Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

Elements of Law

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 456
At a glance
Powered by AI
The document appears to be about elements of law and jurisprudence. It discusses concepts like sovereignty, torts, and succession.

In the preface to the first edition, the author acknowledges that the arrangement of the work is defective for a scientific study of law.

The document is about elements of law and discusses concepts related to general jurisprudence.

'.^U''-''^-.

'"f/"^

^fi^s^

^iAfy

J!

1905"

DATE DUE

PRINTED

IN U.SJt

S'

3 1924 018 028 567

OlorttfU

Ham

^rljioal SItbraty

Cornell University Library

The
tine

original of

tiiis

book

is in

Cornell University Library.

There are no known copyright

restrictions in
text.

the United States on the use of the

http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924018028567

ELEMENTS OF LAW
CONSIDERED WITH EEFEEENCE TO

PEINCIPLES OF GENERAL JURISPRUDENCE

SiE

WILLIAM MAEKBY,

K.C.LE., D.C.L.

FELLOW OF BALLIOL COLLEeE LATE A JUDGE OF THE HIGH CO0BT OF JUDIOATOKE AT CALCUTTA KEADEK IN INDIAN LAW IN THE UNIVEESITT OF OXFORD AND FELLOW OF ALL SOULS COLLEGE

SIXTH EDITION

OXFORD
AT THE CLAEENDON PRESS
LONDON,

NEW YOKK AND TORONTO HENRY FROWDE


:

ALSO SOLD BY

STEVENS & SONS, LIMITED,

119

&

izo

CHANCBEY LANE, LONDON

1905

B ^/isi
LONDON
HENEY PEOWDE,
M.A.
PUBLISHER TO THE UNIVEBSITY OF OXFORD

STEVENS AND SONS, LIMITED

PEEFACE TO THE FIEST EDITION


I

HAVE

explained, in a place where

it is

likely to

receive

of this of
its
it.

more attention than in a preface, the object book, and the use which I intend to be made I have now only to add a word or two as to
its

form and

arrangement.
:

Its

form

is

that of Lectures

and

in fact

a good

deal of

what the book

at present contains formed

part of a series of Lectures delivered to a small class

of Hindoo and

Mahommedan law
It

students in Calcost

cutta, in the year 1870.

would have

me no
enables

additional trouble to divest the book of that form,

but I have preserved

it,

for this reason

it

me

to speak in the

first

person,

and thus

to

show

more clearly than I could otherwise do, how far I have depended on the labours of others, and how far I must take the whole responsibility of what I have said upon myself The arrangement is obviously defective and this, in a work which professes to be a contribution
;

(however small) to the

scientific

study of law,
it

is

a serious admission.
this
defect.

But

do not think

possible

to enter hei'e into an explanation of the cause of


I

have indicated

it

very partially,
in the

in one particular, in

some observations made

IV

PREFACE.

course of the work.

What

I maintain

Is,

that

when

a work

is

written on

EngHsh Law, which


will

is

complete

in point of arrangement, the long series of labours

which are now just commencing

have been

brought very nearly to a conclusion.


London,
October, 1871.

PREFACE TO THE EOUETH EDITION


I

AM

encouraged to hope that this book

may

still

be of some use to students.

It is true that there

has

been a slight tendency

of late to underrate the im-

portance of a close inquiry into the meaning of legal

words and phrases.

But

this

tendency will pass

away

and the

historical research

which at present

engages most attention wUl in the meantime have

The recently published treatise of PoUock and Wright on Possession is a most valuable contribution to an investigation which I hope to see carried further, and it has, I feel sure, greatly gained by the historical inquiries which
done good
service.

preceded
I

it.

am much

indebted to Mr. Montague, of Oriel

College, Oxford,

and to Mr. Sheppard, of Trinity


the suggestions and cor-

College, Cambridge, for


I'ections

which they have sent to me.

OxFOED, August, 1889.

PREFACE TO THE SIXTH EDITION


This edition
I have
is

largely identical with the last.


to the

somewhat expanded the discussion as


'

meaning of the term


the subject of so

sovereignty,'

which has been

much

contention.

OxFOBD, August, 1905.

CONTENTS
Inteoduction

....
CHAPTER
I.

...
II.

PAGE
ix

General Conception of Law

CHAPTER
SoiTBCEs OE

Law

38

CHAPTER
Persons and Things

III.

79

CHAPTER
Duties and Rights

IV.

92

CHAPTER
On the
Expression oe the

V.
.

Law

107

CHAPTER
The
Relations

VI.

Creation, Extinction, and Transeeb oe Legal


114

CHAPTER
The Arrangement of the Law

VII.
. .
. .

152

CHAPTER
Ownership

VIII.

157

CHAPTER IX
Possession
180

CHAPTER
Easements and Proeits-a-prendre

X.

....

205

VIU

CONTENTS.
PAGE

CHAPTEE XL
Secueity
214

CHAPTEE
Acquisition op Ownership

Xir.

235
XIII.

CHAPTEE
On
Pbesceiption

264

Liability

.........
XIV.

CHAPTER

292

CHAPTEE XV.
Liability upon Conteact
. .

298

CHAPTEE XVL
Liability foe Toet

322

CHAPTEE
Geounds oe Non-Liability
. .

XVII.
.
. .

346

CHAPTEE
Succession

XVIII.
371

CHAPTEE
Sanctions and Eemedies

XIX.
403

CHAPTEE XX.
Peoceduee
416

Index

.27

INTEODUCTION
In order that
very limited
this

work may

accomplish, to

any

extent, its

object, it is absolutely necessary that it should be


it is

understood from what point of view of the study of law


written,

and what

is

the particular use which

it is

intended

to serve.

For
very

this purpose it is necessary to bear in

mind

that, until

lately, the

only study of law

preparation for

in England was that the actual practice of the profession which

known

was procured by attendance in the chambers of a barrister or pleader. The Universities had almost entirely ceased to teach law and there was nowhere in England any faculty, or body of learned persons, who made it their business to give Nor were instruction in law after a systematic method. there any persons desirous of learning law after that fashion.
;

Forensic

skill, skill

in the art of drawing

up

legal documents,

and

skilfulness in the advice given to clients,

were

all

that

was taught, or learnt, by a process of imitation very similar to that by which an apprentice learns a handicraft, or a
schoolboy learns a game.
This method of training produced
last
its

natural results.

rays of learning seemed to be dying

The away from English


;

Law with

the old race of conveyancers and pleaders

the only

lawyers of eminence
activity of the courts.

who were

undisturbed by The Chancery lawyers as a

the bustling
rule have

retained a higher standard of culture than those of the


;

Com-

mon Law Bar and at both Bars there always were, and still are, to be found many men of eminent attainments in all
departments of knowledge.
little

But the law

itself is, at present,

influenced

by these attainments, and no one would


lie

venture to assert that they


ful professional career.

in the direct path of a success-

X
This
is

INTRODUCTION".
not the place to consider the effect of this decay of
'
'

and exclusively professional training, either upon the profession itself, or upon the law, or upon the judges
legal learning,

who

administer the law.

causes which have led


legal knowledge,

Nor is it men to seek

the place to consider the


for

a higher standard of

and thus
to

to a revival of the

demand

for

systematic education in law, apart from professional training. All I have

now

take notice of

is

that, as a natural

consequence of this demand, the Universities of Oxford, of

Cambridge, and of London, are taking active steps to re-constitute the study of

law

as part of their course.


earliest,

But

it is

only with the

and what
directly

may

call

the

preliminary portion of a lawyer's education that a University

has to deal.
skill

Towards imparting

that professional

of which I have spoken above, no University or Faculty

of

Law

can do anything whatever.


I

That must be done


indeed one of those

else-

where, and at a later stage.


are persuaded that the

am

who

skill in

question will be at least more

easily acquired, if not carried even to a higher point than it

has at present reached, after such a preparation and grounding as a University


is

able to give.

But the only preparation

and grounding which a University is either able, or, I suppose, would be desirous to give, is in law considered as a science or at least, if that is not yet possible, in law considered as
a collection of principles capable of being systematically
arranged, and resting, not on bare authority, but on sound
logical deduction
;

all

departures from which, in the existing

system,

must be marked and explained.


society,

In other words, law


general relations to

must be studied

in a University, not merely as it has resulted

from the exigencies of

but in

its

the several parts of the same system, and to other systems.

But
law in

it is

this

not sufBcient simply to take a resolution to teach way. Experience shows that to establish a study

on

this footing

we must have books and


At

teachers specially

suited for the purpose.


scarcely any.
I do not

we have wish to say a word in disparagement


present, of the first


INTEODUCTION.
of the books XI I only

which are now usually read by students

wish to observe, that with two or three notable exceptions,

which

cover, however, but little ground, they belong to that

period of the study of English

Law which

is

now

passing

away, and that they are only suited to


of professional skill
;

assist in the acquisition

this

being the object which master and

student have hitherto kept steadily and exclusively in view.

two or three generations of those who take to the study of law after the new fashion will undoubtedly find this a considerable difiiculty in their way. It must be many years before the scattered rules of English Law are gathered up and and for some discussed in a systematic and orderly treatise

The

first

time to come students of law will find themselves obliged to

work a good

deal with the old tools.

Nor

does

it

follow,

because these tools are not quite perfect, that they are to be
discarded as useless.

The actual
is laid

state of the English

Law on
and
very

a variety of subjects

down with
works
;

clearness, brevity,

precision in several elementary

and though

it is

easy to exaggerate the use of acquiring a knowledge of the


existing rules of law
is
;

though

this

knowledge, standing alone,

only part of the skill of which I have spoken above, and

will always be far better acquired in a barrister's chambers

than in the lecture room of a professor


ledge
is

though

this

know-

emphatically not that which

is

the chief object of the


consideration,

preliminary training which I have


yet the existing law
is (if

now under

may

use the expression) the

raw

material upon which the student has to begin to work. Being


told that the law contains such and such a rule,
it

will be his
its

business to examine

it,

to ascertain

whence

it

sprang,

exact

import, and the measure of

its application.

he must assign to

it its

proper place in

Having done so, the system and must


;

mark out
which
far it
it

its relations

with the other parts of the system to


will

belongs.

This

require

a comparison with

analogous institutions in other countries, in order to see


is

how

a deduction from

those principles

of law which

are generally deemed universal, and

how

far it is peculiar to

xu
ourselves.

INTRODUCTION.
For this purpose some acquaintance with the
its

Roman

Law
sions,

will be at least desirable, if not absolutely necessary

because the principles of that law, and

technical expres-

have largely influenced our own law, as well as that of every other country in Europe ^. It is for students of law who occupy the position indicated
in the above observations that this

book

is

intended, and I

repeat that

it is

absolutely necessary that those


I

who

use

it

should bear this in mind.


the course of

have presumed that they are in

making acquaintance with the more elementary

rules of English

Law

that they are desirous to understand


of their

those rules, and to


relation
defence.
;

know something

origin

and

not merely to use them as weapons of attack or


This
difficult,

but by no means uninviting, inquiry is

the one in which I have


1

made some attempt

to assist them.

This

is

expected to

the great difBoulty of Indian law students. They can hardly be make themselves generally acquainted with the Roman Law.

But I do not think that it is at all impossible for them, even with a very slight knowledge of Latin, to obtain a useful insight into some of its leading principles. Being most desirous to render some assistance to this class of
students, I have simplified, as

much

as

possible,

the

references to the

Eoman Law.

ELEMENTS OF LAW
CHAPTER
I.

GENERAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.


1.

Law
;

is

a term which

is

used in a variety of different General


'

conception
of law.

meanings

but widely as these

differ^ there

runs throughout

them

all

the

common
rule,

idea of a regular succession of events,

governed by a
or agency,
2.

which originates in some power, condition,


are about to Part of the
of a politl"^^ society.

upon which the succession depends. The conception of that law which we
law of the lawyer

consider the

is

contained within and


society.

forms part of the conception of a

political

Fully

to develop the ideas comprehended under the term political

society
full
3.

would require a very long

discussion.

Nor

is

this

development necessary for our present purpose^

For

this purpose it is sufficient to observe

some of

its Characterpolitical
^"'^^^ ^'

most striking features ; and one that mainly distinguishes


a political society from other associations of

men

is,

that

in a politieal society one member, or a certain definite body of members, possesses the absolute power of issuing com-

mands
4.

to the rest, to

which commands the

rest are generally

obedient.
It
is

desirable to observe that this,

though a characit

teristic of a political society, does

not belong to
it.

exclusively,

so as to serve as a definition of

Though

not, however,

GENEEAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.

[Chap.
it is

I.

a distinguishing characteristic of a political society^

marked and conspicuous one; just


erect is a
race.

as the habit of

walking

marked and conspicuous

characteristic of the

Butj in the same

way

as animals other than


societies other

human man have


political

been known to walk

erect, so

than

ones are known, of which the members are in the habit of


obedience to a ruler,
to issue

who

is

acknowledged to have the right

and

to enforce his

commands.

The

association called

a 'family* has existed in

many
it

countries,

and possibly

stiU

does exist in some, in such a form that, just as in a political


society, the

members of
its

are

in

the habit

of

complete

obedience to

head,

who has the

absolute right to enforce,

and actually does


What
issued in a
"''wjiet*'

enforce, that obedience.

5.

It

is

the body of
its

commands

issued

by the

rulers of

a political society to

members which lawyers


so issued

call

by the

name
Very

'law.^

There are only two small and very

insignifi-

la-ws properly so called.

cant classes of the


,
.

commands
. .

which are not laws.

rarely notifications in the


rulers of
:

form of commands are issued


rank and precedence
dies,

by the

a political society, which are nevertheless

not enforced

as, for instance, rules of

in society, orders to wear

mourning when a great person

and

so forth.

These are no part of law in our sense of the


rulers of a political society sometimes,

term.

So also the

but

very rarely, address a


or individuals

command

to

a particular individual
specifi.c

by

narae.

Such occasional and


a general
class.

com-

mands
as

are not properly comprised under the


said, involves the idea of

term law, which,


rule, applicable

we have
6.

to all cases

which come under a common

Laws

declaratory

Austin considers that there are two other objects ini

and laws
'^^

cluded Within the p-ovmce ot jurisprudence and called laws,

..i

.i

[aws^

which
laws,

are, nevertheless,

not commands ; namely,, declaratory


Bu,t, as it

and laws which repeal laws.


if
it

seems to me,
or

every such law,

is

addressed

by the sovereign one


Austin-'s

number
desire

to its subjects generally, if it is a signification of


is

and

imperative, falls
it

under

conception
is,

of law:

though

may

only be a complete

law, that

Sec. 5-10.]

GENERAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.


in-

a complete command, when taken


other signification of desire.

connexion with some

There
to

are^

no doubtj eases in

which

it is

somewhat tedious

work out the ways by which

a particular- form of expression


conception, but I
difiiculty
7.
is.

may be brought under

this

am

not aware of any cases in which the


^.

insurmountable
.

special order of forfeiture of property


,

made against
IT

Orders of
forfeiture.

a particular person as a punishment for open rebellion^ though


it

may

be in form an act of parliament,

is

not a law.

Nor

are the acts annually passed

by parliament

for appropriation

of the revenue laws properly so called.


8:

We
be

thus arrive at a conception of the term law which Summary ^


as follows.

may
of

summed up
to

That

it is

the general body tion


of

01 concepof

rules

which are addressed by the


the

rulers

a political

society

members

of

that

society,

and which are

generally obeyed.
9.

The aggregate of powers which


. .

is
.

possessed

by the
.

Sovereignty.

rulers of a political society is called sovereignty.


ruler,

The

single

where there

is

one, is called the sovereign; the


several, is

body

of rulers,

where there are

called

the sovereign

body, or the government, or the supreme government.


rest of the

The

members
it,

of a political society, in contradistinction


^.

to the rulers of

are called subjects

10. It is implied in

what I have

said above that there are Laws set

other rules than those set by sovereign authority which are than properly called laws

example, the rules which the head authorUy. of a household imposes upon the members of his household':
:

as, for

and when we

desire to distinguish

between these laws and


authority, are the

those laws which, being set

by a sovereign

' Mr. Prederic Harrison gives a, number of such c^sqs in an article ip the Fortnightly Review, No. 143, N. S., p. 684. But he adds (p. 687), I am far from saying that Austin's analysis of law cannot he applied to
'

all
'

these cases.'

The King of England" is sometimes called the sovereign, but this is only out of courtesy. The ruling power of Great Britain and her dependencies is the sovereign body, consisting of the King and the Houses of Parliament. The use of the word Sovereign ' as a title of honour, not expressing exactly any political condition, is now very common in Europe.
'

B a

' '

GENERAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.


appropriate

[Chap.

I.

matter of jurisprudence,

we

call

the latter by

the
This conception of

name
This

of positive laws'^.
is

11.

the conception of law as stated by Austin in

law estab- his lectures


lished byAustin.

on the 'Province of Jurisprudence'; and I have

only repeated his conclusions^.

Many

of

them

rest

upon

arguments
Austin
distin-

drawn

from

Austin's

celebrated

predecessors,

Hobbes and Jeremy Bentham.


12. "What, however, Austin's predecessors to

do not appear

guished law from


morality.

me

to

have fully apprehended, at least not with that sure


full conviction, is

and firm grasp which proceeds from a


distinction

the

between positive law and morals.

We
line

find, for

example,

that

Bentham, when drawing the

between

jurisprudence and ethics, classes legislation under jurispru-

dence

^,

whereas, as Austin has shown

*,

it

clearly belongs to

ethics.

Austin,

by

establishing

the

distinction

between

positive

law and morals, not only

laid the

foundation for

a science of law, but cleared the conception of law and of sovereignty of a

number

of pernicious consequences to
it

which
lead.

in the hands of his predecessors

had been supposed to

Positive laws, as Austin has


ing,

shown ^, must be

legally bind-

and yet a law may be unjust.


it

Resistance to authority
a virtue.

cannot be a legal right, and yet


are only examples.

may be

But

these

Into whatever discussion the words 'right

and

'

justice

'

enter

we

are on the brink of a confusion

from

which a careful observance of the distinction between law


and morals can alone save
us.

Austin has _shown not only


it is

what

positive

law

is,

but what

not.

He

has determined

accurately the boundaries of


assigns to
it

its

province.
it is

The domain he

may

be small, but
itself

indisputable.

He

has
it

admitted that law

may

be immoral, in which case


it;

may
1

be our moral duty to disobey

but

it

is

neverthe'

when
'^

Following the example of other writers, I drop the epithat the context makes it clear what kind of law is meant.
See the
first, fifth,

positive

and sixth Lectures.


i.

'

Bowring's ed.
Lecture

vol.

p. 148.

*
'

v. p. 177.
vi. p. 275.

Lecture

Sec. 11-14.]
less

GENERAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.


it

laWj and this disobedience, virtuous though


less

may

be,

is

nothing

than

rebellion.

13. Austin^s conception of positive

law and o sovereignty

Austin's

does not depend upon the theory of utility discussed and ad- of law not

vocated by hun in his second, third, and fourth lectures

as

on^Xfit"*
oJ"

the interposition of that discussion into an inquiry to which,


strictly speaking, it does not belong, has led

^^^y

some persons

theory,

erroneously to suppose.

Austin was a
to

utilitarian,

and made
it

an attempt (which seems


not been treated with
is

me

to be creditable,

though

has

much

respect) to

show that

utilitarianism

consistent with the belief in a Divine providence.

But

in

truth Austin^s conception of law and sovereignty does not

depend upon any theory of


politics,

religion,

or

of

morals, or of

whatsoever.

It

might be accepted by a Hindoo, by


despotic

Mahommedan, or by a Christian; by the most of monarchs or by the staunchest of republicans,


a
14. Austin's conception of positive

law has of

late years Criticism

been subjected to a good deal of criticism, chiefly on account


of the conception of sovereignty which
it

involves
is

but

it is

not

always easy to understand exactly what view


authors of their criticisms.
reject Austin's conceptions,

taken by the
to

They do not seem altogether


still less
:

do they make any attempt

to substitute others in their place

and yet they seem anxious


would lead to
results

to prove that Austin's conceptions

which

are false, or which, at

any

rate,

the world would be unthat in what has been


real

willing to adopt.

It appears to

me

said there has been


position.

some misunderstanding of Austin's


thought to
result

It

has been

therefrom

that
;

sovereignty must be regarded as incapable of limitation


as one writer expresses
inclined
it,

or,

that Austin's military training has


It
is

him

to despotism.

also suggested that if Austin's

explanation of sovereignty be accepted the aggregate of powers

which go to make up sovereignty cannot be divided; and,


again,
it

has been supposed that he intended his conceptions


This
is

to be applied to all governments in all ages.


Burpi-ising, because, so

very

long ago as 1874, Sir Henry Maine,

6
in

GENERAL CONCEPTION OE LAW.


two

[Chap.

I.

lectures evidently intended for this purpose, carefully


;

pointed out the true object of Austin's analysis


scientific

that

it

was

and not

political

that
j

it is

based upon assumptions


it

and not upon

historical facts

and that
is

rests

not upon

authority but upon logic.

It

an

abstraction^ just as all

the statements of mathematics and

many

of 'the statements

of political economists are abstractions.

At

the same time

Maine was

careful to state that it is not


;

upon that account

to be laid aside as useless

on the contrary, that rightly

viewed Austin^s analysis


students of lawj

is

a precious inheritance to English


is

'that

it

the only existing attempt to

construct a system of jurisprudence


process,

by a

strictly scientific

and

to

found

it,

not on a priori assumption, but on

the observation, comparison, and analysis of the various legal


conceptions^.''
Maine's

15.

The passage I have

just quoted

ought to be sufE-

as regards cient to

make

it

quite clear It
is

what was Maine's own attitude


well

Austin.

j^jj

regarij to

Austin.

known
it

to

all

those

who
a

studied law

under Maine that he was from the

first

warm

admirer of Austin, and that

was largely due

to his

teaching that Austin acquired that wide and deep influence


over English jurisprudence which up to that time he had

not enjoyed.

considerable

number

of eminent

men

at-

tended Austin^s lectures, which were delivered between 1826

and 1833.
prudence,''

In that year he published the 'Province of Juris-

which contains that portion of his lectures which

has become celebrated.

But no

notice

was taken of
it

it

until

Maine
It

insisted

upon the importance of

to English students.

may

be noted in passing that this did not cause any dis-

appointment to Austin.
sincere inquirers

As he

says himself,

'

So few are the


worth of

who

turn their attention to these sciences,

and

so diflficult it is for the multitude to perceive the

their labours, that the


is

advancement of the sciences themselves

comparatively slow; whilst the most perspicuous of the

truths with which they are occasionally enriched are either


^

Early History of Institutions,

p. 343.

Sec. ig, i6.]

GENERAL CONCEPTION OP LAW,


as worthless

rejected
or

by the many

and pernicious paradoxes^ and obstinate errors/


sincere inquirers/

win their laborious way to general assent through a long


established
'

and dubious struggle with

But Maine was

precisely one of those

He

waSj however, fortunately, a great deal more^

Besides being

able as a jurist to appreciate the inestimable value of Austin's


analysis as
historical

basis for the philosophy of law, he


political insight

had the

and

which enabled him to per-

ceive the precise limits of the task

which Austin had


in
to
Haines's

set

himself

to

perform.

Consequently

writings,

particularly in that portion of


alluded,

them

which I have already


ex-*

we have
is

exactly that correction which a too

elusive study of Austin's rigid analysis necessarily requires^

But

there

not the slightest indication, as far as I

am

aware,

that Maine ever hesitated about his acceptance of Austin's


analysis and of
its results.

In the passage which I have already

quoted, and in other passages both of his earlier and later

works, he speaks in the most emphatic terms of their value.


16.

In one respect I think Maine's observations do not

Maxiin

quite correctly represent Austin's views.

He

cites cases

in a goye-

order to

show that the


'

application of Austin's conceptions to


:

ig

P^i-

them would be

doubtful ' and amongst them he comPunjaub under the rule of Kunjeet cites the case of the Singh, where, as Maine thinks, there were no positive laws
difficult or

at

all,

the people being governed by customs which were

enforced

by the
is

quasi-domestic authority of a village court

^i

All this

probable enough.

But Maine then makes the

somewhat remarkable suggestion that Austin would have


brought such a condition of things within his conceptions of

law and sovereignty by a

resort to

what he
that

calls 'the

great

maxim'
In the

that 'what
first

the

sovereign permits he commands.'


find

place

I cannot

Austin ever gave


I suppose that the

expression to any such

maxim

as this,
i.

passage referred to

is

in Lecture

p.

104, but the


is

maxim

which can be extracted from that passage


'

one of a very

Early History of Institutions,

p. 381.

8
different

GENEEAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.


character.

[Chap.
is^

I.

What

Austin there says

not that

everything which the sovereign permits he commands, but


that a rule which the sovereign permits a judge to lay down,

and which, when

laid

down, he will himself enforce, he must

be taken to have commanded.

But

in this

form the maxim

could have no application whatsoever to the state of things


described

by Maine
it.

we

cannot, therefore, solve any difficulty


difficulty is there to solve ?

by means of

But what

What

Maine shows

is

that in the Punjaub, in the time of Runjeet

Singh, the people were governed, not by positive laws, but by


rules chiefly of a religious or semi-religious character, to the

enforcement of which no regard was paid by the reigning

monarch.

But the

existence of such rules

neither

affects

Austin's conception of laws in general, in which

many

of

them

are included, nor does

it affect

his conception of positive

law or of sovereignty, with which they are not concerned.

In every

state,

even the most modern ones, there are rules


life

regulating the
presently)
justice,

of the people,

and even

(as

I shall show

entering largely into the decisions of courts of

which do not belong to positive law,

In the Punjaub,

in Runjeet Singh's day, the distinction between positive

law

and morals
now.

as

drawn by Austin was


seems to

certainly not recognised.


it
is

I should be rather surprised to hear that

recognised

Moreover,

it

me

that

Maine has overlooked


similar

that the application to the case supposed, and to


cases, of
all

any such vague maxim

as

he suggests, would sweep

laws which
or

men

obey, whether positive laws, or moral


into

laws,

divine

laws,

one

net,

and thereby destroy

entirely the distinction

between positive law and other laws


called,

properly or improperly so

which

it

was the prime

object of Austin's analysis to define and maintain.


Austin's analysis reducible
evid^ent

17.

Maine has more than once observed that Austin's


.

conceptions
historical

When
This

rightly viewed, that

,i

is,

as legal, not as

Conceptions,
is

have the appearance of self-evident


quite true.

propositions.

propositions.

But

it

does

not at

all

follow from this that his labours were unfruitful, and I have

Sec. I7, i^a.J

GENERAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.


this

9
Selfit
is

already
evident

shown that

was not Maine's meaning.


contain truths which

propositions very often


:

convenient to ignore
are ignored
is

and the common way in which they


of

by the nse
is

ambiguous language, in which

the contradiction

so artfully concealed that it takes


it.

much
set

time and patience to detect

The task which Austin

himself was the comparatively humble one, but the useful

and even necessary one,


contradictions,
carelessness to

of

hunting out and exposing these


it

making repeat them ^.


and
criticism of

impossible

without

wilful

17

^.

Another

Austin

is

as to his introduction The It has

ele-

into the conception of law of the element of force.

been more than once observed that Austin gives somewhat excessive prominence to the element of force, which (it is
admitted)
is

foj.ce in the con-

ception of law.

contained in every law, but which

is

very often
effort

so far in the to discover

background that

it

requires a

good deal of
is

it.

That the

force

by which law
is

sanctioned

does remain very

much
by

out of sight

undoubtedly true,
shall
it is

and the forms of


hereafter, affected

legal procedure

have been, as I

show
true

this circumstance^.

So

too

that

many
;

laws do not even bear the external form of


in fact,

commands

very few do

so.

We may

turn over

page after page of the statute-book and not find an imperative passage.
*
'

But

at the

same time

it is

impossible that law

In the confidence of private friendship, Mr. Austin once said of had any special intellectual vocation, it was that of "untying knots." In this judgment he estimated his own qualifications very correctly. The untying of intellectual knots the clearing up of the puzzles arising from complex combinations of ideas confusedly apprehended, and not analysed into their elements the building up of definite conceptions where only indefinite ones existed, and where the current phrases disguised and perpetuated the indefiniteness the disentangling of the classifications and distinctions grounded on differences in things in themselves from those arising out of the mere accidents of their
himself, that if he
; ; ;

history, and,
first

when

disentangled, applj'ing the distinctions, often for the

time, clearly, consistently,

and uniformly

these were, of the many


jurist, those

admirable characteristics of Mr. Austin's work as a

more
'

especially distinguished him.'


iii.

J. S. Mill,

Dissertations

which and Dis-

cussions, vol.

p. 207.

See post,

sects. 839, 843,

10

GENERAL CONCEPTION OF LAW,


it is

[Chap.

should exist without foreej and

desirable in the analysis


it^

of law to bring into prominence this feature of

for the
is

very reason that


desirable that

it

might otherwise be overlooked.

It

also

we

should be reminded that (as Mr. Harrison


force

says

^)

it is this

which causes every declaration of the


is
'

sovereign to be something which

not advice^ nor an

ideal,

nor custom^ nor an example of any kind/ but an imperative

command,
Divisibil-

as

much as any
who
"

article of

the penal code.

17 b. Austin''s conception of sovereignty has been vigorously

reignty

attacked by writers
occupied
called
''

deal with the very peculiar position to

by the British Government in regard


and
'

what

are

protectorates

spheres of influence,'

and

also in
all

regard to the native princes of India.


these
cases

Undoubtedly in

the stronger governnlent

assumes to exercise

functions in the territory of the weaker one which only

a sovereign authority can exercise, whilst

it

leaves

other

sovereign functions in the hands of the weaker government.


It follows, therefore, that in these cases sovereignty
is

divided.

From
of

this it seems to be

inferred that Austin''s conception

sovereignty must be

erroneous, because, as
it

is

alleged,

according to his conception of


Surely, however, this
is

no such division

is possible.

not the case.

Not only

does Austin

nowhere say

so,

but he, almost in express terms, says directly

the contrary.

He

explains the position of (so-called) 'half


their case the sovereignty

sovereign' states^
is

by showing that in

shared by two otherwise independent political societies j and


is

he supports this view by pointing out that this


of the infinite variety of

only one

ways in which sovereignty may be


or bodies of persons,

shared

by -different persons
members

and that

it

makes no
constituent
society.
in international
law.

difference that in
is

any

particular c^ase one of the

also sovereign in

another political

17
.

c.

Speaking more generally, Maine

View ot sovereignty
1

...

asserts that Austin's


^.

is

not that of international law

This

Fortnightly Eeview, No. 143, N. S., p. 688. = Leot. yi. p. 258. See Maine's International Law, p. 58, qnoteA by Jerkyns, British

Sec. I7b-i7d.]

GENERAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.


many
cases

11

may

be true, though I suspect that in

where the

term 'sovereignty' has been used in international arrange-

ments

without
to
it

any such
the

precise

meaning
definition

as

Austin has
only been

assigned

necessity

of

has

adjourned,

and that though the language used may for


all practical

a time be sufficient for

purposes, yet
it

when the
be found
it

necessity for greater precision does arise


difficult to

may

deal with.

But however convenient


to

may

be

in international negotiations

avoid

difficulties

by using

language which

is

not very precise,

it still

remains true that

a lawyer dealing with legal questions must always be prepared


to prove,
if
it

is

denied, that there

is

a determinate and

supreme sovereign or sovereign body of whom, or of which, the


intentions as

regards the matter under

consideration

are

capable of being ascertained, and that the

commands

of this

person or body will be obeyed.

Of

the component parts of

a sovereign body some

may

be able to act independently of

the others, and then the lawyer must be prepared to show


precisely

how

the hne of demarcation


is

is

drawn.
in

17 d.

There

no

difficulty,

therefore,

making the and


international

in

admission that in the kind of law which


law, the word
attributed to
'

is called

sovereignty

'

is

not used in the precise sense


is

it

by Austin.

Still less difficulty

there in

admitting that Austin's conception of sovereignty has nothing


to do with
politics.

It sometimes suits politicians to use

language of a very vague kind, as when they speak of the


'

sovereignty of the
'.

people.''

Such a phrase has no

legal

significance

Kule and Jurisdiction Beyond Seas, p. i66. See also in some observaby Sir Courtenay Ilbert in The Government of India, p. 460. Kecently the word ' suzerain has come into us6. Like some other terms used in international arrangements it has no precise meaning, though it
tions
'

may
'

be useful for the moment. I entirely dissent from the view that in this country the sovereignty

can in any legal sense be said to be shared by those who elect the members of the House of Commons. No doubt Austin says this (Lect. vi.
p. 253),

but

it

conflicts

with

all

which he has said on the subject of

sovereignty elsewhere.

12
Rules of

aENEEAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.


17 e.

[Chap.

T.

different,

and

to

my mind
'

a far more serious^

criti-

whichare cism of Austin^s conception of law and sovereignty lies in not laws, ^jj^g observation that there are many rules of conduct which
but are enforced
_
^

are treated as binding,

and which are enforced just


This

like other

tribunals, laws, but

which nevertheless do not proceed from the soveall.

reign authority at

is

boldly asserted
.

who
all

accordingly divides laws into real

by Bentham, commands and fictiwhich do

tious commands'-.

But, as he then proceeds to argue that


is,

laws which are not real commands, that

not proceed from the sovereign authority, ought to be at

once got rid

of, his
is

view does not help

us.

The

assertion

I have to meet

that there are rules of conduct, and these

not rare and exceptional ones, but abounding in every system

and recognised by judges, which do not answer


description of laws as being
authority.

to Austin's

commands

issued

by sovereign

This

is

a different kind of objection to that stated

above, namely, that some laws do not fall within Austin's


conception, because they are not imperative in form.

The

objection

is

the graver one that they do not proceed from the

sovereign authority.
It
is

pointed out, for example, that courts called courts of

equity exercise systematically a corrective and supplementary


jurisdiction

avowedly
:

based
all

not

upon

positive

law but

upon morality
custom; that

that
all

courts acknowledge the validity of

English courts administer law which the

sovereign never heard of and which they manufacture for

themselves
or
not, to

that all courts, whether called courts of equity

some extent try the actions of men, not by a standard fixed by the sovereign, but by their own estimation
of

prudence,

honesty,

skill,

and
it

diligence.

It

is

urged

that whilst, on the one hand,

would be impossible to
bringing

deny that the courts acting as I have described administer


law, on

the

other,

there

is

no

possibility

of

the law so administered under the conception of a


issued

command

by a
'

sovereign.
Bowring's
ed. vol.
i.

p. 263, n.

vol.

ill.

p. 223.

Sec. I7e-19.]

GENERAL CONCEPTION OP LAW.


answered

13
this Austin's

18.

Austin has, in part, forestalled and

objection.

With regard

to

any

rule

which emanates from tkmof the


is

a judge he has pointed out^ that a judge

merely a minister
J'^'^j'^

with delegated powers, and any

made by him, so long tribunals, as he acts within his delegated authority, are as much commands of the sovereign power as if they had been issued by
rul'es

itself.

With

regard to customs, which the judge does not

make but

only applies, he asserts ^ that until applied they are

moral rules only, and that the judge transforms them into
legal rules

by

the same authority as that Under which he

makes
to

rules

which are not suggested by custom.

Any

judge

permitted to

make

rules

he considers to be

tacitly

empowered

make laws ^.
10.

This answer, so far as

it

goes,

seems to

me

to be

How far
leign comi
"'v'^rjjg

complete.

The
is

point at which

it

has been most strongly

attacked
is

the assertion that the sovereign's acquiescence


to a

equivalent

command
he
tacitly

and
'

if

Austin intelided to

permits,

state,

broadly and generally, that permits

everything which the


assertion
is,

sovereign

commands/ the

no doubt, untenable*.
does not say

But, as I have already said*, Austin


it

does not say this, nor was


'

possible for

him

to say this.

He

whatever the sovereign permits to anybody,^


'
:

but

'

whatever the sovereign permits to a judge


'

nor does
'

he even say
ever
is

whatever

is

permitted to a

judge,'*
is

but

what-

permitted to a judge to order, and

enforced
is

by

sovereign authority

when

it is

is

ordered.^

This

what I
issued

understand Austin to say

equivalent to a

command

1 '

It

' lect. xxx. Lect. xxix. p. 547. p. 560. has been objected that the Talldity of a custom cannot be dated

from
true

meant influence, this is by an inferior court, it may be still doubtful n'hether the custom would be recognised by the Court of Appeal. But at most this only proves that there are rules of conduct which, though recognised by judges, are still not law. This I admit, and I shall discuss almost immediately the consequences of the
its judicial recognition.

If

by

validity is

as

it is also

true that, after legal recognition

admission.
*
'

Maine's Early History of Institutions,


Supra, sect. 16 a.

p. 374.

See post,

sect. 121,

14

GENERAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.


itself.

[Chap.

I.

by the sovereign authority

Nor

does this

seem to

me
Rules of

to be

an extravagant
regards

assertion.

20.

As
.

morality, Austin's opinion

seems to be
morality

applied by that courts of equity


courts of

do not,

now

at

any

rate, enforce

^g g^gj^

^^g^^ ^j^g
is

notion of courts of equity being courts of

conscience

obsolete,

and that the

rules

upon which courts


law as any which

of equity proceed are as

much
^.

rules of

prevail in ordinary courts


siders the

In the ordinary courts he con-

attempt to introduce morality as a basis of decision

to be limited to a single decision of

Lord Mansfield's, which

he thinks deservedly failed


and by
courts of

^.

21.

Austin does not consider the case of courts of


_

common

common

law enforcing rules of conduct founded upon considerations


of honesty, prudence, skill or diligence. It
is

not unlikely

that

if

he had done so here also he would have said


call rules of

these
'

which you

conduct are really rules of law.

It

makes no

difference that they are rules

which men generally

think that they ought to observe apart from law.

The judges
;

have adopted them and the sovereign enforces them

and

upon the principle stated they


Austin's
tiou action of

are, therefore, law.'


all

22. It

is

obvious that these answers


first,

depend upon the


authority

onhe assumption,
^Q

that the judge has a delegated

make

rules of law,

and secondly,

that, in requiring that

bunalsin- the actions of

men

should conform with any rule of conduct

which the judge approves, he means to lay down a rule of law.

That judges in England can and do make law no one can deny. Take for example the action of judges in regard to

what

is

called

'

undue

influence.'

Morality suggests that

when one person

stands in a confidential relation to another,

as his legal or spiritual adviser, he should take

no advantage

of his position to obtain

any pecuniary

benefit for himself.

Judges have transformed this rule of morality into a rule


' =

Lect. xxxvi. p. 640.

Lect. V. p. 224.
I).

Lee

decision here referred to is probably that of Muggeridge, reported in Taunton's Reports, vol. v. p. 36. It is
it

The

frequently quoted as a decision of Lord Mansfield, but a decision of Sir James Mansfield.

was

really

Sec. 20-23a.]

GENERAL CONCEPTION OP LAW


;

15

of law as binding as an act of parliament


similar instances

and hundreds of

might be given.

23. Accepting, however, Austin's explanation as sufficient


in such cases as this, I do not think it solves the whole
culty.
diffi-

There
are

are,

I think, cases even in England in which

rules

adopted and acted upon by judges, which have

not hitherto existed as law, and which judges do not even


pretend to

make law by

acting upon them.

In other words,

I think judges constantly arrive at a point at which they


refer to a standard

which

is

not a legal one.

This takes
if

place

frequently in
afield, if

modern English law.


to the earlier

But

we

look

further

we turn

English law, or to
even
not

modern continental law, we


a

shall find the same, perhaps

larger, importation into decisions of

matter which

is

legal.

The

very notion that a rule can

by any

possibility
is

be transformed into law by judicial recognition

quite

a modern one even in England, a,nd nothing of the kind has ever been recognised except in England, and in countries

which have formed


of England.
is

their legal system

under the influence


it

This I shall explain more fully hereafter;


the present to indicate the fact which
yet

sufficient for

is

indisputable.

And

we

find

that

everywhere

judges

unhesitatingly refer to

the principles of jurisprudence as

generally recognised, to the principles of equity, and to the

guidance of

common

sense.

And
said

they take their guidance

as willingly from these sources as from

any
^,

other.
it
is

23

a.

After what I have

already

scarcely

necessary to observe that I entirely reject the notion that


these cases can be explained

by the
and

facile

suggestion that

the judge acts by the implied permission of the sovereign.

That he does

so

act

is

true,
if

it

is

also

true that the

sovereign authority can,

necessary, be invoked to enforce

the judge's decree.


difficulty.

But

this does not help us to solve the

It

is

not, as

judges are permitted to

we have seen, make rules of


Supra, sect. i6a.

universally true that


law,

and even where

16
it

GBNERAI, CONCEPTION OF LAW.


is otliei?wise it is

[Chap.

I.

no part of the

judge-'s intetitioa in the


:

cases I have

piit to construct

a rule of law

all

he aims at

is,

the issue of a particular


Not,

command.
seem to place the
to
disciple of

how-

24. These admissions


in a
difficulty.

Austin

ceas^ary^to

They seem

show that Austin's conception


'^

modify his q
conception of law.

^^ g j^^^ adequate ^
it is

even as appKed to modern English law^ ^


.

and that
In

equally inadequate

if

we

look into our

own

past history^ or into the condition of law in other countries.


shortj it

seems to show that Austin^'s conception of law


oi*

fails as

a general

Scientific conception;

Judgesfreact with-

25.

The

difficulty,

however, appears to
It
is

me

to be created

by an erroneous assumption.
an analysis
is

always assumed
it

when

out law.

made

of a judicial decision that

consists of

two parts
which

only, a finding of the facts,

and an application of
is
^,

the law to the facts so found.


this

There

perhaps a sense in

language

may
lies

be justified

but under this lanis

guage there generally


isrroneous
;

an assumption which

certainly

namely, that

when once we have

ascertained all

the events which have occurred, and which in any

way

bear
left

upon the matter

in dispute,

we can

never have anything

to do but to apply the law.

26. This conception of a judicial


application of rules of

decision,

as

the mere

law

to

events which have occurred,

may

possibly be an ideal which

we ought

to endeavour to

realise.

It was, no doubt, Bentham's ideal, and I should

feel disposed to

say that he wasted a great part of his


intellectual

life

and much of his vast


realise it too hastily.

power in endeavouring to But the history of law shows a very


It
is

different conception of a judicial decision.

worth while

to reflect to

how

large an extent tribunals have existed,

do
1

exist,

without law.

We

may

see this easily

and enough when


it is

Speaking of courts in which caSes are tried before a jury,


all all

some-

times said that


for the jury.

questions are questions of law or questions of fact, questions are questions for the judge or questions

tneaning thereby that

Of course in this Sense the statement is obviously true. I have discussed this subject in an article in the Law Magazine, 4th series, Vol, ii. p. 311, to which I beg leave to refer.

Sec. Z4-27.J

GENERAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.


is

17

a rude and turbulent people

being gradually brought round


This I shall show more at

to peaceful and orderly habits.

length presently.
of the

But I

will take

my

first

example from one

Civil

modern countries of Europe. Art. 4 of the French Code contains an express provision that the judge who
upon the ground of the
is

refuses to give a decision

silence or

the insufficiency of the law

guilty of an offence, for which

the penal code by Art. 185 renders him liable to a fine of two

hundred

francs.

Yet the French judge cannot

issue

any

repentinum eclidum or fall back, as an English judge often


can,

upon the inexhaustible ' common


from pretending

law.'

Curiously enough,
fifth,

the very next article of the Civil Code, the


hibits judges

expressly pro-

giving their decisions ^.

to lay down general rules when Under such circumstances one might

imagine that a French judge would abandon himself to some


such indolent

negative decision.
'

maxim as Not
the
'

prout res
at
all.

incidit,

and give a merely


to

la doctrine et la jurisprudence.^
calls

He refers He looks
'

what he
relies

calls

at the case

from

what he
'

point de vue juridique.'


le

He

on the

principes generaux de droit,' or

bon sens

et I'equite.'

And he

does this not because the rules thus vaguely referred

to are law, or because


like a sensible

he can make them


prefers

so,

but because,
unassisted

man, he

them

to his

own

judgment.
27.

The extent

to

which

judicial

tribunals

can

act,

and Function
to regulate

are obliged to act, without law, becomes stiU

more apparent

when we go back
easily reach a time

to the early history of law.

We may ^^ ^^^^

when we
any law

find a species of rude tribunals disputes,

in

action without

at

all.

In a very interesting
legal

lecture

upon the primitive forms of


has shown that
'

remedies^. Sir

Henry Maine

many

ancient forms of pro-

1 Code Civ, Art. 4 Le juge qui refusera de juger sous pr^texte du silence, de I'obsciirit^, ou de I'insuffisance de la loi pourra Stre poursuivi comme coupable de dfei de justice.' Art. 5 'II est d^fendu aux juges de prononcer par voie de disposition g6u6rale et r^glementaire sur les causes qui
: :

leur sont soumises.'


"

Early History of Institutions, Lect.

ix.

18

GENERAL CONCEPTION OP LAW.


may

[Chap.

I.

cedure

be analysed into disorderly proceedings^ which

some one

steps in to regulate.

So too the early history of


to

most Teutonic nations reveals

us a stage at which for

the simple struggle between the opposing parties there was


substituted a combat under fixed rules.

The

contrast becomes

most striking when we

find, as in

our

own

early legal history,

the judges of a regular court prescribing the rules and conditions of a combat,
it.

and even present at and presiding over

We

read in our

Law

Keports

how

the judges of the

Court of

Common

Pleas used to attend in person at the day


attired in their scarlet
^.

and place appointed for the combat,


robes,
series

and accompanied by the sergeants-at-law


of cases to be

The long

found in our reports upon wager of

battle terminates

with one which was decided as late as

the year 1819.

The

incidents of that case


little

from a

juristic

point of view are not a

remarkable
sister of

^.

One Thornton
with the ver-

was

tried for the

murder of the

Ashford, and was

acquitted,
dict,
'

whereupon Ashford, being


'

dissatisfied

appealed

Thornton for the murder.

Thornton replied

that he was not guilty, and that he was ready to defend

himself against the charge

by

his

body

in other words,

that he was ready to fight Ashford.

that Thornton was not entitled to

'

To this Ashford replied wage his battle,'' bewere


stated), his guilt

cause, under the circumstances (which

was manifest.

At

this point the ease

was submitted

to the

Court of Queen's Bench, and the judges, after a very long


argument, decided that Thornton was entitled to his wager
of battle.

They doubted, however, whether Ashford had


right
to
his

not lost his appeal by contesting, upon invalid grounds,

Thornton's

wager
:

of

battle,

instead

of

ac-

cepting his challenge at once

and upon

this point,

which

was
ease
'

reserved,

judgment was never given. All through the was argued upon precedent and authority, precisely

but which went


2

See a very full report of a combat which was arranged to take place, off because one of the combatants failed to appear, in Dyer's Reports, temp. Elizabeth, p. 301 a. See the report in Barnewall and Alderson's Reports, vol.
i.

p. 405.

Sec. 28, 29.J

GENERAL CONCEPTION OE LAW.


way
as if the Court had beea trying

19

in the same

an action

of trespass, or upon a bill of exchange.


substantial

And

yet the only

question

before

the

Court was,

whether the

parties should be remitted pretty nearly to the position of

a couple of savages one of

whom had

suffered

an injury

which he sought
the

to revenge.

28; Cases like these furnish most interesting examples of

way

in

which law can accommodate

itself to

circum-

stances.

In the same way

as a judge does not refuse to

act, because

he cannot find or create a rule of law applicable

to the dispute, so he does not refuse to act, because the dis-

pute

is

not altogether under his control.

It

is

in this

way
it

that the law recovered inch by inch the ground which

had

lost in turbulent times.

After the

fall of

the

Roman

Empire there was a


not wholly effaced.

step

backwards, and private warfare


Still

superseded regular judicial procedure.


It regulated the

the

law was
it

combat which

would

not suppress.
of law verdict
is

So too the

vitality as well as the pliability

well illustrated
their

when we

find a jury defending their

by

own

bodies, or a magistrate

demanding

satis-

faction for a contempt of court in precisely the same terms


as if he were resenting a personal insult.

29. It being understood, therefore, that the function of Judges

a judge

is

not only to apply law to ascertained facts, but to both go

decide or to put in train for decision every dispute which comes ^^e^'aw. before him, we are now prepared to consider the position of

a judge who, having two litigants before him, finds that one
of

them has done something which


any
rule of

is

contrary to the habits,


parties belong.

feelings,

or opinions of the society to which the

Is there

law which binds him to the decision of

the case in a particular


wliatever he or others
if

way? If there is, he must apply it may think of the propriety of it. But
still

there

is

not,

he must

give a decision

and he

will

naturally decide against that party whose conduct has been

unusual or unreasonable, or dishonest, or negligent.

If,

as

Austin seems to say, there are in


c 3

all

such cases rules of


GENERAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.

20

[Chap.

I.

conduct which judges have transformed into rules of law cadit


quaestio, our
rules of
it

assumption that the judge has gone outside the


is

law

unfounded ^.

But

if it

be admitted, as I think
resort to a standard

must be admitted, that judges frequently

of conduct which, according to Austin's conception of law,


is

not a legal one, then I say that the mere fact that a judge

refers to such a standard does not

compel

me

to conceive

law

so as to include
lots,

it.

If a judge comes to a decision

by drawing
parties to
trial

or after inspecting entrails, or

by causing the
it

submit to some
of strength
it

ordeal, or the terrors of


skill,

an oath, or to a

and

we do not think
all

necessary to say

would simply throw

notions of law into confusion to


all

say

that these matters were


:

thereby brought within the


in such cases, as in
it is true,

province of jurisprudence.

The judge

every case in which he makes any order, delivers,

command
;

but this command

is

not exclusively founded

upon law

it

may

be founded upon chance, or upon the result


of the divine will of

of a combat, or
pleasure, or

upon some indication

and

upon the judge's own notion

what
of

is

right and

expedient.

30.
of

The power which EngHsh judges have


it

making

rules

law makes

sometimes

difficult

to say precisely,

when
of

they are importing rules of conduct into law, and when they
are

going outside the


of

rules

of

law and making use


find

the rules

conduct which

they

elsewhere

for

the

purposes of their decision.


I'ules

Consequently there are


courts of
justice

many
which

made use

of

in

English

hover upon the borders of law, and

we

are hardly able to

say whether they are legal rules or not^-

Of

course such

^ There are a vast nnmber of broad and general presumptions which judges sometimes make use of, in order to avoid any very definite conclusion such for example as potior est conditio possidentis, semper
:

praesumitur pro negante, &c. These are rules of law, but, unless they are indolent, judges do not often take -refuge in these maxims. ^ There was at one time a struggle to establish as a rule of law that it was the duty of the servants of a railway company to call out the name of a station before a train had reached the platform, and for a time it seemed likely to be recognised that this was a matter of law; but it is

Sec. 30, 31.]

GENERAL CONCEPTION OE LAW.

21

a doubtful condition could only exist in English law.


nevertheless, it so happens that

But,
clearly

we can

see rather

more

in the English courts than elsewhere the operation of rules of

conduct which are not law, because of the separation of the


functions of decision between judge and jury.
is

When

a case

being tried by a judge with the assistance of a jury, the

rule

which assigns the respective duties of these two parts of


and to leave
is

the tribunal directs the judge to decide questions of law


himself,
to the jury questions of fact.

Generally

nothing

said as to

how

questions of conduct are to be


left to

decided; but they are, in practice, always


unless

the jury,

and

until

the judge chooses to take any particular

question out of the province of the jury


rule of law.

by applying
is

to it a

To
is

say, therefore, that a standard

to be applied
is

by the jury

the same thing as to say that the standard

not a legal one.

But the non-legal standard


is

is

in fact also

applied in courts in which there

no jury, and the nature of

the standard does not depend upon the person


31. It
is

who

applies

it

a rigorous deduction from Austin's conception


sovereign authority
is

Sove-

of law that the

a ^ purely
!

this,

view absolute. Bentham^ ^ and Blackstone ^ has been forced to admit


lesjal
^

supreme, and from nt^caphas also maintained f.'^^'r t^

it.

No

doubt by

limitation law.

we commonly speak
now
able.
Ir.
"^

of

some governments
must determine in each

as

free,

and of
is

settled that the tribunal

case

what

reason-

See Bridges versus North London Railway Co.,


vol. Tii. p. 213.

Law

Eep. Eng. and

App.
It

be suggested that since tribunals can act entirely without law (which they certainly can conceivably do), law is not a necessary element in the conception of a political society. It is doubtless possible to conceive a political society with tribunals for settling disputes without law but, as I consider that it would be the inevitable tendency of such a society to develope law, I do not think that what is said above ( i sqq.) as to the

may

conception of a political society requires modification. 2 Fragment on Government, s. 26 vol. i. p. 288 of Bowring's edition.
;

Blackstone says (Commentaries, vol. i. p. 48) of governments, that, however they began, or by what right soever they subsist, there is and must be in all of them a supreme, irresistible, absolute, uncontrolled authority, in which the jura summi imperii, or the rights of sovereignty,
'
'

reside.'

See also Burgess, Political Science,

vol,

i.

p. 5a,

and the authori-

ties there cited.

22

GENERAL CONCEPTION OE LAW.


it

[Chap.

I.

others as despotic; and

would be
;

idle to

deny that these


is

terms hare important meanings

but they do not mean, as

often assumed, that the powers vested in the one are, in the

aggregate, less than the powers vested in the other.

As

Bentham has pointed out, the distinction between a government which is despotic and one which is free turns upon circumstances of an entirely different kind ' on the manner
:

in

which the whole mass of power, which taken together


is

is

supreme,

in a free

state distributed amoiig the


it
j

several

ranks of persons that are sharers in

on the source from


derived;

whence

their titles to it are

successively

on the

frequent and easy changes of condition between governors and

governed, whereby the interests of one class are more or less


indistinguishably blended with those of the other
responsibility of the governors
ject has of
; ;

on the

on the right which the sub-

having the reasons publicly assigned and canvassed

of every act of

power that
all

is

exerted over him.''

But,

if

we

once admit that

law proceeds from the sovereign body, to

speak of the authority of the sovereign body being limited, or


of its acts being illegal,
Limitation by express
is

a confusion of terms.

32. There

is

only one limitation of sovereign authority


'

which Bentham thinks possible ; namely,


tion.''

by express conventhan

convention.

am

not at

all

disposed to underrate such restrictions,


is

but

it

seems to

me

that their value

political rather

legal.

They

serve as a guide to a conscientious

man when
authority.

he

is

considering whether he

ought to

resist

Bentham has

elsewhere

shown the

futility of

attempting to

create irrevocable laws,

and there must


or,

be, therefore,

some

body which has the power to revoke,


to
set

in exceptional cases,
;

aside

even

the

most

fundamental rules

and in
it

that body the supreme authority will reside.


that very
often

Hence

is

what was intended

as

a restriction upon

authority really operates as a re-distribution of power.


instance,
it

For was no doubt intended to limit the authority of the President and Congress of the United States, by the fifth
'

Bo-wring's ed., vol.

ii.

p. 401.

Sec. 32-34.]

GENERAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.


But
it is

23

article

of the Constitution.

Austin^s opinion, that

the

effect of

that article

is

to place the ultimate sovereignty

in the States, taken as forming one aggregate body,

and to

render the ordinary government, consisting of the President

and Congress,

as

well as the

States'

governments, taken

severally, subordinate thereto^.

33.

There would

still

be this peculiarity in the United

States' Constitution, that the ultimate sovereign

power was

generally dormant, and was only called into active existence

on rare and

special occasions.

This

is

not inconsistent with

sovereignty, or with our conception of a political society ; but


it is

peculiarity.

And

the exact nature of the American

Constitution

may

possibly, in relation to certain questions of

international law, become a topic of further discussion.


34. It
is

this peculiarity in the

American Constitution which

Functions

gives the

Supreme Court

of the United States its apparently supreme


course, whatever

anomalous character.

Of

may

be the

effect p'^^>
political,

of the Articles of the Constitution in limiting the sovereign

powers of the President and Congress, those provisions would


fall far short of

the object they were intended to secure,

if

there were not

some ready means and that and


all

of declaring

had been
were void.

violated,

acts

in violation of

This function has accordingly


;

when they them been exercised by

the Supreme Court


^

if

Austin

is

right in considering the

This article provides


shall

tliat

Congress, whenever two-thirds of both

Houses

deem

it

necessary, shall propose

amendments

to the Consti-

tution, or,

on the application of the

legislatures of two-thirds of the several

states, shall call

case, shall be valid to all intents

a convention for proposing amendments, which, in either and purposes, as part of the Constitution,
legislatures of three-fourths of the several states, or

when

ratified

by the

by conventions in
ratification

three-fourths thereof, as the one or the other

mode

of

may be

proposed by Congress.

See also Art.

X of Amendments

to the Constitution.
^ Lect. vi. p. 268 (third ed.). So too Mr. Montague Bernard says Behind both general and local authorities there is a power, intricate in respect of its machinery, and extremely difficult to set in motion, requiring the concurrence of three-fourths of the States acting by their legislatures or in conventions, which can amend the Constitution itself. This power
'

is

unlimited, or very nearly so.'-^Neutrality of Great Britain during the


p. 43.

American War,

24

GENERAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.


is

[Chap.

T.

President and Congress as not supreme, this

only an ordinary

function of a Court of Law.

The
It

acts of every authority, short

of the supreme, are everywhere submitted to the test of judicial

opinion as to their validity.

may,
is

therefore, be perhaps

doubted whether

De
is

Tocqueville

correct in calling this

function of American judges an 'immense political power ^.'


It
is,

if

Austin

correct

in

his

view of the American


all,

Constitution, not a political

power at
called

but precisely the


exercise,

same power

as

any court

judging of the acts


Courts in India, for

when of a subordinate legislature. The High instance, exercise a similar power, when
is

upon to

judging of the acts of the Governor-General in Council.

And

it

might be claimed as one of the advantages of Austin's


it

view of the American Constitution, that


of the

makes the
;

position

Supreme Court capable

of a clear definition

and thus

renders the dangerous transition from a strict judicial inquiry


to considerations of a political character,
acts of the

when

the validity of
still

Government

is

called in question,

though

far

from improbable,

at least less easy.


i

35. Moreover, even

the power of the Supreme Court can be

correctly described as a political


it

power at

all,

I doubt whether

has not been exaggerated.

Should the Supreme Court and

the President and Congress ever really measure their strength,


it

must be remembered that by the Constitution ^ the President

nominates, and with the advice and consent of the Senate


appoints, the Judges of the

Supreme Court, to hold

their office

during good behaviour 3.

This would probably be taken to

mean, that they could be removed after conviction, upon impeachment for misconduct. They are thus appointed by, and
are responsible to, the very persons to

whom

they would by

the hypothesis be opposed;


tyrannical *.
^
"^

and who by the hypothesis are


all

Now

it is

not at
vol.
i.

impossible that, so long as


vi.
3

Democracy in America,
Art. II. sect.
I
2. cl. 2.

chap.

Art. III.

sect. i.

'

assume

this,

and

also that the President, the Senate,

and the House


act

of Kepresentatives are acting

imanimously in their opposition to the

Supreme Court.

As a check on each other these separate bodies can

Sec. 35, 36.]

GENERAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.


its

25

the Supreme Court preserves

high character for integrity

and independence,
but
it
'

seems to

it may serve many very useful purposes me to go too far to say^ as De Tocqueville says,

that

the power vested in the American courts of justice of

pronouncing a statute to be unconstitutional, forms one of the

most powerful

barriers

which has ever been devised against


I think

the tyranny of political assemblies/

Bentham,

in

the passage I have quoted, has

much more
it is

correctly stated

the true securities against tyranny, whether of individuals


or of political assembHes, so far as
possible for this

protection

to

be constitutionally secured.

These

securities

Americans enjoy to the

fullest extent, coupled

with certain

national sentiments of perhaps even greater importance.

36. It

is

also necessary to observe that

what I have

said Practical
tjo^g
^''^'
J^f'

as to the absolute nature of the sovereign authority,


is

which

the purely legal view of the relation between subjects and

their rulers, does not in

any way
aspects.

represent this relation in ture of

many
all

of its

most important
is

Though for legal purposes

reignty.

sovereign authority

supreme, as a matter of fact the most

absolute government

is

not so powerful as to be unrestrained.

Though not restrained by law, the supreme rulers of every country avow their intention to govern, not for their own
benefit, or for the benefit of

any particular
;

class,

but for the

members of the
country

society generally

and they cannot altogether

neglect the duty which they have assumed.

In our own

we

possess nearly

all

the institutions

which have been

above referred to as the characteristics of a free government.

regular machinery exists for introducing into the ruling


all classes

body persons taken from


changing them,
distasteful.
if

of the community, and for

the measures of those in power become


is

Liberty of the press


subjects,

everywhere conceded.

The humblest
to

though they

may have no

defined

any extent. But it is upon their tyrannical action when united that an external check of some kind is required, and this I think the Supreme Court would fail to supply.

26

GENEEAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.

[Chap.

I.

power; have a right to meet and to state their grievances,


provided they do not disturb the public peace.

And
such

the
re-

Government

hardly

ever

refuses

to

hsten

to

monstrances, though, through ignorance and selfishness, they

not unfrequently turn out to be unfounded, or to represent

but very feebly,


at large.
Persons
sovereign

if

at

all,

the real interests of the community

37.

We

must
to

also

distinguish the

independence of the

sovereign body itself from the independence of the

members

generaSy^
subject to

who happen
of
^iie

compose that body.

The

King, the members

British

Parhament, the Viceroys of India and of

Ireland, the President of the

United States of America, are aU


:

subject to the same general laws as ourselves


of convenience the process against
is

only for reasons

them

in case of disobedience

somewhat

different.

ImportoT|/ip

38. I have dwelt

upon these

practical qualifications of the

or

understanding distmction be-

doctrine of the supremacy of the sovereign authority, because


^jjg^j-

(Jogtrine has been thought to arm the actual rulers of a country with unlimited powers ; to destroy the distinction

and
"''

poll-

between

free

and despotic governments; and


all responsibility.

to absolve the

holders of

power from

It does nothing of

the

kind.

Even where no attempt has been made,


submit
it,

as in

America, to bind the exercise of authority by a special set of


rules, or to

as in

France under the Republic and

the Second Empire, to the popular wilP, powerful checks


exist

upon the

exercise of arbitrary authority,

which are none

the less effectual because they do not belong to the province


of law.
Delegasovereign y.

39.
such,

Having then estabhshed that the sovereign body,


is

as

independent of law, and that the sovereign body lays

^q^jj^ ^g positive law, the rules

which are to regulate the

' The Constitution of the Fourteenth of January 1851, does not, like that of the Fourth of ifovember 1848, contain a declaration 'that the sovereignty resides in the whole mass of French citizens taken together'

(Art. I), but it attempts to give effect to a similar notion by declaring the right of the Emperor (then called President) to appeal to the people
at large (Art. V).

Sec. 37-43-]

GENERAi CONCEPTION OF LAW.


it

27

conduct of the political society which


into the relation of rulers

governs, the inquiry

and

their subjects would, for legal

purposes, seem to be complete.


of governors

It

would be a simple

relation

and governed.
is

40. But, in fact, this simple state of things

nowhere

known
it

to

exist.

Not

only does the sovereign body find


its

necessary to employ others to execute

commands, by

enforcing obedience whenever particular individuals evince

a disinclination to obey the law ; but in almost every country


authority
is

delegated by the sovereign body to some person


itself,

or body of persons subordinate to

who

are thereby

empowered, not merely to carry out the sovereign commands


in particular cases, but to exercise the sovereign

power

itself,

in a far more general manner;


to the

sometimes extending even

making

of rules, which are law in the strictest sense

of the term.
41.

