Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

The Summa Theologica: S1. Thomas Aquinas

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 11

---------

Summa Theologica
Page I of II
S1. Thomas Aquinas
The Summa Theologica
(Benziger Bros. edition, 1947)
Translated by
Fathers of the Engl ish Domi nican Province
----.----
Index [ 1
Second Pan of the Second Pan [ I ]
Question : 64 [ I ]
V1CES OPPOSED TO COMl\1UTATIVE JUSTICE (Questions [641-81)
(A) BY DEEDS (Questions [641-66)
OF MURDER (EIGHT ARTICLES)
In due sequence we must consider the vices opposed to commutative justice. We must consider (1)
those sins that are committed in relation to involuntary commutations; (2) those that are committed with
regard to voluntary commutations. Sins are conunitted in relation to involuntary commutations by doing
an injury to one's neighbor against his will : and this can be done in two ways, namely by deed or by
word. By deed when one's neighbor is injured either in his own person, or in a person connected with
him , or in his possessions.
We must therefore consider these points in due order, and in the first place we shall consider murder
whereby a man inflicts the greatest injury on his neighbor. Under this head there are eight points of
inquiry:
W. Whether it is a sin to kill dumb animals or even plants?(2) Whether it is lawful to kill a sinner?
ill Whether this is lawful to a private individual, or to a public person only?
(4) Whether this 1S lawful to a cleric?
W Whether it is lawful to kill oneself?
((i) Whether it is lawful to kill a just man?
(7) Whether it is lawful to kill a man in self-defense?
(.8.) Whether accidental homicide is a mortal sin?
3/1312008 hIIp:11\\'\'/\1/ . ceel. org/aJaq uinas/sumrna/SSISS064. htmI
Page 2 of II
r n d e ~ [ 1
Second Part of the Second Part [ I~
Question: 64 [ I]
Article: I [ I]
Whether it is unlawful to kill any living thing?
Objection 1: It would seem unlawful to kill any living thing. For the Apostle says (Rm. 13:2) : "They
that resist the ordinance of God purchase to themselves damnation [*Vulg.: 'He that resisteth the power,
resisteth the ordinance of God: and they that resist, purchase themselves damnation.']." Now Divine
providence has ordained that all living things should be preserved, according to Ps. 146:8,9, "Who
maketh grass to grow on the mountains . .. Who giveth to beasts their food." Therefore it seems
unlawful to take the life of any living thing.
Objection 2: Further, murder is a sin because it deprives a man of life. Now life is common to all
animals and plants. Hence for the same reason it is apparently a sin to slay dumb animals and plants.
Objection 3: Further, in the Divine law a special punishment is not appointed save for a sin. Now a
special punishment had to be inflicted, according to the Divine law, on one who killed another man's ox
or sheep (Ex._22:1). Therefore the slaying of dumb animals is a sin.
On the contrary, Augustine says (De Civ. Dei i, 20) : "When we hear it said, 'Thou shalt not kill,' we do
not take it as referring to trees, for they have no sense, nor to irrational animals, because they have no
fellowshi p with us. Hence it follows that the words, 'Thou shalt not kill' refer to the killing of a man."
I answer that, There is no sin in using a thing for the purpose for which it is. Now the order of things is
such that the imperfect are for the perfect, even as in the process of generation nature proceeds from
imperfection to perfection. Hence it is that just as in the generation of a man there is first a living thing,
then an animal, and Jastly a man, so too things, like the plants, which merely have life, are all alike for
animals, and all animals are for man. Wherefore it is not unlawful ifman use plants for the good of
animals, and animals for the good of man, as the Philosopher states (Polit. i, 3).
Now the most necessary use would seem to consist in the fact that animals use plants, and men use
animals, for food, and this cannot be done unless these be deprived of life: wherefore it is lawful both to
lake Iife from plants for the use of animals, and from animals for the use 0 f men. In fact this is in
keeping with the commandment of God Himself: for it is written (Gn. I :29,30) : "Behold I have given
you every herb ... and all trees ... to be your meat, and to all beasts of the earth": and again (yo. 9:3):
"Everything that moveth and liveth shall be meat to you."
