by no means leads to a state having any new value
of As an example, let us consider a certain superposition
of states
(a I I + (a I I.
We shall measure the in this state. As a result,
we get every time one of the earlier values, or
Moreover, it is impossible to accurately predict which of
the two states will be obtained in any particular measure-
ment. We can only indicate the probability of getting
or These probabilities are equal to I (a I 1
2
and
I (al 1
2
, respectively. It is this specific uncertainty in
the results of measurements that determines the funda-
mental difference between quantum and classical super-
positions.
Taking into consideration the quantum-mechanical prin-
ciple of superposition, let us return to the question of
quantum transitions discussed in Sec. 2. Suppose we con-
sider, as before, two energy levels E
1
and E
2
of the micro-
particle. We denote the corresponding states of the par-
ticle in which it has energy E
1
or E
2
(i.e. is on the first
or second level) through (1 I and (21 respectively. Accord-
ing to the principle of superposition, in addition to
states (1 I and (2 I we can also get the state
(fl=(fI1)(11+(/12}(21. (10.3)
Measurement of energy of the microparticle in this state
leads either to the result E
1
or to the result E
2
(as if the
microparticle were on the level E
1
and simultaneously
On the level E
2
). The first result is obtained with the
probability I (f 11) 1
2
, and the second, with the proba-
bility I (f I 2) 1
2
The possibility of the existence of such
I
1:1
"I
Sec. 10
II
I
,,'
...rz
t,
(10.4)
a specific quantum-mechanical situation immediately
removes the basic contradiction of the quantum transi-
tion, mentioned in Section 2. It is sufficient to assume
that an interaction of a microparticle with radiation leads
to a superposition state of the type (10.3). Then the prob-
ability of finding a particle on one energy level or anoth-
er (on its earlier level or on a new one) will be described
simply by the square of the modulus of the corresponding
amplitude of state.
In order to finally convince ourselves that the quantum-
mechanical principle of superposition has in fact nothing
in common with the classical superposition we turn to
expression (10.2) and see how it changes upon the tran-
sition to classical physics. Since in classical physics all
the quantities can be simultaneously measured, they form
together one "complete set". Considering that the superposi- .1.. ..
tion bonds described by relation (10.2) operate between .
different complete sets, we arrive at the conclusion that
in the classical case such bonds simply do not exist and, ~
consequently, all formally composed amplitudes of statesf
must be taken as being equal to zero:
(ex I ~ = o.
In quantum mechanics condition (10.4) also exists, but
only "within the limits" of the given complete set (for
states belonging to the same set). Thus, for example,
(exi I exj) = 0, if i =1= j. (10.5)
The amplitude of a state is equal to zero if and only if
the two corresponding states are mutually independent
(if an object is in one of these states, it cannot be found
in the other). Such states are called mutually orthogonal.
In this respect all the states of a classical particle are
mutually orthogonal, while in quantum ,mechanics only
the states belonging to the same complete set are orthog-
onal and the states belonging to different sets are non-
orthogonal. This last fact is reflected in the principle of
superposition of states.
The idea of mutually orthogonal states permits us to
define more precisely the concept of complete and partial
distinguishability. For this purpose it is convenient to
make use of the above-mentioned example of the scatter-
ing of microparticles of one type by one another. Since
such particles are identical, their distinguishability is
determined by the distinguishability of states (states
{"1 I and (8
2
I; see Sec. 9). We recall that in Sec. 9 we dis-
cussed, in particular, microparticles of the same kind
but in different spin states, as examples of completely
Mutually Orthogonal States;
Total and Partial Distinguishability
<If States
.1
.,fl
Ii
.1
" 100
I
1
1
t
distinguishable microparticles. We thus tacitly assumed
that different spin states are completely distinguishable.
We can now clearly indicate the criterion of complete and
partial distinguishability of states: if (Sl I S2) = 0, the
states (Sl I and (S2 \ are completely distinguishable;
there are no superposition bonds between them. But if
(Sl I S2) =1= 0, the states under consideration are partially
distinguishable. In other words, orthogonality of states
is the criterion of their complete distinguishability.
Suppose we are considering scattering of two bosons of
the same type. The result (9.16) will hold good if the
initial states are mutually orthogonal (let these states
be (al I and (a
2
I). The result (9.17) will be valid if the
initial states are similar (say, (a
l
I and (al I). Both these
results are just two extreme cases corresponding to com-
plete distinguishability and complete indistinguishability
of microparticles, respectively. However, different inter-
mediate situations corresponding to partial distinguish-
ability are possible, when the initial states of microparti-
cles are a superposition of several mutually orthogonal
states:
(S1 I = (S1 I(1) (a1 \ +(S1 1(2) (a2 I,
(S2 1= (S2 I (1)(a1 I +(S2 I (2) (a2 I. (10.6)
It can be shown (see [31]) that in this case the probability
of simultaneous activation of detectors is determined by
the expression
I!V= I cp(El) 1
2
+ I cp(n-El) 1
2
+ I (S1\ S2) 1
2
[cp(El)cp*(n-El),+cp*(El)cp(n-El)]. (10.7)
For I (Sl I S2) 1
2
+ 0, the result (10.7) turns into (9.16)
(we come to the limiting case of complete distinguish-
ability). For I (Sl I S2) 1
2
+ 1, the result (10.7) turns into
(9.17) (we come to the limiting case of complete indistin-
guishability) .
Thus, we find that the question of the complete and par-
tial distinguishability of alternatives in quantum mechan-
ics is closely linked with the quantum-mechanical prin-
ciple of superposition, more precisely, with the mutual
orthogonality or non-orthogonality of states.
The different states corresponding to the same complete Basic States
set of quantities are called basic states (eigenstates).
The amplitudes of elementary states satisfy the condition
(ai I aj) = {jij, (10.8)
where {jij is the so-called Kronecker delta symbol; it is
equal to zero for i =I=- j and unity for i = j. The expres-
Sec. 10
101
II
il!
sion (10.8) is called the condition of orthonormalization of
basic states. It is obtained by taking into consideration
{1O.5) and the fact that the probability of getting the
value at in the state (at I is obviously equal to unity.
The important property of the system of basic states is
its completeness: any state may be expanded in a system
-of elementary states.
Basic states may be selected in different ways depending
-on the complete set under consideration. Thus, different
systems of basic states may be used: {(at J}, { ~ t I},
etc. It is said that different representations are possible.
For a more general approach, the principle of superposi-
tion of states signifies the fact that any state (f I of a
microparticle may be expanded in any system of basic
states:
(f I = ~ (f I at) (ai I,
i
(10.9)
...........
<I I = ~ (f I ~ i < ~ i I,
i
The principle of superposition permits an explanation
-of the results of experiment 3 in Sec. 7. Using this prin-
ciple, we shall consider the passage of individual photons
through the system of three polarizers shown in Fig. 7.6.
We denote the state of polarization of a photon after the
first polarization by (s I. According to the principle of
superposition, the state (s I may be considered as a super-
position of the basic states (1 , and (2 I, corresponding
to two independent polarizations of the photon-along
and perpendicular to the axis of the second polarizer,
respectively:
(ql = (311)(1/ + (s/ 2)(2/ (10.10)
"
{note that in this example, the system of basic states con-
tains only two states). The amplitudes of the states may
be written in this case in the form (3 I 1 ) = cos a and
(3 I 2> = sin a. Thus,
(3 I = cos a (1 [ + sin a (2 I. (10.11)
The second polarizer lets through photons from the state
(1 I only. Since according to 00.11) the state (1 I is
"represented" in state (s I with a probability cos 2 a,
out of N photons only N cos
2
a photons will pass through
the second polarizer. Moreover, all the photons that pass
will appear in the state (1 I (i.e. they will be polarized
along the axis of the second polarizer). Thus, in front of
the second polarizer, the photon exists as if partially in
Superposition of States and
Passage of Photons Through
Polarizers
102
'W
i ~ 1
I
If
n
e
s
0-
'J'
t
the state (1 I and partially in the state (2 I. At the instant
when the photon passes through the polarizer, this "dual-
ity" vanishes. In some cases a photon exists in the state
(2 I and so cannot pass through the polarizer, while in
some other cases it is in the state (1 I and can thus pass
through the polarizer. Further, for any individual photon
it is impossible to predict in which state it will appear
(hence it is impossible to predict whether a given photon
will pass through the polarizer or not).
While studying the passage of photons through the third
polarizer, we proceed in a similar way. The state (1 I is
expanded into a system of basic states (1' I and (2' I
corresponding to a polarization of photon along or perpen-
dicular to the axis of the third polarizer:
(1 I = sin a (1' [ + cos a (2' I. (10.12)
The third poll'!,rizer lets through photons in the state (1' I
only. This state is "represented" in the state (1 I with a
probability sin
2
a. Hence out of N cos
2
a photons only
N cos2 a sin
2
a photons will pass through the third po-
larizer, all these photons being in the state (1' [.
If we now remove the second polarizer, then in place of
(10.11) and (10.12) we get
(81= (.9\1')(1' 1+ (8\2')(2' l, (10.13)
where, as can be easily seen, (.9 11') = 0 and (3 I 2' > = 1,
so that (3 I = (2' I. Naturally, in this case, at the outlet
of the system of polarizers no photons are observed at all.
Let the transition from state (.'lIto state (f \ take place
through certain intermediate v-states. We suppose that
the microparticle is not fixed in the intermediate state so
that a case of physically indistinguishable alternative
takes place. In this case, as \Ve know, the transition ampli-
tude (f I 8) is given by the expression
(f I s) = (f I Vi) (Vi Is), (10.14)
i
where (f I Vi) and (Vi I 3> are the amplitudes of the re-
spective transitions. The intermediate v-states must be
completely distinguishable, since otherwise there is no
point in introducing the concept of distinguishable or
indistinguishable alternatives, since the very concept of
alternatives loses its meaning. Consequently, the v-states
must form a system of mutually orthogonal basic states.
Taking this into consideration, we make use of the prin-
ciple of superposition and express the state (f I in the form
(f I = (f 1Vi) (Vi I, (10.15)
i
Sec. 10
Principle of Superposition of
States and Interference of
Transition Amplitudes
103
\1
IIi
:;
I
jj;
"Mechanics of Quantum
Mechanics"
where the amplitudes (/ I Vi) are essentially the ampli-
tudes of the states (the bar is used to distinguish the ampli-
tude of the state from the transition amplitude (/ I Vi .
If superposition (10.15) exists, there is actually no need to
perform a transition from (8 'to (/ I. Since the state (/ I
is a superposition of states (Vi I, it is sufficient to simply
accomplish transitions from the state (8 I to each of the
states (Vi I This means that the transition amplitude
(/ 1 8) is a superposition of the transition amplitudes
(Vi I 8):
(f I s) = L (f I Vi) (Vi Is). (10.16)
f
Comparing (10.16) and (10.14) we conclude that
(f I Vi)=(j I Vi). (10.17)
This means that at the level of mathematical apparatus,
we have accomplished a reduction of the amplitudes of
the states to transition of amplitudes. In other words, the
amplitudes of the states in fact play the same role in the
apparatus of quantum mechanics as the transition ampli-
tudes. Incidentally, we have also established that rela-
tions (10.14) and (10.15) are closely related to each other
and hence the effect of the interference of transition ampli-
tudes and the principle of the superposition of states are
directly interrelated.
In conclusion, we mention an important method which
is widely applied in quantum mechanics. It is easy to
see that if we delete the sign of the initial and final states
in the expression for the interference of amplitudes, we
automatically obtain the superposition expression for
the undeleted state. Thus, if in (10.14) we delete [8)
on the left- and right-hand sides of the equation, we obtain
the superposition expression (10.11) for the state (/ I
(note that in addition to the symbol ( /' the symbol I )
is used for denoting a state).
We shall demonstrate the basic methods reflecting, in
Feynman's words, the "mechanics of quantum mechan-
ics". Let us delete the state (/ I from the left- and right-
hand sides of equation (10.14). This gives
V
I
t(
F
t}
(v
(t
w
pI
(f
Sl
(f
Sl
th
fo.
fo:
Let us further assume that some apparatus converts
state 1
8
) into some other state 18'). We express this in
the general form as
104
A 18) = /s').
(10.18)
(10.19)
Fi]
an,
thl
wo
Sec
1
II' We shall say that the operator A has acted on the state
1.9 >giving rise to state Is'). We shall apply the operator A
to both sides of equation (10.18). Using (10.19), we get
Is') = 2: A I Vi) (Vi I s) (10.20)
i
Further, in place of the state (1 I deleted earlier, we restore
the state (vi I belonging to the system of basic states:
(10.21)
(the notation (Vi I A I Vi) should be taken as (v, I vi ),
where I vi) = A I Vi . Finally, we rewrite (10.14), re-
placing 1.9) by 1.9'):
<f Is') = (f I Vj) (Vj I Sf) (10.22)
i
Substituting (10.21) into (10.22) we get
(f I A I s) = .LJ .LJ <f I vi) (Vi I A I Vi)(vi Is).
j i
(10.23)
Summarizing the methods demonstrated above, we write
the equations obtained so far and leave it to the reader to
follow the logic and appreciate the beauty of the trans-
formations:
(f I s) = (/ Is),
<f I s) = .LJ <f I vi) (Vi Is),
i
I s) = .LJ I Vi) (Vi Is),
i
A I s) = 2J A I Vi) (Vi Is),
i
(Vi I A I s) = (Vi I A I Vi) (Vi Is),
t
(/ I Vj) (Vi I A I s)
j
= 2J <f I vi) (Vi I A I Vi) (Vi Is),
j i
(f I A I s) = 2j (f I Vj) (Vi I A I Vi) (Vi Is).
j i
!I
i
:1
105
It
s
e
e
h
n
y
:e
m
Firstly, we shall note that any definite superposition of
states in a microparticle arises as a result of its inter-
action with the surroundings. The latter may be some
macroscopic body (which is either produced artificially
or is a part of the natural external conditions). This macro-
scopic body is referred to as the analyzer. The expression
(11.1) should be interpreted in the following way: as
a result of the interaction with a particular analyzer (in
this case, we may speak of a a microparticle
lying in state (ex I is transformed into the superposition
state >-J (ex I I. Taking into account the quantum-
i
mechanical nature of the superposition state, it may be said
that by interacting with the the microparticle
in some sense is "transformed" at once into all the states
I Here, the amplitude (ex I should be treated as
the amplitude caused by the indicated interaction of the
transition (ex I + [. The quantity I (ex I 1
2
is the
probability of finding the microparticle finally in just
the I state.
One can anticipate at least three questions from the reader.
First question: What do we really mean by the expression
"the microparticle is at once transformed into all the
I states"? The answer to this question will be given
below in the subsection "Potentialities and their realiza-
tion in the measuring process". Here, we just remark
that although the microparticle is "simultaneously trans-
formed into all the I states" as a result of its interac-
tion with the it can be found in principle each
time in only one Hence it may be said that no
confusion arises. By the way, the reader has already come
across a similar situation when considering experiments 1
and 2 in Sec. 7. Here we once again remind the reader
that quantum-mechanical logic does not always have
a corresponding graphic model.
Second question: If the amplitude of state is really the
transition amplitude, what about the definitions of am-
plitudes of states given in Sec. 10? Answering this qu.estion
we recall the following definition given in Sec. 10:
"(ex I B) is the probability amplitude of a microparticle
existing in state (ex I being also registered in state (B I".
In this definition the word "existing" should be replaced
by a more accurate word "existed", since after interaction
with the analyzer the microparticle no longer exists in
the state (ex I. Now the word "also" becomes redundant.
The definition then assumes the following form: "(ex I B)
is the amplitude of probability of a microparticle that
existed in state (ex I being registered in state Reg-
Sec. 11
107
III
II
il
p
(11.3)
Examples of Analyzers
108
istering is a kind of measuring process and (a i P> plays
the role of the amplitude of the transition (a I + (P I
which takes place in this process. Here we remark that
in the above-mentioned interaction of the microparticle
with the analyzer is just one part of the measuring process.
A more detailed treatment of the measuring process will
be given at a later stage.
Third question: It was agreed earlier (see Sec. 8) to read
the transition amplitudes from right to left. If (a I Pi>
is also transition amplitude, it should also be read in the
reverse direction (from left to right). Isn't it confusing?
Actually, if we strictly follow the condition of writing
the preceding states to the right of the ones that follow,
then (11.1) should be written as
'l
L..J I Pi) (Pi I a) = I a). (iLia)
i
However, such a notation, as a rule, is not used. Hence
we decided to allow some inconsistency, and in order to
avoid possible confusion in this connection we shall in
future retain the term amplitude of state along with the
term transition amplitude. When using both these terms
the reader must remember that from the point of view
of physical meaning, the amplitude of state is nothing
but the transition amplitude (this has already been shown
from a mathematical point of view in the previous section).
The reader has in fact already come across analyzers
each time the interference of transition amplitudes was
considered. We shall give a few examples.
First example: [see (9.3)l-the analyzer is a screen with
two slits. It gives rise to the superposition
(8 I = (8 I A)(A I + (8 I B >(B I. (11.2)
Second example: [see (9.35)l-the analyzer is a crystal
lattice consisting of nuclei of the same type with zero
spin. It generates the superposition
]V
(8 I = (8 I i) cp (i /.
i
Third example: [see (9.39)l-the analyzer is a nonuniform
magnetic field B
1
It gives rise to the superposition
(81 = 2.j (8 I i) (i I. (11.4)
i
It may be said that an analyzer, generating a certain
superposition of states, in fact ensures the emergence of
indistinguishable alternatives. Moreover, the number of
alternatives is equal to the number of basic states in the
given st'perposition. In the first example this number is
j
i
i
I
B
c
v
IJ
V
IJ
i
I
s
u
t
I
I
Il
<
I
t
1
i
1
s
s
Il
v
e
a
t
s
a
r,
o
v
s
P
t
ti
C
c
a
s:
s
1
just equal to two (i.e. to the number of slits in the screen);
in the second example, it is equal to the number of nuclei
in the crystal, while in the third example it is equal to the
number of spin states (Le. to 2s + 1, if s is the spin of the
atom).
The process of measurement in quantum mechanics
consists of three successive stages: (1) a preparatory stage
when the microparticle is "prepared" in a certain state
(ex I, considered below as the initial state; (2) a working
!tage in which the "prepared" microparticle interacts
with a certain analyzer and goes over to the superposition
!tate, and (3) a registering stage in which the microparticle
is registered in one of the basic states forming the super-
position. In this stage the microparticle interacts with
some macroscopic body, capable of changing its state
under the influence of the microparticle. This macroscopic
body is called the detector.
If for the sake of simplicity we do not consider the pre-
paratory stage, the abstract "scheme" of the measurement
process may be written in the following way:
1 " l 2
{sl (11.5)
i
The Essence of Measuring
Process
r
)
3
3
1
)
I
o
a
)
Here the arrow 1 corresponds to the working stage, and
the arrow 2 to the registering stage.
The basic elements of the measuring instrument (measur-
ing apparatus) are thus the analyzer and the detector.
The role of the analyzer has already been explained. We
shall now consider the role of the detector. Figuratively
speaking, its role boils down to "spying" on how the micro-
particle "behaves itself" in the superposition state which
was created by the analyzer. If we make use of the above
examples of analyzers, this "spying" could provide an
answer to the question: Which slit did a particular elec-
tron pass through? Which nucleus of the crystal lattice
scattered a particular neutron? What is the spin state of
a particular atom? The reader who is familiar with the
results of similar "spying" (in particular, with the results
of the experiment 2 in Sec. 7) may foresee that an "inter-
vention" by the detector leads to the destruction of the
superposition of states. The detector registers the micro-
particle each time in one of the states which constitute
the superposition. This is done at the expense of the destruc-
tion of superposition. From the point of view of the ideas
Considered in Sees. 8 and 9, this means that the detector
converts indistinguishable alternatives into distinguish-
able ones and thus destroys the interference of the tran-
sition amplitudes.
109
s.c. 11
II
-'n
Some Peculiarities of the
Quantum-Mechanical Measuring
Process
110
We separate from the "scheme" (11.5) the registering
stage corresponding to the interaction of the micropar-
ticle with the detector:
(11.6)
It is often said that a "scheme" of the type (11.6) de-
scribes a "construction" of the superposition (.'I I ) I
i
to the state I. This process is also known as "reduction
of the wave packet".
Thus, while the analyzer creates a definite superposition
of states, the detector destroys it by confining this super-
position of states to one of the states constituting it.
It is obvious that if the "scheme" (11.5) is tried on a
single microparticle, it is difficult to say anything about
getting any u"leful information. It is necessary to repeat
the measuring process for a sufficiently large number of
microparticles. In this case the observer may find out,
firstly, the values of the quantities of the -set encoun-
tered in practice, and, secondly, the frequency with which
the microparticle is found in one or another.
This allows us to experimentally determine, firstly, the
spectrum of the values of the quantities in a -set and,
secondly, the probabilities I (8 I > 1
2
Sec. 12
119
...._------------------
Causality in Statistical Theories
Statistical Nature of Quantum
Mechanics
120
It has already been remarked in Sec. 6 when discussing
the problem of necessity and chance in microphenomena.
that quantum mechanics is a statistical theory. Hence,
the question of causality in quantum mechanics may be
seen first of all from the point of view of the manifesta-
tion of causality in general in statistical theories (as
statistical mechanics, physical kinetics, microscopic
electrodynamics).
In any statistical theory necessity and chance appear as
dialectical categories. The relationship between them is
that of unity and conflict of opposites. The velocities
of molecules in a gas are random (any instantaneous
velocity distribution of molecules is random) but the
average velocity of a molecule can always be determined.
The incidence of any electron passing through a screen
with slits at any particular point of the detector screen
is random, but the resulting interference pattern can
always be determined. Necessity, like chance, is present.
in every statistical theory. It expresses causal relation- .
ships. Consequently, causality in statistical theories leads
to necessity in these theories.
While in dynamic theories necessity dominates, thus
making exact predictions of the values of physical quanti-
ties possible, it appears in statistical theories through
distribution laws which give only the probabilities of
various values of physical quantities.
As an additional (quite important) manifestation of
necessity in statistical theories, we mention the conserva-
tion laws. It is well known that conservation laws may
be seen as exclusion principles. From this point of view,
the role of conservation laws in statistical theories is
fairly obvious: they serve as conditions which reduce
the probability of definite processes to zero.
When treating quantum mechanics .as a statistical
theory, one must remember that it occupies a special
place among these theories. Within the framework of
classical physics the laws describing the behaviour of
large number of objects are of statistical nature, while
the laws relating to the behaviour of an individual object
are dynamic. By considei'ing the element of chance in the
behaviour of a single object, quantum mechanics places
itself in a special position-that of a statistical theory of an
individual object. That is why we earlier called quantum
mechanics a statistical theory in principle.
This circumstance predetermines the specific nature of
statistical ensembles in quantum mechanics.
According to Fock [1], the elements of statistical collectives
considered in quantum mechanics, are not the microobjects
Ig
1
la
,e,
be
a
H
as
l
ic
'.
as
is
es
1S
Ie
d.
m
m
Lll
It,
l-
Is
IS
i-
'h
)f
)f
z-
y
r,
is
,e
II
:l
,f i
,f
e
t
e
s
1
f
I
sl
C,
tl
t]
p
tJ
n
[
T
ti
0
b
d
0
t
t,
d
t
t,
I-
d
e
e
I-
s
I
e
t
"\
s
t
\
1
s
[it is easy to see that if the states (1 I and (2 I satisfy
the orthonormalization condition (10.8), the states (I I
and (II I also satisfy this conditionl. By using (13.12),
we rewrite (13.1) in the form
(13.13)
e
n
l)
I)
Y
t
l)
) )
Le
1-
d
)-
lS
).