When

the sovereign body thus substitutes for

its

own
said

will the will of another person, or

body of persons,

it is

to delegate its sovereignty

^.

42.
specific

There

is

scarcely

any authority, even


is

to

execute a Gradation
detegate^
^y.

command, which
on

conferred

by the sovereign body

in terms so precise as not to leave something: to the discre ^ tion of the person

^"

reign.

whom

it is

conferred.

On

the oihet

hand, there
is so

is

scarcely

any delegation
uncontrolled.

of sovereignty

which
it,

general and extensive as to leave the exercise of

at

any time, completely

And

it

would be easy
advancing by

to construct out of the powers usually delegated to others

by the sovereign body, a continuous


insensible degrees, discretion
is

series,

from the most

precise order,

where the

scarcely perceptible,

up

to a viceregal authority,

which
divide

is

very nearly absolute.

Any

attempt, therefore, to

these powers accurately into groups by

a division

founded

on the extent of the authority conferred must


fail.

necessarily
43. It

is,

however,

common
vi. vol.

to
i.

mark

off

and

classify

some

Austin, Lecture

p.

250 (third edition).

28
of the

GENERAL CONCEPTION O^ LAW.


more extensive and general
of the delegated
'

[Chap.

I.

powers
"
;

by describing
(in

them

as

'

sovereign

or

'

legislative

or

order to distinguish

these

delegated powers from the


itself) as
' '

powers of the supreme sovereign body


sovereign
'

subordinate

and

'

subordinate legislative
as
'

whilst the powers


'

which are

specific are described


'

judicial

or

'

executive.'

The term administrative/ so far as it has any definite meaning at all, seems to be used to describe powers which
lie

somewhere between the powers which are more general


specific.

and those which are more


the use of these terms,
if
it

No harm

results

from

which are sometimes convenient,

be

borne

in

precise distinction.
'

mind that they do not mark any They are just as useful as the terms
'

great

'

and

'

small/

long

'

and

'

short,^

but are not more

precise.
Different

44.

spicuous de'iegating
sovereignty,
.
_

To Confer the power of making laws is the most conmode of delegating sovereign authority, and it has
if it
_

been sometimes spoken of as


,

were the only mode. '

But

it is

not

so.

The Viceroy
as

of India,

when he

declares war, or

makes a

treaty, exercises the sovereign authority as directly

and completely

when, in conjunction with his Council,

he passes an Act.

So the Governor of Jamaica or the So every

Lieutenant-Governor of Bengal, when he grants a pardon,


exercises

a peculiar prerogative of sovereignty.

Judge, from a Justice of the Peace up to the Lord Chancellor,


exercises a

power which in

its

origin,

and

still

theoretically,

belongs exclusively to the sovereign, and which was at one

time considered the most conspicuous attribute of sovereign


authority.

Tiie actual

45. I have deferred until this point


tlie

any consideration of
;

the au-

origin
i-ijg^^

and foundation

of political society

as to

thonty

to

^^g
this,

^^^

^^^

^g^j^g ^^ j^^j^g

j^^g ^^^ another; and

how it why

hws.

which was the practice in

earlier associations, is still the


:

characteristic of every political society

and I do not now

intend to enter upon this inquiry fully, but only in order

Sec. 44-47.]

GENEEAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.


some misconceptions which seem
to

29

to get rid of

me

to be

subversive of all law.

46.

The

inquiry into the origin of political society

is

ob-

viously an historical one, and does not admit of speculation.

But obvious
historically

as this

is,

it

is

very rare to find the subject


are very

treated.

People

apt

to

declare

the

origin of political society to be that which best accords with


their

own

political theories.

Thus

it

is

the theory of some


it to

that kings rule by divine right, and so they assert

be

a fact that political societies under a monarch are a divine


institution.

Other people say that


,

it

is

natural to be so

governed, and then they allege that nature, as a sort of


deity, or occult agency, led people to institute a society

upon

that basis.

Other people think that no one could be obliged

to obey any ruler without his

own

assent,

and then they


a great advance

say there was a compact that


rulers.

all

should obey their ruler or


is,

This

last

notion, false as it

is

upon the other two,


any
are

for it accounts better for all the difit

ferent forms of government, and


rate,

appreciates, partially at
all

the important fact that in


interests

governments there
is

mutual

to

be considered, and that there

always some sort of concession and compromise.


of the social compact
is,

The theory
ground

in fact,

a protest against the desoit

lating theory of divine right, but


before the

falls

to the
it

obvious and simple remark, that


real existence.

never had

and never could have any


47.

The

actual origin of

most governments

is

shrouded
it

in obscurity, but one thing seems to be clear, that

never

occurred to any one to invent government.

New

forms of

government have been invented, and one form of govern-

ment has been substituted for another. But government itself did not come into existence all at once as a brilliant It grew idea, or as a device to escape from a difficulty.
up very gradually, and probably without even those who were engaged in establishing it knowing exactly what they
were about.

30
Present
basis of

GENEEAL CONCEPTION OE LAW.


49.
It
is

[Chap.
all^

I.

very possible

authority
laTra'is^ utility.

governments had their origin


individual, or a
their

mostj ,,,....., m
that

not
.

existing
.

the passions

ot a single

few individuals banded together to oppress

neighbours.

But whether They


exist

this

be so or not makes

no difference whatever when we are considering

why

govern-

ments

exist

now.
is

now

because the happiness

of the people

thereby promoted, or at least because their


less

unhappiness

is

likely to
it
is

be increased by leaving the


it.

government where
think,

than by disturbing

No

one, I

now which we
it is
is

seriously denies this.

These are the grounds upon


a government,

lend our support to

even when

obviously bad.

We
all,

know

that the worst government

better than none at

and that the chances of improving

an estabhshed government are generally far better than the


chances of setting up a
place of one which

new and improved government we have destroyed.


is
!

in the

The only
guide to the legisutility.

49, The happiness of the people, therefore, ^^ r r >


true end of government.

the only J
ruler dare

No

ruler does

avow, no

avow, any other.

Various pretexts have been put forward

in times past for the claim of one

man

to rule over another,

and they have not unfrequently been answered by pretensions equally unfounded.

All these

Bentham has thoroughly


social

exposed

divine right, the


these, in the

law of nature, the

compact,
rights of

the principles of liberty, and the imprescriptible

man

and of

form at
little

least in

which they were


this,

then in vogue, we hear but


there
is still

now.

But admitting

a desire to substitute some a priori conception

between us and the principle of utility. We are told that although the happiness of the people is the ultimate end of
government,
it
is

useless to

attempt to arrive at happiness

by placing that
to try

object directly before us.


life

We

are directed
of

and discover the laws of


existence, which,
it
is

and the conditions


will

human

said,

alone lead us to these

happiness.
conditions,

Doubtless

if

we

could discover

laws and

and could

feel

sure

that by obeying
is

them we

should arrive at happiness, this

advice which ought to be

Sec. 48-52.]

GENERAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.

31

followed.
(as

No

utilitarian

would object to

this, for utilitarians

Mill observes^) always desire the tendency of actions

to be
flicting

judged not, as

tbeir

enemies

assert,

by the coninductions

views of individuals^ but by the widest

possible.

50.

When
we

however,

we

are

asked to accept a principle


is

as a guide of action because it of life,

one of the primary laws


it

are justified in examining


is

with some caution; now, for I fear


for

and

this caution
is

especially necessary just

that there

great danger

of the

respect

law being
to accept

undermined by a principle which we are asked on the ground that


it is

one of these primary conditions, and


is

which, though invented by philosophers,


of

adroitly

made

use

by the 51. The

declared enemies of society.


principle

which has been put forward by a great The


that which
called the principle of
is

prin-

authority as a safer and more direct guide to happiness than equal

the principle of utility


equal freedom.
'

is

is

''^eedom.

Stated more at length the principle


all

that

every

man

has freedom to do

that he

wills provided that


''.'

he infringes not the equal freedom of any other man

The
it

form
to

in

which the

principle

is

stated

is

peculiar,

but I take
to

mean

that 'every
'

man

ought to have freedom


stated.

do

all

that he wills

with the proviso

I should, however,
principle
it.

have
not

still

some doubt as to the meaning of the


one
is

had
It

its

most celebrated exponent himself explained


all

means that
is

coercion of

human being by

another

immoral: that immorality


its

inherent in government and

attaches to all

functions

^.

52. It

is

worth while

to observe that
this.

up to a certain point

all utilitarians

would agree with


evil
;

They agree
all

that all
is

coercion
evil

is

an

and therefore that


is

subjection

an

But

they say that this

a fact out of which you

can make nothing for the purposes of society.

Bentham,
with which

no doubt, says a good deal more than


1
'
'

this,

Essay on Utilitarianism, p. 24. Herbert Spencer, Social Statics,


Social Statics, p. 116.

ed. 1892, p. 54.

32 I

GENERAL CONCEPTION OE LAW.


not
is

[Chap.

I.

am

now

concerned.

It

may
It

be that Bentham's ethical

theory
sophers

altogether unsound.

may
in

be that moral philo'

may
'

understand the assertion that

all
is

coercion
true.

is

immoral
it is

in

some abstract sense


the aiJairs of

which

it

But

impossible to apply
live to

any such
life.

principle in the world in

which we
apply
for if
it

Further^ to attempt to

will open the door

wide to anarchy and eonfusioUj


is

we once admit
gone.

that law

immoral^

all

hope of defend-

ing

it is

53. In a former edition of this

work

I discussed at

some

length Mr. Herbert Spencer's assumption of the law of equal

freedom from which he deduces the disastrous consequence


that
all

law

is

immoral.
great

I did so because he applied the

principle with

severity to

some of the existing

in-

stitutions of soeietyj especially to the ownership of land.

But

that eminent philosopher has somewhat changed his views, as

appears by his more recently published works


still

and though he

maintains as the primary law of society a principle which

renders the private ownership of land inequitable, he

makes

the important concession


application of his principle

that,

inasmuch as the practical


(in his opinion)

would

'work

ill,'

and 'the resulting

state of things

would be a

less desirable

one than the present/ the principle need not be acted on^.

In other words Mr. Herbert Spencer


does

(as I

understand him)

himself

agree that

the question whether the private

ownership of land shall be retained as an existing institution


does ultimately depend upon considerations, not of freedom,

but

utility.

I have always maintained that the principle of


is

equal freedom

really useless as a guide, because it is subject

to an indefinite

number

of exceptions of

which we can only

determine the existence by the method of observation and experience as applied to their results
:

in other words

by

deter-

mining

their utility.

Though
it

therefore I

may

deplore that

any philosopher should think

necessary to

commit himself
immoral, I think

to such a dangerous statement as that


'

law
444

is

Principles of Ethics, vol.

ii.

p.

(ed. 1893).

Sec. 53-56.]

GENERAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.

33
is

the very fact that he finds such a doctrine unworkable


a strong testimony against
54.
it.

Moreover

it

is

the less necessary for

me now

to say

anything at length on this subject^ seeing that the


position has been defended

utilitarian

by a far

abler

hand than mine.


'

Professor Sidgwiek in his

'

Principles of Polities

maintains^
of

as I do, that the ultimate standard

by which the action


its

government must be measured

is

conduciveness to the

general happiness of the governed^.


55.

The

principle

of

equal freedom^

as

set

forth

by The

prin-

Mr. Herbert Spencer^ does not differ very materially from that whieh has been enunciated by a German writer of a very
different school.
Lassalle^ in his
is
'

^j^g j-eali-

s^tion of

Theory of Acquired Rights,'


the realisation of the will of
is

lays

it

down

that private law

'

the individual ^/

This captivating paradox

not apparently

used by Lassalle for any very destructive purpose in the work


I have referred to, but the preface discloses that the author
well understood the use that might be

made

of it:

and the you

worst of

all

such dogmas seems to

me

to be that

may

draw from them any consequences you


56.

please.

Nothing

to

my

mind

is

more refreshing than

to turn Utility the


tioal test

from these vague and dangerous speculations


ground of
tions
'

to the solid

utility.

Though

there

may

be use in such specula-

^j

in their proper

place I object to their

being thrust

Pp- 34, 36.


Vol.

I gather

In this passage he speaks of private right only, but p. 57. from the preceding page that he would apply the same principle
i.

to all law.

Referring, I suppose, to Savigny's definition of a jural relation


'

(Rechtsverhaltniss) as

a province of the independent mastery of the


52)

individual will' (System d. h. r6m. Rechts,


p. viii)
:

Lassalle saya (Pref.

'

So

it is

well

known

that in Germany, Savigny, as the head of

the historical school, is considered to be the most prominent representative of the reactionary party, whereas his notions upon the subject of
acquired rights are in reality revolutionary and subversive, as compared with the follies and inconsistencies in the position taken up in regard to
this subject

by those who are supposed

to represent liberalism in philo-

sophy.'

I do not pretend to understand exactly

what Savigny's theory

of

acquired rights was, but there seems to be something dangerous in his talk about them. See further as to Lassalle's views the passage quoted
infra,

note to

sect. 56.

34

GENERAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.

[Chap.

I.

across the difficult path of legislation, not to

show us the way,

but only to mislead us, and reduce us to a condition of helplessness.

Why

are

we

to be led at every turn to the brink to trust to the goodnature of


?

of a precipice,

and then have

those about us not to throw us over


principle of utility
is

People say that the

barren.
please.

It certainly will not enable us

to do just

what we

But

at

any

rate

when I have

found out which of the several courses of action open to


is

me

most

likely to be

useful

that

is,

when
is

I have

formed

a judgment as to which course of action the greatest

likely to produce
least

amount
whose

of happiness
interests are

and the

amount

of
to

misery to
do.
it
'

all

affected I

know what
evil.

This no

dogma about freedom


all
it is

will ever tell me.


is

I hear

loudly proclaimed that


so,

government
is

I answer
still.'

undoubtedly

but anarchy

a greater evil
is

am

told that the institution of property

a cruel injustice.

I reply that this depends


subsistence, abundance,

upon whether
security.

it

tends to promote

and
all

It

may

probably be
it

answered that
to

it

promotes

these to some extent, but that

some extent defeats them.

But does

it

on the whole pro?

mote them, more than


to be looked into,

its abolition

would do

This requires

and every one of the rights of property


this test.

requires to

be examined by

If the changes proposed


arise.

be examined by the same

test,

no harm can

Some men

may come
mankind
happier.
it

out of the process richer and others poorer, but

at large will be at least as happy,

and probably

At any

rate

we may be
They

sure that, whether

we

like

or no, all the rights of property will presently be tried


test or other.

by some

are being so tried now.

In this
is

I agree with Lassalle,

who

asserts, truly

enough, that this


is

the great social question of the age.


question which
lies at

This (as he says)


all

the

the bottom of

other questions, and

which the moment


the pulse beat
'-

it is

touched makes the chest heave and

This excitement will certainly lead to blood'

' Preface, Was ist es, das den innersten Grund unserer politi. p. vii. schen und socialen Kampfe bildet ? Der Begriff des erworbeuen Eechts


Sec. 57.]

GENERAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.

35

that to do right

we go about telling people that all law is immoral^ and we have only to see that we realise the will of the individual. On the other handj we may just escape bloodshed if we can induce people to reckon up
shed
if

what

will
:

be the probable gain or


if

loss

of

any proposed

change

especially

we can

get

them

also to

remember
worth

that every violent change involves a great risk of security,

and that without security nothing


having.
57. If instead of saying that

in the world

is

we ought not
all,

to take utility Legisla-

as our guide in legislation,

it

were said that

with

utility for its guide,

is,

after

even fgg^ie inbut a feeble instrument strament


legislation,
ness.

of happiness, I should be
it,

however, that this

is

much more inclined to agree. I take not because we have chosen the wrong

principle to guide us in legislation, but because legislation

can never under any circimistances be a potent instrument


for happiness.

Nearly

all

that the lawgiver can do


for

is

to

remove impediments to people procuring happiness


selves
j

themin

and to secure them from being disturbed


it.

the

enjoyment of
necessaries of

Even

as regards procuring for persons the


is

life,

the best the law can do


If this

to secure

them the
itself

fruits of their labour.

is insuflScient,

the law can only

supply the deficiency by doing (as


that
is,

it

were) violence to

by

seizing the property of one

wants of another.

Security

is

the main,

it

man to satisfy the may almost be said


foster

the sole object of the law.

But

here again the action of the

law

is

almost wholly negative.

The law can only


it.

security

by punishing
is

or redressing invasions of

More-

over not only

the action of the law thus limited, but the


protecting security necessarily involves

very process
a

itself of

sacrifice of security.

In whatever way security

is

protected,

whether by

courts of justice, or

by an armed

force, or
it

by a

police, the process is


ist

an expensive one, rendering


geworden.
TJnd dieser Streit
tief

necessary
der das
this is

wieder einmal

streitig

ist eg,

Herz der heutigen Welt durchzittert und die


becoming truer every day.

inwendigste Grundlage

der politisoh-socialen Kampfe des Jahrhunderts bildet.'

And

D 3


36

GENERAL CONCEPTION OE LAW.


;

[Chap.

I.

to impose taxes

and every tax

is

more
still

or less a sacrifice of
sacrifice,

security fore a

a small one no doubt, but


if

and there-

remedy which,
^.

applied on too large a scale, would

fail in its effect

58.

The same
it

truth

may
is

be put in another form by saying

that the value of law

to be

measured not by the happiness


it

which
us.

procures, but
it is

by the misery from which


inflict in

preserves

And

also unfortunately true that besides the

misery

which governments are compelled to

the

way

of

punishment and coercion in order to prevent mischief, they


inflict

untold misery for their


as

must remember that, ment ever known is


at
all.

own Bentham

selfish purposes.

Yet we

says, the worst govern-

infinitely better

than no government

Without government one half of the world would


This,

be robbing and murdering the other half.


the loj'alty or affection which
really strong

and not
is

we owe

to our rulers,

the

argument against

revolution.

Over and over

again governments

fear it

must be

said all governments

are guilty of iniquities

which would fully justify their exstill

pulsion from power;

but the question must always

be
?

asked

Can the existing government be replaced by a better


be replaced at
all ?

Can
Law
<

it

The righteousness

of a cause

is

never alone a sufficient justification of rebellion.


59.
neither
increase

We

shall, therefore,

look for happiness in the


to be
is

direction, if

we

expect

it

conferred

wrong upon us by the


law to

nor dis^^* ^^^tribute


it

Moreover, not only

it
:

impossible for the


it is

increase the stock of happiness

just as impossible for


it.

the law to ensure an equal distribution of

Equality
it.

be hindered by the law,

it

cannot be promoted by

may Any

attempt to promote

it

by taking from one man and giving


it is

to another could only end in destroying wholesale the sources

of happiness.

But though

impossible that

men

should

These somewhat trite, hut still useful, observations on the objects of law are set forth in the Traits de Legislation ' published by Dumont from the original MSS. of Bentham. They may be read (and they deserve reading) either in Hildreth's translation of Dumont's work, or in Bentham's collected works, vol. i. pp. 301-322.
'

Sec. 58, 59.J

GENERAL CONCEPTION OF LAW.

37

ever be

made

equal in the sense of eacb obtaining an equal


it
is

share of happiness,
tarians that all

still

a cardinal assumption of

utili-

men
it,

are equal

in the sense that in esti:

mating happiness one counts for one and no more


as I understand
to

that

is,

that no person whatever has a right

say that he has a better claim to consideration than


If the

another.
all

law could,

it

would make the happiness of


is

one

men man
it

exactly equal.

If this

not attempted,

if

when

has appropriated to himself a larger share of the

sources of happiness than his neighbours, the law protects

him,
or,

is

because this protection

is

for the benefit of all:


it

which comes to the same thing, because to withdraw


all.

would injure
extent ought
dividuals.

For no other reason and to no greater


to maintain the unequal condition of in-

we

CHAPTER

II.

SOURCES OF LAW.
What
^"'^'-

is

60. There are several inquiries which have been prosecuted

l!lf,tl?l^^

under this head, and some writers have thrown themselves and their readers into inextricable confusion, by pursuing

more than one


I

of these at the

same time, without noticing

the distinction between them.

am

not

now about

to inquire

whence

it is

that rules of
already-

conduct acquire the binding force of law

that I have
why
make laws
;

made Nor am

to depend on the will of the sovereign authority.

I about to inquire

how

or

the sovereign
that, as

authority came to have the power to


far as I think necessary,
is

also discussed in the previous

chapter.

if

What I mean now to inquire into is simply this where, a man wants to get at the law, he must go to look for it ^.
:

The primis

61.

The primary and most

direct source, and,


is

where

it

is

declared to

be found, the exclusive source of law,


will of the sovereign authority.
its will

the expressly the sovereign


is

w'remV^ declared

When

authority declares
legislate;

in the

form

of a law, it

said to

and

this function of sovereignty is called legisla-

tion
'

the body which deliberates on the form and substance


still

room for much indefiniteness mean by it, as will appear from the text (sect. 99), something stricter than mere literature I do not pretend, however, that it would be possible to draw an exact distinction between literatura and auctoritas. Lawyers fi'equently fortify their conclusions by references to opinions which are not, in a forensic sense,

Even with these limitations there is

in the term 'sources of law.'

We

generally

authoritative.

SOURCES OF LAW.
of such laws before
legislature
legislature.
;

39
is

they

are
so

promulgated

called

the

and the laws

made

are called acts of the

62. It has already been remarked that legislation, like or sub-

any other function


subordinate person

of sovereignty, or

may

be delegated to a

legisla*''^'

body
is

of persons.

In

this

case

the

subordinate legislature
authority,

the mouthpiece of the sovereign


legislature

and the declarations of the subordinate

derive their binding force from the will of tbe sovereign


authority, just as

much

as if they
itself.

had been framed and issued

by the sovereign

authority

63. All the colonies of

England present examples


so great

of this Suboi-dii^tioii*in^'

delegation of legislative power, but nowhere have subordinate


legislative authorities

been multiplied to

an extent

'"'^'^ ^""^
ies.

as in India.

Thus

in the province of

Lower Bengal alone


each possessing
is

there are four distinct bodies or persons,

a very extensive legislative authority.


British

There

first
;

the

King and

Parliament, the supreme authority

then

the General Legislative Council; next the Governor-General

himself; and lastly the Council of the Lieutenant-Governor


of Bengal.

This example of subordinate legislation illustrates

not only the extent and importance of the function, but also
the evils which
tion
is

may

attend

it.

Where

the power of legisla^


it
is
is

conferred on such a variety of persons

certain

that there will

be confusion of laws, and there


all
evils,

also great

danger of the worst of

namely, of doubts being

raised as to whether the legislative authority of

some

of the

subordinate bodies has not been exceeded.


sovereign authority
of
its
is

For the supreme

always obliged to allow the authority

subordinates to be questioned, in some form or other,


courts of law, in order to keep a check on their usurpa-

by the

tion of power;

though sometimes

it

resorts to that highly

unsatisfactory expedient for getting out of the difficulty

an
^^^'
l^f^^_

ex post facto ratification of acts which are admittedly illegal.


64. It
is

may

also be desirable here to notice that sovereignty Methods

delegated upon two distinct principles in the dependencies

40
of England.

SOURCES OF LAW.

[Chap.

11.

In India the Governor-General and Legislative

Council constitute together a legislature whose functions are


expressly limited in several directions^ and whose action
expressly
is

made
it

subject to the control of the British Parliais

ment, which,

obviously contemplated, will in no wise

discontinue the habit of occasionally

making laws
legislative

for India,

On

the other hand, most of the colonies possess constitutions


their

which confer upon


together with the

respective

assemblies,

King

of

England (usually represented by


the ordinary funcitself.

a Governor), legislative authority of the most general kind,

and which obviously contemplate that


tions of legislation will be carried

all

on within the colony


still

But

colonies possessing such constitutions are

subject to

the same sovereign body as ourselves, the

King and the two

Houses of Parliament.

The power
is

of the British Parliament

over a colony, though dormant,

not extinguished by the

grant of such a constitution as I have described.


is

There

amply

suflScient

in the Acts of Parliament

which grant

colonial constitutions to

make
i.

the very acceptance of them

a
Indirect
t

mark

of subordination

65. Legislative functions are also exercised,

not only by

ions of

bodies expressly constituted for that purpose,

and under the

aifthoritT

^^^^
power

f legislation, but
to

by

bodies of persons

who have

the

frame rules for the protection or convenience of the

inhabitants of certain localities.

Thus
to

in large

and populous

towns we frequently find a body called by the name of a


municipality,
called,

which has power

make

bye-laws, as they are

for regulating the conduct of

the inhabitants, and

even to impose taxes.

So the Privy Council, and Boards

of Health, and of Education, frame rules for special objects


See the 15 and 16 Vict. chap.
iii.

'

Ixxii.

(New

Zealand),
all

and the 30 and 31

Vict. chap.

(British North America).

In

these acts the supreme

sovereignty of England
referred to as if
it

is, in accordance with traditional usage, studiouslywere vested in the Crown alone. But of course no one can doubt that the King and the Colonial Parliament are technically subordinate to the King and the English Parliament. See Parliamentary Government in the British Colonies, by Alpheus Todd, pp. 34, 168, 188, 192.

Sec. 65-68.]

SOURCES OF LAW.
are

41

intiTisted

to them, whicli

some of them laws in the


of

proper sense of the word.


rules

So too Courts

Law

issue general

of

procedure in matters of litigation which are also


legislation has been expressly

law.

In these cases the power of

conferred.

legislation to

The sovereign body can always delegate its function of any extent it pleases ; it being wholly uncontrolled not only in the matter, but in the manner of legislation.
66.

Subordilatures"

^^1*^

In other words, the sovereign body not only

exercises the

legislative function, but is the author of it also.

But a subordinate legislature, not being the author of its own functions, and having no control over the manner of legislation,
can only delegate
ised to do so.
its

functions so far as

it

has been author-

General legislative powers, such, for example,

as are possessed

by the Legislative Council

in India,

would
the

undoubtedly carry with them some powers of delegation,

which should, however, be very carefully exercised


bounds of authority be exceeded.

lest

67. I have mentioned legislation as the primary source of

law because
say, the

it

is

the most direct, the simplest, and, so to

supreme source of law.

But

active legislation

is

a characteristic of advanced
stages of civilisation there

societies

only.
:

In the

earlier

is little

legislation

in the earliest,

none

^.

68.

The

sources of law other than legislation are complex Sources


to

of

and

difficult

understand ;

and without a glance

at the tiian legisg^pj^^j^g^

general history of the development of law I do not think I

could

make what

I have to say as to the sources of law intel- by the


therefore,

ligible.

Without attempting,

anytmng approachmg

history of law.

to a complete historical discussion, I propose to give a short

sketch of the general development of law, adverting after-

wards to certain

peculiarities

of

its

development in some

countries of Europe
'

and

of Asia.

I hope in this

way

to be

In India there

legislation:
is

is a whole field of law which has never been touched by and in all Mahommedan countries the action of the legislature

greatly restricted.

42
able to throw a

SOURCES OF LAW.
little

[Chap. II.

light

upon some obscure questions in the

history of the sources of English law.


Early
ance of
codes.

69. Early in the history of most ancient systems of


find something in the nature of a code, using that

law we

term with

some

latitude to express

any

collection of written laws

more

or less complete

and formal.

Such a code was the Mosaic


of

law, the law of the Twelve Tables, the so-called laws

Manu, the laws

of Solon,

and the Koran.


is

How early
loped.

70.

code once

made

the basis of

all

future progress,

The future

history of law

is

the history of the modes

by which
no more

the provisions of the code are extended and modified in order to

meet the growing wants

of the

community. There

is

interesting study in the history of law than that of the

modes

by which
Notgenerlegisla-

this modification
is

and extension have been

effected.

71.

A code
is

always an
is

effort of legislation, yet the early

preparation of a code

not by any means a sign that the

nation

capable of a continued effort of legislative activity.

In Rome, in the centuries which immediately followed the


introduction of the code of the Twelve Tables, there
little

was very

legislation;

in

Eastern nations continued legislative

activity has never been developed at all; in


it

Western nations

has never been able to satisfy the requirements of a pro-

gressive people.

Other means of modifying and extending

the law have had to be devised, and one of the most potent

instruments which have been used for this purpose

is

that

which
Interpre-

is
1

called interpretation.

explained
jjy

which would produce neither extension nor modification of the law. Given the rule of law, the only question which, strictly speak72.

Strictly speaking, interpretation is a process

ing, interpretation has to solve


rule prescribe?

is

what

conduct does the

There are three elements into which this

inquiry

may

be analysed

the
First,

grammatical, the logical, and

the historical element.


'

we may

consider the words

See and compare what

is said

Savigny, System d. h. rom. Eeehts, Bk. many of my observations are taken.

on the subject of interpretation in i. ch. 4, ss. 32 sqq., from which

Sec. 69-75.]

SOURCES OF LAW.
them according
this is the

43

used^ and take

to their ordinary

meaning and
con-

construction

grammatical

element in the process.


its

Then we may
textj

consider each portion of the rule with


relation in

and observe the

which the
is

several portions

of the rule stand to each other: this

the logical element.

Lastly^
rule

we may

consider the condition of the law


defect or error
it

when the

was introduced^ and what


:

was proposed
and

to

remedy

this is the historical element.

73. Closely

connected with the

historical
it,

element,

searcelyj I think, distinguishable

from

is

the ratio legis

as

an instrument of interpretation.

But caution must be


mistaken
especially

exercised in referring to the ratio legis as an instrument of


interpretation, as it

may

easily be

we

must be careful not to confound the true ratio legis with the
mere accident which may have
74.
led to its introduction
^-

The grammatical

interpretation of a rule of law


it.

may
it

leave no doubt as to the meaning of

But, on the other

hand, a rule of law

may on
;

a grammatical consideration of

present several meanings


historical

and neither the


it

logical nor the

consideration of

may

indicate

with certainty
it

which of these meanings is the correct one. Or happen that the grammatical consideration of a rule
consideration of

may
law

of

suggests one meaning, whilst the logical, or the historical


it

suggests another.

In a case of

conflict

the grammatical meaning generally prevails, but not always.

The

plain grammatical

and

logical

meaning

of the act of

Elizabeth relating to leases by

ecclesiastical corporations has


legis.

always been restricted by the ratio


75.

When

the grammatical consideration supplies several Interrep-

meanings, and neither the logical nor the historical considera- ^ged to tion determines with certainty which is the true meaning,
Savigny gives the example of the Senatusconsultum Maeedonianxim which was passed in consequence of the murder of his father by one Maoedo, who was pressed for money to satisfy Mis creditors (Gliick, Pandekten, vol. xiv. p. 306). So the maiming act (22 and 23 Charles II, chap, i) was passed (as appears from the act itself) on the occasion of the cutting off Sir John Coventry's nose.
'

l^^^

44
where the then
dcmbtfuf.'^

SOURCES OF LAW.
we
resort to other considerations.

[Chap.

11.

If the rule of law


is,

is

looked on with favour


to bring

we

interpret it liberally, that


cases as possible
it
;

so as

under

it

as

many

if it is
is,

looked on
so

with disfavour, we interpret

strictly,

that

that

it

may embrace
76.

as few eases as possible.

So far we have been considering interpretation proper.


to have before

But suppose the judge


to

him one

of those eases
is

which I have already alluded, for which there


precisely suitable.
Still

no mle of

law

the judge must decide the case,

and being

desirous, as judges generally are desirous, not to

rest the case

upon

his

own

arbitrium, he will naturally try to

get more out of the existing rules of law than can be obtained

by the regular process of


discover

interpretation.
is

He

will try

and

from what actually

said

what probably would


one

have been said had a larger

class of cases, including the

before him; been within the contemplation of the framers of

the rule.

This attempt on the part of the judge

is

not due to

any assumption of authority, but rather


authority of others.
chiefly to those It
is

to a respect for the


it is

a logical process and

applicable

new

relations
it is

which have arisen since the rule


sometimes expressed,

was made, and which


within
its

impossible, therefore, to say are process


is

provisions.

The

and

in a

manner
is

justified,
is

by saying
its

that the case to which


equity.

the rule

extended

within

This equitable

extension of a rule involves, of course, the process of interpretation,

and the judge assumes

it as

certain that

he

is

acting

in conformity

with the declared will of the legislator in his


Still,

application of the rule.

put
is,

it

how you

will, it is

more

than mere interpretation.

It

to

some extent, an

applica-

tion of the principle of analogy.


Extension
77. It
is

by

by analogy.

this use of his judicial discretion, in cases

where

^ doubt leaves

him a

discretion, that a

judge manages to make

a rule of law cover more ground than was intended;

and
its

sometimes, but more rarely, by a reverse process, he narrows


application.

There are indeed cases of bolder extension

still

which one

hesitates to class under extension

by

interpretation.

Sec. 76-78.]

SOURCES Or LAW.

45

and which perhaps ought


tension
scarcely pretend that he
of the legislator, yet,
it

to be classed apart as cases of ex-

by analogy. Even though the judge


is still

in such cases can

carrying out the declared will

having no other rule to go by, he thinks

safe to extend a rule

which he has learned from experience


will put it in this way.

to be a salutary one.

Or perhaps he

He

will

say that the rule

may

be taken to be a single
it

example of the application of a wider principle which


involves,

and

so he will justify the application of the principle

to cases not specially provided for.

78. of

Thus
law.

it is

that so-called interpretation becomes a source Dislike of

new
it

The authors

upon

with disfavour,
all

modern codes generally look as did the Emperor Justinian. They


of

to judge"^^*^ ^^^''

wish to stop
tion,

extension of the law except by direct legisla-

and

to bind

down the judges by


by future

inflexible rules,

proposing

to

make

provision

legislation for all unforeseen

cases as they arise.

But an

active legislature

is

not even which

is,

now

popular

nor do legislative assemblies deal by any means generally


Judicial legislation, on

successfully with matters of detail.

the other hand,

is

generally popular, and I have very great

and^s'u^cessful.

doubt whether the extension of the law by judicial interpretation


^

is

so great

an

evil as

has been alleged ^.

Justinian forbad

tion,

all attempts to extend the law by way of interpretaincluding in the prohibition commentaries as well as judicial

decisions.
nisi

'Nemo .... audeat commentaries isdem


si velit

legibus adnectere,

Graecam vocem transformare sub eodem ordine alias eaque consequentia sub qua voces Romanae positae sunt autem legum iuterpretationes, immo magis perrersiones eos jactare non
tantum
eas in
: .

Si quid vero ut supra dictum est ambiguum fuerit concedimus visum hoc ad imperiale culmen per judices referatur et ex auctoritate Augusta manifestetur, cui soli concessum eat leges et condere et interpretari.' Co. Just. i. 17. 2. 21. The French legislature has taken a middle course. Art. 5 of the Code Civil (quoted above, a. 26, n.) prevents the ordinary judicial interpretation from becoming authoritative. But by a law of 27 VentSse, An viii, art. 88, Si le commissaire du gouvernement apprend qu'il ait 6ti rendu en dernier ressort un jugement contraire aux iois ou aux formes de proofider, ou dans lequel un juge ait exc6d6 ses pouvoirs, et centre lequel cependant auoune des parties n'ait r6clam6 dans
'

le d^lai fix6, aprfes ce dSlai expire,

il

de cassation ; et

si les

formes ou

les Iois

en donnera oonnaissance au tribunal ont iti viol^es, le jugement sera

46
Custom
dent
''^^^

SOURCES OF LAW.
79.

[Chap.
is

IT.

Of the

several processes

by

whicli law

extended the
writers say

to

lext which I shall consider


that a custom

is

custom.

Some
its

may

exist as law independently of the will

of the sovereign authority, and they derive

obligatory force

from the consensus utentium,


national will, or

modern phrase, from the But the growth of national conviction.


or, in

custom into law seems to


period

me
of

rather to be a survival of the

when

disputes

were generally settled by tribunals

without law.

The growth
itself in

custom into law


society.

is

analogous to
first

the growth of law


is

an infant

At

there

no conception of law proceeding from a


If a dispute
is

distinct author, but

only of commands.

decided

by

authority, the
inspiration.

decision is supposed to

come from some divine


first

Such commands were issued at

by an

aristocracy,

which was in

by the king and then the West political, and in


a
village,

the East religious.

Where we

find the heads of

or the lord of the soil, exercising a sort of rude jurisdiction,

these tribunals would naturally tend to base their decisions

upon custom, that


becomes law by

is,

upon the habits

of those

with

whom

the judges were best acquainted within their


It
is

own

jurisdiction.

however scarcely too much to say that every such

authority, if allowed to continue, in time transforms itself, or is being re corded and transformed, into a court, and treating its traditional customs i > ^
obserred.

as binding rules, brings into existence a

body

of law.

law

so generated is called custom.

I do not, of course,

The mean

by this that all custom necessarily originates within a tribunal. But the members of the tribunals would know the customs
better than their fellows;

they would give

effect to

them,

and would ensure


cass6, sans

their permanence, first,

by a

precise oral

de la cassation pour 61uder de ce jugement, lequel vaudra transaction pour elles.' This interpretation would, I understand, be authoritative notwithstanding the provisions of Art. 5 of the Code Civil. So also (I understand) would
les dispositions

que

les parties puissant se prevaloir

be a decision of the Court of Cassation given a second time on a second appeal between the same parties. See Dalloz, E6pertoire, s. v. Lois, In England all judicial interpretation by the superior courts ss. 458 sqq.
is

authoritative, because all their decisions are authoritative.

Sec. 79-8I.J

SOURCES OF LAW.

47

tradition^

and afterwards by a written record ^.

Customs are

suggested by the habits of the people, but they axe preserved,


strengthened, and given effect to by the practice of the
courts.

80. Nothing more

is

necessary for the grovrth of a custom

than that people should have some tradition of what their


fathers did before them, that they should repeat the

same

conduct on similar occasions, and that they should be convinced that what
is

so

done

is

right.

And

no external force
of

is

needed for the growth of custom.

The tendency
is

men

to

allow their conduct to be ruled by custom

always strong

and those whose duty


especially ready to fall

it is

to arbitrate in disputes, are always

back upon custom, whereby they reduce

their

own

responsibility

and are almost sure to gain the


custom

applause of their neighbours.


81.

The operation

of

and

of

interpretation in Various

modifying the law depends upon a variety of circumstances,

The reduction
to check the

of custom of rules of law into writing has a tendency andmter '

pretation.

growth

of

custom

but interpretation^ which


is itself

is

always ready to act upon the written law,

acted upon

by custom;
'

it

being the practice of judges to accept the

usual ^ interpretation of a law as the true one.


It also

makes a very great

difference

whether the manipu-

lation of these processes remains in the hands of unprofessional

persons, or falls into those of trained lawyers.

In the ordinary

Influence

course of national progress^ as soon as the usual division of

labour takes place^ the latter event will happen.

But the

lawyers must always in the main exert their influence not by


separating themselves from the current ideas of the community mainly a
to

which they belong, but by representing those

ideas,

and

one.

' The old village coxirts (SchOffengerichte) mentioned by Savigny no doubt based their decisions entirely upon customs, though the practice of drawing up records of their decisions (Weisthiimer) probably gave a decided preponderance to the judicial over the popular element. The tendency to substitute written rules for oral tradition appears everywhere in the West, even in lay tribunals. In the East the tendency towards the production of written laws is not so marked.

48

SOURCES OF LAW.
The lawyer

[Chap. TI.
class does

putting them into legal shape.

not
first

come

into

existence suddenly.

Lawyers are generally

found giving advice only^ either in cases of dispute, or as to


the performance of the proper solemnities in legal transactions.

From
still

this

they generally proceed to draw up formularies or


it is

guides for the transaction of business; and

only later

that they venture to deal with law theoretically, either

in written treatises or

by

oral teaching.

Gradually also under

their influence the decisions of the courts

assume a

different

tone

from being mere dry adjudications of the matter in

dispute they

come

to be reasoned out,

and acquire a more or

less

scientific character.

tradition also of a special legal kind,

apart from ordinary custom, grows up about the courts which


largely influences the decisions of the judge.
It
is

when law
arti-

has arrived at this stage that interpretation becomes most


ficial,

and

serves, perhaps, only to veil the process of innovation.


it

Unchecked by public opinion


under this restraint
it

would be

intolerable,

but

produces useful results.

For

it

must

never be forgotten that, whether the law be interpreted so as


to cover

an increasing area of

cases, or
it is

whether customary

rules be imported into the law,

never a mere arbitrary

modification or extension of the law which thus takes place,

but a formulating of the popular ideas by a skilled

class.

On

the other hand, without the skill of the lawyer society would
scarcely

ally supposed

make any advance at all. by those who have


it is

Contrary to what

is

gener-

paid no particular attention the lawyers

to the development of law,


ally

who have

gener-

made

the

first

advaiice

by breaking through the

stiffness

of early forms

and the

rigidity of ancient rules.

Lawyers

have been frequently attacked as being too technical, just as they have been frequently attacked for the assumption of unauthorised power: and doubtless, at different times, they

have been made justly

liable on both charges. But the general observation remains true, that large and beneficial

reforms in the law have been


could have been

made by

lawyers, and very few

made without them.

This could hardly be

Sec. 82.]

SOURCES OF LAW.
The law may correspond
;

49

otherwise.

to the legal culture of

those

of law Developmore particularly by a glance at the development of law in Roman ^^^' cei-tain countries of the ancient and modern world; I shall
refer to the influences

82. I will

who produce it it cannot go beyond it. now endeavour to illustrate the growth

which have operated upon the law of

Rome, upon the Hindoo law, upon the Mahommedan law, upon the law of continental Europe, and upon the English
law.

Beginning with the law of


which

Rome we

find that the early

law was gathered up, as early


Christ, into a code
is

as the fourth century before as the

known

Twelve Tablesi

From

that time forward the legislative powet was always at

hand, but nevertheless the most important modifications of

Roman law

were brought about by other influences.

Taking
jurists

the law of the Twelve Tables as their text the


busied themselves about
its

Roman

interpretation,

and with much

dexterity developed from this rude code rules of law suitable


to the

growing wants and complicated


Still

relations of a thriving

and active community.


affected
is

more largely was the Roman law


called equity.

by an

influence

which has been

This
influ-

a term which has been used to describe a great

many

ences which have some similarity to each other, but are not
identical^

To a

great extent equity^ as administered at

Rome

through the

prsetor's edict,
it

was custom

of a very general kind

The
as
is

source from which

was, in a great measure^ derived was,


'

well known, the

'

jus gentium,'' or

jus
'

gentium,'* subsequently identified with the


practical result

commune omnium jus naturae.' The

was that forms which had become too cumbrous


;

for use were dispensed with

principles

which had been found

too narrow Were expanded; and laws which had become unsuitable were ignored.

Custom

also, in

the narrower sense

of the practice prevailing at


section

Rome

in the

whole or in some

of

the community, was constantly being imported


of

into the law, but always through the hands


jurisconsult,

a skilled

or

of

a prsetor who, though not necessarily

himself a lawyer, was completely under the lawyer's in-

50
fluence.

SOURCES OF LAW.
The
issue of the edict

[Chap. IT.

by the

prsetor

was a process

more

like

legislation than a creation of


it

law by a modern

English judgCj in that

announced beforehand in an abstract

form the

rule

which would be applied.


prsetor
is

But a
it.

rule so issued

was only binding on the method of creating law

who

issued

This curious

almost unintelligible unless

we
to

remember that the


was supreme
decide
;

praetor, as representing

the sovereign power^

as to the matters

which

it

actually fell to

him

and that he was exercising

this

supreme power under

the important restriction that

all his

proceedings were watched

by competent and jealous

critics.

Practically, therefore^ each

prsetor followed in the footsteps of his predecessors^ adopting

only such well-considered changes as were pretty sure to be


acceptable.
Develop-

83.

Turning to the Hindoo law^ we do not find any

ment
of the

distinct epoch

when

it

was

first

reduced into a written form,

Hindoo
law.

but we have a number of so-called codes, of which the code


of

Manu

is

the best

known and most


aspect;

influential.

These

codes are the written basis of all subsequent

Hindoo law.
religious
as

They have a double


legal.

being as

much

Antiquity of the

It

is

doubtful whether any of

these codes, though they

Hindoo
L-odes.

now

bear the

name

of an individual, are the product of a


It
is

single

hand; or even of a single age.

more probable

that they represent ancient texts in a more or less modified

form.

The form

in

which they now

exist is said to indicate

a comparatively modern date, but this seems to


material, because there
is

me

not very

internal evidence that in substance

they belong to a very early stage of society.


the so-called code of

For example,

in

Manu we
conflict

do not find the ownership of


it

land at

all dealt

with, undoubtedly because


of

was not yet

known.

So too the
of the family

rights

between individual

members

Nor had

the

widow

as she appears to

had scarcely yet attracted legal notice. asserted any independent rights. So far have had any rights at all, it was as head
which looks
like

of the household after her husband's death,

Sec. 83.J

SOUECBS OF LA.W.
1.

51

a survival of polyandry

Whenever,
it is

therefore, this code

may

have assumed

its

present form^

certain that its matter

belongs to a very early period 2.


venerated as
it still is,

But the code


as it
is^

of

Manu^

and antiquated

has not placed


Fortunately

an insuperable barrier in the way of advance.


the code
itself

contains

a recognition of the influence of


it

custom, and so far from discountenancing this influence


expressly

encourages
revealed

it.

'

The

king,'

says

Manu,

'

who
and
Brahminence upon ^^'

knows the

law [ought] to inquire into the parand the


rules of certain families^
^.'

ticular usages of trades

to establish their particular laws

The Hindoos themselves


use of this latitude^ and
tlon largely developed the

did not fail to recognise and

make

by means of custom and interpretaHindoo law. These processes were


Brahmins,

for a long time chiefly in the hands of learned

who were
oflScial

neither skilled lawyers^ nor priests, nor a simple


Stili,

aristocracy, but something of all three*.

having no

position their real claim to influence depended

upon

their personal qualifications,

and

chiefly

upon

their learning.

The formal

process

which they adopted was that of writing

commentaries on the older written law.

But

these

com-

mentaries, though mostly couched in the language of interpretation, are to a large extent occupied in engrafting
'

new
seems
it

'

Manu, chap. ix. sect. 104. See also chap. viii. sect. 416. The date of the code even in the form in which we possess
still

it

to

be

unsettled

but the statement in the text that in substance

belongs to an early stage of society is, I think, incontroyertible. Like the Twelve Tables, it may have been considered a carmen necessarium long
it had been largely supplemented by custom and interpretation. Manu, eh. viii. sect. 41, 'if,' adds a commentator, 'they be not repugnant to the law^ of God.' But the original author did not think this

after
'

precaution necessary.
* There is some analogy between the position of learned Brahmins and the Pontifices at Rome. I do not observe that the Brahmins, like the ecclesiastical lawyers of Europe, have endeavoured to use their influence This accusation has been brought for promoting the interests of a class.

any evidence of it. The learned Brahmins who wrote the great commentaries mixed, I imagine, very little directly in the management of human affairs, and they seem to have been animated by a very lofty spirit. E 2
against them, but I have not seen

52

SOURCES or LAW.
rules,

[Chap. II.

customs upon the old


apologies

and in pointing out (with manyfor the degeneracy o the times

by the authors
of

in which they wrote) the rules

which had become


solely

obsolete.

The value

these commentaries depends

upon the

reputation of the persons


like the Institutes of

by

whom

they were compiled ; but,

mere

literature.

Lord Coke^ they are authority and not The Hindoo law is now administered by

British courts of justice in which the judges are partly native

and partly European.


of law

Under

their influence the development

by

interpretation

and by the recognition of custom has


it

been actively continued, and

has been accelerated by a third

process which I shall explain presently, the creation of law


judicial decision Develop^-

by

ment

84.

The Mahommedan law

rests

also

on a written
is

basis,

of

the Ma-

the Koran, which, like the Hindoo Shasters,

divine, but,

dan law.

^^ing comparatively modern, bears


the ordinary affairs of
life.

much more
is

directly

upon
same

There
there

not, therefore, the

room

for development, and

is

no admission in the

text of the

Koran
its

of the necessity or the propriety of

any

modification of

precepts.

Even

in Europe,

where

Mahom-

medans have become familiar with the


imperial legislation of

exercise of legislative

functions both in the modern form, and in the form of the

Rome, they have

rarely ventured

upon

a development of their law by this direct process.

In a few

instances, as, for example, the acceptance of interest for a loan,

the precepts

of the

Koran have been departed from, but

every judge professing to administer


every ruler professing to be guided by

Mahommedan

law, and

its principles, is

loaded

with
'

fetters.

The Mahommedans have made


in India,

scarcely

any

The British courts been accused by some


little,

and

especially the

of paying too

European judges, have much, and by others of paying too

attention to the commentators. As a matter of fact the courts in India have innovated very largely, and it is not a little remarkable that modern Hindoos, who Will not tolerate any interference with their law
legislature,

have always accepted with deference the decisions of our to popular feeling. This is especially so with the decisions of the Privy Council, but all the High courts have from the first been liked and respected by Hindoos.
tribunals even

by a

when they have been counter

Sec. 84-86.]

SOURCES OF LAW.

53

attempt to free themselves from this thraldom.


to be paralysed

They seem
would

by a

sort of superstitious feeling that it

be irreligious to doubt that the word of the Prophet was


sufficient

for the

wants of mankind even twelve centuries

after it

was spoken.
no
remained

certain

amount

of the old

Arabian
has

custom was,
always
nised
^
;

doubt, assumed by
in
force,

Mahommed, and
not
expressly

though
or

recog-

and

at

some time

other

the

Mahommedan

lawyers seem to have come temporarily under the influence


of the Latin

jurisprudence to their very great advantage.

Traces of this influence

may be

easily

discovered

in the

great commentary of Khalil Ibn Ishak translated into French

by M. Perron, and a commentary much used


the Hedaya.
85. I

in India called

now

pass on to the development of law in

modern

Dovelop-

j^^ ^^ the great nations founded on the continent of Western o<iein " Europe. Europe after the fall of the Roman Empire have constructed
of
.

Europe, where

we come upon an

entirely

new

phase.

None

an independent legal system of


Austria,

their

own.

France, Italy, General

Germany, Holland, and Spain have every one of of Eoman them adopted the Eoman law as their general or common ''^^"
law, and have only departed from
occasions
it

so far
filled

as

particular
special

might

require.

Every gap not

up by

legislation, or specially recognised custom, has

been supplied
to a very

from the

Roman

law, and even their

modern codes

large extent only contain the ideas of the Corpus Juris in

a nineteenth-century dress.
86.

The

history of the process

by which the Roman law


to here with ex-

History of

became the common law of the Western portion of

the cess^"'

European continent can only be referred


*

The male agnates

(asabah,

whom we

incorrectly call residuariea) are


;

yet they occupy an unnot mentioned, even casually, in the Koran doubted and important position as heirs. The old Arabian law of inheri-

tance gave them, no doubt, the entire inheritance, and this rule was modified by Mahommed, who directs the setting apart of certain shares
before the division amongst the residuaries takes place
786.

See post,

sect.

54

SOURCES OF LAW,
its

[Chap. II. It commences^

treme brevity and in


of course,

broadest features^.

when the Goths,


to

the Burgundians, the Franks,

and the Lombards began


ruins of

found new kingdoms upon the

the

Roman

Empire.

In none of these were the

Roman
side

citizens deprived of the

enjoyment of their own laws.

The conquering
by
side each

invaders and the conquered inhabitants lived

under their own system, just as the natives

of India

and Europeans do at the present day^; and when

the

German races began to conquer each other, especially when several of them were united by Charlemagne under
Empire, the

one

same

forbearance was

exercised.

Each

person retained the law indicated by his birth, so that

you

could find side

by

side not only

two systems, a

Roman and

a barbarian, but several systems, a

Roman, a Gothic, a BurIt


is

gundian, a Lombardic, and so forth.

the conflict of

laws thus produced to which Bishop Agobardus refers in


his letter to

Louis
five

le

Debonaire when he says,

'

it

often

happens that

men

each governed by different laws,


^.'

may
took

be found sitting or walking together


87.
'

At

this period

law was personal

that

is,

man

It will be

found

at length in Savigny's Gesdiichte dea

rom. Kechts

im

Mittelalter, the first

volume of which has been translated by Cathcart

(Edinburgh, 1829).
' The parallel often drawn between the relative position of the German conquerors and the conquered inhabitants of Europe, and that of the English and natives in India, is in some points a striking one, but there is this capital distinction, that in one case the conquered, in the other the conquering, race are the higher in civilisation. ^ Savigny, Gesch. d. 1. E. im Mittelalter, vol. i. The notion that 30. every one had a free choice (liberum arbitrium) as to the law by which he would be governed has been exploded by Savigny. The law of a man was determined by hia descent. So was that of a single woman and

widows.

could choose between the law of her father The Clergy were governed by the Roman law. Bastards had the right of choosing their law and in private transactions the parties could agree as to the law which was to govern the transaction. Just in the same way in India, until recently, a party used frequently to be brought into 1 transaction as (what was called) 'jurisdiction trustee'

married

woman

and that

of her husband.

in order to ensure, in case of dispute, the case being tried before the Supreme Court according to English law. See also Abraham v. Abraham,

Moore's Ind. App.

vol. ix. p. 195.

Sec. 87, 88.]

SOURCES OF LAW.

55

the law of his parents simply by reason of his descent, and Law in

not because he or they were domiciled on any particular spot one time
or

owed

allegiance

to
;

any
that

particular ruler.
is

Subsequently

P^8^1-

law became

territorial

to say, a given

body of law

was made
cal
limits,

applicable to a district

marked out by geographiwithin


those
limits,

and

applicable

generally

because of their inhabitancy and their consequent allegiance


to a single government.
torial

The

influence under

which a

terri-

Law

be-

law and

territorial

sovereignty were arrived at was,

ritorial

I conceive^ feudalism^ '

prevailed the ^^^^^ *^6 Wherever feudalism ^


liifluence

tenant began to take his law from the land and not from his
descent 88.
^.

of feudal-

But we have
call

still

to see

how

the several Barbarian laws

became welded together with the Roman law and with that
which we
the feudal system into one compact body of law
for each country.
citizen

How

did the descendant of the

Roman
come
little.

and the descendant of

his barbarian conqueror


?

Of this we know but But the amalgamation probably commenced at a very


each to lose his distinctive rights
period after the barbarian conquest
:

early

and

this

amalgamation

would be greatly facilitated by the circumstance that even the


barbarian laws consisted of something more than the rude

customs which these tribes had brought with them from their
native forests*

The

leges barbarorum all bear obvious traces of

having been themselves influenced by the

however

is

for the most part not the


earlier

Roman law. This Roman law of Justinian,

but of the

Hermogenian, the Gregorian, and the Theoand above

dosian Codes ^.

Language,
'

literature, education,

all,

commerce,

citizenship
all

The combination of the notions of uniTersal empire with universal might ha,Te the same practical results as the rendering of law territorial, but would not necessarily beget the conception of
It used to be thought that for a time the

territoriality.

Roman law was wiped out was revived again upon the discovery of the Corpus Juris at Amalfi when that city was taken by the Pisans in 1135. The Pisans are supposed to have carried away this, the only copy in existence in Western Europe, as part of their booty, and the emperor Lothair the
'

of Europe,

and that

it

56

SOURCES or LAW.
side

[Chap.
Still
it is

II.

were on the

of the

Roman
we

lawyers,

not

without astonishment that


silently displacing the

find the

law of the conquered

law of the conquerors, and the

Roman

law adopted everywhere as the law of the land.


tion of the

This adop-

Roman law

took place rapidly after the twelfth

century.

A flourishing school of

Roman law arose

at Bologna^

and another at Paris immediately after ; and the Corpus Juris

became the general source of law throughout the contiaeut of

Western Europe ^,
Influence

89. In
-^
g,

England alone we
of the

find the

overwhelming influence
True
it is

law r^'^
sisted in

*^

Rowaa law

successfully resisted.

that not

few maxims

England,

Roman law have

been transferred to

English law, and, avowedly or upavowedly (for the most


part unavowedly), the doctrines of the

Roman law have largely

influenced the opinions of English lawyers; but no one has

ever been able to quote a text of the


either

in

the
It

courts of

Roman law as authority common law or in the courts of


jurisdiction

chancery.

was only within the very narrow

which the

ecclesiastical courts

managed
felt

to secure,

and in the

comparatively insignificant affairs of the admiralty courts

(which de9,ling with foreigners


law), that the

the want of a universal

Roman law was

9,ccepted.
it

For a long time


a more general
^,

the ecclesiastics struggled to procure for


acceptance.

The crown generally leaned

in its favour

though

Second (so the story goes) ordered it to he used as law throughout his dominions. It has been shown by Savigny that this is an altogether mistaken view of the fate of the Eoman law prior to the twelfth century. See G-esch. d. rom. Rechts im Mittelalter, vol. iii. 35 sqq.
'

See Weiske's Rechtslexieon,

s.

v.

Quellen des teutsehen Rechts,

toI.

Brunner in Holtzendorffs Encyclopadie (ed. i88a), p. 2g6. Theoretically the Eoman law was held binding because the German Empire was considered to be a continuation of the Roman. In the north of France (Pays Coutumier) the Roman law was never, strictly speaking, the common law, but still it had a powerful influence as raison 6crite. Ultimo vero loco e jure scripto Romano mutuamur, quod et aequitati consonum et negotio do quo agitur aptum eongruumque invenitur.' Dumoulin, no. torn. i. p. 23. Pothier, (Euvres, 6d. Bugnet, torn,
viii. p.

846

'

i.

p.
2

ji.

Besides the servile

maxim

so often quoted,

'quod principi placuit

legis

Sec. 89.]

SOUECES OF LAW.

67

occasionally, under the influence of the fear that its intro-

duction might throw too

much power

into the hands of the

church, the sovereign cast his weight into the other scale.

But the

^English

lawyers as a body never wavered.

The

judges with a dogged persistence kept the Corpus Juris as

an authority out of
ecclesiastical courts if

their

own

courts,

and restrained the


and the commons

they attempted to interfere in matters

which did not belong

to them.

The

nobility

were equally opposed to the introduction of

Roman

law.

It

must

at times have been a hard struggle to maintain against

the learning and influence of the clergy the ruder customs of

England, to which Glanvil, Fleta, and Bracton can scarcely


bring themselves to allow even the name of law^.
the writers I have
ciples of

And

all

named attempted

to introduce the prin-

Boman law
But
this

into English courts

by incorporating

them

into

works professing to treat of the laws and customs


attempt to treat the rules of
little success.

of England.

Roman

law as authoritative met with


due to this very admixture of

It

was perhaps

Roman law

that the authority

of even so accomplished a writer as Bracton

was repudiated

so

emphatically by the judges


habet vigorem,' which Bracton
Juris
'

^-

qualifies,

there

is

much

in the Corpus

which flatters and favours (Jespotism, ' Cum autem fere in omnibus regionibus utantur legibus et jure scripto sola Anglia usa est in suis finibus jure non scripto et consuetudine. In ea quidem ex non scripto jus venit, quod usus comprobavit. Sed absurdum non erit leges Anglicanas (licet non scriptas) leges appellare, cum legis
vigorem habeftt quicquid de consilio
publicae
'

et de consensu

magnatum
i. b. 2.

et rei-

eommuni sponsione
case quoted

authoritate regis sive priucipis praecedente

juste fuerit definitum et approbatum.'

Bracton, chap.

by Pitzherbert in his Abridgment (Garde 71), decided in the 35 Hen. VI, the court is represented as agreeing that Bracton was never accepted as an authority in our law.' So in the case of Stowel against Lord 2ouch, in Plowden's Reports, vol. i. p. 357, 'And to this purpose he cited Saunders' argument is thus reported Bracton, not as an author in the law, for he said that Bracton and Glanvil were not authors in our law, but he said he cited him as an ornament to discourse where he agrees with the law.' As far as I am aware, neither Bracton, Fleta, nor Glanvil are ever quoted in the Year Books. Eeeves

In a

'

(Hist. vol. iv. p. 186) says that Bracton is


lie

'

does not give the references.

It

may

once or twice referred to, but be said that it was not the
'

58
Custom
place

SOURCES OF LAW.
90. The resource of the English lawyers

[Chap. II.

Roman
law.

when called on to fill the gap which was elsewhere supplied by the Roman law ^^^ custom, usually called by us the common law. Of this
custom the judges were themselves, in the
repository.
last resort, the

But

the judges usually observed a discreet sUence


rules

as to the source
their decisions

iiom which they derived the


were based.

upon which

Here and there a judge or a


if

counsel arguendo would mention a precedent, but


trust the reports contained in the
rare.

we may
this

Year Books, even


little

was

StiU there appears to have been very


;

tendency

to innovation courts to

and there was doubtless a tradition of the

which every judge knew that he must conform at

the peril of his reputation.

Some

record of the proceedings

of the superior courts of justice was always kept, and

we have

a series of such records commencing as early as the 6 Ric. II


Character -(1394). of the
early reports.

These early records might, and probably did, afford

That practice seems to have first by reference to Littleton's Tentires, then to Cok's edition of that book, and then to Coke's own works. Other books have by degrees crept in since. But the value attached to a work may be fairly estimated by the demand for it, and of this we have a pretty clear indication. Littleton's Tenures was printed in 1481, again shortly after without date, again in 1528, again in 1543, again in 1572, and I think there were other editions. The Year Books, Fitzherbert's Grand Abridgment, a variety of books on the manner of holding courts, a book called The Justice of the Peace, Fitzherbert's Natura Brevium, and several other law-books were frequently printed during the same period. Britten, on the other hand, was not printed at all until 1530 Bracton was not printed till 1569 Glanvil not till 1557 and Fleta not till 1647. And the demand for these books has never increased none of them have been reprinted more than once until recently. They are
practice in former times to quote books.

come in

after the reformation

very gradually,

now

being printed chiefly for purposes of historical research.

am

not

aware upon what authority the oft-repeated statement of Bracton's influence on English law rests. It may be that Bracton's book was used privately by English lawyers to a much larger extent than appears, and that the judges were influenced by it without acknowledging their obligation whether this was so, or whether they studied the Roman law in any other work, I have no means of judging. Of course, the extent of the influence of Roman on English law cannot be measured by the value which English lawyers have attributed to the work of Bracton, but it still remains a most important fact that the authority of the Roman law has always been repudiated in England.
:

Sec. 90, 9I-]

SOURCES OF LAW.
cases^

59

some guide in future


with that
object.

though they were not drawn up

Moreoverj at least as early as the reign of

Edward

I the practice was begun of drawing up^ in addition

to these records, reports of cases heard

and determined, the

main, and apparently the sole object of which was to furnish

judges with precedents to guide them in their future decisions.

In these Year Books there

is

very

little

argumentj but only


a/t

an ascertainment by
quently

oral discussion of the points

issue

with the decision of the court.


criticises

The

reporter however fre-

the decision, and sometimes indicates in

a note the general proposition of law which he supposes the


decision to support.

Reference

is

also sometimes

made by
The
fully^

the reporter to other cases ilivolving the same point.


later

Year Books give the arguments somewhat more

but
this

still

we do not find previous cases frequently cited. From we might be disposed to infer that the practice of citing
argument
Yet
t>r

Practice

cases in support of an

a judgment was

still cases.

very rare even in the reign of Henry VIII, when the

last

Year Book was published.

this can hardly

be

so, for

the reports of Plowden in the reign of


are

much

fuller

than the

latest
cited,

Edward VI, which Year Books, show that cases


it is

were at that time freely


practice

and

not likely that the

came suddenly into

existence.