Reply 10 Objection l: According to the Divine ordinance (he life of animals and plants is preserved not
for themselves but for man . Hence, as Augustine says (De Civ. Dei i, 20), "by a most just ordinance of
the Creator, both their life and their death are subject to our use."
Reply to Objection 2: Dumb animal s and plants are devoid of the Iife of reason w hereby to set
themselves in motion; they are moved, as it were by another, by a kind of natural impulse, a sign of
which is that they are naturally enslaved and accommodated to the uses of others.
Reply 10 Objection 3: He that kills another's ox, sins, not through killing the ox, but through injuring
another man in his property. Wherefore this is not a species of the sin of murder but of the sin of theft or
http://www.ccel.org/alaguinas/summalSS/SS064.html 3/)312008
Summa Theologies
Page 3 of II
robbery.
Index [ J
Second Pan of the Seco nd Pan [ I
Question: 64
Article: 2 [ I 1
Whether it is lawful to kill sinners?
Objection 1: It would seem unlawful to kill men who have sinned. For our Lord in the parable
forbade the uprooting of the cockle which denotes wicked men according to a gloss. Now whatever is
forbidden by God is a sin. Therefore it is a sin to kill a sinner.
Objection 2: Further, human justice is conformed to Divine justice. Now according to Divine justice
sinners are kept back for repentance, according to Ezech. 33: 1l , "I desire not the death of the wicked,
but that the wicked tum from his way and live." Therefore it seems altogether unjust to kill sinners.
Objection 3: Further, it is not lawful, for any good end whatever, to do that which is evil in itself,
according to Augustine (Contra Mendac. vii) and the Philosopher (Ethic. ii, 6). Now to kill a man is evil
in itself, since we are bound to have charity towards all men, and "we wish our friends to live and to
exist ," according to Ethic. ix, 4. Therefore it is nowise lawful to kill a man who has sinned.
On the contrary, It is written CE:5.. 22: 18): "Wizards thou shalt not suffer to live"; and (Ps, 100:8): "In
the morning r put to death all the wicked of the land."
I answer that, As stated above (Article (11), it is lawful to kill dumb animals, in so far as they are
naturally directed to man's use, as the imperfect is directed to the perfect. Now every part is directed to
the whole, as imperfect to perfect, wherefore every part is naturally for the sake of the whole. For this
reason we observe that if the health of the whole body demands the excision of a member, through its
being decayed or infectious to the other members, it will be both praiseworthy and advantageous to have
it cut away, Now every individual person is compared to the whole community, as part to whole.
Therefore if a man be dangerous and infectious to the communi ty, on account of some sin, it is
praiseworthy and advantageous that he be killed in order to safeguard the common good, since "a little
leaven corrupteth the whole lump" (I Cor. 5:6).
Reply to Objection 1: Our Lord commanded them to forbear from uprooting the cockle in order to
spare the wheat , i.e. the good . This occurs when the wicked cannot be slain without the good being
killed with them, either because the wicked lie hidden among the good, or because they have many
followers, so that they cannot be killed without danger to the good, as Augustine says (Contra Parrnen.
iii, 2). Wherefore our Lord teaches that we should rather allow the wicked to live, and that vengeance is
to be delayed until the Iast judgment, rather than that the good be put to death together with the vvicked.
When, however, the good incur no danger, but rather are protected and saved by the slaying of the
wicked, then the latter may be lawfully put to death.
Reply to Objection 2; According to the order of His wisdom, God sometimes slays sinners forthwith in
order to deliver the good, whereas sometimes He allows them time to repent, according as He knows
what is expedient for His elect. This also does human justice imitate according to its powers; for it puts
http ://www.ccel. org/aJaguinas/summa/SS/SS064. html 3/13/2008
Summa Theologica
Page 4 of 11
to death those who are dangerous to others, while it allows time for repentance to those who sin without
grievously harming others.