1-
lS
4
w
l)
It can be seen from here that a transition from the basic
states (1 I and (2 I to the basic states (I I and (II I
corresponds to a transition from amplitudes C
1
and C
2
to amplitudes (C
1
- C
2
)IV2 and (C
1
+ C
2
)IV2. Since
the latter describe the stationary states of the micro-
particle, it follows that the transition under considera-
tion is associated with a diagonalization of the Hamilto-
nian matrix.
Thus, suppose we have a certain microparticle under cer-
tain external conditions. Let us choose a certain system
of basic states. The attempt is usually made to choose
basic states which have a clear physical meaning (as we
did, for example, in the case of the ammonia molecule
or the hydrogen molecule). The basic states chosen on
the basis of such considerations lead, in the general case,
to a Hamiltonian matrix whose non-diagonal elements are
different from zero (the microparticle undergoes transi-
tions between the basic states). Further, it is possible
to go over to a new system of basic states for which the
Hamiltonian matrix is diagonal. The new basic states
describe the stationary states of the microparticle; the
elements of the diagonalized Hamiltonian matrix are
essentially the values of the energy in these states.
In the general case the non-diagonal elements of the General Case
Hamiltonian matrix are different from zero and so the
simplifying conditions (13.6) and (13.7) are not applicable.
In this case one must solve not the simplified system of
equations (13.8), but the more general system of equa-
tions (13.2) for a microparticle with two basic states.
We suggest that the reader, if he so desires, solves the
system (13.2) himself, assuming for the sake of simplicity
that the Hamiltonian matrix is invariant in time*.
We shall limit ourselves here giVing some results.
The energy of the stationary states of a microparticle is
Such a solution is given, for example, in [3].
Sec. 13
129
... 5
determined by the expression
--,,.,,--=------,,-----
E - Jf
ll
+H
22
+ -. /( H
ll
-H22 )2+
H
H
1, II - 2 - V 2 i2 2i'
(13.14)
i:
d
1
(13.15)
(t::U6)
"
,
'I
j
1
Example of the Ammonia
Molecule
130
The basic states (I I and (II I corresponding to these
energy values are expressed in terms of the elementary
states (1 1 and (2 I describing the equation system (13.2)
in the following manner:
(I 1= ad
1
1+bi (2 I, }
(II I = a2 (1 I +b2(2 I,
where
I ai 1
2
+ I bi 1
2
= 1 a2 1
2
+ I b2 1
2
= 1, }
ai/b
i
= H
i2
/(E
I
- H
u
),
a
2
/b
2
= H
2i
/(E
n
- H
22
).
It can be easily seen that if H
ll
= H
22
= Eo and H
12
=
= H
21
= - A, the result (13.14) gives E
r
,I1 = Eo +
+ A, the superpositions (13.15) turn into (13.12). In
other words, we arrive at the simplified case of the non-
diagonal Hamiltonian matrix discussed above in detail.
But if H
12
= H
21
= 0, the result (13.14) gives E
r
= HUt
Ell = H
22
-we arrive at the case of the diagonal Hamil-
tonian matrix (I I = (1 I, (II 1= (2 I).
,We recall that the basic states (1 I and (2 1 of the
ammonia molecule were chosen using graphic physical
considerations: they correspond respectively to the posi-
tion of the nitrogen atom on one side of the ~ p l n e
and on the other. Since these positions are symmetrical,
we may take JIll = JI
22
- Eo. Assuming further that
the elements H
12
and JI
21
are real (JI
12
= H
21
- -A),
which, as it turns out, does not involve the loss of gene-
rality in this case, we arrive at the situation to which
the simplified system of equation" (13.8) corresponds.
It follows from this that the energy levels of a molecule
are essentially Eo + A and Eo - A. We emphasize
that if no transitions took place between the states (1 I
and (2 I, there would have been only one level Eo in
place of the levels Eo + A and Eo - A. It would have
been doubly degenerate since there would be two states
corresponding to it. It may be said that transitions be-
tween the states (1 I and (2 I (associated with "pushing"
of the nitrogen atom through the H-plane) correspond
to a removal of degeneracy, Le. to a splitting of the
level Eo into two levels Eo + A and Eo - A.
Further, let us assume that the ammonia molecule is
placed in a static electric field with intensity ~ which
By using (13.14), we obtain the following expressions
for the energy Jevels of the molecule in a static electric
field:
E1=E
o
+ V En=E
o
- -VA2+e
2
d
2
. (13.19)
Figure 13.2 shows the qualitative dependence of the
energy levels of ammonia molecule on the field intensity.
It can be easily seen that the effect of "throwing" the
nitrogen atom through the H-plane is important for
relatively small fleld intensities. In strong fields, when
the levels diverge considerably, this effect becomes in-
signiflcant.
--
-"-.------- ----
--
The Hamiltonian Matrix for an
Electron in a Magnetic Field
(13.18)
The Electron in a
Magnetic Field
It is well known that the projection of the electron spin
momentum in any direction may assume only two values
(-1iI2 and +1iI2). This allows us to treat the electron
as a microparticle with two basic states. The problem
of an electron in a magnetic field is of great practical
interest. Besides, this problem is also quite interesting
from a methodical point of view: its analysis enables
one to get acquainted with not only the general nature
of a system with two basic states, or, in other words,
the two-level system, through a physically suggestive
example, but also with the general approach to the analy-
sis of such systems.
Let us first fix the direction of the coordinate axes
(including the direction of the z-axis). For the basic
states (1 I and (2 I we choose states for which the pro-
jections of the electron spin on the z-axis are equal to nlZ
Section 14
is perpendicular to the H-plane. Denoting the electric
dipole moment of the molecule by d, we write
(1;-U7)
Now the positions of the nitrogen atom on either side of
the H-plane are no longer physically symmetrical (H
u
=F Fig. 13.2
;:/= H
22
). Assuming that H
12
= H
21
= -A as before,
we write the system of equations (13.2) for the case under E
consideration:
-;I,:, }
-in c
2
= -AC
1
+(Eo-ed)C2
4)
is
ch
he
si-
ne
11,
at
l ),
le-
ch
Is.
lIe
lze
1 I
in
ve
Je-
19"
nd
he
u,
il-
In-
il.
+
In
6)
5)
se
ry
2)
lee. 14
1}1
...._---------------
and -fi/2, respectively. We switch on a static magnetic
field (we denote the value of the magnetic induction
by B) and consider the following two cases.
First case: the magnetic field is directed along the z-axis
{B
x
= By = 0). In this case the basic states (1 I and
(2 I are stationary; the state (1 I has energy -f-tB z and
the state (2 I has energy f-tB z (f-t denotes the magnetic
moment of the electron). The amplitudes C
1
and C'I.
satisfy two independent equations of the type (13.3):
I-
n
C
E
t:
The Hamiltonian matrix of the electron is of the form
"Ji del B C
-l -=-11 1
dt r z ,
(14.1)
(14.2)
I
v
i
\
,Second case: the magnetic field is in an arbitrary direction.
In the first place, we note that irrespective of the direc-
tion of the field (in other words, irrespective of the choice
-of the direction of the coordinate axes) the energy levels
of the electron are determined by the expressions -f-tB
and f-tB; while in the previous case we had to take B =
= B z, in this case we must have B = + +
+ BD
1
/
2
Thus
E1 = -f-t En=f-t
(14.3)
Note that
E1=-E
u
(14.4)
:Further we make use of relation (13.14). By taking (14.4)
:into account, we may assume that H
ll
+H
22
= O. As
.a result, by combining (14.3) and (12.9', we get
(14.5)
(14.6)
We shall assume a linear relationship between the ele-
ments of the Hamiltonian matrix and the field. It turns
.out that this fairly natural assumption allows us to
derive the following relations from (14.5): H
ll
= -f-tB z'
H22 = f-tB z' H
21
= Hi2 = -f-t (B
x
+ iB y). Thus, the
Hamiltonian matrix of an electron in a magnetic field
"has the following general form:
. ',. [ -f-tBz -f-t(Bx-iBII)l
.un= (B +'B ) B J .
:" , -f-t x l iJ f-t z
~
18
I
I
I
,
I
I
,
I
\ I
''1
z
Fig. 14.1
Projection Amplitudes-
(14.8)
(14.7)
(14.11)
}
It can be easily seen that when B x = By = 0, the
matrix (14.6), as expected, coincides with the matrix
(14.2).
By using (14.6) we write the system of equation (13.2) for
the case under consideration:
- i'n tt C
t
= _. ,.![BzC
t
+(B
x
- iB
y
) C
2
],
-in :r C
2
= -",,[(Bx+iBy)Ct-BzC21.
a
l
= cos (8/2) exp (-ilp/2);
b
i
= sin (8/2) exp (ilp/2).
Thus, we have determined the amplitudes of the proba-
bilities that the electron has its spin directed along the
Z-axis (amplitude aI) or in the opposite direction (ampli-
tUde b
I
) by assuming that the electron spin is directed
along the field (Le. in the direction determined by the
'angles 8 and lp).
where, as we recall, (1 I and (2 I are the states in which
the projections of the electron spin on the z-axis are
equal to nl2 and -nl2, respectively, and the coefficients
al and b
i
are determined by the relations (13.16):
at/bt = H
t2
/(E
1
-H
11
), /a
t
I
2
+/btl
2
=1. (14.9)
By using (14.6) we write
H11 = -""Bz = -""Bcose, }
H
t2
= -I-t (B
x
- iB
y
) = -""B sin eexp (- ilp). (14.10)
Substituting (14.10) into (14.9), we find that
ai/bi = sin eexp (--ilp)/(1 - cos e).
Taking into account that I al 1
2
+ 1 b
z
1
2
= 1, we arrive
at the following final result:
In conclusion, we note that although the above argument
was conducted for the case when the Hamiltonian matrix
is invariant in time, the results (14.6) and (14.7) are
valid even when the magnetic field varies with time.
Let the direction of the magnetic field be determined by
the polar angle e and azimuth lp (Fig. 14.1). We shall
assume that t ~ e electron spin is directed along the field;
consequently, the electron is in the stationary state
(I I with energy E
1
= -""B. According to (13.15), the
state (I I can be represented as a superposition:
6)
le-
ns
to
, %'
he
ld
,5)
,4)
,4)
As
"
tic
on
ds
nd
nd
tic
C
z
3):
.1)
rm
.2)
m.
~
ice
als
tB
+
,3)
Stc. 14
133
(14.13)
(14.15)
(14.14)
I
;1
.;j
~
p
,
Note that (14.11) does not contain the magnetic i n d u ~
tion B. It is obvious that the result (14.11) must be valid
in the limiting case B -+ O. In other words: we may exclu-
de the field from consideration and interpret (14.11) in
the following way. It is clear that the direction of the
electron spin is determined by the angles 8 and cp. In
this case the amplitude of the probability that the electron
spin is along the z-axis is al and the amplitude of the
probability that the electron spin is in the opposite
direction is b
1
Expression (14.8) should be treated in this
case as an expansion of the spin state (8, cp I in terms
of the spin states (z I and (-z I:
{8, cp I= cos (8/2) exp ( - icp/2) (z I
+sin(8/2)exp(icp/2)(-zl. (14.12)
The amplitudes of the states occurring in (14.12)
(8, cp Iz) = cos (8/2) exp (-iqJ/2);
(8, (pi - z) = sin (8/2) exp (icp/2)
are called projection amplitudes.
By using projection amplitudes, we may predict the
result of the following experiment. Let an electron beam,
polarized in a direction given by the angles 8 and cp,
pass through some "filter" which only allows through
electrons whose spin is along the z-axis. In this case the
amplitude of probability of an electron passing through
the apparatus (through the "filter") is (8, cp I z). The
projection amplitude here plays the role of the amplitude
of the electron transition from the state (8, cp I to the
state (z I.
Precession of the Electron Spin Let the direction of the electron spin be given by the
angles 8 and cp (the electron is in the state (8, cp I). This
state can be represented in the form" of superposition
(14.12) of the states (z I and (-z l Suppose that at
time t = 0 we switch on a magnetic field B which is
directed along the z-axis. Now the states (z I and (-z I
become stationary states. Using this, we write [see (13.4)]
(8, cplz)=CdO)exp(-i/-tBzt/n), }
'<8, cpl-z)=C2(0)exp(i/-tBzt/n).
Comparing (14.14) with (14.13), we conclude that
C
t
(0) = cos (8/2) exp ( - icp/2);
~ (0) = sin (8/2) exp (icp/2).
,
It follows from this that in time t after the magnetic field
has been switched on the projection amplitUdes assume
tl
(I
(I
1
z
lJ
t
f
c-
ld
11-
In
1e
n
III
1e
te
is
as
2)
3)
1e
is
m
at
is
, I
4)
5)
ld
ne
1 ,) "" (612) cxp [ - -H ,tin)J'
(14.16)
; <e,
I
.,i,'.. Thus, the switching on of a magnetic fIeld along the
, z-axis does not change the polar angle 8 but changes the
azimuth cp, the change in cp being proportional to the
i
'.,"", time interval t which elapses after switching on the
, field. This means that the spin of an electron precesses
, around the z-axis (around the direction of magnetic
I field) with a constant angular velocity. It can be easily
I seen that the angular velocity of the spin precession is
i given by the relation
I ill = (14.17)
!
We move one step further by ignoring coordinate axes.
Suppose that at time t = 0 the direction of electron spin
forms an angle 8 with the direction of the magnetic field.
This angle will remain constant with time, but the
electron spin will precess around the field direction with
an angular velocity
(i) = (14.17a)
We further suppose that the magnetic field is varying
with time (in the general case, both the direction and
the magnitude of the vector B-'> are varying). A change in
the field leads to a corresponding change in the electron
spin precession: a change in the magnitude of the magne-
tic field results in a change in the angular velocity of
precession, while a change in the direction of the field
causes a change in the direction around which the pre-
cession takes place.
A knowledge of the precession enables one to predict
changes in the electronic state over a given period of
time. We shall consider a simple example (Fig. 14.2).
Suppose that at the instant t = 0 the field is directed
-
along the z-axis [vector B (0)1, and the is
in the zy-plane and forms an angle 8
0
with the direction
of the field. Thus the initial state of the electron
<8 (0), cp (0) I is determined by the angles 8 (0) = 80
and cp (0) = n/2. We shall assume that the magnitude
of the field does not change with time, but that the direc-
tion of the field changes. Suppose after time h = nn/2It
B
the field becomes directed along the y-axis [vector B(t
1
)
.in Fig. 14:21. What will be the state of the electron at the
Sec. 14
Fig. 14.2
z.
135'
Generalization of the Problem of
an Electron in a Magnetic Field
to an Arbitrary Two-Level System
time t
1
? It is clear that if the field direction had remained
unchanged, the end point of the electron spin vector,
while precessing around the z-axis, would have described
a semicircle during the time nnl2ltB, thus shifting from
point SI to point S2. If we take into account the variation
in field direction, we shall find that it has shifted not
to the point S2 but to the point S3. Consequently, the
required state of the electron (8 (tl), cP (tl) I would be
determined by the angles 8 (tl) = n/2 - 8
0
and cP (tl) =
= n/2.
According to Feynman [3], it is interesting that the
mathematical ideas we have just gone over for the spinning
electron in a magnetic field can be applied to any two-
state system. That means that by making a mathematical
analogy to the spinning electron, any problem about two-
state systems can be solved by pure geometry.... If we can
solve the electron problem in general, we have solved all
two-state problems. Let us clarify these remarks.
We shall consider some two-level system with the basic
states {1 I and (2 I. We assign some vector to each state
of the microparticle. A choice of the basic states {1 I
and {2 I in this case is equivalent to a choice of the
z-axis (as if these two states correspond to the two z-
projections of the electron spin). Suppose that the micro-
particle is in the state {s (0) I at the initial moment
of time. We assign to this state a vector whose direction
is determined by the angles 8 (0) and cP (0):
{s (0) I +-+ (8 (0), cP (0) I. (14.18)
In order to find the angles 8 (0) and cP O ~ we must Expand
the state (s (0) I in terms of the basic states {1 I and
{2 I and use for the coefficients of expansion expression
(14.13) for the projection amplitudes. This expansion
is of the form
{8 (0)1 = cos [8 (0)/2J expl[ _ iCPJ(0)/2j!{11 "
+sin [8 (0)/2J exp [icp (O)/2J!{2/. (14.19)
Further, let us turn to the Hamiltonian matrix of the
microparticle. First of all we shift the zero point of the
energy in such a way that it is located precisely half-way
between the two energy levels or, in other words, so
that the condition (14.4) is satisfied. In this case
8 11 +822 =0. H . ~ O
->-
We now formally introduce a vector ItB (it is in no way
associated with any magnetic field!) such that its projec-
tions on the coordinate axes (remember that the axes
are determined by the choice of the basic states) satisfy
d
.
,
d
n
n
t
e
e
e
g
l
j
i
t
I
I
t
the conditions
H
11
= -lJBz, H
12
= -f-l(Bx-iBy). (14.21)
By using (14.21) we determine
(14.22)
In order to solve this two-level problem, Le. in order
to determine the change in the (s I-state during certain
time t, we must consider the precession of the vector
1
';
I
C
';
,
(15.5)
It can be easily seen that (15.5) is the expression for the
superposition of amplitudes of states:
(15.5a)
If the y-values vary continuously, we get in place of (15.5)
(15.6)
Let us consider the eigenfunction of the quantities of a
certain set given in the representation ()Lthe quantities
of the same set. If these quantities change discretely, we
have, according to (10.8),
(15.7)
140
If, however, the quantities vary continuously, we get in
place of (15.7)
(15.8)
where (') (a - a') is the so-called Dirac delta junction,
which is a generalization of the Kronecker's symbol for
the case of continuously varying quantities. *
The delta function is discussed in detail, for example. in [t3}.
I
i
The delta function is determined in the following way:
Strictly speaking, it is impossible to plot the function
6 (a - a') because it would involve drawing an infinite-
ly narrow and infinitely high peak at the point a = a'
with a finite "area" under it equal to unity. One of the
most important properties of the delta function, which
can be easily derived from its definition (15.9), can be
written as follows:
where f (a) is a bounded function, continuous at the
point a = a';
Assuming that the a-values are discrete and the Condition of Orthonormalizatioll
lues vary continuously we rewrite (15.6) in the form of Eigenfunctions
'I'c<;(aj)= 5 (15.11)
By using (9.33). we can write
<1>f:l (aj) = (15.12)
]
From (15.12) and (15.7), we obtain from (15.11) the
condition for the orthonormalization of the eigenfunction8
"'I%i
51pa; 1pci
j
= 6i /. (15.13)
If the a-quantities vary continuously. we must use (15.8)
instead of (15.7). In this case the condition of orthonor-
malization of the eigenfunctions assumes the form
s
1 s
It
f
e
s
t
s
'J
t
}
e
e
t
'J
e
I
'J
)
)
o(a-a')==O at a*a';
00
i f (a) 6(a-a') da = f (a'),
-00
00
r ' I'
J 6 (a - a ) da = 1. (15.9)
;(15.10)
51pa = 6(a-a'). (15.14)
As an example, we consider the case of a freely moving The Wave Function of a Freely
microparticle. For simplicity, we assume that it has Moving Microparticle
zero spin. The wave function in coordinate (three-dimen-
sional) representation has the form*
.... ........ -3/2 ........
1p-+ (r) = (Po Ir) = (2nli) exp (iporlli)1 (15.15)
Po
where Po is the momentum of the microparticle and -; is
its spatial coordinate. The function 1p-.. (;:) is an eigen-
Po
... We shall derive this result later (see Sec. 20).
Sec. 15
141
I '
.t
142
(15.17)
1
J
+00
crease g. This will bring the points A in the figure closer to a = 0,
and raise the point B on the ordinate axis. In the limit as g --+ 00
we get an infinitely narrow and high peak whose integral is
equal to unity. This is just the delta function. Thus, 0 (a) =
= lim sin (ga)/na. We can easily get (15.17) from this since
.
f{
sin (ga)/na = _1_ r exp
2n J
-f{
--+ -+ -)0 -+ 3/2
{fJ-. (p) = (r
o
Ip) = (p I r
o
)* = (2:n:nF exp (- tpro;n)
To
(15.16)
(the quantities and represent the components of the-
spatial coordinate and the momentum of the micro-
particle).
The function CP-+ (P) is an eigenfunction of the coordinate
To
of the microparticle given in the momentum represen-
tation.
It can be seen from (15.15) and (15.16) that the states of
a freely moving microparticle are described by wave
functions in the form of plane waves (in coordinate or
momentum space).
The functions '-+ (;:) and Cp-+ (p) satisfy the condition
])0 . To '
(15.14) of orthonormalization. This can be verified by
using the integral representation of the delta function*
function of the momentum, given in the coordinate
representation. It describes the state in which the momen-
tum components of a microparticle have definite values,
while the spatial coordinates may be assigned only pro-
bable values.
Switching over from the coordinate to the momentum
representation and making use of (9.33) we get
Fig. 15.1
* Let us consider the function sin (ga)/ITa (Fig. 15.1). Irrespective
00
of the value of parameter g, j do. sin (ga)/na = 1. Let us in-
-00
Section
16
Quantum Mechanics as a
Qualitative Leap in Man's
Knowledge of the Laws of
Nature
)
Of course it IS impossible to distinguish sharply between
natural philosophy and human culture. The physical
sciences are, in fact, an integral part of our civilization,
not only because our ever-increasing mastery of the forces
of nature has so completely changed the material conditions
of life, but also because the study (If these sciences has con-
tributed so much to clarify the background of our own
existence.
N. Bohr
Although quantum mechanics deals with microparticles,
its significance is by no means limited to microphenome-
na. In our endless quest for understanding and perfecting
our knowledge of the laws of nature, quantum mechanics
represents an important qualitative leap. Without a com-
prehension of the importance, and radical (we could even
say revolutionary) nature of this leap, it is impossible
to understand the modern physical picture of the world.
In this section, an attempt has been made to look at
quantum mechanics from this point of view. This may
serve as a logical conclusion to the chapter, which has
been devoted to the physical foundations of this astonish-
ing theory.
The expression "crazy theory" as one which is "crazy "Crazy Ideas"
enough to be true" was once coined by Bohr. This expres-
sion reflects the stunning impression produced on Bohr's
contemporaries by the astonishing physical discoveries
made at the beginning of the 20th century, discoveries
which could not be confined within the framework of
classical concepts. It became obvious that an explanation
of these discoveries required radically new ideas and a new
approach.
In Sec. 2 we considered two fundamental ideas of quantum
mechanics-the idea of discreteness and the idea of duality.
Returning, in our imagination, to the beginning of the
century, we could call the first idea "incomprehensible"
and the second, "not properly understood". The intro-
duction of discreteness to the physical picture of the
world led to incomprehensible and, apparently, logically
controversial quantum "jumps". The idea of duality,
which asserts the specific nature of microparticles, elimi-
nated the contradiction of quantum "jumps" by suggest-
ing a "manoeuvring" between the "particle" and the
"wave" concepts. But the meaning of the wave concept
introduced here remained in fact unclear for a very long
time. These two "absurd" ideas led to the emergence of
Sec:. 16
143
lIIIIiIIIt
)
.r
The Essence of Quantum
Mechanics
144
the extravagant "uncertainty relations" which resulted
in a different outlook on even such fundamental con-
cepts as "energy", "momentum" and "angular momen-
tum".
Quantum mechanics was born under circumstances of
a significant breaking up of physical traditions. It called
for a rejection of many usual and accepted notions such
as the strict continuity of the spectra of values of physical
quantities, the trajectory as an essential attribute of the
motion of an object, Laplace determinism as the basic
form of expression of the principle of causality, the possi-
bility of an infinite detailization of the structure of an
object or of a phenomenon with respect to time, the
possibility of distinguishing between two objects, however
similar to each other, under any circumstances, the belief
that it is always possible, at least in principle, to disre-
gard the measuring instrument when conducting any
measurements, etc. (all these questions have been analys-
ed in detail in the preceding sections).