Moreover,

we can
all

scarcely account for the existence of the Year

Books at

unless

we
is

suppose that the lawyers studied them and

made

some use of them.

Books

further

The importance attached to the Year shown by the numerous reprints of them
as soon as the art of printing

which were issued


covered, and also of

was

dis-

by the popularity

of the abridgments

made

them by Fitzherbert and Brooke. Probably, therefore, the influence of precedent upon the decisions of the judges is not to be measured by the number of cases quoted in the
Year Books.
81. It
is,

however, always as indicating the custom of Decisions


earlier latertimew
tative."

England, and not as authority, that the decisions of


judges were cited during
all this

period and even afterwards,

60

SOURCES OF LAW.

[Chap.

II.

In the patent of James I^ for the appointment of


reporters
is it is

official

indeed recited that the

common law
resolutions

of

England
arrests

principally declared

by the grave
to time,

and

of the reverend and learned judges upon the cases that come

before

them from time

and that the doubts and

questions likewise which arise upon the exposition of statute

laws are by the same means cleared and ruled.

Nevertheless

we

find Blackstone

still

saying that the

first
is

ground and
general and

chief corner-stone

of

the laws of England

immemorial custom.

But long before Blackstone^s time, and in some measure perhaps owing to the patent of James 1, a very important change had taken place in the view held by
judges as to the force of prior decisions.
at first evidence only of

These decisions were

what the

practice

had been, guiding,

but not compelling, those who consulted them to a conclusion.

But when Blackstone wrote, each single decision standing by itself had already become an authority which no succeeding judge was at liberty to disregard.

This important

change was very gradual, and the practice was very likely
not altogether uniform.
it

As

the judges became conscious of

gave

much more careful of their expressions, and much more elaborate explanations of their reasons. They also betrayed greater diffidence in dealing with new
they became
cases to

which no rule was applicable, cases of


;

first

impression
practice
desire

as they were called

and they introduced the curious

of occasionally appending to a decision

an expression of

that
General

it

was not

to be

drawn

into a precedent.

Thus it comes to pass that English case law does for what the Roman law does for the rest of Western Europe. compared ^^ And this difference between our common law and the common of the*''^*
92.

Eoman

law of continental Europe has produced a marked difference


between our own and foreign legal systems.
principles of the

Where

the

Roman law

are adopted the advance

must

always be made on certain


'

lines.

An

English or American

Pat. 15 Jac.

I.,

in vol.
vol.
i.

vii.

part

3. p.

19 of Rymer's Foedera, ed. 1741.

Blackstone,

Comm.

p. 7a.

Sec. 92.]

SOUECES OF LAW,
The
is

61
result

judge can go wherever his good sense leads him.


has been, that whilst the law of continental Europe

formally

correct it is not always easily adapted to the changing wants

of those

amongst

whom

it

is

administered.
it is

On

the other

hand, the English law^ whilst

cumbrous,
is

ill- arranged}

and barren

of principles, whilst it
itself^ is
it

obscure and not un-

frequently in conflict with


justice

yet a system under which

can be done.

Anyhow

stands alotie in the history

of the world.
all

The

records of decisions have no doubt at

times and in

all countries

served as evidence of custom,


rolls

just as the
of

Year Books formerly served, and the court


still

manors

serve,

amongst

ourselves.

And

even without

the influence of custom judges are never likely to disregard


or to remain uninfluenced
cessors.

by the

decisions of their prede-

But nowhere

else

than in England and in countries

which have derived

their legal systems

from England have

the decisions of judges been systematically treated as authoritative.

There seems to have been a good deal of fluctuation

under the

Roman law

as to the authority to be attributed to

the imperial rescripts and decrees given in particular cases.


Still if these

were ever

ti'eated as generally

binding

it

seems

to have been because the Emperor was himself the supreme

source of

all

authority,

and could

legislate

when and how

he pleased.

But no

decisions of
'

any

tribunal had^ as such,

any authority whatsoever.


consultationes quas

Nemo

judex vel arbiter existimet


sequen-

non

rite judicatas esse putaverit

dum, cum non exemplis sed


all

legibus judicandum

sit,'*

Nearly

modern continental codes contain

similar prohibitions,

and

this is the
'

modern continental practice '.

'The opinions of law professors and the views taken by prior judges any way considered in future decisions.' Allgem. LandKeeht, Introduction, s. 6. The stringent provisions of the French Code have been already referred to. (See note to sect. 26.) Of course previsions of this kind do not prevent judges from resorting to the opinions of those
shall not be in

who preceded them

for guidance,

and

this inevitably results in these

opinions producing an influence which is of great importance, though widely distinguished from the 'authority' of English decisions. French

judges really rely on such opinions

when they

refer to

'

la doctrine et la

62
Jural
basis of

SOURCES OF LAW.
93.

[Chap.

II.

Well

established as the practice of the judges to

authority
law**^^

the law has now become


ourselves to the notion
observation.

m England,

...

make

it is

not easy to reconcile


is

when

the practice

brought under our

The explanation of it is the delegation to the judges of what was once a peculiar function of sovereignty. If we look at the history of all early societies we find
that the principal duty of the sovereign, in time of peace,
is is

not the making of law, but the decision of law-suits.


the

It
his

king himself who decides he


in
is

all

disputes between

subjects;

the judge before

whom

the issue

is tried-';

and whilst

some of the

oldest treatises

on law we find

the judicial function of kings carefully and prominently considered, the legislative function is scarcely noticed.

This

is

notably the case in the treatise of


is

Manu, where the king

always spoken of as 'the dispenser of justice/ and his

duties as such are minutely laid


recollect a single passage

down; whereas I do not

and good laws.

which enjoins him to make wise Nor does this in any way result from the

claim of Hindoos to have received a divine revelation.


find the

We

same thing

in societies

which lay no such extensive


all to

claim,

and indeed which hardly claim at


direct

have received

commands
94.

from God.

Even

in England, where Austin thinks the judicial

function was more completely separated from the legislative

than in any other country

^,

we

find strong indications of the

extent to which those functions were mixed in early times.

The

present judicial authority of the


its

House
of

of

Lords

is

generally traced to

representation

the Aula Regis,


justice

which was
jurisprudence
'

at the
or
'

same time the supreme court of

point de vue juridique.' German judges seem to have no hesitation in referring to treatises, and to the Gerichtsgebrauch or usus fori. Thus a kind of customary law (Juristenrecht) is formed by the courts, but Unger says that it cannot be applied by the courts in Austria, because the application of all customary law is forbidden by
le

legislation,

Code,
'

i. p. 42 Austrian Civil I should doubt if such legislation could ever be effectual. See Grote's History of Greece, Part I. ch. xx.
:

(linger, Syst. d. Oster. Privat-E., vol.

s.

12.)

Leot. xxviii. p. 536 (third edition).

Sec. 93-96.]

SOURCES OP LAW.
legislative

63
It

and the supreme


required a

assembly in the kingdom.

special

clause in

Magna
sit

Carta to

enable the
in

Court of

Common
is

Pleas to

anywhere except

the

place where the king happened to reside.

By

a fiction the

sovereign

always supposed, even at the present day, to

preside in person at every sitting of the Court of King's

Bench
95.

and

it
is

is

as keeper of the

king's

conscience that

the chancellor

said to exercise his authority.


is,

The truth
and

as Sir

Henry Maine has shown ^, that


date to that of judicial

Idea of
terior to

the idea of law


decision
'
:

itself is posterior in

it

*^j! ?^, was the actual observation of a succession judicial

of similar decisions

of the

same kind which gave

rise

to decision,

the idea of a rule or standard to which a case might be


referred.

As soon

as this observation

was made every one


of stating

would naturally recognise the advantage


abstract form the rule which
of uniform decisions,
tolerable
certainty,

in

an

might be inferred from a


it

series

and which,

might be reckoned with

would be applied, whenever a similar


This was the
first

dispute should arise.


first

germ

of law

and the

recognised laws were probably collections of the scattered

rules

which had thus come

to be adopted.

96. It was only in the simplest condition of society that Delegathe king could really be also judge in
tion.
all

matters of litiga-

judicial

At a very

would

early period this function of sovereignty go^g^eign be delegated to persons whose duty it was to decide

disputes and punish offences.


elderly persons,
their advice,
his absence.

The

wise,

and learned, and


assist

who

sat

with the king to

him with
cases in

would be deputed by him to decide

But

this

change in the person of the judge

would not materially


would occur

affect either the character of the ofiice

or the exercise of the function.


:

The same

repetition of cases

by deciding them

successively in the

same way,

the subject judge, just like the sovereign judge, would give
currency to certain rules, and these rules would come to be
looked upon as law.
'

Ancient Law,

p. 5 (ed. 1861).

64.

SOURCES OF LAW.
97.

[Ohap.

II.

Judicial

The

process

by which law

is

made by judges

in the

law not a exercise of their judicial function has been undoubtedly misusurpaIt has been said, that the exercise by judges understood.
of the legislative function at all
is

a usurpation.

If

by the
is

exercise of the legislative function be

meant the

evolution,

of law

by the

process above described, this statement

the

very reverse of truth.


his

judge who merely substitutes for


is

own

opinion the concurrent opinion of others

no breaker
could

of the law.

The only

result of saying that judges

make no

law, would be to say, in effect, in a large

number

of cases, that there was no rule of law applicable to the pur-

pose in hand, and to leave the judge entirely uncontrolled.


Characterjudiciary ^^"

98.

A very much more important


decision.

question has been raised,

as to the correct appreciation of the process of

making law
this

by

judicial

Austin has

minutely

criticised

procesSj

but the
is,

published Lecture
is

which

contains

these

criticisms

as

so frequently the

case with the scanty

remains

We have
of

of

the writings of that eminent jurist,


it

made

rip

two disjointed fragments; and

is

of course,

therefore, not

summed up
that the

into

any

final

conclusions.

It

appears

to

me
two

essential

difference

between the

generation of law by judicial decision and by express legislation lies in

of the characteristics of judiciary

law noted
it is

by Austin,
Case in

namely,
it is

that

it is

ex post facto, and that

always implicated with the peculiarities of the particular

which

applied*

All the objections which can

be raised against judiciary law


of these characteristics
it,
;

may

be traced to one or both

its

bulk, the difficulty of ascertaining

its

inconsistency,

and

so forth.

To the combination
its

of

these

two

characteristics

may

be also traced

great,

though

possibly

its

only advantage

that

of flexibility, or capacity

of being adapted to

any new combination of circumstances


the judges in England compelled, as
as has been attempted in
call

that

may

arise.

Were

in Italy, France

and Spain, and

India, to state separately

and fully what French lawyers

the motives, and Spanish lawyers the points of their decisions

Sec. 97-99.]

SOURCES OP LAW.
and the
rules of

65

that

is

to say, their findings in fact

law

which guide them

there

would be a complete revolution

in the history of English case law.

The law being


from the

stated
facts,

in distinct propositions, altogether separate

would be

easily ascertained.

This, coupled with our notions

as to the authority of prior decisions, would render a conflict


so conspicuous, as to be almost impossible.

The law would


rigid.

soon become clear and precise enough; but so far as judicial


decision
is

was concerned,

it

would become much more

It

because English judges are absolved from the necessity of

stating general propositions of law, and because, even

these are stated, they are always read as being qualified

when by

the circumstances under which they are applied, that our law

remains bulky and uncertain, but has


respect" for precedent,

also, in

spite of our
flexible.

remained for

so

long a period

Whether

it

would be found

possible to

combine our practice

as to the generally unquestionable authority of prior decisions,

with the practice of laying down abstract propositions of

law separate from and independent of the particular


is

facts,

an experiment which, as far as I

am

aware, has not yet

been tried ^.
99.

The nature

of the process of reasoning which has to Proceas of


j,y
^J'

be performed in order to extract a rule of law from a number


of decided cases
stances, is

which
^"

by

elimination of

all

the qualifying circum-

'^

a very peculiar and

difiScult one.

The opinion of
its authority

the judge, apart from the decision, though not exactly disregarded,
is

considered as extra-judicial, and

may
from

be
'

got rid of

by any suggestion which can

separate

it

even

The High Court at Calcutta has gone somewhat near it, by requiring its own members, when they differ in opinion on a matter of law,

to, the arbitration of a majority of the whole Com-t. This sometimes leads to the enunciation of propositions of law in an abstract form, which it is made imperative on all the members of the

to refer the difference

and of course on all the inferior Courts, to accept, until overruled by the Privy Council. See Eule of High Court of Calcutta of July 1867, in Mr. Broughton's Civil Procedure, p. 710 (fourth edition). The government saw no usm-pation of power in this proceeding on the contrary, the rule is said to have been made at the suggestion of government.
Court,
:

66
the actual result.

SOUECES OP liAW.

[Chap.

II.

Unless, therefore, a proposition of law

is it

absolutely necessary to a decision, however emphatically

may

have been stated,

it

passes

from the province of


Curiously enough

auctoit
is

ritas into

that of mere literatura.

not the opinion of the judge, but the result to the suitor

which makes the law^.


Competition of opposite analogies.

100. Paley has called the process by which law

is

extracted

from a
gies^.

series of decisions

the competition of opposite analois

Austin considers that this process

not necessarily

confined to the extraction of law from judicial decisions, and

that

it

may

as well be

employed in the application of ascerBut, as I have said ^,

tained rules of law to particular cases.


it is

the peculiarity of English judgs that they do not think

themselves bound to distinguish these two operations, and


that they very frequently perform

them simultaneously. They,


it.

in fact, determine the law only hy applying

And
'

I think

Paley^s description of forensic disputation


is

and

judicial decision

both forcible and accurate.

'

It

is,^

he says,

by the urging
is

of the different analogies that the contention of the bar


carried

on

and it

is in

the comparison, adjustment and reconin the discerning of such

ciliation of

them with one another,

distinctions,

and in the framing of such a determination as

may
if

either save the various rules alleged in the cause, or,

that be impossible,

may

give up the weaker analogy to

the stronger, that the sagacity and


exercised/
Third
source of
:

wisdom

of the court are

101. Closely connected with the


is

law which emanates from


is

law Com- a series of judicial decisions


mentaries,

the law which


jurists.

derived
also

from the commentaries of great


This

These are

'

is

consistent with the idea that the basis of the law

which comes

to us through judges is custom,


'^

and not opinion.

first

Moral Philosophy, vol. ii. p. 259. Austin seems to have thought at that Paley was speaking only of the application and not the extrac(Lect. xxxvii. p. 653.)
p.

tion of law.

opinion.

(Fragments,
sect. 98.

1031.)

Very

But he afterwards changed that likely Paley did not, any more

than judges, distinguish the two processes.


'

Supra,

Sec. 100-104.]

SOURCES OF LAW.

67

expounders of the law, and their works are constantly read

and referred
weight.
102.

to in courts of justice,

and have the very greatest

The authority

of a commentator

cannot, however;

like that of a judge, be traced immediately to the sovereign,

and, as a general rule, a commentary


is

when

it first

appears

only used as an argument to convince, and not as an au-

thority which binds.

But just as judges by

successive decisions

give currency to custom as a rule of law, so by successive


recognition they establish the authority of a commentator;
at last the opinions
till

which he has expressed count for as much,

or even more, than the opinions of the most eminent judge.

This

is

the case with such commentaries as those of Lord

Coke, Lord Hale, and Littleton in England ; the Dayabhaga,


the Mitacshara, and the

Hedaya

in India.
is Difference

103. Between commentaries and judicial decisions there

a distinction of form which


Judicial decisions are, as

it is

we have

important not to overlook, between seen, by their very nature c'^'^menis

concrete; all the judge professes to do

to decide the case judiciary

before him; and the principle of law which guides

him has

very often to be extracted with

much

labour and difficulty.


deals with matters

But the commentator not unfrequently entirely in the abstract. He lays down
one principle from another;

propositions of

law

capable of being applied to a whole class of cases | he infers

he foresees new combinations

and provides

for

new

results.
is

A commentary of this character,


established,
is

when
few

once

its

authority

far

more comprebut very

hensive than any

number

of volumes of reports;

treatises of this kind,

and scarcely any modern ones, have

attained the necessary standard of reputation.

104. I have not, as will have been observed,

made

either Divi ne
law.

the divine law, the law of nature, or the moral law, separate
sources of law
;

and

do not think that they ought to be

so

made, although many learned persons strenuously maintain


the contrary.

The terms themselves


is

are very vaguely used,

but I think by divine law

generally

meant that body of

p 3

68
rules whicli is set

SOURCES OF LAW,
by God
to

[Chap. II.

man through

inspired revelation'.

Nearly

all

nations claim to be possessed of some such revelation,


it

but the nature o

differs considerably

and the

relation

which these revealed

rules bear to law, in the proper sense of

the term, also varies very greatly.


Christians.

105. Christian nations lay claim to

nothing more than

a revelation of certain doctrines of religion and certain very general rules of morality.

The Author of the Christian

faith,

though repeatedly appealed

to for that purpose, always refused

to interfere in questions of a political character, or to lay


specific rules of conduct.

down

Greeks and Romans.

IDS.

a divine revelation at
to the term.

The Greeks and Romans had scarcely any notion of all, in any sense which we should attach The
divine communications which they received

were rather in the shape of advice or warnings how to act on

some
at

special 'occasion.

If

it

was supposed that there had been

any time

persons,

who

spoke habitually imder divine in-

spiration, these

were not sages who directed the conduct,


stirred the feelings

but poets
hearers.
Hindoos.

who

and imagination of their

The Hindoos, whilst they too have been largely influenced by a mythic poetry of supposed divine origin, have
107.
also, as

I have already mentioned, a very distinct revelation

of the will of God.

And

this revelation is quite

as

much

occupied with the ordinary affairs of daily hfe as with the regulation of religious observances.

The general moral

precepts

are few, and, consequently, its actual influence


life

on the modern

of a

Hindoo

is

not very great.


to

Mahom
iriedans

108.

The extent

which Mahommedans are

still

under

amTjews. ^^^ influence of a divine law I have already explained.

They

have carried the notion further than any other people except
perhaps the Jews of old,

who

for a long period claimed to be

' Rules of conduct, not actually revealed, may also be referred to a Divine Author, and, I believe, are sometimes called divine, but I am at liberty to

restrict the expression

divine law as I have done, and as it is convenient do comprising the unrevealed rules, as is more commonly the practice, under moral law, or law of nature.
' '

to

Sec. 105-109.]

SOURCES OF LAW.

69

under the direct personal government of God Himself, and


to be in constant communication with

Him.

It appears that

the Jews felt at times this form of political society to he


inconvenient, and the traces of a struggle to obtain a different
constitution are to be found in the Bible, where

we read that
^.'

they desired to have a king

'

like all the other nations

And though
prayer
is

they are rebuked for their ingratitude their

at last granted.

But the Jews never seem

to have

arrived at
'

any very

clear notions about law, at least not about

their

109.

own law. Modern

nations have recognised a very important Divine


application
of

principle

as to the

divine rules

by human

always
enforcer!.

authority, that some divine rules are not to be so enforced,

No

one, whatever he
:

might pretend, could


therefore,

practically assert
for it but to

the contrary

and there seems,

no help

admit that the law, as a human


standard of morality of which
leaves something unfulfilled.

institution, takes the highest


it is

capable, but

which

still

The Mahommedan law

supplies

one example of this in the recognition of the lawfulness of taking interest for the use of money, though I
still

doubt

whether a Mahommedan,

if

asked, would acknowledge

any
find

distinction in the obligatory force of divine precepts.

We

other and clearer examples in the various cases in which under

nearly every system of law a

man

is

relieved

from the

fulfil-

ment

of his promise under certain circumstances.

In the case
is

of infancy, for example, the debt incurred by the infant


enforced, but very often he ought, nevertheless, to

not

pay

it.

curious case of this kind occurred early in our administration

of justice in India.

The Hindoos

of

Lower Bengal generally


The English judges
power to them, but
in the way.

desired that as between father

and son the father should have

power

to dispose of the family property.


this

were by no means unwilling to grant

some very plain precepts of divine authority stood


that a sale once

The Hindoos thereupon enunciated the convenient maxim,


made could
' I

riot

be set aside, because


viii. 5.

'

a fact

Samuel


70

SOURCES OF LAW.
texts.'
'

[Chap. II.

cannot be altered by a hundred

The English judges


non debet, factum

capped this with a Latin maxim,


valet.''

Fieri

And

no one has ever since questioned the power


^.

of alienation
Influence
],^^

110.

But though the operation


it

of divine
it

law has been


has indirectly

thus limited,

would be

idle to

deny that

had a large

influence

upon law.

deny that a large portion of


religious belief at
all.

To deny this would be to mankind has had any sincere


it is

Still

impossible to

admit, as

Blackstone and some other English lawyers seem to assert ^,


that there
is

implied in every

human law some


;

sort of reser-

vation or exception in favour of the divine law


divino absolving
it conflicts

a salvo jure
if

men from
it is

obedience to the

human law
is

with the divine.

This proposition

not the

less

objectionable because
in which
scientious
it is

capable of being read in a sense


If Blackstone

not untrue.

meant that a con-

man, with a firm and well-grounded conviction

that there existed a conflict between a particular divine and

a particular

human

injunctioii,

ought to obey the


is

first

and

not the second, he was enunciating what


this is a truth very rarely applicable,

strictly true.
is

But

and

wholly foreign

to the subject

which Blackstone had under consideration

namely, the nature of laws in general.


111.
it

If,

on the other hand, Blackstone intended to lay

down

as a principle of general application that every

one

is

entitled to institute for himself a comparison

between the
law, he

human and

divine law,

and

that, in case of

any proceedino-

taken against him for disobeying the

human

may

plead the divine precept in his defence, the absurdity of the


principle

may

be demonstrated at once by attempting to

apply

it.

If a judge were to say, 'I find so

and

so in

an
is

act of parliament, but in

my

opinion the divine precept

otherwise, and I decide according to the divine precept,-" he


> See the Dayabhaga of Jimuta Vahana, Hindoo Law, vol. i. p. 53.

chap.'

ii. ss.

28,

39

and Strange's
8 (fifth ed.).

See

Comm.

vol.

i.

pp. 42, 43

Fonblanctue on Equity,

p.

Sec. 110-113.]

SOURCES OF LAW.

71

would be certainly overruled by the court o appeal, and


probably declared unfit for his
112. It seems to
office.

me

that the fundamental error

lies

in

treating the conflict between divine and

human

laws as

an

ordinary one, which the lawyer must be constantly prepared


to meet.

In

every

Nothing can be further removed from the truth. country which acknowledges a revelation, the

general precepts of law which have emanated from a divine


source have been over and over again acknowledged

human

sovereign authority.

by the The Koran and the Shasters are


respectively
in

expressly declared

by

act of parliament to be the law of the

Mahommedans and Hindoos


of daily life

India ^.

The

precepts of the Bible have been applied to the institutions

by

Christians, to

as great

an extent as the

difference of circumstances

wiU admit; and there has been


to the

a tendency rather to strain than to contract the application


of the rules of the
society.

Old Testament
conflict

wants of modern

So far from a
should

between human and divine


it is

law being an ordinary occurrence,


such
conflict
arise.

very unlikely that any


is

sovereign body
all,

not very

likely to

promulgate laws which

or even a large majority,

of

its

subjects would believe to be contrary to the

commands
It
is is

of a
far

Being of

infinite

powerj wisdom, and goodness.

more probable that any supposed antagonism

the sug-

gestion of ignorance or presumption.

How

a case of real

antagonism
it
is,

is

to be dealt with, should it arise (and, rare as


it

no one will assert

to be impossible),

is

a question

as unfit to be considered in a treatise

on law, as the some-

what

similar question

when
?

is

a nation justified in rising in

rebellion against its rulers

113. It

may, indeed, happen to an advocate or to a judge,


opinion of what
is

that his

own

enforced

by a divine precept
is

is in conflict

with some rule of positive law which he


support.

called

upon

to

But no one would pretend that


affected

the law was in any


'

way

by the private opinions of


e. 70. . 17.

See 21 Geo. III.

72
those whose duty
Christians

SOURCES OF LAW,
it is

[Chap. II.

to administer

it.

Thus there

are

some

who

believe that, for reasons founded on divine


tie is indissoluble.

commands, the marriage

But

this

would

not justify a judge who thus thought in refusing to pronounce A large majority a sentence of divorce in case of adultery.
of those

there

is

form an opinion have thought that no such divine prohibition and 'have made the law
qualified

to

accordingly.
114.

So there are to be found Mahommedans who consider

that

God has forbidden the taking of money for the use of money but the judges, with the general consent of a vast majority of Mahommedans, have long been in the habit of giving* interest on loans of money to Mahommedan lenders
;

and

it

would be preposterous for a single individual to


overwhelming opposition.

set

up
Use made

his opinion against this

115.
is

What
clear

use the lawyer

may

still

make

of the divine to decide, of


positive

ofdMnT^law
'^^^"

enough.
all

The judge, being obliged


efforts

even when

his

to discover a
rules
is

rule

law have

failed, or

where there are

which

conflict, or

where the interpretation of the rule

doubtful,

may
if

safely
it

assume in such cases that the sovereign power,


declared
its vnll in

had

the form of a positive law, would have

done so in conformity with the divine precept.

And
is

a judge

who

acts

upon the divine precept in such cases

fully within

the limits of his authority.

He is doing that which a sovereign


is

judge would undoubtedly himself do under the circumstances,


that
is,

he

is

deciding the case according to that which

believed to be right and just.

So much of divine law has,

however, been incorporated into positive law, that even in


this

Moral law
nature.
i*

way the lawyer has very seldom to resort to it. With regard to the moral law and the law of nature, would be impossible to say whether or no we should enu116.

merate either or both of these amongst the sources of law,


until

we had

assigned to those terms some more definite


is

meaning than

commonly

done.

That there

are rules of

conduct which are regularly observed amongst men, and

Sec. 114-116.]

SOURCES OF LAW.

73

to a considerable
decrees,

degree influence judges in making their

but are yet neither positive law nor the revealed


of God,
is

commands

undoubtedly true

such, for instance, as

the rules which regulate the intercourse of nations, the laws


of war, and constitutional practice.

There are also rules of


to,

conduct which judges constantly refer


a tendency to become so
fair-dealing.
to the

and

act

upon,

which, nevertheless, are not law, though in England they have


:

such, for example, as the rules of

Rules of this kind are sometimes said to belong

moral law, and at other times to the law of nature.

Speaking very generally, these two expressions seem to


to

me

comprehend very much the same


to different sources.

rules,
'

but they refer

them

The term

moral law " appears

to assume

wrong.

some innate faculty of distinguishing right from The law of nature, on the other hand, seems to refer

to the disposition of

man

in an uncorrupted state

^.

But the
rules

moment a
are

difference of opinion arises as to

what the

which are to be derived from


is

either of these sources,

no

further attention

paid to them.

There

is

something almost

absurd in

my

asking you to accept a thing as right, because

my moral

sense tells

me

it is

so,

or because 1 think that

it

can be traced to nature.


pressions as moral sense

Bentham^ has

said that such ex-

and law of nature are only pretences,

under which powerful

men have

concealed from themselves

and others the


appeal
to

exercise of arbitrary power,

by making a sham
are really

some external

standard,
wishes.

when they
This

consulting only their


potentates.

own

may

be true of

But though a lawyer might

also choose to avail

himself of these or similar expressions, he would really be


driven, in every case, to support himself

by an appeal

to

an

external standard, and one of a very different sort, namely

the

common

experience of mankind.

And

where conduct

is

I am not sure that persons who refer the existence of niles of conduct to utility or expediency, might not use the term 'moral law' to describe them. But the term generally implies the existence of an innate faculty.
" Fragment on Government, chap. Works.
ii.

sect. 14

vol.

i.

p.

8 of Collected


74
to be considered, or
ficient,
is

SOURCES OF LAW.
where the rule of law
is

[Chap.

IL

obscure or de-

that which
it

mankind

at large has regarded as right

a guide

would be presumptuous to neglect, whatever

may

be the influence which has led us in that direction

our moral faculties, or our uneorrupted nature.


117.

The

history of these expressions exemplifies this in

a very remarkable manner.


nature
is

The general

idea of a law of

said to be due to the

Greek philosophers of the

Stoic school.

'According to nature' expressed their idea of


^

moral as well as material perfection

But by what

test did

they discover what was and what was not according to


nature
?

Simply by that of uniformity.


and amongst
all

What was
;

the

same

to all

they accepted as natural

what-

ever varied they rejected^.

So too the

Eoman

lawyers, before
is

they had learnt the Greek philosophy, had, as

well known,

adopted as the result of intercourse with other nations a body


of law, whichj under the

name

of jus gentium, or law

common
they

to all nations, they very extensively applied^.

When

adopted the notion of a law of nature, they did not abandon


these rules, or change
necessity to
said) the

them a
all

single whit.
is

There was no
(as

do

so

for the law of nature

only

has been

law common to

nations seen in the light of

a peculiar theory*.
118.

So too the very expression 'moral law' shews unhave been formed by habit.
is

mistakeably, that consciously or unconsciously the rules of

conduct comprised under

it

The
of

word
a

mos,

from signifying what


is

customary, has come to

signify

what

right.

It

was

to explain the

phenomenon

common agreement upon


:

this point, that

an innate faculty

was suggested
it is

and whenever

this faculty is called in question,


its

only by pointing to this agreement that


its

existence can

be proved, or
Principle of utility.

extent measured.
observe,

119. Nor, I
'

may

would
p.

it

make anv
'

difference'

Maine's Ancient Law,


Grote's Plato, vol.
iii.

54

(first ed.).

^ ' *

p. 510, u.
d.

Danz, Lehrbuch

d.

Gesoh.

rOm. Eechts,

46.

Maine's Ancient Law, p. 50

(first ed.).

Sec. 117-120.]

SOURCES OF LAW.
now under
consideration,

75

so far as regards the matter

were

we

to drop these terms altogether,

and substitute the prinwould have us do


For however useful
men's

ciple of utility in their place, as those

who have most


it

strongly attacked them.

may

be, politically speaking, to establish clearly in


all is

minds that the greatest happiness of


other than public opinion ^.

the true guide

of action, the test of conformity to this principle can be no

reference to utility, separated

from experience and

resting on a bare assertion of the good


is

or evil tendency of a particular line of conduct,

just as

powerless to convince, and just as apt to serve as a disguise


of arbitrary power, as an appeal to either nature or a moral
sense.

In whatever

dress, therefore,

we may

choose to put

our sentiments, I do not think the lawyer need go beyond


actual experience.

120. There are, however, two countries of Europe in which


the rules of conduct

W have

just

been considering have


I have already

played a different and more conspicuous part.


alluded to the effect of equity on
of the
effects

Roman

law, and the equity


its

Enghsh Chancellors
have not been
less

is

not wholly dissimilar, and

important.

For a fuU and clear


principle

exposition of the

method by which upon an assumed

of natural equality, or equity, the


to get

Roman

lawyers managed

rid of

dogmas and

distinctions

which belonged to

the strict law of Rome, but which were not found in the

law common to aU nations, I must

refer the

student

to

the chapter on 'Equity^ in Maine's Ancient Law.

Our
that

own

notion of equity

is

so

far

identical with

this,

the moral law comes in as an avowed remedy for the inconvenience and inapplicability of an already existing system,
' Bentham admits this. He says Tiiose who desire to see any check whatsoever to the power of the government under which they live, or any limit to their sufferings under it, must look for such check and limit to the source of the Public Opinion Tribunal, irregular though it be, and, to the degree in which it has been seen, fictitious to this place of refuge, or to none for no other has the nature of things afforded. To this tribunal they must on every occasion apjreal.' Securities against Misrule adapted to a Mahommedan State, sect, i ; vol. viii. p. 562 of Collected Works.
: '
;

76

SOURCES or LAW.
origin of English equity
is

[Cbap. II.

But the
history

in that early stage of

when

the idea of law was very incomplete, and the

exercise of the judicial function

had not been

clearly separated

from the ordinary

exercise of sovereign authority.

The

decrees

of the Court of Chancery were in their origin founded on

a sort of remedial power residing in the sovereign by virtue


of the prerogative.
It

was the King^s conscience which was


and because
it

moved by an

injustice;

was one which was

not remediable by the ordinary law, the Chancellor received


a commission to remedy
self,
it,

sometimes from the King him^.

but sometimes also from Parliament

Of

course

it

was

easy to pass from this to a general commission to redress


grievances for

which the

strict

rules

of

law supplied no
the limits
cases the

adequate remedy, without noticing that thereby power was

given to the Court of Chancery practically to


of
its

fix

own

jurisdiction,

by determining
rendered
it

in

what

deficiencies of the

common law
this,

necessary for itself

to interfere.

Whyequi-

121.

Notwithstanding

equity has to a great extent


first

come com- lost in England that feature, which at


^tgii!^^

sight

it

would
^

^ seem

easiest

to

preserve^
is

namely,

its

elasticity,

Maine

considers that this

due to courts of equity having originally

adopted certain moral principles, which have been carried out


to all their legitimate consequences,

and which

fall short of

the corresponding

ethical
it is

notions

of the present day.

venture to think that

also due, in part at least, to the


itself
is

very different conception of law

by modern lawyers,

and

to the great importance

which

now
and

attached to the
secure
it,

stability of law,

and

to the necessity, in order to

for a complete separation of legislative

judicial functions.

I do not, of course, canvass the acute and truthful generaliza'

Spence's Chancery Jurisdiction, vol.

i.

p.

408.

Ancient Law, p. 69 (first ed.). Notwithstanding the high authority of Maine on such a point as this, I doubt if equity has become so inelastic as he supposes. I rather think it has taken a fresh start lately and that the closer relations of courts of law and equity may have had something
=
;

to do

with a relaxation in the

stiffness of both.

Sec. 121-124.]

SOURCES OF LAW.

77

tion that equity precedes legislation in the order of legal ideas,

but I would base

it

on a far more general principle than the


rules.

preliminary assumption of fixed ethical

122. Consider the matter from the opposite point of view.

Equity precedes legislation in legal

history.

Why ?

Because

the idea of law as an inflexible rule without the possibility


of rnodification
is

wholly unsuited to the early notions of

the functions of courts of justice.

According to a notion

which extends

own history, the function of judges is not only to enforce the commands of a soTereign, but under his authority to redress grievances. But it is only when there is a separation of judicial and legislative functions
far

down

into our

that

it

becomes possible to distinguish the province of law

from the province of morality.


under the term
'justice.'

Both

ideas are

comprehended

When

this separation has taken

place, then the flexibility

and adaptability

to special circum-

stances,

which are the very essence of the remedial functions

of courts of equity, conflict with the idea that the rules to be

administered are rules of law, and with the conception of law

which now prevails in jurisprudence.


123.

Inasmuch however

as the rules of equity have a tenrigid, their

dency under the influence of precedent to become


elasticity

depends on the same causes which give elasticity


:

to the

common law
;

that
;

they are made by judges in the


that they are ex pot facto and
not, like

course of judicial decision


concrete

and that they are

an act of parliament,
In India.

prospective

and

abstract^.
is

124.

very curious problem with reference to equity

being worked out in India.


of the

We

scorn the exclusive

maxims

Eoman Law, and we


Nevertheless, there
It
is

emphatically profess to extend the King's subjects

the protection of law to


alike.

all classes of

are in India

enormous gaps in

the law.
siderable

not too

much

to

say that there are conare,

classes

of persons
topics,
'

whose legal rights


very imperfectly
sec. 98.

with

reference

to

many

defined:

and

See supra,

78
there
are

SOURCES OF LAW.

many

topics

affecting

all

classes

on whicli

it

would be scarcely

possible to lay

down a

single

principle

wbich there would not be some hope of challenging with


success.

It has been supposed that in India these

gaps are
to

to be filled
'

up by the judge deciding the case according

equity and good conscience/


all

And

it

has even been said,

that

the rules of law which a judge has to apply in India

are subject to 'equity

and good

conscience.'

But though

in

the present state of Indian law some such

maxim and some


lead.

such expedient

may

be necessary,

it it

is

well to be on our

guard against the dangers to which


criticized

may

Constantly

by an able

bar, always closely

watched by a jealous

public, generally dealing with suitors

who have

the energy

and means

to resent injustice, judges

administering equity

have been under a restraint as


as judges administering

effective, if

not as obvious,
these restraints,

common

law.

Under
do^

and

with ethical ideas generally accepted in a


as in England, equity

homogeneous
where
it is

society,

may

and no doubt has


like India,

done, very useful work.

But

in

a country

these restraints are almost wholly wanting,

and where

perfectly possible (not to speak of minor antagonisms) that

in successive courts af appeal a Hindoo, a

Mahommedan, and
same
case,
is

a Christian might have to


the attempt
ethical,

sit

as judges in the

to

apply a

system which

assumed

to

be

and which has only been extensively applied in two

countries of the world,


^

might seem somewhat hazardous^.

The

difficulty of transferring the ideas of


all

together with
illustrated

by

European systems of law, their traditional modifications, into Indian courts, is a line of argument which I have more than once heard.

law in India are courts of equity also, and that the law must therefore be administered equitably. And (it is urged) it would be inequitable to apply strictly the rules of procedure, where they would press hardly

It is said (and truly said in a certain sense), that all courts of

on particular litigants. No one would think of claiming any special favour on such a ground in the English Court of Chancery. But it is not so easy to explain to a person wholly ignorant of the history of the terms, why, with the principles which they profess to adopt, courts of equity do not more frequently than any other courts relax the rules which they have once laid down.

'

CHAPTER

HI.

PERSONS AND THINGS.


125.

Tte terms 'persons' and 'things' occur very


it is

fre- Things

quently in law, and


of
'

necessary to try and get some idea imagi-

what we mean by them.


In
its

I will

first

deal with the term ''^"


is

thing.'

narrowest and strictest sense a thing

a permanent sensible object other than a person.

But

it is

sometimes used to denote any object real or imaginary about

which we can speak or think.


that

To

its

use in this extended


it

sense there can be no objection provided

be imderstood

we cannot give

physical attributes to imaginary objects.

126. Objects which are sensible are what


as land, gold, corn, and so forth.

we

call corporeal,

But

if

we

include

amongst

things those objects which


classes of things, corporeal

we can
and

conceive,

we have two

incorporeal.

127. Rights

are

incorporeal

things

and the law deals Things

with them as such.


sold,

Thus a debt
be

or a patent

may

be pledged, and

corporeal incor-

and transferred either

inter vivos or

by

will.

In other

^"^^'^

words, a right

may

itself
is

the object of rights.


necessarily incorporeal, the

128. Whilst a right


object of the right

itself

may
to

be either corporeal or incorporeal.


is

Thus
and

if

owe a debt

, the object of B's right

money

is

corporeal; but the debt itself treated as the object of


is

pledge, or sale, or bequest,

incorporeal.

80
Thinga

PERSONS AND THINGS,

[Chap. III.

129. Things are divided into moveable and immoveable

and immoveable.
Things
perso^ial.

^^^

this

division

corresponds to an obvious physical


is

dis-

tinction.

This division of things

not

much

in use in

England.

English lawyers prefer to divide things into real

and

personal.

learned modern author suggests that the

terms 'real' and 'personal' were not in use prior to the


seventeenth century
i.

But I

find

them
and

used, apparently as
It

familiar expressions, in the reign of


is

Henry the Seventh ^


'

not unlikely that the terms

'

real

'

personal

'

are coninto of

nected with the division of actions in the


actions in

Roman law
actio in

rem and

actions in personam.

The

rem

the

Roman law was


'

founded on what was called a jus in rem;


I shall explain
fully hereafter.
is

the actio in personam upon a jus in personam.

the terms

in

rem ' and

'

in personam

'

more

It is sufficient to say

now

that a jus in

rem

a right of

ownership, or a right available like ownership against persons


generally; whilst a jus in personam
is

a right available against

an individual or against determinate individuals.

Now Enghsh

lawyers also divided actions into real and personal, and the
real action, like the actio in

rem, was based upon a jus in rem,

whilst the personal action, like the actio in personam,

was

based upon a jus in personam.

But

in the English law there


real

was a further

distinction

between

and personal

actions,

a distinction of which the a real action the very thing

Roman law knew


itself

nothing.

In

could be recovered in specie,


satisfied.

and the judgment could not be otherwise


sonal action the

In a per-

payment
point of

by the sum of money. But further (and this is the connexion we are seeking for) a real action could only
satisfied

judgment could always be

of a

be brought in respect of immoveables, and hence immoveables got the name of realty. Moveables, on the other hand, were

always sued for in a personal action, and got the name of


personalty \
1

'

Williams on Real Property, p. 7 and note. Year Book, 6 Hen. VII, fo. 9. Bracton says nunc cum sit res mobilis quae petatur, sicut
: '

leo,

bos

Sec. 129-130.]

PERSONS AND THINGS.

81

130. In

general way, therefore, real things, in the

English law, were things which could be recovered in a real


action
;

in other words, land

and rights over land

and

all

things which could not be so recovered were considered as


personal
:

if

there were any things the nature of which was

doubtful they were set aside as mixed ; and for some purposes
of procedure this rough classification was sufficient.
classification of things into real

But the
Eeal
to

and personal had

to be applied

to a purpose for which greater accuracy was requisite.

things at a man's death go to his


his executor or administrator.
fore, has

heir,

and personal things


its
;

Everything in

turn, there-

had

to be

marked

as real or personal

and the courts


considerable
affixed to

in

making

this notation, though professing genferally to adhere

to the old line of distinction, have

made some

departures from

it.

For example, certain things

the land, such as machinery and the

like, are, nevertheless,

sometimes treated as personal.

Shares in a railway or canal

company
due.

are also considered as personal.

So

is
is

rent actually
real.

But the

right to receive future rent

Leases
Partner-

for lives are sometimes real

and sometimes

personal.

quod consistit in pondere vel mensura, prima facie, quod actio vel placitum esse debeat tarn in rem quam in personam, eo quod certa res petitur, et quod possidenstenetur restituere rem petitam, Sed revera erit in personam tantum, quia ille a, quo res petitur, non tenetur precise ad rem restituendam, sed sub disjunotione, vel ad rem, vel ad precium, et solvendo tantum precium liberatur, sive res appareat, sive non. Et ideo si quis rem mobilem vindicaverit ex quacunque causa ablatam, vel commodatam, debet in actione sua definire Et undo quia non comprecium et sic proponere actionem suam pellitur precise ad rem quae petitur, erit actio in ipsam personam, cum
vel asinus, vestimentum, vel aliud

videtur,

implacitatus per solutionem

tantumdem

possit liberari.'

(Book

III.

102 b, vol. ii.p. 134 of Twiss's edition.) Bracton here expresses, in the language of the Koman Law, a distinction which was quite unknown in that system. The actio in rem was applicable to both moveables and

chap.

i.

fol.

immoveables, and down to a very late period neither one nor the other could be recovered in specie. Afterwards, under the legislation of Justinian, specific restitution could be ordered in any action and in respect of any kind of property. The distinction between the remedies for the
recovery of real and personal property is of German origin. See Gains iv, Beseler, Syst. d. Gem. Deutsch. Privat-K. 86 ; Holtzendorffs I, 2
;

Encycl. Syst. Th. pp. 526, 547, 554.

82

PERSONS AND THINGS.


is

[Chap. Ill

ship property o every kind

personal.

And

land

itself,
;

as

soon as

it

is

agreed to be

sold^

becomes

person9.1

whilst

money agreed
actions
is

to be laid out in land becomes real.

Now

therefore that the distinction between the various kinds of

abolished

it

would be

difEcult to say

more than that


and personal

real things are those

which go to a man's

heir,

things are those which go to his executor or administrator.


Persons.

i3i_

Persons

are

human

beings capable of rights.

To

constitute a

human being

capable of rights two things are

necessary, birth and survival of birth.

What conbirth,

132. There are expressions to be found in English law-

books which look as


mother's
that the

if

the foetus, or even the embryo, in the


^.

womb

were capable of rights

Thus we

find

it

said

unborn child

may

take by devise or inheritance.


of this
is,

But

I think the true

meaning

not that the unborn

child really takes, but that the right until the

is

reserved for the child

moment

of its birth.

This appears also to be the

view of the best German

jurists^.

The framers

of

the

Prussian code state, no doubt, that certain rights, e.g. to be


protected from violence, belong to the unborn child
there
is,
^
:

and

undoubtedly, a duty generally recognised to abstain


child, quite distinct

from injuring the unborn


to abstain

from the duty


is

from injm-ing the mother; a duty which


herself.

imposed

upon the mother


there
is

But

this

may

be a duty to which
is

no corresponding right, and therefore there

no

necessity on this account to attribute

any right
are

to the infant.

The French code uses But the maxim always


in utero est pro

expressions which
relied

ambiguous
'

*.

on by French
This

jurists is
is

qui

jam nato habetur ^.'

fiction,

and

such a fiction
' '

is

only necessary on the assumption that birth


i,

Blackstone's

Comm.

130.

TJuger, Syst. d. Osterr. allgem.


d.

Land-R.

vol.

i,

p,
d.

233

Lehrb.
' * '

Pandekten-R.

a.

52; Vangerow, Lehrb.

Windschied, ; Pandekten, 3a.

See Dig.

i. 5.

7; 50, i6 lag.
;

Land-R. i. x, la Dernburg, Lehrb. Code Civ. art. 725, 906.


Pothier, (Euvres, ed. Buguet, torn.

d. Preuss. Pr.-Eechts,

voL

i.

p. 83.

viii. p. 7

torn.

i.

p. 484.

Sec. 131-133.]
is

PBRSONS AND THINGS.

83
the other hand,
if

a necessary condition of personality.

On

we

take the view that an embryo from the


is

moment

of con-

ception

a person,
it

get rid of
existed.

we must then, if it should never be born, by the contradictory assumption that it never
constitutes

133.

What

birth

has
in

been

very
to

carefully

considered

by English lawyers

reference

the very

common

charge of child-murder.

If the child has not been

born the charge of murder cannot be sustained.


therefore,

The

question,

what

constitutes

birth

is

in

these

cases

a very

important one.
birth, so

The main circumstance which


from the mother^.

constitutes
is

as to render a

charge of murder sustainable,

complete

separation

Nothing

is

said

about maturity, but the use of the word 'child' seems to

assume that the

foetus also be

must have assumed the human shape.


born
alive.

The
be,

child

must

There

is

no other express
vague.
It

requirement.

The French law


called,

requires that the child should


is

what

is

viable^.

This expression

seems to iudicate that the foetus should have advanced to


thati

stage in which
life,

it possesses all

the organs necessary to

continuous
living.

and should be in other respects capable of


is

But

there

always great

difl&culty in

getting an

exact account of the condition of a child dying immediately


after its birth,

and not very carefully examined by any


attempt has been made to meet this

skilled

person

'.

An

difficulty

by a

rule that every child born prior to the hundred

and

eighty-second

day after

conception,

should
of,

be

presumed

incapable of living, and, therefore,

becoming a person.

The Roman law


objection that
it

does not (as has been supposed) countenance


;

any such presumption

and

it

is

open to the very strong

necessitates for its application a determination

of the date of conception with


'

an accuracy which

is

very

Steph. Dig. Crim. Law,

art. 218.

The

division of the navel string is

not necessary.

Code Civ. art. 725, 906. There seems to be a presumption in favour of viability. Codes anuot^s, notes 5, 6, and 7 to Code Civ. art. 725.
2
'

See Sirey,

G3

84
rarely attainable.

PERSONS AND THINGS.


The

[Chap. III.

question whether there should be

any

requirement o vitality beyond the bare survival after the


child has left the

body of

its

mother and the acquisition of


has been

the external

human

shape

much

discussed

by

German

jurists,

but their opinions are based to a large extent


^.

upon the authority of the Roman law


134. There has been

some

disposition to

make

it

a requisi-

tion to the attainment of personality that the child should

have

cried,
is

but the Code of Justinian expressly declares


not requisite, and modern jurists generally take

that this

the same view^.


Death.

135.

A human being

ceases to be a person at death.


difficulties of
is

The

determination of this event presents no

the kind

we have been
is

considering.
difficulty in

If the body

under view there


it

raTely

any
live.

determining whether or no
leaves his

has

ceased to
all

But

if

man

home and

gives

up
all

communication with his family and friends, so that

trace of

him is lost, then it becomes very difficult to determine whether or no he is alive or dead. So also it is sometimes difficult to determine at what exact moment death has taken
^.

place, if tbat determination is necessary

There are certain


but these

rules

which are intended to obviate these

difficulties,

belong to the head of evidence.


Eights

and

136. Ricphts and duties are sometimes attached to an ussve-

duties

attached
eates^of " gates of persons.

gate of

human bemgs

.... m

such a

way

that the individuals


lost sight of
;

composing the aggregate are altogether


'

that

See the subject discussed at length in Savigny, Syst. d. h. r5m. Eechts, ii. Bell. 3 Vangerow, LehrK d. Pandekten, s. 32 and particularly Wachter, Pandekten, s. 40. ^ Code, 6. 29. 3 Sav. Syst. vol. ii. p. 8.
vol.
;

There is no such thing in England now as civil death and there is very little said about it even in our old books. It was of two kinds, that which took place on conviction for certain crimes, and that which took place on becoming a member of a monastic order. See Coke's Reports,
'
:

vol.

ii.

p.

48
3.

Sav. Syst. d. h. rOm. R. vol.


i.

ii.

p. 151

Dernburg, Lehrb.
2.

d.

Preuss. Pr.-R. vol.


Just.
I.

p.

80

Domat,

Liv. prelim. Tit. a. sect.

12

Code

The effect of entering a religious order is very ably 56. I. by Dr. Friedrich Hellmann in a pamphlet entitled Das Gemeine Erbrecht der Religiasen Munich, 1874.
discussed
;

Sec, 134-137.]
isj

PERSONS AND THINGS.


is

85

the aggregate

looked upon as a single person (a fictitious

one of course) to

whom

the rights belong and upon

whom
very-

the duties are imposed.


to

Strange as this conception appears


it
is

us

common.

when we come to reflect upon it, yet As a familiar example of it I will take

the case of
is

the University of Oxford.

The University of Oxford


is

an

aggregate of persons consisting of the Chancellor, Masters,

and Scholars.
to

In common language the University

said

own a
sell,

large

amount

of property, to
actions.

make

contracts, to
is

buy
per-

and

to bring

and defend

This language

fectly accurate.

These things are done, and, in the eye of

the law, not by any individual

member

of the University but

by the University
which compose
he occupies

as a whole.

And

the complete distinctness

of the University, as a person, from the individual members


it, is

seen by this, that

if

any member of the

University occupies (say) a house belonging to the University,


it,

not as being himself owner, but as tenant or

licensee of the University.

So

also if

a member of the UniI were to

versity were to intrude

upon the property of the University So


also
if'

he would commit a

trespass.

make

a contract with the University there would be no 'vinculum


juris
'

whatsoever between myself and the individual members


University.

of the

The contractual
is

relation

would

exist

between
alone.

me and

the fictitious person called the University

The University

always present to our minds as

the person to
137.
.

whom

the rights

and duties are attached 1.

to an

The attribution of a capacity for rights and duties Rights attached -1 i.j.T.iij imagmary person is not to be looked on sunply as } g^riy

..

the resource of an advanced and highly technical system of *^^ .*"


jurisprudence.

The

idea,

though

it

has received considerable

modem
*

development, reaches far back into antiquity.

Some

See the Essay on Juristische Personen in Savigny, Syst. d. h. r6m.

ii. 85 sqq., which is, as usual, moat instructive and inThe Boman lawyers generally said of such an imaginary person 'personam vice fungitur,' and as regards its rights and duties they expressed themselves thus, Si quid universitati debetur singulis non debetur, nee quod debet universitas singuli debent.' Dig. 3. 4. 7. 1.

Eechts, vol.

teresting.

'

86

PERSONS AND THINGS.


we meet with

[Chap. III.
are those in

of the earliest legal conceptions

which rights and duties are attached not to single individuals but to families. Now a family is an aggregate which in
early times formed such
describing.

an imaginary person as

have been

In early times the homestead, the


'of

cattle,

and

the household utensils are spoken

in law as belonging,

not to the individuals family


itself.

who composed
of this

the family, but to the

The reason

I take to have been the

simple one that the law did not advance beyond the threshold
of the family residence.
(if it

The
of,

rights of the family inter se

could be said that there were any) were not yet legal
:

rights

they were disposed


It

not by the law, but by the


therefore, for the

family council.

was enough,
further.

law to say

that the rights belonged to the


defining

family en bloc without


after the rights of

them any

But even

the individual members of the family inter se began to be


lec^ally recognised,

the conception of the family as the subject


still

of legal rights

and duties

remained, and was extended

to artificial aggregates.
.Juristical

138. Continental lawyers call an imaginary person to which


j.jgij^g

persons,

ceived by continentai law''*'

-fjical

^nd duties are attributed a juristical person^- A jurisperson is generally an aggregate of real persons, but
is

there

.,..!,in no difficulty

creating an imaginary person which

not%e

does not contain any real person.

Thus under the Roman


his
it

aggregates ^^^^ ofpersoas.

there was an interval between the death of a person

and the assumption of the inheritance by

...

successor.

During

this period the

Roman

lawyers found

very incon-

venient that there should be no one to represent the estate.


Thibaut uses the expression 'Gemeinheit,' which Lord Justice Lindley But Thibaut's original definition of a Gemeinheit would hardly coincide with what is called a corporation in the English law. From Lord Justice Lindley's translation it would appear that this definition was modiiied by the author in later editions, but I have not been able to ascertain exactly how. It would seem, however, that Thibaut was disposed to substitute for 'juristical person' the expression 'moral person.' See Thibaut, Syst. of Pandects Law, General Part, s. 113, transl. by Lindley. The same expression is used in the Italian Civil Code, art. 3. This is a new abuse of a term already pretty well misused.
1

translates 'corporation.'

Sec. 138, 139.]

PERSONS AND THINGS.


itself

87

Accordingly they made the estate


persoHj or, as the phrase was,
'

into

an imaginary

haereditas personae vice f ungi-

tur/
the

So in order to have some person who could represent


claims
of

the public they created another imaginary


fiscus or treasury.

person called the


139. There
is

a natural tendency whenever we consider How they


*"^^*

a group of rights and duties as connected with a particular

ed?

thing to speak of them as belonging to that thing


example,
hospital
pital
'
;

i;

For

if

property be given for the maintenance of a


naturally speak of
is it

we

as 'belonging to the hos-

made with some three or four persons who are jointly carrying On trade we speak of it as a contract made with the firm.^ So when a man has become insolvent we speak of the property which is divisible
SO if a contract
'

amongst

his creditors as 'belonging to his estate.^

So

also

we

speak of rent being due from the land, of an estate being

liable for a debt for

which

it is

mortgaged, and so forth.

If the rights and duties thus spoken of were really attri-

buted to the hospital, the firm, the

estate, or the land, there

would

in each case be a juristical person.

But

if

we examine
is

these cases more closely

we

shall often, find that there

a natural person to

whom

the right or duty in question really

belongs, and that these expressions are only used to indicate

the extent of the right or duty, and

how

it

is

transferred.

when we say that an do not mean that the owner


Thus,
estate

estate

is

liable for
is

a debt, we
liable,

of the estate

not

but

that the liability can be enforced by seizing or selling the

whoever

may happen
If that
is

to be the owner,

and that on the

transfer of the estate this liability of the estate passes over to

the transferee.

our meaning there

is

no

juristical

person, but only the use of a figurative expression which indicates

shortly

the legal situation, but does not fully or


it.

accurately describe

This tendency

tions.

is by no means confined to lawyer's and to legal relaIn common language we use such expressions as a school gaining
'

a distinction,' or 'a club getting into

debt.'

88
Difference

PERSONS AND THINGS,

[Chap. III.

140. All lawyers agree that juristical persons should be

amou'^t"" created to
continen- ^s to
yers.

some

extent.

But

there

is

a difference of opinion
as to

what

are juristical persons,

and

what

is

necessary

for their creation.

Some
is

persons would allow that the estate


juristical
is

of a deceased person

person
so.

',

but would not

allow that the public treasury

Others again,

who

would admit the public treasury, would not admit the land
subject to burdens.
Opinion of indicated.

The

real question

seems to be that just

To whom do the
in a court of

rights

and duties belong ? Is the

lasers,

person
sents

who

law or in a legal transaction repre-

those rights

and duties acting on his own behalf,


fictitious creation

or on behalf of

some

which acts through


it is

him ? This
this latter

is

substantially the
it is

same question, and

in

form that
is

generally put by English lawyers.


particular

When

an inquiry
is

made whether a
it

thing or

aggregate

a juristical person, they always consider one

point only, namely, whether or no


If
it

has capacity to act.

has capacity to act

it

is

a juristical person, other-

wise not^
Juristical
p(,t

141.

Of
it

course this capacity to act

is

also

an

ideal capacity

though

produces real

effects.

An

ideal being

can never

ho.

.rough

really act, but it can be represented


act,

by a

real person

who can

''^Jisenta-

and can create duties and obligations on behalf of the

'

juristical person

by way

of representation.
so in reality,

The

act of the

representative,

though not

may

conveniently be

treated as to

all its

legal effects exactly as if it


;

were the act

of the juristical person

and where the

ideal creation has this

s. 89 TTnger, System d. 6sterr. allgem. 317 Holtzendorff, Jurist. Encyc. s. v. Stiftungen. ^ The figurative language in which lawyers attribute rights and duties to things or aggregates is, of course, very important, because it may, in ^

See Sav. Syst.

d. h.
i.

rBm. Kechts,
;

Privat-Rechts, vol.

p.

effect, define

the rights

and duties themselves.

Thus when
is liable,

a judge says

that an estate (meaning perhaps a piece of land)


to assert

he

may

intend

and

to define the liability of the present

owner

of the estate.

So when, in a recent case. Sir William James, by a rather daring use of language, spoke of the estate of a deceased person as a 'co-contractor,' he both affirmed and at the same time limited the liability of the representatives.

See

Law

Eeports, Chancery Appeals, vol. ix. p. 343.

Sec. I40-I43-3

PEESONS AND THINGS.

89

capacity of acting through a representative,

EngHsh lawyers

allow that

it

is

a juristical person,

or,

as

we

call

it

in

England, a corporation^.

And

the term corporation with us

implies the attribution of the capacity to act through a representative.

This

is

so clear, that

when

a corporation

is

created

the capacity to act need not be specially granted.


it is possible

So far as

that acts should be done through a representa-

tive it will be

presumed that a corporation

may

do those

acts,

provided that they are consistent with the purpose for which

the corporation was created.


142.

Corporations in

England

consist

of aggregates
said,

of Corpora-

persons, but, as appears from

what has been already

the England
are always aggregates of persons:

iuristical person, the corporation, is > > > r r

from the persons who compose


no change
in the

it:

something totally distinct J o and hence it follows that


the

persons

who compose
is

corporation but a

produces any change in the corporation. goes out of a company which

If one shareholder the mem^ a corporation and another ^^^^ ^^^


cor'
'

comes

in,

the corporation

still

remains the same corporation the

as before.

The shareholders of the New River Company have been all changed over and over again since its formation,
and yet the
rights
juristical person, the corporation, to

^'^

whom

all

the

and duties are attached, has been one and the same
its

continuously from
143.

creation.

The view that the

individual

members

of the cor- even

poration are not the owners, not even the co-owners, of the the memcorporate property, which is undoubtedly the true view, is l^ers man-

sometimes obscured by the circumstance that the members of property


the corporation have in their
'

own hands

the

management

of poration
in their

not sure that some questions may not arise on the language of o^"^ ^^Order 48 a, rr. i, 3, and 8, of the Eules of the Supreme Court which provide that partners may sue and be sued in the name of the firm. It was, of course, not intended to make every firm a corporation, but these rules
I

am

seem

to give a firm capacity to act,

and

also to treat a firm as the

owner

of property,

and

this is going a long

way

towards making a firm a cor-

See also a case where a society which was not incorporated, and which was not a partnership, was notwithstanding held liable to be
poration.

sued in the name of the society Appeal Cases of 1901, p. 426.

Allen

v.

Flood reported in

Law Reports,

90

PERSONS AND THINGS.

[Chap. III.

the property of the corporation, and have also a right to apply the profits of
it

to

their

own

use.

Thus

in a municipal

corporation, or corporation of a town, the freemen,

who

are

the persons

right to regulate the


to

who compose the corporation, have very often the common lands adjacent to the town, and So too a shareholder in turn out their own cattle there.

a railway company has a right to vote at meetings and to Still the receive his share of the profits of the undertaking.

freeman has only what


he might have
if

is

called a jus in alieno solo, just as

he were not a freeman.


is

So the shareholder's
If he were to help

right to his dividend

a claim by him against the company,

a debt due to

him from the company.


theft.

himself to his dividend out of the company^s cash-box he

would commit a
Corpora-

144.

corporation can, of course, be created

by

act of

created in parliament,

and

many
seal.

corporations

are

so

created.
letters

The
patent

England.

]^|jjg. j^g^g g^jg^

povper to create corporations

by

under

the

great

Private
will

persons

cannot

create

corporation at their

own

and pleasure, but under the

authority and restrictions of certain acts of parliament any

number
Corpora-

of persons, not less than seven,

may by
1.

following the

prescribed forms become a corporation

145. There

is

a curious thing which


sole.

we meet with
corporation sole

in
is

English law called a corporation

always some sort of ofBcer, generally an ecclesiastical

officer.

Rights and duties are frequently attached to an


purposes of his
office office

officer for

the

only.

When

an

officer

vacates his
;

these rights and duties pass to his successors

and

it

being convenient to distinguish the rights and duties which


attach to a
jure

man jure

proprio from those which attach to

him

officii, it is

permissible to speak of the latter as attached,


office
j

not to the man, but to his

just as it is permissible to

speak of rights and duties which pass with the land from
' It is a general rule that juristical persons cannot be created except by the express authority of the ruling power given specially or generally. This was a rule of the Eoman law; Dig. Bk. xlvii. tit. 22. See the

Italian Civil Code, art.

2.

Sec. 144, I45-]

PERSONS AND THINGS.


as attached to the land.
is

91
this

owner to owner
is

But

language
the one

merely figurative, and there

no doubt that,

as, in

case, the rights

and

duties spoken of as attached to the land

are really attached to the natural persons

who

are successively

owners of the land,

so, in

the other case, the rights and duties


office are really

spoken of as attached to the


natural persons

attached to the
office.

who

are the successive holders of the


' is,

The term
tions sole

'

corporation sole

therefore, as it appears to

me,

a misnomer.
is

The
sole,
is

selection of persons

a purely arbitrary one.

a corporation

and

so is
^,

who are styled corporaThe King is said to be a parson. But the Secretary of
is

State for India


at least as

not so

nor

an executor ; though there

is

good reason why both these persons should be

treated as corporations sole as a parson.

And on an examination
it

of the position of so-called corporations sole

will be seen

that they are not

-really juristical persons,

but only natural

persons peculiarly situated

as

regards the acquisition and

incurring of rights and duties^.


^

The Secretary of

State for India not only exercises powers but

incuM

liabilities virtute officii.

This

is

because he represents the dissolved East

India Company, of which he is the universal successor. If the conception of a coi-poration sole (with the substitution perhaps of a less ridiculous

name) could be extended to all cases where rights and duties were attached to an office it would be convenient. ' This I think is the result of what Grant says about -corporations sole. See Grant on Corporations, especially p. 635.

CHAPTEE
DUTIES

IV.

AND

EIGHTS.
what
is

146. I have hitherto considered

meant by the

term

'

law/ where
to

it is

to be found,

and what are the persons

and things
Duty.

which

it relates.