Reply to Objection 3: By sinning man departs from the order of reason, and consequently falls away
from the digni ty of his manhood, in so far as he is naturally free, and exists for himsel f, and he falls into
the slavish state of the beasts, by being disposed of aceording as he is useful to others. This is expressed
in Ps. 48:21: "Man, when he was in honor, did not understand; he hath been compared to senseless
beasts, and made like to them," and Provo II :29: "The fool shall serve the wise." Hence, although it be
evil in itself to kill a man so long as he preserve his dignity, yet it may be good to kill a man who has
sinned, even as it is to kill a beast. For a bad man is worse than a beast, and is more harmful, as the
Philosopher states (Polit . i, 1 and Ethic. Vii, 6) .
Index [ )
Second Pan of the Second Pan [ I )
Question: 64 [ I ]
M iele: J [ ~ I ~ ]
Whether it is lawful for a private individual to kill a man who has sinned?
Objection J: It would seem lawful for a private individual to kill a man who has sinned. For nothing
unlawful is commanded in the Divine law. Yet, on account of the sin of the molten calf, Moses
commanded (Ex . 32:)7): "Let every man kill his brother, and friend, and neighbor." Therefore it is
lawful for private individuals to kill a sinner.
Objection 2: Further, as stated above (Article (2], ad 3), man, on account of sin, is compared to the
beasts. Now it is lawful for any pri vate indi vidual to kill a wild beast, especially if it be harmful.
Therefore for the same reason, it is lawful for any private individual to kill a man who has sinned.
Objection 3: Further, a man, though a private individual, deserves praise for doing what is useful for
the common good. Now the slaying of evildoers is useful for the common good, as stated above (Article
UJ). Therefore it is deserving of praise if even private individuals kill evil-doers.
011 the contrary, Augustine says (De Civ. Dei i) [*Can. Quicurnque percutit, caus. xxi ii, qu. 8]: 1PA
man who, without exercising public authority, kills an evil-doer, shall be judged guilty of murder, and
all the more, since he has dared to usurp a power which God has not given him."
f answer that, As stated above (Article [1]), it is lawful to kill an evildoer in so far as it is directed to
the welfare of the whole conununity, so that it belongs to him alone who has charge of the community's
wel fare. Thus it belongs to a physician to cut off a decayed limb, when he has been entrusted with the
care of the health of the whole body. Now the care of the common good is entrusted to persons of rank
having public authority; wherefore they alone, and not private individuals, can lawfully put evildoers to
death.
Reply to Objection 1: The person by whose authority a thing is done really does the thing as Dionysius
declares (Coet. Hier. iii). Hence according to Augustine (De Civ. Dei i, 21), "He slays not who owes his
service to one who commands him, even as a sword is merely the instrument to him that wields it."
Wherefore those who, at the Lord's command, slew their neighbors and friends, would seem not to have
http://ww\v.ccel.orgiaiaquinas/summa/SS/SS064.html 3/1312008
Summa Theologica
Page 5 of 11
done this themselves, but rather He by whose authority they acted thus: just as a soldier slays the foe by
the authority of his sovereign, and the executioner slays the robber by the authori ty of the judge.
Reply to Objection 2: A beast is by nature distinct from man, wherefore in the case of a wild beast
there is no need for an authority to kill it; whereas, in the case of domestic animals, such authority is
required, not for their sake, but on account of the owner's loss. On the other hand a man who has sinned
is not by nature distinct from good men; hence a public authority is requisite in order to condemn him to
death for the common good.
Reply to Objection 3: It is lawful for any private individual to do anything for the common good,
provided it harm nobody: but if it be harmful to some other, it cannot be done, except by virtue of the
judgment of the person to whom it pertains to decide what is to be taken from the parts for the welfare of
the whole.
Index [ J
Second Pan of Second Pm [ I
Questi on: 64 [ I ]
Article: 4 I ]
Whether it is lawful for clerics to kill evil-doers?