It is difficult to recall any other period in the history
of physics when such a serious and large-scale revision
of physical concepts was carried out. According to Bohr,
... the new lesson which has been impressed upon physicists
stresses the caution with which all usual conventions must be
applied as soon as we are not concerned with everyday expe-
rience... In the study of atomic phenomena we have
repeatedly been taught that questions which were believed
to have received long ago their final answers had most unex-
pected surprises in store for us.
The revision of the concepts and the rejection of many
accepted notions could well be considered as a "negative
aspect" of quantum mechanics. Let us now consider its
"positive aspect".
If we try to summarize the main p s t v ~ knowledge im-
parted by quantum mechanics to man: in his search for
learning about his surroundings, the following two impor-
tant points stand out:
First: quantum mechanics showed that the basic laws of
nature are not dynamic but are statistical, and that the
probabilistic form of causality is the fundamental form
while the classical determinism is just its limiting (degene-
rate) case.
Second: quantum mechanics revealed that probability in
nature should not be dealt with as in classical statistical
theories. It was found that in certain cases it is not the
probabilities of events that should be summed, but rather
the amplitudes of these probabilities. This leads to the
interference of probability amplitudes.
I
I
f
1
d
l-
l-
.f
d
h
II
e
c
1-
y
y
tl
.
,
:s
e
'e
d
:-
y
e
S
r
'-
~
l
El
r
El
flo Thus we empha,;'. firstly the probabili3tte eharacter oj
I, ~ the laws of nature (the pre-eminence of statistical laws)
I r and, secondly, the special relations among the probabilities,
which assume not only the summation of the latter, but
also the specific interference effects. In our view, it is in
this that the main importance of the information one gets
from quantum mechanics is to be found.
As Born pointed out in [14], the statistical methods found
wider applicability with the development of physics.
As regards modern physics, it is completely based on sta-
tistical foundations. In Born's view, it is the quantum
theory that established the closest links between statistics
and the basic aspects of physics. This should be considered
as an important event in the history of human knowledge,
with consequences reaching far beyond the limits of science.
It is sometimes said that the fundamental difference be-
tween quantum mechanics and classical mechanics is
determined by\ the statistical nature of the former and
dynamic nature of the latter. Upon careful consideration,
this apparently bland and irrefutable statement turns
out to be incorrect. While revealing the pre-eminence of
statistical laws in physics, quantum mechanics shows
at the same time that dynamic laws with their unique
predictions are, as a matter of fact, a special (degenerate)
case of probability laws. In this respect not only quantum
mechanics, but classical mechanics as well, must be,
strictly speaking, formulated in the language of probabil-
ities*. The qualitative difference between quantum me-
chanics and classical mechanics (or classical physics in
general) depends on how the relations among probabilities
are considered. It has been mentioned in [27] that the
main difference between quantum mechanics and classical
mechanics does not lie in the statistical nature of the
former. It lies in the fact that it is not the probability
but its amplitude, the wave function, that is of primary
importance in quantum mechanics. This leads to the
interference of probabilities, an effect which does not
have an analogy in classical mechanics.
Developing the above ideas, let us single out the follow-
ing points: (a) the special interrelations among quantum-
mechanical states and the resulting specific nature of
quantum-mechanical description of phenomena; (b) the
* This point of view is systematically analysed in [27], where it
is stated, in particular, that Feynman's concepts of path integrals
in fact converts the principle of least action into the principle of
maximum probability, i.e. it proves that the fundamental dynamic
Principle is essentially statistical in nature.
Sec. 16
145
..6rr.. '1
I!:
"
Ii
The Specific Nature of
Quantum-Mechanical Description
of Phenomena
146
specific nature of the application of probabilities in
quantum mechanics; (c) the special role of interference
in quantum mechanics; (d) the complementarity principle
as a logical foundation of quantum mechanics, and (e) the
dialectical nature of quantum mechanics. We shall con-
sider these questions one by one.
According to Feynman, one of the most outstanding
achievements of quantum mechanics lies in the fact that
it allows so much to be extracted from so little.
The reader has already found out how much can be
achieved from the phenomenon of interference of ampli-
tudes (see Sec. 9), on the basis of the principle of super-
position of states (see Sec. 10), and from a consideration
of the simplest quantum-mechanical systems, Le. micro-
particles with two basic states (see Secs. 13, 14). The
relative formal simplicity of the description of microphe-
nomena is connected with the specific nature of this
description. Remember that for a quantum-mechanical
description we must know firstly the basic states and,
secondly, the Hamiltonian matrix, which reflects the
physics of the phenomena under consideration. A simplifi-
cation in the description can be achieved because of the
following two circumstances.
Firstly, it is important that the number of basic states,
and consequently the number of elements of the Hamilto-
nian matrix required for describing a definite phenome-
non, should not be large. Thus, in the examples given
in Secs. 13 and 14, this number was equal to two. Here
the contradiction regarding the diversity in the possible
states of the microparticle does not arise, since according
to the principle of superposition either of them may be
represented in the form of some superposition of basic
states. The principle of superposition itself is the deciding
factor, which permits us to manage usually with a small
number of states selected as the basic "states. As Dirac
wrote [9], ... in departing from the determinacy of the classi-
cal theory a great complication is introduced into the descrip-
tion of Nature, which is a highly undesirable feature. This
complication is undeniable, but it is offset by a great
simplification prOVided by the general principle of superpo-
sition of states....
It has been noted earlier (see Sec. 10) that in classical
physics all states of a particle should be considered as
mutually orthogonal, or, in other words, as basic states.
Because of this, the above-mentioned simplifying situa-
tion is impossible here in principle.
Secondly, the relative simplicity of superposition relations
allows us to draw analogies among microparticles having
l,
[l
e
e
e
1-
g
.t
e
l-
'-
n
I-
.e
l-
is
11
1,
Le
i-
Le
s,
)-
e-
m
re
1e
Lg
le
ic
19
11
1C
i-
el-
is
'It
0-
al
as
s.
a-
llS
19
the same number of basic states and reduce all the real
problems in practice to a consideration of the two-level
problem, three-level problem, etc. It has been shown
in Sec. 14 how an arbitrary problem with two basic states
can be reduced formally to the problem of an electron
in a magnetic field.
Of course, it cannot be deduced from all this that in
general "quantum mechanics is simpler than classical
mechanics". Certainly it is simpler in the above-mentioned
sense. However, it has sufficient problems of its own,
especially problems connected with a rational choice of
the system of basic states and with finding the form of the
Hamiltonian matrix. It is hardly necessary to recount
all the difficulties which invariably result from the
necessity of departing from graphic representations of
accustomed concepts. That is the way things are. Hence
it wouldn't be wise to say that "quantum mechanics is
simple!". And 'yet one must remember that the peculiar
relations that exist among different states of a micropar-
ticle and appear in the specific principle of superposition
of states considerably simplify the quantum-mechanical
description of phenomena.
Quantum mechanics forces us to take a fresh look at
the well-known theorem of addition of probabilities for
incompatible events. We have to consider not only the
incompatibility but also the distinguishability of the
events. This is where the novelty of the approach lies.
It is well known that in the probability theory used in
classical physics, as well as in engineering, it is always
implied that events are distinguishable.
In order to demonstrate the specific nature of the applica-
tion of probability in quantum mechanics, we make use
of the example considered in Secs. 9 and 10 of the scatter-
ing of bosons of the same type by each other. We recall
the notations introduced in these sections: lp (8) =
= </1 1 81} </2 I 8
2
}-the probability amplitude of one event
(one transition), lp (n - 8) = </2 I Sl} <Ii 1S2 }-the proba-
bility amplitude of the other event, w - the probability
of simultaneous activation of both detectors. Since
microparticles of the same type are scattered by each
other, the question of their distinguishability leads to
the distinguishability of the initial states <81 I and (S2 I.
In this connection three cases may be isolated:
First case. The events are completely indistinguishable.
This means that the initial states are the same, and
(16.1)
Probability in Quantum
Mechanics
"
See. 16
147
I
,
I
i
I. j
148
In this case, we get [see (9.17)]
w=lep(8)+ep(n-8)12. (16.2)
Second case. The events are partially distinguishable. This
means that the amplitude (SI I S2) satisfies the condition
0< I (SI I S2) 1<1. (16.3)
In this case, we get [see (10.7)]
w = I ep (8) 1
2
+ I ep (n - 8) 1
2
+ I (s{ I S2) 1
2
[ep (8) ep* (n - 8) +ep* (8) ep (n - 8)]. (16.4)
Third case. The events are completely distinguishable.
This means that the amplitude (.'11 I S2) satisfies the
condition
(SI I S2) = O. (16.5)
This gives us [see (9.16)]
IV = I ep (8) 1
2
+I ep (n -- 8) 1
2
(16.6)
Thus we find that the theorem of the addition of proba-
bilities "holds" only in the third of the above-mentioned
cases, i.e. in the case of completely distinguishable
events. From (16.5) it follows that the states ~ 1 I and
(S2 I must be mutually orthogonal* in this case. In the
remaining cases the theorem of the addition of probabili- I
ties does not hold. If the events are completely indistin- \
guishable, the amplitudes of the probabilities should be
summed. But if the events are partially distinguishable, ..
we must use the more complicated relation (16.4). When
deriving this relation, both the law of the addition of
amplitudes and the theorem of the addition of probabili-
ties have been used in the same way as in Sec. 9 when
deriving (9.10).
It can be easily seen that the result (16.4) based on the
addition of probabilities as well as the addition of ampli-
tudes is the most general one. When the condition (16.5)
is satisfied, it at once leads to the "purely" classical case
of addition of probabilities while condition (16.1) is
fulfilled "purely" in the case of addition of amplitudes
of probabilities.
It should be emphasized that the very possibility of the
existence of the general result (16.4) is caused by the
presence of superposition bonds between the states (S1 I
* It is worthwhile mentioning here that the mutual orthogonality
of all states of a classical object stipulates a complete distinguish-
ability of events and, as a result, leads to the theorem of addition
of probabilities.
2)
tis
)n
3)
4)
~
he
5)
6)
>a-
ed
.le
ad
he
li-
n-
be
Ie,
en
of
li-
en
he
li-
.5)
lse
is
les
he
he
11 I
ity
sh-
ion
and ("2 I [see (10.6) in this connection]. Thus we track
the active connection between the quantum-mechanical
principle of superposition of states and the specific nature
of the application of probability in quantum mechanics.
The superposition relations among states and the inter-
ference of probability amplitudes have the same physical
nature.
We draw the reader's attention to the following fact.
In order to explain the interference results in experiments
with microparticles (for example, the interference pattern
on the detector-screen in Experiment 1 of Sec. 7), we can
formally proceed in two different ways. One way corres-
ponds to the "conservation" in quantum mechanics of
the theorem of the addition of probabilities for any incom-
patible events. This way, however, requires a comparison
of the microparticle with some classical wave. The other
way corresponds to the addition of probability amplitudes.
In this case an explanation of interference results no
longer requires the introduction of any visual wave
model.
The specific nature of microparticles, which has been
discussed in detail in the preceding sections, precludes
the first way and so puts the question of interference and
wave processes in a new light. Before the appearance of
quantum mechanics, interference was always considered
as an example of a typical wave effect. If a characteristic
interference pattern was observed in any experiment,
it was considered sufficient evidence to draw conclusions
on the presence of waves. In this sense, wave" were consid-
ered as being "primary", and interference as being se-
condary. Quantum mechanics shows that the reverse order
of emphasis is more correct.
In revealing that the probability laws of nature involve
the addition of probability amplitudes and not of the
probabilities themselves, quantum mechanics revealed
the fundamental role of interference in physical phenome-
na. Simultaneously, it showed that classical wave proces-
ses need not essentially be at the root of an interference
pattern. In the general case, interference is a specifically
quantum-mechanical effect associated with the addition
of probability amplitudes.
Traditions, however, die hard. This explains attempts to
"translate" the interference of probability amplitudes
into the graphic language of classical waves, which
inevitably leads to a definite misuse of wave terminology
(see the above interlude "Are these the same waves?").
In a number of cases the "translation" into wave language
is not justified even from a formal point of view. For
Sec:. 16
Quantum Mechanics and
Interference
149
I
. i'
:i'
150
example, the division of microparticles into fermions and -
bosons, which is such an important consequence of the
interference of amplitudes, is fairly difficult to explain
on the basis of wave processes. The analysis of the process
of the destruction of interference of amplitudes in the
measuring process ("the reduction of the wave packet")
directly indicates the impropriety of using classical wave
concepts when considering microphenomena. All this
indicates that an explanation of interference obviously
does not come within the framework of the traditional
wave model.
By the way, the last fact may be taken as the starting
point for a generalization of the very concept of "wave
process". Such a generalization assumes a transition from
visual classical waves with real amplitudes to some sort
of generalized waves with complex amplitudes. The classi-
cal waves must appear as an extreme (degenerate) case of
such generalized waves. In other words, quantum-mechan-
ical interference may be used for an extension of the
framework of the accepted wave picture (which, incident-
ally, is invariably accompanied by rejection of a graphic
representation) and for creating a theory for the general-
ized wave processes which would reflect not only the
probability nature of physical laws but also the special
relations among probabilities in nature.
By demonstrating the fundamental nature of the pheno-
menon of interference, quantum mechanics naturally
arises an interest in the study of this phenomenon in
different branches of physics. In our view, it raises definite
hopes that modern physics, stimulated by the effect of
interference, will develop in future into a study of the
interference of effects in the fields of both microphenomena
and macrophenomena.
The idea of "addition" (summation, accumulation) of
different phenomena is familiar to u8.1n a way, this can
be compared with the "addition of probabilities". It is
likely that quantum mechanics tells us (indicates in its
own way) that such a picture is the result of a certain
"averaging", approximation or simplification of a finer
and better pictne in which we "add up" not the effects
themselves, but something different (corresponding to
probability amplitudes in the language of quantum
mechanics), thereby arriving at the phenomenon of inter-
ference of effects.
.d
Le
n
,S
Le
")
'e
is
.y
11
19
re
III
rt
i-
)f
l-
ie
t-
ic
l-
ie
II
)-
ly
in
te
of
rre
la
of
m
is
ts
in
er
ts
to
m
r-
A Brief Interlude
11lIerlude
Fairy tales, though oft untrue,
Teach good lads a thing or two.
Pushkin
Reader: It is not clear what you wanted to say in the last sentences
which, though quite eloquent, are tentative. Please explain them,
if possible.
A uthor: Gladly. Let us take a definite example. It is well known that
if a substance is placed in a condenser, its optical properties will
change under the influence of the external electric field. Such effects
are called electro-optical effects. If the substance is subjected to
a light field of sufficient intensity (generated, say, by a high-power
laser), the optical properties change in this case also. These effects
are called nonlinear optical effects. It so happens that if a condenser
field and an intense light field are simultaneously switched on, then
in addition to the familiar electro-optical and nonlinear optical
effects we observe qualitatively different effects which may be
explained only as a unique interference of electro-optics and non-
linear optics. This is an example of the interference of effects.
Reader: But can one perceive in this example any tendency towards the
development of modern physics?
A uthor: Let us take another example, that of a laser. We shall not dis-
cuss the principle of its working here; it is just sufficient to mention
that it is based on some nonlinear effect, called the saturation effect.
Let us take another instrument, the second-harmonic generator
(that is what a transformer of coherent light which doubles the
frequency is called in quantum mechanics). We shall simply state
that this instrument also is based on the principle of nonlinear
optical effect called the generation of second harmonics. Thus, the
laser produces coherent light of a definite frequency, while the
second-harmonic generator partially transforms the frequency of
this light. We can say that we first use the saturation effect and
then the effect of second-harmonic generation. Such is a general situa-
tion corresponding to a simple "summing" of these effects. Now,
suppose that both these effects are used simultaneously. In order
to do so, we must place a special crystal, which causes a trans
formation of the frequency of light passing through it, inside the
l ~ r (or, more precisely, inside the resonator of the laser). Here,
we are speaking of a qualitatively different situation corresponding
to the interference of two nonlinear optical effects. It is quite signifi-
cant that this and other similar situations have been increasingly
drawing the attention of specialists engaged in the field of quan-
tum electronics. Intraresonator generation of second harmonic
is already being put into practice; it has been proved that it can
ensure a more effective transformation of optical frequency.
Reader: This really sounds interesting. It is possible that some tendency
is indicated here. But what has:this got to do with quantum me-
chanics?
151
< ,
Author: When studying reality on a fundamental level, quantum mechan-
ics highlighted some important points. It showed that the question
of interference is deeper than it was considered, and that this ques-
tion can be posed independently of wave questions; and finally,
that interference is an example of qualitatively new interrelations,
Le. relations which obviously have more prospects than the tra-
ditional interrelations corresponding to a simple summing, adding,
or accumulation.
I,
I
\
11
I:
f
I
i,
I
dl
Complementary Principle
152
The dialectical nature of quantum mechanics is reflected
in its very initial principles. In this connection the
principle of complementarity, put forth by Bohr, is of
special interest. This principle forms in fact the logical
foundation of the entire system of quantum-mechanical
ideas.
The essence of the principle of complementarity lies in
the following: it is stated that in any experiment with
microparticles, the observer gets information not about
the "properties of the particles themselves" but about
the properties of the particles associated with some par-
ticular situation including, among other things, the meas-
uring instruments. The information about the object
obtained under some definite conditions should be consid-
ered as complementary to the information obtained under
different conditions. Essentially, the information obtained
under different circumstances cannot be added, accumu-
lated or combined into a single picture; it reflects various
sides (complementing one another) of a single reality,
to wit the object under investigation. The principle of
complementarity finds a direct expression, in particular,
in the idea of wave-particle duality and in the uncertainty
relations.
According to Bohr, the term 'complementarity' is used
in order to stress that in the contrasting phenomena we have
to do with equally essential aspects of all; well-defined know-
ledge about the object (N. Bohr, "On the Notions of Causal-
ity and Complementarity") .
.. .In atomic physics the word 'complementarity'is used to
characterize the relationship between experiences obtained
by different experimental arrangements and visualizable
only by mutually exclusive ideas... (N. Bohr, "Natural
Philosophy and Human Cultures") .
.. .Evidence obtained under different experimental conditions
cannot be comprehended within a single picture, but must
be regarded as complementary... (N. Bohr, "Discussion
with Einstein on Epistemological Problems in Atomic
Physics").
In quantum physios, however, evidence about atomic
objects obtained by different experimental arrangements
exhibits a novel kind of complementary relationship. Indeed,
it must be recognized that such evidence which appears con-
tradictory when eombination into a single picture is attempt-
ed, exhausts all conceivable knowledge about the object
(N. Bohr, "Quantum Physics and Philosophy").
We advise the reader to carefully read the words of Bohr
once again. Thus, data about a microparticle may be
"graphically interpreted" only on the basis of "ideas mutu-
ally excluding one another". In this sense they cannot
be added in a simple way, and "cannot be contained in
a single picture". Various data have "peculiar" (the reader
must not let this epithet go unnoticed) relations with one
another, hence the term "complementarity". The peculi-
arity of the "complementarity" relations lies in the fact
that data "complementary" to one another may be ob-
tained only "under different experimental conditions".
The specific nature of quantum-mechanical ideas,
emphasized frequently in the foregoing, and their somewhat
unusual logic rests to a considerable extent on the prin-
ciple of complementarity. A microparticle is neither a cor-
puscle, nor a wave, but still we employ both these images,
which mutually exclude each other, for describing a micro-
particle. Just imagine the situation: the corpuscle and
wave pictures are used for describing an object which is
neither a corpuscle, nor a wave, nor even a symbiosis of
them! Naturally, this could give rise to a ticklish
question: Doesn't this mean an alienation of the image
from the object, which is fraught with a transition to the
position of subjectivism? A negative answer to this ques-
tion is given by the principle of complementarity itself.
From the position of this principle, pictures mutually
excluding one another are used as mutually complementary
pictures, adequately representing various sides of the
objective reality called the microparticle. According to
Bohr, this point is of great logical consequence, sin'ce it is
only the circumstance that we are presented with a choice
of either tracing the path of a particle or obserVing inter-
ference effects, which allows us to escape from the paradox-
ical necessity of concluding that the behaviour of an electron
or a proton should depend on the presence of a slit in the
diaphragm through which it could be proved not to pass.
It is true that dialectical nature is inherent in every
physical science to some extent. Still it may be stated that
classical physics, because of the very style of its philo-
sophy (unambiguous predictions in theories of dynamic
type, the approach to any object as a "combination" of
The Dialectical Nature of
Quantum Mechanics
153
certain "details", and to any phenomenon as a succession
of certain elementary events, etc.) is drawn towards
metaphysics. In this sense the significance of quantum
mechanics cannot be overestimated. It has convincingly
shown that a higher level of knowledge of the laws of
nature is inevitably linked with a deeper and more serious
knowledge and application of the methods of materialistic
dialectics.
In considering the cases in which the dialectical character
of quantum mechanics is especially manifested, we single
out two points which appear most important to us.
These are the statement of relations of dialectical type
and the application of the categories of dialectics.
Statement of Relations of Dialectical Type. Simple accu-
mulation, or summation of data, properties and concepts
are characteristic (we shall say that summation relations
are characteristic) of a metaphysical method. These rela-
tions to a considerable extent form the logical foundations
of classical physics. Quantum mechanics lays emphasis on
relations of a qualitatively different, dialectical type,
like the relations of complementarity and relations of inter-
ference. Thus, it shows that data about an object, strictly
speaking, do not simply add up but complement one ano-
ther, that the probabilities of different events, strictly
speaking, are not summed, but interfere with one another.
We have discussed these specific relations above when
considering the principle of complementarity and the spe-
cific nature of the application of probability in quantum
mechanics. When evaluating complementarity and inter- > ~
ference as new relations, or new interrelations correspond- f
I, ,
ing to a higher level of knowledge of the laws of nature,"
'/:
it can't be denied that quantum mechanics really deter-
mines the direction for the development of modern physics.
Application of the Categories ot Materialistic Dialectics.
In classical theories of dynamic typ(j' the concepts of
necessity and chance, possibility and actuality do not
appear as dialectical categories. Necessity here is abso-
lutely (metaphysically) the opposite of chance. The latter
is simply banished from the theory, which immediately
leads to an identification of the concepts of the possibility
and actuality. As dialectical categories, relations among
which is unity and struggle of opposites, these con-
cepts appear in statistical theories, primarily in quan-
tum mechanics. It is essential that in quantum mechanics
the dialectical categories of necessity and chance, possib-
ility and actuality are applied not only to the ensembles
of objects but also to an individual microparticle. The
application ,of dialectical categories in quantum mechanics
I
:1
I'
II
till
154
1
S
1
Y
f
s
c
r
e
e
s
s
s
11
y
Y
11
11
has been considered throughout this book when discuss-
ing certain questions. We remind the reader that an
analysis of the problem of causality in quantum mechanics
could be accomplished only on the basis of the dialectical
categories of necessity and chance. An explanation of the
quantum-mechanical superposition of states and its
destruction in the process of measurement was made pos-
sible only by using the dialectical categories of possibility
and actuality.
In conclusion, we: note that quantum mechanics has clearly
demonstrated the dialectical struggle between form and
content. In Bohr's words, the lesson we have hereby received
would seem to have brought us a decisive step further in the
neverending struggle for harmony between content and form,
and taught us once again that no content can be grasped
without a formal frame and that any form, however useful
it has hitherto ,proved, may be found to be too narrow to com-
prehend new experience.
,f
t
r
y
y
g
s
s
e
s
t: .....
...------------------_...
Interlude. Do Quantum-
Mechanical Concepts
Contradict Our Common
Sense?