I
it.

now

proceed to consider

the relations which arise out of


14.7.

Every law

is

the direct or indirect

command

of the

sovereign authority, addressed to persons generally, bidding

them
is

to do or not to do a particular thing or set of things

and the necessity which the persons to


addressed are under to obey that law 148.
is

whom

the
'

command

called a

duty.'

The word ' duty

"

does not belong exclusively to law.


it is

Thus

it is

frequently said that

our duty to revere God,

or to love our parents. of duty,

But

in this place,

when we speak

we

refer only to such duties as arise out of positive

law.
Right.

149. 'Right'

is

a term which, in

its

abstract sense,

it is

in the highest degree difficult to define.

Fortunately, w^here

the term

is

used to describe a particular relation or class

of relations,
to

and not

as

an abstract expression of
it is

all relations

which the name may be applied,


is it

far easier to conceive.

Nor

impossible to explain some of the ideas which the


;

term connotes

and

this is

what

I shall attempt to do here.


;

150. Every right corresponds to a duty


unless there
is

no right can
it.

exist

a duty exactly correlative to

On

the other
its

hand,

it

is

not necessary that every duty should have

corresponding right.

There

are,

lq

fact,

many

duties

to

DUTIES AI^D RIGHTS.


which there are no corresponding rights^to animals, to serve certain public offices

93

For example,

there are duties imposed upon us to abstain from cruelty

when

called upon,
;

and

to abstain

from

certain acts of immorality

but there

are no rights corresponding to these duties, at least none

belonging to any determinate person.

If

it is

asserted that
it

a right exists at

all

in the cases I have put,


j

must be

meant that

it

belongs to society at large


'

but, as used

by

lawyers, the term

right

'

indicates something

which

is attri-

buted to a determinate person or body of persons.


151.

Of

course, as every right corresponds to a duty,


is

and

as every duty

created directly or indirectly

by the sovereign

authority, so rights are created directly or indirectly

by the

sovereign authority also.

And
it,

as the

term 'duty' implies

that

its

observance

is

capable of being, and will be enforced


so also the term
'

by the power which


152.

creates

right ' implies

protection from the same source.

A
is

right has sometimes been described as a faculty

or power of doing or not doing.

faculty or
;

power

of

doing

undoubtedly the result of some rights

for instance,

the right of ownership enables us to deal with our property


as

we

like,

because others are obliged to abstain from interso.

fering with our doing

But we can

hardly, I think,

identify the right with this faculty or power.

153. It

is

essential to every legal duty,


it

and therefore
This
is

to Eightsand
specific

every legal right, that


because otherwise
it

should be

specific.

necessary

cannot be ascertained whether or no


it

the

command on which

rests

has been obeyed.

If the

legislature

were simply to command parents to educate their

children, without saying

what constituted
but
it

education, such a

law would not be


because

ineffectual,

could only become effectual

its deficiencies

would be supplied by some authority


itself.

other than the legislature

Before

we can punish a
is

man
to

for breaking the law something

more

necessary than

make education
'

in general terms compulsory.


lii. p.

Somebody,

Austin, Lecture

356 (third

ed.).

94

DUTIES AND EIGHTS,

[Chap. TV.
or,

such as a board of education constituted for the purpose,


in default of such a body, the tribunals

which administer the


ages at which the

law^ must have power to settle all the particulars which have

not been settled by the legislature

the

children are to be sent to school, the period during

which

they are to remain, the penalty to be incurred

by

their not

doing
plied

so,

and so

forth.

If the defects in the law were sup-

by a board under the powers conferred upon them there


legislation

would be

on these subjects in the ordinary sense

by a competent subordinate authority. If they were supplied by the tribunals there would be legislation of an indirect
kind which would be called by the name of interpretation.
Sovereign

154. It being

moreover the essential nature of a duty


of

no

rights,

^^^^

i^

*li6

result

a command^

it

follows that

it

is

*'*h''^tT*
duties.

iiecessarily

imposed upon some person other than th& person


the

who

issues

command.

No man,
is

figure of speech, can be said to issue

except by a strong commands to himself.

Every

legal

duty, therefore,

imposed by the sovereign


itself.
it is

body on some person other than


155. It
is

equally true, though

a truth by no means

so easy to grasp, that every right belongs to a person other

than the sovereign body which creates

it.

This, like

most

truths which result directly from fundamental conceptions,


is

scarcely capable of demonstration, yet

it

would

not, I think,

have ever been brought into doubt, had

it

not been for a slight

confusion of language, which I shall endeavour to remove.


156.
itself

Though the

sovereign authority cannot confer upon


citizen, it

a right against a
specific

may

impose upon a citizen


itself, as, for

a duty to do a
to pay a certain

thing towards

instance,

sum

of

money

into the

Government treasury

and

this will result in a relation very closely analogous to

the ordinary one of debtor and creditor.

tax, or a fine,

imposed upon a subject


debt to the Crown, and
to that
157.

is is

indeed constantly spoken of as a


recovered by a process analogous

by which ordinary debts are recovered.

But between the

so-called

rights

of

the

sovereign

Sec. 154-158.]

DUTIES AND BIGHTS.

95

to a tax, or a fine, and the right o a citizen to receive

a debt from a fellow-citizen, there


essential differences.

are, as it

seems to me,

The

citizen holds his right to recover

his debt,

but can only exercise and enjoy that right at the

will

and pleasure of another, namely, the sovereign who


it

conferred

upon him.

The sovereign power, on the


fine,
is

other

hand, which imposed the tax or

also

the

power

which enforces
debt, which
is

it.

Moreover, the right to payment of a

possessed

by the
its

citizen, is

not only dependent

on the will of another for


it is

exercise

and enjoyment, but

limited

by that

will;

and nothing but the external


Whereas, in the case of
specific

sovereign power can change the nature of the legal relation between debtor and creditor.

a tax or

fine,

although the sovereign has expressed in

terms, and therefore for the

moment

limited, the

duty to

be performed towards
sovereignty that
at

itself, it

follows from the nature of


will

by the sovereign
would

the duty
is

may be
difiiculty

any moment changed.

And though

there

no

in conceiving the duty -which


sive

arise

upon each

succes-

command,

it is

impossible to conceive a right of so flue^

tuating a character;
easily as a duty,

not because
its holder.

a right cannot change as

but because we cannot conceive a right as

changing at the will of

158. Looking to the habit that prevails of enforcing those


duties

which the sovereign body has directed


itself

to be performed

towards
in

by

a procedure nearly similar in

form

to that

common

use for the enforcement of duties which have to

be performed by citizens towards each other,


understand, that the former
latter,

we

should readily

class of duties, as well as the

had come

to be considered as

having correlative rights.

Nor, when confined to such duties as the payment of taxes


or fines,

would there be any objection to the extension of


fiction, to

the term 'right,' by a sort of

the claims of the

Crown.

It

is,

however, with reference to political discussions

that the distinction becomes of importance.


respect

Knowing

the

which men have for

legal rights,

and the feeling

96

DUTIES
all

AND

EIGHTS.

[Chap. IV.

which

men have

that legal rights ought to be secure,

politicianSj

especially the partisans of authority, constantly

base the claims of the sovereign body on the simple assertion that they are rights.

Nor

(as

in a phrase to

which

I have already adverted) are the partisans of liberty,


it

when

serves their turn, reluctant to assert that the people have

rights against the


strip off

Government; though
(so-called) rights the

it is

more easy to

from these

appearance of being

founded in law.

If both sides were ready with the answer,

that these are only rights in the sense of being sanctioned

by morality,

or the general usages of

mankind; and that

they are not rights in the sense in which we speak of rights


of property and personal security
;

then, I think, the assertion

would

lose

a great part of

its force, its

and the discussion would

be more easily reduced to

true ground, namely,


^.

what

is

expedient for the Welfare of the people at large

159. Austin sums up the characteristics of right, on which

I have last insisted, as follows


therefore,'

"
:

'

To every
:

legal

right,

he

says,

'

there are three parties

the sovereign

government of one or a number which

sets the positive law,

and which through the

positive

law confers the legal right,


:

and imposes the

relative duties
is

the person or persons on

whom

the right
is

conferred

the person or persons on the positive law


is

whom
set or

the duty
directed.'
'

imposed, or to

whom

The proposition that a sovereign body has no

to duties has been denied.

rights and is not subject For the reasons stated in the text I adhere to

As instances to the contrary King to take criminal proceedings, and the right of the subject to proceed by way of Petition of Eight. That the King himself may be party to a proceeding is not denied, but this he may well be without the assertion of any right vested in that body which constitutes the sovereign body in Great Britain and as to the proceedings by way of Petition of Right, they seem to me to be carefully framed so as to avoid giving even the semblance of a judgment against the Crown. If there is a judgment against any one it is against the Commissioners of
are given the right of the
;

the Tiew which I had already expressed.

the Treasury.

4th
"

ed., p.

no;

See 23 & 24 Viet., u. 34. a. 14 Holland's Jurisprudence, i Kent, Comm. 297, note c. (There is some error in the
;

reference given in Kent's note.)


Lect. vi. p. 291 (third ed.).

Sec. 159-163.]

DUTIES AND RIGHTS.

97

160. Rights generally exist in respect of some specific Some

person or thing which

is

called the object of the right.

For "fye no
the.'^*^'^''

example, the right of the purchaser of a house to have

house delivered to him by the vendor, or the right of a master ject.


to the labour of his hired servant.

But

there are some rights


as,

which

have no determinate object,

for

example,

the

right of a

man

to his

good name.

Rights which have no


'.

determinate object are rights to forbearances merely


161.

Every right

resides in a determinate person or persons. But


is

all

and whenever a duty


162.

to be performed towards or in respect a deteris


-"^

of a determinate person that person ^

invested with a riffht "

^.

'"''^**

person or

we

see that

Making the various combinations which we may have (i) rights of persons over
;

are possible, persons.

persons; Law of

(2) rights of persons over things

or forbear in respect of persons or forbear in respect of things.


chiefly concern, the rights

(3) duties of persons to act and *hg^(4) duties of persons to act

Laws which concern,

or which

and duties

of persons in respect

of persons, have been sometimes classed together and called

the law of persons

and laws which concern, or which


called the

chiefly

concern, the rights and duties of persons in respect of things,

have been likewise classed together and


things.
163. of

law of

The

chief, in

my

opinion the only, use of a division Rights


of things
is

of

law into the law of persons and the law

as and

a convenient arrangement of topics in a ^ As used for this purpose I shall speak of

^^ treatise or a code. *"'"S^' erroneous it hereafter. But classifica-

by

slightly changing the terms in

which

this classification is

expressed, Blackstone has introduced an important error, which


it is desirable

to notice here.

He

speaks not of the law of

persons and of the law of things, but of rights of persons


' '

Austin, Lect. xv. p. 400.


J. S.

Mill (Essays, vol. iii. p. 228) objects to this view of a right that compels us to say that a prisoner has a right to be imprisoned. I do not think so. When the law has a human being for its object, there is no duty to be performed for or towards that being. The human being is looked upon as airpiaaiiros or, as Heineccius puts it (Elem. Jur. i. 135), in the case of the filius familias, respectu patris res habebatur. This was the general condition of slaves. See Austin, Lect. xv. p. 398.
it
;

98

DUTIES
of things^.

AND

RIGHTS.
of persons

[Chap. IV,

and o rights
undoubtedly
;

Rights

there

are

for all rights are such.

There

may

be also
of,

rights over things^

and rights
to,

over persons j

but rights
of,

that
isj

isj

belonging

things, as opposed to rights

that

belonging
164.

to, persons, there

cannot be ^.
only as against one or

Eights in

Sometimes a right

exists

personam,

more
of the

individuals, capable of being ascertained


it

and named;

sometimes

exists

generally against

all

persons,

members
the right
it

same
or,

political society as the

person to

whom

belongs;
exists

as

is

commonly

said,

somewhat arrogantly,

against

the world at large.

Thus

in the

case of

a contract between

A and

B, the right of

to

demand

performance of the contract exists against

only; whereas

in the case of ownership, the right to hold

and enjoy the

property exists against persons generally.

This distinction

between rights
the Latin
:

is

marked by the use of terms derived from


;

the former are called rights in personam

the

latter are called rights in r^m.

165.

The term

'

right in

rem "

is

a very peculiar one

translated literally it
it

would mean nothing.

The use

of

in conjunction with the term 'in personam' as the basis

of a classification of actions in the

Roman law

has been

explained above

^,

and
in

its

meaning

will be further illustrated

by two passages
tit. %. sec. 9,

the Digest of Justinian.


is

In Book
is

iv.

the rule of law

referred to

that what
:

done

under the influence of fear should not be binding

and compar-

menting on

this it is
'

remarked, that the lawgiver speaks

here generally and

in

rem/ and does not specify any

ticular kind of persons

who

cause the fear; and that there-

fore the rule of

law

applies,

whoever the person


it

may

be.

Again, in Book

xliv. tit. 4. sec. 2,

is it

laid

down

that, in
specially

what we should

call
is

a plea of fraud,

must be

stated whose fraud


' ^
'

complained

of,

'and not in rem.'

On

Analysis (passim) prefixed to the earlier editions of the Commentaries. Of course 'persons' here include 'juristical persons.'
Supra,
sect. 129.

Sec. 164-168.]

DUTIES AND EIGHTS.


it

99

the other hand,


fraud
said
is

is

pointed out that,


of, it is

if it is

shown whose
need not be

complained

sufficient;

and

it

whom

the fraud was intended to injure; for (says the


is

author of the Digest) the allegation that the transaction


void,

by reason
In

of the fraud of the person

named,
is

is

made

'in rem.'

all these

three cases 'in rem'

used as an

adverb, and I think


its

exact equivalent,

we should express as nearly as possible if we substituted for it the English word


it is

'generally.'

In the phrase 'right in rem'

used as an

adjective,

and the equivalent English expression would be


is

a 'general right'; but a more explicit phrase


availing against the world at large
'
:

a 'right

and

if this,

which

is

the true meaning of the phrase 'right in rem,' be carefully

remembered, no mistake need occur.

On

the other hand,

if

we attempt

to translate the phrase literally,

and get

it

into
it,

our heads that a thing, because rights exist in respect of

becomes a sort of

juristical person,

and

liable to duties,

we

shall get into endless confusion.

166.

The term

'

right in personam,' on the other hand,


particular

means a right which can be asserted against a


person, or set of persons, and no others.
167.

The persons

to

whom

a right in rem belongs

may

be changed to any extent within the limits allowed by the


law, but the persons upon

whom

the duty corresponding to


all

a right in rem

is

imposed cannot be changed, because


Either the persons to

persons are under that duty.

a right in personam belongs, or the persons

duty corresponding to a right in personam

is

whom on whom the imposed, may

be changed within the limits allowed by the law ^.


168. I will

now
'

endeavour, not without misgiving, to Meaning


'

explain the term

status

or

'

condition,' about

which much

status or condition.

1 It is necessary to distingtush carefully between a right in rem and real right is a right over a specific thing (a jus a (so-called) real right. in re, as will be explained hereafter). Thus a right of ownership is

a real right

it is also

a right in rem.

But a right to personal safety

is

not a real right, though it is a right in rem. The other use of the term 'real,' as opposed to 'personal,' has been explained above, sect. 129.

H %

100

DUTIES AI^D RIGHTS.

[Chap. IV.

has been written^ but, as the writers themselves generally


confess, without

much

result.

I shall confine myself to the

use of these words by

modern English lawyers.


if

169. It will, I think, clear the ground

we remember
in-

that rights and duties

may

depend, either upon the previous

assent of the parties affected

by them, or they may be


I say that they
parties

dependent of that assent.

When

may depend
by them,

upon the previous assent of the


I

affected

mean

this

that without
j

such assent they would not come


is

into existence

the assent of the parties

not the cause of

their existence, but the sine qua non.

170. So there are rights and duties which, though they

depend,

in the

sense

above stated,

on the assent of the

parties affected

by them,

will, nevertheless,

when they have

once come into existence, not be changed, or prolonged, or

ended at the desire of the


171.

parties.

And

again, there are other rights and duties which

not only depend on the assent of the parties affected by

them, but which remain dependent on that assent, in this


sense

that they

may,

at

any time,

if

the parties assent, be


latter case

changed, prolonged, or ended.


said to

In the

they are

depend upon contract.

172. Lastly, there are rights and duties which are attached
to persons in

common with

the whole community

there are

other rights and duties which are attached, not to the whole

community, but to every member of certain classes of persons


in the

community

and there are again other rights and

duties which are attached only to individuals

and not

to the

whole community, or to any classes of


178.

it.

Of

the rights and duties which depend upon the assent

of the parties affected

by them, some may depend upon the

assent of an individual, others

may depend upon

the concur-

rent assent, the consensus as


174.

it is called,

of several individuals. to

The

rights

and duties which attach

the

com-

munity generally might conceivably depend upon


but never upon contract.

assent,

Those which attach to certain

'

860.169-177.]
classes

DUTIES AND EIGHTS.


or

lO'l
'^

may,

may

not,

depend upon contract.

Those also

which attach to individuals may or may not depend upon


contract.

175.

As an example

of the rights

and

duties

attaching

to the

members o the community

generally, I

may

give

the right to personal safety, and the duty to abstain from


trespass.

Most persons enjoy


birth.

this right

and are subject to

But a person may acquire this right and become subject to this duty by his own act, when a foreigner comes to reside in this country. As an example of the rights and duties attaching to a class, and not dependent
this

duty by reason of

on contract, I
as such.

may give the may observe that

rights

and duties of a

soldier

soldier,

though he generally

gives his assent to enter the army, never

makes a contract
and duties
of the community,

on that occasion.

As an example

of the rights

attaching to an individual, not as a


or as one of a class,

member

and dependent on contract, I may give

the rights and duties of

A who

has agreed with

to work for

him.

individual, not as a

As an example of the rights and duties attaching to an member of the community, or as one of
and not dependent on contract (an example which
find),
it

a
is

class,

not easy to

may

give the rights and duties of

Lord Hobhouse

as commissioner for settling the disputes in

Epping Forest under the 41 & 42, Vict. c. 213. 176. Now when we speak of 'status' or 'condition'' we always mean, I believe, some aggregate of rights and duties
attached to a person, and the difficulty there
plaining the meaning of the word
arises
'

is
'

about excondition

status

'

or

from

its

being used sometimes for one such aggregate


for another.

and sometimes

We may apply it
It

to the aggre-

gate of rights and duties

which attach to a man as a member


would be permissible to speak

of the general community. of the


177.
'

status

'

or

'

condition ' of a citizen.


'

But the word

status' or

'

condition'

is also,

and more

generally, used to express the aggregate of rights

and duties

which are attached to a person as one of a

class.

Thus

102

DUTIES AND RIGHTS.


of the
'

[Chap. IV.

we may speak
178. at

status
child.

"

or 'condition^ of a parent,

a husband, a wife, or a

But I do not think that, where " accuracy, we use the word ' status or
of rights

there
'

is

any attempt
'

condition
is

to express

any aggregate

and duties which


so as to be

capable of being

changed, prolonged, or ended at the desire of the persons

who
in

are affected

by them,

always under their

control.

The rights and duties modern times, for example,


'

of a master or a servant are

not
are

usually described

as
'

status

'

or

'

condition.^

They

what are
other

called

mere matters

of

contract

^.'

On

the

hand, the

rights

and duties of parent and child are only to a very small extent under the control of the parties, and are usually described as a status " or a condition." The rights and duties
' '

of

husband and wife are coming more and more under their
control,
'

own
from

and, therefore,
"

we say that they


"

are passing

status

or

'

condition

to contract.
'

179. Another

mark which

will serve to distinguish

status

'

or 'condition,'' if

we

use

these

terms in the sense above

suggested,

is

that breaches of the duties comprised in

them

do not give

rise

to that particular kind of remedy which the

law provides for breaches of contract, even when the rights


violated depend

upon a contract for


cases be

their existence.

There

would in many
There
is

no

difficulty in

giving this remedy.

no reason

why

a husband should not sue his wife to

SlaTery is usually described as a status or condition. If in any country slavery were a recognised institution the status of slavery might he acquired by assent. And in any country the liberty of an individual may be largely curtailed, either by his assenting to belong to a particular

a soldier, or by his making a contract, as, e.g. a domestic Consequently the line between slavery and free service is not one which is easily dravyn. Bentham thinks that the distinguishing
class, as, e.g.

servant.

mark
I

of slavery is the perpetuity of the service (see Works, vol. i. p. 344). disposed rather to attach importance to the consideration whether the class is put under some degrading disabilities not necessary to the

am

performance of their duties under their masters. I may observe that recently the Legislature has interfered a good deal between masters and servants, imposing certain liabilities on the master for the px-oteotiou of
the servant which the master cannot get rid
of.

Sec. 178-183.]

DUTIES AND EIGHTS.

103

compel her to return to him on the contract made at the


marriage.

But

this

is

never allowed.
contract) as
is

He may
it

sue her, but

in a different way^

The

were^ comes to

an

end as soon as the condition

brought into existence.


is

Even

when a husband and


of separation, which
their
is

wife enter into what

called a deed

a formal contract affecting extensively


duties, neither of
it

mutual rights and

them can sue the

other upon the promise which

contains
is

^,

180. It will

now

be seen what

meant by the saying


is

so often quoted that the progress of society

from status

to contract.

What

I think

is

meant

isj

that the rights and

duties which are attached to individuals as


class are

members of a
and

coming gradually more and more under the control


more frequently

of those upon whose assent they came into existence j that the remedy for any breach of them
is

now than
tract.

formerly the ordinary remedy for breaches of conis

This

obviously the case with the rights and duties


serva,nt
:

which attach to master and

and

it

is

even begin-

ning to show itseK very strongly in the relations of husband

and
an

wife.

181. Duties are either to


act.

do an act or to forbear from doing Duties


is

When
;

the law obliges us to do an act the duty

negat^e'^

called positive

when the law


is

obliges us to forbear

from doing

an

act,

then the duty

called negative.

182. Duties are further divided into relative and absolute. Eelative

Absolute duties are those to which there


right belonging to
as, for

is

no corresponding body of persons

jute.

any determinate person

or

instance, the duty to serve as a soldier, or to

pay

taxes.

Relative duties are those to which there

is

a cqr^

responding right in some person or definite body of persons


as, for instance, the

duty or obligation to pay one's debts.

183

^.

Duties are also divided into primary, and secondary Primary,

or sanctioning.
'

Primary duties are those which


until recently.

exist per se, dary^or"


j

This was the law marriage from Status to contract has been taken in the Married Woman's

But another step in reducing

Property Act of 1883.


^

Austin, Lect. xlv. p. 787 (third edition).

104

DUTIES

AND

RIGHTS.

[Cbap. IV.

and independently of any other duty; secondary or sanctioning duties are those which have no independent existence,
hut only exist for the sake of enforcing other duties. Thus the duty to forbear from personal injury is a primary one
hut the duty to pay a

man damages
is

for the injury

which

I have done to his person


rio'ht

secondary or sanctioning.

The
called

which corresponds
duty

to a

primary relative duty

is

a primary right.
or sanctioning

The right which corresponds


is

to a secondary

called a secondary or sanctioning right.

184.

The

series

of

duties

in

which are comprised the


exist

original primary one

and those which


it^

merely for the

purpose of enforcing

very often, indeed generally, extends

beyond two.
is

Thus

I contract to build I omit to do so,


is

you a house; that and I am,


therefore,

the primary duty.

ordered to pay damages ; that


to

the secondary duty.


therefore ordered to

I omit

pay the damages, and I


;

am
as

go

to

prison

that

is

also called a secondary duty,

though

it

comes

third in the series.

And
is

if,

we

are at liberty to do, as

we

look upon the duty to pay damages


one, the expression

now

the primary

not incorrect.

The terms primary and

secondary will thus express the relation between any two


successive terms of the series.

Obhgations.

jgg
a right

Where

the duty
'
_

is

relative, that '

is, '

where there
this

is

corresponding
is

to

the

duty,

and where
not

cor-

responding right

a right available,

generally, but

against a particular person or persons (not in

rem but

in

personam), the duty


186.

is called

an obligation i.
enforce

The secondary

or

sanctioning duties which

primary absolute duties are themselves always absolute; that


is

to say, there is

no right to enforce such duties belonging


or

to

any determinate person

body of persons other than the

sovereign body.
' It is I think a matter of regret that the word obligation ' is not adopted as a technical term of English law in the sense above indicated, instead of confining it to a small class of contracts. We certainly require some general term to express the relation to each other of two persons, one of whom has a specific duty to perform in respect of the other.
'

Sec. 184-190.]

DUTIES

AND

EIGHTS.

105

187.

On

the other hand^ secondary or sanctioning absolute

duties are used to enforce primary relative duties also.

Thus
some-

the primary relative duty of a servant to his master

is

times enforced by the provisions of the criminal laWj by

means

of a fine or imprisonment;

and

as these relative duties

have, generally speakings each their relative secondary or

sanctioning duty or obligation

also,

they are in such cases

doubly enforced.

Thus

if

a man's property be wilfully insuffer the

jured, there arises the absolute duty to

punish-

ment

for

mischief or trespass,

and the

relative

duty or

obligation to

make compensation

to the party injured.

188. Secondary or sanctioning absolute duties are for the

most part the pains and


law.

penalties imposed

by the criminal

I shall have occasion to discuss hereafter

how

far they

are resorted to in civil procedure.

189. Primary relative duties correspond either to primary


rights in rem, or to primary rights in personam.

Those which

correspond to primary rights in rem are for the most part

negative;

that

is

to

say, they are duties to forbear

from
Their

doing anything which


general nature

may

interfere with those rights.

may

be best seen by considering the nature

of the rights to which they correspond.

Thus there

are the

large classes of rights comprised respectively under the terms

ownership, possession, personal liberty, and personal security.

These are

all

primary rights in rem, and the corresponding

duties are to forbear

from

acts

which infringe these

rights.

Primary

relative duties corresponding to rights in

personam
rights

are chiefly those

which are created by

contract.

The

comprised in the relations of family, of husband and wife,


of parent

and

child,

guardian and ward, and other similar

relations, are partly

primary rights in rem, and partly primary

rights in personam.

Thus the right of a father


is

to

the

custody of his child


of a

a right in rem; the conjugal rights

husband over

his wife are rights in personam.

190. Secondary or sanctioning relative duties, which arise

on the non-observance of primary ones, are for the most

106

DUTIES AND EIGHTS,


by
civil

part penalties and forfeitures whicli are enforced


as distinguished from criminal procedure.
Sanctions.

191.

In speaking of those duties which have no indein.

pendent existence, but only exist


duties, I

order to enforce other

have resorted to the somewhat clumsy expedient

of calling

them

'

secondary or sanctioning/ in order to keep

in view both their characteristics,

that

they

exist only for

the sake of enforcing other duties, and that they enforce


these duties

by means
desirable

of a sanction.
to conceive clearly the nature of a

192. It
sanction.

is

A command,

as Austin has pointed out

^,

'

is

a sig-

nification of desire, but a

command
is

is

distinguished from

other significations of desire, by this peculiarity

that

the

party to

whom

it is

directed

liable to evil
desire.^

from the other


as every

in case he
is

comply not with the

And,

law

command, every law imports


it
is

this liability to evil also,


call

and
of

this

liability to evil

which we
sometimes
it
is

by the name
as

sanction.

Duty

is

hence

described

ob-

noxiousness to a sanction, and

no doubt a correct

description from one point of view.


'

Lect.

i.

p.

91

Lect. ixii. p. 457 (third edition).

CHAPTER

V.

ON THE EXPRESSION OP THE LAW.


193.
its

Were

the law ideally completej every

command with

Inade

by

appropriate sanction would be expressed clearly and fully the ex the sovereign authority. But this not having been done Pj^^p" *
is

a great deal of the time of lawyers and judges

occupied in

the endeavour to arrange and interpret obscure and conflicting


ruleSj

and

to

make
arisen.

these rules wide enough to cover the cases

which have
clear

We

are perpetually in search of

some

and authoritative expression of the law^ which expression


rarely find.
is

we very

194. This unsatisfactory condition of the law inade a reproach to lawyers, and the reproach
is

frequently

not altogether

unfounded.

good deal of laWj especially in England^ has

been made by lawyers, and they might have done the work
better.

But under

this

reproach there

generally

lies

the

suggestion that lawyers have done the work badly because

they are lawyers


greater success.

and that laymen would have done

it

with

and say

it, is

thought by

Make up your mind what you want to say, many to be a maxim Worth volumes
to be sufficient to solve all difficulties.

of jurisprudence-,

and

This

is

a mistake.

The adaptation

of language to the endless

variety of circumstances and the complicated situations of an

advanced

civilisation, is

one of the most

difficult
if

tasks to

which human ingenuity can be applied.

And

lawyers have

108

ON THE EXPRESSION OP THE LAW.


difficult

[Chap. V.
it
is

not accomplished this

task satisfactorily,

not

because they have pursued their special studies too closely, but because they have not pursued them closely enough.

The

setting apart of the study of the law as a separate profession,

a separation which
clearly

we

find

in

every civilised community,

shows that

it is

only persons specially educated

who

are

likely to perform even tolerably well the task proposed.

only successful legislation has been the work of lawyers.


talk one hears about the advantages of an appeal to
sense from the refinements

The The

and

intricacies of

law

is,

common when you

come

to

examine

it,

nothing more than the suggestion of an ap-

peal from knowledge to ignorance.

may

be at a low ebb.

Just

now

in

The knowledge of lawyers England I think it is so.

But the knowledge of laymen on legal subjects is at zero. You might (as Ihering says) just as well go to a carpenter for
a coat, or to a tailor for a pair of boots, as go to a layman for

your law^.

If the law

is

bad

it

must be made

better

by

skilled

persons and not by unskilled,

195. It was Bentham's grand mistake, that he failed to


perceive
this,

and

it

was

this

failure

which shipwrecked

many

of his finest efforts.

By

the well-founded indigna-

tion which he felt for legal abuses he

was

led to try

and throw

the lawyers on one

side.

He

not only thought that they

were corrupt, in which opinion he he thought that


all

may

have been correct, but

their

methods were mere contrivances

to conceal their corruption.

He

dismissed

all their

labours

in one sweeping condemnation, and determined to begin the

work

afresh.

For

fifty

years at least he laboured hard to

improve the law.

Yet he accomplished scarcely anything.


or complete

The Pannomion,
Duties are

body

of laws,

which he proone.

jected, is but a skeleton,

and that an incomplete

igg.

jg

certainly surprising

how

little

has yet been done

implied
'

""e sed
it

tive,

*^^^^* ^' ^'^' ^^*^' ^- 37"^^^ whole section Is most instrucshowing the true functions of law and la-wyers. I have paraphrased in an article in the Law Magazine, vol. iii. p. 281, to which I ask leave

^^^

generally to refer.

Sec. 195-198.]

ON THE EXPRESSION OF THE LAW.


expressing the legal duties which

109
it is

by any one towards

incumbent upon us to perform.

The

duties

which have been

most nearly expressed are those the branches of which are


called
is

crimes.

But even here the form

of the expression

a definition, not of the primary duty, but of the breach


it.

of

It

is

nowhere said in positive law, 'thou shalt not


is

steal,'

but whoever does such and such an act

guilty of

theft;

we
kill,
is

are nowhere bidden

by the sovereign authority

not to
stances

but whoever causes death under certain circumguilty of murder, or manslaughter, or culpable

homicide.
tual,

The

expression

is

in these cases not the less effecit

but I draw attention to the form of

as remarkable.

197.

None

of the ordinary duties of daily life are

anywhere Not very


implied.

fully expressed,

and most of them are not very distinctly implied,

We

should look in vain for any formulae fixing accurately

the mutual duties of parent and child^ husband and wife,

guardian and ward

for

any exact statement of the

acts

which

are forbidden as hurtful to the person, property, or reputation


of others
;

even for any very precise rule as to the payment


It is only

of debts, or the performance of contracts.

when
is

a breach of these duties

is

complained of that any attempt


;

made

to ascertain

them with exactness


itself, it

and even then the


if

inquiry almost invariably assumes that,


thority

the sovereign au-

had expressed

would, as in the ease of crimes,


itself.

have defined the breach of duty, and not the duty

198. Take for instance those duties which correspond to the Not

stated
"

right of ownership, of personal liberty, and personal security, g^ne"" Even a writer like Blackstone, who professes to set before
his readers a complete

and exhaustive view of the English

law, scarcely touches upon

them

at

all.

He

does not, and

could not wholly overlook them.

He

appears to consider

(rightly enough) that the discussion of


fall

them would properly


^-

under the head of the rights to which they correspond

Considering that such rights would belong to a

man

even in

a state of nature, he calls


>

them

absolute rights
yol.
i.

and

if it

were

Commentaries,

p. 124.

110

ON THE EXPKESSION OF THE


maa
;

LA"W,

[Chap. V.

possible that a

in a state of nature could


is

have any rights

in a legal sense, there

not the least reason

why
'

they should
'

not be so called

though of course the word

absolute

would

then mark an antithesis different from that which I have used


the word to express.

But what does Blackstone,


tell

after

having
plunges

given them this name,

us about these rights

He

at once into the consideration of political Hberty, of

Magna

Carta, Habeas Corpus, taxation, the prerogative, and the right


to carry arms.

Not a word about


refers

rights in

any

legal sense

that

is,

rights corresponding to duties imposed

upon individjuals.

At one time he
when he comes

vaguely to such rights, but only with


be better considered
This takes us to the

an observation that

their nature will

to treat of their breach.

Third Book, which professes to treat of 'Private Wrongs,'


but we find that nearly the whole book
is

taken up with

a description of the different courts of law and procedure.

Even when he
tinctions

professes to discuss the wrong, or violation of


is

the right, his attention

absorbed almost entirely by dis-

between the forms of action suitable for enforcing

the remedy which the party wronged has against the wrongdoer.
this,

Nearly

all

that Blackstone has to say anywhere besides

even about so important a topic as ownership, relates to


it,

the transfer of

and the various modes

in

which the rights

comprised under that term

may

be apportioned.

The nature

and extent
silence
'

of the rights themselves are passed over nearly in

^.

Though the scantiness of expression to which I here advert is a feature and though this tendency to confound the rights which protect person and property, so far as they are the subject of civil
of general jurisprudence,

procedure, with the forms of pleading,

is observable in other systems, it has had a special influence in English law. It would not be convenient here to trace the connexion between procedure and the evolution of law, it will suggest itself to any one who reads the account given in books on pleading, of the original writ,' and the action on the case.' See Stephen on Pleading, seventh ed. chap. i. and the note ad flnem. With the narrow notions of courts of civil procedure on this subject in early times, we may contrast the maxim of the criminal law, that where a statute forbids the doing of a thing, and provides no special sanction, the

but

'

'

doing of

it is

always indictable.

Bacon's Abridgement, Indictment (E).

Sec. 199-201.]

ON THE EXPEESSION OF THE LAW,

111
or other

199. Other writers have escaped the confusion into which

Blackstone has fallen between the legal rights of subjects as


against each other, and the (so-called) constitutional rights
of subjects against the government
;

but no writer^ whose

opinion

is

acknowledged as authoritative in courts of law,


acknowledge the necessity to observe, and upon
for the security of person

has yet attempted to put into an express form those duties

which we

all

which we depend

and property.

No

such writer has attempted to ascertain, with anything

approaching to accuracy or completeness, what constitutes


a wrong, or breach of such duties.

Even where the sovereign


its

authority has taken upon itself the task of promulgating

commands
that
little

in a complete form,

by means

of a code,

we

find

progress has been

made
it

in this respect.

Thus

the French Civil Code, while


rights, is

also abstains

from defining

no more

explicit

on the subject of wrongs than


civil injuries, to

Blackstone on the subject of


correspond.

which they

We

are

told that

whoever causes damage to


it ^.

another by any

act, is

under the obligation to repair


is

It will be observed that here also the expression

of the

secondary obligation only, and


scarcely

it is

so

vague as to give us

any

assistance in ascertaining the primary obligation

even by inference,

200.

No

doubt

it is

this absence of clear expression


it

on the
desires

part of the sovereign authority of the duties which


to

have performed which has caused people sometimes to

forget the principle stated above, that all legal duties derive
their force

from the sovereign authority

alone.

201. This neglect of the expression of the law could never Expres-

not (as I have already explained ^) that necessary admmthe administration of justice between man and man does not *<>

have occurred were

it

require that the laws of a country should have received any of justice.

On
^

Law

the subject of this note I may be allowed to refer to an article in the Magazine, vol. iii. p. 410 sqq.

Code

Civil,

art.

1382.

I shall discuss this definition

more

fully

hereafter.
^

Supra,

sect.

25 sqq.

112
full

ON THE EXPRESSION OF THE LAW.


expression.

[Chap. V.
is

All that the judge absolutely requires


all

authority to settle

disputes which

come before him.


all

In

every civilised country the judge will settle

such disputes,

whether the law


even when
it is

is clearly

and

fully expressed or not;


all.

and
not

not expressed at

tribunal altogether
is

without lawj though scarcely within our experience,


a contradiction.

The

question, therefore,

how far the

precision

of legal rules shall be carried, depends


or less precision will produce a

upon how far a greater


satisfactory administra-

more

tion of justice

a question which, I imagine, ultimately turns


fixed rules are likely to produce a better

upon how far your


result

than the unfettered discretion of your judges.


is felt

Con-

sidering the strong dislike which


interference,

to constant legislative
legislative failures,

and the frequent recurrence of


to

we may be permitted
legislation,

doubt whether Bentham did not go


all

too far in wishing to dry Up

sources of law except imperial

and thus

to give to that source a

new and
it is

vastly

increased activity.

At the same

time, however,

obviously

desirable that the rules of law, so far as they go, should be as


short, as simple,
is is

and

as intelligible as

we can make them.


detail,

It
it

possible that the

law

may

be too precise in

but

impossible that

it

can be too clearly expressed.

Very little

202. The law of England has grown up almost entirely

law in the outside the councils of sovereigns and the deliberations of


statute
^Yie legislature.

Most

of

it is

to be

found in the law-reports


It

and

in a

few authoritative

treatises.

would surprise any one

not accustomed to such inquiries to find

how

little

of the

law which regulates our daily


book.

life is to

be found in the statute

This judge-made law consists of certain principles ex-

A con-

pressed for the most part in technical terms.

A considerable

portion of portion of these terms, and that the most intelligible, is the law the common property of the western nations of Europe, and of their r r r j j common

property
ofciyilised nations,

descendants scattered throughout the world.


spread
j

mto

j.

-n

itussia,

mto Turkey,

mi

into India,

tt

They have
and
into

also

Japan ^.

1 In Eussia, Turkey, and Japan, recourse has generally been had to the French law, especially the Code Civil. In India the language has been

Sec. 202.]

ON THE EXPRESSION OE THE LAW.


we
find local Yariations,

113

Everywhere, of course,

but we find
is

very few points of entirely

new

departure.

There

scarcely

a topic dealt with in this book which has not been discussed

by the lawyers
where
if

of every country in Europe,

and upon which

the views of any single writer might not be accepted every-

they commended themselves to our understanding.


in

Hence we seek
this aid

the law and legal literature of

other

countries enlightenment as to the law of our

own

and with

we endeavour
and
to

to arrange

and to express our legal


our
technical

principles,

define

accurately

terms.

This

it is

which, as I can conceive, elevates law into a science.


is

No
and

doubt a good deal of what


is

called the science of juris-

prudence

occupied in ascertaining the meaning of words,

this has

been sometimes made a reproach.


is

The reproach
it is

seems to imply that the inquiry

one into which

not

worth while to

enter.

In

this I

cannot agree.

In law, words

are the instruments not only of thought but of action. are the

They
it
is

means by which our conduct

is

tested

when

challenged by

human

authority

and by which we have

to guide our actions


citizens.

when we

desire to fulfil our duties as

borrowed from English sources, scarcely, I


fellow- subjects in the East.

fear, to

the advantage of our

CHAPTEE

VI.

THE CEBATION, EXTINCTION, AND TEANSFEB


OE LEGAL RELATIONS.
203. Every law afEects the legal relations of those to
it is

whom

addressed, by the

creation, extinction, or transfer of rights

or duties.

204. Eights and duties can be created by the sovereign


authority

when and how

it

pleases, either directly,

by a com-

mand

that they shall exist, or indirectly, as the pre-arranged

consequences of certain sets of circumstances which


events.

we

call

205. So too rights and duties


or their extinction

may

be extinguished directly,

may

be the pre-arranged consequence of

certain events,

206. Rights and duties already in existence

are, in

the

view of the law, things, and they are within certain limits
capable of being transferred from one person to another.

This

may likewise command that they


transfer

be made
shall

either directly

by a sovereign
indirectly

be

transferred, or

as

the pre-arranged consequences of certain events.


Events

207. Rights and duties are not often created, transferred,


extinguished directly, but
are generally
;

happening ^^

their

creation, transfer,

and
of

"egalrelations are certain


3.1tGr6(i

^^^iiiction

the pre-arranged consequences


is

events

and a great part of the law

taken up in

the enumeration and description of those events.

Some

of

these events are, indeed, so familiar, and so well ascertained.

THE CREATION,
that

ETC.,

OF LEGAL RELATIONS.

115
is

we have only

to

name them.

Death, for example,

one o the events upon which rights and duties are created,
transferred and extinguished
:

and when we say that a man's

rights of ownership are transferred at his death to his heir,

the description of the event upon which the transfer depends


is

complete.
1

But there

must determme, not

11 merely the

are

many

Legal determinaresult of the event, but, ii tion of the

cases in
1
I.

which the law


1

<

we

are to exclude uncertainty, the nature of the event


is

"
itself,

For example, birth

an event upon which rights and duties

^^ese** events,

are created, extinguished and transferred.

We

are told (for

example) that a contingent estate given to an unborn son

becomes a vested estate upon the birth of that


have
still

son,

to ask

what

is

birth ?
it

And

there

is

so

but we much room


^

for controversy about this, that to lay

has been found necessary

down
is

rules

on the subject, as I have already


of events

stated.

There
less
sale,

a vast

number

which the law has more or

accurately ascertained, as, for example, fraud, contract,


pledge, tort.

208. The events which I have just now mentioned, ex- Legal and
cept the
last,

are events of

which

all

persons have, or think descripof these events have


g^'^e event.

they have, some conception.

And some

been discussed and defined for other purposes than those of


law.

In such

cases, therefore,

(and they are very numerous,)


;

we

get more than one description of the same event


description of
it.

mean

more than one accurate


also a large

We

have frequently

number

of confused popular meanings attached to

the same expression.

209. It would be very convenient


describe

if

expressions used to Desirable

events having legal results could have meanings only one

attributed to
least,

them upon which


all

all

men

could agree,

or,

at

t-g^"^"

upon which
it

accurately speaking

men

could agree;
expressions

for
^

then
That
is,

would not be necessary to

define

But observe that without any such would still have decided without hesitation whether or no the event had happened. The question would have been called one of that is, the standard of determinfact and not of law (see sect. 25 sqq.) ation would have been not law, but experience.
practically necessary.

rules the courts

2,

116

THE CREATION, EXTINCTION, AND


But

[Chap. VI.

separately for the purposes of law.


case,

since this is not the

and

since the

law has to range through a variety of

conceptions, moral, physical,

and psychological,

it

is

neces-

sary, in order to obtain precision, to define

beforehand the

expressions used.
arbitrary,
it

If then our definitions are to

some extent

is

to be regretted, but cannot be avoided.


is

An

ambiguous expression
trary definition,

generally a worse evil than an arbi-

and

that,

210. It

is

obviously advantageous to use a popular exits

the popu-' pression lar one


;

according to
is

popular acceptation

and where

proper attention
is,

paid to legal phraseology this acceptation


If

if

possible, never departed from.

from the vagueness


it
is

or obscurity

which attaches to the popular expression


it

necessary to attach to
if not,
-to

a special acceptation^

it is

then best
it

attach to
scientific

it

then an
accurate
ojjg

that acceptation which has been attached to

by

men

generally

and

if this

again

is

not possible,

then the law must define the expression for


giving a

itself.

Somean old

in the last times it is better, instead of


legal one.

new meaning
^-

to

expression, to invent a
211. Clearness

new

expression altogether
is itself

and brevity (which


and above

a condition of

clearness) can only be attained

by great

care in the choice of


their use.

legal expressions

all,

by consistency in

Far too
lawyers

little
;

attention has been paid to this subject

by English

and

until our legal language has been rectified, all


^.

attempts to remodel English law must be unsuccessful


212. It
is

not unusual to eke out legal expressions by using

The use made of Latin terms derived from the Roman lawyers, or from commentators on the Roman law, is due to the accuracy with which these terms have been explained. They have been used (as Ihering says somewhere) till they have become like polished steel. The special pronunciation sometimes used by lawyers as, for example, when they say

record instead of record

is

intended to indicate that a popular word

is

used in a technical sense. ' In 1878 an attempt, which proved abortive, was made to introduce a Criminal Code for England. I do not think sufficient care was exercised by the framers in the selection of the terms used to express the grounds
I will give an example. Amongst the various adverbs used an act and to show the grounds on which it is punishable, I find the following unlawfully, not in good faith, with culpable ignorance.

of liability.

to qualify

Sec. 210-213.]

TRASSFEE OF LEGAL RELATIONS.

117
Qualifica-

popular expressions in a very special sense, and then to attach


to the expression the

word

'

legal/ or

'

constructive/ or
is

'

quasi, pressions

to remind the hearer that the use of the expression


one.
J
.

a special ^^J'^^
'

Thus we speak
J

of
.

'

legal

'

fraud where no one has been


.

legal,'

deceived

or
;

'

constructive

notice,

when nothing has been


makes it But much care
difficult to
is

'eonstructive ' or
*^"''^^*

announced
agreement.

of a

quasi-contract

where there has been no

The poverty

of language

dispense with these contrivances.


in resorting to them,
objection.
is
is

required

and they are never altogether

free

from
which

Such an expression as

'legal fraud/ for example,


'

specially objectionable.

To

call

a thing

legal fraud

'

really innocent,

is

very likely to confuse the distinction

between right and wrong, and to make people indifferent about


incurring charges of fraud.

213.

What

follows in this chapter

is

an attempt to

clear Acta

the ground by making some general observations upon that

very important class of events which we


such as contracts,
torts, wills, thefts,

call acts.

Many acts,

murders, and so forth,


there are some general

have been separately considered.

But

observations to be made about acts in general which will find

a proper place here.


manner likely to injure, with culpable with intent, knowingly and with intent, knowingly and unlawfully, knowingly and corruptly, knowingly and wilfully, wilfully and corruptly, wilfully and unlawfully, wilfully and with intent, knowingly wilfully and with intent, by a wilful omission, fraudulently, fraudulently and in violation of good faith, unlawfully and for a fraudulent purpose, wilfully and with intent to defraud, falsely and deceitfully, falsely deceitfully and with intent fraudulently to obtain, from motives of lucre. If these do not represent so many different
recklessly,

negligently, in a

neglect, wilfully, knowingly,

grounds of liability sufficiently distinct to enable a jury to appreciate the distinction (and this seems hardly credible), some of them are I am inclined to think that some are also misleading, from superfluous. the grounds of liability not having been first made sufficiently clear to the minds of the framers. So too it seems very objectionable that precisely opposite meanings should be attributed to the expression good faith by the Indian Penal Code (sect. 52) and the English Sale of Goods Act 1893 Surely some agreement as to the meaning of words might be (sect, 62).
'
'

come

to

amongst English-speaking

legislators.

118
are events

THE CREATION, EXTINCTION, AND


The
is

[Chap. VT.

214.

first

thing to be considered

is

what kind of
it,

under

human
control.

event

an

act.

An

act,

as I understand
control.

is

an event
(if

regarded as under

human

There are few

any)

events which can be said to be wholly within

There

are,

on the other hand, few events by which

human control. man is in


events, there-

any way

affected, the results of

which might not have been

changed had his conduct been


fore, can, strictly

different.

Few
of,

speaking, be said to be either altogether

dependent on, or altogether independent

human
as under

control.

But many
control,

events are regarded

by the law

human

and I know of no reason

why

they should be so

regarded except that the legal result of them depends, in

some measure^ upon the conduct of the party who has


control over them.

exercised

215. I will analyse

-"^

little

further the nature of

an

act.

An

act

is

the bodily

upon a
with
it

volition.

movement which follows immediately What follows upon an act in connection


It
is

are its consequences.

necessary to remember

this, altiiough, in

common

language, we often use the word


its

'act' to express both an act and


No
1

consequences;
of

as, for

act

example,
^ bodily
less

bodily

when we speak of an act movement no act can be done.


can only forbear.
'

murder.

Without

A silent and motion-

'""
ment.
A.ct

man

216. Every act

is

prompted by some antecedent desire


will.

bydesire.

which determines the


of
at
tiig
all.
-^yii]^

This incentive to a determination

Motive.

is

called motive,

and without

It follows that in every act

result,

namely, the result of satisfying

it we should not act we contemplate some the desire. If I yawn

or stretch

my limbs

it is

to relieve the discomfort of weariness,

and I contemplate
Intention.
'

this relief as the result of

my

act.

217.

When

the doer of an act adverts to a consequence of

In this analysis I have closely follovred Austin, Leet. xviii-xxi. His explanation seems to me the most intelligible that has been put forward. His authorities are Locke, especially the chapter on Power in the Essay on Human Understanding, Bk. II, ch. xxi., and Brown's Inquiry into the Eolation of Cau&e and Effect, particularly
Part
I, sect. i.

Sec. 214-221.]

TEANSFEB OF LEGAL RELATIONS.


it

119

his act and desires

to follow, he is said to intend that con-

sequence.
218.

The contemplated end


and
this

of every act
is

is

the satisfaction

of desire,

which

is

the end

also the motive.

The

end and the motive are only the same thing seen from two
different points of view.

The end
a

is

rarely attained directly.

In

common

language. End not


it.

man

rarely does

an act for the mere sake of doing

Per-

directly,

haps we sometimes laugh or shout for no other reason.

But

generally there are some, and frequently there are many,

intermediate events resulting one from another, all of which

must happen hefore the ultimate end


For example,

or purpose

is

attained.
:

A
:

and

have been competitors for a prize


B's.

A
so

is

successful

thereupon

rage and disappointment are

great that he conceives the desire to do

an injury.

B, accordingly, contrives an elaborate plot


the contrary
causes

to injure A.
;

B
on

has no immediate satisfaction in carrying out this plot


it

him

infinite pains

and trouble which


desires,

he would much rather avoid.

But he expects and

as an ultimate consequence of his act, that

having been

injured he will himself find pleasure in the pain suffered

by

A, and so his
219.

own

pain of envy will be assuaged.

must always be intended, although the con- Act For an act is always the intended, sequences of an act may not be so. result of a determination of the will which sets the muscles
act

An

in motion in order to produce that motion as a consequence,

even

if

no other consequence

is

desired.

This excludes from

the category of acts the reflex motions of the muscles, and


the motions of a

man

in his sleep.
is

220. Intention, then,

the attitude of mind in which Oouse-

the doer of an act adverts to a consequence of the act adverted and desires it to follow. But the doer of an act may advert *? "^"^
'

to a consequence

and yet not

desire it

and

always therefore not desired or


expected,

intend

it.

221. Adverting to a consequence the doer of an act


either expect
it

may

to follow or not expect

it

to follow.

120

THE CREATION, EXTINCTION, AND

[Chap. VI.
or, as it

Knowledge.
is

222. Expectation that a consequence will follow,

sometimes expressed, knowledge that


it

it is

likely to follow,

without any desire that

should follow,

is

an attitude of
not, I venture as one, as

mind which

is distinct

from intention, and

it is

to think, permissible to treat the

two attitudes

Austin does^.
223. I shall call this second attitude of mind, in which

consequences are adverted to and are expected to follow, but


are not desired, knowledge.
Effect of

224. These two attitudes of mind, in each of which there


,

intention

and knowledge on
legal results of
acts.

is

advertence to consequences, have the most important effects


legal results of acts.

upon the

There are numberless rights

and duties which depend upon the existence of a particular


intention or knowledge in the doer of an act, that
is,

upon

the act being done with advertence to particular consequences,

and
they
Mere advertence
without
desire or expectation lias

either a desire that


will, follow.

they should, or an expectation that

225. If consequences of an act are adverted to and are


neither desired nor expected, then there
is

neither intention

nor knowledge

and

so far as

any

legal result of the act


it

depends upon intention or knowledge

will not ensue.

Nor

no

effect.

do I think that in any case the simple attitude of advertence

without expectation or desire has any bearing upon the legal


result of an act.
if

But advertence without

expectation or desire,

coupled with one other circumstance, does affect the legal


If consequences be adverted to and considered as not

result.

likely to

happen upon grounds which a reasonable


For example, the doer of an act

consider insulEcient, then the legal result^ in


affected.
'

man would many eases, is who stands in this

The framers

of the Indian Penal Code, in their definition of murder,

had before them, I think, either Austin's analysis, or a similar one. But they introduce 'knowledge' as a state of mind differing from intention. The objection to this term is that it may either mean knowledge with advertence,' or 'knowledge without advertence.' I think it must mean knowledge with advertence in the Indian Penal Code. The framers of the Draft Criminal Code for England have used the word means instead of 'intends.' I do not know what is gained by this. See sect. 170 of the
' '
'

'

'

Draft Code.

Sec. 222-229.J

TEAMPEE OP LEGAL

EELATIONS.

121

attitude of non-expectation as regards consequences, and

who

has arrived at this attitude in a reprehensible manner, very


often becomes thereby
legal result
is

liable,

which means that a particular


:

attached to the act

whereas,

if

the same act had

been done, and the same attitude of mind had been arrived
at upon reasonable grounds, he would not be liable.
if

Thus,

fire

at a target, having
kill

first

taken

all

proper precautions,
incur no liability
;

and I nevertheless
but
if

a passer by, I

may

I do the same act, having

first

taken only

insufficient

precautions, I

may

be guilty of manslaughter.

226.

When

a person does an act adverting to consequences Rashness,

which upon
he
is

insufficient

grounds he does not expect to follow,


his conduct
is

said to be rash,

and

called rashness.

227. These are the cases


to

of

advertence.

I p.ow come Inadver-

consider cases in which

consequences not in any


act.

way

adverted to by the doer have followed from an


ence, however, taken

Inadvert-

by

itself, like

advertence without desire

or expectation, does not affect the legal result of an act.

But

if

the inadvertence

is

due to an absence of that care and


reasonably be expected to

circumspection which a
exercise,

man might
is

then the legal result


if

very often affected.


first

For

example,

fire
is

off

rifle

without

looking to see
kill

whether any one

in the line of fire


:

and I
if

some

one,

I shall be guilty of manslaughter

but

buy a
it

rifle

of

a well-known maker, and, without examining


has any defects, I
fire it off,

to see

if it

and

it

bursts and kills some one

standing near, I shall incur no 228.

liability at all.

When

a person does an act without adverting to the Heedless-

consequences, and he has failed to do so because he has not

used due care and circumspection, he

is

said to be heedless,

and

his conduct is called heedlessness.

229. Acting with intention, acting with knowledge, acting

with rashness, and acting with heedlessness, are four different


conditions affecting the legal result of the act done.
It
is

obvious that in the explanation I have given of these terms


there
is

no pretence of complete

scientific

accuracy.

The

122

THE CREATION, EXTINCTION, AND


may
of

[Chap. VI.

explanation I have given

even be open to objection


in daily use

on psychological grounds.

But these terms are

by

lawyers,

who by means

them

describe the conditions

under which legal results ensue.


to state

I have therefore endeavoured

what I conceive to be meant by these terms.


if,

If

lawyers attach any other meaning to them, or

with the

meaning I have attached to them, they express


are false, let this be stated

ideas

which
at

and the

error rectified.

But

any

rate let us endeavour to understand


;

what we
let

ourselves

mean
Other con-

and when we have arrived at a meaning

us adhere

to iti.

230. If an event be adverted


its

to,

the expectation of

its

minTthau happening, or of
those described.

consequences happening,

may vary
^

very

greatly, ji o

and

it is

conceivable that the legal result should be o

made

to

depend upon the strength of the expectation.

So

there are degrees of reprehensibility in rashness and heedlessness which

we endeavour sometimes
'crass.' lata, culpa levis,

to express

by the use

of

such words as 'gross' or


spoke of culpa

So the

Roman

lawyers

and culpa levissima,

diligentia,

and exacta

diligentia.

These terms assume the possibility of

assigning so
conduct.

many

different standards

by which

to

measure

I do not think the use of them, or the neglect of

them, affects the analysis of the mental attitude of the doer


of
Forbearance.

an act which I have given above.


231.

A
:

forbearance
is

is

the determination of the will not

to act

it

inaction or omission together with advertence


is

to the act
it.

which

not done, and a determination not to do


is

forbearance, therefore, like an act,


of a forbearance

always intended.

The consequences
'

may

be desired or not

If the long catalogue of adverbs extracted from the Draft Criminal

all or

Code, given in a note to sect, sji supra, be referred to, it will be seen that very nearly all describe an attitude of the doer's mind with or

T^ithout an element of reprehensibility in the way in which this attitude is arrived at. I suppose these adverbs have, or aim at having, a definite meaning. One longs to know what jt is. The Indian Penal Code as
originally

drawn exhibited much

care in the choice of these qualifying


it is

and even in its present form respect than the Draft English Code.
adverbs
;

much more

precise in this

Sec. 230-233.]

TRANSFER OF LEGAL RELATIONS,

123

desired, expected or not expected, adverted to or not adverted


to,

and

there

will

accordingly

be

intention,

knowledge,

rashness, or heedlessness, under the

same conditions as in

the case of acts.

It

is

not, therefore, generally necessary

to distinguish forbearances

from

acts.

232. It
condition

is,

I believe, generally agreed that a mere mental Mental


is,

unaccompanied by any external act


nullius

legally without
result

speaking,

momenti, and produces no

legal

^uceJno
Ibs^I ^^-

whatever.

This might well be so for the simple

reason

that such a mental condition would in most cases be undiscoverable.

It

may

also

perhaps be doubtful whether the

mental condition

is sufficiently

under our control to justify


it.

legal results being based

upon

233. There are, of course, cases in which the legal results


either of

an act or a forbearance are wholly independent of

the mental attitude of the person

who

acts or forbears.

In
case.
less

the earlier stages of law

we

find this to

be largely the
act

We find there much more attributed to the


to the attitude of the doer's

and much

mind

as regards the consequences.


call contracts

Thus

in that class of acts


'

which we

we

are told

that in early times,

not only are the formalities of equal


itself,

importance with the promise


of greater importance.
.
.

but they
is

are, if

anything,
if

No

pledge

enforced

a single
if

form be omitted or misplaced, but, on the other hand,


with
under
of no avail to plead that the promise
or

the forms can be shown to have been accurately proceeded


it is

was made
is

duress

misconception^.'

The same thing

ob-

servable in the early English law.

In early times a deed was

looked upon as valid and binding, not as a forinal expression


of intended consequences,

but as an outward and visible


jurisdiction

solemn

act.

Only a deed made within the

and

process of the court could be relied on in an action of debt,

And
^

a deed sealed by a party's seal might be good against


ist ed. p. 313.
;

Maine's Ancient Law,


is

that the act itself


as to

always intended

We must not, of course, forget and the forms preclude any doubt

what kind

of act is intended.

124

THE CKEATION, EXTINCTION, AND


seal

[Chap. VI.

him even though the


his directions
^.

had not been

affixed

by him

or

by

But now
does
so.

234.

Amongst the

cases

still

existing in which the mental


entirely disregarded

attitude of the doer of an act

is

may

be

mentioned the ofEences of manslaughter and assault under


the English law.

But these
it

cases are

now very few.

In the

Indian Penal Code

would be

difficult to find

a single offence

which

is

not

made

to

depend on the way in which the conse-

quences of the act presented themselves to the mind of the


doer;

and in some cases the distinction drawn between two

attitudes of

mind

is

very

fine

indeed

a circumstance which

has vastly increased the diilieulty of administering the criminal

law in India 2.

So too the courts in the present day give


executed^ so as to ascertain the

themselves the greatest latitude in inquiring into the circumstances under which a deed
is

intention of the parties, and the real nature of the proceeding,

and

this inquiry largely modifies the construction

which they
is

put upon the deed.

Indeed so

much importance
it

attached

to the mental attitude in

modern law that

would almost
were

seem as
arising

if liability

could not in

many

cases be conceived as

from an act unless either the


to, or

consequences

adverted

the inadvertence were

itself reprehensible.
is

234
'

a.

This habit of referring everything to intention

tion of the seal

So an accidental destrucp. 151, third ed. would make the deed void Sheph. Touch, p. 67, ed. 1780. Under Mahommedan law, if a husband uses words of divorce they are effectual whatever may have been his intention Baillie's Digest of Mahommedan Law, p. 208. Some of the rules relating to seisin were founded on the notion that the act without any reference to its intended consequences was effectual and this conception of a deed as something which in itself produces a legal result apart from intention was, no doubt, the origin of the classification of contracts into contracts by deed and contracts by parol. ^ In the Indian Penal Code as it now stands, a very fine distinction is drawn between culpable homicide, which is not a capital offence, and murder. If the accused knows that by the act he is likely to cause death, he is only guilty of culpable homicide. But if he knows that the act is so imminently dangerous that it must in all probability cause death, he is See sections 399, 300. The original framers of the guilty of murder. Code attempted no such nice distinction.
See Pollock on Contracts,
;
;
:

Sec. 234-236.]

TRANSFER OF LEGAL RELATIONS.


class of

125

shown by that very large


courts
is

modern

cases in
is

which the

insist

upon declaring that there


legal liability,

a promise, that
it

an intention to create a

where
exists.

is

quite

certain that
this

no such promise or intention

Possibly

practice originated to

some extent in the impediments


an

to the administration o justice arising out of the rules as to

forms of action.
action
still
is

But notwithstanding that the form


'

of

no longer material, the


its

implied

"

contract or promise
to be simpler to

holds

ground, though

it

would seem

refer the liability directly to the facts as they really exist

without resorting to a
235. There
is

fiction

^-

a very important class of acts in which the Acts


if

in

legal result follows mainly,


ticular legal result

not entirely, because that par-

i^^^i
''s"lts

was

itself

contemplated and desired as one of

are

the consequences of the act.

From
call

the fact that legal results

plated.

are in contemplation in this class of acts,

Rechtsgeschafte.

Frenchmen
'

Germans call them them actes juridiques.


'

English lawyers have not yet agreed upon any name for

them.

The terms

juristic acts
all

'

and

acts in the law


(as

'

have
is)

been suggested.
'

In

such acts the doer


"
;

the phrase
is

expresses his intention

that

is,

he indicates, or

sup-

posed to indicate, by some means or other that he desires


something.
236. It
is

probable that before long English lawyers will

follow the example of continental lawyers, not only in ap-

propriating a

name

to acts of this class (and whether they

are called acts in the law, or juridical acts, or juristic acts,

does not seem to

them

generally.

If

me very material), but also in discussing we take the commonest examples of this
mortgages,
wills,

class, contracts, sales,

and settlements of

property,
ciples
'

we

shall find that

up

to a certain point the prin-

which regulate them are very nearly the same.

The

Of course the implication of a contract or of an authority to make is one of the ways in -which judges conceal that they are legislating. But the legislature itself can discard such fictions, and it does so. In the case of a sale of necessaries to an infant the Sale of Goods Act simply creates a duty to pay (sect. 2).
a contract

126

THE CREATION, EXTINCTION, AND


in

[Cbap. VT.

mode
or at
in

which the intention

is

ascertained, the effect of fraud,


influence,
be,

misrepresentation, mistake,

undue

and agency,

are,

any

rate

might

be,

and ought to

much
is

the same

all.