Objection 1: ft would seem lawful for clerics to kill evil-doers. For clerics especially should fulfil the
precept of the Apostle (li.Qr. 4:16): "Be ye followers of me as I also am of Christ ," whereby we are
called upon to imitate God and His saints. Now the very God whom we worship puts evildoers to death,
according to Ps. 135:10, "Who smote Egypt with their firstborn." Again Moses made the Levites slay
twenty-three thousand men on account of the worship of the calf (Ex. 32), the priest Phinees slew the
Israelite who went in to the woman of Madian ilium. 25), Samuel killed Agag king of Amalec (I
12), Elias slew the priests of Baal (3 Kgs. 18), Mathathias killed the man who went up to the altar to
sacrifice (l Mach. 2); and, in the New Testament, Peter killed Ananias and Saphira (Acts Therefore it
seems that even clerics may kill evil-doers.
Objection 2: Further, spiritual power is greater than the secular and is more united to God. Now the
secular power as "God's minister" lawfully puts evil-doers to death, according to Rm. 13:4. Much more
therefore may clerics, who are God's ministers and have spiritual power, put evil-doers to death.
Objection 3: Further, whosoever lawfully accepts an office, may lawfully exercise the functions of that
office. Now it belongs to the princely office to slay evildoers, as stated above (Article [3]). Therefore
those clerics who are earthly princes may lawfully slay malefactors.
0" the contrary, It is written (I Tim. 3:'J.3): "It behooveth ... a bishop to be without crime [*Vulg.:
'blameless.' 'Without crime' is the reading in Tit. 1:7] . . . not given to wine, no striker."
I answer that, It is unlawful for clerics to kill, for two reasons. First, because they are chosen for the
ministry of the altar, whereon is represented the Passion of Christ slain "Who, when He was struck did
not strike [Vulg.: 'When He suffered, He threatened not']" (I Pc ? :23). Therefore it becomes not clerics
to strike or kill: for ministers should imitate their master, according to Ecclus. 10:2, "As the judge of the
people is himself, so also are his ministers." The other reason is because clerics are entrusted with the
http://www. ccel.org/a/aquinas/suroma/SS/SS064.html 3/1312008
Summa Thcologica Page ti of l l
ministry of the New Law, wherein no punishment of death or of bodily maiming is appointed: wherefore
they should abstain from such things in order that they may be fitting ministers of the New Testament.
Reply (0 Objection 1: God works in all things without exception whatever is right, yet in each one
according to its mode. Wherefore everyone should imitate God in that which is specially becoming to
him . Hence, though God slays evildoers even corporally, it does not follow that all should imitate Him
in this. As regards Peter, he did not put Ananias and Saphira to death by his own authority or with his
own hand , but published their death sentence pronounced by God. The Priests or Levites of the Old
Testament were the ministers of the Old Law, which appointed corporal penalties, so that it was fitting
for them to slay with their own hands.
Reply to Objection 2: The ministry of clerics is concerned with better things than corporal slayings,
namely with things pertaining to spiritual welfare, and so it is not fitting for them to meddle with minor
marters.
Reply to Objection 3: Ecclesiastical prelates accept the office of earthly princes, not that they may
infli CI capital punishment themselves, bUI that this may be carried into effect by others in virtue of their
authority.
Index < ;]
Second Par t ofJ he Second Pan Is I ]
Question: 64 [ I ]
Article: 5 [ ~ I ~ ]
Whether it is lawful to kill oneself?
Objection 1: It would seem lawful for a man to kill himsel f. For murder is a sin in so far as it is
contrary to justice. But no man can do an injustice to himself, as is proved in Ethic. v, It. Therefore no
man sins by killing himself.
Objection 2: Further, it is lawful, for one who exercises public authority, to kill evil-doers. Now he
who exercises public authority is sometimes an evil-doer. Therefore he may lawfully kill himself.
Objection 3: Further, it is lawful for a man to suffer spontaneously a lesser danger that he may avoid a
greater: thus it is lawful for a man to cut off a decayed limb even from himself, that he may save his
whole body. Now sometimes a man, by killing himself, avoids a greater evil, for example an unhappy
life , or the shame of sin. Therefore a man may kill himself.
Objection 4: Further, Samson killed himself, as related in Judges 16, and yet he is numbered among
the saints (H eb. I 1). Therefore it is lawful for a man to ki II himsel f.
Objection 5: Further, it is related (2 Mach. 14:42) that a certain Razias killed himself, "choosing to die
nobly rather than to fall into the hands of the wicked, and to suffer abuses unbecoming his noble birth."