In this unusual discussion the
author is joined by two
physicists (Bohr and Cooper) and
two Iiterateurs (Dobrolyubov and
Perrault).
Excerpts from the following
works have been used in the
discussion: N. Bohr, "Natural
philosophy and human cultures"
in "Atomic Physics and Human
Knowledge", 1958; N. Bohr,
"The Unity of Knowledge",
1955; N. A. Dobrolyubov, "What
Is Oblomovshchina?" 1948;
L. N. Cooper, "An Introduction
in the Meaning and Structure of
Physics", 1968; C. Perrault, "The
Sunshine Book" 1946.
Common sense is that layer of prejudice we ac-
quire before we are 16.
A. Einstein
In the balance between seriousness and humour,
characteristic of all truly artistic achievements, we
are reminded of complementary aspects conspicuous
in children's play and no less appreciated in ma-
ture life.
N. Bohr
f I
I
d
Cooper: There have been bitter complaints from some of our contem-
poraries, that physics in the twentieth century has become too
abstract, has lost touch with those things ordinary people can
understand, has lost contact with common sense and substituted
instead constructs so abstract that the ordinary mind can never
attain them.
Author: That is why I want to talk about quantum mechanics and
"common sense". I have many times heard the complaint that
quantum mechanics is hard to follow because its concepts are in
"contradiction to common sense". Unfortunately nobody knows
precisely the meaning of "common sense". If I am not mistaken,
you are of the view that "common sense" is a relative concept, and
that its meaning changes significantly with the development in
science. .; "
Cooper: Yes, it is a cliche that the commonsense of the new generation
is formed from concepts laboriously constructed by their elders,
that what is avant-garde for one generation is common sense and
prosaic for the next. It seems dubious that the Newtonian concep-
tion of the world would have been common sense to the Greeks
in the time of Aristotle, for that matter to the scholastic scholars
It was not even so for many of his contemporaries. And those so
enamored of common sense (at present Newton's world) are often
just those who complain that the mechanical Newtonian view
destroyed the magical medieval world.
Author: It is difficult to counter such a point of view. By the way, it
immediately solves the question posed by us at the very beginning.
Isn't it?
II 156
i'
II
I
Interlude
Cooper:
Author:
Bohr:
Author:
Bohr:
Author:
Bohr:
Author:
Bohr:
I think so, for the present generation of physicists it is quantum
physics that is common sense. It is the structure of the quantum
theory that is closest to them, relations of the quantum theory
that have an immediacy and an intuitive correctness....
However, without denying the justification of the point of
view mentioned above, let us try to solve the question of common
sense and look at this question from a more open position. More-
over, we would like to speak of the commonsense not of physicists,
but of "ordinary people", those who "bitterly complain" that the
"ordinary mind can never attain" the ideas of modern physics.
An approach from a more open position to the "common sense"
in quantum mechanics was strongly advocated by one of our ho-
noured participants. It would be nice to hear in this connection
his remarks on the complementarity principle, for example.
Using the word "complementarity" much as it is used in atomic
physics, to characterise the relationship between experiences ob-
tained by different experimental arrangements, and visualizable
only by mutually exclusive ideas, we may truly say that different
human cultures are complementary to each other. Indeed, each
such culture represents a harmonious balance of traditional con-
ventions by means of which latent potentialities of human life
can unfold themselves in a way which reveals to us new aspects
of its unlimited richness and variety.
What is there that an ordinary person cannot comprehend?
And yet the complementarity principle finally boils down to un-
certainty relations as well as wave-particle duality of micropar-
ticles. Meanwhile, all these incomprehensible ideas find their
due place not only in questions linked with human cultures but
even in quite common questions, for example questions linked
with psychology.
We all know the old saying that, if we try to analyse our own
emotions, we hardly possess them any longer, and in that sense
we recognise between physical experiences, for the descriptions
of which words such as "thoughts" and "feelings" are adequately
used, a complementary relationship similar to that between the
experiences regarding the behaviour of atoms obtained under
different experimental arrangements.
But can't we go one step further, and try to draw some anal-
ogies between modern ideas in physics and ideas contained in
famous literary works? It would be quite interesting to compare
poetical truth and scientific truth.
In other words, is there a poetical or spiritual or cultural truth
distinct from scientific truth?
Precisely.
We are indeed directly confronted with the relationship of
science and art. The enrichment which art can give us originates
in its power to remind us of harmonies beyond the grasp of sys-
tematic analysis.
157
f
I
i
I
Ii
I
:1
158
Author:
Dobrolyubov:
Author:
Dobroluybov:
Author:
Bohr:
Author:
Perrault:
Author:
I am extremely grateful to you. You have helped dispel some
of my doubts. I would now turn to particular examples, the first
example being Oblomov, a novel by 1. A. Goncharov. Let us recall
what one of our distinguished participants has written about the
image of Oblomov.
Well, take for example this: Oblomov's wishes always assume
the form "how good it would be if this were done", but how this
can be done he does not know. That is why he is so fond of dreaming
and dreads the moment when his dreams may come in contact
with reality.
I remember that you drew analogy between Oblomov and such
literary heroes as Onegin, Pechorin, Rudin.
Yes, indeed. But the point is that they all have one common
feature-a fruitless striving for activity, the consciousness that
they could do a great deal but will do nothing.
(to Bohr): And what would you say to this?
I would say that the relation between the experience of a feeling
of volition and conscious pondering on motives for action is es-
pecially instructive.';.
I should state that the ideas expressed by my learned friends
pertain to different situations and were profounded at different
times. And yet they do have something in common. To a certain
extent the personal tragedy of Oblomov lies in his inability to
overcome the dialectical contradiction between the possible and
the actual. Potentially, much is vested in Oblomov; this is an
evidence of the considerable superposition of possibilities. But
the "act of measurement", which would allow Oblomov to realize
some aspect of his nature at the cost of this superposition is miss-
ing. This actl does not occur, the superposition is not destroyed
and everything remains as it was.
Let us now consider the second literary example, the famous fairy-
tale "Cinderella" by Charles Perrault. Will you please narrate the
scene in which the fairy godmother sees I laIl
at King's palace.
Here you are: The fairy godmother then' said to Cinderella,
"Her(is a coach fit for the ball, and coachman and footmen" .... As
Cinderella stepped into the carriage, her fairy godmother said,
"Remember, you must not stay a minute after twelve, for if you
do, your coach will become a pumpkin again, the horses will turn
back into mice; the footmen will become lizards, and the coachman
will become a rat; and your dress will turn to rags."
Thank you. I wanted to draw your attention to the fact that
the omnipotent fairy godmother gave the coach and the dress to
Cinderella only for a while, until midnight. And why not for good?
It is clear that she could have done that but it would be agailllst
the inherent logic and the central idea of the tale. It would, so
to say, take away the "charm". If it is for a while, well and good;
but if it is for ever, there is no charm. Doesn't it remind us of a
model of virtual transitions? The conservation laws are violated,
treasures are created out of "nothing" with the help of a magic wand,
but all this is allowed only for a finite interval of time-"until
midnight". After this, Cinderella must return to her previous state,
and without the beautiful dress. Just compare: a quantum system
visits a new level without any expenditure of energy from outside,
only for a limited interval of time after which the system must
return to its previous level. In the same way, Cinderella performs
l'virtual transitions" between her house and the royal palace, enjoys
and dances but is careful not to overstep the agreed time limit.
Then a messenger with the crystal slipper appears on the scene.
Please narrate what happened after this.
Perrault: The messenger, who had been sent with the slipper, said that
everyone was to try it. He looked at Cinderella and saw that she
was beautiful. He ordered her to sit dOwn and put the slipper on
It fitted her perfectly... Just then the fairy godmother appeared
and touched Cinderella with her wand and her rags became a dress
more beautiful than any she had yet worn.
Author: And so, it came true. The fairy godmother gave Cinderella
the dress to keep for ever. The virtual transition led to a real tran-
sition by Cinderella to "a new level". The prince, the slipper, the
messenger-all played the role of the photon which, by interacting
with the system undergoing virtual transitions, has led to a real
transition. Of course, the Cinderella story should not be seriously
taken as an illustration of the idea of virtual transitions, as an
explanation of quantum jumps. In the same way the novel Oblomov
should not be seriously taken as an illustration of the principle of
superposition of states or as an explanation of the problem of
destruction of superposition in the act of measurement. However,
it is easy to see the general internal logic in the comparison drawn
above.
Bohr: It may not be irreverent to remark that even at the climall'
of his work the artist relies on this common human foundation
on which'twe stand.
Author: With this interesting discussion we come to the end of our
consideration of the basic concepts of quantum mechanics. Of
course, quantum-mechanical ideas are quite unusual and peculiar.
And yet they did not appear from nothing but rather arose on the
basis of a solid foundation of concepts and ideas which are a result
of the entire human experience. Hence the analogies between phys-
ical models and[ literary images are not incidental, but trather
inevitable.
..---'J
Section 17.
Section 18.
Section 19.j
Section 20.
Section 21.
Section 22.
Section 23.
Section 24.
Section 25.
Section 26.
A Brief Look at the Theory of Linear Operators 163
From Hamiltonian Matrix to Energy Operator 171
Linear Operators in Quantum Mechanics 177
The Quantum-Mechanical Apparatus in Coordinate
Representation 184
Applications of the Schrodinger Equation 195
The Hamiltonian in Some Specific Problems 208
Transition to the Momentum Representation 215
An Electron in a Periodic Field 220
The Probability of Quantum Transitions 228
Ways of Describing Evolution of Micr0sYs(ems with
Time 233
i
i i
[;Chapter 3
1) Linear Operators
in Quantum Mechanics
~ '.. ,
3
,')
I
~ ,
,!
7
t
i I
.
i
Ii
1\
i
lip-----------------------c:r
Some General Remarlcs
162
Every physical theory is a synthesis of certain physical
ideas (advanced on the basis of experiment) and a certain
mathematical apparatus. The building-up of a theory is
a complicated and controversial process developing accord-
ing to successive approximations. However, in this contro-
versial process, at least in its initial stage, a completely
definite logical structure is envisaged, including three
logically successive stages: (1) a stage in which the basic
ideas are formulated and interpreted, and the physical
foundation of the theory is built; (2) a stage in which
an adequate mathematical aparatus for the physical ideas
is found and the physical ideas and the mathematical
apparatus are linked together, Le. it is postulated exactly
what physical meaning corresponds to the various mathe.
matical symbols (as a result, the mathematical relations
acquire the meaning of physical laws), and (3) a stage
in which the "physicized" mathematical apparatus is "set
to work". The new results thus obtained are checked exper-
imentally where this is possible. This leads to a further
understanding of the physical content of theory an&to
a further development of its apparatus.
At the time of creation of a theory the mathematical
apparatus adequate for the description of physical ideas
mayor may not be available. When Newton created his
mechanics, he also had to work out the corresponding
mathematical apparatus-the method of fluxions which
later developed into differential and integral calculus.
But when quantum mechanics was created, the appro-
priate mathematical apparatus was already available in
the form of theory of linear operators.
In Quantum Physics and Philosophy [6], Bohr writes
... in quantal formalism, the quantities by u"hich the state
of a physical system is ordinarily defined are replaced by
symbolic operators subjected to a non-commutative algorism
involVing Planck's constant. This procedure'prevents a fixa-
tion of such quantities to the extent which would be reqUired
for the deterministic description of classical physics, but
allows us to determine their spectral distribution as revealed
by evidence about atomic processes. In conform ity with the
non-pictorial character of the formalism, its physical inter-
pretation finds expression in laws, of an essentially statisti-
cal type...
Turning to the mathematical aspect of quantum theory,
we shall consider below how quantum-mecbanical ideas
"are introduced into" the apparatus of linear operators. We
shall demonstrate the working of this apparatus by a num-
ber of specially selEcted examples and problems.
1
I
linear Operators (Basic
Definitions)
17-
Section
A Brief Look at the Theory
of Linear Operators
This section is essentially mathEmatical in nature. It
includes different questions on the theory of linear opera-
tors. In other words, it describes the fundamentals of the
mathematical apparatus which proved to be suitable for
the creation of quantum theory. We emphasize that in
this section none of the mathematical symbols is "loaded"
with any physical meaning.
An operator, when applied to some function, transfmms
it into a new function. The notation
L1p (x) = cp (x) (17.1)
means that the operator denotEd by the symbol L acts
on the function 1p (x), as a result of which we get function
cp (x).
The operator L is called linear if it satisfies the condi-
tions
L (1pi +'!'2) = L'!'i +1'!'2; 1 (a'!') = (17.2)
where a is some number. We shall be using only linear
operators below.
The effect of an operator acting on a function be
represented as a definite or an improper integral:
f1p (x) = f (y) dy. (17.3)
The quantity L (x, y) is called the kernel of the operator.
If the variable is discrete, we will have instead of (17.3)
L'!'n = LJ (17.4)
m
The totality of coefficients L
nm
forms the matrix of the
operator [, and we speak of the matrix representation
of the operator. A matri:x representation is
sible because the kernel L (x, y) in (17.3) may obviously
be treated as a continuous matrix.
Suppose .L1p = cp; the operator L* is called the complex
conjugate of the operator L, if by the action of this opera-
tor on the function 1p* we get the function cp*:
L*,!,*(x)=cp* (x). (17.5)
The operator I is said to be the transpose of the operator
L if the following condition is satisfiEd:
r'l'(x)I.L,!,(xrdx = J,!,(x)L'l'(X)dx.,
Sec. 17
The kernel of the transposed operator satisfies the condi-
tion
L (x, y) = L (y, x).
while the matrix satisfies the condition
(17.7)
(17.8)
I
f
Let us consider some linear operator . Let us find its
complex conjugate operator L*. We then find the transpo-
sed operator L* for the operator L*. This operator is
denoted by + and is said to be conjugate to the operator t.
By using the concept of the conjugate operator, two impor-
tant types of linear operators are defined: Hermitian
operators and unitary operators. If
L=L+, (17.9)
the operator L is called Hermitian (self-adjoint). If
(17.10)
the operator L is said to be a unitary operator. Note that
unitary operators are usually denoted by the symbol (j.
The matrix of a unitary operator satisfies the condition
(17.11)
Note an important property of unitary operators. Sup-
pose Unm'!'m = lpn' It can be easily seen that
m
(17.12)
164
The basic equation of the theory of linea,lO operators has the
form'
'!'=A'!'. (17.13)
The numbers A for which the equation (17.13) has finite
solutions, form the spectrum of eigenvalues of the operator [
The spectrum of eigenvalues of an operator may be con-
tinuous, discrete or mixed. The solutions,!, (x) of equa-
tion (17.13) are called the eigenfunctions of the opera-
tor i. One or more may correspond to
a given eigenvalue. If s linearly independent eigenfunc-
tions correspond to a certain value AI, it is said that the
Al is s-fold degenerate.
We shall state three theorems concerning the basic Properties of Hermitian Operators
properties of Hermitian operators. (The proofs of the
first two theorems are given in Appendix A.)
First Theorem
An operator has real eigenvalues if and only if it is Hermi-
tian.
Second Theorem
The eigenfunctions of a Hermitian operator, correspond-
ing to different eigenvalues, are mutually orthogonal.
Let .L'ljJn = Anti-ln. The theorem states that for An =t= Am,
(x) 'ljJn (x) dx = O. (17.14)
Since (17.13) is "hbmogeneous, the eigenfunctions are
determined upto an arbitrary constant multiplier. We
choose this multiplier so that the normalization condi-
tion is satisfied:
J (17.15)
By combining (17.14) and (17.15), we get the condition
of orthonormalization of the eigenfunctions of a Hermi-
tian operator:
j (17.16)
If the spectrum of the operator is continuous, we get
instead of (17.16)
.\ (17.17)
Let us consider the case of the s-fold degeneracy of an
eigenvalue. The eigenfunctions corresponding to this
eigenvalue are, generally speaking, not orthonormalized.
However, we can form s linear combinations of the
given functions which satisfy the condition of orthonor,
mal ization.
Third Theorem
Any bounded function may be expanded in a series
(integral) of eigenfunctions of a Hermitian operator.
In other words, the system of eigenfunctions of a Hermi-
tian operator is a closed (complete) one.
Using the last theorem, we represent any particular
function dl(x) in the form of a series of
'ljJn (x): dl = In order to find C
n
, we multiply
n
Sec. 17 165
(17.19)
(17.20)
Representations
166
this equation by (x) and int.gmt. with ,"speet to x:r
) 'P;';. (x) <I> (x) dx = :c
n
f 'P;';. (x) 'Pn (x) dx.
n
Using (17.16), we get from this
5 2: c
n
6
mn
=c
m
n
Thus,
<I> (x) = Cn'Pn (x), }
where (17.18)
Average Energy
where r
1
, r
2
, r
3
are three Cartesian coordinates in space.
In this case the relation ~ = iI; acquires the form which
is familiar to those who have studied vector analysis:
...,. ...,.
c = curl a.
In conclusion let us reiterate the various aspects of the
vector analogy: (a) corresponding to the choice of basic
states, we have a choice of the system of coordinate axes;
(b) a transition from one set of basic states to a.nother
corresponds to a transition from one system of axes to
another (note that such a transition does not involve
the physics of the problem being considered); (c) the
expansion into basic states corresponds to a representation
of the vector in terms of its projections on the coordinate
axes. The analogy with vectors is a good example of
abstraction and of the representation of relations in
a form taking into account only strictly physical infor-
mation.
Let us demonstrate some of the advantages of the oper-
ator approach. We shall show how the mean value
(E) of the energy of a microparticle in some state (3 I
is determined. Let {(i I} be the basic states with ener-
gies E j This means (see Sec. 13) that the Hamiltonian
175
p------------------.,..
matrix is diagonal. Hence,
(j 1Ii Ii) = {jiJEft
or
(jIHli) = (jli) E
i
(18.13)
We expand the state (s I in terms of the system of basic
states {(i I : (s I = LJ (s Ii>(i I, and try to find the mean
value of tHe energy <1? >with the help of a formula of
the type (12.3):
(E) = I(sli) 1
2
E
i
(18.14)
i
By taking (9.33) into account, we rewrite (18.14) in the
form
(E) = 2}(sli}E
i
(i!s}=(slcp}, (18.15)
i
where
"
!cp) = Ii} E
i
(ils).
i
From (18.13) it follows that
H!i) = Ii) E
i
Substituting (18.17) in (18.16), we get
!cp) = Hli}(ils}=Hls},
i
(18.16)
(18.17)
after which we get the required result from (18.15):
(E> = (3 I iI I 3 >.
(18.18)
Energy Operator (Hamiltonian)
176
It can be seen from (18.18) that mean value of the energy
of a microparticle in the state (s Iis expressed only through
the operator iI. Basic states do not enter this relation.
The convenience of the relation (18.18) is due to its inde-
pendence from the choice of basic states, which allows
one to use freely any system of basic states when carrying
out calculations. For example, suppose it is convenient
to use the basic states {(m I}. In this case the operator
relation (18.18) immediately acquire the corresponding
form
(E) = 2] 2] (slm) (mIHln) (nls). (18.19)
m n
It has been mentioned above that the Hamiltonian
matrix could be called the energy matrix (remember
that the elements of the diagonalized Hamiltonian matrix
(18.21)
(18.12)
(18.18)
(18.20)
i
'.
Using (18.21) and taking into account that (il s) = ct,
we can rewrite (18.2) in a form which, as can be easily
seen, is completely analogous in form to (18.12):
in ~ (i Is (t) = Ii (i Is (t. (18.22)
Correspondingly, (18.20) may be written in the form
H (i I f) = E (i I f). (18.23)
are essentially the possible values of the energy of the
roicroparticle). The connection between the operator Ii
and the Hamiltonian matrix as well as relation (18.18),
expressing the average energy ofIa microparticle in terms
of the operator H, justify the name energy operator given
to it. In the literature the operator H is also called the
Hamiltonian.
We write expressions derived above in which the Hamil-
tonian of a microparticle is present (we emphasize the
exceptional importance of these expressions):
~ Is (t) = His (t),
dt
(E) = (sIHls),
HI!) = If) E.
.
In expression (18.20), (f I denotes some stationary state
and E is the energy in this state.
Finally, we note that the Hamiltonian (as well as any
other operator) may act not only on the state Is), but
also en its amplitude (i Is), since we always have the
representation [see (17.4)1
HCi(t) = 2J HiJC
j
(t).
j
We now come to the main problem of this chapter, Le.
that of imparting physical meaning to the mathematical
apparatus of linear operators in order to convert it into
the apparatus of quantum mechanics. In this sense the
previous section should be considered as a preliminary
step towards solving this problem.
The following two points must be noted when consider-
ing the role of linear operators in quantum mechanics.
Firstly, in quantum mechanics to every dynamic variable
(spatial coordinate, energy, momentum, angular momen-
Section 19
Linear Operators in
Quantum Mechanics
Role of Operators in Quantum
Mechanics
p---------------,-
tum, etc.), there is assigned a definite Hermitian opera-
tor.
Secondly, the transition from one representation to an.,.
other without changing the physical meaning of the prolr-
lem is achieved with the help of unitary operators.
Let us consider the first point in detail. It means that
besides the energy operator fl, other "physical operators"
like the coordinate operator;-' the operator
the angular momentum operator if, etc. must be
duced. In this respect, it if' significant that the well-
known dynamic relations vf classical mechanics may be
transferred to quantum me.t.hanics in the same form, if
we replace the physical quantities in these relations by the
corresponding Hermitian operators. In other words, the
apparatus of quantum mechanics may be built up in
analogy with the apparatus of classical mechanics, if we
replace the dynamic variables with their corresponding
Hermitian operators. As an example, let us compare the
following expressions:
In classical mechanics
I
In quantum mechanics
p2
I
p2
(19.1)
E= 2m+U H= 2m+U
- -
-
I
- - -
M=(rx p)
M=(rX p)
(19.2)
It should be remembered, however, that a complete formal
analogy between the apparatus of classical and quantum
mechanics does not exist. We point out (for details see
Sec. 20) that in the algebraic manipulation of operator
relations we must remember that operators may not com-
mute. Thus if ..4 and Bdo not commute, then (..4 + B)'1. =1=
=1=..4'1. + 2AB + jJ'1.. In this case (A + B)'1. = A2 + AB+
+ BA + B'1.. Besides, there are operators in quantum
mechanics which do not have classical analogies (for
example, the spin operator).
Note that we may formally assign corresponding opera-
tors to all classical dynamical variables including those
which do not have any meaning in the microworld.
Thus, we may introduce the operators of velocity;,
of potential energy 0, kinetic energy T, etc., though
neither velocity nQr the breaking-up of total energy into
kinetic and potential components which is characteristic
178
for classical mechanics, have any meaning for micropar-
ticles.
Let us consider the question: In exactly what way can
we compare a physical quantity with a Hermitian opera-
tor? In other words, what is the meaning of the word
"compare" here? The following two basic postulates pro-
vide an answer to this question.
Postulate 1. If the operator L is compared with aphys-
ical quantity l, it means that the eigenvalues A of the
operator are identified with the values of the physical
quantity under consideration obtained by measurement.
Postulate 2. If operator L is compared Fith a physical
quantity l, it means that the eigenfunctions 'Iv,. (a) of
the operator are identified with the eigenfunctions of the
quantities from theA-set, expressed in a-representation.
By the remarks nul.de in Sec. 15, this means that the
eigenfunctions '1. (a) of the operator are identified with
the amplitudes of states {Ala >, often called the wave
functions. ' . .
Thus a study of the fundamental equation of the theory
of linear operators [see (17.13)]' '
..... j I
L (a){Ala) = A(Ala) (19.3)
includes physical problems such as finding the spectrum
of possible values Aof a physical quantity l, and finding
the amplitudes of states {A I a> in which the correspond-
ing values of A occur.