Brevity and simplicity, therefore,


these
principles

attained
this

by

discussing

once for

all,

and

have

endeavoured to do to some extent, though in the present


condition
of English law it
is

not possible to carry the

discussion very far.

Mental
condition, how ascer-

237.
.

mane's

and
like
is

his conduct in arriving at that condition, are facts, and,

mental ...

condition

at

any given moment,


.

any other

facts, if disputed,

they must be proved.

There

a special set of rules which the law has prescribed for

the conduct of an inquiry into the existence of disputed facts,

and amongst them there are


dition at the time

special rules

which are applicable

to the inquiry into the particular facts of a man's mental con-

when he

does an act and into his conduct

in arriving at that condition.

These rules

fall

under the head

of evidence.
Eules for
ascertainIn ing.

.,.._,.
238. Whatever

may be thought

of the

wisdom

of iudgres
"^

early times in disregarding to the extent they did the


it,

attitude of the doer of an act as regards the consequences of

there can be no doubt that the difliculty which they appre-

hended in ascertaining this condition was not an imaginary


one.

The mental condition


it,

of a person at

any time
it is

is,

unless

he chooses to inform us of
to ascertain.

a matter which

very

difficult

The

inquiry into the conduct


is

by which he
it is

arrived

at that condition of this kind that are daily called

no

less difficult.

Yet

into inquiries
juries,

modern judges, and even modern


enter.

upon to

There

may

in

some cases be
likely to lead

evidence, of the usual kind, of motives

which are

to the absence or presence of the intention imputed.

Means
It

of knowledge
inferred,
is

may

also exist

from which knowledge may be

and other circumstances may indicate advertence.


an ordinary

also probable that

the ordinary consequences of his

man adverts to and expects acts. And there are standards

of conduct supplied by experience by which heedlessness and

Sec. 237-239.]

TEAlifSFER OE
be determined.

LEGAL RELATIONS.
But
it

127

rashness

may

cannot be denied that

we

generally arrive at a conclusion as to a man's attitude

with regard to the consequences of his act by a very rough


method.

We

compare the conduct o the person doing an

act with that of an average

man, and by

this comparison

we

determine whether or no he was acting intentionally, or heedlessly, or rashly.

Thus

if

man

uses language which, under

ordinary circumstances would

mean one
it to

thing, whilst

the

speaker protests that he has used


little

express another, very


^.

attention would be paid to this protest

We

are

com-

pelled,

when we wish

to determine

what was intended by the

words used, to consider how a

would understand them.


the
street, it is

So

if

man of ordinary intelligence a man rides over another in


is

determined whether he

rash or heedless by

considering whether he has acted as an average


act.

man ought

to

Such cases might

seenl to suggest that the reference of

the legal result of an act to the mental attitude of the doer of


it

in relation to the consequences

is

but a pretence after


If

all.

This however would be an erroneous conclusion.

an act

produced a legal result merely because a particular person


did
it,

and not at

all

because of the mental attitude of that

person as regards the consequences

when he

did

it,

then the

existence of circumstances affecting that attitude would have

no

effect.

But, to take the examples I have just put, we do

not, because of the language used

by him, impute intention

to

an insane person, nor do we treat an insane person as rash or


heedless because his conduct differs from the ordinary standard
of carefulness.

239. Perhaps as strong a ease as any which could be put


is

the following.

Suppose

to have

made a

will giving

a legacy to B.

Suppose further that

after having

made

his

will declares in the presence of several persons


is

whose credit

unimpeachable that he has altered his mind and that he

' This is not upon the doctrine of estoppel (a doctrine which English judges are rather fond of resorting to to get them out of all difficulties),

but

it is

one of the rules for inferring intention,

128
revokes
in

THE CREATION, EXTINCTION, AND


tlie

[Chap.

VL

legacy.

Now a will is
is

an event in which more than


is

any other

case the legal result

said to

depend upon that

mental condition which

called the intention of the testator.

The whole

object

is

said to be to fulfil the testator's wishes.

will nevertheless, in the case put, take the legacy.

This

is

because

we

are in the habit of arriving at a conclusion as to


artificial

the existence of a testator's intention by an

method

by looking only

at

sence of witnesses, and to nothing

what he has written and signed in the preelse, however trustworthy it


artificial

may

be.

And

every

method

of inquiry into the truth


it

of alleged facts, though, taken on the whole,

may

serve the

cause of truth in the majority of cases, always involves error


in a minority,

and the case

have put

is

one of the minority.

But though we make use

of this artificial method, the legal

result is not independent of the intention.

We
:

refer to the

surrounding circumstances to explain the directions of the wUl

we ask what were the motives which induced it we inquire mind and the legal result may be modified by these inquiries. If the legal result of the act
into the state of the testator's
:

were independent of the intention these inquiries would be


altogether fruitless.
Rules of
tion,

240. It
tion;

is

the same with what are called rules of construcI

by which

mean

those rules which have been laid


is

down

for determining

what inference

to be

drawn

as to intention

from express manifestations of


of evidence just

it.

These

rules, like the rules

now

referred to, are artificial,

and there

is

no

doubt that
rules, to

it is possible,

by the application of such


It
is,

artificial

miss the real intention.

however, supposed that


is

by the

application of these rules the intention

in the general
^.

run of cases better ascertained than in any other way


supposition

The

may

or

may

not be correct, but there

is

no doubt

^ The practice of reporting cases in which the courts have construed documents, and then treating these decisions as authoritative, has led to the formation of a very large body of rules of construction in English lavp larger, I think, than could be found under any other system. Doubts have been expressed whether judges are not now too much hampered by these mles.
;

Sec. 240-241.]

TRANSFER OP LEOAL RELATIONS,

129

whatever that, whether the rules are


legal result
is

efficacious or not, the

still

connected with the intention.

Thus we

constantly hear judges lamenting the result to which some


established rule o construction drives

that this result

was not intended.


is

them because they think But the intention which is


real intention.

thus presumed

always treated as a

If there

has been fraud or undue influence, or the party using the expressions under consideration
is

insane, the result is modified

accordingly.

We

never

now go back
is

to the view of earlier

times and say that the act alone

conclusive.

English judges

have sometimes
construction,

said,

when applying

these arbitrary rules of

and referring to the person whose intentions are

in doubt, that they will consider


dixit.

non quod

voluit sed

quod

Roman

lawyers,

who were
judges
is

less fettered

by

rules of

construction, used to

say non quod dixit sed quod voluit.


the same.

Still the situation of all

They can only

infer the intention

from the language, and in drawing that

inference they mnst, whether they resort to rules of construction or not, be liable to err, because they

must

still

be

guided by their experience as to what ordinary persons would

mean by the terms


that a legal result

used.
of

241. In the large class of cases in which the mere fact Acta
is

intended and expressed


'

induce

it, '

the

connexion between the


is

sufficient to object is expressed intention *^ latenis

tion to

and the
speak as

legal result
if

so

immediate and direct that we often produce


guit.

the legal result was due to no other agency than

that of the party or parties expressing the intention.

This

way

of looking at the matter

is,

however, not strictly correct,

and, although the inaccuracy

is

sometimes harmless,

it

has,

I think, led to some confusion.

It seems in some cases to


easier process to arrive at

have been thought that


liability
it

it

was an

where there was intention than where there was none


liability is

being apparently forgotten that the affixing of

an

independent process, to which the one preliminary requisite,

and the only one,

is

the sovereign

will.

It

is,

probably, in

consequence of some misunderstanding as to the origin of


e:

130

THE CREATION, EXTINCTION, AND


we
occasionally find judges

[Chap. VI.

liability that

efforts to base liability

upon

intention,

making desperate when they might just


to intention

as well have explained it without


at
all.

any reference

For example, the struggle to explain the right to

recover

money

paid

by mistake by an imaginary intention on


it

the part of the receiver to repay

seems to

me

to be labour

wholly thrown away.


Formal

242.

Manifestations of intention

may

be either formal or
is

mal mani- informal.


oTinteiT-^
tion.

formal manifestation of intention

a manifesta-

tion of intention

made

in accordance with certain

forms which

the law has prescribed as necessary for producing a legal


result.

Forms

are useful for four reasons

first,

to

make

us

act with deliberation j secondly, to distinguish the preparations

which often precede a


determination
itself
;

final

determination from the final

thirdly, to facilitate proof ; fourthly, to

give publicity to the act.


Express

243. ^Manifestations of intention


.

and

tacit.

tacit.

An
It

intention

...
is

may

also be express or
,

is

manifested

expressly

when

it

is

manifested by any means which are resorted to for that


purpose.
tacitly manifested

by any means which, though

not resorted to for that purpose, have the effect of disclosing


it.

The commonest ways of manifesting an intention exby speaking and


writing, but

pressly are

any action

of the

muscles, such as a nod or a wink,

may be
^.

used for that purpose

provided only that

it is

understood

^ See Savigny, Syst. d. heut. r8m. Eeehts, vol. In early law 3, 130. the performance of all important acts was generally accompanied by

religious solemnities.

This, no doubt,

was

called in to sanction the proceeding,

Divine wrath to a breach of monies are singularly well adapted to serve the secular purposes stated
in the text.
stipulatio,
"

was because the Divine authority and to add the terrors of the the obligation. But these religious cere-

See as to a similar function served by the formalities of the Maine, Auc. Law, p. 328. See Savigny, Syst. d. heut. rom. Eechts, vol. 3, 131.

' Contracts are sometimes divided into express and implied, as in the Indian Contract Act, where a contract is said to be express if it is made in words, and implied if it is made otherwise than in words. I doubt if

it is

desirable to distinguish words from other significations of desirefor

nodding the head,

example.

Moreover the word implied


'

'

is

used for

Sec. 242-246.]

TRANSFER OF LEGAL

RELATTOlSfS.

131
Surrou'nd-

244.

When we

infer the existence of intention

from an act

or acts not done for the purpose of manifesting

it,

we always

cumstances.

look at the surrounding circumstances to see what light they

throw upon the

action.

How

far

we can

look at the surround-

ing circumstances to explain acts which are done for the express
purpose of manifesting intention has not, I believe, been
discussed generally, but only in reference to those manifestations

which we

call contracts.

I shall not, therefore, discuss

that question here, further than to observe that the permissibility of

a resort to the surrounding circumstances depends in


of intention,

some measure upon whether the manifestation


besides being express, has also been formal.

245. I have referred to the distinction between express and


tacit manifestations of intention because it is one frequently

made.
to
it

There seems, however, to be a disposition to attribute


it

more importance than

deserves.

In some things which

are said upon the subject there seems to lurk a notion that an

express manifestation of intention and a tacit manifestation of


intention operate in different ways.
is

I do not think that this express or tacit,

the case.

Whether the manifestation be


is

the endeavour

to decide on the existence of the intention.

246. I have already said that no one can do an act without Action

puttmg

his

own

muscles

mto motion.

-r.

But a man very

through often an inter(.

does no more than communicate motion to some inanimate

''

^^'

at a distance.

when he fires a gun and hits with a bullet an The blow struck by the bullet is in such considered as his act, as much as the pressure of his
object, as

object

a case
finger

on the trigger.
Sometimes, instead of communicating motion to an in-

animate object, he communicates a wish for some motion to

an animal) as when he

sets a

dog

to

hunt game in a
to be his act.

field.

Here

also

we

consider the hunting of

game

another purpose to express that the legal result of intention will follow whether the intention exists or not and it is in this sense that the Indian Contract Act speaks of the implied authority of an agent see sect. 187
; ;

and

illustration.

132

THE CREATION, EXTINCTION, AND

[Chap.

VL

Or tlie wish for the motion may be communicated to a human being; as when a tradesman bids his servant deliver
goods to a customer.
the tradesman's act.
Agency.

Here

also the delivery is considered as

247.
called

When

human

being

is

employed to do an act he

is

an agent.

248.

human being employed

as

an agent

may

be either

a free person or a slave, a grown-up person or a child, a

person of average intellect or one

who

is

non compos.

These

and other
legal

differences in the agent

may

sometimes affect the

results

of

an act done through the agent, but only


;

with reference to particular consequences


observations which I
consider them.

and in the general

am now making

I shall not further


arise

Of

course, however,

no question can

in English law as to the legal result of an act where the

agent

is

slave.
is

249. The general principle of agency

that the act of the

agent done under the orders of another person,


in future call the principal,

whom

I shall

has the same legal results as

regards the principal as

if

he had done the act himself.

250. So too,

if

one does an act avowedly as the agent of

another, even without any orders of that other, and he on whose

behalf the act

is

done accepts

it

as

an act done on his behalf,


if

the legal result will be the same as

the relation of principal

and agent had existed

all

along, and the case

was one
is

of

an

agent acting under the

principal^'s orders.

This
it is

the case

both where the legal result follows because

contemplated,

and where
cases where

it is

independent of the contemplation.

But

in

an agent does an act contemplating a legal


it

result,

whether he does

avowedly as agent or not, the person


result

may
of

by accepting the
principal.

put

himself

in

the

position

Law

of

251. It

is

sometimes stated in general terms that the law

dlrivJcT" of agency has been derived ^'0 some extent this may be so.
law.

by us from the Roman law. To Scarcely any portion of our law

has wholly escaped the influence of the

Roman

law.

But

it

See. 247-2S1.]
is

TEAJSrSPER OF

LEGAL RELATIONS.

133

easy to exaggerate this influence, and I think that in the


it

case of agency

has been exaggerated, and that the develop-

ment
is

of the law of agency has been rather impeded

by a
it

reference to principles which are not applicable.


true, in the

We find,

law of agency traces of the law of master and


traces of the

servant,

and in the law of master and servant


slave,

law of master and


every day
;

but these traces are becoming fainter

and the
of

relation of master

and

slave, of

which the

Roman law
principal

agency seems to have been a modification,

stands at every point in strong contrast with the relation of

and agent.

It

lies,

for example, at the root of the


is

Roman law that


like agency,

the relation of master and slave

based, not,

on employment, but upon ownership.

slave

could acquire property, but the result was that the property

belonged to his master, not because the master employed the


slave to acquire the property, but because the master

owned
non

the slave.

That

this is so is

shown by the maxim 'melior


potest;
deterior
fieri

conditio nostra per

servos

fieri

potest

"

a maxim

that could have no meaning as applied to

agency based upon employment.

So too when a slave was


for

a long time doubtful owned by two masters it whether, if a slave made a stipulation by the orders of one, it did not enure to the benefit of both

was

doubt which could

not have been

so

long maintained but for the stubbornit

ness of the principle that

was the ownership and not the


be looked
to.

employment which was


ultimately recognised

to

And

the

view

by

Justinian,

which gave the whole

benefit of the stipulation to

evidently considered

as introducing

him who gave the order, was a new principle-'. So


if made made on behalf

with the very peculiar rule that a stipulation made by a slave

who formed

part of an haereditas jacens was valid


estate,

on behalf of the

but was not valid

if

of the future heir

by name, because the

slave at the time

belonged to
^

the estate and not to the future heir^.


6
;

On

Dig. 45,

3,

Code Just,

4, 27,

Inst. Just. 3, 28, 3


'

Puchta, Inst.
3, 16.

281.

Dig. 45,

134
the
other

THE CREATION, EXTINCTION, AND


hand,
in

[Chap. VI.
actio

the

actio

de

peculio

and the

tributoria, the slave

was considered

to be the principal in the

transaction which gave rise to the proceeding, and not the

master, though the master might indirectly incur liability.


actio quod jussu, by which the master was made liable what he had expressly ordered, and the actio de in rem verso, by which the master was made liable for benefits actually receivd, depend upon a principle which approaches

The
for

that of agency.

And

in the

actio

exercitoria,

and in the
closely

actio institoria, the

principle

was approached more

star.
252. But in the matter of delict the contrast between the
relation of principal

and agent and that of master and

slave

is

most

striking.

The master was only

liable for a delict

which

was done by

his express orders, or in his presence with his

knowledge, and which he was able, but did not choose to prevent.

The

slave

was then looked upon

as a

mere passive

instrument in the hands of the master, like a tool or a weapon

and the act was looked upon as that of the master himself.

But

for

any other
liable,

delict
is

done by the slave the slave was alone

liable;

that

to say, to

pay with his person.

The
was

master only became

liable if

he refused to give up his slave.


slave,

That

this refusal,

and not the employment of the


is

the true ground of the master^s liability that


if

clear

from

this

the master sold the slave, then he had nothing more to

do with the matter, which

now

concerned the

new master
slave.

only,

who

in his turn

became

liable if

he protected the

So

also if the slave

were set free the master ceased to be

liable,

and the freedman was himself proceeded against in the usual


way^.
Messenaers.

253. There has been

much
is

discussion, especially

amongst

German
'

jurists, as to

what

the true distinction between an

The view always taken in Roman law was, not that a contract made by a representative could impose a liability on the principal as for an act of his own, but that a principal might be liable as for the act of another Sohm, Inst. R. L. 88 (Ledlie, p. 447). person. " Sohm, last. R. L. 45 CLedlie, p. 232).

Sec. 252-254.]

TRANSFER OP LEGAL RELATIONS.


Some

135

agent and a mere messenger ^.


is is

persons deny that there

any

distinction,

and I

am
and

also incHned to think that there

none.

It

is possible,

no doubt, so to narrow the functions


so completely to deprive

of the person employed,


all discretion as to

him

of

make him
up

the mere

'

tool

'

of his employer.

But from
I

this case

to that of a general agent with the

widest discretion,

we advance by
So too the

imperceptible degrees, and

know

of no point where the line can be

drawn between agents


mere messengers;

and messengers.
generally seem to

principles applicable to agents

me

to be applicable to
is

only the authority of a messenger

so limited,

and the act


is

by which he produces
so simple, that
it is

legal results affecting his employer

very rare that any legal question arises

about

it,

any more than about an inanimate intermediary.


has been debated whether a postman
It seems to
is

Thus

it

an agent or

a mere messenger.

me

to be of little consequence

whether he

is

considered as one or the other;

nor does

it

make any
'

difference if for the

'postman' we substitute the

post,''

and consider
case, if

this inanimate object as the intermediary.

In any

we

consider the

postman as an agent he

is

an

agent for a very limited purpose and with a very limited


authority.

254.

which I

When I do an act under the fear of some evil with Duress, am threatened by some one, not in pursuance of
it

a legal right, and I do


evil,

for the purpose of avoiding that

am

said to

do

it

under duress.

It

is

also

sometimes
act against

said that I do the act against

my

will.

To do an
;

the wiU of the doer

is,

however, impossible

for an act supposes

a determination of the will to do the


determination there can be no act at

act,

and without such


Thus,
if

all.

by sheer
it,

force I put a pen into your hand and trace your name with
this is not

your act done against your


if

will

it is

not your act

at aU.

But

I hold a pistol to your head and threaten to


is

shoot you unless you sign, the signature


'

then your act, and


;

57

See TJnger, Syst. d. 6sterr. Privat-E. Sohm, ubi supra. ;

90, vol. a, p. 134

Say. Obi. R.

136

THE

CEEATIOjSI,

EXTINCTION,

AND

[Chap. VI.

follows on a determination of your will just as

much

as if

you had signed under any other inducement. you the choice of two things, to sign or
choose the less disagreeable alternative.

Having before to be shot, you


as

255.

An

act, therefore,

done under duress

is

much

a
it

man's act as an act done under any other motive.


is

And

also quite conceivable that a person acting

under duress

should have the same attitude of mind as a free agent.

When

under duress I do an

act,

although I do not desire the conI

sequences which follow,

still

may know
fire

that they are likely.

Thus
you.''

says to B,

'

unless

you

this pistol at

I will kill

If thereupon

fires

and

kills C,

though he does not


is likely

desire C'^ death, yet

he knows that C's death

just as

well as

if

A had

offered
so.

him a

bribe to

fire

the pistol at

and he had done

256. In these cases, therefore, there


of
a.

is

the same combination


is

mental and physical element as where there


if

no duress,

and

the normal legal result does not follow

it is

because, for

reasons which have appeared sufficient, a different legal result

has been assigned.


257.

person may,

if

he chooses, express an intention to


it.

do a future act with a mental resolve not to do

It

is,

I believe, a universal rule to give to the words used the


legal effect as
if

same
said
case,

the intention really existed.


:

Sometimes the
is

intention
to be
'

is

said to be implied
'

sometimes the person


its existence.
is

estopped

from denying
is

In any

what

really

happens
;

that the legal result

attributed to

the words used

in this case, without regard to the intention.


it is

I think, however, that

a convenient form of dealing with


exists.
it is

such cases to presume that the expressed intention really


258.

Where an

intention

is

expressed under duress

very likely not to be the real intention; the party


the expression merely pretending that such
is

who

uses

his intention.

But, according to principle, the normal legal result ought to


follow in
expresses
all

such cases.

Thus,

if

the party under duress

an intention to promise, there should be a contract \

Sec. 255-261. j
if

TEANSFER OF LEGAL RELATIONS.

137

to

make

a testamentary disposition of his property, there


if

should be a will;

to

make a

conveyance, the ownership


if

should pass

these results being modified,

necessary,

by

enabling the party charged to set up duress in answer to the


claim, or to use the duress as a

ground

for setting aside the

transaction

^.

259.
It
is

How

the law stands in England


clearly stated.

it is difficult

to say.
little

nowhere very

Indeed we find very

about duress in our law books.

It is sometimes mentioned

in connexion with criminal liability,

and sometimes

also in con-

nexion with contracts


is

but in either case only when the duress


limb. I think, however, that the

an injury affecting

life or

normal legal
duress.

result does always follow as if there

had been no

But

this legal result is counteracted,


it

sometimes by

a decree of the court setting

aside

sometimes by giving

the party subjected to the duress a special defence to any


claim made against him
;

and sometimes by other methods ^.


is

260. Another matter which


of acts, but in a

said to affect the legal result Error.


it is

way and
is

to

an extent which

not always

easy to perceive,

ignorance or mistake.

Ignorance and

mistake are generally classed together, and the considerations


applicable to

them

are the

same.

If

it

were necessary to
is

distinguish them, I should say that ignorance


of facts
exist

not to

know

which do
not.

exist,

and mistake

is

to suppose facts to

which do

But both

are covered

by

the

word
only.

'error,'

and

for the sake of brevity I shall use that

word

261.
'

Of

course

when a man

acts under the influence of

between treating a transaction as having normal legal result, and allowing that result to follow whilst giving the party affected the means of modifying it or getting rid: of it altogether, has not been sufBoiently attended to in English law.
difference failed in producing its

The important

See the contradiction in the Indian Contract Act, infra, sect. 274 note. " Of course the topic of undue pressure as a ground for setting aside a contract in courts of equity has been discussed very frequently: but

many

of the reported decisions are based to a considerable extent upon fraud and undue influence. Courts of equity in cases of this kind do not

often lay

down any

strictly defined principles


so.

their discretion were they to do

it would greatly fetter The text-books on equity are not


;

more

explicit.

138

THE OBBATION, EXTINCTION, AND


which his

[Chap. VI.
desires lead

error he nevertheless wills to do that to

him.

Such phrases,

therefore, as 'nulla voluntas errantis'

have no real meaning. Nor do I understand what Blackstone

means when he says that


deed act separately
Error
^.

in cases of error the will

and the
do

when
wholly

262. If there

is error,

then the act which a

man

wills to

produces consequences other than those which he desired or


expected.

immaterial.

But

in considering the effect of error

upon the

legal result of

an act we

may

get rid of those cases in which


those cases in which there are

the error

is

immaterial ; that

is,

other consequences as to which there was no error, and which


are sufficient to induce the legal result.

For example, a bar

of metal belonging to

is

examined by B, who, without

asking any questions, erroneously comes to the conclusion


that
it is

gold.

He

thereupon offers to purchase


error
is

it,

and the
is

offer is accepted.

The

immaterial, because there


is

an

intention to

buy a

specific

thing which

alone

suflEicient to

induce the legal result.


Error in criminal
oases.

263.
fusion

The law

as to error has, I think, got into

some con-

by not bearing

material.

mind what is and what is not Thus a great deal has been made of the distinction
in
fact,

between errors of law and errors of


often told,

and criminals are

when they

set

up an excuse that they did not know

the law, that though they


fact,

may

excuse themselves by errors of

yet they are presumed to

know

the law, and therefore

they cannot set up as an excuse an error of law. very unreasonable, and would be unreasonable

This sounds

if it

were
to

tnie.

But generally speaking


the law, that
is,

it is

not true.

The intention
not, in

break

the contemplation of a breach of the law as


is

one of the conseqiiences of the act,

most

cases,

an
is

element in the offence.

Where an

intention to break the law

an element in the offence, as in theft as defined by the Indian


Penal Code
'

^,

ignorance of the law can be successfully pleaded.


'

Comm.

vol. It. p. 27.

loss

There can be no theft ' without an intention to cause either gain or by unlawful means. The animus furandi in larceny is not so strictly

defined.

Sec. 262-265.]

TRANSFER OF LEGAL RELATIONS.


is,

139

264. But in some cases, where there

by reason

o error, Imputa-

no intention or knowledge which would induce the legal


the same result
is

arrived at

by imputing' to the doer


. .

result, jnention of the act "' J^nowledge.

an mtention or knowledge which had no existence.


or no this imputation will be

"Whether

made

is

a matter of law.
of

265. In determining whether or no an intention or know- Error


ledge will be imputed

when by reason
is

of error the intention

fact.

or knowledge does not exist, I do not think the law pays

any attention
fact.
is

to

whether the error

one of law or one of

The whole

question of imputing intention or knowledge

a very intricate one, and depends on a variety of consider-

ations,

but not on this one.

Thus

in criminal cases
all,

we hardly
imaginary
very

ever impute intention or knowledge at


of

the direct infliction


for

punishment being reserved


^.

for real

and not

offences

In transactions between man and

man we

often do impute intention, but, as I shall show hereafter,

mostly by reason of the assumption that the expressed


tention and the real intention
actually
correspond.

in-

This

' There is a rough a4;tempt to sanction the imputation of intention ov knowledge In criminal cases concealed under the plausible maxim drunkenness is no excuse for crime.' But I doubt whether the imputation is ever really made. The drunken soldier who in a fit of fury fires his rifle at his commanding officer really intends to kill him. There is, however, a formal legislative attempt to impute knowledge (not intention) in cases of drunkenness in the Indian Penal Code, sect. 87. Cases of real difficulty are such as the following; 'The prisoner was sentinel on board the AchiUe when she was paying off. The orders to him from the preceding sentinel were to keep off all boats, unless they had officers with uniforms in them, or unless the officer on deck allowed them to approach and he received a musket, three blank cartridges, and three balls. The boats pressed upon which the prisoner called repeatedly to them to keep off but one of them persisted and came close under the ship, and he then It was put to the fired at a man who was in the boat and killed him. jury to find whether the sentinel did not fire under the mistaken impression that it was his duty and they found that he did. But a case being reserved, the judges were unanimous that it was, nevertheless, murder.' Kussell on Crimes, by Greaves, fourth edition, vol. i. p. 823. The difficulty of this case cannot be met by any talk about ignorance of law. The best lawyer would have been in the same difficulty as the sentinel he would have been placed between two confiicting duties. See how the case is met
'

by the Draft Criminal Code,

sect. 53.

140

THE CREATION, EXTINCTION, AND


many
cases,

[Chap.

VL

undoubtedly, in

leads to the imputation of an

unreal intention, but one of a very special kind.

The

as-

sumption that the expressed intention and the real intention


necessarily agree is justified

by our experience that upon the


So
also intention

whole
is

this

assumption

is is

a useful one.

imputed where there

what

is

called 'malice

in

law,'

because in such cases a


desires to redress.
is

wrong has been done which the law

But, as I have said, in none of these cases

the distinction between errors of law and errors of fact of

any importance ^.
In what cases important.

266.

If,

therefore, the distinction

between errors of law


of, is

and
of in

errors of fact,

which has been made a great deal


all, it

any importance

at

must be
result

so in that class of cases

which the normal legal


is

having followed notwith-

standing the error, there

an attempt made to get rid of

that result by the action of the court.


in one class of cases there
is

That

this
if

can be done
pays money

no doubt.

Thus

to

on account of a debt which has already been paid,


still

believing the debt to be

due, the usual legal result of

such a transaction follows, namely that the


the property of

money becomes
law now
errors

but

it

can be recovered back by A.


also,

267. In this same class of cases


stands,

as the

the
is

distinction

between errors
if

of

law and
is

of fact

of importance, since

the error

one of law
so

the

money cannot be
is

recovered.

Why

this

should be

I cannot say^.
In courts
of chancery.

268. There

also a peculiar class of cases in

which courts of

chancery have endeavoured to undo what has been done under


' The subject of error (mistake) is very fully discussed by Sir F. Pollock in his work on Contracts, fifth ed. chap. ix. There is the

customary
contract
is

close

running between cases in which

it

is

held that the

which it is held that there is a contract which may be set aside. The argument that 'the mind of the signer did not accompany the signature,' and that the document therefore, not only
a nullity,
cases in

and

may

be set aside, but is a nullity, very often operates to the injury of innocent persons. See infra s. 621. ^ I do not think any continental lawyers recognise the distinction in this case. Dalloz, Eep. s. v. Obligation, art. 5546.

Sec. 266-269.]

TRANSFER OF LEGAL RELATIONS.

141

the influence of error, and try to restore the parties to their

former position.

They

deal with such cases in a very free


it

manner, and I doubt whether


action under

is

possible to bring their

any

fixed rules.

But here

again, as far as I can

judge by what

I find in the text-books,

and in the

cases there

referred to, the distinction between errors of law of fact,

and

errors

though very emphatically announced, has had very

little practical effect

upon the

decisions of the courts.

The

distinction is not wholly ignored,


influence, but it is always

and

it

may

have had some


considerations,

mixed up with other

which, not unfrequently, altogether outweigh

it.

269. The distinction between errors of law and errors of Not an


fact
is,

therefore, probably of

much
is

less

importance than
satisfaction

is distiuc-

commonly

supposed.

There

some

in
is

this,

*'"

because the grounds upon which

the distinction

made

have never been

clearly stated.
is

Blackstone says that the

reason of the distinction

because every
the law
^.

man

not only

may
is,

Distinc-

know, but
_

is

bound
'

to

know

This statement

explained

however, obviously untrue, and even ' '

if it

were true

it

would

^^^''^' stone,

not explain the distinction.


stone's explanation, says,
'

Austin, after rejecting Black-

if

ignorance of law were admitted Austin,

as a

ground of exception, the courts would be involved in


it

questions which

were scarcely possible to solve and which


^.'

would render the administration of justice next to impossible

Why

so?

Alleged errors of fact are as

difficult

to

inves-

tigate as alleged errors of law.

And

neither in the
is

Roman

law nor in modern continental systems

the distinction

drawn between
were large

errors of

law and
^-

errors of fact

with the same


there

sharpness as in England

According to the

Roman law
Amongst

classes of persons to

whom

as

it

was

said, in rather

quaint language, permissum est jus ignorare.


'
^

these

Comm.

Tol. iv. p. 27.

Xect. XXV. p. 498 (third ed.).

'

See Dalloz, Rep.


;

s. v.

Obligation, art. 142 sqq.


;

3.

v. Peines, art.

369

sqq.

Code

Civil, art,

1108 sqq.
ii.

Preuss. Allgem. L. E.

Syst. d. asterr. Pr.-B. vol.

Sav. Syst. d. h. rOm. Eechts, vol.

pp. 33, 34 ; iii. Beyl.

75 Unger, Schwarze, Strafgesetzbuch, 9


4,
;

viii.

142

THE CEEATION, EXTINCTION, AND


rustics,

[Chap. VI.

were

minores xxv annis, and persons so placed as not to

have ready access to legal advice (jurisconsult! eopiam habere).

So too
there

it

was considered whether the point


error

of

law as to which
which the
necessity

was

was a

settled one, or one as to


'.

authorities (auctores diversae scholae) differed

The

for the

distinction cannot,

therefore,

rest

upon the broad

ground of
and Savigny.

practical convenience stated


^,
.

270. Savigny

in his review of the


.

by Austin, Roman law as

to error,

endeavours to bring
differs

all

the rules of

it

under a principle which

from those of Blackstone and Austin^ an error

He

considers,

or at least appears to assume, that fact cannot be put forward

either of

law or

by the person labouring under


the error
to

the error as any ground either for changing the legal result
or for getting rid of
it,

if

is

caused by his

own

negligence

and then he goes on

assume that errors of law

are prima facie negligent.

How
it

far these assumptions are


it is

consonant with the

Roman law
if

I cannot say, but

clear

that the English law,

imputes anything, imputes not

negligence but intention.


Error as to
private
rights.

271.

A suggestion was made


that, at

in a

well-known case by Lord


'
_

Westbury^j

any

rate,

an error in regard

to a

man's

private right
fact.

must be put upon the same ground as an

error of

Savigny had already made a similar observation.


says)

'We

must distinguish (he

between jus ignorare and jus suum


It
is

or de jure suo ignorare*.'

difBcult,

on account of the

vagueness of these phrases, to say exactly to what they lead. I suspect that
if

applied to

any considerable extent they would few cases


in

go

far to break

down

the distiuction between errors of law

and

errors of fact, even in the

which that

distinc-

tion has
Error as to

had any

influence.

272.

question of considerable difficulty which

may

arise

tkm'of
law.

^^ * *^6 application of the distinction between errors of law


See the references in Hunter, Eom. Law, p. 480. Syst. d. heut. rOm. Eechts, vol. iii. Beyl. viii.

2 '
'

Cooper

V.

Phibbs,

Law

Rep., Eng.

and

Jr.

App.,

vol. ii pp. 149, 170.

Syst. d. heut. rOm. Rechts, vol.

iii.

Beyl.

viii. p.

327, note

c.

Sec. 270-274.]

TEANSFER OF LEGAL RELATIONS.


:

143

and

errors of fact is this


is

Suppose
also clear.

the case to be one in


it

which the law

clear,

but the doubt arises whether

ap-

plies to the facts,

which are

If in such a case
it

an

error is

made

in applying the law where


it

ought not to be

applied, or in not applying

where
?

it

ought to be applied,
error of

how
as

is

such an error to be treated


?

As an

law or

an

error of fact
is

Doubts have Crossed


;

my mind

whether
it

such a case
is possible.

possible

but jurists seem to be agreed that

Savigny

says^ not, I think, as Professor


is

Unger
^.

seems to suppose, that the case

one of an error of fact, but

that the result ought to be the same as on an error of fact

The question has


has been

scarcely been discussed in

England

but

it

much

discussed in Germany, without

any decided
Infancy,
fraud,

result at present.

273.

There are other circumstances which influence the


act,

contemplated result of an

which continental lawyers are and discussing generally, but which for English in the habit of
lawyers can as yet be hardly disengaged from the particular
classes

of transaction with

which they happen

to be con-

nected.

As examples
that
it

may mention

insanity, infancy, mis-

representation,

and fraud.
is

I may, however, point out once

for

all

very rare indeed that, on any of these


its

grounds, an act simply fails to produce


result.

contemplated legal
delicate

The matter generally

requires a

much more
is

adjustment than

this, especially

where, as

frequently the

case, the interest of third persons is concerned.

274. English writers on law generally assume that all the Void and
cases in

which the legal

result of

an act

special circumstances
'

may be
But

covered

is affected by these by saying that the act is

void

'

or

'

voidable.^

these are words of very uncertain

meaning.

legal result contemplated

The word 'void^ means, I think, devoid of the ^. The word ' voidable " means that
rOm. Kechts,
ii.

Syst. d. h.

vol.

iil.

Beyl.

yiii.

pp. 328, 338 n

Unger,

Syst. d. 5sterr. Pr.-R. vol.


^

p. 34.

See infra,

s.

649,

and

also Pollock
if

times acts are spoken of as

on Contracts, fifth ed. pp. 8, 59. Somethey were void of all legal result whatsoever.

144
the result

THE CREATION, EXTINCTION, AND


may be made
?
'

[Chap. VI.

and by what process


division.

But by whom Continental lawyers make a triple


void
'

by some

one.

First they set apart those cases in


fails

which the conexample a will


call
'

templated legal result


of lands
void.'

altogether

as for

made by an

infant.

Such

acts they

absolutely

In the next

class

they place cases in which, as regards


altogether to produce
its
is

some persons, the act

fails

contemproduced

plated legal result, but, as regards others, the result

'

as for

example in the case of a bishop's lease exceeding the

period prescribed

by the law, which

is

good as against the


These acts they
call

bishop but not as against his successor.


relatively void.'

Then
of

the third class comprises those acts


result
;

which produce their legal


aside

but this result can be

set

by the action

some person concerned

as for
'

example
voidable.'

a contract induced by fraud.


I think there
is

These acts are called

some advantage in

this triple classification,

but

it

does

not carry us far towards attaching a precise

meaning

to the terms

employed ; and in the hot contests that


is

have taken place whether an act

void, or absolutely void,

This is not perhaps impossible, but it must be rare. The word 'void' cannot, I think, be conveniently extended further than I have extended it in the text. Nor does current legal language virarrant our extending

even the term

'

absolutely void

'

beyond

this.
'

Thus the contracts


'

of

an

infant are with some exceptions declared absolutely void by the Infants'
Relief Act, 1874, but
if

made during
;

minority,
;

the infant, when of age, is sued on a contract and he does not plead infancy, judgment will be

given against him money paid on such a contract could not be recovered back and property delivered in accordance with it would pass to the receiver. See Pollock on Contracts, p. 63, iifth ed. See also Anson on Contracts, seventh ed. p. in. I cannot admit that a transaction which puts a party to his plea of confession and avoidance can be called destitute
of legal effect.
I

may observe
:

that there appears to be some inconsistency

in the Indian Contract Act.

10

makes

free consent necessary to the

creation of a contract
free.

by fraud, &c., is not an agreement when the consent has been similarly caused is a 'voidable contract.' There is a somewhat similar inconsistency in the French Code, which, after declaring that consent is necessary to a contract and that there is nullity de convention if there

14 says that consent caused

Then

19 says that

'

'

fraud, error, or violence in obtaining the consent, subsequently provides that the contract must be treated as existing until it is set aside by a comis

petent court.

See Co. Civ.

art.

1108-1117.

Sec. 275-277-]

TRANSFER OF LEGAL RELATIONS.


seems to

145

or voidable,

it

me

that the disputants have frequently

used the words in different senses.


275. It
is

in connexion with eases in which the contem- Eestituis

plated legal result has taken effect, but

to be set aside, that

we come across a large number

the important topic of restitution.


of cases in

There

is

which the legal

result contemplated

will foUow, but it can be set aside

by a
This

court, not
is

however

simply, bat upon certain conditions.

called restitution,

the parties being restored as nearly as possible to their original


condition.
requires,

This

is

the course which justice most frequently


inability to order restitution that

and

it

was the

crippled the action of courts of

common law

in England,

and

relegated cases of this class to

courts of chancery.

But

though courts of chancery have been in the daily habit


of

making

restitution,

it

is

remarkable that this convenient


in accepted English legal

word has not yet found a place


terminology.
276.

From a

consideration

of the

steps

which may be

Eatifiea-

taken to invalidate the legal result of an act


pass to the subject of ratification.

we

naturally

There has been some dis-

pute as to what

is

meant by

this

term
'

also.

What
:

I under-

stand to be meant

by

'

ratification
its

is

this

After

an act

has been done which has had


legal result

legal

result,

but which

may by

taking the proper steps be counteracted

or modified, if the person

who

is

empowered to take these


some
them, he
said to

steps signifies his intention not to take them, or does

act

by which he

loses his right to take

is

ratify the act in question.

277. This, I think,


'ratification.''

is

the proper meaning of the word


is,

The word

however,

sometimes used by

English lawyers to express something different from this^.

Thus
to be
^

if

an agreement be made by

in the

name

of

without ^'s knowledge or authority, and then

A
is

consents the same

bound by the agreement, the


;

legal result

See Pollock on Contracts, fifth ed. p. 96

Sav. Syst. d. h. rSm. Rechts,

203, vol. iv. p. 558.

146
as if

THE CREATION, EXTINCTION, AND


A had
antecedently authorised the
is

[Chap. VI.

making

of the agree-

ment, and A, in such a case^

said to ratify the agreement.

There are various ways of looking at this matter which I

may
this

discuss hereafter.

All I have to say

now

is

that

if

be called ratification, then

we

give the same

name

to

two things which are


Convalescence.

essentially different.

278. There
legal result of

is

rather a loose Latin phrase concerning the


is

an act which

sometimes quoted by English


attach to

lawyers, but I hardly


it
^.

know what meaning they


'

The phrase

in question runs

quod ab

initio

non

valet

in tractu temporis non eonvaleseit.^

The
is,

first

question in
is

endeavouring to understand the phrase


'

what
it is

meant by
:

convalescence

'

According to Savigny

this

There
has

are cases in which an act has not

any legal

result, or

not the full legal result, because of some hindrance, and


in which,

when

that hindrance

is

subsequently removed, the


:

full legal result ensues.

For example
is

sell

man

a horse.

At

the

moment

of sale the horse

not mine, and I have no

power to dispose of him.


becomes mine.

But

shortly afterwards the horse


This,

The
it

sale at
is

once becomes effectual.


;

according to Savigny,
objection to calling

convalescence
;

and I know of no
then

so

but

if

this be convalescence,

the

maxim

I have quoted

is

incorrect.
is

Cases of convalescence

in this sense are perhaps rare, but, as

shown by the example

I have given, they are not unknown.

279.

What

I think those
intend,
is
it

who

use the phrase negativing


is

convalescence

something which
is

little

more
act

than a truism, though

sometimes overlooked.

An

to which the law refuses to attribute its contemplated legal


result cannot

by any subsequent conduct


to produce that result.

of the parties con-

cerned be

made

Something which has


act

been begun
missed
its

may

be completed.

Some

which has once

mark may be
failure.

repeated effectually.

But a

failure
this,

must remain a

We

are,

however, apt to ignore

and the maxim under consideration may be useful


'

to recall

Broom's Legal Maxims,

p.

178

Dig. 50,

17, 29.

Sect. 278-281.]

TRANSFEE OF LEGAL RELATIONS.


the

147

it.

Thus
girl

in

Roman

law

if

man

took as his wife

under twelve years of age, and she remained with

him, she became his wife as soon as she attained that age. This has been called convalescence, on the assumption that
the original invalid marriage became a valid one.

But, as
is,

Savigny points out^, the true explanation


that under

of this case
is

Roman law no ceremony


There
girl
is
is,

of

any kind

necessary

to a marriage, but only an actual cohabitation with the inten-

tion to marry.

therefore,

an actual and complete

marriage after the

has attained the age of puberty, and


altogether immaterial.

what happened before


is

The marriage
So in the case

not then completed, but begun and ended.

of

an

infant's will of lands

his acts after

age might wear


;

th.e

form of ratifying the

will already

made

but unless they

were

sufficient to constitute
insufficient.

a new will then made, I imagine

they would be

280. Sometimes in consequence of arrangements made by Measurethe law, or by private individuals in transactions recognised time.

by the law,

rights or duties

come

into existence after a certain

time has elapsed, or cease after a certain time has elapsed.

Thus I may agree

to

sell

a cargo of wheat to you and that

I shall be paid for

it

ten days after delivery; or the law

may
ment

say that the party

who

fails in

an action

may
first

appeal

to a higher court within two months after the


is

judgto see
ful-

given.

In these and the

like cases

we have

whether the prescribed conditions as


filled;

to time

have been

and as

this question has to be determined very fre-

quently and with great accuracy, certain rules have been laid

down

as to the

measurement of time, which


of time

are not, in

any

special sense, legal rules, but the

law has adopted them.

281.

The measurements

now

universally used are

founded partly upon certain astronomical observations, partly

upon

calculation,

partly upon authority,

and partly upon


measure-

custom.

There are certain divisions of time called respectively

the day, the week, the


'

month and

the year, and

all

Syst. d. h. rOm. Eeohts,

203, vol. iv. p. 555.

L 3

148

THE CREATION, EXTINCTION, AND


divisions.

[Otap. VI.
It is tbese

ments of time are made in terms of these


divisions, therefore,
Da\-.

which have to be accurately measured.


is is

282. The exact length of a day


observation

the result of combined

and computation.
is

It

the

mean

solar

day,

that

is,

it

the time in which the earth would


its

make

a revolution on

axis, if

the earth moved at an equable

rate in the plane of the equator.

This computation cannot

made wrong in
be

exactly

by every

one, but

no one need go far

his reckoning of days, because each computed day

coincides very nearly with

an actual revolution of the


of the earth
is

earth,

and each actual revolution


be easily counted.
Hours.

accompanied by such

conspicuous phenomena, that the days at any one place

may

283. The day

is

divided into twenty-four equal parts called

hours, twelve in the forenoon,

and twelve

in the afternoon.
fixes

Noon

is,

therefore, the point of time


is

which

the day.

This point of time


putation.
It
is

also the result of observation

and com-

ascertained

by

observiiig the point of time

at which the sun reaches its greatest altitude.

This of

itself

does not give noon, but what


will enable us to calculate ally visible natural

is

called the equation of time


it.

noon from

There

is

no gener-

phenomenon which

indicates noon, but

a clock indicates
Difference
different

it

with

sufficient exactness.
is

284.

Noon

however, as thus calculated,

not the same at


at Syd-

places in different degrees of longitude.

Thus noon
two places

tudes'

^^y corresponds with


London.

five

minutes to two in the morning at


will not

The
it is

dates, therefore, at these

always correspond.

It

is

already the 2nd of January at Syd-

ney whilst might get

early in the afternoon of the 1st in London.

Persons, therefore, corresponding between these

two places

into a confusion of dates if they were not careful to

mention which time they go by.


actions, however, the difference
is

In ordinary business transof less consequence, as the

change of date generally takes place outside of the hours of


business at both places;
so that

during business hours the

dates are the same.

The

necessity of

any

nice calculation is

Sec. 282-288.]

TRANSFER OP LEGAL RELATIONS.


by disregarding Thus

149

also frequently avoided

fractions of a day, as
of
it

weU
it is

as

by limiting the day to those hours


if

during which

usual to transact business.


of

were bound to pay

sum

money
ji

to

three
A
to

days after notice, and notice were

given to

at 10 o^clock in the

morning of the

3rd, it

would

not be necessary for

morning of the

6th.

He

make payment by 10 o'clock of the could make the payment at any

time during business hours on the 6th.


285. Probably where a thing had to be done at a certain

time and at a certain place,


be

all

measurements of time would

made
286.

to accord with those in use at the place where the

thing was to be done.

When

rights or duties are

made

conditional

upon the Days how

lapse of a certain period of time after a certain event, a dis-

cussion has sometimes arisen whether, in reckoning the period,

the day on which the event happens should be included. general rule

The

now

is
'

that this day


'

is

excluded

^.

287. The word

month.

A
is

month means either a lunar or calendar Lunar and lunar month is twenty-eight days. The lunar month,

month

a period suggested by the moon^s revolution round

the earth, exhibiting the phenomenon which


of moon.

we

call

a change

The

true period of a revolution

is

nearly agi days

and

new moon brought in a new month ^. But when the calendar month was introduced, the lunar month was
at first every

reduced to an arbitrary period of 28 days.

288. The calendar month

is

the result of an attempt to

make

the lunar periods correspond with the solar year without

resorting to fractions of a day.

In Eome, before the time of

Julius Csesar, the twelve lunar months, which

make 354 days


The

Julian
year.

Roman law
'

See Kules of the Supreme Court 1883, Order IjXLV, no. 972. seems to have been otherwise. See Arudt'a Pandekten,
ii.

89

TJnger, Syst. d. osterr. Allgem. Land-K. vol.


' '

p. 295.

place

With us, the term new moon indicates the change which takes when the visible portion of the moon passes through the vanishing point and begins again to increase. But the new moon is sometimes reckoned from the time when it becomes full. It is so reckoned in many

parts of India.

150

THE CREATION, EXTINCTION, AND


up to the
solar year

[Chap. VI.

only, were brouglit

by the
But
was

occasional
either

intercalation of days at irregular intervals.

from

the corruption of the


intercalation, or

officers

whose duty

it

to see to this

from

their ignorance, the calendar got into

great confusion, and accordingly Julius Csesar rearranged the


calendar,
last,

making March the and varying the number

first

of

month and February the days in each month so as to


civil

give 365 days in each year, except every fourth year, which
contains
>fi6.

This brought the

year very nearly into


;

exact correspondence with the solar year, but not quite

and
so

by the year 175a the


been the 14th.

error

had amounted to twelve days;

that the 2nd of September in the year 1752 ought to have


Altera-

Accordingly, by the 24 Geo. II.

ini7S2

directed that the intervening days

i.

e.

c. 23 it was from the 3rd to the

13th inclusive

should

be omitted, and the and of September

was followed immediately by the 14th; and further, in order


to preserve the true reckoning
it

was ordered that none

of the

hundredth years (1800, 1900, and

so on) should in future be

leap years, except every fourth hundredth year (2000, 2400,

and so

on).

289. At the same time another important alteration was

made.

Prior to the act of George II there were two dates for

the beginning of the year; one used by lawyers and the other by
historians.

The lawyers began the year on the a5th


it

of March,

whilst the historians began


therefore, to fix

on the 1st of January.

In order,
ist of

any date

in a given year
it

between the
to

January and the 25th of March,

was necessary
7,

know

which year was spoken

of.

For instance, January

1658, of

the lawyers corresponded to January 7, 1659, of the historians

and

to prevent mistakes this date

By the

act of George II

it

was directed that the


ist of

was very often written 165I. ist of January


January, 1752, for
all

then next following should be the

purposes, and all future reckoning should be

made

accordingly.

This

is

a very important matter for lawyers to recollect

when

dealing with dates more than a hundred years old, otherwise

they will frequently meet with imaginary inconsistencies.

Sec. 289-90.]

TRANSFER OP LEGAL RELATIONS.


'

151

290. The ambiguous word


stood to

mean
is

the lunar

month

month ^ was formally under- 'Month' of a8 days, unless it was calendar


'"
" '
"

expressly stated that a calendar

the rule

now reversed.

month was intended. But The word month now presumably


This^
it is true, is it

means a calendar month


longer or shorter.

^.

an irregular
includes are

period, varying according as the

months which

Thus a calendar month reckoned from the


reckoned from the aist of

31st of January expires on the 21st of February, and contains 31 days.

A calendar month
it is

February expires on the aist of March and contains a 8 days


only, or 39 if in leap year.

And

a calendar month from

the 31st of January cannot be reckoned so as to expire on the

corresponding date of the following month, because no such


date exists.
last

It

is,

therefore, usual ta
is,

make

it

expire on the

day of February, that

on the 28th or a9th according

to circumstances; so the second calendar of January

month from the 31st

would expire on the 31st of March, the third on


This seems rather an arbitrary
it

the 30th of April, and so on.

method of computation, but

has the advantage that the

period can be instantaneously calculated.


'

Rules of the Supreme Court, Order LXIV, no. 961.

CHAPTEE

VII.

THE ARRANGEMENT OF THE LAW.


Divisions

291.

Whenever people have attempted


it

to

write

syste-

matically about law, certain divisions of

have been adopted,


lines.

not always identical, but running mostly on the same


Publioaud

292. The best-known and most widely accepted of these


divisions of
private.

law

is

that which separates law into public and

Not a
division

293. There has been

much

said about this division

which
is

Seems to proceed upon the assumption that the division


scientific one,

based upon some principle which can be ac-

curately stated

and
is

applied.

Austin has, I think, clearly


principle,
is

shown that there


is

no such
^.

and that the

division

not of that character

It

only a convenient method of

arranging the topics of law for the purpose of discussion. This


is

how

it is

put forward in the place where

it
:

originally ap'

peared, namely in the Institutes of Justinian


est

Jus publicum

quod ad statum

rei

Romanae
is

speetat, jus

privatum quod ad

singulorum utilitatem pertinet^.'

All that I understand to

be meant by the passage

this
is

Public law
is

is

that portion

of law in which our attention

mainly directed to the state


it

private

law

is

that in which
it

mainly directed to the


topics are

individual.

I do not think
;

means that these


as

capable of exact separation

but that our attitude changes in

regard to them.

And, according

we assume
private.
^

the

one

attitude or the other,


'

we

call

law public or

Loot. xliv. p. 770.

Inst.

I.

i. 4.

THE AERAJSTGEMENT OF THE LAW.

153

294. The fact that this classification has been used for but

more than a thousand years


i
it
is

testifies to its

convenience

and upon
it
is

con-

unscientific, this,

though

it

is

a fact which
it

"^ni^"^-

desirable to

remember^ does not render


I

incumbent upon

us to discard the division.

the principle of

the division

may also observe, that though may not be more accurate


little practical differ-

than I have

stated, there has

been very

ence of opinion as to what branches of law should be placed


in each department;

and such

differences

as have existed

have been by no means important.


295. If the view that I take of the distinction
is

correct, it

How

would obviously be a waste

of time to discuss at

any length
I will,

the various attempts that have been made to explain accurately the distinction between public

and private law.

however, notice one of those attempts, being that which has

been most generally accepted as successful.


public law comprises that body
at large, or, as
it is

It

is

said that

of law in

which the people

sometimes put, the sovereign, or the


is

state as representing the people,

interested

whilst private
are
of

law comprises that body of law in which individuals


interested.

This is a forcible, and sometimes a useful

way

putting the distinction.

But

it is still
is

not accurate.
in

For

though the

interest

of the public
is

public

law con-

spicuous or predominant, there

hardly any law in which

the interest of individuals


also in private law.

is

not also concerned.

The
it
is

interest of the public

And may be

so

in

the background, but

almost always there.

Thus the
is

criminal law of theft ad statum rei publicae spectat, and

always

classed

as public
it.

law, but

still

private

rights

are

largely concerned with

So with the law of contract. Here

we have

to deal

mainly with matters of private concern, but


So the criminal law of

the legality of the transaction in other words, the public

concern in

it

is

not forgotten.

tres-

pass and the eivU law of trespass to a considerable extent


effect

the same objects, though in one the public interest


is

and

in the other private interest

chiefly regarded.

154

THE ARRANGEMENT OF THE LAW.

[Chap. YII.
classifiea-

Law

of
'

296. Private law has again been subjected to a


tioii

things

which

is

nearly as celebrated, and which

is

derived from
'

and pro-

^j^g

g^me

souTce.

In the language of the Institutes,


vel

jus
";

privatum vel ad personas pertinet,


or, as

ad

res, vel

ad actio nes ^

modern authors

say, private

law consists of the law of


This

persons, the

law of things, and the law of procedure.

classification is just as inaccurate


last.

and just as useful as the

In one sense

it

may

be said of every law, public or

private,

ad personas pertinet.

Evdry law

is

addressed to

persons, bidding

them do

or not do a particular thing.

But

the objects of law, as they are called,


persons
:

may

be either things or

and

it

is

with reference to this division between the


classification of private

objects of

law that the

law into the


There

law of persons and the law of things has been made.

are however very few laws of which the objects are' exclusively

persons or exclusively things.

The law,

for example,

which

places the son under the control of the father, gives also to

the father the fruits of the son^s labour.

And

even the law


affects the

which enforces a contract for the supply of goods


liberty of

action

of

the contracting parties.

Yet no one

hesitates to place the first in the

law of persons and the second


no more be accurately

in the law of things

^.

297. The law of procedure can

separated from the law of persons and the law of things than
these

two can be separated from each

other.

The

rules of

procedure which compel a

man

asserting a right, or defending

himself against a claim, to do so in a particular way, do in fact


constantly affect the right
itself.

When

the judges say that

after a certain time has elapsed

we wiU no
a contract.

longer enforce

a right,

it is

impossible to say that this rule of law does not


So, again, I

affect rights.

make

If I

a certain form I can sue upon

it;

If I do not
it

make it make it
This

in

in

that form, whether I can sue upon


the nature of the defence set up by

or not depends

upon
is

my

adversary.

because of certain rules of procedure.


'

But

my

rights under

Inst.

I, 3, 13,

Sec. 296-302.]

THE AERANGEMENT OF THE LAW.

155

the contract are clearly affected.

So in the ease of adoption


is

under

the

Hindoo law.

Adoption

considered

by the
do, the

Hindoos as a religious
religion of the Hindoos,
it.

act,

and respectingj as we

we endeavour not

to interfere with

But we make
adopted

rules of procedure,

and cases have occurred and sons not


as

in

which adopted sons have


have

lost their rights

really

established
solely

their

position

such,

through judgments based


cedure.

upon considerations of prorule, absolute duties (duties

298. I believe that, as a general

with no corresponding rights) are classed in public law;


whilst relative duties (duties with corresponding rights) are
classed in private law.

299. As to the subdivision of private law,


be found that in the law of persons

it will,

I think,

we

chiefly find rights


classes

and duties which


community, that
than
all.

are
is,

attached

to

certain

of

the
less

a certain indeterminate

number

In the law of things we find

chiefly rights

and
at

duties which affect either individuals or the


large.

community

300.

When we
(as I

find

an aggregate of rights and duties Law

attached to certain classes of the community

we

call

that

aggregate

have explained above ^) a

status, or condition.

Hence the law


301.

of persons has sometimes been called the law

of status or condition.

The

topics usually discussed under the headings, con-

stitutional law, revenue law,

and criminal law, are by general


Criminal procedure
is

agreement placed under public law,


also placed in public law,

and some persons are disposed

to

include civil procedure also.

But most persons agree that


it

whether procedure be placed in public or private law


should be discussed separately.

302. Ownership, possession, security (pledge and mortgage),

and servitudes (easements) belong,


private law,

it is

generally agreed, to

and to the law


^

of things.
sect, 177.

Supra,

156

THE ^BEANGEMENT OF THE LAW.

303. The conditions of husband, wife, parent, child, guardian and ward belong also to private law, and to the law of
persons.

304. Succession
after

is

considered to belong to private law, but,


it

much

discussion whether

should be placed in the law


it is

of persons or the law of things,


class it apart.

now

generally agreed to

305. Ecclesiastical law I should be inclined myself to class

under public law.

But

it is it

generally classed by

itself,

without

saying distinctly whether

belongs to public or to private law.

806. Obligations, in the sense of duties which correspond


to rights of persons against particular persons (jura in per-

sonam), are considered to belong to the law of things.

But
law

German

writers generally class

them

apart, confining the

of things to rights over things (jura in re) which are available

against the world at large (in rem).

Under the law

of things

thus circumscribed they include ownership, possession, security,

and

servitudes.

Also, inasmuch as the conditions which

it is

usual to consider under the law of persons are those which

belong to the family,

German

writers have substituted for the


'

law of persons the expression the law of the family.'


with them the subdivision of private law runs thus
of things,
succession,
:

Thus

the law

the law of obligations, family law, the law of

and

civil

procedure.
this.

I shall adopt

an arrangement

nearly identical with

CHAPTEE

VIII.

OWNERSHIP.
307. If

we

consider

any material

object, such, as a field^ Eights


things.

a piece of furniture, a sum of money, or a sack of wheat, we


shall see that various rights exist

with respect to

it.

There

is

the right to walk about the


till
it,

field, to till it, to


is

allow others to

and

so forth

there

the right to use the piece of


it

furnitute, to repair

it,

to break

up, to
it,

sell it;

there

is

the

right to spend the money, to hoard


is it

to give it
it

away

there

the right to grind the wheat, to

make

into bread, to

sow

for next yearns crop, and so forth,

308. All these rights, which I have spoken

of,

are rights
:

over the thing available against the world at large


re

jura in

and

in rem.
all

309. If

the rights over a thing were centred in one Ownership


j.jgj,j.soygj.

person, that person would be the owner of the thing: and

ownership would express the condition of such a person in


regard to that thing.

things.

But the innumerable

rights

over

a thing thus centred in the owner are not conceived as


separately existing.

The owner

of land has not one right to


to
till

walk upon

it,

and another right

it

the owner of a
it,

piece of furniture has not one right to repair

and another

right to

sell

it

all

the various rights which an owner has

over a thing are conceived as merged iu one general right of

ownership.
310.

person in

whom

all

the rights over a thing were

158
Absolute

OWNERSHIP.

[Chap. VIII.

centred, to the exclusion of every one else,

would be

called the

own

ft I*"

ship.

absolute and exclusive owner.

This means that no one has


It does not

any right over the thing except himself.


that he

mean

may

exercise his

ownership in accordance with his


all

uncontrolled fancy.

In the exercise of

legal
each, of

rights,

whether of ownership or of any other kind,


under a certain control arising out of the

us

is

relation, in

which we

stand to the ruling power or to other members of the society


to

which we belong.

I cannot exercise

my

rights in such

way

as to infringe the
:

law or the rights of others.


absolute

To take
of

an example

am

the

and exclusive owner


I
to

a large quantity of charcoal, sulphur and saltpetre.


still

am
mis

the absolute owner, although the law forbids


in

me
Nor

them together and keep them


ownership
only.
311.
affected.

my

house.

No

one by reason
is

of that restriction has a jus in re over them.

my

The

restriction is

on

my

liberty of action

But

if

I have pledged the saltpetre as security for a


;

loan, then the pledgee has a jus in re over it

and

dispose of

it

is

restricted,

not by a mere restriction on

my right to my
of

liberty of action, but because one or

more of the rights

ownership have been detached and given to another.


312.

So

if

I grant a right of

way

to a neighbour across

my

land, or if

my

neighbour has a right to graze his cattle

there, he has a jus in re over

my

land,

and certain rights have and yet

been detached from

my
is

ownership and transferred to him.


is

313. Absolute and exclusive ownership

rare
is

I do not think

it

possible to explain

what

meant by
are

ownership except by starting with this abstract conception


of
it.

It

is

to

this that

we always
is

revert

when we

trying to form a conception of ownership.


Ownership
aggregate
ot rights,

314. Ownership, as I have said,


right,

conceived as a single

and not as an aggregate of

rights.

To

use a homely

illustration, it is

no more conceived as an aggregate of distinct rights than a bucket of water is conceived as an aggregate of
separate drops.

Yet, as

we may take a drop

or several drops

Sec. 311-318.]

OWNERSHIP.
so

159

from the bucket,


from ownership.
315.

we may detach

a right or several rights

The

distribution of rights detached


find in use
is

from ownership
Thus,

Distribu-

which we actually

very extensive.

it j-ights.

would be no strange thing to

find a piece of land,

and that

A
to

had a right
on

to

till it,

a right to
in

walk across

it,

a right

draw water from a spring


it

it,

a right to turn his


it,

cattle

to graze,

Ua

right to take tithe on

F a right

to hold

it

as security for a debt,

and yet possibly no one of

these persons would be considered as the owner.


316. In such a case as this the owner would be stripped Difference

nearly bare of his rights, and

it

may

seem, at

first

sight, ownership
''"'i J."^^ .'"

purely arbitrary to continue to call such a person the owner,

But
he

this is not so.

Though

his ownership is greatly reduced,

is still

in essentially a different position

from that of any

other person.

So long as the rights I have mentioned are in

the hands of any other person they have a separate existence,

but as soon as they get back into the hands of the person

from

whom

they are derived, as soon as they are

at

home

'

as it were, they lose their separate existence,

and merge in
detached,

the general right of ownership.

They may be again


is

but by the detachment a new right


317.

created

^.

However numerous and

extensive

tached rights, however

insignificant

the holder of this residuary right


as the owner.

may be the demay be the residue, it is whom we always consider


described as

Descrip-

owner.

the person in

An owner might, therefore, be whom the rights over a thing


merged

do not exist

separately, but are

in one general right.