Now nothing that is done nobly and bravely is unlawful. Therefore suicide is not unlawful.
0" the contrary, Augustine says (De Civ. Dei i, 20): "Hence it follows that the words 'Thou shalt not
kill' refer to the killing of a man-s-not another man; therefore, not even thyself. For he who kills himself,
http://www.ccel.orgia/aquinas/swnma/SS/SS064.htmI 3/13/2008
Summa Theologica
Page 7 of 11
kills nothing else than a man."
I answer that, It is altogether unlawful to kill oneself, for three reasons. First} because everything
naturally loves itself, the result being that everything naturally keeps itsel f in being, and resists
corruptions so far as it can. Wherefore suicide is contrary to the inclination of nature, and to charity
whereby every man should love himself. Hence suicide is always a mortal sin, as being contrary to the
natural law and to charity. Secondly, because every part, as such, belongs to the whole. Now every man
is part of the community, and so, as such, he belongs to the community. Hence by killing himself he
injures the community, as the Philosopher declares (Ethic. v, II). Thirdly, because life is God's gift to
man, and is subject to His power, Who kills and makes to live. Hence whoever takes his own life, sins
against God, even as he who kills another's slave, sins against that slave's master, and as he who usurps
to hirnsel f judgment of a matter not entrusted to him. For it belongs to God alone to pronounce sentence
of death and life, according to Dt. 32:39, "1 will kill and 1 will make to live."
Reply to Objection 1: Murder is a sin, not only because it is contrary to justice, but also because it is
opposed to charity which a man should have towards himself: in this respect suicide is a sin in relation
to oneself. In relation to the community and to God, it is sinful, by reason also of its opposition to
justice.
Reply to Objection 2: One who exercises public authority may lawfully put to death an evil-doer, since
he can pass judgment on him. But no man is judge of himself. Wherefore it is not lawful for one who
exercises public authority to put himself to death for any sin whatever: although he may lawfully
commit himself to the judgment of others.
Reply to Objection 3: Man is made master ofhimself through his free-will: wherefore he can lawfully
dispose of himself as to those matters which pertain to this life which is ruled by man's free-will. But the
passage from this life to another and happier one is subject not to man's free-will but to the power of
God. Hence it is not lawful for man to take his own life that he may pass to a happier life, nor that he
may escape any unhappiness whatsoever of the present life, because the ultimate and most fearsome evil
of this life is death, as the Philosopher states (Ethic. iii, 6). Therefore to bring death upon oneself in
order to escape the other afflictions of this life, is to adopt a greater evil in order to avoid a lesser. In like
manner it is unlawful to take one's own life on account of one's having committed a sin, both because by
so doing one does oneself a very great injury, by depriving oneself of the time needful for repentance,
and because it is not 13w ful to slay an evildoer except by the sentence of the public authori ty , Again it is
unlawful for a woman to kill hcrsel f lest she be violated, because she ought not to commit on herself the
very great sin of suicide, to avoid the lesser sir; of another . For she commits no sin in being violated by
force, provided she does not consent, since "without consent of the mind there is no stain on the body,"
as the Blessed Lucy declared. Now it is evident that fornication and adultery are less grievous sins than
taking a man's, especially one's own, life: since the latter is most grievous, because one injures oneself,
to whom one owes the greatest love. Moreover it is most dangerous since no time is left wherein to
expiate it by repentance. Again it is not lawful for anyone to take his own life for fear he should consent
to sin, because "evil must not be done that good may come" CRm. 3:8) or that evil may be avoided
especially if the evil be of small account and an uncertain event, for it is uncertain whether one will at
some future time consent to a sin, since God is able to deliver man from sin under any temptation
whatever.