When applied to the energy operator, (19.3) takes the
form of (18.23). A study of equation (18.23) permits us
to find the possible values of the energy.of a microparticle
and the corresponding amplitUde values O'f the stationary
states.
The postulates formulated above "knit together" the
-physical and mathematical aspects; they "load" the mathe-
matical symbols and inferences with a definite physical
meaning. We shall demonstrate this with a _number of
observations.
1. The eigenvalues of a Hermitian operator are real.
From a physical point of view this means that the values
of quantities obtained during measurements are real.
2. The spectrum of the eigenvalues of a Hermitian opera-
tor may be discrete or continuous. This corresponds to
quantization or a continuous variation of the physical
quantities characterizing a microparticle.
3. The eigenfunctions of a Hermitian operator satisfy
the condition of orthonormalization. This mathematical
'lact becomes the condition of orthonormalization of eigen-
1unctions of physical quantities and, in particular, the
Basic Postulates
Mathematical Results and Their
Physical Meaning
I'
t
p
t80
condition 01 orthogonality 01 basic states 01 a micro-T
particle. In other words, the mathematical result' (17.16) !
is converted into physical relations (15.13) and (10.8),
while the mathematical result (17.17) is converted into
the physical relation (15.14).
4. The system of eigenfunctions of a Hermitian operator
is a closed (complete) one. From a physical point of
view, this means that it is possible to expand any ampli-
tude in terms of amplitudes which are eigenfunctions of
a physical quantity, Le. in terms of basic amplitudes. In
other words, the completeness of a system of eigenfunc-
tions of a Hermitian operator is converted into the phys-
ical principle of superposition of states.
5. The eigenvalues of a Hermitian operator may be degen-
erate. Physically this means that one value of a quan-
tity may correspond to several different states.
6. The mathertical result (17.28) for the eigenfunctions
of operators corresponds to the physical result (9.33)
for amplitudes of states.
7. Unitary transformations corresponding to the transi-
tion from one representation to another, physically cor-
respond to a transition from one complete set of quanti-
ties to another and, in particular, from one system of
basic states of a. microparticle to another.
8. ,The existence of a common complete system of eigen-
functions means that the operators commute. This mathe-
matical fact corresponds to the possibility of 8imulta-
noous measurement of the corresponding physical values.
Note ,that the impossibility of the simultaneous measure-
~ n t of such physical quantities as the coordinate and
momentum of a microparticle means that the operators of
coordinate and momentum do not commute.
9,. The mathematical fact of commutativity of the Hamil-
tonian it and the operator meanstllt. physically the
quantity l corresponding to the o p r t ~ r L is an integral
of'motion. In other words, the condition
IH, L] = 0
from the physical point of view is the law of conservation
of the quantity 1.
The last remark will be rigorously proved below. Here,
we shall just mention Some ideas of a qualitative nature
for this purpose. If operators iI and L commute, the
quantities E and 1can be simultaneously measured since
there are states in which both these quantities have defi-
nite values. A state in which energy has a definite value
;is stationary, Le. has an infinitely long "life" time. But
I
I.........'.. . ~ - 5 ;
t ..
this means that the quantity 1 must also be conserved
for an infinitely long time, just like any other physical
quantity for which the given state is an eigenfunction.
If the quantity 1 is measured in a state described
by the amplitude (AI ex), then, according to basic postu-
lates, the measured value will be A. We assume now that
the quantity 1 is measured not in its eigenstate, but in
some "other" state, for example, in the state described
by the amplitude <1>s (ex) = (3 I ex). In this case the result
of a single measurement cannot be predicted unambiguous-
ly; probabilistic predictions enter into the picture now,
thus permitting an estimation of the mean value (A)
from a relatively large number of measurements (in this
connection see Sec. 12). We shall show how to compute
the mean value (A) in the state (s I, if we know the Hermi-
tian operator L corresponding to the quantity l. Note
that in the particular case when energy is used in place
of the quantity l, this problem was considered in Sec. 18,
where the following result was obtained:
Mean Value of a Quantity
(we assume for definiteness in this case that the variable ex
which characterizes the representation varies contin-
uously). Let us prove this.
We expand the amplitudes <1>s (ex) and <1>:(ex) in terms
of eigenfunctions 'n (ex) = (An I ex) of the operator (we
assume that the spectrum of the operator L is discrete):
<E) = (3 I Ii Is).
In the general case, (18.18) takes the form
(A) = J<1>: (ex) L(ex) <1>s (ex) dex
(18.18)
(19.4)
<1>s (ex) = 2l (siAn) 'n (ex),
n
<D: (ex) = ~ (sIA
m
)* ~ (ex).
m
Substituting these superpositions in (19.4) and using
(19.3) and (17.16), we get
J<1>: (ex) L (ex) <D
s
(ex) dex
= ~ ~ (sIAn)(SIAm)* J ~ (ex) L (ex) 'iJn (ex) dex
n m
. ~ ~ (sIAn)(sIA
m
)* An J ~ (ex) '!'n (ex) dex
n m
Sec. 19
181
i'
'.
n m n
By (12.3), the last sum is equal to {A >, Q.E.D.
The result (19.4) is very important. In fact this one result
is sufficient to demonstrate the usefulness of the applica-
tion of operators in quantum mechanics.
In analogy with (18.18), the result (19.4) can be written
in a more abstract form which avoids a choice of repre-
sentation:
<A> = {s I Is>. (19.5)
The Variation of the Mean Value Using (19.5) and assuming at the outset that the op-
of a Quantity with Time erator L is independent of time, let us write
d d
dt (P.) = dt (s (t) IL Is (t
=( :t (s(t)I) lils(t+<s(t)ILI (:t Is(t). (19.6)
Further, we turn to (18.12) and transform it into the form
d A
- in at (s (t) I = (s (t) IH+,
or, taking into account the hermiticity of the Hamil-
tonian,
d
- in_
tlk
(s (t) I = (s (t) ,H. (19.7)
Substituting (18.12) and (19.7) into (19.6), we get
d i
dt (A) = h (s (t)IHL -LHls (t),
or
d i
;:rt(A)=n(sl[H, L]18). (19.8)
If the quantity 1 is an integral of motion, ft(A) = O.
It follows from (19.8) that the above-mentioned condi-
tion [Ii, L1 = 0 is a condition for the conservation of
he quantity l.
We introduce a new operator i, defining it by the relation
d
(s ILl s) = dt (A). (19.9)
Comparing (19.9) with (19.8), we conclude that in the
case when L is independent of time, the operator L
182
:1>9
*., L =-;:; [H, L].
If L varies with time, we get instead of (19.10)
(19.Hl)
(19.11)
The physical meaning of any result is obviously inde- Unitary Invariance of Physical
pendent of the choice of a representation. In other words, Results
the physical meaning of a result should not change upon
a transition from one representation to another. Since
these transitions are accomplished by means of unitary
transformations, it means that physical results must enter
the mathematical apparatus as unitary invariants.
Thus, the requirement of unitary invariance of corre-
sponding results may serve as an additional criterion of the
correctness of the basic postulates formulated above and
the consequences that follow from them. In this connec-
tion, we first mention the fact of unitary invariance of
the property of hermiticity of an operator mentioned
in Sec. 17, and also the unitary invariance of the spectrum
()f eigenvalues of a Hermitian operator. I t is easy to see
that the commutator [fI, Ll is also a unitary invariant
and, consequently, the condition of conservation of any
physical quantity is, as expected, independent of the
choice of a representation. We mention further that uni-
tary invariance of the relation J dx now indicates
the i Ildependence from the choice of representation of the
-condition of orthonormalization of eigenfunctions of a
physical quantity. Finally, unitary invariance of the
-expression ) <D* r(x) L (x) <D (x) dx indicates the inde-
pendence from the choice of representation of the mean
values of physical quantities.
Note that the result (19.4) could have been obtained unambiguous-
ly from the requirement of the unitary invariance of the quantity
<1..) using the expression (18.18) obtained for a special case. Indeed,
from the requirement of unitary invariance it follows that (I..)
must be represented by an expression of the type
) <Xl. (x) in (x) <D (X) dx,
and a comparison with the particular result (i8.i8) indicates that
in this case n must be put equal te t.
Sec. 19
183
Section 20
r
f
Operators of Coordinate and
Momentum
18A
The Quantum-Mechanical
Apparatus in Coordinate
Representation
A further treatment of the apparatus of quantum mechan-
ics requires a knowledge of the definite form of the oper-
ators of various physical quantities. For this it is essen-
tial to choose a definite representation. Let us choose the
coordinate representation for this purpose.
Note the importance of finding the form of the two basic
"physical operators", the coordinate and the momentum
of a microparticle. Knowing these operators, we may
obtain the energy operator [see (19.1)] and the angular
momentum operator [see (19.2)1.
For simplicity we shall consider one-dimensional motion
along the xi-axis (the result so obtained can be easily gen-
eralized to a. three-dimensional case). Taking into account
the remarks made in Sec. 17 about the form of Hermitian
operator in its eigen representation [see (17.26)], we con-
clude that the operator of a coordinate in the coordinate
representation is the coordinate itself:
x (x) = x. (20.1}
This result can be generalized to any coordinate function:
V (x) = lZ{x). (20.2)
Let us now try to find the form of the momentum opera-
tor. First we shall prove the following theorem. Suppose
an operator {j somehow transforms a coordinate. If the
Hamiltonian Ii remains invariant under this transfor-
mation, the operators lJ and H commute. Proof: Let
Ox = x'; we act on H (x) 1J' (aJ) with the operator {)
to get on (x) 1J' (:) = Ii (x') 1J' (x') = iJ. (x) 1J' (x') =
= H (x) VIp (x), which proves the theo,rem.
Suppose the operator 0 is the operator of infinitesimal
translation along the x-axis: 61J' (x) = 'I\J (x + dx). Mak-
ing use of the smallness of the translation, we write
(X+dX)=[1+dX (x)
Thus
d
0= 1+dxa;-
Proceeding from the properties of homogeneity of space.
we conclude that an operation by {) must leave the Hamil-
tonian of a microparticle invariant. Hence, according
to the theorem proved above, we obtain [6, H] = 0
1
..... >.' ..... '.,
or L ~ h] = O. Bm it was shown above in Sec. 19 that
a commutation with the Hamiltonian expresses the law
of conservation of a physical quantity. This means that
dld:JJ is the operator of Some physical quantity which is
conserved. We know that momentum is a quantity whose
conservation is a consequence of the homogeneity of
space (see Sec. 1). Consequently, the operator dldx must
coincide with the momentum operator of a microparticle
up to some constant factor:
II ...
(fX= 'VPx' (20.3)
The factor y is determined from a consideration of the lim-
iting transition from quantum" mechanics to classical
mechanics (see Appendix B). It can be shown that y =
= i/n. Thus the operator of the x-component of a micro-
particle momentuih in the coordinate representation has
the form
A d
Px = - ~ h dZ' (20.4)
The results (20.1) and (20.4) can be easily generalized
to a three-dimensional case:
r== r, (20.5)
~
p== -in'V. (20.6)
Using (20.4), we can write an equation for the eigen- Eigenfunctions of Momentum
functions of the x-component of the momentum:
-in :x ljJpx (x) = PX'Px (x). (20.7)
It can be easily seen that (20.7) can be solved for any
values of the parameter P.t. Consequently, the momentum
of a microparticle is not quantized (the spectrum of the
eigenvalues of the momentum is continuous).
From equation (20.7) it follows that the eigenfunctions
of operator Px have the form of plane waves:
\lJPIll (x) = A exp (iP
x
x/1i); (20.8)
To determine the factor A, we make use of the condition
of orthonormalization (17.17):
JljJ* p; (x) 'Px (x) dx = <') (Px- p;).
SUbstituting (20. 8) into this equation, we find
4'1
2
. Jexp [- ix (p:- Px)/1i} dx = <') (Px- p ~ .
'.
f ,1
"l ,
f',
185
Schrodinger Equation
Further, taking into account (15.17), we obtain
i exp fix (Px- p;)/n] dx = 2:rtM(Px- p;).
Comparing the last two equations, we get A2 == (2nnt1.
Consequently,
'/Jp (x) = (2nn)-1/2 exp(ipxxlh). (20.9)
x
A generalization for the three-dimensional case gives
'/J-p (;:) = (2nn):o:3/2 exp (ipr!1i). ;(20.10)
Note that the eigenfunction of the momentum (20.10)
coincides with the wave function (15.15) derived in
Sec. 15 tor a freely moving microparticle.
Let us consider the equation (18.23) for eigenfunctions
of a ,Hamiltonian:
. /'
Hrp (x)=Erp (x). (
E
Using (19.1) for the Hamiltonian of a microparticle
moving in an external field with potential U (:Il), and
taking into aC(jount (20.2) and (20.4), we get
h2 d2
HI(X) = - 2m dx
2
+U(x). (20.12)
Substituting (20.12) into (20. 11), we get
h
2
d
2
e
- 2m dx2 rpg (X) +[U (X) -; 1rpE (X) = O. (20.13)
This is the one-di mensional SchriJdinger equ,ation. Gener-
alizing it for the three-dimensional case, we write
(20.14)
Knowing the functions cp g (:Il), we may write the expres-
sions for amplitudes of stationary states 'YE (:Il, t), since
the time dependence in this case has the universal form
discussed in Sec. 13. Using (13.4) and taking into account
the fact that!
'Yg (x, t)= (E I X, t}=(x, t I (t),
(20.15)
1'86
we get
'Yg (x, t)=rpB (x) exp (-iEt/1i). (20.16)
I t can be easily seen that the functions 'Y (:Il, t) are
the solutions of equation (18.22), where the Hamiltonian
(20.12) has been used in place of fl. In this case, the equa-
tion has the form
(20.17)
The operator of the square of angular momentum is given
by the expression
It is also called the Schrodinger equation More precisely,
equation (20.13) is called the time-independent Schrodinger
equation and the equation (20.17) is called the time-
dependent Schrodinger equation.
Schrodinger's contribution was that he guessed (yes,
guessed!) how to write the Hamiltonian of a microparticle
in the form (20.12). It is true that in our discussions (20.12)
does not appear unexpectedly, it appears here as a conse-
quence of results (19.1), (20.2) and (20.4). It should,
however, be l'emembered that (19.1) has not been derived
here, in fact it was.postulated (more precisely, an analogy
between classical and quantum-mechanical relations was
postulated). When Schrodinger proposed his famous
equation, this analogy was not yet apparent. Moreover,
the result (20.12) itself, as we shall see below, served
as the basis for this analogy. (For establishing the rela-
tion (20.17), we may make use of the transition from
quantum to classical mechanics-see Appendix B.)
, By using (19.2) and (20.4) we can easily get the expres-
for the operators of projections of the angular mo-
mentum:
. a a) 'I
M = -in(y --Z-. I
x 'Uz dy' I
(d a )
M = - in z - - x -
Y ax az' I
M
' (a a) J
= - ili x - - y - .
z ay ax
(20.18)
(20.19)
Operators of the Angular
Momentum Projections and the
Square of Angular Momentum
'.
While considering the angular momentum operators, it is
convenient to use spherical coordinates r, a, <p instead
of Cartesian coordinates x, y, z: '
:t= r sin acos <p, }
Y.= r sin asin <p,
Z = rcos a.
(20.20)
187
(20.21)
,
Using (20.20), we represent the derivative a ~ ' in
form
a iJl/J ax al/J all al/J az
acp 'IjJ = ax aqJ +ay aqJ +az aqJ
alp . e . al/J. e
= -a;; rsm smtp+ayrsm costp
=(x3--
y
3-).h.
ay "ax 'f'
From this, with the help of (20.18), we get
iII = -in3-
z aqJ
In a similar way from the derivative a .1, we find
ae 'f'
(20.22)
Commutation Relations
M M ~ n +" (a e a)
x + i y= e-
1
(j) + as +i cot acp
from which, with the ht!If of (20.19), we get
~ L' 1 a
2
1 a (. a )-1
M2 = - n
2
sin2e acp2 + sin e as sm eas J. (20.23)
These relations form the commutation rules for the
operators of coordinate, momentum and angular momen-
tum of a microparticle. Denoting the Cartesian compo-
nents of these operators by subscripts i, j, k, we can
write these commutation rules (it will be shown later
on how they may be derived):
(20.24)
(20.25)
(20.26)
(20.27)
(20.28)
(20.29)
(20.30)
[ril rj] =0.
A A
[Pi,Pj]=O,
LPil rj] = - i'h6ij ,
A ,.. ~ a . ~
[Pi> t (r)] = - in -at (r),
rt
[.111 il ;j] = in ~ eijk;k,
II.
[M
i
, Pj] = in ~ eijkPk,
II.
~ ~ '\.' ~
[Mil MJl = in L.J eij.kMk
II.
Here etJk is a unit antisymmetric tensor of the 3rd rank,
e123 = e
2
31 = e312 = 1, e
132
= e
321
= e213 = -1, and the
remaining 21 components of thi s tensor are equal to zero
(in these components at least twolsubscripts have the
same value). It can be easily seen; that in summations
with respect to k not more than one term is present.
188'
ln the coordinate representation ri = ri; therefore, the
..esult (20.24) is obvious. It means that all three coordi-
nates of a microparticle can be measured simultaneously
{as was mentioned in Sec. 3, they OCcur in the same com-
iplete set of quantities).
Prom (20.4), we write
p.].1._ -n
2
(_8
2
8
2
_).1.
II J '" - 8ri 8rj 8rj 8ri "'.
Since the value of the mixed derivative is independent of
1;he order in which the differentiation is carried out, it
follows that [Pi> Pi] = O. This result means that all the
1;hree components of momentum can be measured simul-
otaneously (they belong to the same complete set of quan-
otities).
"The result (20.2&) IS derived in the following way:
:{Pi, ij] '\jJ= -in (rj'\jJ)-rj '\jJ}
.f, 8rj .1.
= - Ut 8ri '" = - lnUij'\jJ.
It means that components of momentum and coordinate
which have different subscripts can be simultaneously
measured, while components with like subscripts are
unmeasurable, in complete accord with the uncertainty
,relations for coordinate and momentum of a micropar-
ticle described in Sec. 3. The result (20.26) also indicates
that the three components of coordinate and the three
eomponents of momentum enter in different complete
sets of quantities.
The result (20.27) is a generalization of (20.26). In fact,
'n { 8 (/.1,) / 8 .I'} 'n 8/ .1.
[Pi' f] '\jJ= -l ar; '" - 8ri '" = -l 8r; "'.
Results (20.28)-(20.30) can be obtained from (19.2) by
using the preceding commutation relations (see Ap-
pendix C).
Results (20.28) and (20.29) mean that components of the
angular momentum and coordinate (angular momentum
and momentum) with like subscripts can be measured
simultaneously, while those with different subscripts
cannot be measured simultaneously. These results also
mean that projections of the angular momentum cannot
belong to complete sets which include coordinates or the
momentum components.
. The result (20.30) means that different components of an-
I gular momentum don't have a common closed system of
eigenfunctions and cannot appear in the same complete set
..
189
.'
'.
$
r
" I
of quantities. Considering the examples discussed earlier,
we can conclude that different components of angular
momentum cannot be measured simultaneously. This
conclusion is correct, but it should be slightly improved
on the basis of the example of the components of angular
momentum. As a matter of fact, there is one case when
all the three components of angular momentum can be
simultaneously measured-this is the particular case when
all of them are equal to zero. This case, however, does not
essentially change anything since, as has been remarked
in Sec. 17, the presence of one common eigenfunction is
in no way connected with the commutation of operators.
By using relations (20.19) and (20.30), we can establish
one more rule for commutation (see Appendix D):
[M2, M
i
] = 0 (20.31)
This means that we must include the square of the angu-
lar momentum and anyone of the projections of the angu-
lar momentum in the same complete set of quantities.
Note that the simultaneous measurability of all the components
of momentum and the impossibility of similar measurement for
the angular momentum components have a very simple explana-
tion. The fact is that the parallel translations associated with the
momentum operator are commutative, while the rotations asso-
ciated with the angular momentum operator are noncommutative.
It is immaterial whether we move first along the x-axis and then
along the y-axis, or in the reverse order.
However, the sequence of rotations is certainly not immaterial.
Take, for example, a point on the I-axis and make two successive
rotations through 90
o
-in one case first around the x-axis and then
around the z-axis, in the other case first around the z-axis and
then around the x-axis. It can be easily seen that the final positions
of the point are different in these two cases.
The Inversion Operator; Parity
190
The inversion operator P is defined in the following:
way:
P'ljJ (;, t) = P'ljJ ( - -;,t), (20.32)
where P is a constant. By applying the i"ersion operator
twice, we obviously return to the initial function 'ljJ (;, t).
It follows from this that p2 = 1, Le. .
P = 1. (20.33)'
The quantity P is called the spatial parity. If P = 1,_
and consequently, P'ljJ (;, t) = 'tV (-;, t), the m i r o p r ~
ticle is said to possess even parity. If, however, P = -1'
191
* It must be noted that in some processes involving elementary
particles, the symmetry of "usual wOJ;'ld" and "mirror world" is
Violated. It was shown by Wu in 1957 that in experiments on the
fl-decay of nuclei, spatial parity is not conserved. This result
was predicted in 1956 by Lee and Yang.
and, consequently, t) = -'IjJ (--;., t), the micro-
particle is said to pos'>ess odd parity.
Suppose [P, ill = O. In this case, according to (19.10),
the parity is a conservahle quantity. If at the initial
moment of time the microparticle was, for example, in
a state with even parity, it must have the same parity
at subsequent moments of time (which, of course, imposes
certain restrictions on the possible changes in the state
of the microparticle).
It was mentioned in Sec. 1 that the laws of conservation
of energy, momentum and angular momentum are the
results of definite propertills of the symmetry of space and
time. The law of conservation of parity is no exception to
this. It is a consequence of the symmetry with respect
to inversion operation, which, as can be easily seen,
reduces to a combipation of the operation of rotation and
reflection fin fact, the operation (x, y, z) -+ (-x, _y,
-z) consists of rotation through 180, say, arround the
z-axis, and reflection in the plane perpendicular to the
z-axisJ. Taking into account that the conservation of
angular momentum is linked with rotational symmetry,
we conclude: the conservation of spatial parity is asso-
ciated with the fact that physical processes take place
identically in the "usual world" and the "mirror world".*
Let us write the equation for the eigenfunctions of the Eigenvalues and Eigenfuncfions
operator ifz' defined by (20.21): of the Operators Mz and M2
(20.34)
The solutions of this equation are of the form ..
..p (cp) = A exp (iM ". (20.35)-
The function .p is periodic: 'IjJ (cp + 2n) = 'IjJ (cp). Conse
quently, '.
M z = Jim, m = 0, 1, +2, . . . . (20.36)
The reader is already familiar with this results: the pro-
jection of angular momentum is quantized; it assumes
values differing by multiples of Planck's constant (see
Sec. 2). The factor A in (20.35) is determin.ed from the
2n
, normalization condition 'ljJi:.'ljJmdcp = 1. It is easy to
o
T
We now turn to the operator M2. Using (20.23), we write
>
see that A = (2n)-1/2. Thus
'i'm (cp) = (2n)-1/
2
exp (imcp).
1.2 [ 1 8
2
'IjJ + 1 a ( . e 8'IjJ ) ] _ M2'h
- n sin2 e 8<p2 sin e as sm as - 'Y'
(20.37)
(20.38)
? i
'\
This equation is known in mathematics as the equation
for spherical junctions. It has bounded solutions under
the condition that
M2 = lZ
2
l (l + 1), l = 0, 1, 2, ....
