Karl Marx On The Transition From Feudalism To Capitalism
Karl Marx On The Transition From Feudalism To Capitalism
Karl Marx On The Transition From Feudalism To Capitalism
CLAUDIO J. KATZ
Loyola University- Chicago
struggle effects this change rather than that," Cohen explains, "we must
turn to the dialectic of forces and relations of production which
governs class behaviour and is not explicable in terms of it, and which
determines what the long-term outcome of class struggle will be.''3 His
challenge to a version of Marx's theory that makes class struggle funda-
mental is to "explain, other than by reference to the disposition of clas-
ses to develop the productive forces, what makes successful classes
succeed.''4
The argument of this article moves back and forth between two levels
of analysis. The first level is that of Marx's mature historical studies.
There exists a widely recognized disjuncture in Marx's writings
between his ascription of the basic cause of historical change to, on the
one hand, technological progress and, on the other, class struggle]
Marx's earlier works, notably the German Ideology, provide an account
of human history that awards primacy to material progress. When
generalizing about history, Marx typically defends the technological
thesis. In his later writings, particularly in the Grundrisse and Capital,
Marx's practice as a historian awards primacy to classes. Marx did not,
however, spell out the logic of the historical explanations at work in
these texts. My aim, then, is to lay bare and explicate the causal prin-
ciples shaping Marx's own historical judgements. The result of this
study is a "reconstruction" of Marx's theory of epochal change that
seeks to correct several misunderstandings of its central claims.S
365
This article is divided into four sections. The first places the controver-
sy about Marx's theory of history in the context of his account of the
rise of English capitalism. The second examines Marx's conception of
the feudal dynamic and its characteristic crisis complex. This section
argues that Marx's understanding of the fundamental contradiction
precipitating the dissolution of a social formation is sharply at odds
with that which Cohen attributes to him. The third section reconstructs
Marx's analysis of the class conflicts resulting in a qualitative social
transformation. This section shows that Marx's text provides an explana-
tion for why successful classes succeed (and fail) that relies solely on the
internal dynamic of class conflict. The concluding section formulates
the logic of epochal change that emerges from Marx's historical study.
The lacuna in this story lies in its failure to explain the shifting fortunes
of the contending classes. 21 Brenner argues that the English lords failed
to maintain or restore their traditional prerogatives in the face of fierce
peasant resistance at the close of the Middle Ages, and yet succeeded
in evicting the peasants from the soil in the early modern period. = He
admits, however, that he does not have a good answer to the question
why feudal class struggle in England produced this outcome. Indeed,
Brenner points out that the very strength of peasant communities
necessary to cripple the feudal regime would have precluded the expro-
priation of the cultivators from the land. In his view, however, small
peasant proprietorship is incapable of engendering economic develop-
368
Take it, for instance, that the enforced labour for the landlord originally
amounted to two days per week.These two days of enforced labour per week
are thereby fixed.... But the productivity of the remaining days of the week,
which are at the disposal of the direct producer himself, is a variable magni-
tude, which must develop in the course of his experience.... The possibilityis
here presented for definite economic development taking place. 37
This account of the basic cause of feudal economic growth turns the
orthodox reading of Marx's theory upside down. In Cohen's interpreta-
tion, "the class which rules through a period, or emerges triumphant
from epochal conflict does so because it is best suited, most able and
disposed, to preside over the development of the productive forces at
the time. ''39 But in Marx's view, it is the class of subordinate producers,
the peasantry, that was primarily responsible for the material progress
witnessed in medieval Europe. On the whole, the lords did not either
directly or indirectly encourage it. Quite the contrary, their economic
strategies systematically impaired the optimal use and development of
the existing productive forces. 4°
What was rational for the lords, given their position in the class struc-
ture, was ultimately irrational for the feudal economy as a whole.