318.

Or an owner might be
it^.

described as the person whose

rights over a thing are only limited by the rights which

have been detached from


1

man
'

This I take to be the meaning of the maxim 'nemini res sua servit' cannot have a separate jus in re over his own property. I do not attempt to define ownership. The following are three

attempts which have been


'

made

at a definition

Eigenthlimer heisst derjenige, welcher hefugt ist, fiber die Substanz einer Sache oder eines Eeehts, mit Ausschliessung Auderer, aus eigener

160
Presumpfavour* of owner.

OWNEESHIP.
its

[Chap. VIII.
slenderest fornij
it

319. This residuary right^ even in

is

of

great legal importance.

It enables the holder of


all

to

assume
All (he

^ position of great advantage in

legal disputes.

can say) belongs to

me which

cannot be shown to belong to


is

any one

else.

Every one who intermeddles what he


entitled to

an intruder.
else

Unless he can establish his right to do so.

Everybody

must take
sumption

just

is

and no more.
^.

The

pre-

is

always in favour of the owner

320. Having thus endeavoured to explain the conception of


ownership, I

now

advert to an extended use of the word which

has given
Ownership
of jura in
re aliena.
'

rise to

much

controversy and to some confusion.


its

321.

The word 'ownership/ and t

property/ as well as the corresponding words in other lan-

in

English equivalent
i

guages, dominium, propriete, eigenthum, besides being used


to express that relation of a person to a thing

which I have

just

now endeavoured

to describe, have been used to describe

generally the position of any person ovef a thing.

who has

a right or rights

Any

person having a jus in re has been called

owner

not indeed of the thing, but of that right ^.

Perhaps

this extended use of the

term

is

to be regretted as tending

to

confuse

the

conception of ownership.
it.

Nevertheless
it

it

exists

and we must master

Nor can

be denied that

between the ownership of a thing and the so-called ownership


of a right there
re
is

much

analogy.

Both owners have jus

in

and in rem.

Both can
selbat,

deal with the object of their right


Allgem. L.-E. de jouir et disposer des choses de la
'

Maoht, durcli sich


I. 8. i.

oder einen Dritten zu verfiigen.'

'La propriSt6
ou par

est le droit

maniere
les lois

pourvu qu'on n'en fasae pas un usage prohibS par Code Civil, Art. 544. The ownership of a thing is the right of one or more persons to possess and use it to the exclusion of others.' New York Civil Code, sect. 159. AH these definitions seem to me to be valueless. See the remarks of Sohm, Inst. E.-L. 61 (Ledlie, p. 827), and the German Biirgerliches Gesetzbuch, J 903, where, prudently, only a description and not a deiinition is
la plus absolue,

les rgglements.'

attempted.
'

See infra,

sects.

844 sqq.
of a right is expressly recognised in the Prussian Code.

The ownership

See the quotation in the note above. Also in the Austrian Code, see AUgem.
biii-g.

Gesetzb. Art. 353, 354.

Sec. 319-323.J

OWNEESHIP.
they please.

161

(with the usual Hmitation i) as

The owner-

ship of the right as well as the ownership o the original

thing can very frequently he divided;

subordinate rights
to others.
lets it to

may
Thus,

be again detached from


if

it

and made over

be the owner of a piece of land, and he

for a term of years,

is still

the owner, and, as regards him,

merely has a jus in re

aliena.

But, as regards other per-

sons than A,

B will be
;

considered as the owner, not of the land,


if

but of the lease

and

then

sells his

growing crops

to C,

C
to

will

have a jus in

re aliena as regards

B, namely the right

come on

to the land

and take the crops when they are ripe


analogy between the position of

and there

is

this further

A
to

and B, that
so

just as ^'s detached rights, if they

went back

A, would merge in A's general right of ownership of the land,


(7's

detached right to take the crops,

if it

went back

to

B,

would merge

in ^^s general right of ownership of the lease.


is it

322. In the view of some jurists not only

wrong

to

speak of the ownership of a jus in re aliena, but


to speak of the ownership of anything

it is

wrong

which

is

not a material
It seems

object capable of being perceived


to
is

by the

senses^.

me

a strange thing to speak of a thing as erroneous which

universally
is

done

and

especially

when, after
shall

all,

the

question

only one of convenience


?

how

we shape

our

conception of ownership

The Roman lawyers,

as a matter

of fact, did speak of the ownership of things which had no


corporeal existence.

They
;

spoke, for example, of the owner-

ship of a usufruct

and they spoke of the ownership of an and

haereditas; both which the authors of the Institutes^ have

been careful to show are incorporeal

modem

legislation

has in the clearest manner adopted the view that things

which have an
this use of the

ideal existence

may

be owned.

In England

323.
'

word ownership has taken deep root. The long-standing discussion as to the ground upon
sect. 310.

See supra,

See Windscheid, Lehrb.


Inst, of Just. 2,
I, 1.

d.

Pand.-E.

168,

and the references in the

note.
^

162
Ownership wtich authors, artists,
Hons^^""
right.

OWNERSHIP.

[Chap. "VIII.

and inventors are protected by the law

seems to

me

to resolve itself into a question

how you

choose

and copy- j^ conceive ownership. conceived as a right


existence.
;

What we
,

call
,

copyright can only be


,

that
it is

is,

as a thing

having only an ideal

I'll

Moreover

not conceivable as a right which has

been detached from ownership, or from any other aggregate


of rights, but only as an independent right.

It

may

be de-

scribed generally as a right to reproduce a certain collocation


of words

and

sentences, or a certain design,


so.

and to exclude

others from doing

If

we do

not admit that there can


of

be ownership of things incorporeal,

admit the ownership of copyright.


ownership of things incorporeal
sons do

If

course we cannot we do admit the

and

practically

most per-

make

this admission

then

copyright seems to

me

a very proper subject for ownership, and 'owner' seems a very


suitable

term by which to describe the person who has the

copyright.

The other way

of looking at the matter

is

to

conceive the copyright as a personal privilege of the author,


in the

same way as we conceive the right of exclusive audience


law as the personal privilege of a barrister, or the

in courts of

right to

sit

and vote in the House of Lords as the personal

privilege of a peer.

But whether a right


privilege, or
(as it

or

any

particular

set of rights is referred to ownership, or

whether
is

it shall

be

referred to personal

sometimes called
is

but which comes to the same thing) to personal condition,


after all only a question of convenience.

As Austin

points

out

',

some of the rights in rem over persons have been


ownership and some to privilege or condition.
is

referred to

The
is

right of a master, for example, over his slave

always

called ownership, that of a father over his son in

modern times
a

not so called.

This

is

partly perhaps due to sentiment,


is

partly also because the slave

bought and sold and


is

is

source of wealth, which the son


'

not^.

But whatever the

Lect. xlvii. p. 819.

' See Bentham, Collected Works, vol. i. Blackstone evidently p. 136. thinks that every right in rem belonging to n person over person or thing must be a right of property (ownership). Thus, he says, the child
'

Sec. 324, 325.]

OWNERSHIP.
it

163

reason

may

be

would make no

difference

from a legal point


if

of view, so long as the rights were not altered,

what

is

now
ship,

referred to privilege or condition were referred to owner-

and vice

versa.

324. Ownership being the relation of a person to a thing, Ownersliip


or to a person considered as a thing
either a
1,

the person

may

be

poration.

human being
call

or a juristical
it:

persona corporation,

as

we

generally

and in legal contemplation the


be ownership which

ownership of a single individual and of a corporation are


the same.

But

there

may

is

neither

of an individual nor of a corporation, but of several individuals.

The co-ownership

of several individuals

^ is

something
If a piece

quite distinct from the ownership of a corporation.


of land or a house
rolling stock is

members of have any right over If a member of the


pass;
it
:

is owned by a college, or a quantity of owned by a railway company, neither the the college nor the shareholders of the company

or interest in these things whatsoever.


college without the permission of the

college were to enter on the land he would


if

commit a

tres-

he lived in the house he would have to pay rent for

if

a shareholder of the company took away any of the


steal.

moveable property of the company he would

But

in

co-ownership the individuals themselves are the owners, only


the rights of each are necessarily somewhat limited by the
rights of his fellows.

325.

Of

course this case

is

quite distinct from that in Owner-

which the several rights over a thing are distributed amongst


no property in his father or guardian as they have in him for the him education and nurture.' And further on lie says of the servant, tiiat he had no property in the master.' Comm. vol. iii. p. 143. And a modern editor of Blackstone thinks that, since the wife and child can now recover damages for the injury sustained by the death of the husband or father, they have a kind of property in him. Kerr's
liath

sake of giving

'

Blackstone, vol.

iii.

p. 134.

So too the right of a pledgee


a,
;

is

called a

'special property.'

Co. Litt. 89

2 Lord

Eaym.

pp. 916, 917.

See

Donald v. Suckling, Law Kep. Q. B. vol. i. p. to this by the poverty of our legal language. ^ See sect. 160 supra, and note.
'

595.

We

have been driven

See

sect.

143 supra.

164
several persons
;

OWNERSHIP.
as also

[Chap. VIIT.
consists of

from that where a thing


different

parts

and each part has a


and
it,

owner;
it,

as, for

example,

a piece of land with a house upon


of the land,

where

is

the owner

of the house

or of a gold ring with

a jewel set in the jewel.

where

is

the owner of the ring, and


is

of

We

are considering the ease where there

but

one object and several persons standing in the relation of

owner
Family ownership.

to

that object

or,

as

it

has been put, where each

'to tins corporis pro indiviso

dominium habet^/
.

originally into use as a modified

...

326. I think

it

very probable that co-ownership came

form

of

what I

will call

family

ownership.
is

There

is

ground

for

believing

that

family ownership

the oldest form of ownership, and very


its

high authorities think that in

original

form

it

was pretty

much

the same thing as that which


^.

we now

call corporate

ownership

There

is

no more interesting chapter in legal

history than that of the different processes

by which

this
in-

family ownership has been

transformed into separate

dividual ownership, and the intermediate forms of ownership

which they have

left

on the way.

These forms survive with

us as joint tenancy, tenancy in

common, and coparcenary.

As

far as I

am

aware the forms of ownership existing on

the continent are not materially different.

But

in India,

where the transition from family to individual ownership


is

still

in progress, there are

some very peculiar forms of

co-ownership, analogous to forms found in Europe, but identical

with none.
^

I shall have occasion to speak again of

these hereafter
Conditional ownership.

327. Ownership, or any of the various rights which

make

up ownership,

may
to

be subject to conditions
or cease

that

is

to say,

may

be

made

commence

upon the ascertainment


not
exist.

by our
1 ^

senses that
xiii. 6, 5, 15.

a certain fact does or does

Dig.
It is

not possible to avoid using the word corporate,' though, of is necessary to be careful in drawing conclusions as to the complete identity of family ownership with corporate ownership.
'

course,

it

See the chapter on Succession,

ss.

780 sqq.

Sec. 326-328.]

OWNEESHIP.

165

Thus, I

may

be the owner of a piece of land on condition of

paying a certain fixed sum of money annually to the crown


or I

may become

the owner of the estate which belongs to you,


to take the

upon your declining


328. I

name

of a certain family.

am
by

not

now about

to discuss the rules

which regu-

Peisevei-to

late the transfer of the ownership of property,

whether inter tempts


I

vivos

or

succession,

testamentary or intestate.
to

am

ceti^on to'

however about
ideas

to

refer

them, because

many modern

owner-

upon the

subject

of ownership were introduced in

order to satisfy the eager desire of owners of landed property


to direct the course of succession according to their liking,

and

to thwart the efforts of the legislature to prevent owners


call
'

from what we
and extend

tying up

'

their property.

To

exercise

to the very utmost the

power of directing the

course of succession to land has been the steady object of

owners of landed property in every country of Europe; and,


at this

moment,
in

it
^.

largely occupies the attention of landIt

owners in India powers

has been

the policy of the ruling

different

countries

sometimes to increase these

facilities,

sometimes to diminish them.

They were swept

France by the Revolution of 179*^ and have only been very partially restored^. In England, though many
in
See infra, sect. 337 note. See Code Civil, Art. 896, and the observations of M. Troplong, Droit Civil Expliqug, Donations entre Vifs et Testaments, vol. i. p. 138. M. Troplong's observations upon the effect of what at the time was conThough strongly sidered a very extreme measure are remarkable. repudiating all sympathy with the extreme republican School, he declares
'

away

his conviction that the abolition of the old law of substitution has been Cette question ne in the highest degree beneficial to France. He says divise plus les esprits. L'abolition des substitutions a pu paraitre un
:

'

coup hardi a la gfin^ration qui n'en avait pas fait I'epreuve ; mais I'experience d'un demi-sifecle a d^montre h I'epoque actuelle les immenses avantages d'un regime de liberty qui laisse la propriety h, son mouvement

en fait un gage sgrieux pour le credit, et un patrimoine assure a chaque membre de la famille. Les substitutions ^taient un obstacle Suorme au dfiveloppement de la richesse publique. EUes avaient, sans doute, un certain avantage de conservation, mais elles pr6f^raient une immobilite sterile au mouvement f^cond qui donne la vie aux interets 6couomiques.' The rapid change of ideas which has taken place in England during the When this work was first published, last few years is very remarkable.
legitime, qui

166
attempts have been

OWNERSHIP,
made
to restrict them, they
else ever

[Chap. YIII.
still

exist in

a form and to an extent nowhere


Furthered
notions 'of

known.

329.

Certain peculiarities

the

law of ownership in

England have
aware,
there

specially tended to favour the exercise of the

owner-

power of tying up landed property; and, as far as I


is

am

nothing analogous to these in any other

system of law, ancient or modern.


First,

by
.

330. It
,,

is

not at
/.

all

uncommon

to find in
j

many

countries
j!

separation
of owner-

two, three or tour persons mdicated as successive owners or

j-

ship into

property

the property shifting over from one to the other on

the happening of certain events.

These persons in their turn

become owners of the property^ each taking by substitution


for the one
plete

who
;

preceded

him

each in his turn being comtill

owner
is

but each taking nothing

his turn comes.

There

a substitution of this kind in English law,

when

(as

frequently happens) a
to give

man who

inherits

an estate

is

compelled

up one which he previously held

so as to provide for

another

member

of the family.

But

besides this the English

lawyers have invented a

ownership of land in a
in

way of dealing with the successive way peculiar to themselves. If land


after his death to

England be given to A, and


and

, and after
be four

his death to G,

after his death to I), these four persons are


else, to

not considered, as they would be anywhere

successive owners, differing only in the date of the

commencethat came.

ment and end


their turn as

of their ownership; each taking


it

by
till

substitution^

came, but having nothing


ia

The English lawyer views them


highly technical
imagination, he
itself,

a far different
effort

and
of

light.
first

By
it

an extremely bold

detaches the ownership from the land


to

and then attaches

an imaginary thing which he

the remarks in the text were considered somewhat hazardous. Since then a measure radically affecting the principles of the English land law has

been carried almost without a dissentient, and further reforms are promised. ' This is a technical term of French law it was by means of substitutions that succession was tied up under the old French law, and it was
;

by the abolition of substitutions that the great change was Code Civil, Art. 896.

effected

see

Sec. 329-331.J

OWNERSHIP.

167

calls

an

estate.

This enables him to deal with ownership in

a more fanciful

way than

if it

were attached to the

soil.

He

treats the ownership of the 'estate'' in perpetuity as

some-

thing out of which he

may

carve (to use his


slice

own

expression)
different

any number
person
;

of slices,

and confer each

upon a

each, of

whom, though he may have


is

to wait a long

time for his enjoyment of the property,


present owner of his
consider this
peculiar
;

nevertheless the

slice.

English lawyers do not seem to

mode
it

of dealing with ownership as anything


is

but

nevertheless

peculiar to English law.

Other

nations share with us the idea that, as certain events arbitrarily chosen

may
to

happen, the ownership of land

may

pass

from one person

another

and have invented contrivances,


on alienation
',

which

are, for the

most

part, restrictions

to

when the event happens, the land shall so pass. But the notion of an estate,' as it is called, is, I think, unknown in any system which has not taken it directly
insure that,
'

from us; and


of an
'

tricks
'

have been played with the ownership

estate

which could hardly have been ventured on


itself.

with the ownership of the land


in

If I give an estate

my

land to you for your

life,

am

not looked upon as


this indefinite

having parted with the land altogether for


period, at the

end of which

it

will

come back

to

me, or go

to

some other person.

According to the language and ideas


is

of English lawyers the land

in one sense yours, but


:

still

remains in another sense mine

and with what

is

mine I

may

deal.
is

331. It

true that the results of both devices for con-

trolling the succession to the ownership of land are very often

the same.

It

might come

to pretty nearly the


eldest son for
life,

same thing,
his

whether I gave land to

my

and after

death to his brother, or 'substituted'

my

younger son for

my

elder,

on the death of the

latter.

But

it

does

not

follow from this that the existence of two different devices


' The shifting use of English real property law is very than a well-conceived device for preventing alienation.
'
'

little

more

168

OWNERSHIP.

[Chap. VIII.

does not widen the facilities for tying up succession, though


this
is

not the point to which I


I wish to establish
is,

now wish
is

to

draw

attention.
of

What
332.

that the English


peculiar^.
is

method

dealing with the ownership of land

ease has arisen in India


it

which

remarkable as

being one to which


or the
of
it

was open to apply

either the English

more general notion;


little

and the actual determination

may have no

influence on the future development

of law in that country.

If a

Hindoo

dies leaving a

widow,

she sometimes takes his property, but her ownership terminates


at her death.
fore,

It

would have been perfectly in accordance, thereideas,

with English

though contrary to the general ideas

of jurisprudence, to treat her

not

as unlimited

owner of the
only of what

property for the limited time, the ownership shifting over


at her death to the next taker

but as owner
;

we should
this is

in

England

call

an

estate for life

the next taker


rest.

being at the same time present owner of the

But

one of the instances in which English lawyers have

escaped the error of transferring into a foreign system the


ideas peculiar to their own.

The widow
life,

in India,

though
is)

her ownership lasts only for

has (as the phrase

the

whole estate vested in her

and the next taker after the

widow

has, as he

would have in most countries under similar

circumstances, nothing, until his turn comes

by the death

or other determination of the widow^s ownership,

when the
land-

whole
Leases for
of years.

shifts over to him.

333. There are

many
is

other things which an


is

Enghsh

Owner, but no
instance, whilst
'

other landowner,
it

permitted to do.
for the

For

common everywhere
to land,

owner of

I confine

my observations
;

although the ideas of English law

relating to other species of property, the funds for instance, possess


peculiarities

some

but I have selected land as the best for purposes of illustration. Nor do I vi^ish to indicate it as my opinion that these ideas could be wholly swept away though I cannot conceal my opinion that they might be advantageously simplified. This simplification is not
:

effected

by the recent Settled Estates Act, though some


;

evils

are

mitigated

but

it

is

not improbable that a further advance

may

be

made.

Sec. 332-334.]

OWNEESHIP.

69

land to be allowed to separate the right to use and enjoy the


land from the ownership, and to confer
it

on some person for

a limited period, this period has generally been a short one,

conterminous with the

life

of the grantee.

English lawyers

have adopted the strange device of separating the use and

enjoyment of the land from the ownership

for periods of as
is is

much
mode

as a thousand years.

As a thousand years

for all

practical purposes equivalent to a perpetuity, this

new
call

of creating an

owner

the right to use and enjoy being

unlimited.

The

incidents of this ownership,


'

which we

the ownership of a

term,' are not the same as the incidents of


life,

the ownership of an estate for

or in

tail,

or in fee.

The

owner of the term

is

the owner of a jus in re alienS.


is

It is for

this very reason that the device

resorted to, in order to It

satisfy the capricious fancies of landowners.

might create

little

immediate inconvenience, but

it

would vastly simplify


if

the law and be a great benefit to posterity,

every grant of

the use and enjoyment of land for more than one hundred
years were declared to be equivalent to a grant in fee
^.

334.

But
.

there

is

more

extraordinary
1

device
J.

still. Restric1

Every
ation
all

civilised

country has arrived at the opinion not only be alienated, but that a free power of alien-

VI

tiois on aiiena'""

that land
is

may

a necessity of well-being.

other systems of law, has clearly laid

The English down the

law, like
principle

that restrictions upon alienation are objectionable, and in

a general

way

illegal.

'

Also

if

a feoffment be made upon

this condition, that the feofEee shall not alien the land to any,

this condition is void

because

when a man

is

infeoffed of

lands or tenements he hath power to alien them to any

person by the law ^.'


the principle they lay

These are the words of Littleton, and

down has been

reaffirmed
^.

by judges

innumerable down to the present day


the prohibition
'

And
step

yet every day


is

is

avoided, and the owner of land


u.
s.

restrained

41, 65, See 44 and extinguishing long terms of years.

45 Vict.
360.

by which a small

is

taken towards

' ^

Littleton,

s.

Tudor's Leading Cases in Real Property,

p. 971.

170

OWNERSHIP.
artifice

[Chap. VIII.
is

from alienating by an
deceive a child.

which

too transparent to
is

The power

of alienation

detached from
is

the ownership of the estate

when

the estate

parted with,
to

and
else.

is

either retained

by the grantor, or given

some one
of

Thus the ownership goes one way and the power

alienation goes another.

The

policy of the law

is

that they

should go together.

The

evil is

that a

man

should not be
usefully or

able to get rid of land which he cannot


profitably.

manage

The land
is

gets into a bad condition, and this great


diminished.
evil

source of wealth

An

impoverished owner

is

an
for

evil,

but this

is

an

which has a tendency to cure


is

itself,
sell.

an impoverished owner
US
it is
,

almost always willing to

Powers sale by
rersons

of

With

possible to check that tendency

by putting the
not the owner,
is

power of

sale into the

hands of a person who

is

owners.

^^^ ^^ ^^ been
335

selected expressly because


^.

he

not likely

to be willing to sell
Separalegal
_

Another peculiarity of the English law of ownership


between common law
I

and

arises out of the very strange conflict

ownership.

^^^
jj^

equity.

To take a simple

ease

If

gave land to you

trust for myself, at

common law

I cease to be the owner,


this

in equity I continue to be so.

How

came about

is

an

inquiry which belongs to the history of English law, and need

not be

now

pursued.

It

is

only noticed here as an idea of

ownership by which the attempts at simplifying the notions


comprised under that term have been eluded.

The Court

of

Chancery, had

it

confined
fulfil

itself

to

compelling owners of

property either to

certain fiduciary relations, such as


fulfil

those of guardian and ward, or to

the wishes of persons

from whose bounty they had received the ownership, would have kept within the limits of analogous institutions in other
systems of jurisprudence.

Had

too this been done, not only

in those cases where there are special reasons for the exercise of good faith, but in all cases alike, where the
This evil
lessened by the Settled Estates Act.
of the Courts.

owner of land
It

is

seen

how

far land

becomes easily saleable under that Act.

remains to be Much depends

upon the attitude

Sec. 335. 336-]

OWNEESHIP.

171

had accepted the ownership subject


his rights for the benefit of

to a condition to exercise

some other person, and the ordinary

remedies of law were insufficient to compel him to do so

this

would have been a stretch perhaps of the doctrines of equity,


but would have been very likely
introduced no entirely
beneficial,

and would have


It has

new

principle.

But the English Court


more than
;

of Chancery has done a great deal

this.

created an entirely

new

interest in land

an
as

interest as

comas

prehensive,

as

general,

as
is

beneficial,

transferable,

ownership
of the

itself

which

ownership in

fact, only the rights

owner are somewhat clumsily exercised; and


This equitable ownership, or

so it is

frequently called.
estate, or

use, or trust
it,

whatever other name we

may

give

exists side
is

by

side

with the

common law
this double

ownership, and there

no

immediate prospect of

ownership being got

rid of.

It has been said that the Courts of for this conflict


;

Common Law are


is

to

blame

that

it is

to their action,

and not to the


due. It
is

action of Courts of Chancery, that the anomaly


is

not the least worth discussing which of these charges

correct.

The important thing


out of which

is
:

to

get rid of this double


conflict
is

ownership as quickly as possible


of jurisdiction

and now that the

arose this conflict


difficult

of law

abolished

it

ought not to be

to

accomplish this

reform^.

Simply

to recognise the equitable

owner as

legal

owner would effectually cause the anomaly complained of to

and it would not be in any way difiicult to provide gome new method of enforcing upon owners of property certain
disappear,
fiduciary

and other

obligations, such as are recognised in all

modern systems

of jurisprudence, but which, in

common with

the whole system of trusts, depend in England upon this

anomalous double ownership.


336.

The

doctrine of the

Enghsh Court

of Chancery in No

respect of ownership has been compared first to one,


to another institution of tlie
I doubt if

and then
only the
ago,

^^ equit*
^'^''^

Roman

law;

and

if

and

we are nearer to it now than we were twenty years do not think any attempt is being made to bring it about.

;:

172
ownership
law.

OWNERSHIP.
o
it

[Chap. VIII.

germ

were to be there founds

its

existence in
for.

any modern
there
is

system would be more easily accounted


nothing
like it.

But

There

is

to be

found in the

Roman law

a body

of rules supplementing the old stricter law, something like our

system of equity.
ship

There was what was called bonitary ownercalled quiritary ownership


;

and what was two kinds


For

and in theory

these

of ownership

might

co-exist.

But where

there was a bonitary owner the quiritary owner was entirely


excluded.
all practical

purposes there was but one owner;


re-

there was no conflict.

There are also to be found well


certain
relations

cognised in the

Roman law

of a

special

fiduciary character, which are governed

by

special rules

framed

with a view to their nature.

Hence much

that takes place

in our Courts of Chancery, where similar fiduciary relations


are specially considered, has its analogy in

Roman

law.

But

there

is

nothing in the

Roman

law analogous to the relative


equitable owners of property.

position of the

common law and


what may be

The point

of contact has been supposed to be,

where the
there was
case.

praetor, exercising

called his equitable jurisdiction,

enforced what was called a fidei commissum.


not, as in England,

But

any

conflict of

ownership in such a

What

the praetor did, was

to

compel the transfer of the


the fiduciary
request.

ownership in accordance with


other institution of

The

Roman law which

has been referred to as


is

analogous to the Chancery ownership

what

is

called nsus

and in former times (probably


connexion) what

in reference to this supposed


trusts

we now

call

were then called

uses.

But the Roman

nsus was a wholly different and a far less

comprehensive conception. house granted the

When

the

Roman owner

of

nstis of it to another, there


;

was nothing

fiduciary in the matter


like that of

and the relation created was very


It was, as

an ordinary tenant to his landlord.

the

name
It
all

imports, a right to occupy and

make

use of the

house.

was however a right over the thing available


the world, and therefore a fragment of ownership

against

but the grantor remained owner, he did not even lose the

Sec. 337.]

OWNERSHIP.

173

possession o the house.

And
;

the same was the ease with the

more extended right


detention,

of usufruct.

The grantee

of the usufruct

had not even the possession


these rights were classed

he had only the bare physical

which he held on behalf of the owner.

And

both

among

servitudes
^-

with rights of
features

way, rights to support, and so forth


of the relationship between the

The leading

common law and

equitable
trust

owner in England are wholly wantingconflict.

namely,

and

The

rights of the grantee of the

Roman

use no

doubt derogate from the absolute ownership, but the rights of


the grantee and the rights which remain in the owner stand
clearly separated,
benefit.

and each may use

his rights for his

own

In England the common law rights of one owner


in conflict,

and the equitable rights of the other are constantly


of Chancery,

and the common law owner would be restrained by the Court


if

he attempted to use a single right on his own

behalf

2.

337. I have noticed these peculiarities of the English law


at

Why

it is

some length, and have pointed out the


_'

fallacy of linking ^^ observe


'

them with

institutions of a wholly different character, chiefly '

*l'f? P?culiarities.

because of the very peculiar position

which English lawyers

occupy, with reference to the law which they are called upon
to administer.

Englishmen

are frequently transferred

from

the arena of the English courts, and the familiar practice of the English law of real property, to countries in which they

have to apply systems of law, which are either altogether


different
plete.

from their own, or which are


such circumstances

to a large extent incom-

Under
force

it is

certain that

we

shall

The

of this distinction will appear

more

clearly

from the

Chapter on Possession. ' To the reader who has had no experience of the working of English courts it may seem impossible that these conflicting views could co-exist in any one system. The Courts of Chancery, however, ingeniously contrived to avoid a direct conflict with Courts of Law by giving decrees which were in form in personam only. If the Courts of Law declared A to be the owner, the Courts of Chancery did not deny it, but took measures to compel A so to act as to give the real enjoyment of the
property to B.

74

OWNERSHIP.

[Chap. VIII.

be strongly tempted to transfer into the

new system

the ideas

we take with

us.

Some such
in India it

transfer

may

be in some cases

forced upon us

certainly has been so


filling'

as

the

only safe and practical method of


the declared law of that country.
in all such cases, to distinguish

up the huge gaps in


it is

But
to

most important
is

between that which

in conjuris-

sonance with the ideas

common
is

most systems of

prudence, and that which

anomalous and peculiar to our


it is

own.

Ideas of the former kind

sometimes not unsafe to


is

transfer.

But

to transfer ideas of the latter kind

always
fit is

very dangerous.
in

The imported

principle does not easily


it

with the institutions of the country into which


its

introduced, and consequently

introduction

is

very likely to
^.

throw the whole law


Feudal
Jiature ot

of that country into confusion


is

g3g_

rpj^g

ownership of land in Enorland r o

often said to be
it

English

based on feudal ideas

that
It

is,

upon ideas impressed upon

owner"

hy the
system.
'tenure.''

feudal system.

is

worth while to inquire what

^P'

j)^''ticular

form the ownership of land assumed under that


This form of ownership
is

what English lawyers

call

The word 'tenure'


all

indicates, as the books tell us,


lord.

the feudal relation between a tenant of land and his

Now
or

at

times and in

all places

we

find cases in which,

two

more persons having rights over a thing, some

sort of

relation exists between

them

arising out of those rights.


case under consideration

The
must

peculiarity, therefore, of the

' The recent attempts to employ English conceptions of ownership for the purpose of tying up the succession to property in Lower Bengal, are probably intended to counteract the effects of the impulse given under

British rule to the counter notion of the right of absolute alienation. It is a curious history. Owners of landed property -in Bengal met the introduction of English ideas as to the absolute right of alienation inter

demanding the right to make a. will declaring the course of This was again met by insisting that, if this were allowed, the English restrictions on perpetuities must also prevail. It may indeed be well doubted whether this method of proceeding can be justified, either legally or politically. Perliaps a compromise acceptable to the natives of India may be one day arrived at, by putting some restrictions on the
vivos by
succession.

caprice or prodigality of a single heir, without a wholesale introduction of our cumbrous English law of real property.

Sec. 338. 339-]

OWNERSHIP.
relation^

175

be sought not in the existence of the


nature of
it.

but in the

What

is

there peculiar from a legal point of

view in the feudal tenure ?


339. In examining the nature of the feudal tenure one Various
.

meets

with

the

,,

forms of
feudal

preliminary difficulty

that

it

ongmally

manifested

itself in

very various forms in different parts of


of these forms

Europe
into

and some

had probably penetrated


conquest.

England

before

the

Norman
it

After the

Norman
it

conquest the Frank type of feudalism became pre^

dominant^ but from the

moment

was planted
It
is,

in Eng^lish soil

became subject

to local influences.

therefore, a very

diflScult

thing to give a description of tenure which would

be accurate and complete.


is

But

for

my

present purpose this


is

not necessary.

All I

am now
may

seeking for

the legal

characteristics which distinguish the feudal tenure.

And
well

whatever discussions there

be about minor points, the


are

broad legal characteristics of the feudal tenure


established.

In

all cases of

feudal tenure

we

find ourselves

in presence of

two persons

an

owner of land, and one who

has rights over the land derived from the owner.


find that there
parties,
is

We

also

some kind of mutual obligation between the


it

which obligation (however


its

may have

originated)

does not depend for

continuance on any contract between


Further,

the parties, but

is

attached to the land.

we

find

that the grantor has parted with the whole use and enjoy-

ment

of the land to the grantee

but though the rights of

the grantor are thus reduced to a mere right to receive that

which has been agreed


grantee
is

on, yet

the grantor and not the

considered to

be the owner of the land;

the

grantee being merely owner of a right over a thing which


belongs to the grantor.

But

still

there

is

nothing peculiar in

any one

of these characteristics.

They
and

are to be found in the

emphyteusis of the

Roman law

in the

modern tenancies
There
is

of a fanner or other lessee, which are not feudal.

Chief pe-

however, one thing which distinguishes the feudal relation

^^^^.fj

from

all

other relations between the owner of land and his tenure.

76

OWNERSHIP.

[Chap. VIII.

grantee.

This consists in the introduction of a very stringent


or, to

personal relation between the grantor and grantee,

use the

feudal expression, between the lord and his tenant.


sonal relation

This perof the jus

was created separately from the grant


it

in re, but as soon as to


it,

was created it became inseparably annexed


It

and with

it

constituted the feudal tenure.

was not

concluded in the form of a contract, or of a gift upon condition,

but of submission

the tenant binding himself by oath to be

faithful to his lord,

and the lord undertaking

to protect his

tenant.

Services were attached to the tenure, which varied,

and might be altogether absent.


of mutual defence
Political

But the one

essential

and

distinguishing feature of the feudal relation was the obligation

and

protection.

rather

than legal
taiu;T" of it.

^ immense, and in turbulent times


.
.

340. The

political \

importance of
.

such a

relation

was

it

held out great advantages.

-"-^

^'^^ ^

bond of union as

close as that of kinship,

which

it

probably to some extent replaced.


political

It

was a ready means


it

of

and military organisation, and


it

was

so used.

In

England

was

carried

so far as to

embrace the ordinary

relation of sovereign

and subject, which was united to tenure

by the

fiction that all land


is,

was held

xiltimately of the king.

341. It

I think, obvious that the importance of the


is it

feudal system

due almost entirely to the use which was


for
political
(if

thus

made

of

and military purposes


it

its

special juristical features

indeed

has any) appear to be

mostly accidental.

The

reciprocal duties of lord

and tenant

could easily have been created


action without

any legal

by contract and enforced by innovation. That they were not so


and arrange-

created and so enforced was a mere matter of convenience.

That they were

in reality matter of negotiation

ment

there can be no doubt.

Even some

of the services which

are considered specially feudal, because they are found annexed


to the feudal tenure,

and have not been found except in that

connexion in Europe, are

common enough
upon
hills

in India.

The
is,

ghatwals of Lower Bengal, for example, the holders, that


of the agri limitrophi bordering

occupied

by

hostile

Sec. 340-343.

OWNERSHIP.

177

tribes,

are

bound to guard the ghats or mountain passes

as a condition of their holding.

Nothing

is

wanting but

homage to make their relation to the rajahs, who granted them their lands, a feudal one. But just because homage is
wanting
it

seems to be quite unwarrantable to speak of this

relation as feudal.

342. enjoys

The
all

incident of feudal tenure that the feudal tenant Feudal


tenant an

aliens,, is

the rights of an owner, and yet has only jus in re owner. found in many other arrangements for the enjoyland.

ment of
lord:

The grantor

of the

emphyteusis has com-

pletely severed his connexion with the land as the feudal

the rights of the emphyteuta might be as full and

general as those of any feudal tenant; yet the former was


still

dominus and the

latter

had only jus

in re aliena

down

to

the very latest period.

343.

As soon

as people

came

to rely for protection not

on Feudal

the feudal relation, but on the ordinary courts of justice and unsuited on the government, a feudal tenure ceased to be anything * p<lern

more than an arrangement, and that a clumsy


lands which he had granted away.

one, for ad- ments.

justing the pecuniary interest of the superior owner in the


Its vagueness

gave great

power of oppression, and


which
it

it

was in many ways objectionable.


itself,

These objections have been removed, but the thing


is

now a mere

shadow, remains.

It does no

good and
the But
evils

does some mischief, by the perpetuation of obsolete forms.


it
is

But

desirable to

remember that the


if

abolition of

remaining traces of feudalism would not,

the above observa-

not

tions are correct, suffice to cure the evils of the English land fgu^alism Those evils are due, not to feudalism, but to the conlaw.

trivances

by which English lawyers have been allowed to elude the wholesome maxims which have prevailed elsewhere.
In almost every case where the law has forbidden something
with regard to the land, the lawyers have
set

about doing the

same thing with regard


not allowed to do
the 'use.'
it

to an
'

'

estate

'

in the land.

When

with the

estate^ they have done it with


it

When

not allowed to do

with the 'use' they

178

OWNERSHIP.
it

[Chap. Vlir.

have done

with the

'trust,' or

with the 'term.^

Much

more than a complete eradication of feudal


to counteract these devices.
Discussions as to

ideas is necessary

344. There are

many
it

points of view from which,


difference

and many

who

is

purposes for which,

makes no

who

of several per-

owner.

sons having rights in

owner.

The

rules as

rem over a thing is considered the to the mode in which the right is to
;

be enforced
it is

if

denied, or recovered if lost


;

the rules by which


its

transferred or inherited

and generally

legal aspect,

will be the same whether the person claiming the right be

considered as owner or not.

But two very important

questions

which

lie

at the bottom of all contentions as to the ownership


to

are these

whom

do the accessions belong ? and upon


lie ?

whom

in an action does the burden of proof

Ownership of

345. These are the two questions which are at the bottom
of the controversy

land in
India.

which has been

so

long carried on in India


sight
it

as to the ownership of land. to be so very important

At
is

first

does not appear

who

called the owner,

and

it is

only

when we
of
it
;

perceive the

immense advantage

of the presumptions of the importance

attached to ownership that

we become aware

and of the necessity of being very careful to

whom we
itself

give this advantage, and on what conditions.


Legislation of

346. This

was the problem which presented


It does not appear that

for

Lord
Cornwallis

solution to the Indian Legislature in Bengal at the end of the


last century.

in

Lord Cornwallis and

Bengal.

his advisers fully apprehended the

nature of the problem.

Being mainly dependent for their resources on the land


revenue, they naturally inclined to
hitherto

make
still

the person
for
this

who had
and at

discharged that burden

liable

it,

the same time to declare

him

the owner.

In

they were

probably right; indeed they could have hardly done otherwise.

But probably because they did not

perceive the dangerous

position in which they thereby placed all the other persons

who had
persons
:

claims on the land, they did nothing to protect these

simply leaving them to prove their rights against


if

the landowner

they could.

Practically this

was

in a vast

Sec. 344-346.]

OWNERSHIP.

179

number of cases impossible^ and numberless subordinate tenureholders had to succumb.

Obviously what should have been

done wasj contemporaneously with the grant of ownership to


the zamindars (landholders) the rights
of all

the

under-

tenants should have been recorded and confirmed.

This

is

what has been done


years
of

in other parts of India.


injustice,

In Bengal, after
has been

misery

and

the

legislature

compelled to step in and endeavour to redress the grievances


of the under-tenants^.
See the Bengal Tenancy Act (Act VIII of 1885). A story which of the land question in India was told by Lord Lawrence when the question Was being debated in the Indian
'

illustrates the difficulties

who were the owners of the land in the Punjab. Happening on one occasion to meet a party of hill-men he asked, pointing to the hill side, Whose land is this ? Ours,' they all exclaimed. Then he went to some of the chief men in the village and
Legislative Council, as to
'

The land is ours,' said thy. Then he went and again asked the same question. 'The land is all mine,' replied the Kajah, 'to whom else should it belong?' Each of these parties had certain jura in re over the land, and might, in a sense, have proved their assertions without settling any real dispute. The injustice that was done by simply declaring the zamindar to be the owner without making any provision for the protection of the rights of the raiyat is graphically described in the Introduction to Sir William Hunter's Bengal
asked the same question.
'

to the Bajah,

Manuscript Becords.

CHAPTEE
POSSESSION.

IX.

347. In this chapter I propose to base

my

observations
subject.

mainly upon Savigny's well-known

treatise

on the

Notwithstanding the criticisms to which Savigny's conception


of possession has been subjected,
it

seems to

me to
to

be

still

the

only one

which

is is

clear

and

consistent,

and

be in the Savigny's

main that which


treatise is

accepted by English lawyers.

founded upon the

Roman

law, and consists in a

great measure of minute criticisms of the Latin texts, and an


exhaustive inquiry into the actual views on possession held

by
his

the

Roman

lawyers.

It

is

not these parts of Savigny's works

of which I have

made

use.

What

I have borrowed

is

analysis of the general conception of possession.

We

also

now

possess a systematic treatise

on possession in

the English language of the highest value, to which I shall


also frequently refer
Physical idea of
possession,
^.

348. Possession originally expresses the simple notion of


a physical capacity to deal with a thing as
exclusion of every one
else.
,
.
,

we like, The primary and main

to the

object
;

of ownership
^

is

the protection of this physical capacity


originally published

and,
later

Savigny's treatise was

in

1803.

The

editions published in the author's lifetime

him.

The

last edition

was published

at

were considerably altered by Vienna in 1865. It has been

translated by Sir Erskiue Perry.

Ihering's treatise (Der Besitzwille)

was published
in the

at

Common Law was

Jena in 1889. Pollock and Wright's Essay on Possession published at the Clarendon Press in 1888.


POSSESSION.
as pointed out

181
condition

by Savignyi,
all

if

this physical

had

aJone to be considered,

that could be said upon possession

from a

juristical point of view,


:

would be contained in the

following sentences
possess
it.

The owner of a thing has the right to Every one has the same right to whom the owner

has given the possession.

No

one

else

has that right.


is

349. The legal notion of possession, however,


to this simple physical condition.

not confined Legal idea


treated in ll^^^^'

Possession
is

is

law, not only as a physical condition which

protected

by

ownership, but as a right in

itself.

From

possession, under

certain conditions, important legal consequences are derived

and in advanced systems

of

law the right of possession

is

frequently separated from the right of ownership.

Moreover,
is

the possession with which the law thus deals


simple physical condition which

not that
above,

we have

described

and to which,
the

for the sake of distinction, therefore, It


is

we give
is

name

detention.

true that the physical element

never altogether lost sight of j

on the contrary, a physical


is

element of some kind or other


possession in
sequel.
its

essentially necessary to

widest legal sense, as

we

shall see in the

But
So

this physical

clement greatly varies under rules

prescribed

by law.
also,

350.

inasmuch as possession

is

a right in

itself,

rules are laid

down by
it

the law, as in other similar cases

in the case of ownership, for instance

which

prescribe the

mode

in

which

may

be gained or

lost.

351. There has been a good deal of controversy in

Germany
(from

Legal con-

upon the
possession ?

question,

What

are
^

the

legal

consequences

of ^f j

Savigny maintains

that the

Roman Law
;

which, no doubt, modern

jurists

mostly derive their ideas on


namely,

the subject) attributed only two rights to possession the acquisition

of ownership by possession (usucapio),

and
of

the protection of possession from disturbance (interdicium)^.

Other lawyers
possession,
'

would

include,

as

legal

consequences

the acquisition of
s.

ownership by occupancy or
a. 2,

Sav. Poss.

1, p.

27.

"

lb.

p. 29.

'

lb. 6. 3, p. 32.

182
delivery
;

POSSESSION.

[Chap. IX.

the advantage which the person in possession has,


is

in a contest as to ownership, that the burden of proof

thrown upon his adversary ; the right to use


possession
;

force in defending

the right of the possessor, merely as such, to use

and enjoy

(to

some extent) the thing

in possession

and some

other advantages of a more intricate kind.


is

This controversy

one which

it

is

not necessary for us to pursue.

Every

known

system of law attributes some legal consequences to


;

possession

and even in cases in which

it

may

be, strictly

speaking, incorrect to attribute legal consequences to possession, as in the case of

occupancy or tradition, the acquisition

of possession

may

yet be an important element of inquiry, and

the subject of legal regulation.


Physical
tlie

352. I will

now

proceed to consider what


;

is

the conception

con-

of possession in a legal sense

and I

will first
lies

examine the

"

Physical element which, as I have said, ossession the conception of possession.

at the

bottom of

853

^-

It

is

very

common

to say that possession consists

in the corporal seizure or apprehension of the thing possessed

by the

possessor,

and

that, in all cases


is

where

this corporal
fictitious

contact does not exist, there


possession.

not a

real,

but only a

And

there has been derived from this a theory

of symbolical possession,

which Savigny considers to be not

only erroneous, but to the last degree confusing,

when we

come
Contact not necessory.

to

deal with practical questions,

and which he has

The truth is that, though we ii-i undoubtedly do possess most of the thmgs with which we are in corporal contact, and though we come into corporal contact
taken great pains to combat.

iinii

cii-

at

some time or other with most of the things which we


whatever to do with the
sits

possess, corporal contact has nothing

matter.

A man

walking along the road with a bundle


his bundle

down

to rest,

and places

on the ground at a short

distance from him.

No

one thinks of doubting that the

bundle remains in his exclusive possession, not symbolically


or fictitiously, but really
'

and actually
s.

whereas the ground

Sav. Poss.

14, p.

206 sqq.


Sec. 352-356.]

POSSESSION.
sits,

183
is,

on which he

and with which he

therefore, in corporal

contact, is not in his possession at


it

all.

So, as Savigny puts

bound hand and foot with cords no one thinks of saying that he possesses the cords it would be just as true to say that the cords possess him.
is
;

very forcibly, a

man

354 ^. Corporal contact, therefore, is not the physical element which is involved in the conception of possession. It is rather
the possibility of dealing with a thing as we
like,

and of excludposses-

ing others.
sion
is

If

we

consider the various

modes in which

gained and lost


^.

we

shall recognise this


first

very clearly.

355

Take, for instance,

the case of land.


price,

man Acquisi^'^^^'

buys a piece of land.


sign the contract of
It
is

He

pays the

and both

parties session of

sale.

The buyer goes


all

to take possession.

not necessary for him to come into physical contact with


over
it.

every part of the land by walking

He

enters

upon

it

and stands there; the


;

seller

withdraws or

signifies

his assent
is

and the buyer


If the seller

is

at once in full possession.

This
is

on the supposition that the claim to take possession


is

unopposed.
right

there and disputes the purchaser's

to take
is

possession,

however unjustly, or

if

a third

person

there

who

disputes the right of both, all the walking


is

upon the land

in the world, until this opposition

overcome,

will not give the buyer possession;

and for
is

this reason

because the physical element which

necessary to put the

buyer in possession

is

not corporal contact, but the physical

power of deahng with the land exclusively as his own. In such a case there are but two modes in which he can obtain
possession
yield, or

by inducing those who oppose him by overcoming their opposition by force.


either
is

to

356. It

not necessary in order to obtain possession that


all.

the purchaser should step on to the land at


at hand, and the seller points
it

If

it is

near

out to the buyer, and shows

that the possession


it

is

vacant, and signifies his desire to

hand

over to the buyer, whilst the buyer signifies his desire to


it,
1

receive

enough has been done


s.

to transfer the possession*


'

Say. Poss.

14, p. 211.

lb.

b.

15, p.

212 sqq.

84

POSSESSION.

[Chap. IX.

The

physical possibility of the buyer dealing with the thing


is

exclusively as his own, which

all
it

that

is

necessary, exists,
to the land

whether he thinks proper to use


or not.
Possession

by stepping on

357. If
possession,

how

re-

we we

consider

what

is

necessary in order to retain

shall find the

same notion more strikingly


possession, it
is

tamed.

exemplified.

In order to retain

not necessary

that the possessor should remain on or even near the land.


Possession having been once received,
it is

not necessary that

the physical power of dealing with the land as he pleases should be retained by the possessor at every

moment
it.

of time.

He

will

continue in possession,

if

he can reproduce that


wishes

physical power at any

moment he

A man

who

leaves his home, and goes to follow his business in a neigh-

bouring town,

may

still

retain possession of his family house

and property.
Acquis!-

368^.

An

examination into the mode of acquiring the

session of possession of

moveable things will lead us to the same

result,

move-

Possession

of moveable things
is

can undoubtedly be taken,


oneself in corporal

and very frequently


contact

taken,
I

by placing

with them.
it

can take possession of money by


of a coat

putting

into

my
by

pocket;
sitting

back

of a chair

upon

it.

by putting it on my But this contact is not

necessary.

I should take possession of the

money
if it

just as
if

well
it

if it

were laid on the table before

me

of the coat,

were put into

my

wardrobe ; of the chair,


if

were placed

in

my

house.

In the same way,

I purchase heavy goods

lying at a public wharf, I take possession of


to

them by going

them with the

seller,

and by

his

there signifying his

intention to deliver them, and


to receive them.

by

my

signifying

my

intention

So
is

also, if I

buy goods stored

in a ware-

house, possession

given to

me by handing

over the keys.

So

too,

timber

is

delivered
seller
;

by the buyer marking the logs in


not because of the corporal contact

the presence of the


or prehension

which takes place in marking, but because that


*

Sav. Poss.

a.

16, p. 216.

Sec. 357-361-]
is

POSSESSION.

185

the intention of the parties.

The marking might take


if

place without any change of possession; as for instance,.

the logs were marked to prevent their being changed, but

they were not to be delivered 359. In alL these cases


that there
is

till

the price was paid

^.

it

is

a great mistake to suppose


constructive

anything

fictitious, or symbolical, or

in the acquisition of possession.

Each

case depends on the

physical possibility of dealing with the thing as


of excluding others.

we

like,

and

In

all

the cases above put, except two,

the thing

is

actually present before us.

But

in

one of these

two, namely that in which

ing the thing in

my
;

house,

a well-known principle,

we say possession is taken by placwe only apply to a particular case which embodies the very idea we are
by reason
of the complete
it^.

now

insisting on
is

namely that a man has the actual custody and


of

of all that
exclusive
these

in his house,

dominion which he has over


cases
is

The other

two

that in which the keys of the warehouse,


stored, are

where the goods are


the buyer.
this, of

handed over by the

seller to

But

there cannot be a

more complete way than

giving to the buyer the power of dealing with the

things sold exclusively as his

own ^.
them has once been
^bies how 'stained,

360.

And
it

as in the case of immoveable things, so in the Possession

case of moveables,

when

possession of

taken,

may

be retained so long as the power exists of re-

producing the physical capacity of dealing with the thing and


of excluding others.

Thus,

if

after

handing over and

receivseller
so,

ing possession of goods at a public wharf both buyer and

go away, the goods remain


however,
if

in possession of the buyer.

Not

the goods are in the warehouse of a private person,


to give the

unless the

owner of the warehouse agrees

buyer the

use of the warehouse as a place for keeping his goods.

361
sion

*.

Instructive illustrations of the conception of posses- Capture of

may also

live animals.
'
'

be gained by a consideration of the possession of ^jjnais Those animals which ordinarily exist only in
o.

Sav. Poss.
lb.
s.

16, p. 319.

'
*

lb.

s.
D.

17, p. 226.

16, p. S23.

lb.

31, p. 342.

186

POSSESSION.
state,

[Ohap. IX.

a domestic

such as cows and horses, hardly differ from

other moveable property.

Animals, on the other hand, which

are in a wild state, are only in our possession as long as they are so completely in captivity that

we can immediately
fish in

lay

hold of them.

We We

do not possess the

a river,

even
it,

though the

river,

and the exclusive right


do not even possess the

of fishing in
fish in

belongs to us.

a pond,

if

the pond be so large that the fish can escape from us,

when

we go
at

to take them.

But we do

possess fish,

when once they


we can

are placed in a stew or other receptacle, so small that

any moment go and take them

out.

Animals that have

been born wild, but have been tamed, are generally considered to be in the

same position as animals which are


if

bom
wild

tame, so long as they do not escape

let

loose.

A
is

animal that has been wounded mortally by


our possession until

us,

not in
is

we have

laid hold of it

for not only

the physical control yet wanting, but a thousand things

may

happen which
larger animal

will

prevent us ever getting


;

it.

Another
get into

a hole
'

may seize it and carry it off it may we may lose its track and so forth ^.
;

For the purpose of explaining possession, I state the law relating to the capture of wild animals as deriTed by continental lawyers fronj the Roman Law. This law has, in England, been Tery considerably modified, by reason of the more exclusive privileges generally conceded to owners of land. There is not the lesst difficulty in a man having possession of that of which he is not the owner ; and it was not inconsistent with the
idea

which attaches
Jf so,
it

to our
all

land as in possession of
there.
! trespasser kills

word close,' to treat the owner of enclosed the game which at any time happens to be
'

was correct to decide (as has been decided) that when game on my land the game is mine. See the case of

Common Bench Eeports, new But the idea analogous to that expressed by the word close hardly existed under the Boman Law, and I doubt if there is anything quite analogous to it on the continent. We find, however, that the French Law does not apply the restrictions as to killing game to a person doing so dans ses possessions attenant a une habitation et entour^es d'une clSture continue faisant obstacle a tovjte communication avec les heritages yoisins.' Loi du 3 Mai, 1844, sur la police de la chasse
Blades against Higgs, reported in the
series, vol. xx. p. 214.
' '
'

probably because the nature of the locality is inconsistent with the absence of possession, and the absence of possession as well as ownership is assumed in all the French laws on the subject of
art.
i.

sect. 2.

This

is

game.

See infra,

sect. 48a.

Sec. 362, 363.J

POSSESSION.

187
of

362.
is

The
will

consideration of the modes in which possession Loss

lost

make

the result clearer


is

still.

Every act by
puts

of mOTe"-'^
^^'''^

which our physical control


us out of possession.
It

completely destroyed
difference

makes no

whether the

person

who

does the act himself gains possession thereby,

or indeed whether

any one does

so.

Thus,
it

if

I take any-

thing belonging to you, and throw


lose

into
it.

the sea,

you
also

possession,

though no one gains

We may

lose possession of

a thing, not only by the act of another


it,

person in removing
stances,

but simply because, under the circumlonger exercise that control;


as,

we cannot any
if

for

instance,

a tiny jewel drops from


forest, or if

my

hand

in passing
its

through a dense

a captured animal of

own

accord escapes back into the wild.

So

also, if

we
is it

leave a

thing somewhere, but cannot recollect where, and search for


it

in vain,

we have
still

lost possession of

it.

There

said to

be an exception to this where the thing, though

cannot

be found,
premises ;

is

in the owner's house, or on his adjoining

as, for instance, if I


it,

drop a coin in
it
is

my

garden, and

cannot, on searching, find


possession of
it.

said that I do not lose

But

there

is

a reason for this which shows

that

it is

no

real exception.
is,

Everything in a man's house,


^,

and in
widely

his garden,

on a principle already adverted to


the law,
considered
to

and
the

recognised

by

be

in

immediate custody of the owner of the house and garden,

by reason
and
all

of his exclusive control

and dominion over them


does not lose possession

persons residing therein,

363.

On

the other hand, a

man
if

of a thing
to

by leaving

it

in a place

which he knows, and

which he can return.

Thus,

I leave

my

hatchet in

a wood, intending to return the next day and continue

my
if

work, I retain possession of the hatchet

all

the time
it

^.

But

any one

else

should find

it,

and should take

away, from that

moment

I lose possession.
'

Supra,

sect.
s.

359

Sav. Posa.

s.

31, p. 340,

'

Sar. Poss.

31, p. 341.

188
Loss of

POSSESSION.

[Chap. IX.

364.

of land! ables.

control
ceases.

The same general rule applies to the loss of immoveThe possession lasts so long as there is any physical over them, and ceases when that physical control
I do not lose possession of
friends
there.

my

house by

filling

it

with
leave

my

and servants, even

if

I should go away^ and

them

But should

they, on

my

return, refuse

me

admittance, declining upon some pretext to acknowledge

my

rights as owner, then, until I have ejected them, I have lost


possession.
Loss of
by^intru6ion.

365

^.

There was a rule in the

Roman Law

that

if,

in

absence, a piece
possession,

of land, which had hitherto been in

my my
if

was occupied by another, who would oppose me

I attempted to return and exercise

my

rights over the land,

I did not thereby lose possession until I was informed of the intrusion.

Such a

rule
it

is

clearly in conflict with the

notion of possession, as

has been developed above.


a thing as

The

physical power of dealing with

we

like being

necessary, according to our conception, to constitute possession


in a legal sense,
it

follows that

when

I have lost this, whether

I
is,

know

it

or not, I

have

lost possession.

The question then


this rule,

whether we must, in consequence of


of possession,

modify our
does not

general conception

with which

it

harmonise

Savigny has examined

this at great length,


it

and

has decided that


as

we ought
case.

not,
is

but that

ought to be treated

an exceptional

It

in fact a fiction, introduced, as

fictions

generally are, to avoid consequences that are con-

sidered to be inconvenient or unjust.

The

fiction is

that I

remain in possession when I have really ceased to be so ; and


it

no more modifies the general notion of possession than

the similar fiction on which was founded the old action of

ejectment.

It has never (as far as I


it

am

aware) been ex-

tended to moveables ; and, of course,


those systems of law in which
Mental
concepit

can be applied only in

has been expressly recognised.


in Savigny's opinion,

366

The physical element, however,

forms only one portion of the conception of possession.


'

Be-

Sav. Poss.

s.

31, pp. 348, 353.

n,_ g

20, p. 246.

Sec. 364-368.]

POSSESSION.
is

189
I

sides this,

he considers that there

what

may

call

a mental

element, without which the physical relation will remain as

tion of P^^^^^^io"-

a mere

fact,

having no legal consequences, and not in any


In order to conexist,

way

subject to special legal considerations.

stitute possession in a legal sense, there

must

not only

the physical power to deal with the thing as

we

like,

and

to

exclude others, but also the determination to exercise that


physical power on our

own

behalf.

367. This
possession
case.

important feature in the legal conception of Transfer


be illustrated by the consideration of a simple
tion with!^*Pss63-

may

person has a valuable article of jewelry which he

wishes to send from London to his house in the country j and


for that purpose he gives
to take it to his house,
it

to his servant

with instructions
to his wife.

and there
True

deliver

it

The

servant does not thereby gain possession of the jewelry, nor

does the master lose

it.

it is
;

that the servant has the

physical control over the jewelry

but, if he is obedient to his

master's orders, he has no intention of exercising that control

upon

his

own

behalf.

The

master, on the other hand,

by

delivering the jewelry to his servant, does not for one


lose possession of
it, if

moment
Through
also

his orders be carried out.

his servant,

who
is

is

obedient to his orders, he has the physical

control

which

necessary to possession;

and he has

determined to exercise that physical control on his own behalf.


368. The position, that possession (in a legal sense) con- Transfer
sists
^

not

only

in

the

physical control,
it

but

also
is

determination to exercise
apparent,
if

on one's own behalf,


is

the aion"bv equally change of


in

mindonly.

Supwe consider how possession pose that you and I are living together in the same house And that you are the owner, and that I am a lodger. in want of money, sell the house suppose that you, being to me that you receive the money, aqd formally acknowledge
transferred.
;

me

as the owner, agreeing to pay

me

a weekly sum for permis-

sion to continue to reside in the house.

No
;

external change

whatever need have taken place in our relative position ; we

may

continue to live on precisely as before

yet there can be

190

POSSESSION.

[Chap. IX.

no doubt that I

am now

in possession of the houses

and that

you are not


Intention
to possess
.

i.

ggQ j^ order
it is

to constitute possession (in a legal sense)


. .

need not
present,

not necessary that the intention to possess should be

constantly present to
to exercise

my

mind.

If I

have once determined

my

physical control

over a thing on

my own
I

behalfj

and

so completed

my

possession, it will be sufficient

for the purpose of retaining possession, that I should, if

adverted to
to

it,

keep to that determination.

Savigny seems

go further, and to think that, provided the physical conpossession continues also unless I have

trol continues, the

adverted to
is

it
;

and changed
it is it

my determination ^. Whether this


or whether
it is sufficient that, if

so or not

whether

necessary, in order to lose possession,


;

that I should advert to


I adverted to
it,

should determine not to exercise that

physical control any longer, or at least not on

my own

behalf,

we need
case,

not further discuss

because in this, as in every other


into the state of

where we have

to inquire
it

mind

of
:

a person, we can only judge of

from external circumstances

and the external circumstances from which we should


place, are precisely those

infer

that afUr advertence a change of determination had taken

which upon advertence would render


likely.

a change of determination

For instance, we infer that

the gold digger has abandoned his possession of the quartz

from which he has extracted the gold, because we know that


he could have no further use for
^

it,

and men do not generally

In Pollock and Wright on Possession, p. 124, it is stated that 'a purse the street, the owner knows not where, may in point of law still he in his possession.' Further on it is said, 'even bona vacantia for which no owner or possessor can be found are perhaps to be treated not
lost in

as being in the possession of nobody, but as being in the possession of

a person
wilful

who cannot be

ascertained.

It is

even doubted whether

it is

possible for a possessor to divest himself of his possession of a thing

by abandonment of it.' Of course, this involves a view of possession radically different from that taken in the text. It gets rid entirely of both the physical and mental elements, some combination of which is considered by most persons to constitute the legal conception of possession (see Pollock and Wright on Possession, pp. 11, 16).
'

Sav. Poss.

s.

32, p. 355.

860.369,3700
care to keep
inference,

POSSESSION.

191

what

is

useless

and we should draw the same


is

whether an actual determination to abandon In

necessary or not.
possession
is

many
it

such cases
troubling

we

affirm that the

gone, without
exactly

ourselves

with

the

inquiry

when
,

was parted with.


it

370. Questions however sometimes arise which render


necessary to determine with exactness the point of time
possession
is lost
;

How
change of
as'

.,,

when mind
^^^

and

if

the physical control does not pass


this is frequently a question of

"^"^"^

at once into

any other hands,

no

little difficulty.

If indeed the party in possession chooses


it,

publicly to declare his intention to abandon


is

the difficulty

then solved.

But

in the absence of such a declarationj

we have not
For
instance,

only to infer the change of mind from the

surrounding circumstances, but also the date of that change.


if

the person

of a piece of land neglects to

who has been in possession cultivate it, or make any other


pretty safely infer that he

use of

it

for some years,


it.

we may

has abandoned

But

if it is

necessary to determine exactly

when he abandoned

it,

we can
first

hardly
instance^

tell.

He may
when he
:

have

omitted to cultivate, in the

from want

of means,
finally

and may have abandoned

his possession only

discovered that to procure such means was hopeless

or

from
not

the experience of previous years he


cultivation at present prices

may have

concluded that
;

was unprofitable

but

may

then have abandoned

all

hope of a better market.

Thus, the

date at which his determination to possess finally changed

may

have been considerably

later

than the

first

season for
case,

cultivation which he allowed to pass.

In such a

howwould

ever, in the absence of all evidence to the contrary, it

be usual to take the date of the


to

first

indication of an intention

abandon

that

is,

of the first omission to cultivate


it

as the

date of that determination, leaving


establish

to those interested to
'.

any other

date, if they could

^ I do not think an intention to abandon possession would ever be presumed from the mere inaction of the owner with regard to waste and valueless land or unworked mines. On the contrary, I think the owner would be considered as always in possession so long as there was no in-

192
Possession
represen-

POSSESSION.
1.

[Chap. IX.

371

That a person can be in possession o a thing by


been doubted.

his representative has never

But

there has
to the

^ "'

not been a complete agreement amongst jurists as nature of that possession.


as a fictitious possession
;

It has been frequently treated

but against this Savigny argues,

and,
is real
"

it

appears to me, successfully.

372.

The

error of treating possession

through a represenis

tative as fictitious or constructive possession only

a branch

of the error noted above,

which

treats corporal contact as


is

necessary to true possession.


possession being the

All that

necessary to
control,

my
and

power to resume physical

the determination to exercise that control on


it
is

my own

behalf,

clear that I possess the

money

in the pocket of
bailiff,

my

servant, or the
as the rings

farm in the hands of

my

just as

much

on

my

finger, or the furniture of the

house in

which I
Subsesent of
sufficT^t

live.