(20.39)
(20.40)
Assuming that the condition (20.39) is satisfied, we write
the solutions of (20.38) in the form of spherical harmonics:
'1
1
= .. /" (l-I mJ)! (2l+1) pi m I (cos 8) eimQJ
-1m V (l+lm/)14n I ,
where m = 0, 1, .., l. Taking (20.31) into consid-
eration, we conclude that the eigenfunctions of Mt
and M2 are common. Hence, m should be treated as a mag-
netic quantum number corresponding to the projection
of the angular momentum of the z-axis. It assumes 2l + 1
values (from -l to l). The functions p!ml(cos 8) appear-
ing in (20.40) are essentially the associated Legendre
functions. We remind the reader that
m d
m
PI (x) = (1- x
2
)m/2 dx
m
PI (x)
where PI (x) are Legendre polynomials*: I
1 dl /
PI(x)= 2
1
11 dx
l
[(x
2
-1)1].
(20.41)
(20.42)
(20.43)
192
The spherical functions '\JIm (8, cp) are orthonormalized:
2lt It
Jj '\Jim (8, cp) '\JI'm' (8, cp) sin 8 d8 dcp = 6 1 1 ~ ~
o 0
If the result (20.36) is known, we can derive the result
(20.39) by assuming that
M2 = 3 (M;) = 3/is (m
2
).
Legendre polynomials and associated functions are considered
in Appendix D.
I
\
The Relations of Classical
Mechanics in Operator Form
I:
t
If
I
The mean value (m
2
) is determined by the expression
I 1
"" m
2
"" m
2
1
(m
2
)= .L.J 21+1 =2 .L.J 21+1 =3
1
(1+1).
m=-I m=O
This leads directly to (20.39).
It follows from (20.18) that the inversion operators Parity and Angular Momentum
commute with operators of any projection of the angular
momentum. Moreover, the inversion operators and the
operators of the square of the angular momentum com-
mute:
[P,Mi]=O, [P,M2]=0. (20.44).
This mean that the operators Pand Mi have a common
complete system of eigenfunctions. The same applies to
the operators P and,M2. From this it follows in particu-
lar that a state with a definite orbital quantum number 1
must also be characterized by a definite spatial parity.
In spherical coordinates the inversion is of the form
r--+r, 8--+n-8, cp--+ljJ+n. (20.45)
Using (20.40)-(20.42) we find that for such a transforma-
tion the function 'ljJ/m (8, cp) is multiplied by (_1)1:
I "
'\JIm --+ (-1) 'ljJ/m' (20.46)
It follows hence that states with even 1have an even parity
while the states with odd 1 have an odd parity.
It is appropriate here to recall that the example given in
Sec. 3 for the complete set of quantities describing the
state of a photon includes M2, M z and P [see (3.7b)1.
Note that the parity and the angular momentum occur
in the same complete set of quantities. Formally, this is
a consequence of relations (20.44). However, one can
start from considerations based on direct physical intui-
tion. In fact, the obvious "affinity" between the parity
and the angular momentum is connected with the above-
mentioned fact that the inversion operation includes rota-
tion in addition to reflection. The order in which these
operations are carried out is immaterial; rotation can
follow reflection or, the other way round, it can precede
reflection.
So far, we have several times used the fact that the
apparatus of quantum mechanics is based on the well-
known equations of classical mechanics written, however,
in operator form. This fact is so important that it is ap-
propriate to return to it once again.
We have mentioned above the brilliant guess by Schrodin-
gel', who proposed the expression (20.12) for the Hamilto-
'.
s.c. 20
-.
193
194
nian of a microparticle. If we use this guess and the funda';"
mental result (19.10), we can easily see that the equations;.
of classical mechanics can be actually transferred to quan- .t
tum mechanics by replacing the physical quantities by the'
corresponding Hermitian operators. Substituting the oper-
ator L = x in (19.10), and using the expression (20.12)
for the operator iI, we get
;; = Px1m. (20.47)
This is the well-known classical result: the velocity is
equal to momentum divided by mass. In quantum-mechan-
ical interpretation this result means that the velocity
operator is equal to the momentum operator divided by
the mass. Further, we substitute the operator L = p ~
in (19.10). Using the expression (20.12) for ii as before,
we get
:' d
P:r.= -lh" U (x). (20.48)
It can be easily seen that this is just Newton's second law
of motion, written in operator form. ~ ,
. .
Remember, that the operators of the type x and Px are
introduced in accordance with the definition (19.9). Hence,
it follows that the results (20.47) and (20.48) indicate
the validity of the classical relations for the mean values
of physical quantities:
d ~
7ft (x) = (s I ~ I s)1 m, (20.47a)
d d
dt (Px) = - dx U (x). (20.48a)
Ehrenfest was the first to point out this and hence rela-
tions of the type (20.47a) or (20.48a) ~ l l e d Ehren/est
theorems. In short, Ehrenfest's theorems lstate that clas-
sical relations for physical quantities al.re transformed
in quantum mechanics into relations for mean values of
physical quantities.
It was noted in Sec. 19 that the mathematical analogy
between classical mechanics and quantum mechanics con-
sidered here requires a certain amount of caution since
operators don't always commute with each other. This
leads to the conclusion that the information contained
in the classical relations is insufficient for building up the
quantum-mechanical apparatus. It is necessary to have
additional information about the properties of commuta-
tion of the operators under consideration. In other words,
the classical relations must be supplemented by the com-
mutation relations of the type (20.26)-(20.30).
Thus, it is the commutation relations which carry the
specific information essential to the apparatus of quantum
mechanics. In this connection, we note that the right-
hand sides of the commutation relations contain the speci-
fically quantum-mechanical constant, i.e. the Planck's
constant.
Section21
Applications of the
Schrodinger Equation
I
We shall mention three types of problems involving the
solution of the Schrodinger equation.
First type of problems. We consider the motion of a micro-
particle in a limiJ;ed region of space or, in other words,
in a potential well (for example, the motion of an electron
in an atom). Such a motion is called finite and the micro-
particle is said to be in a bound state. In this case the
time-independent Schrodinger equation is used [see (20.13)
or (20.14)1. By solving the Schrodinger equation under
certain boundary conditions imposed on the wave func-
tion and its first derivative*, the spectrum of the values
of the energy of the microparticles and the wave functions
of the stationary states can be found.
Second type of problems. The infinite motion (motion un-
bounded in space) of a microparticle in an external field
is considered. For example, the microparticle passes
through a potential barrier (we recall the tunneling
effect mentioned in Sec. 4) or is scattered by some energy
centre. Since the motion is infinite, the energy spectrum
of the microparticle is continuous. By solving the time-
independent Schrodinger equation, we can find the form
of the wave fun-etions of the microparticle far from the
scattering centre (or barrier) from which, for example, the
probability of scattering at a certain angle (or the prob-
ability of tunneling through the barrier as well as of reflec-
tion from it) can be calculated.
Third type of problems. In the two types of problems indi-
cated above, we spoke of the stationary states of a micro-
particle. For those the time-independent Schrodinger
equation was used. The third type of problems involves
a change in the state of a microparticle with time, and for
this the time-dependent Schrodinger equation is used [see
* The boundary conditions are considered below during a dis-
cussion on specific problems.
Sec. 21
Some Characteristic Problems iB
Quantum Mechanics
195
A Particle in a One-Dimensional
Potential Well with Infinitely Hign
"Walls"
(20.17)1. By solving this problem we can fmd the prob-
ability of any quantum transition taking place under
the influence of a given external force.
Examples of problems of first two types are given in this
section and in Sec. 24. The third type of problems can be
found in Sec. 25. Naturally, we shall limit ourselves to
just a few typical examples. But it should be mentioned
here that the applied aspects of quantum mechanics are,
reflected quite comprehensively in the existing literature '
(in this connection, we recommend [34, 35] which give
specially selected quantum-mechanical problems).
Such a well is described by a potential U of the form
{
OO' x<O,
U (x) = 0, O-<x-<a, (21.1)
00, x>a.
The parameter a is the width of the well. The energy is
measured from the bottom of the well. Within the limits
of the well (0 -< x -<a), the Schrodinger equation (20.13)
is of the form
At the boundaries of the well (for x = 0 and x = a)
the continuous wave function cp vanishes, since the infi-
nitely high "walls" make it impossible for the particle to be
found beyond the limits of the well *. Thus in this case
the boundary conditions are of the form
where
= 2mEln2.
cp (0) = cp (a) = O.
We can write the general solution
tion (21.2) as follows:
cp (x) = A sin (kx) + B cos (kx).
Since cp (0) = 0, it follows that
cp (x) = A sin (kx).
(21.2)
(21.3)
(21.4)
ofl.rential equa-
(21.5)
B = O. Thus,
(21.6)
From the condition cp (a) = 0, we conclude that
ka = nn, where n is ail integer. (21.7)
196
* In the case of "walls" having a finite height, this possibility,
as will be shown helow, is not excluded.
Taking (2'1.3) into account, the last result can be rewritten
in the following form:
En = n
2
J[,2/t
2
/2ma
2
. (21.8)
The expression (21.8) determines the spectrum of values of
the energy (energy levels) of the particle in the potential
well. It coincides with the expression (5.2) derived ear-
lier.
According to (21.5) and (21.7), the wave function CPn (x)
corresponding to the nth energy level, is of the form CPn (x) =
= A sin (Jtnx/a). The integration constant A is deter-
mined from normalization condition [see (15.13) in this
a
connection] S (x)dx = 1. It can be easily seen that
o
A = V2/a and, consequently,
CPn (x) = V2/a sin (21.9)
Thus, we have found the energy levels and the orthonor-
malized wave functions for the stationary states of a par-
ticle in a rectangular one-dimensional well with infinitely
high "walls".
Let us consider a rectangular potential well shown in
Fig. 21.1 (a). Since the particle is inside the well, E <
< VI and E < V2' The rectangularity of the potential
enables us to clearly distinguish three spatial regions:
region 1 (x < 0), region 2 (0 <. x <. a) and region 3 (x >
> a). We shall consider these regions separately and will
then combine these results at the boundaries of the regions,
Le. at the points x = and x = a. The Schrodinger
equation (20.13) has the following form:
for region 1
- = 0, where = 2m (V1 - E)/lt
l
,
for region 2
d
2
rp
dx
2
+k
2
cp=0, where k
2
=2mE/1t2,
and for region 3
d
2
rp
dx
2
(21.10a)
(21.10b)
(21.10c)
Rectangular Potential Well with
"Walls" of Finite Height
Fig. 21.1
V,
E
X
1
t'
2-
a
(
ftl)
x
R{q,e,
(I;
,
The general solutions of these differential equations may
be written in the following form:
for region 1
CPI = Al exp (Xl' x) +B
I
exp (-XiX), (21.11a)
Sec. 21
191
198
for region 2
<P2 = A
2
exp (ikx) + B
2
exp (-ik:JJ), (21. 11 b)
for region 3
<P3 = A
3
exp (x
2
x) + B
3
exp (-x
2
x). (21. 11c)
[Note that the solution of equation (21.10b) may be
written in the form (21.11b) or (21.5).] The boundedness
of the wave function requires that B
t
and A
3
be put
equal to zero. Thus,
<Pi (x) = Ai exp (Xi x),
<P2 (x) = .1
2
exp (ikx) +B
2
exp (- ikx), (21.12)
<Pa (x) = B
a
exp (- x
2
x).
The qualitative form of the functions CPt, CP3 and Re {CP2}
is shown in Fig. 21.1 (b). The reader should pay attention
to the fact that in the case of a potential well with "walls"
of finite height, there always exists a probability of
finding the particle beyond the limits of the well; this
probability decreases exponentially with the distance
from the boundaries of the well.
In order to find the four coeffIcients (AI, A
2
, B
2
, B
3
),
we make use of the fact that both the function and its first
derivative must be continuous at the boundaries. The
continuity of the wave function is obvious, while the con-
tinuity of the derivative can be easily shown. In order
to do so, let us integrate Schrodinger's equation (20.13)
over a certain interval (a - a + M containing the
potential jump. We get
a+1\.
dcp A dcp 2m r
dx (a +Ll) - a:; (a - M= fi2 J [U (x) - E] cP dx.
a-I\.
Since the functions under the integral sign are bounded,
in the limit of -+ 0 this integral vanishes. As a result
/
we get di (a +0) = dx (a - 0), which w,.J)e proved.
Returning to our problem, we write the condi-
tions (conditions of 'piecing' together the solutions at the
boundaries of the region):
cpdO) = cpdO) , I
CP2 (a) = CPa (a), I
drpl (0) = drp2 (0) (21.13)
dx dx' I
(a) = (a).)
Substituting the expressions (21.12) in these equations, we
get the system of equations ior the coefficients Al' A 2' B2J
B
3
:
At =A2+B
2
, I
A
2
exp (ika) +B
2
exp ( - ika) = B
3
exp ( - X2a), I
Xt A
t
=ik(A
2
-B
2
), (21.14)
ikA
2
exp (ika) - ikB
2
exp ( - ika) I
= - X2
B
3 exp ( - x
2
a). J
The system (21.14) is a homogeneous system of linear
equations. In order that such a system should have non-
trivial solutions, it is necessary that its determinant should
be equal to zero. Equating the determinant of the system
to zero, we get an equation for the energy E (we recall
that the quantities k, Xl' X
2
are expressed in terms of E).
The solutions of this equation will give us the possible
values of the energy of the particle.
We emphasize that from a mathematical point of view,
the quantization of the energy in a well is a direct conse-
quence of the homogeneity of the system (21.14). This
is the crux of the problem of finding eigenvalues of phys-
ical quantities: the particle is left to its own devices, Le.
the external influences are eliminated thus eliminating
inhomogeneities from the equation. As a result, the particle
chooses its own course characterized by certain funda-
mental parameters (frequency, energy, etc.). The simplest
example, taken from classical physics, is that of a pendu-
lum. If a pendulum is not disturbed, it will oscillate with
a difinite natural frequency, irrespective of the way the
oscillation have been induced.
Thus, in order to determine the value of the energy of
a particle, we should equate to zero the determinant of the
system (21.14) and solve the equation so obtained. How-
ever, it is inconvenient in practice to consider a determi-
nant of the 4th order. Hence we shall first simplify the
system of equations. To do so, we rewrite the function
(jJ2 in the form lp2 = C sin (kx + b) (this form is equiva-
lent to the one used earlier; the reader may independently
express the coefficients C and b in terms of the old coef-
ficients A 2 and B2)' The system (21.14) will now have
the following form:
At = Csin b, I
Csin(ka+b)=B
3
exp(-x2
a
), I
r (21.15)
xtAt = kC cos b, J
kCcos (ka+b) = -x
2
B
3
exp (-X2
a
).
Dividing the third equation of this system by first and
Sec. 21
199
'.
Fig. 21.2
200
the fourth by second, we get
Xl = kcot b, }
X2=-= -kcot(ka+b).
We now have a system of two equations in place of the
system with four equations. From the first equation of
the system (21.16) we fwd cot b = xl/k, hence
kft
sin b = (1 +cot
2
b)-1/2 = --;-==-
Y2mU
l
Similarly, we get from the second equation of (21.16)
sin (ka+b) = -"IIkft
v 2mU
2
As a result, we get an equation that determines the value
of k (and, consequently, the energy levels) in implicit
form:
k
. kft . kft (21 17)
a = n:rr - arCSIn ,I - arcsIn ,1' .
v 2mU
l
v 2mU
2
where n is an integer. Figure 21.2 shows the left- and
right-hand sides of equation (21.17) as a function of k.
In the situation shown in the figure, the particle has three
energy levels corresponding to values of k equal to k
I
,
k
2
, k
3
If we change the width of the well, the slope of
the straight line y = ka will change thus changing the
the position and the number of possible energy levels,
A decrease in the width of the well will decrease the
slope of the straight line. The energy levels will "creep"
out of the well, and their number will gradually
decrease. An increase in the width of the well will
raise the line y = ka; it will intersect a larger num-
ber of branches of the inverse sine graph, thus
leading to a larger number' of levels in the
well. As a -+ 00, the numbes of levels in the well will
rise indefinitely, and we finally get a continuous energy
spectrum. It is easy to examine similarly the effect of
a change in the depth of well on the the
greater is the depth, the mOlel levels there t.he well.
We should proceed further in the followin w y. find from
(21.17) the possible values of k and the valu sE, Xl' and
X
2
corresponding to them, then substitute these values in
(21.15) and solve the system of equations containing the
coefficients, and then substitute the final result in the
expression (21.12) for the wave functions. However, on
account of the mathematical complications involved,
we shall not embark on this venture here.
In conclusion, we note that (21.17) may also be used for
determining the minimum energy E
I
of a particle in a
potential well. For this we just have to consider the
hatched triangle in Fig. 21.2 and put k1a;:::::,rr" whence we get
E
1
;:::::, rr,2fi2J 2ma
2
This result is in good agreement. with the
estimate (4.11) obtained in Sec. 4 on the basis of the
uncertainty relations (3.3).
When considering the motion of a particle in a spherically A Particle in a Spherically
symmetrical field, it is convenient to use spherical coor- Symmetrical Field
dinates r, 8 and cpo Spherical symmetry of the field means
that U (--;) = U (r). The in spherical coor-
dinates has the form
1 a ( a) 1
r
2
- (21.18)
r
2
iJr ar I r 2 q;,
1 iJ2 1 a (_ a)
where = sin
2
8 [acp2 +sin 8 as sm 8 as' (21.19)
Taking this into we can rewrite the Schrodinger
equation (20.14) in the form
1 iJ ( a ) 1
72a; r
2
a;'IjJ (r, 8, cp)
+(2m/1i2) [E - U (r)] 'IjJ (r, 8, cp) = O. (21.20)
Equation (21.20) allows the separation of variables. This
means that its solution may be found in the form of
a product of two functions, one of which depends only
on r, and the other on the angular coordinates 8 and cp:
'IjJ (r, 8, cp) = R (r) ll> (8, cp). (21.21)
Substituting (21.21) into (21.20), we get the following
result:
d ( dR) 2m
(Ii" r
2
a;:- +r
2
[;2[E-U(r)]R(r) =_ dSq><D
R(r) <D (8, cp) (21.22)
Since the left- and right-hand sides of (21.22) depend on
different independent variables (on r and on 8 and cp, -.
respectively), both sides must be equal to some constant,
which we denote by A. Introducing this constant, we write
- (8, cp) = All> (8, cp). (21.23)
Comparing (21.19) with (20.23), we conclude that (21.23)
is in fact the equation for the eigenvalues and eigenfunc-
tions of the operator JVj2. This allows us to use (20.39)
and (20.40) and write
A = 1(1 + 1), 1 = 0, 1, 2, . , (21.24)
rh 8 .. / 2l +1 (l-I m I )! pi m I 0) imlp
w(,cp)=V l (cosue
=Y
lm
(0, lp), (21.25)
Sec. 21
I'"
It should be noted that (21.27) may be reduced to the
one-dimensional Schrodinger equation with a special
boundary condition at r = O. For this we must use the
substitution
(21.28)
(21.27)
(21.26c)
where we have introduced the notation
r-
Y 9 +2 = 1/ ~ sin
2
8e2irp
~ - 32n .
cp (r) = rR (r) .. (21.29)
and in view of the boundedness of the \ 4 \ ~ n R (r),
require that the condition q> (0) = 0 be satisfied. It can
be easily seen that the substitution (21.29) in fact con-
verts (21.27) into the one-dimensional Schrodinger equa-
tion
d
2
cp 2m ) rrJ 0)
dr
2
+fi2 [E - Ud
r
hI (r) = O. (21.3
In this case the boundary condition q> (0) = 0 corresponds
to the one-dimensional potential well having an infinitely
high vertical wall on the left (at r = 0).
We emphasize that the "angular part" of the wave function
is independent of the particular form of the potential
U (r); this is a direct and important consequence of the
spherical symmetry of the potential.
'Ve now turn to the "radial part" of the wave function,
i.e. to the function R(r). According to (21.22) and (21.24),
this must be a solution of the equation
1 d ( dR) 2m
-- r
2
- +-[E-U[(r)]R(r)=O
r
2
dr dr fj2 ,
U ( ) = U ( ) _I- !l2l (l+ 1)
[ r r I 2mr2
where m = 0, +1, ... , +l. The functions Y
'm
(8, q
are spherical harmonics (they were introduced in Sec. 20).
It will be useful to write down the expressi ons for the
first few spherical harmonics:
1
Y
oo
= f - , (21.26a)
1 4n
/3 .. /-
YIO=ll 4n cos8; Y1,1= V 8 ~ sin8eirp, (21.26b)
202
where T= P; is the vector of the density of flow of the
liquid.
Equation (21.31) is independent of the choice of the vol-
ume V. Using this fact, we can decrease the volume V
to some particular point. In the limit as V -+ 0, (21.31)
Thus,
a i" .t --..-+
at j p dV +Ypv dS = 0.
v s
By replacing the integral over the closed surface by a
volume integral, we can rewrite the last equation in the
following form:
'It
203
The Continuity Equation and the
Schrodinger Equation
(21.31)
J ~ ~ +divT) dV=O,
v
Further study of (21.30) obviously requires a considera-
.. tion of the particular form of the potential U(r).
It should be noted that among the problems on the motion
of a particle in a spherically symmetrical field are the
problems of an electron in an atom and the scattering
of particles by spherically symmetrical centres.
We shall establish a formal analogy between the time-
dependent Schrodinger equation and the continuity equa-
tion, which is widely used in classical physics, especially
in hydrodynamics. We assume that there is a certain
medium (for example, a liquid) described by the functions
p (;) and - ; ~ [p(;) is the density of the medium and
-; ~ . is the velocity of the particles of the medium at
--..
the point r; naturally, these functions may also depend
on time!. Let u ~ imagine a certain volume V in the
medium to be isolated. The change in the quantity of
liquid in this volume per unit time is equal to .!!.. r pdV.
atJ
v
Let us isolate a certain element of surface area dS on
the area S bounding the volume V, and associate with
-+
it a vector dS equal to dS in magnitude and directed along
the outward normal to the surface. The amount of liquid
passing per unit time from the volume V through an
-* -+ ---*
element of surface area dS is equal to pv dS. The amount
of liquid passing through the entire surface per unit
~ --..-+
time is equal to ;y pv dS. The law of conservation of
s af ~ - - . . - +
matter requires that --aJ p dV and ;y pv dS be equal.
tv S
(21.33)
(21.32)
, I
i
204
becomes a differential equation at this point:
ap +d' ":'" 0
- IVJ=.
at
This is the classical continuity equation.
Let us turn to the time-dependent Schr6dinger equation.
We shall generalize the one-dimensional equation (20.17)
for the three-dimensional case:
a -r !i2 -r -r-->-
in- 'P' (r, t) = --2- lV (r, t) +U (r) 'P' (r, t).
(}t m
We introduce purely formally a certain "medium" and
define the density of this "medium" as 'P''P'*. This density
may be called the "probability density". In other words,
the probability of finding a particle will be greater at
those points of space, where the density of the "medium"
is higher.
This "probability density" may be given a fairly simple
physical meaning if we imagine that the space is filled
with a large number of particles (the interaction of parti-
cles is to be neglected in this case). Obviously, the number
of particles in some volume is proportional to the
probability of finding a particle in this volume. With
this approach, W'P'* may be considered simply as the
density of the number of particles.
As in the classical case, we start by considering a certain
finite volume V:
r dV = rIf'P'* dV = r (W* a'l' + 'P' a'l'* ) dV
at JP at J J at at .
v v v
Substituting into this :t Wand :t If* from the Schr6d-
inger equation (21.33), and from the complex conjugate
of equation (21.33), we get
rIf'F* dV = r 'P' - If qr*) dV
at J 2m J
V V
= j div ('P'*Y'lf - WY'W*) .