The economic impact of feudal rents was primarily disruptive, and the
lords' distance from the economy afforded them little incentive to
gauge the effects of their levies on the peasant holdings. As Marx
noted, rents had to be treated as an obligatory prior expense that whol-
ly determined the share of the surplus retained by the village econ-
omy.42 Rents were inescapable and sometimes arbitrary; they could not
be adjusted to suit the tenants' changing circumstances. Rent increases
not only depressed the peasantry's economic situation but also dimin-
ished the funds necessary to reproduce feudalism's material base.
Feudal rent, wrote Marx, "may assume dimensions which seriously
imperil reproduction of the conditions of labour, the means of produc-
tion themselves, rendering the expansion of production more or less
impossible....,43
The nature of the feudal crisis complex is plainly incompatible with the
account of crises given by orthodox historical materialism. In the
orthodox view, grounded in the thesis that there is an autonomous ten-
dency for the forces of production to develop, "it is possible to speak of
a contradiction between the forces and the relations of production, but
not between classes.''45 A contradiction obtains when a society's class
relations fetter the optimal use and development of its productive ca-
pacity, "when prospects opened by its productive forces are closed by
its productive relations. ''46 The collision between the developing forces
and the increasingly restrictive relations is ultimately resolved in favor
of the forces, by a qualitative change in the relations.
The private property of the labourer in his means of production is the foun-
dation of petty industry, whether agricultural, manufacturing, or both; petty
industry, again, is an essential condition for the development of social pro-
duction and of the free individuality of the labourer himself. Of course, this
petty mode of production exists also under slavery,serfdom and other states
of dependence. But it flourishes, it lets loose its whole energy, it attains its
classical form, only where the labourer is the private owner of his own means
of labour set in action by himself: the peasant of the land which he cultivates,
the artisan of the tool which he handles as a virtuoso.6~
The growing prosperity of the peasant village was, however, only the
first consequence of its emancipation from feudal rule. The second,
already evident in the sixteenth century, was the growing differentiation
within its ranks. TM The peasantry's success in crippling the feudal
376
regime was its last act as a cohesive social class. The peasant commu-
nity had never been an idyll of cooperation. E c o n o m i c conflict, par-
ticularly between wealthier and p o o r e r peasants, was not uncommon.
To be sure, conflicts within the village were always sharply circum-
scribed by the conflict between the village and the lords. Against the
nobility, their c o m m o n antagonist, they maintained their unity; in other
respects, large and small holders were increasingly divided. 71 More-
over, the peasants' achievement in securing the conditions of free
tenure contributed to growing land transfers, disrupting the ancient
tenemental arrangements that had given peasant villages their internal
solidity and resilience. Thus, if their cohesion made successful struggle
against the lords possible, their very success against the lords destroyed
the rationale for concerted action, spelling the end of village solidarity.
The logic of the new class system required the members of the domi-
nant class to adopt strategies for optimizing surplus appropriation that
consisted primarily in productive investments. On the one hand, the
market in tenants created by the introduction of purely commercial
relationships between landlords and farmers produced a situation in
which all but the most efficient farmers went under. On the other hand,
competition among landlords for tenants ensured that they could not
simply "squeeze" the farmers, threatening the funds available for im-
provement and hindering progressive husbandry. The resulting pattern
of investment allowed England to overcome the "crises of subsistence"
which plagued pre-capitalist economies.76
This is the economic meaning of the English Civil War: its special
accomplishment was to replace the political and juridical conditions of
feudal exploitation with conditions facilitating capitalist exploitation.