373.

This, however,

presumes a

representative

who

is

obedient to

my

commands.

In other words, whilst, in order

^ constitute possession of a thing through

I must determine to exercise control over

it

my representative, on my own behalf,


me
to exercise

the representative must also determine to allow that control.


trusion.

As soon

as

my

representative determines to

This I take to be the true ground of the decision in the case

Agency Company 0. Short, Law Eeports, Appeal Gases, vol. xiii, P- 793) which has been much discussed both in Europe and America. There the question was as to the possession of a piece of waste and valueless land. If an owner gets out of possession, and the Statute of Limitations
of

begins to run against him,

it is difficult

to see

how

it

can cease to do so

But the Court in this case seems to have thought that, when the intruder went out and no one else "went in, the owner was restored to possession without any act of ownership on his part. This, under the peculiar circumstances of the case, was a justifiable inference. It has no connexion with the legal doctrine of remitter. ^ Sav. Poss. s. 26, p. 304, The idea of possession through another person varies somewhat with the relation between the parties. It is strongest (if I may use the expression) where the relation is that of master and slave less strong where the relation is that of master and servant but nevertheless stronger here than where the relation is that of ordinary principal and agent. The difference between theft by a servant, and criminal misappropriation, in the Indian Penal Code depends upon this variation. See ss. 381 and 405.
until he again gets into possession.
;
;


POSSESSION.

Sec. 37I-375-]

193

assume control on his own behalf, or to submit to the control of another than myself, my possession is gone. If there
be any cases in which this rule does not apply, they are exceptions which the law has introduced to obviate the effects
of fraud, or for
discussed,

some similar purpose

as in the case already

where some one has intruded upon the property


^.

of an absent owner

374. It

is

not necessary, in order that the principal

may

Represen-

get into possession, that he should have had his attention ^^gt turned to the fact that his representative has brought the i5.ssent,

thing under his control.

It
;

will

be

sufficient

that

the

representative has this control


it,

that he means to exercise


;

not for himself, but for his principal

and that

in so

doing, he acts within the scope of the authority conferred

upon him.
that, even

Probably also English lawyers would consider


if

without

my

authority you assumed

control
to

over a thing on

my

behalf,

and I subsequently assented


as if the act

your

act, I

was in the same position

had been

done originally by
really

commence
^.

my order. But my possession till my assent was given.


how

would not

375

It

is

desirable here to point out

the doctrines Possession

of representative

possession are applied to such persons as and luua-

infants and lunatics,

whom

"^' the law considers as labouring

under incapacity.
first

The

case

of

these persons appears at


difficulties.

sight to present considerable

It

may

be

said that, as possession in the legal

sense comprises a de-

termination of the will,

it

follows that persons

whom

the

law considers

as incapable of

making such determination

such as children under a certain age and lunatics


capable of acquiring possession;
that,

are

in-

however completely

they

may

have obtained physical control over a thing, they


it is

can have no possession in a legal sense; that

(as the

Roman

lawyers expressively said) as

if

one were to put a

thing into the hand of a person asleep^.

Nor

can they

acquire possession through the act of a representative; for


^

Supra,

s.

365.

'

Sav. Poss.

s.

21, p. 248.

'

Dig. 41.

2. i. 3.

194

POSSESSION.

[Chap. IX.
still

the assent of the lunatic or infant as principal would

be necessary to complete
is

it,

and this the infant or lunatic

equally incompetent to give.

376.

To

solve

this

difficulty

we must remember
is is

that

the only representative of an infant


dian,

his parent or guarhis

and that the only representative of a lunatic

com-

mittee.

Now

the relation of the parent or guardian to the

infant, or the relation of the


is

guardian to the lunatic


not the
simple

who

intrusted

to

his

care,

is

and ordinary
a very special

relation of principal

and representative
it is,

it

is

one

and the primary feature of

that the representative

here supplies the mental deficiency of the person


represents.

whom

he

His determination on behalf of his incapacitated


result

principal

has the same

as

the

determination of a

principal of full capacity on behalf of himself.

Hence

it

follows, that if the guardian, for instance, acquires the physical control

over a thing, and determines to exercise that

physical control on behalf of his ward,

though

it

might

be a straining of language to say that the ward was in


possession, yet

between the guardian and the ward, who


is

are

in
is

a manner identified, there


in

one complete person


possession has pre-

who

complete possession

which

cisely the

same

results for the benefit of the infant as the

possession of a fully competent person.

So

too,

where the

ward himself
possession.

obtains

the physical control over the thing,


is

the guardian can supply what

necessary to complete the

For
so

the the

ward

is

under
can

the

control

of

the
the

guardian,
control

that
his his

guardian

determine

that

which

ward has obtained

shall be exercised

by
is

the ward on
complete.
377. It
is

own

behalf

and thus the possession

no doubt curious to find ideas presented in this


order

somewhat inverted
acquiescing
in

to

find

the

representative

ac-

quiescing in the act of the principal, instead of the principal the


act
of

the representative.

And
some

diffi-

culties natui-ally arise out of this inversion in

cases.

Sec. 376-380.]

POSSESSION.
cut short

195
solving

But many have been


378.

by simply

them

in

favour of the disabled persons.

Reverting to

the

main subject

of

consideration, Con-

we

see that, in order to constitute possession in a legal sense necessaryfulfilled


:

through a representative, three conditions must be


first,

^gntaSve
possession.

the representative must have the physical control over

the thing; secondly, the representative must determine that


this physical control shall be exercised on behalf of his princi-

pal

thirdly, the principal must assent to its being so exercised.

379.

If either the representative has not


i

the

physical

control over the thing, or

the principal does not assent to

that physical control being exercised on his behalf, then the


possession
is

gone.

So

too, if the representative

changes his

determination to hold the thing for his principal, and deter-

mines to hold

it

for himself, or for another, then, properly


is

speaking, the possession

gone.

But

here again the law

sometimes steps in to prevent the consequences of fraud.


instance,
if

For

the thing were land, and

if

the representative

were simply to change his determination, from a determination


to hold the land on behalf of his principal to a determination to hold
it

on behalf of himself, I think that in every system of


principal

law the possession of the


terrupted

would be treated as unin-

at least, until the denial of the principaFs right,

or some unequivocal act inconsistent with that right, had

been brought to the knowledge of the principal.

Such a

ease

would be very

closely analogous to that


is

mentioned above;

namely, where a man's land


stranger in his absence,
possession
till

taken possession of by a
lose

in

which case he does not


^.

he becomes aware of the intrusion


is

380^- Derivative possession

the possession which one Derivative

person has of the property of another.


of a representative as
is

The physical

control

P^^^*''^"-

sometimes called his possession ; though,


is

we

have seen, the legal possession in this case

in the

principal.

But

derivative possession

is

true legal possession


it

the holder of the thing having the physical control over


1

Supra,

s.

365.

'

Sav. Poss.

s.

23, p. 282.

196

POSSESSION.
determination
to
exercise

[Chap. IX.

coupled with the

that physical

control on behalf of himself.


Distinc-

381. Hence, between the bare detention of a representative,

tween

which

is

not possession in a legal sense at

all,

and derivative

and representative
possession.

possession,

which

is

true legal possession, though detached

from ownership, there can be no confusion.


.
.

But

there are

many well-known legal relations, m which the transfer to one man of the physical control over the property of another
,
.

forms an essential feature

and

it is

frequently a question to

be determined, whether or no, subsequently to this transfer of


the physical control, the possession
is

in the

owner through

the transferee as his representative, or whether the transferee


holds
it

derivatively on behalf of himself.

The

relations in
;

reference to which the question arises are very numerous


it

but

most frequently occurs in reference to the relation of

principal
hirer, of

and agent,

of lender

and borrower, of

letter

and

pledgor and pledgee, or of bailor and bailee.

These

are relations which constantly arise out of the


transactions in daily
life.

commonest

Under the
law.

382. The

Roman

lawyers would seem to have proceeded

upon the principle

that,

where an owner transfers to another

the physical control over a thing without the ownership, the


transferee should hold the thing as a representative,

and that

the possession should remain in the owner in


it

all cases, unless

was necessary

for the

enjoyment of the other rights which

the transferee was to have, that he should have the right of


possession also.

383. Nevertheless there has been very considerable contention,

even under the

Roman
is

law, in reference to

some of the
is,

relations

enumerated above, as to where the possession


transferred.

after

the physical control

Savigny thinks that

under the

Roman law

in the ease of the agent, the borrower,


is

the hirer, and the bailee, the possession

never transferred

but that in the case of the pledgee


distinction

it is.
^-

And

he makes no

between land and moveables


'

Sav. Poss.

s.

23,

passim.

Sec. 381-387.]

POSSESSION.

197
of

384. The views of Savigny as to the mental element which Views

he considers necessary to possession are rejected in toto by


Ihering,

to possession

who maintains that the only mental element necessary is just so much as distinguishes it from mere

accidental physical contact

the intention to retain


(if

it.

Whouse the

ever has

the physical control coupled


this
all

may

expression) with

minimum

of intention has the legal


is

possession with

its

consequences, unless there

some
as he

express rule of law which declares the contrary.

385. It

is

quite possible that Ihering's theory

is,

endeavours to prove, more consonant to the


that of Savigny.
It

Roman

law than

would not be worth while to inquire


all)
is

into this, which (after

to us

a matter of secondary
is,

importance.

The question
lead

of primary importance to us
to

which theory would


Ihering's conception

the

best

practical

results ?

of possession

has

the advantage of

great simplicity, but the exceptional cases which the law

would have to deal with would be numerous, and the experiment of setting forth these exceptions has not yet been
tried.

386. The language of the English law upon the subject of English
possession
is

not

very

clear.

There are

certainly

some

possession.

English judges who think that intention


element in the acquisition of possession
'
:

may

be a necessary

but very likely they

had

not,

when they
it is

expressed that opinion, the arguments on


Still there

the other side present to their minds.

can be no

doubt that

true to say that by the animus of the person


it
is

who
seems
it

is

in

physical possession
is

frequently determined

whether or no that person


could be got rid of

in legal possession also.

Ihering

to think that this is undesirable, but I doubt


:

whether
of,

and, unless

it

can be got rid

the

.language of Savigny seems to

me

to be appropriate.

387. Before the English law can be reduced to clearness English

and consistency on any theory of

possession, it

would I think
itself.

possession

be necessary to remodel to some extent the law


'

Some

^^^^^^^

Wright and Pollock on Possession,

p. 208.

198
points

POSSESSION.
of English law appear to

[Chap. IX.

me

to

have

got

into

inextricable confusion.

This

is

particularly the case with the

law

of larceny.

The

gist of the offence of larceny is the

taking possession of a thing dishonestly ;

and

it

required a

good deal of ingenuity to establish that a


with taking
with intent to steal
if

man who

took a

thing innocently could by his subsequent conduct be chargeable


it
it.

One way

of doing this

has been to hold that

delivers a thing to

with the
it,

intention on both sides that

should take possession of

yet

if

both are mistaken as to the nature of the thing the

possession does not pass until

discovers the

mistake and

then determines to retain

it^

which determination they hold to


This
is

constitute a 'taking' dishonestly.

not the opinion


It follows

of

all, if

but

it is

of a great

many, English judges.

that

were to make
it

a present of a picture by mistake,

thinking

to

be a Rubens, and

thought so

too,

and

B
to

were to keep the picture for twenty years, and were then
give
it

away without

discovering the mistake, the picture would


all
:

never have been in ^'s possession at

or if

handed
it

to

a box which both supposed to contain


books,

plate,

and

contained

would never, unless he opened the

box, be in

possession of the books.

Where, one would


were not in

like to-

know,

would the possession be

if it

^ ?

387 a. So far

as the criminal
difficulty.

law

is

concerned

it

would be

easy to solve the

man who

receives as a gift

a sovereign knowing that he was only intended to receive

a shilling, or buys a chest of drawers with a bag of gold in

it

which he has good reason to believe the owner did not know
to be there, clearly ought to be punished for appropriating the

sovereign or the bag of gold, but not for larceny.


rational

The only

only
'

way of meeting these cases, and I venture to say the way in which they can ever be made intelligible to a jury,

This follows from the cases of Meriy v. &reen, Meeson and Welsby's 7, p. 623, and the judgment of seven judges in Eeg. v. Ashwell, law Eeports, Queen's Bench Division, vol. 16, p. 190. See some veryEeports, vol.
subtle reasoning
p. 102.

on

this subject in Pollock

and Wright on Possession,

Sec. 387a, 388.]


is

POSSESSION.

199
of goods, the
itself

by making the dishonest misappropriation


of

possession
offence.

which has been lawfully obtained,


is

an

This

the law which has been adopted in the


it

Indian Penal Code^j and

works admirably.

It restricts
is

at once the offence of theft or larceny to cases where there

a real outward and visible act of taking, such as no judge or


jury can misunderstand.

388. As regards the pledgee of goods probably most English As applied


lawyers would agree that

when

the goods are delivered to


in a recent work,

him

he

is

in

legal

possession.
first

And
is

where

I believe for the

time the question has been generally


that whoever, otherwise than

discussed, the view taken

as a servant, receives a thing

from another upon an underit

taking to keep and return

it

or to apply

in accordance with
is

the directions of that other,


possession of the thing
^.

is

bailee,

and as such
is

in legal

But

there

very high authority


in the case of

against this view.

Lord Justice Mellish


:

against Rogers

says distinctly

It seems to us that goods


'

Ancona

delivered to a bailee to keep for the bailor, such as a gentle-

man's plate delivered to

his

banker or his furniture warehoused

at the Pantechnicon, would in a popular sense as well as in

a legal sense be said to be


it

still

in his possession.'

No

doubt

was at one time

settled

law that a

bailee did not

commit

larceny

by a dishonest misappropriation of the goods, whereas a servant by the same act did commit that offence and no
:

doubt this distinction


has,

rests

on the assumption that the


not, the legal possession.
is,

bailee

and that the servant has

But

the inference from these decisions

as

it

seems to me, greatly

weakened by the

fact that this distinction has been swept


;

by an

act of parliament

and that a

bailee

misappropriates the goods delivered to


larceny*.
'

away who dishonestly him is made guilty of


cases in

Moreover there are certainly some


'

which

See sect. 403.

Pollock and Wright, Poss. pp. 131, 163.

Reported in Law Eeports, Exchequer Division, p. 292. * Larceny Act, 1861. On the other hand, it may be said that the Indian Penal Code makes a dishonest misappropriation by a bailee a separate offence, and not theft.
"

200

POSSESSION.

[Chap. IX.

a bailor can bring trespass for an injuiy done to his goods


in the hands of his bailee^ a position
to

which

it is

very

difficult
is

explain unless

it

be

also

held that

the bailor

in

possession \

Further^ a delivery

by the
it

seller to

a carrier

may

be a delivery to the buyer, which


this delivery puts the

could hardly be unless


^.

buyer in legal possession

388

a.

It is

no doubt quite possible to draw a distinction

between the case of moveables handed over to be held simply


at the will of the

owner and moveables handed over under


is

conditions

by which the owner

bound

and possibly the

true view of the English law in regard to moveables

may be

that the owner remains in possession after delivery in the

former case but not in the


As applied

latter.
it is

388

b.

In the case of land

even more

difficult

than in

the case of moveables to seize the position of the English law,


because in this case special inconveniences have been remedied

by

inconsistent methods.

When

land

is

let to

a tenant for

the ordinary purposes of occupation he can bring an action for

any disturbance

of his physical control over the land, not only

against strangers but against his

own

landlord.

He

also re-

covers the enjoyment of his physical control


precisely similar
in

by a judgment

form

to

that by which an owner in


is

possession recovers.
plaintiff or

And

the landlord

not nominally either

defendant in any action relating to the possession


is let

whilst the land

to a tenant.

So

far, then,

it'

would seem
some
it is

clear that the tenant is in

legal possession.

But when we
True

come
that

to look at the landlord's position


is

we

find that for

purposes he also

considered to be in possession.

we generally speak
seised,

of the landlord being not possessed


is

but

but this distinction

merely verbal,

it

being

impossible to give any definition of seisin which would exclude


possession,

and we have

to extricate ourselves
all

from

this diffi-

culty

it

being conceded on

hands that two persons cannot

be at the same time in possession of the same thing ^.


' '

Pollock and Wright on Possession, p. 145 and p. 71.


lb. p. 20.

Sec. 388a-390.]

POSSESSION,

201

389. The tendency of modem English lawyers is probably towards treating the tenant as in legal possession of the land^ but there is one difficulty in the way of doing this which
cannot be overlooked.

Whilst giving the tenant the legal

possession they do not shew

any signs of abandoning the

position that he has nevertheless no interest in the land.

Now

without saying that

it is

absolutely impossible

it

would be

at least very strange, that a

man

should be in the entire and

exclusive possession of land on his

own

behalf and should be

in the enjoyment of all the fruits of

it,

and yet not be the


This position
is

owner

of

any

interest

in

it

whatsoever.

scarcely intelligible.

390. There
ing the

are, as it

seems to me, three methods of solvis

difficulty.

One

to treat the person physically in

possession as tenant as a sort of bailiff for the owner, paying

the owner a fixed sum out of the profits and retaining the

remainder for his remuneration.


relation of landlord

There

is

no reason

why

the

and tenant should not be of

this character.

A similar
in

view has been taken of the position of the colonus


of the pachter in

Rome,

Germany, and,

I believe, of the

iailleur in

France

and

it

was certainly
is

at one time the

view

taken in England.
as the

Another method

to consider the tenant

owner and in

legal possession not of the land but of

some jus in

re over the land,

something in the nature of what

Roman

lawyers called a usufruct.

A third

method

is

to con-

sider the landlord as in possession or seised not of the land but

of the freehold

the
left

freehold being some right in or over the


itself.

land distinct
itself

from the land

The

possession of the land


^.

being thus

vacant for the tenant

* See Pollock and Wright on Possession, pp. 47, 49, where the third method seems to he adopted. But the adoption of any one of these methods would require an extensive revision of our legal phraseology.

It

may

also be objected that the landlord has


is

then only jus in re aliena,

because there

no suggestion that

know

of that the landlord's owner-

because

ship and possession are of different things. But this is not a real difficulty, all rights over land are according to the theory of English law

jura in re aliena, the alius being the sovereign.

202
Quasi poaincor-^
it,

POSSESSION.

[Chap. IX.

391.

The term

possession^ as

we have

hitherto explained

clearly assumes

some tangible existing thing, over which

poreal

^\^q

party in possession

may

exercise his physical control

but the

Roman

lawyers extended the idea of possession to ab-

stractions ; to things

which are not perceptible to the senses ;

to incorporeal things, as they are usually called

by lawyers.

392. Possession, in a legal sense, as distinguished from


the mere physical control or detention, does not rest upon

a notion exclusively applicable

to

things

corporeal.
is

The

notion upon which the legal idea of possession rests

that of

making the simple


But the simple
To what
applfcable.

exercise of this physical control a subject

for legal consideration

and

protection, apart

from ownership.
obvious, be so

exercise of

any right may,

it is

considered and protected.

393.

We

must not conclude from

this,

that

all

that

we

have said about possession


nation, to the exercise

may

be applied, without discrimi-

and enjoyment of any rights whatever.

Many
felt,

of the rules

which govern the question of possession

are founded on the existence of something which

may

be seen,

and handled, and

it

is

only by a metaphor that these

rules can be extended to

a right which

may

be enjoyed.

This
limits

is
;

an easy metaphor when confined within certain


as,

for example,

when we speak

of a person

who

enjoys the use of a pathway, or a watercourse running over


the land of another, as being in possession of the way, or of

the watercourse.

But

it

would be at the

least a bold

metaphor

to speak of a doctor in large practice as in possession (in

a legal sense) of his practice.


394. The

Roman

lawyers contented themselves with ex-

tending the legal idea of possession to those rights which

they denominated servitudes

a class of rights

similar to, but


call ease-

more extensive than, that


ments.

class of rights

which we

And

they constructed for the protection of the enjoy-

ment

of rights of this class rules closely analogous to those

for the protection of the physical control over things corporeal.

Modern lawyers have attempted

to give to the idea

Sec. 391-397.]

POSSESSION.

203

of possession a

much

wider extension j

and

this extension

with us
sion of

is

somewhat

indefinite.
is
:

Thus by

statute the posses-

an advowson
title

expressly protected as distinguished

from the

to

it

so also a person collecting tolls has


tolls

been treated as in legal possession of the right to take

and

it

has been even suggested that

we might

treat a person

collecting the interest of a debt as in possession of a debt.

395. Whether or no such an extension of the idea of


possession
is

useful, this

is

not the place to consider.

It is

certain that the extension^ if

made

at

all,

should be

with some circumspection.

Care must be taken in

made each new


is

application, not only that the nature of the subject

such

that the idea of possession


applied to
it,

is

capable of being analogically

but also that

it is

one to which the legal con-

sequences of possession are suitable. sequences to the exercise of


all rights,

To apply

those con-

without discrimination,

would produce the greatest confusion ^.


398. To whatever extent the idea of possession has been
carried, the discussion of it has

remained within the limits

assigned by the

Roman

lawyers, namely, the possession of


All, therefore, that

things corporeal, and of servitudes.

we
2.

can say further on this subject, must be in connexion with


the latter class of rights, which

we

shall hereafter consider

397. It

is

a fundamental principle, which

is

obscured by Only one


lost sight possession ^* ^ *""-

language in ordinary use, but


thing at the same time.

which must never be

of, that only one person can be in possession

of the

same

This principle

is

easily

deduced

from what has been above


possession.

stated as to the legal notion of


is

Possession, in a legal sense,

the determination

to exercise physical control over a thing on one's

own

behalf.

'

I gather from the observations of Covaok, Jahrbuch

d.

D. 6. B., vol. 2,

p. 62,

that the

German

Civil

Code attempts

to get rid altogether of the

notion that there can be possession of incorporeal things ; but, aa he points out, the attempt is not perhaps wholly successful, see Art. 1029.
2

See infra, chap.

x.

204

POSSESSION.
;

coupled with the capacity of doing so


necessity exclusive.

and

is,

thereforej of

398. This principle has, however, been obscured by the


double meaning of the term possession.
times means the physical control simply
for
;

Possession

some-

the proper word

which

is

detention.

the detention

And of course, one person may have and another may have the possession in the
Thus the money which
under his immediate
is

legal sense of the term.

in the

hands of

my

servant
is

is

control,

and in

popular language

in his possession;

but in a legal sense,

inasmuch as that control will be exercised on


exclusively, it is in
Possession o^^co-own-

my

behalf

my

possession,

and not

in his.

399.
jjjjgjigij

A more
la^

diflfiicult

case

is

that of co-ownership.

But the

j^a^g

expressed itself on this subject


in a very remarkable

which recognises

by a phrase manner the distinction


away, so far

between possession in the sense of simple detention, and possession in a legal sense
|

and by

so doing clears

as co-owners are concerned,

any

difficulty as to the proposition

which we are now considering.

The
if

rule of English

law

laid

down by
up
is in

Littleton

^,

and adopted by every succeeding lawyer


is,

to the present time,

that

there be

two co-owners each

possession of the whole


is,

and

of the half.

What
to,

this

must

mean

that whereas each owner has access

and control

over every part of the property, and so

may

be said to have

possession in the sense of detention of the whole, yet he exercises that control,

not on behalf of himself alone, but partly


his

on behalf of himself, in respect of

own

share,

and partly as

representative of his co-owner, in respect of his co-owner's


share.

In contemplation of law, therefore, he

is

only in posses-

sion of his

own

share.

However many co-owners there may


law be exactly in the same
each will be in possession of his

be, each will in contemplation of

position
share.

that

is

to say,

'

Sect. 288.

CHAPTER

X.

EASEMENTS AND PKOPITS-A-PRENDRE.


400. The rights which I propose to consider in
this chapter These
re.

are those comparatively few out of the innumerable jura jura in


in re

which

exist over

thing-

upon which English lawyers


profits-a-prendre.

have bestowed the names easements and


401. In most systems of law
classed

we

find certain jura in re

apart and specially treated.


re
is

Thus
apart

in the

Roman
called

Servi-

law certain jura in


'

are

classed

and are

servitudes.'

This

metaphorical

expression,

at

the

bottom of which seems

to lie the idea of a thing used

by and

placed under the control of a person


it.

who

is

not the owner of

Between the owner

of the thing

and the person who has


:

this right there is no direct legal relation

the control being

not over the person of the owner, but over the thing: res
servit, as

the expression was.

402. In English law we have not the term 'servitude'


but

we have

the idea.
'

We
'

call

the thing over which the

right exists the

servient

thing.

The

continental nations
'

of modern Europe have adopted the term

servitude

"

or
is

an equivalent one^, and the law relating to servitudes in those countries substantially the same as the Eoman law.

400. Neither easements alone, nor profits-a-prendre alone,


nor both taken together, correspond to the servitudes of the Roman law ; the classification of jura in re with us, so far as
it

has proceeded, being different.


^

But

nevertheless the English

In German,

'

Dienstbarkeit.'

206

EASEMENTS AND PEOFITS-A-PEENDRE.

[Cliap.

X.

law of easements and of profits-a-prendre has been, and


isj

still

largely influenced

by the Roman
if

law.

It will therefore,

I think, be found useful,

I give a brief general description

of the leading features of the


Positive
tive servi- or
^^'

404. Servitudes under the


negative.
in,

Roman law ^. Roman law were


is

either positive

positive servitude

a right to do

some-

thing on,

or in respect of,

a thing owned by another,

which the owner, as such, might have done, and which no


one
else,

except under special circumstances, might have done

(servitus

quae in patiendo

consistit.).

A
if

negative servitude

is

a right to prevent the owner of a thing from doing something,

which, as owner, he might have done

unrestrained (servitus

quae in non faciendo


Servitudes

consistit).

405. Both kinds of servitude correspond to a duty on


part of

spend to a the
fo'i-bear

the owner to forbear.

positive

servitude

corresponds to a duty on the part of the owner to forbear to


exercise
his

right

of preventing

an interference with his

property.

He must

endure that interference (patientia).

A
The

negative servitude corresponds to a duty on the part of the

owner to forbear to

exercise

some right of ownership.

right to compel a person to do an act in respect of a thing


does not fall within the conception of servitude; and
it

has

been doubted whether


as
it

it

was brought by Roman lawyers,

has been by modern lawyers, within the conception of


^.

a jus in re
Prasdial

406. Servitudes were divided by the


'

Roman

lawyers into

personal
tudes.

prsedial

and

'

personal.'

The conception
There
is

of a personal ser-

vitude

is

simple enough.

a person to

whom
which
is

the
it is

jus in re aliena belongs,


exercised.

and a
of a

res aliena over

The conception

prsedial servitude

more
stated,

'

The

authorities will mostly be found, briefly

and conveniently

in Salkowski's
2

Eoman

Private Law, p. 444.


d.

See also Sohm, Inst. E. L.,

Ledlie's translation, p. 358.

Vangerow, Lehrb.

Pandekten,
call a
s.

338, Aniu. 2,

i.

Koman law was


later

that servitus in faciendo

non

consistit.
' :

The phrase of As will appear

we have

a thing,

which we
See

'

service

it is

a jus in re aliena,

and

it

consists in faciendo.

430.

Sec. 404-408.]

EASEMENTS AND PROPITS-A-PRENDRE.

207
is

complicated.

Besides the res aliena over which the right

exercised^ there is another res to

which the right


is

is

attached.

The owner

of
:

this

second res

the person

who
though

enjoys

the servitude

and the enjoyment

of the servitude always


res,
it is,

accompanies the ownership of the second


of course, not

merged

in

it.

The meaning
is

of a right being

attached to a thing, which


with,
is,

an expression we often meet

I take

it,

that the enjoyment or exercise of the

right follows the ownership of the thing to which the right


is

attached.

In a

praedial
is
is

servitude

each

res,

that over
it

which the servitude


attached as a right,
or a house.

exercised,

and that to which


is,

is

a prsedium, that

a piece of land

407. It

is

not inconceivable that a servitude should exist


is

Servitudes

the burden of which

attached to one res and the benefit ed to move^'^^-

to another without the additional circumstance that each res


is

either land or a house.

But, as far as I

am

aware, no such

servitude

was known

to the

Roman

law.

408. Probably the origin of

prsedial servitudes is to

be

Origin of

found in the gradual introduction of the


exclusive ownership.

stricter notions of

Without some modifications

of

these

notions neighbours could not have lived comfortably together.

Hence

in praedial servitudes are

it

is

always assumed that the

two

prsedia

not far apart.

Hence

also it

was a

rule

that the right of a landowner over the land of his neighbour

must not only be advantageous to him qua landowner, or, as it


tageous to his
land.

to him, but advantageous


is
it

sometimes put, advanfollowed


that,
if

So

again

the

landowner who

had the right sold the land for the benefit


each successive owner
if

of which the right existed, he could not himself retain the


right.

It

passed with the land to

of the land.

Exactly in the same way,

the land over

which the right was exercised were

sold, the

laud remained

burdened with the servitude, following out the idea that the
servitude

was attached

to both lands, to one as a benefit,

and

to the other as a burden.

208

BASEMENTS AND PROFITS-A-PEENDKB.

[Chap X.

409. The land or house to which the servitude was attached as a benefit was called the locus superior
;

that to
locus

which
Perpetua causa of
prsedial servitudes.

it

was attached as a burden was called


a rule that prsedial
servitudes

the

inferior.

410. It was

must have
there

what was

called a perpetua causa,

and

this rule appears to

have been applied with considerable

strictness.

Thus,

if

was a hole

in the wall of a house to let off water used in


floor,

washing the

through which the water escaped on to

the neighbouring land, there could not be a prsedial servi-

tude to receive the water carried through such a hole.


there

But
is

might be a

preedial

servitude to carry off the rain

water through a hole of this description.


thus given
:

Neque
'

This reason

enim perpetuam eausam habet quod


caelo
;

manu

fit;

at

quod ex
fit

cadit, et

si

non assidue

fit

ex
^.'

natural!

tamen causa

et ideo perpetuo fieri existimatur

So the right to take water from a lake or a pond could not be


prsedial servitude
^.

But

these rights

might

exist as personal

servitudes.
Vicinity of praedia to

411. It

was not necessary that the dominant prsedium and

which

ser-

the servient prsedium should actually touch.

But

it

follows

vitudes are attached.

from what has been said that the two prsedia must have
been near, as otherwise the servitude would be useless to the

dominant praedium.
Praedial

412.

prsedial servitude could exist

only so far as

it

was
at-

servitude

must be
useful.

actually useful in respect of the land to which it

was

tached.

Thus a man might have a

praedial servitude to dig

clay in his neighbour's land in order to

make
;

vessels to hold

the wine which he

made on

his

own

land

but he could not

have a prsedial servitude to dig clay in order to make vessels


for sale
^-

Must be
carefully exercised.

413.
little

A A
'

prajdial servitude

must always be

exercised with as

injury as possible to the servient prsedium.


prtedial servitude could only be exercised

Could not
be transferred.

414.

by the

owner of the nominant land, or by


Dig.
viii. 2. 28.

his servants

and family on

lb.

Dig.

vii. 3. 6.

Sec. 409-418.3

EASEMENTS AND PROFITS-A-PRBNDRB.


the mere temporary right to enjoy
it

209
could

his behalf,

^ven

not be conferred upon another.


415. Prsedial servitudes were classed into urban and rural. Urban and

according as the servient praedium consisted of buildings or^^^^l^^'


land.

All buildings were called praedia urbana, whether they


^.

were situate in town or country


416.

Any

jus in re attached to land or buildings both as Restricted

a burden and as a benefit was, as I understand the law, called predial a prsedial servitude, and subject to the restrictions I have
l^J^^

stated.

It

can be easily understood that, owing to these

restrictions, prsedial servitudes

were not very numerous or

common.
class

The most common

prsedial servitudes of the rural

were rights of way, rights to take water, rights to


cattle.

convey water, and rights to water


the right of pasturing
cattle,

We

also

meet with

the right to dig and burn lime,

the right to dig sand, and the right to cut wood.

But always

with the limitation that the servitude must be of such a


nature as to contribute continuously to the enjoyment of

a neighbouring tenement.
417. Personal
restrictions.

servitudes

were not subject to the same

Personal

Any

use that could be

made

of a thing either tudes.


its

moveable or immoveable, or any right to take


could be

produce,

made

into a personal servitude.

But

there

was

this
last

important restriction, that no personal servitude could


longer than the
life

of the person in

whose favour

it

was

created, or, in the case of a juristical person, longer than one

hundred

years.

418. I will

now endeavour

to describe

and

to distinguish Easements
profits-a-

easements and profits-a-prendre.


aliena,

These are both jura in re

and

in both the servient res

must be

land, or a building P^j^^^^


all to land,

attached to land, or water standing or flowing on land,

which English lawyers call by the name of re aliena may exist where the servient res
'

land.
is

jus in

not land, but

Just. Inst. II, 3.

I.

very important.
best

It

This classification is not very clear, but it is not seems only to have been applied to the oldest and

known

servitudes.

; :

210

EASEMENTS AND PEOPITS-A-PRENDEE.

[Chap.X.

such a right would not be either an easement or a profit-aprendre.


Difference

419.

An

easement

is

a right to do something on,

in^ or

in

easements respect of the servient land, or to prevent the


fi^s-a^"^"'

owner of the

^^T^^

from doing something


is

on, in, or in respect of his

own land,

prendre.

profit-a-prendre

a right to take something from the


is

servient land.

This

a cardinal distinction.

There cannot

be an easement to take something from the servient land.

Wliy these
are separately
classed.

420. The only object, as far as I


one
set of jura in re, classing

am

aware, of taking

them

apart,

and

calling
re, =
is

them

easements, and takiner another set of jura in j j a

classing o
in order

them

apart,

and calling them

profits-a-prendre,

to regulate their acquisition.

Easements might be described


set of

as jura in re

which can be acquired by one


as

methods;

profits-a-prendre

jura in re which can be acquired

by

another set of methods.

Then

there are other jura in re

which are neither easements nor profits-a-prendre, and which


can only be acquired by a third set of methods
jura in re cannot be acquired at
is all.
;

whilst some
therefore
it

When

said that there cannot be


all

an easement to dig clay in your


is

neighbour's land,
right in the
there
still
is,

we mean

that you cannot acquire that


are

ways in which easements

acquired;

but

may

be a profit-a-prendre of that description

that
Easements
tenant
aross'^

the right

may

be acquired in an appropriate manner.


kinds of easements

421. There are two

known

to

the

English law.

The

first

and commonest kind are those in

which both the benefit and the burden are attached to land
such, for example, as the right of the owners of Blackacre to
cross the neighbouring field Whiteacre
;

or the right of the

owners of a house on one side of a


of land on the opposite side
their windows.
prsedial

street to prevent the ovsraers

from building

so

high as to darken

These are what

Roman

lawyers would call

servitudes.

We

call

them easements appurtenant.


where the

The second and


benefit
is

rarer kind of easements are those

enjoyed by the inhabitants of a particular district or


;

persons carrying on a particular trade

such, for example, as

860.419-424-]

EASEMENTS AND PEOFITS-A-PBJENDRE.

211

the right of the inhabitants of a village to dance in a particular close


;

or for licensed victuallers to erect booths on the

waste of a manor during a fair. These are called easements by custom, because it is only by custom that they can be
claimed ^. 422.

right to take potwater, that


is

is,

to take water for Eight to

domestic use from a running stream,

an easement and
it

may -s^at^er."

'

be claimed by custom.
profit-a-prendre, but it
is

It

might be thought that


air, is in
is

was a
here

not so considered ; the reason assigned motion;


it is

being that flowing water, like

now

and now

there,

and
This

for this reason

not considered as in the


it

ownership of the person on whose land for the moment

happens to be.
a-prendre ^.

is

supposed to distinguish

it

from a profit-

423.
'

What
'

the

Roman
'

lawyers expressed by the word

prsedial

as opposed to
'

personal,^ English lawyers express


:

by the word appurtenant ' and what the Roman lawyers expressed by the word personal,' English lawyers express by
'

the words

'

in gross.^

There can be no easement in gross in


In other words, an
either as

the English law except

by custom. easement must be claimed by a man


or as carrying on a particular trade.

owner of a

certain piece of land, or as inhabitant of a particular locality,

424. It

is

not unfrequently said that an easement must be Easement

without

profit.

This cannot

mean

that the easement must

profit.

be valueless, for that would be nonsense.


unless
^

On

the contrary,

the

easement were

advantageous to the dominant


'

Writers on the law of easements seem a little doubtful whether they ought not to call this second class of easements by the name of customs,' and exclude them from easements altogether. As the only object of the classification of jura in re is to determine the mode of acquisition, and as these easements can only be acquired by custom, it would, perhaps, be better to exclude them.
2

Race

V.

Ward,
is

Ellis

and Blackburn's Reports,


the thing taken
is

rol. iv. p. 70:2.


:

But
not

the water taken


sure that in
property.

in the possession of the landowner

and' I

am

all profits-a-prendre

the servient owner's

Thus a right to take fish in a running stream is certainly not an easement, and it seems to be considered as a profit-a-prendre. Peers V. liucy, Modern Reports, vol. iv. p. 363 ; see Goddard on Easements, p. ^.

2,

212

EASEMENTS AND PROFITS-A-PRENBRE.


it

[Ghap. X.

tenement

could not be maintained.

It

means that the

easement must not include the taking of anything away, for


then
it

would be profit-a-prendre and not an easement.

The

requirement that the easement must render the enjoyment


of

the

dominant

tenement

more

advantageous

certainly

exists.

Perpetua
ea"emeats.

425. There

is

no direct authority that an easement must


it

^^^^ a perpetua causa^ though

seems to be suggested that

some such
Eight of support.

restriction exists

^.

426. The right to support, as


right of one neighbour to
his soil so as to let

it

is

called,

that

is,

the

prevent another digging away


the
soil

one that

down has been much


built on,

of the adjoining land,

is

discussed lately.

It can hardly

be doubted that such a right

may

exist

both in respect of land

which has been


whether or no

and in respect of land which has


question, therefore,
itself

not been built on.


it

The hotly contested

should be called an easement, resolves

into a question as to

how

such a right can be acquired

it

being

supposed that there are certain modes of acquisition which are


applicable to
'

it if it is

an easement, but not otherwise


work on Easements

^-

The more recent

editions of Gale's

(p. 14)

seem

to suggest this.

Bracton,

whom

such a point, as he puts down never adopted. The case of Arkwright v. Gell, Meeson and Welsby's Eeports, vol. v. p. 203, has no connexion with the Roman law doctrine of perpetua causa, though, in so far as it lays down that an easement cannot
be acquired in a temporary watercourse,
2

Gale quotes, would be no authority upon a good deal of Roman Law which was

it

leads to an analogous result.

See the case of Angus

v.

Dalton,
ia

Law

Reports, Appeal Cases, vol. vi.

p. 740.

The word 'easement'


is

right of support
is

not specifically mentioned.


is

used in the Prescription Act, but the The question whether it


of importance, because the evidence

a positive or negative easement


is

that the enjoyment

'as of right' Is very different for positive


It is difficult to say exactly

negative easements.

Infra, chap. xiii.

and what

the judges in the above case severally understood by 'positive,' or, as they prefer to call it, affirmative,' and ' negative ' easements. But according to the definition I have given above (sect. 404) I should say that both the Lords Justices, Lindley and Bowen, consider the right of
'

support to be negative, though they think that where the land has been built upon so as to increase the burden that might have been treated as an actionable wrong, and if so the right of support would have become
positive in that case.

See pp. 763, 784, 793, of the Report.

Sec. 425-430.]

EASEMENTS AND PEOEITS-A-PRENDRE.


right attached to land as

213
restric-

427.

Any

a burden and also No


is

as a benefit,

which

is

recognised by law, and which

not

a profit-a-prendre, would, I think, be called an easement.

jjjnds of ^^''^"*^-

There cannot be
is

many

such rights, but the

list

of

them

not perhaps yet complete.

The

last

one recognised was

the right of the owner of an inn to place a signboard on

a neighbouring house
428.
appurtenant or in

^-

Profits-a-prendre

may
:

(as
if

I have said) the

be either

Eestrio-

gross

but

profit-a-prendre

be pr^t^aPrendre,

appurtenant

it

can only exist so far as

it is

advantageous to

the enjoyment of the dominant tenement to

which

it

is

appurtenant

^.

429. There does not seem to be any express authority


as to

how

far

it is

possible to create rights in the nature of

a profit-a-prendre under English law.


rights of this nature
is

The

multiplication of

looked upon as undesirable, but their


^.

creation does not seem to have been expressly restricted

430. Both in an easement and in a profit-a-prendre the

owner of the
forbear, that

servient tenement has simply to forbear

to

is,

from exercising from

his ordinary right as

owner
it

of excluding others

his land,

and disposing

of

in

accordance with his wishes.

But because

neither an ease-

ment

in the English law, nor a servitude in the

Roman

law,

can consist in compelling the owner of the servient tenement


to do something,
it

must not be supposed that a

jus in re

of this nature cannot exist.


is

What

is

called a fee

farm rent

a jus in re aliena to compel the owner of the res to pay

a certain sum of money at fixed intervals to the person to

whom
lawyers
'

the fee farm rent belongs.


call

This

is

what English

a 'service.^

vol. xii. p. 261.

See the case of Moody v. Steggles, Law Reports, Chancei-y Division, See some curious rights enumerated in Goddard on
v.

Easements, p. 74. 2 See the case of Bailey


vol. xii. p. gr.
^

Stephens,

Common

Bench, Nevr Series,


v.

Stephens, at

See the observations of Mr. Justice Willes in the case of Bailey p. iii of the Common Bench Reports, Nevi^ Series, vol. xii.

CHAPTER XL
SECURITY.
Insecurity
of obligations.

431.

One

of

the most ordinary results

of the various
is

transactions into which people are daily entering


fall

that they

under legal obHgations of various kinds.


is

Por many

reasons the performance of these obligations


insecure
careless;
;

more

or less
is

sometimes the debtor sometimes he


is

is

obstinate

sometimes he

positively unable to

do what he

ought.
Debtor

432.

I have spoken here of the debtor.

That word

is

and creditor.

generally used

by English lawyers
;

to signify a person
it
is

who

owes money to another

I shall use

to signify

any person

who owes a
presented in
express

service to another

which

capable of being re-

money ^ ; and I
to

shall use the


is

word
due.

creditor to

any person

whom

such a service

Meaning of term
'

433.

I shall also use the word security to express any

security.'

transaction between the debtor

and

creditor

by which the

performance of such a service


of choosing

is

secured.

Unless this liberty

my own

expressions were conceded to me, I could

not attain even a reasonable degree of conciseness and precision in the discussion of this subject.

English law of
security
is

434. It has been often said that the English law of security
derived from the

Eoman; and
difficulty

it

is

certainly true that

derived

from

whenever questions of
law for

have arisen upon this subject,

Roman.

English lawyers have almost invariably looked to the


assistance.

Roman

Study
of

Eoman

435. I do not think that the terms and the rules of

Roman

law in
England.

law have always been fully understood by English lawyers


1 Security may be given for any demand, but a real security will only produce money or a money value. (See infra, sect. 447.)

SECURITY.

215
the

when applying them.


little

At one time
it is

Roman law was

very

studied in England, but

not so now.

Many

of the

best works of continental jurists have been translated, and at


least

an elementary knowledge of Roman law


is

is

now considered
Advana''compre-

to be a necessary part of a complete legal education.

436. It

perfectly clear that if


all,

Roman law
tion.

for assistance at

we are to rely upon the we must try to comprehend

its principles

according to their latest and fullest interpreta- ^^"^7"%


of the Re-

I have, therefore, endeavoured to give a short general

statement of the
it

Roman law

of security;

and I hope that

will

serve to

give the student a general grasp of the


this portion of the

principles

upon which

law must always be


be in particular

administered, whatever diversity there


rules.

may

I also think that

it is

well worthy of study, not only as

illustrating

and explaining our own law, but as a striking


scientific

combination of plain good sense with


expression.

accuracy of

know nothing
more
acute.

in jurisprudence

more sound,

more

forcible, or

437.

From

the earliest times the

Roman

creditor never Earliest


security,

seems to have thought of relying

solely

on the good faith or

ability of his debtor for the satisfaction of his

demand.

By
it

the nexum, the oldest form of contract, the debtor was handed

over bodily to the creditor, becoming, in fact, his slave; and

was no easy matter

for the debtor to escape

from

his obligation.

Upon

entering into the

nexum he had
and

to procure five fellow-

citizens as witnesses to,

assistants in the formalities of

the transaction.
ligation.

This gave strength and precision to the obof these witnesses was in later

But the presence

times further utilised in a

way which

ultimately led to a

great advance in the law.

By

means of the other ancient was easy


to secure the eonto that of

form of

contract, the sponsio, it

current engagement of these five persons, in addition

the principal debtor, that the obligation should be performed


so that, in case of the failure of the latter, the creditor

might

have recourse to them.

216
Entirely
personal.

SECURITY.

[Chap. XI.

438. It will be observed that the creditor was thus to

some extent
but
idea

secured

not only against

the
Still

unwillingness
the prevailing
will of

against the inability of his debtor.

was that

of pressure brought to bear

upon the

the contracting party; of some inconvenience to be suffered


if

the engagement were not fulfilled;

and

this

was quite

consonant to the spirit of the old not long


Creditors

Eoman

law.

But

it

did

suffice for all

the wants of a busy practical people.


creditors

What was wanted by


of the will of the debtor.

was a tangible means

of

want

real security.

obtaining satisfaction for their claims wholly independent

This was actually obtained, though

only after a very long struggle.

The
is

creditor at length got

what
fulfil

is

called real security ;

that

to say, he got, not only

the promise of the debtor and a means of compelling him to


that promise, but he also got a right over a specific

thing which ensured to him the perfoimance of the promise,


quite independently of the wishes or ability of the debtor;
so that at last not only the will of the debtor,

but even the

debtor himself was so


it

little

regarded that, in the latest period,

almost seemed as

if

the thing which was

made

security

was treated
obligation.

as the debtor,

and not the

original party to the

The
is

progress of the
of

Roman law from


its

a simple
ultimate

pressure upon

the will

the debtor to this

development
Fiducia.

in the highest degree interesting.

439. The

first

advance upon the nexum and sponsio was


This was a formal proceeding,
it

the transaction called fiducia.


suitable to

any case in which

was

desired to transfer to

another a specific thing under conditions.

It therefore

was

not confined to the taking of security, but was also used in


cases

of

deposit

or

loan.

Ultimately, however,

it

came

specially to signify the taking of security.

A complete transfer of tlie

440. In the transaction of fiducia the various conditions

upon which the thing was


the contract under which
case in which security
it

to be

returned were defined


transferred.

by

property.

was

If

it

was a

was

to be given, the creditor got the


full

debtor to

make

over to

him the

ownership of the thing,

Sec. 438-442-]

SECURITY.
it

217

binding himself to return


fulfilled.

as soon as the obligation

was

This was an easy and effectual

way

of obtaining

security,

and

it

remained in use even after the introduction

of the other modes which will be hereafter described j indeed,


it

was well known

to the western world, at least in Italy,

up

to the time of the Christian Emperors.

It was, in fact,

a proceeding similar to an English mortgage, but without a power of


441.
sale or foreclosure.

There were, however, many things which were

in This not

every
of

way

suitable to be used as security for the performance eonve-^


well- "i^nt.

an obligation, but to which, on account of certain


diflSculties,
'.

known

the proceeding by

way

of

fiducia

was

inapplicable

I need not enter at length into the nature


;

of these difficulties

they were no doubt technical, but were

too deeply rooted to be swept

away

for a

special purpose

without destroying the symmetry (elegantia) of the law,

and thus causing confusion. which was to get

The Roman

lawyers, therefore,

introduced another proceeding called pignus, the effect of Pignus.


rid of the transfer of

ownership altogether,

and

to substitute for it a transfer to the creditor of the bare

possession, of course under the

same condition

as to its return,

when

the debt was satisfied.


Defects

442. In both these processes, however, there were inherent


defects.

In the case of fiducia the debtor was dependent on fiducia P'^" the good faith of the creditor for the restoration of his pro- ^
perty, for if the creditor

had parted with


;

it,

the debtor had

only a personal remedy against him

on the other hand, the

creditor could not consistently with his contract obtain

any

material satisfaction out of the thing transferred to him,

which was, perhaps, not even in


ease of pignus, the creditor

his possession.

So, in the

was exposed

to the risk of the

property being sold by the debtor to a third person in fraud


of his security; in

which

case, if the

thing pledged were

'

to bring back the property,


first

Either a mancipatio or an in jure cessio seems to have been necessary and I should suppose also to convey it, in the
instance, to the creditor.

See Smith's Diet. Antiijq.,

s.

v. Fiducia.

218
landj the creditor

SECUKITY.
was wholly unprotected against

[Chap. XI.
this third

person's
until it

claim

^.

Indeed this defect was so serious

that,

was removed, land was very rarely given in pignus.


too, like fiducia,
'

The pignus
arising

produced no material satisfaction

of the claim, but only a pressure upon the will of the debtor,

from the inconvenience of being kept out of So


far,

his

property.

therefore,
it

the law was stUl under


will of the debtor

the

dominion of the idea that

was the

which

was
Security

to be acted upon.

443. The most important improvements in the

Roman
of

by land-

law of security were not introduced

until,

by the extension

from their ^^
cultivaLatiftin^^^-

Roman

dominion beyond the confines of Italy, very large

estates first

became common.

From

this

time large numbers


to be

o^ slaves

and even of

free persons^

began

employed in

cultivating these properties.

Small estates also were somenecessity that the land-

times let out to farm.


lord should have

Hence the

some security

for his rent

became apparent
is

at

Rome,

as in all

places where the land of one person

cultivated

by another.
it

They
obtain
old
it

444. Under the old law


to

was not easy

for the landlord

obtain this security from the cultivator.

Generally the

law

only property which the cultivator had was his farming stock
(invecia et illata)
;

and

it

was obvious that

this could neither

be assigned to the landlord by a fiducia, nor given into his


custody by a pignus.
It

was therefore necessary

to devise

some other means of effecting security; and the mode adopted


It was thia inapplicability of pignus in its original form to land, combined with the false etymology of the term (a puguo), which led to the saying that pignus properly (proprie) could only be given of move^

able property.

This has misled

Story

(Bailments, sect. a86),

who

and seems to think that the distinction between pignus and hypotheca was a fundamental one, though occasionally lost sight of the truth being that it was one of little importance and very rarely noticed. In later times a pignus in which the possession was not transferred, and a pignus of land, were everyday transactions. ^ Sir Henry Maine is of opinion that there were no free cultivators (Ancient Law, first ed., p. 299). But see Plin. Ep. iii. 19 and for an account of the colonus see Kuntze, Excursus, p. 299, and Sohm's Institranslates proprie 'generally,'
:

tutes of

Boman Law

(Ledlie's translation), p. 115.

iSec.

443-446.]

SECURITY.

219

was, to allow the tenant by a simple agreement, without any


formalities, to pledge his

farming stock to
validity of such

his landlord as

a
Origin of
theca.

security for the rent.


first

The

an agreement was

recognised by a praetor of the

name

of Salvius,

who

thus

led

the

way

to

the

most important changes in the law


of the tenant could be followed,
off

of security.
if it

The property

had been removed by him

the farm in fraud of his


first,

agreement with his landlord.


removal.
tenant,

At

however, this could

only be done within very short periods of time after the


If the property were
still it

in the hands of the

the landlord
If
it

could

have

brought

back within

the year.

had passed

into the hands of a third person,


if

then

it

could not be pursued,

the latter had held


it

it

either

for a year, or, at least, for as long a time as

had been upon

the land of the tenant.


ever,

This

strict rule of limitation,

how-

was considered

to

make

the security too perilous; and

another praetor,

named

Servius,

removed

this limitation, and.

gave to the Hndlord the ordinary time to sue


the thing alienated.

for

and recover

445. These provisions did not long remain confined to the


claims of landowners.

The Servian

action,

by which the

thing pledged could be followed into the hands of any person


to

whom

it

came, was extended to

all

kinds of property,

and

to security for all kinds of claims.

Thus an

entirely

new kind
means

of right

was

created, a jus in re alien^ available


:

against the world at large

and

this right could

be acquired by

of a simple agreement without

any

special formality.

446. This form of security was called by the Greek name of Greek
hypotheca, and
it

was probably

of

Greek

origin, being copied

"S'ii-

by the Romans from the Greeks of southern Italy, where they had become familiar with it. It was only a development of the original pignus, although it was at the same time
a very considerable advance upon
it
;

and the

Roman law

did

not henceforth keep up any distinction between pignus and hypotheca. Whether the possession was actually transferred
or not, the agreement

Identified

by one man that

his property should

be quently

220
with
pig-

SECURITY.

[Chap. XI.

a security to another was in later times called indifferently

hypotheca or pignus.
Did not
five a real security,

447. Still ^^e

we have not reached the point aimed at. Though creditor had what has been called a real right, but
jg

-yjrhie]!

better called a jus in

re-',

he had no real security.

He

could assert that the thing pledged to


it

subject to the pledge wherever

happened to

him remained be, but he had


the

no means in his own hands of satisfying


debtor neglected to do what he

his claim if

ought.

This had yet to


so

be provided

for,

and the mode of doing


of

was suggested
in the case

by an ancient
Power
of

rule

the

Roman
own
debt.

law, that

of lands pledged to the state [praedia), the state could sell

the property and satisfy

its

It became customary
;

for private creditors to stipulate for a similar right

and

this

right

of

sale,

coupled with

the

rights

conferred

by the

pignus, or hypotheca, gave to the creditor the means of satis-

fying his claim, and rendered him entirely independent of


the debtor.
It

was necessary at

first

for the creditor to

obtain the right of sale by a special concession, but in later

times

it

was always presumed


further.

to

exist.

Indeed, the law

went even a step


creditor not to sell

positive

agreement by the
rendering three

had only the

effect of

several notices to the debtor necessary, instead of the single

one which would otherwise


Extended

suffice.

448. These were the steps by which the law was developed
in the case of pignus

and hypotheca.

In the case of fiducia


it

the result was the same, though the method of arriving at

was
the

different

there the ownership

was already transferred

to the creditor; and the most obvious course in the case of


debtor's
failure

was by express agreement


absolute.

to

make
at

the creditor's ownership


' '

Indeed,

this

could

' The term real right to English ears genei-ally means a right to in or over land, as opposed to a right to in or over chattels which is called a personal right.' That is the reason why the expression is objectionable.
'

chattels are given as a security there is no suitable expression for the right of the pledgee over the goods pledged, and we are compelled to adopt the expression jus in re.

Where

Sec. 447-451.]

SECURITY. But

221

one time be done.


to
sell

as soon as the right of the creditor

and

satisfy the debt

was

fully established in the case of

pignus, the same right was attributed to the creditor in the


case

of fiducia;

and thenceforth the clause of forfeiture^

or foreclosure fell into disuse, a sale in every respect

by the

creditor

being

more in accordance with the

spirit of

the law

as administered under the Christian Emperors than a foreclosure.

449.

Henceforth the right to

sell

and

satisfy the debt Importof

{distractio)

came

to

be considered as the very essence of power

the law of security.

The

person in whose favour the security


;

was given always had

this right

and

therefore, as a pledge

might

in all cases result in a sale, nothing could be pledged


sold.

which could not be which we should

Subject to

this,

however, everything

call

property might be given as a security

any

beneficial right to the use or

enjoyment of land, and even


;

easements might be so dealt with


to be whether
it

the only test appearing the creditor to extract

was

possible

for

from the thing pledged

satisfaction of his

demand.

Debts

due to the debtor could be given as a security ;

the creditor

being able to obtain satisfaction by causing payment to be

made

to himself, or

by

selling the debt to a third person. Pledgee

450.

So too a creditor could give the thing pledged as


If therefore the original debt

a security for a debt of his own; but subject, of course,


rights of the original debtor.

to the pledge
^'''

was paid

off,

the second pledgee lost his security.

451. I pass over the rules which relate to the constitution


of several pledges for one demand, and successive pledges of

the same thing for several demands, and I proceed


state

now

to

more

particularly the nature of a security under the

Roman
it

law, and the position of the debtor and creditor after

has been given.

' This clause in the agreement was called lex commissioria. It was declared by Constantine to be illegal ; Smith's Diet. Antiqq. s. v. Pigrms. But the creditor might still agree to purchase at a fair price. See Wind-

scheid,

LehrbuCh des Pandekten-Rechts,

sect. 238.

222
Obliga-

SECURITY. The
particular nature
of

[Chap. XI.

452.

the obligation of which

any kind ^^^ performance was to be secured was immaterial, and a may be ariven for the whole of a debt or for a part. security might be o o
secured.
.; j.

It

was

also of

no consequence whether the debtor himself


else

gave the security^ or some one

for him.

pledge

might even be given

for a claim

which could not be enforced

by laWj such as a mere debt of honour^ or a moral duty.

A
Owner-

security also, like an obligatioDj could be conditional or

future.

453. Giving a thing in pledge did not prevent the owner


it

altered by from dealing with

as he thought proper, provided that he

pledge.

^j^

j^Q^ interfere

with, or lessen, the security of his creditor.

Any

dealings which would have that efEect were

nuU and

void

as against the purchaser from the creditor, should the latter


exercise his right of sale.

But

in the case of

moveable proit

perty the pledgor was not allowed to alienate


consent of the pledgee
;

without the

the alienation was not absolutely void,


personally liable as for a misappro-

but

the pledgor was

priation,

and of

course such

a sale did not displace the

creditor's security.

Use and
profits be

454. The use and profits of a thing given as security


belonged entirely to the pledgor, unless
t t

,.

long to

tit

i-

it

were expressly

e gor.

agreed to the contrary.

If the pledgee were in possession,


profit as

then he was bound to make as good a


of everything

he could out
profit,

from which

his debtor

had made a

being

responsible for not doing so.

It

was only where there was


all

a loan of money, and no agreement at

about interest, that

the creditor in possession of a security could take the profits


himself,

and then he could do


;

so only to the extent of

a
if

moderate rate of interest


interest

of course he could not take

them

had been expressly excluded.

Sometimes the parties

expressly agreed that the whole profits should be taken in lieu


of interest, and this
Tacking.

was allowed.
recognised to some extent the princall
'

455. The
ciple of

Roman law
for

what English lawyers

tacking.'

If the creditor

had any other claims

money

in writing against the debtor.

Sec. 452-456.]
lie

SECURITY.

223

could retain possession of the security, notwithstanding


it

that the debt for which


satisfied,

had been originally given was


But, as far as I
first

whether these other claims were created before or

after the security

was given.

am

aware, the

unjust rule of English law, that the

creditor has a priority

over a subsequent pledgee even in respect of unsecured debts,

was never adopted ^


456.

Of

course the right to sell the thing pledged and Power of

satisfy the debt

was the most important of

all

the rights of

exercised,

a secured creditor.

This right could not be exercised until

the debt was actually due and notice had been given to pay
it.

The sale was conducted by the creditor, who was looked upon as an agent of the debtor. Not that agency is, strictly
speaking, the legal ground of the transaction
;

the creditor,

when

selling, acted in his

own

right

but the creditor was so

far an agent that he had specific duties to perform in order to


protect the interests of the debtor

when
his

the security was

brought to
the
sale,

sale.

Por instance,

it

was

duty to advertise

and to give notice

to the debtor

when and where

it

would take

place, so that the latter

might know exactly what


if

was being done, and might


was quite was
distinct

interfere

necessary.

This notice
prior to the

from the notice

to

pay the debt

exercise of the right of sale.


sale
left to

And though

the conduct of the


all

the creditor, he was bound in

things to
If

consult the interests of the debtor as far as possible.

no

suitable purchaser could be found, then the creditor could

ask that the thing given as security might be adjudged to belong to himself; but in such a case
it

could
year.

still

be re-

deemed by the debtor


absolutely for himself
stipulation
that,
if

at

any time within a

The only

other case in which the creditor could obtain the ownership

was where there had been an express


creditor

the debt were not paid, the

should become the absolute owner (whilst such an arrange' The whole doctrine of tacking seems very questionable. There has heen an attempt in England to get rid of it, but it has failed. See Coote on Mortgages, 4th ed., p. 827.

224

SECURITY.
or

[Chap.

XL

ment was allowed ^),


price.
Creditor could claim for
deficiency.

by aa agreement

to purchase at a fair

457. It was the duty of the creditor to get in the

money

from the purchaser, and

after

paying himself to hand over


course
if

the surplus to the debtor.

Of

there was not suffi-

cient to discharge the debt, the balance remained due.


Involuntary
pledges.

458.

pledge might be

created

either voluntarily

or

involuntarily.
contract, or
either

A
will

voluntary pledge
;

might be

created

by
as

by

an involuntary pledge might be created


of court, or be attributed

by express order

by the law

an incident of certain transactions.


Only one kind of
security.

459. I do not propose to state at length the particular

modes

in

which a security
of law, or

vpas created

by

contract,

by

will,

by operation
note that the

by the order

of court.

I would only

Roman law had

this great practical convenience,

that there were general rules


security alike
difficulty

applicable

to

all

kinds

of

by whatsoever means
this,

created.

There was no

about

the general object and character of the

transaction being the same throughout;

and

it

conduced

greatly to the brevity, clearness, and precision of the law

that this should be


General

so.

460.

security

was not

necessarily restricted to a single

thing, but there might be a pledge of several things, and

even a general pledge of

all

a man's property.

But

here an

important distinction must be borne in mind.


pledge of
all

general

a man^s property

is
;

not a pledge of his property


for then the debts due
is

viewed as a whole (universitas)

by

him would be included; but


thing
Extinction of

it

a pledge of each several

now belonging

or hereafter to belong to the debtor.

461.

The following

are the principal methods


:

by which

a security came to an end

(i)

when

the pledgee became


(2)

the owner of the property given in pledge;

was agreed that the property should be released;


a third person had held the property honestly as

when it when his own for


(3)

twenty years

(4)

when
^

the obligation, the performance of


sect. 448, note.

See supra,

gee. 457-464.J

SECURITY.
(5)

225

which was to be secured, was discharged;


pledgee exercised his right of
sale.

when

the

462.

No

one can have a right of any kind over his

own When

not

property except the general right of ownership.


fore, I

If, there- guished.

am owner
But
of
if

of property I cannot hold that property


several persons have security

as security.

upon property,

and the

first

them becomes owner


if

of the property in right

of his security, then


all

his security

were simply extinguished

the other creditors would be able to enforce their securities

against the property.

To prevent this

injustice a special right,

which was sometimes


the
first

called a right of security,

was given

to

creditor^

which enabled him to protect himself against

subsequent security holders.


463.

How

to settle the claims of several creditors, each Priority,

holding security upon the same property and each claiming


to exercise his rights, has always been a problem of
difficulty.

some

The Roman lawyers

acted almost exclusively upon

the principle that the creditor earHest in point of time had


the prior right, and they justified this by their view of the

nature of the right of the pledgee, namely, that


in rem, or real right
all

it

was a right

a right

like

ownership available against

the world, which no

subsequent dealing to which the

pledgee was not a party could invalidate or impair.

No

regard was paid to the


acquired, nor did
it

mode make any


as

in

which the pledge had been


the date alone was

difference that another creditor

had

obtained
to.

possession;

rule

looked

464. There were, however, exceptions to this

rule.