Reply to Objection 4: As Augustine says (De Civ. Dei i , 21), "not even Samson is to be excused that he
crushed himself together with his enemies under the ruins of the house, except the Holy Ghost, Who had
wrought many wonders through him, had secretly commanded him to do this." He assigns the same
reason in the case of certain holy women, who at the time of persecution took their own lives, and who
are commemorated by the Church .
httpz /www.ccel.orgia/aquinas/summaiSS/SS064.html 3!l3/2008
Summa Theologica Page 8 of 1I
Reply to Objection 5: It belongs to fortitude that a man does not shrink from being slain by another, for
the sake of the good of virtue, and that he may avoid sin . But that a man take his own life in order to
avoid penal evils has indeed an appearance of fortitude (for which reason some, among whom was
Razias, have killed themselves thinking to act from fortitude), yet it is not true fortitude, but rather a
weakness of soul unable to bear penal evils, as the Philosopher (Ethic. iii, 7) and Augustine (De Civ. Dei
22,23) declare.
Jod_cx l'< J
[ I 1
64 [ I ]
Article: 6 [ I 1
Whether it is lawful to kill the innocent?
Objection 1: It would seem that in some cases it is lawful to kill the innocent. The fear of God is never
manifested by sin, since on the contrary "the fear of the Lord driveth out sin" (Ecclus, I :27). Now
Abraham was commended in that he feared the Lord, since he was willing to slay his innocent son.
Therefore one may, without sin, kill an innocent person.
Objection 2: Further , among those sins that are committed against one's neighbor, the more grievous
seem to be those whereby a more grievous injury is inflicted on the person sinned against. Now to be
killed is a greater injury to a sinful than to an innocent person, because the latter, by death, passes
forthwith from the unhappi ness of this Iife to the glory of heaven. Since then it is lawful in certain cases
to kill a sinful man, much more is it lawful to slay an innocent or a righteous person.
Objection 3: Further, what is done in keeping with the order of justice is not a sin. But sometimes a
man is forced, according to the order ofjustice, to slay an innocent person: for instance, when a judge,
who is bound to judge according to the evidence, condemns to death a man whom he knows to be
innocent but who is convicted by false witnesses; and again the executioner, who in obedience to the
judge puts to death the man who has been unjustly sentenced.
On the contrary, It is written (Ex. 23:7): "The innocent and just person thou shalt not put to death."
I answer that, An individual man may be considered in two ways: first, in himself; secondly, in
relation to something else. If we consider a man in himself, it is unlawful to kill any man, since in every
man though he be sinful, we ought to love the nature which God has made, and which is destroyed by
slaying him. Nevertheless, as stated above the slaying of a sinner becomes lawful in relation
to the common good, which is corrupted by sin. On the other hand the life of righteous men preserves
and forwards the common good, since they are the chief part of the community. Therefore it is in no way
lawful to slay the innocent.
Reply to Objection 1.. God is Lord of death and life, for by His decree both the sinful and the righteous
die. Hence he who at God's command kills an innocent man does not sin, as neither does God Whose
behest he executes: indeed his obedience to God's commands is a proof thai he fears Him.
Reply to Objection 2: In weighing the gravity of a sin we must consider the essential rather than the
accidental. Wherefore he who kills a just man, sins more grievously than he who slays a sinful man:
http ://www.ceel .orglaJaquinas/summaiSS/SS064.htm} 311312008
Summa Theologica Page 9 of 11
first , because he injures one whom he should love more, and so acts more in opposition to charity:
secondly, because he inflicts an injury on a man who is less deserving of one, and so acts more in
opposition to justice: thirdly, because he deprives the community of a greater good: fourthly, because he
despises God more, according to Lk. 10: 16, "He that despiseth you despiseth Me ." On the other hand it
is accidental to the slaying that the just man whose life is taken be received by God into glory.
Reply to Objection 3: If the judge knows that man who has been convicted by false witnesses, is
innocent he must, like Daniel, examine the witnesses with great care, so as to find a motive for
acqui tting the innocent: but if he cannot do this he should remit him for judgment by a higher tribunal. If
even this is impossible, he does not sin if he pronounce sentence in accordance with the evidence, for it
is not he that puts the innocent man to death, but they who stated him to be guilty. He that carries out the
sentence of the judge who has condemned an innocent man, if the sentence contains an inexcusable
error, he should not obey, else there would be an excuse for the executions of the martyrs: ifhowever it
contain no mani fest injustice, he does not has no right to discuss the judgment of his superior; nor is it
he who slays the innocent man, but the judge whose minister he is.