Parliamentary leaders converted all lands that were formerly held of
the king by feudal tenure into absolute ownership. Feudal rights, how-
ever, were abolished upwards only, not downwards: "the landed pro-
prietors," Marx writes, "abolished the feudal tenure of land, i.e., they
got rid of all its obligations to the state, 'indemnified' the State by taxes
on the peasantry and the rest of the mass of the people, [and] vindicat-
ed for themselves the rights of modern private property in estates to
which they had only a feudal title.''79 Both King and Parliament had fit-
fully sought to stem enclosures prior to the Civil War. Enclosure had
been pushed forward mainly by "individual acts of violence against
which legislation, for a hundred and fifty years, fought in vain.''8° After
1660, no government seriously attempted to check them. Whatever
was restored at the Restoration, it is surely significant that feudal ten-
ures and restrainst upon the enclosure of land were not. 81 Enclosures
were now arranged by the government itself. The peasantry lost all
attempts to secure property rights in holdings "to which [they] had the
same feudal right as the lord.''82 By the eighteenth century, the enclo-
sure movement in England experienced a veritable boom, reaching its
climax during the Napoleonic Wars. "The rise of a landless proletariat
was a long-drawn-out process," comments Hill, "but henceforth it was
an inevitable one.''83
Freeman and slave, patrician and plebeian, lord and serf, guild-master and
journeyman, in a word, oppressor and oppressed, stood in constant opposi-
tion to one another, carried on an uninterrupted, now hidden, now open
fight, a fight that each time ended, either in a revolutionary re-constitution of
society at large, or in the common ruin of the contending classes.~
Notes
1. G.A. Cohen, History, Labour, and Freedom (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1988), 3.
2. See in particular Robert Brenner, "Agrarian Class Structure and Economic Devel-
opment in Pre-Industrial Europe," and "The Agrarian Roots of European Capital-
ism," in The Brenner Debate, Agrarian Class Structure and Economic Development
in Pre-lndustrial Europe, ed. T. H. Aston and C. H. E. Philpin (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1987). Compare Robert Brenner, "The Social Basis of
Economic Development," with G.A. Cohen, "Forces and Relations of Produc-
tion," both in Analytical Marxism, ed. John Roemer (Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 1986). See also Joshua Cohen, "Review of Karl Marx's Theory of His-
tory," TheYournal of Philosophy 5 (May 1982): 253-273, and G. A. Cohen,'s reply
in History, Labour, and Freedom, 85-106; John Roemer, Free to Lose (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1988), 108-124.
3. Cohen, History, Labour, and Freedom, 14. See also Roemer, Free to Lose, 114-16.
4. G. A. Cohen, "Reply to Four Critics," in Analyse &Kritik 5 (1983): 207.
5. See Richard Miller, Analyzing Marx (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984),
237; Alan Carling, "Liberty, Equality, Community," New Lefi Review 171 (Septem-
ber/October 1988): 95. Cohen maintains that the transition to capitalism provides
the best example of his defense of Marx's theory. G. A. Cohen, Karl Marx's Theory
of History: A Defenee (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1978), 169-170,
175-180.
6. Marx himself came to question the extent to which lessons drawn from the English
historical experience were generalizable. Compare Karl Marx, Capital, trans.
Samuel Moore and Edward Aveling, ed. Frederick Engels, 3 vols. (Moscow: Pro-
gress Publishers, n.d.) 1:19 and 669-670, with Karl Marx, Letter to the Editorial
Board of Otechestvennye Zapiski, November 1877, in Late Marx and the Russian
Road, ed. Teodor Shanin (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1983), 135-136. See
the discussions by Haruki Wada, "Marx and Revolutionary Russia," 48-49, 57-60,
and Derek Sayer and Philip Corrigan, "Late Marx: Continuity, Contradiction and
Learning," 77-80, both in Late Marx and the Russian Road, ed. Teodor Shanin.
7. Habermas provides an excellent discussion of Marx's oscillation between these two
principles of causality. Knowledge and Human Interests, trans. Jeremy Shapiro
(Boston: Beacon Press, 1971), 25-63. See also Brenner, "The Social Basis of Eco-
nomic Development," 40-47; Robert Brenner, "Bourgeois Revolution and Transi-
tion to Capitalism," in The First Modern Society, ed. A. L. Beier et al. (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1989), 272-95; Perry Anderson, In the Tracks of His-
torical Materialism (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 33-35; Jon
Elster, Making Sense of Marx (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985),
238, 272, 284-285,318; Claudio J. Katz, From Feudalism to Capitalism: Marxian
Theories of Class Struggle and Social Change (Westport, Ct. Greenwood Press,
1989), 1-47. Attempts to reconcile these two versions of historical materialism,
typically by way of an appeal to a dialectical interplay between productive develop-
ment and class struggle, have been largely unsuccessful because two fundamentally
different explanations of historical change are being brought into play. This is a
logical and not a dialectical contradiction.