V
The last result can be written in the form
r[.!...- (W'P'*) - div {.!:.!!- (If*Y'"lf
J Ot 2rn
v
- lfY'lf*) }JdV = 0, (21.34)
or, after decreasing the volume V to a point,
:t (lflf*) - div [ (If*Y'lI' - lfY'W*) J= O. (21.:35)
Sec. 21
'I< The functions 'P' C;, t) and qJ (;:'j are related to each other through
a relation of the type (20.16).
x
205
----"-'
o
~
E
Passage of a Particle Under or
Over a Potential Barrier
Fig. 21.3
(21.38)
(21.39)
k=V2mE/tz,
Y2m(U-E)
x= Ii
. _. iii ( dqJ * * dqJ )
I-2m p ~ p a:; .
By drawing an analogy between (21.34) and (21.31) [or
between (21.35) and (21.32)], we come to the conclusion
that the Schrodinger equation corresponds to some quan-
tum-mechanical continuity equation, if in addition to the
probability density*
p = 1*1Jf = cP*cP (21.36)
we also introduce the vector of probability flow den8ity
-:" in . ill
] = 2m (1Jf'V1Jf*- 1Jf*'V1Jf) ="2,;"i" (cp\7cp* -. CP*'Vcp). (21.37)
If we interpret (21.36) as the density of particles, then
the vector (21.37) may beconsidered as the vector of den-
sity of the flow of particles. With such an interpretation
the quantum-mechanical continuity equation (21.35) ex-
presses the law of conservation of the number of parti-
cles. ,,'
In the case of a one-dimensional motion along the .:r-axis,
(21.37) assumes the form
CPt (x) = At exp (ikx) +B
t
exp (- ikx);
CP2 (x) = A
2
exp (xx) +B
2
exp (- xx);
CPa (x) = Aa exp (ikx) +B
a
exp ( - ikx).
In conclusion, let us note that we cannot assign the mean-
ing of "flow" in the literal sense to the quantum-mechan-
ical vector j, since in order to determine the flow through
any surface we must be able to measure the values of the
velocity (momentum) at fixed points of the surface, which
is obviously in contradiction to the uncertainty relations.
Let us consider a one-dimensional rectangular potential
barrier (Fig. 21.3) and assume that particles arrive at it
from the left with an energy E which is less than the
height U of the barrier. We can isolate three spatial
regions and write the solutions of the Schrodinger equa-
tion (20.13) for these regions:
The terms containing exp (ikx) describe the particles
moving in the positive direction of the x-axis while the
terms containing exp (-ikx) indicate motion in the op-
posite direction. If we take into account that the par-
(21.40)
ticles are moving in the positive direction, we mu
exclude the second term in the function 4l:l: B
3
= O.
The other coefficients are non-zero. The term with At
describes particles falling on the barrier, the term with
B1 describes those reflected from the barrier, while the
term with A., describes particles which have passed
through the barrier.
The conditions of continuity of the wave function and its
derivative at points x = 0 and x = a give the following
system of four equations:
At+Bt=Az+B
z
, ')
A
z
exp (xa) +B
z
exp (- xa) = A
3
exp (ika), I
ik(A
t
-B
t
)=x(A
z
-B
2
), (
x [A
z
exp (xa)-B
z
exp (-xa)J I
=ikA
3
exp(ika). J
It turns out that we have just four equations for five co-
efficients! But actually, only four and not five coef-
ficients are known. The density of flow of particles inci-
dent on the barrier Ulnc) must be given. This density
is given by (21.38), where we must substitute qJ =
= A 1 exp (ikx). As a result of this, we get
jlnc = I At 1
2
ftk/m. (21.41)
Thus by knowing the quantity jlnc we can determine the
coefficient AI'
Similarly for the density of flow of the reflected particles
we get
(21.42)
and for the density of flow of particles passing through
the barrier we have
hr = I A
3
1
2
nk/m. (21.43)
I'
206
Usually in such problems the density jlnc is chosen in
such a way that Al = 1. In this case the system (21.40)
assumes the form
1+B
t
=A
2
+B
2
, }
A
2
exp (xa) +B
z
exp (- xa) = A
3
exp (ika), (21.44)
k (1-B
t
) = X (A
z
- B
2
),
x [A
z
exp (xa)-B
z
exp (-xa)] = ik A
3
exp (ika).
The system (21.44) is the non-homogeneous system of four
linear equations containing four unknown coefficients.
The inhomogeneous system has a solution for any values
of k and x, i.e. for any values of the energy E of the par-
ticle. This is in agreement with the fact that for infinite
motion of the particle its energy is not quantized.
We can determine the fraction of particles that has passed
through the barrier:
D=itr/itnc. (21.45)
The quantity D is called the transmission coefficient of
the barrier. Solving the system (21.44) w ~ shall omit the
steps), we get
Aa=- :k e-ika[exa(t_ i: r-
e
-
xa
(1+ i: )2J-1.
(21.46)
Further, using (21.49) and (21.45),
~ '"
D = 4k
2
x
2
4k
2
x
2
+(k
2
+X
2
)2 sinh
2
(xa) .
In the particular case when xa ~ 1,
as
f
2a ]
D=Doexp. --7': V2m(U--E)
where
Do=16 Z(1- ~ ) .
we find
(21.47)
(21.47) is simplified
(21.48)
(21.49)
In addition to the transmission coefficient, we also have
the coefficient of reflection at the barrier, defined as the
fraction of the particles reflected by the barrier: R =
= jrer/hnc. It is clear from basic principles that D + R =
= 1 (all the particles not passing through the barrier
must be reflected by it).
Finally we consider the case when a particle passes over
the barrier (E > U). In this case, instead of (21.39) we
get
CPt (x) = exp (ikx) +B
t
exp (- ikx),
cpz (x) = A
z
exp (iKx) +B
z
exp (- iKx),
CPa (x) = A
a
exp (ikx),
where
K = V2m (E - U)/Ii.
Using (21.49), we write the boundary conditions for the
points x = 0 and x = a. We then solve the system of
equations so obtained and find the coefficient B
1
Further,
from (21.42) we determine the coefficient of reflection
207
'.
Fig. 21.4
t>
1
I
II
,
-I-t--tu-r-n-s-o-u-t-tO-b-e-e-q-U-a-l-to------r
I _ (k
2
_K2)2 sin
2
(Ka) ,
j, R - 4k2KLt--(k2-K2)2 sin2 (Ka) (21.50)
Using (21.47) and (2(50) we can fwd the dependence of
the transmission coefficient D on the ratio E/U. This
dependence is shown graphically in Fig. 21.4. The same
figure shows the dependence D (E/ U) for a classical par-
ticle (dotted line). A comparison of the solid curve with
the dotted line indicates the quantum-mechanical na-
ture of microparticles. Note that for E < U in classical
mechanics all particles are reflected from the barrier and
not a single particle passes through. In quantum mechan-
ics, however, a part of the is reflected and
a part passes through the barrier. For E > U, in classical
mechanics all particles pass through and not a single
particle is reflected, while in quantum mechanics a part
of the particles passes through, and another is reflected.
Both sub-barrier transmission and above-barrier reflection
of microparticles are specifically quantum effects.
(22.1)
(22.4 a)
(22.4 b)
(22.4c)
The Hamiltonian in Some
Specific Problems
The Hamiltonian is of the form
ft2 d2 m(i)2,y2
H= - 2m dx2 +-2-'
Section 22
It is obtained from (4.5) by taking (19.1) and (20.4) into
account. The eigenvalues are
En=ft(fJ (n+ n=O, 1, 2, ... (22.2)
[for n = 0 we get from (22.2) the energy of zero-point
oscillations, which was determined in Sec. 4 on the basis
of the uncertainty relations]. The eigenfunctions are
'Pn (x) = y m(fJ!1i exp (- 2/2) H n (), (22.3)
where = x ym(fJ!1i, and Hn () are called Hermite poly-
nomials. Let us write down the expressions for the first
few functions 'Pn (x):
'Po (x) = (x
o
Vn)-t/2 exp (- x
2
/2x:) ,
'Pt (x) = (2x
o
Vn)-t/2 exp (-x
2
/2x:) 2x/x
o
,
'P2(X) = (Sx
o
Vn)-t/2exp(-x2/2x:)(4 :; -2)
(where X
o
= Y1ilm(fJ).
208
Linear Harmonic Oscillator
hi
!'I
ir
/I
i
i
I
d
,I
,I
(22.6)
Sec. 22
209
The Hydrogen Atom
Note. Hermite polynomials, generalized Laguerre polyno-
mials (mentioned below), harmonic functions and Legen-
dre polynomials (introduced in Sec. 20) are called spe-
cial functions. A considerable amount of mathematical
literature has been devoted to special functions and their
applications; for reference we mention l36, 37]. A basic
account of polynomials and associated Legendre functions,
special functions and Hermitian polynomials is given in
Appendix E.
The problem of the hydrogen atom is a well-known exam-
ple of the motion of an electron in a sphericallysymmetric.
al Coulomb field. The Hamiltonian has the form
1i
2
e
2
2m r
(22.5)
[it is obtained from (4.1) by using (19.1) and (20.6)].
The eigenvalues 'If (this Hamiltonian are given by the
following familiar expression [see (2.5)]:
En = -me"-/21i
2
n
2
; n = 1, 2, 3, ....
The eigenfunctions of the Hamiltonian (22.5) may be
expressed in the form
1J'nlm = Rnl (r) cp); 1=0, 1, .. , n-1;
(22.7)
m=O, 1, "', l.
Here y 1m (8, cp) are spherical functions. They define the
"angular part" of the wave function irrespective of the
particular form of the spherically symmetrical potential;
R
nl
(r) is the "radial part" of the wave function, it is
defined by (21.30) with the Coulomb potential [U (r) =
= - e
2
/r]. The form of the function R
nl
(r) is described
by the expression
Rnl:(r) = const exp (r/rin)I(2r/rin)1 (22.8)
where r
1
= 1i
2
/me
2
(this quantity is already known to the
reader as the radius of Bohr's first orbit) and are
the so-called generalized Laguerre functions (see, for
example, [36]).
Expressions for some of the first harmonic functions have
been given in Sec. 21 [see (21.26)]. We shall now give the
expressions for the first few functions R
nl
(r):
RiO = 2r
1
3
/
2
exp (- rlrl), (22.9a)
R 20 = (2rD-l/2 exp (-r/
2r
l) (t - ) , (22.9b)
R
2i
= (2 -V6rn-
i
exp (- r/2rl) r/r
1
(22.9c)
I '
I
I'
1
On Degeneracy of Energy Levels
In Sec. 5, when discussing the concept of an electron clou ",
we introduced the functions Un I and Z1m' Figure 5.2
showed the form of some of the functions W
n
I (r) =.
= r
2
u
n
z (r), while Fig. 5.2 (b) showed some of the func-
tions Z Zm- Returning to the functions considered in this
section, we note)hat unz=R;tz (r) and!Zzm= I Y lm (e,q I'.
In particular, we note that (5.4) is in agreement
with (22.9a).
By using (22.9) and (21.26), we can write the first few
eigenfunctions of the Hamiltonian (22.5):
\jJ160 = (nrD-
1
/2 exp (- r/r1)' (22.10a)
\jJ200=(SnrD-
1
/
2
exp(-r/2r1) (1- (22.10b)
\jJ211 = (sVnr; t
1
exp ( - r/2r
1
) sin ee
t
(j)r/r1' (22.10c)
'210 = (4 V exp ( - r/2r1) cos er/ri' (22.10d)
The function (22.10a) describes the ground state of the
hydrogen atom, while the functions (22.10b)-(22.10d)
describe the excited states corresponding to the first ex- /
cited energy level (n = 2).
It follows from (22.6) that the energy of an electron in
the hydrogen atom is determined only by the quantum
number n, whil e the states (the functions Zm) are de-
termined by three quantum numbers n, land m. Besides,
when considering electronic states we must take into
account the quantum number (J which does not occur in
these expressions. Since for a given value of the principal
quantum number n the orbital quantum number l assumes
integral values from 0 to n - 1, and for every l the
magnetic quantum number acquires 2l + 1 values, the
following gn states must correspond to an energy level En:
n-l
gn = 2 ')1. (2l +1) = 2n
2
(22.11)
z=o
(the factor 2 takes account of the two spin states of the
electron). This means that the eigenvalue En of the Ha-
miltonian (22.5) (in other words, the nth energy level) .'
is 2n
2
-fold degenerate.
l
Degeneracy of energy levels, as a rule, is associated with i
symmetry in the atomic system. Thus, for example, owing
to the spherical symmetry of intra-atomic fields, there is i
degeneracy of the quantum numbers mand a-the energy
is independent of the orientation of the orbital momentum
and the spin momentum of the electron. The degeneracy
,of the quantum number l is .associated with the specific
nature of the Coulomb potential; in non-Coulomb fields
the energy of the electron depends not only on n but also
on 1.
Various fields, external as well as internal, may lower
the degree of symmetryofthe system. Thus, for example,
"switching on" an external electric field leads to the ap-
pearance of a physically distinguished direction. As a
result, the spherical symmetry disappears and is replaced
by cylindric< I symmetry. A decrease in symmetry lEads
to a removal of degeneracy (partial or total). This is
exhibited in a splitting of energy levels, i.e. in their con-
version into sets of Jl( w, less degenerate levels. Splitting
of energy levels in an external electric field is known as
Stark's effect, while the splitting in an external magnetic
field is known as Zeeman's effect.
The Hamiltonian of a crystal consisting of N nuclei and
ZN electrons can be written in the form
N .' ZN
H = 2M LJPf+ 2m LJ
i A
., -t-- .....
+Ud{rk}) +U
z
({R
i
}) +Us ({rk}' {R
i
}), (22.12)
where M is the mass of the nucleus, Pi is the momentum
operator for the ith nucleus, m is the mass of the electron,
Pk is the momentum operator for the kth electron, {;k}
is the set of coordinates of the electrons, {R i} is the set
of coordinates of the nuclei. The function U1 desclibes the
interaction of electrons. It is of the form
U
t
= (22.13)
kcf:-l
where rR/ is the distance between the kth and Ith electrons.
The function U2 describes the mutual interaction of the
nuclei, while the function U3 describes the interaction
of the nuclei with the electrons. *
Since M m, the nuclei move much more slowly than
the electrons. This permits us to consider the motions of
nuclei and electrons separately: when considering the
motion of electrons, we assume that the nuclei are sta-
tionary, while when considering the motion of the nuclei,
we assume that the electrons colIectively create an aver-
age field which is independent of the coordinate of indi-
vidual electrons. In this case the waye function of the
The functionsUi. U
2
, Ua, describing the various interaction
potentids, in .fact correspond to operators in the coordinate
.
Sec. 22
Crystal; the Adiabatic
Approximation
I';
,It
i
l;
crystal may be represented in the form of a product Of'
"nuclear" and "electronic" functions:
-+ -+--+-
'IjJ ({rk}, {R1}) = 'I' ({R
1
}) CPe ({rk}). (22.14)
We also represent the Hamiltonian (22.12) as a sum of the
"nuclear" Hamiltonian HI and the "electronic" Hamilton-
ian iI2:
(22.15)
(22.17)
(22.16)
1 1 e
2
.....
H2 = 2m LJ r;-+U3 ({rk }).
k k4=1 I
The function U3 describes the potential energy of the
electrons in the field of the nuclei which are located at the
lattice sites in the crystal.
Thus, instead of solving an extremely complicated Schro-
dinger equation for the entire crystal
" -+
H'IjJ ({rk}, {R
i
}) = Ecr\jJ({rk}, {R
i
})
it is enough to solve two much simpler equations:
(a) for nuclei (for crystal lattice)
jj1'I'({R
i
}) Rtl),
(b) for electrons
.....
H 2CPe ({rk}) = Eecpe ({rk}),
(22.18)
(22.19)
One-Electron Approximation
where Ecr = Elat + Ee. This approximation is called
adiabatic.
In conclusion, we make a fairly important clarification.
When using the adiabatic approximation we consider,
strictly speaking, not the bare nuclei, but nuclei together
with those electrons which are tightly bound to them.
Consequently, when we speak about a separate treatment
-of the electrons ensemble, we mean not all the electrons,
but only those which have been "collectivized" by the
crystal (in other words, the electrons moving over the
crystal lattice, for example, the conduction electrons).
In accordance with the adiabatic approximation, we
shall consider, without going into the dynamics of the
crystal lattice, the motion of electrons which have been
"collectivized" by the crystal. We use the expression
(22.16) and consider that the function U3 ({;k}) may be
represented as a summation over the "collectivized"
(22.21)
f electrons (,ince each electron interacts with the lattice
field independently from other electrons): U
3
({;k}) =
= L} (;k). In this case the "electronic" Hamiltonian
k
(22.16) assumes the form
1 1 e! -+
H= 2m LJPk+2: LJLJ rkl +LJUdrk)' (22.20)
k k
Further simplification is based on the assumption that
the term LjL} e
2
/rkl in (22.20) may be approximated by
k I
a summation over the electrons:
1 e
2
-+
2: LJ LJ '7kl U5 (rk)'
k .
.
In other words, when considering electron-electron in-
teraction, it is assumed that each electron moves in a
certain field which is common for the whole ensemble
(it is called the self-consistent field). As a result, the Ha-
miltonian of the electron ensemble can be represented as
a sum of "one-electron" Hamiltonian. This allows us to
represent the wave function of the ensemble in the form of
a product of "one-electron" functions [we denote them by
...
<p (rk)], after which the Schrodinger equation for the elec-
tron ensemble turns into set of "om-electron" equations
of the form
(22.22)
i
I
.+
Here p and r are the momentum operator and the coor-
dinate of one of the "collectivized" electrons, E being the
energy of the electron.
Thus, by using (22.21) we can go over from a considera-
tion of the electron ensemble to consideration of a single
electron moving in the field:
-+ -+ -+
(22.23)
This transition is called the one-electron approximation.
The potential U (-;) is a periodic function with the period
of the crystal lattice. It will be shown in Sec. 24 that the
energy of an electron moving in a periodic field is broken
up into alternate bands of allowed and forbidden values,
Le. has a band structure. An electron bound to an atom has
energy levels, while a free electron is characterized by a
continuous energy spectrum. An electron "collectivized"
Sec. 22
213
by the crystal occupies an "intermediate" position to a,
certain extent-it is "free", but only within the limits of
the crystal. The band structure of the energy states of
such an electron is obvious and is "intermediate" between
the structure of discrete levels and that of a continuous
spectrum.
The relative freedom of movement of a "collectivized"
eleotron is reflected, in particular, in its wave
which is represented in the form of what are called Bloch
functions:
(22.24)
The Hamiltonian of the
Interaction of an Electron with
Electromagnetic Radiation
This is the wave function (15.15) of a free electron, modu-
lated by the function u (---;), which has the period of the
potential U (for more about Bloch functions, see
Sec. 24).
We shall consider the system of a bound electron plus
radiation. In the absence of interaction between the
tron and the radiation, the system is described by the
"unperturbed" Hamiltonian:
_;;9
HO=2m-+
U
+H
v
,
(22.25)
where p2/2m + U is the Hamiltonian of the electron, and
H
v
is the Hamiltonian of the radiation. In the case of
interaction between the electron and the radiation, the
system is described by a "perturbed" Hamiltonian
11 = : 1)212m +U +Iiv
(22.26)
I
wIleI'cl A is tile oparator of the vector potential of tile ra-
diation field [we recall that in the coordinate'representa-
-+-+ -+-+ .
tionA (r) = A (r)l*. Note that the field potentials here
have beem chosen in such a way that the well-known cal-
ibration conditions div ;; = 0 and <p = 0 (<p is the scalar
potential of the field) are satisfied. Next, we represent the
Hamiltonian in the following form:
(22.27)
214
* It is shown in classical field theory [381 that the interaction of
a charge with an electromagnetic field may be considered by replac-
-+- e-+
ing p by p - -; A. We use this classical result here, replacing
the dynamic variables with the corresponding operators.
i
2t5
Momentum and Coordinate
Operators in the Momentum
Representation
(23.1)
Transition to the Momentum
Representation
Section 23
We shall show how to go over from the coordinate to
the momentum representation and shall give some re-
sults in the momentum representation.
Obviously, the momentum operator in the momentum
representation is the momentum itself:
,... e ~ -+ e2
Ht= -2me(pA) + 2me
Z
A2. (22.29)
It should be noted here that the Hamiltonian (22.29) is
responsible for all processes of absorption and emission
(spontaneous as wll, as induced) of photons by an elec-
tron.
where fi' is the interaction Hamiltonian, which plays
the role of the perturbation. Comparing (22.25), (22.26)
and (22.27), we find that
"., e ~ ~ e2
H
t
= - -2-[pA) +(Ap)] -+ -2zA2. (22.28)
: me me
This expression can be somewhat simplified if we put,in
..:+-+ -+ -+ -+-.:;: -+0-+
accordance with (20.27), pA (r) -A(r) p=-ilidivA(r).
Using the fact that div 1= 0, we get
Px=Px; P=p
We shall, therefore, go over directly to a consideration
of the x-coordinate.
Suppose that the amplitude of a state is given in the coor-
dinate representation by the function cp (x), and in the
momentum representation by the function <1> (Px)' By
using (17.33), we can write
. ) cp* (x) X(x) cp (x) dx= ) <1>* (Px) x(Px) <1> (Px) dpxo (23.2)
The relation between the functions cp (x) and <1> (Px),
according to (15.6), is of the form
q> (x) = J<1> (Px) 'px (x) dpx' (23.3)
where 'px (x) are the eigenfunctions of the operator Px
in the coordinate representation. By using (20.9) we can
-rewrite the expression (23.3) in the following form:
q> (x) = (2nli)-1/2 ~ <1> (Px) exp (iPxx/li) dpx' (23.4)
(23.8}
00
- in Jd;x [<1>exp (iPxxlh)) dpx
-00
By substituting (23.4) in the left-hand side of the equal-
ity (23.2), we get
Jlp* (x) xlp (x) dx
= JJ<1>* (23.5)
The factor x <1>(px) exp (iPxxltt) under the integral sign
in (23.5) may be expressed in the following form:
x<1>(px) exp (ipxxln) = - in dd [<1>exp (ipxx/n))
Px
+iti dd<D exp (ipxx/n). (23.6)
Px
We substitute (23.6) into (23.5) and consider the integral
with respect to Px' In so doing, we take into account that
=-in <1> (Px) exp (ipxx/n) 1:'
00
= 0
[since it is physically impossible to attain an infinitely
large momentum, we get <1> (00) = 0 and <1> (-00) = 0).
Thus in the integral with respect to Px, only the second
term on the right-hand side of (23.6), indd<D exp (ipxx/n)
Px
should remain. As a result, (23.5) assumes the form
Jlp* (x) xlp(x) dx
= JJ<1>* in exp dx.
(23.7)
Integration with respect to x on the right-hand side of
this equation gives, according to (15.17),
(2n
n
t
1
J
Further, using the property of the delta function, we per-
form an integration with respect to
J<1>* c5 (Px- = <1>* (Px)'
As a result, we are left with only the integral with respect
to Px' and (23.7) assumes the form
216
I
Ji
I
!
:1,\
'I
,.
"
Comparing the right-hand sides of (23.8) and (23.2), we
find the expression for the x-coordinate operator in the
momentum representation:
~ . d
x (Px) = In -d-. (23.9)
Px
A generalization to the three-dimensional case gives
..+-->-
r (p) = itt V-->-' (23.10)
p
where V-->- is the gradient in the momentum space.
p
By using (23.1) and (23.9) it is easy to see that the com-
mutators of the operators of the coordinate and momen-
tum components will be exactly the same in the momen-
tum representation, as in the coordinate representation
[we are speaking of the expressions (20.24)-(20.26)]. This
conclusion may abo be extended to the expressions
(20.27)-(20.30). (n other words, the commutation rela-
tions are independent of the choice of a representation,
i.e. are unitary invariants. This is quite natural, if we
recall that the mathematical fact of commutation of
operators has a definite physical meaning which, obvious-
ly, cannot change while going over from one representa-
tion to another.