l J
Second Part of the Second Pan [ I ]
Question: 64 I ]
Article: 7 [ I
Whether it is lawful to kill a man in self-defense?
Objection 1: It would seem that nobody may lawfully kill a man in self-defense. For Augustine says to
Publicola (Ep . xlvii): "I do not agree with the opinion that one may kill a man lest one be killed by him;
unless one be a soldier, exercise a public office, so that one does it not for oneselfbut for others, having
the power to do so, provided it be in keeping with one's person." Now he who kills a man in self
defense, kills him lest he be killed by him. Therefore this would seem to be unlawful.
Objection 2: Further, he says (De Lib. Arb . i, 5) : "How are they free from sin in sight of Divine
providence, who are gui lry 0 f taking a man's Iife for the sake of these contemptible things?" Now among
contemptible things he reckons "those which men may forfeit unwillingly," as appears from the context
(De Lib. Arb . i, 5): and the chief of these is the life of the body. Therefore it is unlawful for any man to
take another's life for the sake of the life of his own body.
Objection 3: Further, Pope Nicolas ["'Nicolas I, Dist. I, can. De his clericis] says in the Decretals:
"Concerning the clerics about whom you have consulted Us, those, namely, who have killed a pagan in
self-defense, as to whether, after making amends by repent ing, they may return to their fanner state, or
rise to a higher degree; know that in no case is it lawful for them to kill any man under any
circumstances whatever." Now clerics and laymen are alike bound to observe the moral precepts.
Therefore neither is it lawful for laymen \0 kill anyone in self-defense.
Objection 4.. Further, murder is a more grievous sin than fornication or adultery. Now nobody may
lawfully commit simple fornication or adultery or any other mortal sin in order to save his own life;
since the spiritual life is to be preferred to the life of the body. Therefore no man may lawfully take
another's life in self-defense in order to save his own life.
http://www.ccel .org/a/aquinas/summaiSS/SS064.html 3/13/2008
Summa Theologica Page lOaf 11
Objection 5: Further, if the tree be evil, so is the fruit, according to Mt. 7: 17. Now self-defense itself
seems to be unlawful, according to Rm. 12: 19: "Not defending [Douay: 'revenging'] yoursel ves, my
dearly beloved." Therefore its result, which is the slaying of a man, is also unlawful.
0" the contrary, It is written (Ex . 22:2): "If a thief be found breaking into a house or undermining it,
and be wounded so as to die; he that slew him shall not be guilty of blood. " Now it is much more law ful
to defend one's Iife than one's house. Therefore neither is a man gui lty of murder if he kill another in
defense of his own life.
J answer that, Nothing hinders one act from having two effects, only one of which is intended, while
the other is beside the intention. Now moral acts take their species according to what is intended, and
not according to what is beside the intention, since this is accidental as explained above (QuesJion (43],
Article DJ; ES, Question rt2l, Article W) Accordingly the act of self-defense may have two effects,
one is the saving of one's Iife, the other is the slaying of the aggressor. Therefore this act, since one's
intention is to save one's own life, is not unlawful , seeing that it is natural to everything to keep itself in
"being," as far as possible. And yet, though proceeding from a good intention, an act may be rendered
unlawful, if it be out of proportion to the end. Wherefore if a man, in self-defense, uses more than
necessary vi0 lcnce, it wiII be unlawful : whereas if he repel force with moderation his defense will be
lawful, because according to the jurists [*Cap. Significasti, De Homicid. volunt, vel casual .], "it is
lawful to repel force by force, provided one does not exceed the limits of a blameless defense." Nor is it
necessary for salvation that a man omi 1 the act of moderate sel f-defense in order to avoid killing the
other man, since one is bound to take more care of one's own life than of another's. But as it is unlawful
to take a man's life, except for the public authority acting for the common good, as stated above (Article
W ), it is not lawful for a man to intend killing a man in self-defense, except for such as have public
authority. who while intending to kill a man in self-defense, refer this to the public good, as in the case
of a soldier fighting against the foe, and in the minister of the judge struggling with robbers, although
even these sin if they be moved by private animosity.