8. "Reconstruction," writes Habermas, "signifies taking a theory apart and putting it
back together again in a new form in order to attain more fully the goal it has set for
itself. This is the normal way ... of dealing with a theory that needs revision in many
384
respects but whose potential for stimulation has still not been exhausted." Commu-
nication and the Evolution of Society, trans. Thomas McCarthy (Boston: Beacon
Press, 1979), 95.
9. E.J. Hobsbawm, Introduction to Karl Marx, Pre-Capitalist Economic Formations
(New York: International Publishers, 1964), 20-27.
10. Perry Anderson, Arguments Within English Marxism (London: NLB, 1980), 66.
Surely one of the most telling objections to Cohen's interpretation of Marx is that
its "distinctive ideas ... have not been put to work, to any significant extent, in any
reasonably successful detailed study of any major historical question by an inves-
tigator sympathetic to Marx." Miller, Analyzing Marx, 264. See also Rodney
Hilton, "Feudalism in Europe: Problems for Historical Materialists," in Class Con-
flict and the Crisis of Feudalism, ed. Rodney Hilton (London: NLB, 1990), 1-11.
11. Marx, Capital 1: 671; also pp. 672, 676.
12. Marx, Capital 3: 806. See also Capital 1: 316, n. 3; Karl Marx, Grundrisse, trans.
Martin Nicolaus (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1973), 510.
13. Marx, Capital 1: 694-695, 713; Capital 3: 798-800, 807.
14. Marx, Capital 1: 165.
15. Marx, Capital 1: 165.
16. Marx, Capital 1: 667.
17. Marx, Capital 1: 669. See also Marx, Grundrisse, 4 7 1 , 4 8 9 - 4 9 0 , 497-498, 5 0 5 -
514.
18. Cohen, KarlMarx's Theory of History, 175-180.
19. Marx, Capital 1: 668. See also Marx, Grundrisse, 506-509.
20. Marx, Capital 3: 796-802.
21. Among Brenner's critics, only William H. Hagen has noted this lacuna in his argu-
ment. See William H. Hagen, "Capitalism and the Countryside in Early Modern
Europe: Interpretations, Models, Debates," Agricultural History 1 (1988): 41-42.
22. Brenner, "The Agrarian Roots of European Capitalism," 291-296.
23. Brenner, "Social Basis of Economic Development," 49-52; "The Agrarian Roots
of European Capitalism," 306-311.
24. Brenner, "Social Basis of Economic Development," 53.
25. See, e.g., Michael Duggett, "Marx on Peasants," The Journal of Peasant Studies 2
(January 1975): 159-182; Alan Macfarlane, The Origins of English Individualism
(New York: Cambridge University Press, 1978), 37-44; David Mitrany, Marx
Against the Peasant (New York: Collier Books, 1961), 31-75. For a more balanced
reading, see Hal Draper, Karl Marx's Theory of Revolution, 4 vols. (New York:
Monthly Review Press, 1977-90) 2: 317-452. Teodor Shanin subscribes to the
prevailing view that Marx's Grundrisse and Capital treat the peasantry as fodder for
history. He argues, however, that Marx came to abandon this conception in the last
decade of his life when he turned his attention to Russia and the Russian peasant
commune. See Teodor Shanin, "Late Marx: Gods and Craftsmen," in Late Marx
and the Russian Road, ed. Shanin, 3-39. The argument of this article suggests that
no sharp break occurred between Marx's "mature" and "later" years. As I argue
later in the article, his historical judgments typically sought to trace the variable
roles of peasants in different historical contexts. See also Claudio J. Katz, "Marx on
the Peasantry: Class in Itself or Class in Struggle?" The Review of Politics 54
(Winter 1992): 50-71. Sayer and Corrigan have stressed both the distinctiveness
and importance of the "later Marx" as well as the significant continuities in his
thinking between Capital and his last years. See Sayer and Corrigan, "Late Marx:
Continuity, Contradiction and Learning," 77-94.