Going over to the momentum representation, we can
write (20.11) in the fOlllll
Ii (Px) TEl (Px)=ETF(Px). (23.11)
where T E (Px) are the eigenfunctions of the Hamiltonian
in the momentum representation. Note that the quanti-
ties E in (23.11) are exactly the same as in (20.11), since
the spectrum of eigenvalues of a Hermitian operator is
a unitary invariant. Since in the momentum representa-
tionpx = Px and x= in -dd, the Hamiltonian (20.12)
Px
will now have the form
iJ (Px) = f ~ +U (in d;x). (23.12)
As a result, we get the following equation in place of
(20.13) :
( ~ - E) TE (Px) +U(in ~ ; = = O. (23.13)
This is the time-independent Schrodinger equation in the
momentum representation.
As an example, let us write out the Hamiltonian of a
linear ha,rmonic oscillator:
~ pi mw
2
Jj2 d
2
H (Px) = 2m --2- dpi. (23.14)
Sec. 23
Unitary Invariance of the
Commutation Relations
Schrodinger Equation in the
Momentum Representation
217
Compare this expression with (22.1), which describes the
same Hamiltonian in the coordinate representation.
The momentum representation allows us to obtain fairly
easily one result with which the reader is already famil-
iar. If a microparticle moves freely, equation (23.13)
is obviously simplified:
( - E) 1:E (Px) = 0, (23.15)
from which it immediately follows that
E = (23.16)
The result (23.16) has been already mentioned in Sec. 1.
It means that a freely moving particle simultaneously
possesses a definite energy and a definite momentum;
moreover, these quantities are related to each other by
the classical relation (23.16). In the case of a freely mov-
ing microparticle, the stationary state is also an eigen-
function of the momentum operator. We emphasize that
this can in no way be extended to bound microparticles
(see the following example).
In Sec. 21 we considered the problem of the motion of
a particle in a one-dimensional rectangular potential
well with infinitely high walls in the coordinate repre-
sentation. The energy levels (21.8) and the orthonorma-
lized amplitudes of stationary states (21. 9) were deter-
mined.
When going over to the momentum representation, the
result (21.8) obviously does not change, while the result
(21. 9) changes. By finding the amplitude of stationary
states in the momentum representation, we can also find
the probability of values of momentum of a particle in
the n-th energy state. We denote these amplitudes by
Tn (Px); the required probability will then be l1:
n
(Px)1
2
The amplitude 1:
n
(Px) are related to the amplitude of
stationary states in the coordinate representation [to
the amplitudes qJn (x)] by superposition relations of the
same type as (23.3):
1:
n
(Px) = JqJn (x) (Px) dx, (23.17)
A
where (Px) are the eigenfunctions of the operator x
in the momentum representation. By using the fact that
(Px) = (x), and (20.9), we can rewrite (23.17) in
the following form:
Probability of Momentum
for a Particle in a Rectangular
Well with Infinitely High Walls
218
a
1:
n
(Px) = (2nn)-1/2 JqJn (x) exp,( - iP
x
xl1i) dx.
o
(23.18)
By substituting (21.9) into this equation and integration,
we finally come to the following expressions for the prob-
,ability:
I
T ( ) 12 = 4nan
2
{ cos
2
( ~ ~ a , n is odd
n Px ( p2a2 ) 2
Ii n
2
n
2
_ :-2 . 2(_Px
a
) n l'S
n sIn 2ft' even
(23.19)
Thus, it has been rigorously shown that the stationary
states (energy levels) of a particle in the potential well
are not characterized by a definite momentum but by a
-corresponding definite de Broglie wavelength. We re-
mind the reader that this circumstance was qualitatively
discussed in Sec. 5"when we solved futility of a graphical
representation oCa bound microparticle in the form of a
-classical wave in a ,resonator.
Summing up, we can compile a "scheme" for the transi-
tion from one representation to another as follows:
1 L ~
This "scheme" assumes two methods of transition. The
first method: the Schr5dinger equation with the Hamilton-
ian Ii (x) is solved and the amplitudes of stationary states
q)n (x) are found in the coordinate representation. Then
with the help of the superposition relation (23.17) we
perform a transition from the amplitudes CPn (x) to the
amplitudes Tn (Px)' This is the method that was adopted
in the above example. However, it is also possible to
follow a second method: the transition from H (x) to
if (Px) is made and the Schr5dinger equation in the mo-
mentum representation (23.13) is solved. In this case,
the derivation of the amplitudes Tn (Px) is reduced to the
solution of the equation (23.13).
Sec. 23
~ ~ -------.,.
A Scheme for the Transition
from the Coordinate to the
Momentum Representation
219
The quantum-mechanical problem of an electron in a
periodic field plays an important role in the solid-state
theory. We turn to this problem, using the one-electron
approximation discussed in Sec. 22.
Let us consider a one-dimensional periodic potential
U (x) satisfying the condition
U (x + p) = U (x). (24.1)
Following the second method in the scheme given at the
end of the preceding section, we change over to the
momentum representation. This means that the poten-
tial U(x) should be expressed as an operator in the mo-
mentum representation, tJ (P:x;). (In order to simplify
the notation we shall write P for Px here.)
We expand the periodic function (24.1) in a Fourier series:
The Band Structure of the
Energy Spectrum. Brillouin Zones
00
U (x) = U (- i2nnx/a)
:::I n=-oo
and, changing to the momentum representation, we write
U(p)=
00
(
2:rtnh d)
exp ----
n a dp
n=-oo
(24.2)
We shall now show that the operator exp (PI is
a displacement operator with a finite displacement in
p-space by the amount P = Pl' This is so, as
dT 1 2 d
2
't
-r (p +Pi) = -r (p) +Pi dp (p) +21 Pi d
p
2 (p) +...
= [ 1+Pi +;, P: :;2 +... ] -r (p) = exp (Pi )
Thus
exp (Pi ) = -r (p +Pi)' (24.3)
From (24.2) and (24.3) it follows that
00
( 2:rth)
U(p)-r (p)= Un-r p+-a-n (24.4)
n=-oo
By using (24.4) we can write the Schrodinger equation
(23.13) in the following form:
'I:'"
I
r
i
220
00
(::-E)-r(p)+ Un-r (p+
2
:rt
a
hn) =0.
n=-oo
(24.5)
J I
j
"
". '.
In fact, (24.S) isa homogeneous system of linear equations
containing the functions 't (P), 't (p - 2'JTJi/a), 1: (p +
+ 2nfila), etc. Generally speaking, this system consists
of an infinite number of equations:
................................................................ 0 ..
[ (p+;:n/a)2 EJ 't (p + 2:n )
+ UnT: (p+
2nn
(:+1) ) = 0,
n
00
[:: -EJ1:(p)+ U
n
1: (p+
2
n:
n
)=0,} (24.6)
n=-oo
[(p-;:n/a)2
+v2 Un't (p+
2nn
(:-1) ) = O.
..................................... ,
Nonzero solutions of this homogeneous system are possible
only if its determinant is equal to zero. We denote this
determinant by D (E, p) and symbolically write
D (E, p) = O.
(24.7)
We fix P (let, say, P = PI) and write the roots of equation
(24.7) as E I (PI)' E
2
(PI)' E
3
(PI), .... For a different
value of P (say P = P2) we get new roots: E
I
(P2)' E
2
(P2)'
E3 (P2)' .... By choosing different values of P, we
finally get a set of functions defined by equation (24.7):
E
1
(p), E
2
(p), E
a
(p), ... , E
j
(P),
(24.8)
For every index j, the energy is a continuous function of
the momentum. By assuming that these functions are
bounded we write for the index j
E
min
/" E .( ) <" E
max
(24 . 9)
j """" j P "'" j
The inequalities (24.9) include the energy values for the
microparticle which constitute the jth energy band. If
Ef-af < Emr, we get a region of unattainable energy
values between the (j - 1)th and jth energy bands. This
region is llsually called the forbidden band.
Thus, the energy spectrum of an electron in a periodic
field must consist of a number of energy bands, some of
which may be separated by forbidden bands. Within every
energy band the energy varies continuously; it is described
by some contil1luous function E
j
(p).
Sec. 2..
(24.11)
...---------------------..
II (24.6) transJ,:
E
j
(p+2n:
n
)=Ej (p). (24.10}
I.'
1:1 Since the above replacement does not change anything,
I' we can say that the momentum p has physically different
r:
i
values within the limits of the band:
Ii' . - nti/a -< p -< nfi/a.
r
I
i'
"
i
.'
In other words, the p-space is split into intervals of length
2nfi/a, and one has to consider p only within the limits
of one individual interval. These intervals are called the
Brillouin zones. In this case we are dealing with one-
dimensional Brillouin zones. In general, the Brillouin
zones are three-dimensional; they often have a very com-
plex configuration, which reflects the specific nature of
the periodic field under consideration.
The band structure of the energy spectrum is characteris-
tic of an electron moving in the periodic field of a crystal
lattice. The concepts of energy bands and Brillouin zones
form the basis of the modern electronic theory of solids
(see, for example, [39, 40]).
BLOCH FUNCTIONS. Let us consider the jth energy band. Figure
(24.1) shows the dependence EJ (p) for this band. We choose some
value EO from this band and denote by pO the corresponding value
Fig. 24.1
of the momentum for motion to the right. The wave function of
the chosen stationary state is denoted through .. (p). It can be
easily seen that this function differs from zero only forp =
= pO + 2Jtnn/a [it can be seen from the figure that only at
222
points does the curve Ej (P) intersect the straight linelE = EO].
Hence the function (p) may be written in the form
-rJ(p)= (24.12)
n
Next, we go over to the coordinate representation by using the
familiar; rule (23.4):
co
(fJ (x) = (2nn)-1/2 J-rJ (p) exp (ipx/h) dp.
-co
we can rewrite the above result in the following form:
(fJ (x) = uJ (x) exp (ipox/h).
The explicit form of the function uJ (x) is not known to
know it, we should have known the explicit form of U (x)]. How-
ever, it can be seen from (24.13) that the function (x) is periodic
with the period of the field:
uJ(x+a)=uH;:) (24.14)
Thus, the wave function of a stationary state given by the indices
j and p has the following form in coordinate representation [ef.
(22.24)]:
y.. '
Substituting (24.12) into this, we get
g (po+2n
a
lin)
n
X exp [t (po+ 2n:ln) XIii].
By introducing the notation
(2nli)-1/2 Q (po+ 2n:n) exp (i 2n
a
nx) = uJ (x),
n
(24.13)
This is a plane wave [exp (ipx/Ii)] whose amplitude [Ujp (x)] is
periodic with the period of the field. The functions (24.15) are
referred to as Bloch functions in the literature.
223
(24.15)
The Kronig-Penney Potential
Fig. 24.2
(fjp (x)=Ujp (x) exp (ipx/h).
tet us consider the motion of a particle is a field whose
potential is shown in Fig. 24.2 (the so-called Kronig-
Penney potential). This is the simplest case of a periodic
potential.
Figure 24.2 shows three spatial regions. Assuming first
that E > U0' we write the solution of the Schrodinger
eqnation (20.13):
Sec. 24
,
,..
for region 1
qJdx)=Ai exp (ikix)+B
i
exp (-ikix);
k
i
= V2m (E-Uo)//i;
for region 2
qJ2(x)=A
2
exp (ik
2
x)+B
2
exp (-ik
2
x); k
2
=V2mE//i.
The solution for region 3 may be expressed in terms of
the solution for region 1 by using results obtained pre-
viously. Let us take a certain point x of region 3. Accord-
ing to (24.15), we can write
qJa (x) = u (x) exp (ipx//i). (24.16)
The symmetric point x - 1 in region 1 corresponds to
the chosen point. At the point x - 1 we have
qJl (x - 1) = u (x - l) exp lip (x - l)//i].
In accordance with (24.14), we rewrite this equality in
the form
qJl (x - l) = u (x) exp lip (x - l)//il. (24.17)
From (24.16) and (24.17) we find qJa (x) exp (- ipx//i) =
= qJl (x - l) exp (- ipx//i) exp (ipl//i) or, finally,
qJa (x) = exp (ipl//i){A
i
exp [ikdx-l)]
+B
i
exp [-ik.(x-l)]} (24.18)
By using (24.18) and the expression for qJl and qJ2' we
can write the continuity conditions for the wave function
and its first derivative at the points corresponding to the
potential jump (the points x = 0 and x = a). These con-
ditions form a homogeneous system of linear equations in
terms of the coefficients AI' B
l
, A
2
, B
2
:
Ai +B
i
=A
2
+B
2
Ai exp (ik
2
a) +B
i
exp (-ik
2
a)
= exp (ipll/i)[A
i
exp (- ikib) +B
i
exp (ikib)],
kiAi-kiB
i
= k
2
A
2
-k
2
B
2
,
k
2
[A
2
exp (ik
2
a)-B
2
exp (-ik
2
a)]
=exp (ipll/i)[A
i
exp (-ikib)-B
i
exp (ikib)]kio
By equating the determinant of this system to zero, we
get the following system (we omit the intermediate steps):
.cos (pll/i) = cos ~ a cos (kib) kJ;;;k:
i
sin (k
2
a) sin (kib).
(24.19)
Since the modulus of the cosine cannot be greater than
unity, we get the following condition imposed on quanti-
ties k
1
and k
2
and, hence, on E:
-1-<: [cos (kza) cos (k
1
b)- sin (k
2
a) sin (k
1
b)]<;: 1.
(24.20)
This condition defines the allowed energy bands.
We next consider the case when E < Uo.
Now k1 is an imaginary quantity. Suppose k
1
= ik
3
,
where k3 = V2m (U
o
- E)/li. Since by replacing k
1
by
ik3 the cosine and the sine are converted into hyperbolic
cosine and hyperbolic sine, respectively [cos (k1b) -+
-+cosh (k
3
b); sin (k1b) -+ i sinh (k
3
b)1, we can make use
of the result (24.19), which in this case assumes the form
cos ( ) = cos (k
2
tl) cosh (k
3
b)
+ sin (k
2
a) sinh (k
3
b). (24.21)
Accordingly, the condition (24.20) defining the energy
bands is transformed into the following form:
-1 -<: [cos (kza) cosh (k
3
b)
+ sin (kza) sinh (k
3
b) ] -<: 1. (24.22)
Let us consider a special when
b (a l); U
o
(24.23)
(the barriers are narrow and high). Since in this case the
quantity b can become arbitrarily small, we can require
that the following conditions be fulfilled:
bV2mU 1, or k
3
b 1. (24.24)
By taking (24.24) into account, we put cosh (k
3
b) /'OV 1
and sinh (k
3
b) /'OV k
3
b, and besides, according to (24.23),
k
3
/2k2 YUo/E.
As a result, (24.21) assumes the following form:
cos (pa/li) = F (k
2
a), (24.25)
where we have used the notation
F (y) = cos y +(mUoblk
2
li
2
) sin y.
The condition (24.22) assumes the form
- 1 -<: F (k
2
a) -<: 1.
Sec. 24
(24.26)
(24.27)
p------------------zr
Fig. 24.:3
The function F (k
2
a) is shown in Fig. 24.3. The parts of
the k
2
a axis, for which the condition (24.27) is satisfied,
have been shaded in the diagram. They correspond to the
allowed energy bands (remember that k
2
= y!2mEln).
I
(
1
(
I
I
Fig. 24.4
\
\1
\.
Using (24.25)-(24.27), we shall make two remarks. First-
ly, if a 00 (transition to a free electron), cos (k
2
a)
cos (pain); this corresponds to a transition to the clas-
sical relation (23.16) for the energy and momentum of a
particle. Secondly, it can be seen from Fig. 24.3 that a
I
I
I
I
I
:1
'I
I
i
I
discontinuity in the energy of the electron occurs when
cos (pain) = + 1, i.e. for pain = nn, where n is an in-
teger. According to (24.11), this means that the discon-
tinuities in the energy of the electron occur at the boun-
dary of the Brillouin zone. '
Figure (24.4) shows the dependence of the electron energy
on momentum as determined by (24.25). The discontin-
uities in the energy mentioned above are clearly seen
(the energy bands are shown on the left side by hatching).
For comparison the classical dependence of energy on
momentum is shown for a free electron: E = p2/2m.
The conversion of energy levels of an electron in the
atom into energy bands of an electron "collectivized"
by the crystal may be seen as an effect of the removal of
commutation degeneracy.
As was mentioned in Sec. 22, the electron energy in an
atom in the general case of a non-Coulomb potential is
determined by the quantum numbers nand l. This gives
rise to a 2 (2l + 1)-fold degeneracy of this energy. By
assuming that the atom is a part of some perfectly ordered
ensemble of N similar atoms and that it remains isolated
from its neighbours', the degeneracy in the electron energy
must be taken as 2N (2l + i)-fold. The factor N is asso-
ciated with the so-called commutation degeneracy: in an
ordered ensemble, there are no physically isolated atoms,
hence the energy of an electron cannot depend on any of
the N atoms near which it is localized. However, in a real
ensemble (i.e. a crystal), the atoms are not isolated-
they interact with one another. This interaction leads to
a "collectivization" of the electron and a partial removal
of degeneracy of its levels. The level with a 2N (2l + 1)-
fold degeneracy is split up into a system consisting of
N (2l + 1) sublevels, each of which remains doubly de-
generate (according to the spin quantum number 0').
: Thus a "collectivization" of the electron by the crystal
leads to a removal of commutation degeneracy and de-
generacy with respect to the quantum number m.
It is significant that a system of N (2l + 1) sublevels is
in reality not discrete, but forms a band of allowed val-
ues of the electron energy. Indeed, let !1.E be the width
of this system of sublevels, and !1.e be the distance be-
tween the neighbouring sublevels: !1.e = !1.E/N (2l + 1).
For the system of sublevels to be discrete, it is essential
that !1.e > hh, where't is the lifetime of an electron in
a crystal. In other words, the distance between sublevels
must be greater than the uncertainty jn the energy of the
Sublevel described by the relation (3.2). This means that
the condition
Formation of Energy Bands as an
Effect of the Removal of
Commutation Degeneracy
h (2l + 1) N/!1.E < 't (24.28)
must be satisfied. Assuming that N (2l + 1) 10
23
,
'dE 1 eV, we find that't should be more than 10
8
s,
Le. more than 10 years. Since the real lifetime of a "col-
p--------------------"..
lectivized" electron in the crystal may only be less than
this, the relation (24.28) is obviously not satisfied. This
enables us to consider the system of N (2l + 1) sublevels
as an energy band. Naturally the number of electron states
in the band remains finite-the band may "accommodate"
up to 2N (2l + 1) electrons. In this connection we speak
of the degree of filling in of a band, of completely filled
bands, etc.
Section 25
The Probability of Quantum
Transitions
Quantum Transitions and the
Principle of Superposition of
States
We assume that a microparticle undergoes a transition
from one stationary state to another under the action of
some external factor. How to find the probability of such
a transition?
The initial and the final states of the microparticle are
described by functions of the type (20.16). For example,
let the initial state be given by 'l'n (x, t)
= ern (Xl exp (- iEnt/fi). For simplicity, the set of spatial
coordinates is denoted by x. The functions 'J!n satisfy
the Schr6dinger equation (20.17): .
(25.1)
(we shall call it the "unperturbed" equation). The phys-
ical nature of external factor, which causes the quantum
transition of the microparticle, is arbitrary. In particular,
it may be the interaction of the microparticle with electro-
magnetic radiation. In the quantum theory apparatus
such a factor appears in the form of an interaction poten-
tial which must be added to the "unperturbed" Hamilto-
nian fl. In Sec. 22 in the example of the interaction of an
electron with radiation, this "addition" to the Hamilto-
nian was interpreted as some perturbation and was denoted
by it'. We shall use the same notation here. By taking
into account the perturbation iI', we can rewrite the
Schr6dinger equation in the form
(25.2)
228
This equation is called the "perturbed" equation. Its
solutions CD
n
are no longer stationary states. Hence the
index n here does not fix the energy level, but merely
indicates the past history: the given "perturbed" state
has "emerged" from nth "unperturbed" state.
Essentially, the state <P
n
is a superposition state:
(25.3)
n
If at a certain time t we "switch on" the corresponding
detector, the superposition (25.3) is destroyed and the
microparticle will be observed in one of the stationary
states, for example, in the state 'm' This means that the
microparticle has undergone a quantum transition from
the state 1fn to the state 1fm' It is well known that the
probability of such a transition is 1 Xnm 0) 1
2
Appendix B
There is a formal analogy between the transition from quantum
mechanics to classical mechanics and the transition from wave
optics to geometrical optics (Le. the optico-mechanical analogy);
see, for example, [10, 11]. A transition to geometrical optics
means that the optical field is described by nearly plane wavtB
of the type
~
eie:tl =ei(k r-lilf).
It can be seen from (B.1) that
- a<D
k=V<D; 00=-
(B.t)
(B.2)
The vector k is directed along the light beam. At every point in
space the light beam is perpendicular to the surface of constant
phase (Le. perpendicuYar to the surface <D = const).
When:going over to classical mechanics, the quantum-mechanical wa-
ve function must acquire a form analogous to (B.1); moreover, the
phase of the wave function will be proportional to the mechanical
action S:
<D = AS.
The momentum-; and energy E of a particle are expressed through
the action S in the following way:
;=VS;
as
E=--
at
(B.3)
250
The trajectories are lines perpendicular to the surface of constan\
action (in the same way as the light rays are perpendicular to the
urface of constant phase). Comparing (B.2) and (B.3) and taking
- - into account that p = ftk, we find that
<D = SIn.
Thus the quasiclassical wave function is of tlle form
'i'= a e i h ~ (B)
By using (B.4) it is easy to determine the coefficient y in the flxpree-
sion for the momentum operator
.;;.
p=yV.
Let us consider the equation for the eigenfunctions of the mome"
..; -
tum operator (the equation P'i' = p') in the quasiclassical caSll.
In this case we get -; = VS, 'i' = aeis/II. Thus the above equatiOP
assumes the form
yVeiB/7a = VSlliS/'A
g
t
e Appendix C
251
(C.1)
== (; X p) may he written in the form
3 3
Ml= t'lm;:kPn,
k_ln_l
Appendices
where e'kn is a unit tensor of tbe 3rd rank (e123 =
== e2S1 = R: f, e132 = e321 = eU3 == -1, all the flther com-
ponents of the tensor are equal to zero).
Let us consider the commutator [Mi' ;:j]' By using (C.1), we tan
wnte thI!! commutator in the following form:
Mj, e'kn
11 n
We shall show how the commutation relations (20.28)-(20.30) can Commutation
he derived. To start with we remark that the equahty M=
It can be easily seen that iy/1i = 1, and, consequently, '\' = -in.
The quasiclassical case may he used to substantiate the Schrodinger
equation. It can be easily seen that the well-known classical Ha-
milton-Iacobi equation
(VS)2+U=0
at 2m
s a limiting case of the Schrodinger equation (20.17). By putting
'I' = e
iS
/,.. we get in this case
tl! .!.... 'I' =
at at e ,
_ 21!2 A'I'= - 21!2 V,(V'I')=
m m 2m
XV (.!:.... VS.e
iS
/,.) = -i2- (VS)! eiS/h.
I! 2m
Substituting these results intEl (20.17) and neglecting terms con-
taiDlng Planck's constant in thu expression for A'I', we get the
equatiEln
e
iS
/,.,;;;-!.- (VS)! Ue
iS
/,..
at 2m
By cancelling out the factor e
iS
/,.. this equation becomes the Ha-
milton-I acohi equation.
.,
yeiS/f,VS
n
)
)
e
I
}
t
Our address:
USSR.129820.Moscow 1-110. GSP
Pervy Rlzhsky Pt*euk>k,2
MIR PUBLISHERS