Reply to Objection 1: The words quoted from Augustine refer to the case when one man intends to kill
another to save himself from death. The passage quoted in the Second Objection is to be understood in
the same sense. Hence he says pointedly, "for the sake of these things," whereby he indicates the
intention. This suffices for the Reply to the Second Objection.
Reply to Objection 3: Irregularity results from the act though sinless of taking a man's life, as appears
in the case of a judge who justly condemns a man to death. For this reason a cleric, though he kill a man
in self-defense, is irregular, albeit he intends not to kill him, but to defend himself.
Reply to Objection 4: The act of fornication or adultery is not necessarily directed to the preservation
of one's own life, as is the act whence sometimes results the taking of a man's life.
Reply to Objection 5: The defense forbidden in this passage is that which comes from revengeful spite.
Hence a gloss says: "Not defending yourselves---that is, not striking your enemy back."
. - -
Index 1 )
the Seco_n.Q..e.m I ?.?]
[ I
Art icle: 8 I ??:l
http://www.ccel.orglaJaquinasisummafSS/SS064.html 3/13/2008
Summa Theologica
Page II of l l
Whether ODe is guilty of murder through killing someone by chance?
Objection 1: It would seem that one is guilty of murder through killing someone by chance. For we
read (Gn. 4:13,24) that Larnech slew a man in mistake for a wild beast [*The text of the Bible does not
say so, but this was the Jewish traditional commentary on Gn. 4:23], and that he was accounted guilty of
murder. Therefore one incurs the guilt of murder through killing a man by chance.
Objection 2: Further, it is written (Ex. 21 :22): "If ... one strike a woman with child, and she miscarry
indeed ... ifher death ensue thereupon, he shall render life for life." Yet this may happen without any
intention of causing her death. Therefore one is guilty of murder through killing someone by chance.
Objection 3: Further, the Decretals [*Dist. 1] contain several canons prescribing penalties for
unintentional homicide. Now penalty is not due save for guilt. Therefore he who kills a man by chance,
incurs the guiIt of murder.
On the contrary, Augustine says to Publicola (Ep, xlvii): "When we do a thing for a good and lawful
purpose, if thereby we unintentionally cause harm to anyone, it should by no means be imputed to us."
Now it sometimes happens by chance that a person is killed as a result of something done for a good
purpose. Therefore the person who did it is not accounted guilty.
I answer that, According to the Philosopher (Phys. ii, 6) "chance is a cause that acts beside one's
intention." Hence chance happenings, strictly speaking, are neither intended nor voluntary. And since
every sin is voluntary, according to Augustine (De Vera Re1ig. xiv) it follows that chance happenings, as
such, are not sins.
Nevertheless it happens that what is not actually and directly voluntary and intended, is voluntary and
intended accidentally, according as thai which removes an obstacle is called an accidental cause.
Wherefore he who does not remove something whence homicide results whereas he ought to remove it,
is in a sense guilty of voluntary homicide. This happens in two ways: first when a man causes another's
death through occupying himself with unlawful things which he ought to avoid: secondly, when he does
not lake sufficient care. Hence, according to jurists, if a man pursue a lawful occupation and take due
care, the result being that a person loses his life, he is not guilty of that person's death: whereas ifhe be
occupied with something unlawful, or even with something lawful, but without due care, he does not
escape being guilty 0 f murder, if his action results in someone's death.
Reply to Objection 1: Lamech did not take sufficient care to avoid taking a man's life: and so he was
not excused from being guilty of homicide.
Reply to Objection 2: He that strikes a woman with child does something unlawful: wherefore if there
results the death either of the woman or of the animated fetus, he will not be excused from homicide,
especially seeing that death is the natural result of such a blow.
Reply to Objection 3: According to the canons a penalty, is inflicted on those who cause death
unintentionally, through doing something unlawful, or failing to take sufficient care.
This document co nvened to HTML 0 0 Sun Jan 11 07:47: 10 1998.
http://www.ccel.org/a/aq uinas/surnma/SS/S S064.htrn1 3/13/2008

You might also like