385
26. See the perceptive critiques by Patricia Croot and David Parker, "Agrarian Class
Structure and the Development of Capitalism: France and England Compared,"
79-90, and J. P. Cooper, "In Search of Agrarian Capitalism," 144-148, 188, both
in The Brenner Debate, ed. Aston and Philpin. See also Robert H. Bates, "Lessons
from History, or the Perfidy of English Exceptionalism and the Significance of His-
torical France," World Politics 40 (1988): 507-509. Peter Kriedte shares Brenner's
Marxian orientation, despite some disagreements, adhering to the view that the
agricultural revolution in England awaited the prior elimination of the peasantry.
Peter Kriedte, Peasants, Landlords and Merchant Capitalists (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1983), 23-24, 74-75. See also Hagen, "Capitalism and the
Countryside in Early Modern Europe," 17-18, 30.
27. For a critical review of this orthodoxy, see Bates, "Lessons From History,"
499-516.
28. Making Sense of Marx, 278.
29. Miller, Analyzing Marx, 198.
30. Marx, Capital3: 790.
31. Marx, Capital3: 790-791.
32. Marx, Capital3: 791.
33. Christopher Dyer, Standards of Living in the Later Middle Ages (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1989), 53-55, 89-91 (for a discussion of aristocratic
household expenditures, see ch. 3). See also M. M. Postan, The Medieval Economy
and Society (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1972), 103; M. M. Postan
and John Hatcher, "Population and Class Relations in Feudal Society," in The
Brenner Debate, ed. Aston and Philpin, 77-78; R. H. Hilton, "A Crisis of Feudal-
ism" in The Brenner Debate, ed. Aston and Philpin, 130-131; Brenner, "The
Agrarian Roots of European Capitalism," 238-242; Perry Anderson, Lineages of
the Absolutist State (London: NLB, 1974), 31-32.
34. Hilton, "A Crisis of Feudalism," 131. See Brenner, "The Agrarian Roots of Euro-
pean Capitalism," 233.
35. Marx, Capital 3: 794-796. See also Perry Anderson, Passagesfrom Antiquity to
Feudalism (London: NLB, 1974), 185-188.
36. Marx, Capital 3: 793.
37. Marx, Capital 3: 794. To be sure, the peasantry's contribution to productive devel-
opment should not be overemphasized. Peasant production, Marx argued, imposed
its own limits on economic growth; Capital 3: 807-808, 810. Moreover, medieval
economic development as a whole involved expanding output, primarily by re-
claiming uncultivated land, rather than increasing productivity. See Anderson, Pas-
sages from Antiquity to Feudalism, 188-190; Postan, The Medieval Economy and
Society, 41-44.
38. Postan, The Medieval Economy and Society, 44-57.
39. Cohen, History, Labour and Freedom, 15.
40. Cohen's thesis that pre-capitalist class rule, despite the obstacles it posed to pro-
ductive development, was best suited to promote material progress given the level
of material development at the time, is widely contradicted by economic historians.
Contrast Cohen's defense of this thesis, in Karl Marx's Theory of History, 169-171
and History, Labour and Freedom, 103-105, with the conclusions of Postan, The
MedievalEconomy and Society, 41-44, 102-104; Hilton, "A Crisis of Feudalism,"
130-131; Brenner, "Agrarian Class Structure and Economic Development," 31-
34, and "The Agrarian Roots of European Capitalism," 232-238; Dyer, Standards
of Living in the Later Middle Ages, 7.
386