Thus

Exception
to rule of priority by

when money had been


of preserving

advanced tor the express purpose


the case of a bond for

a thing from destruction, the lender could


as, for instance, in

"

claim a priority;

money
'

advanced to equip or repair a ship on a bottomry


compare the English doctrine as to
letting in sub;

It is interesting to

sequent incumbrances. See Coote on Mortgages, 4th ed., p. 645 also Vangerow, Lehrbuch der Pandekten, sect. 392 Windscheid, lehrbuch
;

d.

Pandekten-Rechts,

sect. 248, 4.

226

SECURITY.
as

[Chap. XI.

bond
Eight of
subse-

we

should call

it^.

The claims

of

the state for

public dues

had

also a preference over those of private persons.

465. The rights of a subsequent pledgee were the same as


those of any other secured creditor, subject only to the rights
of

quent
pledgees.

the

pledgees
sale,

who

preceded

him.

He

could bring

the

property to

and could even compel a prior pledgee to


also the special right to

do

so.

He

had

pay

off

any prior
If the

creditor

and take

his place

and

if

the prior creditor refused


it

to take the
first

money, he might deposit pay

in Court.

pledgee sold the property, and the produce was more


sufficient to

than

his debt, the

next pledgee could claim

to be paid out of the surplus.

English

466. Having thus stated shortly the


I proceed to consider the

Roman law of
and,
first,

security,

law of
security.

English law:

as it

is

administered in the Courts of


Distinction

Common Law.

467.

The law

is

here certainly in a backward condition.

between
fien.^^^"^

These courts can hardly be said to possess any method of


giving security over immoveable property, and as to moveable property the law appears to
in the

me

to be

somewhere about

same

state of

development as the

Roman law

at

the time of the First Punic


insist

War.

The common lawyers


is

very strongly that possession

necessary to

create

the security, and upon the difference between a pledge and

lien.

They

consider a lien as a mere personal right of

detention which gives the creditor no means of satisfying


his debt, but only produces a pressure
creditor, arising

upon the

will of the

from the inconvenience of being kept out of


is

his property

whereas (they say) a pledge

something more.

The

cases

are

not very explicit as to the distinction, but


is

I gather that a pledge

constituted

by adding

to a lien the

permission to the creditor in case of default to

sell

and

satisfy

' This priority was founded on what was called an in rem versio, and was an application of the general principle that one person oiight not to be enriched at the expense of another. Windscheid, Lehrbuch des

Fandekten-Kechts,

sect. 246.

Sec. 465-469.J

SECURITY.
is

227

the debt.

It

not however altogether clear whea this right


it

of sale exists

and when

does not.
^^^

468. It

is

easy to understand that creditors, dissatisfied Unauthoris

with a dry right of detention which


frequently attempt to
sell

very often burdensome,

the property pledged;

and no
question,

subject has vexed English judges

more than the

what remedy a debtor has for a wrongful, a premature, or an unauthorised sale by a creditor of the property which he holds as security. The knot has been partly cut by the
Factors' Acts
arises
:

but

it

is

a question which
It

still
is

frequently

where these acts do not apply.


settled that

now

pretty

well

the debtor can only recover such actual


suffered
;

damage

as

he

may have

and no one can complain of


at.

the injustice of the result thus arrived

But I

confess that

I do not understand a good deal of the reasoning on which


this opinion
is

based,

and I think that some advantage may be


it.

gained by examining
that so

It

is

in these cases particularly Pledgee

much
is,

learning and ingenuity have been

expended

right,

in establishing that the creditor got not only a lien but a

pledge, that

not a right of detention only of the article


sell

pledged, but also a right to

and apply the proceeds

in

satisfaction of the debt under the conditions of the contract

which right, they say, gives the creditor a 'specific interest


or property
'

in the article, that is to say, a jus in re


it is

^.

469.

Now

no doubt perfectly true that the holder of


'

This does

a thing as security has a

specific interest or

property

'

in the pend on

thing given as a security in the nature of a jus in re ;

but

P**''

*>*

what one

is

at a loss to see

is,

in

what way that depends upon


Still less is it easy to perceive

his having also a

power of

sale.

how

the nature of the creditor's interest can determine the

question, to

what remedy the debtor


sale.

is

entitled in case of

an

unauthorised or wrongful
^

This, as the learned judges


i.

Law

Reports, Queen's Bench, vol.

p. 612.

See Austin, Lectures,

pp. 990, 992, 3rd ed. I may here observe that what Mr. Justice Shee quotes (at p. 603) as Domat's opinion upon the Koman law is really

a statement of the French law, differing in this respect, as out, from the Koman law.

Domat

points

Q a

228

SECUBITY.

[Chap.

XL

elsewhere point out in the cases to which I refer, depends

upon the contract between the


produced by a violation of
True nature of
the real
its

parties,

and the

effect
^.

which

is

terms by one of them

470. I cannot therefore exactly see about the pledgee having a real right
the pledgee has a right to
in
re over the
sell
is

... why

this

discussion

introduced.

Whether
I

or not he

must always have a jus

thing which he holds as security.

am

disposed however to think that there has been some mis-

understanding as to the true nature of a real right, or jus


in re, which the judges are
so as

desirous to attribute to

a a

pledgee^.
specific

jus

in

re

is,

we know,
against

right over

thing available

generally

all

persons, as

distinguished from a personal right in respect of the same

thing which
only;
it is

is

available against

an individual or individuals

therefore a jtts in rem as distinguished

from a

jus in persmiam.
it is

Ownership, for example,

is

a real right, and


^-

in fact the

sum

of all real rights, as explained above

The

particular

kind of real right which the courts were

dealing with in the above cases was not the right of an owner,

but the right of one person over a thing owned by another ;


the right of the creditor in some
debtor's property;

manner

to

deal with the

a right in kind just like an easement.


or

But whether the pledgee has


than a mere
that

has not such a right


sell.

is

wholly unconnected with the right to


lien,
is

If he has

no more

a right over a specific thing available


it.

against any one


Difference
real right and real security.

who

invades

471. Possibly
'^^s,

what the learned judges were thinking


real security.

of

in truth, not a real right but a


'

What
:

constitutes a real security


is

has already been explained * j c

it

the means of getting satisfaction out of a specific thing

independently of the will or ability of the debtor.

This

comprehends a jus in
'

re,

or

real right,
i.

but also a great


;

Law
iii.

Reports, Queen's Bench, vol.

pp. 6oo, 615, 619

id.

Exchequer,

vol.
*

p. 301.

may observe

that in the case in the Queen's Bench, Mr. Justice Shee,

whilst he agrees with Mr. Justice Blackburn, that the pledgee has a real
right,
'

comes to a directly opposite decision upon the case before him.


'

Supra, sect. 309.

Supr.i, sect. 447.

Sec. 470-474.]

SECURITY.
and
it
is

229
that the essence
of

deal more;

perfectly

true
sale.

real security is

the power of

But then
it,

it

must

be borne in mind that the possession by the creditor of a

power of

sale,

and

his

ability to

exercise

in

no

way

affects or is affected
article pledged.

by the nature

of his interest in the

This power of sale when exercised operates,

not upon the interest of the creditor, but upon that of the
debtor, according to a
principle

perfectly familiar to

any

English lawyer.
472.

The law

of security has- been

far

more

satisfac- Pledge of

torily dealt

with by the Courts of Chancery, at


lands.

least

in courtVof

reference to

This portion of the law of England chancery,

bears a considerable resemblance both in its history and in


its

ultimate condition to the

Roman

law, and seems to be,

like the latter, the

combined

result of clear legal ideas

and

practical business habits.

473.

The

class

of

securities

with which the Courts of


I

Mortgage.

Chancery are specially concerned are called mortgages.


as

need not here explain at length the nature of a mortgage,


it

stood before the Courts of Chancery undertook to modify


it

the rights of the parties, and as


of

stands

now

in a Court

Common Law.
if is

It

is

an absolute conveyance, with a conpaid

dition that,

the

money be

by a
owner.

certain day, the

property

to be

restored to the

If that day

is

allowed to pass, the


absolute^.

ownership of the mortgagor becomes

At

this

low point in the development


it

of the

law of

security, so far as

related to lands, the Courts of


fast.

Common Law

seem

to

have stuck

474. In stating the law as applied

to landed security in Present

the Courts of Chancery, I wish for the

moment

to divert

,^^t

attention from the history and course of development of

the English law of mortgage, and also to get rid of the

terms which the Court of Chancery frequently finds


compelled to employ because
of the instrument
^

itself

it

is

cramped by the form


basis of its jurisdiction.
:

and the peculiar

It is

somewhat similar

to the original _^dcia

supra, sect. 440.


230

SECURITY.
is

[Chap. XI.

Stated in ordinary language, the law

now

as follows

The

transaction of mortgage creates a debt

by deed under

seal secured

by the pledge

of lands'-.

the owner of the property, and

may

deal

The debtor remains with it in any


whether in or

way he

thinks proper, provided he does not lessen or impair

the security of the creditor.

The

creditor,

out of possession of the land pledged, has the right to his


security and nothing more.
If the creditor takes possession

he
^'^^^
"^^^^^

is

accountable to the debtor for his

management
creditor

of the

Mortgagee property,

and

for

his

receipts.
;

The
that
is,

who has

mortgage has a

real security

he may, in case the


selling the
is

debtor fails to do so, satisfy his

own debt by
if

land pledged.

The power

to

sell

and satisfy the debt

frequently given by express contract, but even

not given
of

by

contract

it is

given by law^.
is

The concurrence
exercised.

the

debtor in the sale

immaterial;
is

but six months' notice

must be given before the power


unless restricted public auction
shares.
;

The

creditor,

by the

contract,

may
;

sell

privately or

by

in one lot or in parcels

but not in undivided


is left

And though

the conduct of the sale

entirely

to the creditor, he must not adopt any

mode
is

of selling

which

would be

clearly depreciatory.
all

He
if

in fact

fiduciary

vendor, and must use


price.

reasonable diligence to obtain a fair


sell,

But

his

power to

unrestricted

by

contract,

cannot be interfered with, even though his conduct be harsh

and oppressive

the only course to stay the sale


^.

is

actually to

tender the principal, interest, and costs


Chancery
mortgage might be
fixtenned.

475.

Why
and

these clear and sensible rules should have been


is

confined to the Courts of Chancery one


ggJYe
.

at a loss to con-

'

why
>

Courts of

Common Law should have been shut


all jurisdiction

out, or should

have shut themselves out, from


it is

over landed security


'
"^

also difficult to say


i.
;

*.

Coote on Mortgages, 4th

ed., p.

23

&

24 Viet. chap. 145, sect. 11

Dart, Vendors

and Purchasers,

4th ed.,
'

p. 48.

Dart, Vendors and Purchasers, pp. 60, 63. The recent changes by which all Courts have received jurisdiction

to

Sec. 475, 476.]

SECURITY.

231
a complete revolu- Lord

476. There has been one attempt at


tion of the ideas of a

mortgage

security prevailing in the attempted

English Courts of

Common Law, made


The

by a judge who was

* o^'e"<i

fearless of innovation^

and to whose hands innovation might


question arose in this way.
it

have been safely trusted.

A
of

person having a leasehold interest in land assigned

to

another by
land.

way of security, in the usual form of a mortgage Of course, in strict law, this was an absolute
liable

assignment, and the assignee became

to

the lessor

upon the covenants in the

lease.

In an action, however,
lease,

by the

lessor

against the assignee of the


lease,

upon a

covenant contained in the

judgment was unanimously


Justices Willes, Ashurst,

given for the defendant by the Court of Queens's Bench,


consisting of

Lord Mansfield and

and

Buller.

Lord Mansfield argued that


it
is

in order 'to do

justice

between men

necessary to

understand things
according

as they really are, and to

construe instruments

to the intention of the parties,'' treat

He
in

therefore refused to
reality

the mortgage

as

if

it

was

(what

it

no

doubt was in form) a complete assignment of the


interest,

lessee's

and considered
to,

it

as a

mere security 1.
can be
little

Had

these

views been adhered


position of

there

doubt that the

mortgagor and mortgagee in Courts of


if

Common
It Defeated

Law
is

would have been in a great measure,

not entirely,

assimilated to their position in the Court of Chancery.

perhaps, therefore, not surprising that they were firmly Kenyon.

opposed by Lord

Mansfield's verj' conservative


to

successor.

Lord Kenyon ^, who seems

have treated Lord Mansfield's

opinion and those of the other judges

who

concurred with

him
^.'

almost with contempt, and declared that he would over-rule


the decision of his predecessor 'without the least reluctance

do complete justice in every case will lamentably fail of their object unless the common law doctrines as to mortgages are completely eradicated ; and surely it is unnecessaiy that the old clumsy forms should be
retained.

See the case of Eaton against Jaques in Douglas' Eeports, p. 455. Coote on Mortgages, 3rd ed., p. 120. This learned author was also evidently alarmed at what he calls Lord Mansfield's equitable innova'

'

tions.'

Coote on Mortgages, ubi supra.

232

SECXJKITY.

[Chap. XI.

Holder of 477. I caB scarcely say whyj but even Courts of Chancery security on have sometimes shown something of the same timidity as moveables cannot is shown by Courts of Common Law, when they have had to always sell. deal with security over property other than land. If goods

be mortgaged exactly in the same form as land

is

usually

mortgaged, the mortgagee's rights are not considered to be


so full

and complete ^

and when a security has been estabChancery have not


to

lished in the nature of a lien, Courts of

ventured any more than Courts of


effect

Common Law
sale.

give

to

the security by permitting a

In a recent

case,
its

where the Court of Chancery was pressed to exercise

jurisdiction

by directing a
expressed
^-

sale,

Lord Hatherley (then


that
it

Vice-Chancellor)

his

opinion

would be

dangerous to do so
Bare right

478. There are

still,

therefore,

many

cases in

which the

of detention often creditor has a useless to his right, creditor.

bare right of detention, and can neither by

own

nor by the assistance of any court, obtain any


is

satisfaction of his claim if his debtor


beneficial to of
all parties

obstinate,

however

a sale might be.

Thus a vendor
cases

goods

may

before delivery retain,

and in some

may

even after delivery retake, possession of them,

and hold
the
lost

them
sell

as

a security for the unpaid price;

but he cannot
till

them;

and

so

this

detention

may

continue

goods become valueless, when the creditor will have


his security

and the debtor his property^.

Sum
against
Carvalho.

479. There are however cases in which this narrow conception of the law of security as applied to moveable property

appears to

be dropped without hesitation, and the widest

possible validity is given to arrangements

made by

debtors

for giving to creditors security for their claims.


'

I do not

and Purch. p. 48, 4th ed. See the case of The Thames Iron Works Company against The Patent Derrick Company, Law Journal Eeports, Chancery, vol. xxix. p. 714.
Dart, Vend,
'

If the remarks of such able and experienced lawyers as Lord Blackburn and Mr. Benjamin upon the rights of the unpaid vendor be considered, it will be apparent that my observations upon the unsatisfactory condition of the English law are neither presumptuous nor unfounded. See Blackburn on Sale, pp. 320 sqq. Benjamin on Sale of Personal Property, book v. chap. iii.
"'

'

Sec. 477-479.J

SECURITY.

233
of view proceeds.

know upon what distinction this change Of course every variety of right may be
cases
is

created

by agree-

ment, but the difference in the agreement in some of these


very slight, and I suspect a good deal more depends

on the inclination of the court when determining the intention of the parties, than on the exact words.
case before

In the

Lord Hatherley above referred

to-"^

the debtor

actually agreed with his creditor,

who had

already a lien

or

bare

right

of

detention,

that the property should at


for the claim
helpless.

some future time be mortgaged


of sale. case
^,

with a power

There the creditor was

Yet in another

where there was nothing but a promise by the debtor


'

at a future time to

hand over

'

to his creditor property of

an

amount equivalent

to the debt, it

was held by Lord Cottenham


This
a

that this promise alone gave the creditor a right to have the

property applied to liquidate and satisfy his debt.


decision

is

which has been since frequently followed, and the

incidents of the transaction, as well as the effect


so readily given to
it,
;

which was
this case

are

worthy of remark.
'

In

nothing was

specified

the promise related to

any property

in the hands of the debtor^'s correspondent abroad ; the nature

and value of the property were wholly unknown ; the amount


of the debt due

was

also

wholly unknown,

it

being probable

that the debt had been partly paid ; the right was considered
to be created

by the promise to the

creditor alone (the


^)

Lord
had

Chancellor says so expressly in his judgment

before

it

been even communicated to the debtor's correspondent.

what

is

most important

is

the result.

But The mere promise to


until the debt

transfer the goods to the hands of the creditor was considered


to create, not merely a right to hold
paid, but a right to apply

them

was any

them

at once, and without

Supra,

sect. 477.

the well-known case of Burn against Carvalho, reported in the fourth volume of Mylne and Craig's Reports, p. 690. The same case had previously been before a Court of Common Law, and an opposite
^

This

is

view taken.
'

See the report in Adolphus and

Ellis, vol.

i.

p. 883.

See

p.

703 of the report.

234

SECURITY.
:

formality or delay, in satisfaction of the debt


as soon as he
his debtor

the creditor,

got possession,

which he did not do until after


sold
all

had become bankrupt,

the goods without

further notice or ceremony, charging

expenses incurred

upon
Compared
decisions.
is

his debtor.
all

480. I do not at
'
jjj^g

suggest that this decision was eiToneous.


"^

with other ji^pgj.jgjjgg

gjiown that the principle on which ^

it proceeds ^ is is

(commercially speaking) convenient, and there


it

no legal
certainly

difficulty whatsoever in carrying

out.

But
so

there

to

my

mind a

difficulty

in

seeing
case

great a difference

between the agreement in


before
results.

this

and that in the case


such totally different

Lord Hatherley, as

to lead to

481.

From

this account of the

English law of security

it is

apparent that no clear, consistent, and comprehensive state-

ment

of principles can be

made with regard

to

it.

At any rate
no
difficulty

this has never yet


is

been done.

On the other hand,


Roman Empire, Roman law has
it

found in preparing such a statement of the law of security


it

either as

existed under the

or as

it

now

exists in countries

where the

been adopted

with a

real

and comprehensive knowledge of what that law

was, and the principles upon which

was based ^.

I think

therefore that there can be no escape from the conclusion that

the faults of the English law are due, not to

its

connexion
in

with the
the

Roman Roman law

law, but to the imperfect

manner

which

has been understood.

I have therefore,

borrowing the results of the labours of others, given a pretty


full

statement of the

Roman

law, from which I think

it

will

be seen that the principles recognised are not altogether


different

from the principles of our own law, but they are

fewer, simpler, and more consistently followed.


'

See, for instance, the


I. tit.

Staaten, Part

20. sections

Allgemeines Landrecht fiir die Preussischen i and 2. This composition is not to be

compared

for clearness and precision with some portions of the more recent Allgemeines Deutsches Handelsgesetzhuch, yet it is incomparably better than anything to be found on the subject of pledge in the English

language

and although it is in many parts tediously minute, the subject only occupies forty-six octavo pages.
:

CHAPTER

XII.

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.
482.

The
of

acquisition of ownership

may

take place either Acquisinafor^aT


transfer.

in respect of a thing respect

which had no previous owner, or in


If

a thing which had a previous owner.

the

thing had a previous owner, then the ownership of one


person
is

transferred to another.

If

it

had not a previous

owner, then a

new ownership

is

created ^.

483. If a thing be without an owner, and be at the same Occu-

time not in the possession of any one,


of any one
it
'

it

becomes the property P^^^y


if

'

who

takes possession of

it,

he chooses that
is

lii^s-

should so become.

This method of acquisition


there
is

called

occupancy.'

But

in

English

law-books

very

little

upon the subject of occupancy,


fish in

for the

reason that
it

except

the sea there

is

very

little

to

which

can

be applied.

Fish in a river and wild animals on land are

generally considered to be in the possession of the person upon

whose land they happen to

be,

and when
to

killed or captured

they belong either to the landowner or


,
.

the captor ^.
Origin of
A

484. The real interest which attaches to acquisition of

ownership by occupancy or a res nullms

J,

11-

is

not

ownership

connexion not simple


'"'""

with

its

modern

application,

which

is rare,

but in connexion
it

with the origin of ownership.


'

Until recently

was almost

It does not

seem impossible

to analyse every transfer of ownership

into the extinction of the ownership of the transferor and the creation of a new ownership in the transferee, hut I do not think it would tend to

simplicity to do so on the contrary, the idea of transfer carries with it the idea that the incidents of ownership are not changed, which is an idea we wish generally to preserve. ^ This question has been warmly contested in France and Germany. See Dalloz, Eepertoire, s. v. Chasse, art. 172; Wachter, Pandekten, 134,
:

and

Beil.

i.

As

to the English law, see supra, sect. 361 note.

236

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.

[Chap. XII.

always assumed that the acquisition of ownership by occupancy

was
ing

so simple, so obvious,

and

so universal^ as to

be deemed
of acquir-

natural,
all

and that

it

was^ in fact^ the original

ownership.

That assumption

is

mode not now


is

accepted.

Nevertheless occupancy and ownership are historically connectedj and the


its

history of

that connexion
^.

not without

importance in modern controversies


485. The person

Finding
of lost property.

who takes possession of a thing which has an owner, but an unknown owner, cannot acquire ownership
by merely taking possession of
it,

for

it is

not a res nullius.

He may,

however,

if it is

not in the possession of any one,

take possession of

it,

and by lapse of time he may acquire the

ownership like any other possessor.

In some

countries,

where

the owner does not at once come forward to claim the lost
property,
it is

transferred

by a

special

law to the

state, or

to the principal officer of justice, or to the church;

and
to

this

sometimes with, and


finder.

sometimes without a share


it
is

the

In England

only the Crown, or

its

grantee,

which has ever asserted a claim to property

lost

by the
^.

owner, and this only in respect of wreck, waifs, and estrays.

But the
Whales and
sturgeons.

right, even to this extent,

is

now

rarely asserted

486. The Crown has, by an ancient statute called Prerogativa Regis of uncertain date, the ownership of whales

sturgeons taken in the sea or within the realm.


is still

and The right

sometimes claimed in respect of whales by the grantees

of the Crown.
Treasure
trove.
^

487. Treasure trove

is

not strictly speaking a res nullius.

ship will be found in the 8th chapter of Sir

Some interesting observations upon the relation of occupancy to ownerHenry Maine's Ancient Law.
find

We

an example of occupancy without ownership in the (so-called) Manu. The ownership of cultivated land (as distinguished from the homestead and the pasture immediately attached thereto) is not mentioned in that work and as there are no rules as to how such land
Institute.? of
;

is to

be disposed of

when
it

the family breaks up,

it

seems clear that

when

that book was written

was not owned, but only occupied. " See Blackst. Comm. vol. i. p. 399 Code Civ. art. 717, and the observations of Marcad6 in his edition of the Code Dernburg, Lehrb. d. Preuss.
;

Pr.-B. vol.

i.

232.

Sec. 485-491.]

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.

237

It

is

property which once had an owner^ and which has


lost)

been hidden (not abandoned or

by him; and on
as

its

being discovered
if all

it

will

be

considered
is

treasure
If

trove

hope of tracing the owner


is

lost.

hidden in a
field,

place which

itself

owned, as in a house or a

it

would, according to English principles, be in the possession


of that owner; but or to the finder.
it

does not belong either to that person


it is

It belongs to the Crown, and


its

an offence

not to give notice of

discovery.

488. The acquisition of treasure trove has always been

governed by special

rules.

By

the

Roman law
it

half was

given to the owner of the spot where


to the
finder^.

was found, and half

This

is

the rule which generally prevails


^.

on the continent of Europe


489. If a tree bears
offspring,

fruit,

or a domestic

animal bears Produce


the

of

the produce in each ease


it

belongs to

same a^^als.

person as the tree or animal, unless


'

has been parted with.

This has been called acquisition by accession.'

490. The transfer of ownership by what

is

called alluvion Alluvion

and diluvion
shifting

is

of considerable importance in those countries Diiuyion


rivers cause a great

where the magnitude and violence of the


of

the

soil,

and frequent changes

in

the course

of the stream.
rare,

In England disturbances of
all,

this

kind are

and, so far as they occur at

generally occur in tidal


sea.

rivers

and in creeks and arms of the

The open

sea

also

sometimes advances or recedes.

491.

The

shore of the open sea

that

is,

the strip of land


call
it

between high and low water mark which we commonly


the sea-shore

is

vested in the

Crown

or its grantee.

And
is

makes no

difference

where

this strip of land is situate.

If the

sea advances, this strip of land advances also, and

taken

from the adjoining


space which
is

estate.

If the sea recedes, there will be a


it is

not sea-shore, as

never covered by water.


to think

To whom
' ^

does this space belong ?


ij.

Lord Hale seems

Just. Inst.

I.

39
;

Waohter, Pand.

134, Bell.
d.

2.
i.

Code

Civ. art. 716

Dernburg, Lehrb.

Preuss. Pr.-K. vol.

233.

238

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.

[Chap. XII.

that this depends on whether the sea has simply receded, or

whether the sea

is

shut out, as

it

were,

'

by the casting up and


'
:

adding sand and stubb to the adjoining land


to

and he seems
latter

assume that the former would be a sudden, and the

a gradual process.
considers that the

If the sea were gradually shut out, he

owner of the adjoining

estate

would gain

the newly formed strip

by

accretion.

If the dry land were


it

formed by the sea receding, be considers that


to the

would belong

Crown, as

it

did whilst

it

was covered with water.


giving the newly formed

Blackstone makes the whole question depend on the gradual


or sudden nature of the change,

land to the

Crown

in the latter case


^.

and

to the adjoining

owner in the former


and of

492. The margins of creeks and arms of the sea intra fauces
terrae,
tidal rivers

between high and low water mark,

as well as the beds of such creeks, arms,

and

rivers,

belong to

the Crown, or to

its

grantee ; and this ownership shifts as tbe


is

water advances or recedes ; that


of these creeks, arms,

to say, the

margin and beds

and

rivers will

belong to the Crown,

whatever their local limits

may

be at any one time.


estate

As

to

any

land

between
be
left

the

adjoining

and

the

water
out of

which

may

by the receding

or

shutting

the water, I imagine that the same rules would be applied


as in the case of the receding or shutting out of the

open

sea.

493. The beds of inland rivers belong to the adjoining


proprietors,

and

it is

doubtful whether any change in the flow

of the river, causing dry land to appear in one place

and

dis-

appear in another, does, as a general rule, cause any change


in ownership
^.

The
is

root of this doubt appears to be, that


it

where the land

not res nuUius, then the ownership of


it

cannot depend on whether or no


'

happens to be covered

See Hale de Jure Maris, cap. vi, and Blackst. Comm. vol. ii. p. 262. See the ease of Foster versus Wright, in Law Reports, Common Fleas Div., Tol. iv. p. 447 and that of the Attorney General verms Chambers, reported in De Gex and Jones' Reports, vol. iv. p. 55. Also the observa^
;

tions of the Privy Council in Lopez versus

Muddun

Thakoor, Moore's

Indian Appeals,

vol. xiii. p. 467.

Sec. 492-494.]

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.
This was certainly so in the

239
;

with water.

Roman law

and

the doctrine of acquisition of ownership by alluvion and


diluvion, as

developed in that law, depended on the prin-

ciple that the beds of rivers

were not owned by any one.


acquisition of a res nulis

The
lius.

acquisition, therefore,

was an

But
the

in every case where there

acquisition of land

in England, the thing, though possibly not


in sense

owned exactly
is

that

private

property

is

owned,

cer-

tainly not a res nuUius.

The

acquisition of land, therefore,

by

alluvion and diluvion, if not excluded altogether,


us,

must

depend with

not on the acquisition of a res nullius by

occupancy, but upon some other principle.


to

Lord Hale seems


some
special

have perceived
is

this,

and

tries

to put it on
is

ground which
that
it is

not clear 1.

It

better to admit at once

a special transfer of ownership ensuing upon some


:

physical change

nor

is

there

any doubt that such a

transfer
as,

does take place for which no other account can be given ;


for example,

when by the advance


is is

of the sea private land

becomes sea-shore, and


494. There

transferred to the Crown.

one large tidal river in England, the Severn,


is

in which, or at least in one part of which, the rule

that the

manors on
the
the.

either side are

bounded one against the other by


:

medium
^.

filum aquae, or central line of the stream


if

so that
its

boundaries are shifted

the river in any

way changes

course

This also appears to be the rule in America, where


is

the boundary between two estates


soil

a fresh-water river, the


^
:

of which belongs to the adjoining proprietors


is

and a

similar rule
^

found in some parts of India

*-

See the passage in Hargrave's Tracts, vol. i. p. 31. He says, If the soil of the sea which is covered with water be the king's, it cannot become the subject's because the water has left it. But in the case of alluvio maris [i.e. gradual deposit] it is otherwise ; because the accession and the
'

perquisite,
if

addition of the land by the sea to the dry land gradually is a kind of and an accession to the land.' But these observations, even

much

they amount to anything, would apply only to the surface. And I very doubt whether Lord Hale's distinction between the sea receding and being shut out by gradual deposit is a sound one. ^ Hale de Jure Maris, cap. vi. at p. 35 of vol. i. of Hargrave's Tracts.
Kent's

Comm.

vol.

iii.

p. 428.

See Eeg.

xi.

of 1825, sect. 2.

'

240
Confusion.

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.

[Chap. XII.

495. If the goods (moveable property) of one

mixed with the goods of another the ownership

man become may be-

come thereby changed, and the


case have occasioned

rules

applicable to such a

some

discussion.

But

in England, the

question

is

not of

much

importance, because the English

law by the action of trover provides means by which a person

whose goods have been mixed with those of another person


can recover compensation for the loss of his property (which
is

probably

all

he wants) without entering into the question

of whose the goods are subsequently to the mixture having

been made.

Consequently,

if

I take another man's goods

and mix them with


of the
as the
is

my

own, I

am

liable to

pay for the value

goods, and damages

for their detention.

As

soon

judgment

is

satisfied,
'

the ownership of the mixture

wholly in the defendant

The very

nice question as to the

ownership of the mixture before the action could hardly arise


in

England

and

it

has not been discussed.


it

Quidquid
solo solo eedit.

496. English lawyers generally take

for granted that

when the moveable property


i^jjjj

of one

man

is

attached to the

g another
off

it is

at once transferred to the landowner,

who
is

sweeps

everything.
'

This somewhat ruthless doctrine


quidquid plantatur solo solo
is

based upon the maxim,

cedit.'

This, or something like this,

to be

found in the

Roman
in

law,

but

it

was not applied

in the unqualified
it.

manner

which

English lawyers apply

For example, under the

Roman

law the materials of a building did not become the property


of the person

on whose land the building was placed, but


This, though
it

remained the property of the builder.

seems

to us rather clumsy, must have operated as a practical qualification of the rights of the

landowner, probably forcing

him

to

make some

compensation.

So too the

right, so tardily

recognised by us, of the lessee to be compensated for his im-

provements, was distinctly recognised by the


'

Roman law ^.

Infra, sect. 505.


'

'

ad

te pertinet.

Id quod in solo tuo aedificatum est, quod in eadem causa manet, jure Si vero fuerit dissolutum, ejus materia ad pristinum
redit,

dominum

sive

bona

fide

sive

mala aedificium exstructum

sit.

Sec. 495-500- J

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.
is

241
to

497. The French law gives whatever


soil to

affixed

the

the landowner, but then

it also

makes some

careful

provisions in favour of the party


perty,

upon the

just
^.'

principle

'

who thereby loses his proneminem cum detrimento

alterius locupletari

498. The German law does not appear to recognise the


rule quidquid plantatur solo solo cedit as a universal one.

Thus,

if

man

builds

upon the land of another, whether he


has three courses open to
it

does so bona fide or not, the building always belongs to the


builder,

and the owner of the

soil

him.

He

can either acquire the building by paying for

or he can compel the owner of the building to pay for the

land on which

it

stands

or he can insist

upon the building


landowner did

being removed.
not

But

this only in case the

know of the building, or knew it and forbad it. If he knew of the construction and did not interfere, the land passes to the builder, who pays to the owner its value ^
499. Sometimes a

man
This
is

is
:

deprived of his property as Forthat


is,

a punishment for an offence


ferred to the Crown.

his property is trans-

called forfeiture,

and

is

of

some

importance in connexion with the criminal law.


there
is

So too

a kind of forfeiture where property


satisfied,

is

held upon
is

some condition, which not being


forfeited.

the property

Such conditions may be created by the declared


a

intentions of the parties interested.

500.

When

man
his

becomes

bankrupt his

property

is

Bankrupt^'

transferred to trustees to

be turned into

tributed

amongst

creditors.

This

is

money and disa topic of much


position of the
d.

importance in connexion with the law of bankruptcy.


Code

Just.

ii.

32. 2

see Just. Inst.

ii. i.
;

29.

The

mala

fide builder has,


;

however, been doubted

are

329 and see also Dig. vi. i. 59. in conducto fundo, remarkable
:

Vangerow, Lehrb. The words of the Digest as


see
si

Pandek.

to a lessee

'

conductor sua opera aliquid

neeessario vel utiliter auxerit, vel aedificaverit, vel instituerit,

convenisset, ad reoipienda ea quae impendit ex conducto

cum id non cum domino

fundi experiri potest.'

Dig. xix.

a,

55.

Code

Civ. art. 555.

Preuas. Allg. L.

See Marcad^, ad loo. i. 9, 327 Dernburg, Lehrb.


;

d.

Preuss. E. K.

i.

236.

242
Execu^""

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.
is

[Chap. XII.

501. Property

not unfrequently transferred from one

person to another by judicial process.


directly

This

may

be done

by a decree

of the court, or

by a

seizure

and

sale

of the property.
of a sale, there is

Though

the transaction

may

take the form

no true contract, and no

real sale in the

ordinary sense of the term.


Succes-

502. There

is

a transfer of ownership which takes place

at the death of the owner,

and which

is

of vast importance.

This I shall consider in a future chapter.


Prescrip-

503.

Long

possession

of

property by a person

who

is

not the owner

may have
which

the effect of transferring ownership,


is

upon a

principle

called prescription,

and

this also

I shall consider presently.

How
of

far

504. Quite independently however of the transfer of ownership which takes place in consequence of long possession
prescription, there
is

move-

by

f'n^^ posses-

in the

case

of moveable

property a
if

transfer of ownership

which takes place merely,

might

say

so,

by reason

of the refusal of the law to follow moveables

from one hand to another, and of the ease with which ownership
in the case of moveables
I will
Difference
is

presumed from possession.

This

now

consider.

505. The position of a person

who

hast lost possession of

moveables moveable property is essentially different from the position and im^^ ^ person who has lost possession of immoveable property,
ables.

person

who has

lost

possession of immoveable property

may

after a considerable lapse of time lose his ownership,

which ownership another person


scription.

may have

acquired

by

pre-

But

until

this

time has

passed the owner of

immoveable property has ample remedies provided him for


following his property wherever he

may

find

it,

and for

Owner
cannot
recover
specie.

of

recovering
rarely do.

it

in specie.

This the owner of moveables can very

As

a general rule, whatever

may
if

be the form
his ownership

q action in

which he proceeds, and even

be established, he can only recover the value at which the


property
is

assessed,

and not the property


it

itself,

although the

defendant

is

able to give

up.

The

result of the

payment

of

Sec. 501-507.]

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.
T

243

the value, or of the levy of that amount in execution, or other Transfer


,.

,.

satisfaction of the

J!

judgment,

of o\*nersViip

is

that the ownership

is

divested

by

from the

plaintifE
is

and transferred

to the party in possession,


sale.

^^f'^li^I.

and the case

likened to that of an involuntary

Of

course, if the plaintifE himself chooses to take the value of the

goods instead of the goods

it is

reasonable that he should be

understood to have parted with his property.


peculiar that he should be compelled to do so.

But

it

is

Possibly the

reason of this
plaintifE in

may

be that there

is

a great advantage to the

suing in a form of action which enables him to

recover damages instead of the property.

He

need not then

prove that the defendant

is still

in possession of the property.

506. Whether the plaintiff will be allowed as an exceptional case to have

judgment

for a return of the property


it,

with the process necessary to compel


nature as that damages or
cient
satisfaction.

is

decided
is

by the

court after considering whether the property


its

of such a
suffi-

value will not be a


is

This,

however,

rather a matter

for

the plaintifE's
simplified
if

own

decision,

and the law would be much


left

the plaintiff were

to

choose whether he

would sue

for the property or for its value ^. 507. But besides the transfer of the ownership of moveables Transfer
.

which takes place when compensation


loss,

is

recovered for their ship by

i<.i-^ o-wner-

there are still to be found traces of a notion, once widely ^a^^ge of prevalent, that in the case of moveables the ownership always posses-

followed the possession.


origin
of

The

origin of this view, like the

nearly all views

of law

which proceed upon a

distinction

between moveables

and immoveables, must be

sought, not in the

Roman

law, but in the law of Germany.

The Roman
istic

law protected by the same procedure the ownerIt


is

ship both of moveables and immoveables. of the early

a character-

German law

that whilst the ownership of

'

The most recent

case on the subject

Is

that of

Ex parte Drake, in Law

Keports, Chancery Division, vol. v. p. 866, which however proceeds entirely upon authority, and contains no elucidation of the legal principle
applicable to the case.

E3

244

ACQUISITION OF OWNEBSHIP.

[Chap. XII.

land was almost indestructible^ the ownership of moveables

had only a very precarious


Early
]aw.

protection.

508. The old German


moveables in the maxims
'

law expressed
'

this

view as

to

Wo man

seinen

Hand muss Hand wahren/ and gelassen hat^ muss man ihn wieder Glauben
of these

finden.^

The meaning

maxims, and the exact state

of the law which they represented in the remote times

when

they were apphcable, are too

much

disputed for

me

to venture
it

on any exact explanation of them.

In a general way

may

be said that they indicated that when a


possession of goods he

man

parted with the


for their

must himself provide means

recovery.

He

could not, merely relying upon his previous

ownership, put forward

a claim against any person who

happened
to
if

to be in possession of them.

Against the person

whom

he entrusted them he might have a personal action,

the circumstances were such that any obligation to restore

the goods existed.

There was one exception to this which seems to be as


old
as

the

maxims themselves.

If

the

goods

had been

taken from the owner by violence they might be retaken

by him.
Develop-

509. In

modem

times the protection of moveable property

law of ownership ^^^ historical inquiry into the development of it i J of moveables. extremely interesting. It seems to have proceeded
J.

^^ extended everywhere considerably beyond these limits.

would be

upon two

lines

first,

the personal action for the restoration of the goods

seems to have been extended so as to be maintainable under


certain circumstances against persons
in the undertaking to restore
;

who were not

included

secondly, the exceptional right

to retake possession of goods

which had been taken by vioexercisable in a larger

lence seems to have been


of cases,

made

number

and

to

have been used as a foundation of proceedings

for an inquiry into the ownership.

Modern
Ltw.

510. Perhaps the nearest approach to the early

German

law which can be found in modern times


adopted
in

is

in the

maxim
meubles

the

French Civil Code,

'

en

fait

de

Sec. 508-511.]

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.
Its

245

possession vaut titre^.^

only exceptions are where the

property has been stolen from or lost by the owner.


the modern French law also

In

we

still

see in a modified

form

the ancient process by which a person asserted his ownership,

namely, by actual

seizure.

When
first

under the French law such


step
still
is,

an

assertion

is

allowed, the

under the au-

thority and with the assistance of the court, to seize the goods
claimed, and after that
is

done, then the contest as to the

ownership
511.

is

continued before the court ^.


action for the recovery of the goods based
is

The

upon

Action

<if

a personal obligation to restore them


represented by the action of detinue.
action of detinue
obligation exists
:

in

English law

It is true that the

is

not

now

restricted to cases

where such an

it is

equally applicable to all cases in which

one party

is

wrongfully in possession of the goods of another.


still

But the
goods
^,

notion

lingers that
is,

the action of detinue

is

founded on a contract, that

a contract to redeliver the


it

and Blaekstone thought that

was a necessary conAction of

dition to the action that the defendant

possession of the goods

*.

came lawfully into The proceeding by which a person


goods without his assent could

who had
' '

lost possession of his

Code

Civ. art. 2279.


;

Co. Proc. Civ. art. 826


is

Pothier, CEuvres, vol. i, p. 240, ed. Bugnet.


It follows

The process
'

called saisie vindication.

very closely our pro-

ceedings in replevin.

See the case of Bryant against Herbert, reported in the


Div., vol.
vol.
iii.

Law

Reports,

Com. Pleas
*

iii. p.

189.

Comm.

p.

152.

See Year Book, 6 Henry VII.

fo. 9,

where

Brian, C.

J.,

repudiates the contention that a tortious taking cannot

change the property. The reason he gives is, that tlie person who is so put out of possession cannot have any action of detinue to which action it is necessary that the plaintiff should be owner at the time of action brought; and that he should allege that the defendant came by the goods lawfully. But he thinks that the person who has lost the goods by a tortious taking might have replevin that is, he might get the goods back into his possession, and so put himself into a position to assert his
: ;

ownership, which, before retaking, he could not do. Brian seems to have thought that it was impossible to separate the ownership of moveables from the possession. Perhaps in so thinking he was rather behind the
age in which he lived.

246
assert his

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.
ownership by retaking them
is

[Chap. XII.

traceable in the

action of replevin.
session

In replevin the party could recover possherifE^

through the

giving security to restore

it

if

the right were adjudged against him.

This procedure was

generally considered applicable only to cases of goods seized


for a distress.

But I apprehend that

it

was not confined


whenever
it

to

such cases, and that the


alleged that one party

sheriff could act

was

had wrongfully taken

possession of
of the

the goods of another.

The party who complained

wrongful taking by recovering possession put himself in a


position to assert his ownership,
wise.

which he could not do other-

If the other party also claimed the goods as his own,

the proceedings were taken out of the sheriff's hands and tried
in the regular way.

And,

as

it

appears to me, this was at one

time a legitimate way, and indeed the only legitimate way, of


raising the question of ownership.

Afterwards, by the intro-

duction of the action of trover, a person was enabled to claim

goods of which he was out of possession, even when he could


not prove any undertaking to return them and without resorting to any preliminary seizure
retaking of the goods
Practical
:

and hence the procedure by a


or system of procedure

fell into disuse.

512.

Whatever may be the law

of recover-

there will always be considerable difiiculty in following

ing move- ownership of moveables.

often changes so rapidly

up the The ownership of moveables very that to restore them would disturb a
which are perfectly

great
fair

many

transactions, the majority of

and honest.

Nevertheless the English law has gone

very far in recent times in allowing the ownership to be


followed up.

Not only

is

it

now

impossible for
act,

man
be

to give himself a title


persons,

by a wrongful
perfect

but even third


faith,

who have
^.

acted in

good

may

successfully sued

by the owner seeking

to recover possession

of his goods

And

this,

not only in cases where the owner


will,

has been deprived of his possession against his


^

but
iii.

See the case of Cundy

v.

Lindsay,

Law

Reports, Appeal Cases, vol.

p. 459-

Sec. 512-514.J

ACQUISITION OF OWNEESHIP.

247

even where he has consented to part with his ownership^


if

he has been induced to give his consent by fraud


513.

^.

To some

extent this somewhat extreme view of the


statute^

English lawyers has been modified by


mercial transactions persons

and

in

com-

who

honestly deal with those


possession of goods

who

are entrusted

by the owner with the

are protected ^.

Moreover the ownership follows the posses- Owner

sion in the case of coin

and negotiable instruments

and even

ly satisfied

goods stolen which have been sold in market overt belong to Y^*^ =" damages.
the purchaser!
514. In the English law, therefore, as well as in other
systems, there
is

Difficulty

in

some

cases a transfer of the ownership of EngHsh"^


is

moveables which takes place when the owner


session,

out of pos- ^''^


of

though wrongfully

so,

and quite independently


of title

his consent, or of
scription.

any acquisition

by means

of pre-

It would be diflaeult to say exactly


this

when and under


place,

what circumstances
as a whole.

change of ownership takes

since the subject has never been considered thoroughly

and

But the general

attitude

assumed by the English

law has certainly been

in recent times to protect the

owner

of moveable property so far as to allow

him
is

to assert his

ownership, until he has parted with

it

by some

act of his

own.

On
it,

the other hand, the English law

rather lax in

assisting the
sion of

owner of moveable property


it

to recover posses-

even where

allows

him

to assert his ownership.


satisfied

He
'

must, as I have
^.

said, generally

be

with a money

compensation
This

is the remarkable feature in the case of Cundy v. Lindsay. The had not only parted with the possession, he had also parted with but, because he had parted with the his ownership, as he thought ownership to A, believing A to be B, the Court thought he had not really parted with the ownership. Lord Cairns holds, not that there was a contract vitiated by fraud, but that there was no contract, and he seems to think it idle to consider whether the ownership could pass by the transfer without a contract. But I do not think that is a view which all and it is only a modern view in England. jurists would accept ' See the Factors' Acts, 5 & 6 Vict. e. 39 40 & 41 Vict. u. 39 and the Bankruptcy Act, 46 & 47 Vict. c. 52, s. 44. ^ If the owner elects to take compensation there appears to be a sort of

plaintiff

248
Transfer
OT
sl'le

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.
The
is

[Chap. XII.

515.

transfer of ownership

which we meet with most

frequently

that which takes place either on gift or on sale.

These modes of transfer have been very much discussed,

and many
tions are

of the principles

which govern these two transacboth.

common

to

them

In both the transfer

is

voluntary one.

They both

involve a declaration of intention


transferee.

by two persons, a transferor and a


1 have found
it

On

the whole

most convenient to discuss these two modes

of transferring ownership together.

The

observations I shall

make
Lands

are of a very general kind.

516. If

we

attend only to the present aspect of law

we

the free right of alienation of pronofXei^- ^'e very apt to speak of able, perty, that is, the free right of voluntary transfer by gift or
sale, as

one of the so-called natural rights of


is

man

meaning,

I suppose, that it
at all times

a right which prima facie belongs to him


all

and under
all

circumstances

and we are thus

accustomed to treat

forms, restrictions, and conditions,

which have been imposed upon the exercise of the right


of alienation, as so It
is

many

infringements of this natural right.


to

when we come matter that we find this


only

look into the history of the


reversed.

aspect

We
now

see
exists

then
has

that the general right of alienation which

been slowly and painfully gained.

It

has been concluded

by

inquirers

that, in

its all
;

earlier

form, ownership was not

individual ownership at

that ownership was not vested in


in other words, that it

individuals but in families

was

(as

we

should

now

say) corporate

and not

sole

and

alienation,

which was under such circumstances of course


if

difiicult,

was,

not altogether unknown, at least very


517.

rare.

Intervenp'ubirc

Even long

after individual ownership

had come

to

^^ recognised, the right of the individual


' '

owner was not

relation back as it is called. The transactions which have taken place between the time when the owner lost possession and that when he parts with his ownership by receiving compensation are treated in the same way as they would have been treated if the ownership and possession had been parted with simultaneously. But this kind of restitution becomes very complicated when the transactions are numerous. 1 Maine's Ancient Law, iirst ed., pp. 258 sqq.

Sec. srg-Sr;.]

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.
extend
to

249
will

considered to
pleasure.

alienation
or

at

his

own

and
state,

Either the family,

the tribe, or the

must consent to the


tual^.

alienation in order to render it effec-

This idea

is

traceable in the

two most important


In the maneipatio
actual
parties

forms of transfer under the


five witnesses

Roman
is,

law.

were required This number

besides

the

to

the transaction.

I think, not to be referred


^,

to the imperfection of oral testimony

but to the requirement

that the transfer should take place in the presence of and be


consented to by the community at large,
persons

whom

these five

may
cessio,

be taken to represent^-

So in the case of

injure

or transfer under judicial cognizance, I scarcely


is

think the transaction

to

be explained solely upon the


procedure *
attached
;

ground of laxity of
act to which

judicial

it

was a public
as
it

superior

validity

just

now
^)

attaches to the judicial transfer (gerichtliche Auflassung


of

modern German

law.

And

the consent of the state, in


tribe

which the consent of the family and that of the


probably merged,
in
private
their
still

have

plays a part, though a small one,


It
is

transfers.

asserted
still

by German lawyers
holds fast to the old

that
'

law to some extent

The author of the Mitacshara speaks of the consent of townsmen, of kinsmen, of neighboui's, and of heirs, to a transfer of land but apparently he considers that the only consent really indispensable is that of the
;

parties actually interested in the property ;

Mitacshara, chap.
(see

i.

sect.

i.

verse 31.

This treatise

is

perhaps a thousand years old

the Preface
of lingering

to Colebrooke's Translation),

and

it is

evident that a

number

traditions just then becoming obsolete are here alluded to.


^ '

See Maine's Ancient Law,

first ed., p. 204.

Like the panchayat or assembly of five in India. * See Maine's' Ancient Law, first ed., p. 289. The notions upon which our Fine and Recovery are founded are different. These were in fact two wholly distinct proceedings, each being based on a suit, but in the former
the suit was compromised by the parties, whilst in the latter it was carried on to judgment. Both were simultaneously resorted to, in order to give

They combine a variety of warranty, and finality of judicial decision ; and they have been helped out by statute. The general assertion that common recoveries are due to the decision in Taltarum's case is not borne out by
a complete
title
;

their effects being different.

principles

limitation,

the report in the Year Book, 12 Edw. IV. chap. ^ AUgemeines Landrecht, Part i. tit. 10.

19.

250

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.

[Chap. XII.

principle that

every claim to land, to be valid, must


public authority
*

be

recognised

by

and we

shall see hereafter


^.

that the French law exhibits a remnant of the same idea

Modern
signifi-

518.
require

The

real significance, however, of institutions

which

cance of
public intervention.

external

consent to the transfer of land has


it is

now
it is,

changed.

Though

agreed to be desirable that property

of all kinds should be transferable without impediment,


at the

same time, perceived to .be of

first-rate

importance that
It
is

such transfers should be certain and notorious.

in order

to secure this certainty and notoriety in the case of land that

the nations of the continent retain as a requirement the


interference of
Certainty

some public authority.


which have been
felt

519.

The

difficulties

about securing

and notoriety.

the certainty and

notoriety of transfers of property would

have been much

less

had the ownership of property usually


it.

remained unseparated from the possession of


the case of wrongdoers and intruders

Except in

we should then have


But,
is

been able to see at once to


as

whom
The

a thing belonged.

we know, the tendency

of legal development

to separate of

ownership from possession.

question

is

therefore

constantly increasing importance, -can the ownership be transferred without a transfer of possession
?

Eoman
law
re-

520. Fixing our attention for a


law, we can hardly doubt that at

moment on

the

Roman

quired
delivery.

first,

in order to complete in all cases that the

a transfer of ownership,

it

was necessary

actual possession should be transferred from the transferor to

the transferee, simply because ownership without possession

was not a

legally recognised situation.

If it occurred

it

was

by accident or wrong, and was a defective condition


remedied as soon as possible.
to a

to be

What more was


Some
;

necessary

change of ownership than a change of possession dethings, as for

pended upon circumstances.


1

example

Pr.-B.

d. Deutsch. Pr.-R. 89 Dernburg, Lehrb. d. Preuss. 240 Bluhme, Encyclopadie, sect. 190. Bluhme speaks of judicial cognizance as taking the place of delivery; but it also takes the place of

Gerber, Syst.

the consent of the community, and makes the transaction a public act.
2

Pothier, (Euvres, vol.

ix. p.

425, ed.

Bugnet

infra, sect. 529.

Sec.

518-523O

ACQUISITION OF OWNEESHIP.

251

the res nee mancipi, could be transferred by the mere agree-

ment by a

of the

parties

followed by tradition.

Other things

could only be transferred


special procedure.

when

the transfer was carried out

621.

The

original object of this procedure as well as that of

tradition was, undoubtedly, to accomplish the transfer, which,


it

was supposed, could not be accomplished without


simpler means of accomplishing
it

it.

But,

as

this

object

suggested
acts

themselves, then

was probably seen that the


served

which

accompanied

a transfer

another purpose.

It

was

probably perceived that, besides accomplishing the transfer,

which might now be accomplished otherwise, they served as


formalities

which were useful for the

purpose of

giving

notoriety and certainty to the transaction.

522.

The

possibility of a transfer of ownership

by arrange-

possession

ment between the parties unaccompanied by a transfer of had certainly occurred to the Roman lawyers,
it.

because they prohibited

When

it

first

occurred to them,
it

which probably was about the time when


hibited, I do not

was
I

first

pro',

know.

The
it is

prohibition occurs in the Code

and

it is

from thence that

usually quoted.

am

equally

unable to say when the idea of transferring ownership without transferring possession became familiar in modern law.

To some minds
has not held

it

can scarcely be said to be familiar

still ^.

523. There are


its

many

reasons

why

delivery of possession Reasons

transfer of ownership.

ground as a necessary condition to the Uvery not """ Its most strenuous supporters must ^

admit that there are many transactions in


'

modem

times

Codex

Just. 3. 2. 20.

ii. tit. i. sect. 239 (quoted by Austin, vol. ii. p. 997)1 solemnly declares it to be a universal maxim of law that t))ere can be no acquisition of ownership without tradition. He is refuted by Austin, ubi supra. An English lawyer, Mr. Serjeant Manning, has made a similar assertion (Manning and Eyland's Eeports, vol. ii. p. 568 note) and he has been answered by Mr. Justice Blackburn (Contract of Sale, p. 189),

Heineccius, Book

These refutations are interesting and instructive, but they were really not necessary for, as the Hindoo lawyers say, a fact is stronger than a hundred texts.'
; '

252
to

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.
which the condition of delivery
it is

[Chap. XII.

unsuitable;

and to

restore
it

we

should have to revert to a simplicity which

would now be found impossible to maintain.


it
is

Moreover,
that
all

the rapidity with which


business
process
possible.

generally

desired

should be
of

transacted would render the


delivery intolerable, even
or

cumbrous
it

actual

where

was

Whether

no mankind has, upon the whole,

gained or lost by the abandonment of delivery as a condition


to the transfer of ownership
is

not, of course, a question to be

considered here.

At any

rate the

change

is

one which has

been very widely accepted. 524. It


is

by no means an easy thing

to give even the


different

most general idea of the course which the laws of


of the transfer of

countries have taken upon the subject of delivery as a condition

ownership
if

and yet some such general


are not to look

survey

is

almost necessary

we

upon our own

law

as something merely arbitrary

and

accidental.

One thing

can be affirmed generally

that a broad

line of distinction is

everywhere drawn between the transfer of moveables and that


of immoveables
;

though of course

this distinction is a post-

Roman
Delivery still important.

one.
is

525. It
sition,

also desirable to

remember, as a general propo-

that though modern systems of law do not generally


delivery a necessary condition to the transfer of property,
is
still

make

delivery of possession
in such transactions.

a matter of very great

moment

It

is

a large step in legal ideas, and

one fraught with consequences of the highest importance, to


establish clearly that,
if

sell

property to you, the property


is

becomes yours immediately the contract

concluded;

that

you not only have a right to obtain the ownership, but that
the ownership
is

actually obtained.

But, notwithstanding
so obtained

this, it is well to
is,

remember that the ownership

as compared to ownership accompanied

by the

possession,

of a very risky kind.


Precarititle to

526. This

is

very conspicuous in the case of moveables,


easily transferred.

which are very irequently and very

For

Sec. 524-528.]

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.
sells

253
^'s moveables
posaea^'""^

example,

if

a horse to

i?,

the horse

may become

though he remains in A's

stable,

and

has never been near


of law
it

him during
if

the transaction.
sells
if

But under some systems

subsequently
faith,

the horse to C, and


takes the horse

C
it

purchases

in

good

then

away
this

becomes the

property of C.
527.

The general
is

principle

upon which

and numberless

similar eases rest

that the transactions of life could hardly


it

be carried on,

if,

in the case of moveables,

was not

safe to

deal with the person in possession on the hypothesis that he

was the owner.


flicting ideas
;

But

it is

obvious that

we have

here two con-

and by the concessions made

to both

we almost

seem to take away with one hand the ownership conferred by


the other
:

in other words, without delivery

we

give an owner-

ship, but one

which
all.

is

so precarious that it scarcely

seems to

be ownership at

528. This appears most strongly in the condition of the French

French law, where there

is

an actual controversy as to whether


ownership
is

to sale

by a
Code
is

sale without delivery the

transferred, though,
lies.

T^fJ^grv

I confess, I cannot doubt on which side the truth

The

Civil says in express terms that, as soon as a bargain

concluded, without anything more, the ownership passes.


it also

But
is

recognises in a very large and general

way

the

preferential title of a person

who is

in possession over one

who

not

so that ownership
is

which has been acquired without


French law.
Thereupon

delivery
it

especially risky under the

has been maintained that until delivery has been made the
is

ownership
it is

not transferred at

all

or

what

is

worse
it is

still,

that

transferred or not transferred according as

the

seller

or an honest third party to

who

raises the contention.

It seems

me

clear that those


is

commentators are right who maintain


;

that the ownership

transferred

a result fraught with con-

sequences of the most important and beneficial kind, which

would be greatly impaired


the transfer.

if

any doubt were thrown upon


must remember that these

But the

transferee

are advantages which he can only fully enjoy

when he

is

254

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.

[Chap. XII.

dealing with persons in

whom

he has

full confidence.
is

In

dealing with a suspected person the only safe course


possession ^
Delivery
of land,

to get

529.

With

regard to land the development of the law has


different.

been somewhat
land
is

In the

first

place, the delivery of

not the same thing exactly as delivery of moveables.

Moveables can be placed under lock and key.


of

Land,

if it is

any

extent,

and

still

more

if it is

unenclosed, cannot be

placed entirely under the control of the intended possessor

and the possession cannot


notoriety
is

easily be

one of the very things which

made notorious. we desire to

Now
secure,

and delivery in order to give notoriety


be something more than nominal.

to the transfer

must

On

the other hand, another

and a very simple and convenient method has been hit upon
of giving notoriety and exactness to the transfer of land
Publicity
rally se-

without troubling ourselves about possession.

This

may

be

described as the insertion in a book kept at a public office


Qa]ig(j

cured by
registration.

^ register of an account of the transaction between the

parties
is

by which the transfer takes place; which account


It
generally in fact a copy of the instrument

acknowledged by the parties before a public


is

insinuaiio; correct.

the origin
of registration.

executed between the parties themselves.

...
to

ofiieer to

be

The

practice

of

inscribing a copy of private documents in a public register

seems to have been originally introduced by the Emperor

Leo

in reference to gifts ^;
heirs

the object being,

it

is

said, to

enable
'

to

ascertain

what claims the


p.

estate

was

See Austin's Lectures (3rd ed.),


if I

1003.

It will
:

perhaps be con-

venient

quote some passages of the French Code Art. 11 38, 'Elle (I'obligation de livrer la chose) rend le cr^aneier propriStaire encore que la tradition n'en ait point 6t6 faite ;' Art. 1383, 'eelle (la vente) est
.
.

parfaite entre les parties, et la preprints est acquise de droit a I'acheteur

h I'^gard

du vendeur, d6s qu'ou

est

convenu de
le

la chose et

du

prix,

quoique
'

la chose n'ait

pas encore iti livr^e, ni

prix pay6

;'

Art. 1141,

si la chose qu'on s'est oblige de donner ou de livrer a deux personnes successivement est purement mobilifere, celle des deux qui en a 6t6 mise

en possession

rfielle est pr^fSree et en demeure proprifitaire, encore que sou titre soit posterieur en date, pourvu toutefois que la possession soit de bonne foi.' See the observations of M. MarcadS on these articles.
^

Codex

Just.

Book

viii. tit. 54. sect. 30.

Sec. 529-531.]

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.
whether to accept the inheritance.
insinuatio,

255

liable before deciding

The
it

proceeding'

was

called

and under that name


to the time of the

survived in the French law


Civil
1.

down

Code

530. The requirement of registration thus established in Extended


reference to gifts seems
to have been applied
in the next to pledges
*''^"^'

instance to

the pledge of land.

The reason

of this

was

|^^^

obviously in order to supply the publicity which was wanting


in a pledge
;

this being a transaction to

which delivery was

earliest resolved

not to be suitable.
sale^

But a pledge always


find that rules of

contemplates a possible
sales are

and consequently pledges and


:

very closely connected

whence we

registration are frequently extended


also
;

from pledges

to sales

and

in fact to all dealings with land whatsoever. of registration

531.

The law

on the continent of Europe

Notary.

can hardly be comprehended, even generally, without advertence to an


officer scarcely

known

in

England
I
is

in connexion

with land, but who in other countries plays a very important


part in
all

transactions of business

mean

the notary, or
all

notary public^.

The

resort,

which

had upon almost

occasions in France and Italy to a notary to draw up the

documents relating to any business in hand,


partly based on the
prevailed
rigid

is

no doubt

adherence to forms, which has


legal

in countries where the It


is

systems are based

upon the Roman law.

also

partly based upon the

immense convenience which

results to the parties


;

from the

credit which attaches to a notarial transaction

such a transuntil

action being always presumed to be valid


it

and binding,

has been impeached and set aside by a separate proceeding

instituted for that purpose.

But

it

would be

incorrect to Notarial

consider the notary as the

mere private agent

of the parties, tions are


P"^''"

or merely as a person of superior fidelity.


1

Under the French

Pothier, CEiivres, vol.

i.

p.

364

ed.

Bugnet.

'

The Latin term 'which appears to correspond most nearly with notary in the modern sense is tabellio. For an account of the many
'
'

changes in the nature of the ofSce of notary, see Savigny, Geschichte des

Romischen Eechts, chap.

2. sect.

16

chap.

6. sect.

140.

256

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.
is

[Chap. XII.

law the notary


is

clearly a public officer,

and

his intervention

looked upon as the intervention of the


its officer ratifies

public authority^

which through
Transcrip-

the transaction.

532. In France

all

documents executed in the presence of


reference to the creation or transfer of
register,

a notary having any

an interest in land are transcribed by him in a public

which register

is

most carefully kept and

is

rendered as far as

possible available for general information^.

German

533. In

Germany the

transfer of ownership in land

is

strictly judicial proceeding.

The

private transaction between


is

the

parties

which leads them to desire the transfer


to the court for a transfer

not
is

noticed.

They apply

and that

enough.

This application assented to by the court forms

one stage in the proceedings (Auflassung), and the other


is

the entry of the transferee's


^.

name on

the register (Ein-

tragung)
No
regis-

534. There

is

scarcely

any

registration of the kinds above

necessary

described in England.

The
nor

registries of

Middlesex and York-

land fn" England,

shire do not furnish a complete record of the transactions

which

affect the land

is

a registered transferee ever safe

against subsequent transactions.

In Ireland registration
is

is

more

effectual

but even there registration


:

not essential to
is

the validity of a transfer

all

that the law says

that a regis-

'

The following references may be


is

useful,

if

more information
is

is

desired upon this subject than

given in the above slight sketch.


the transcription of gifts

The
inter

transcription of pledges at the Bureau des Hypothfeques

provided for

in France by the Code Civil, art. 2146


vivos

documents relating to land when executed privately (sows signature prime) is required by the Loi du 22 frim. an xi. The general regulations as to the ofiice and duty of a notary are contained in the Loi du 25 vent, an xi. See the Italian Civil Code, art. 1315 sqq., Dell' atto pubblico, and art. 3. 1932 sqq., Delia trascrizione.
art. 939.

by

The

registration of all

' See the German Burgerliches Gesetzbuch, 873, 899, and KOnne, Staatsrecht der Preussischen Monarchie, sect. 362 (Grundbuch und Hypo-

and the rules relating to the office and duty of notary, See also Dernburg, Lehrb. d. Preuss. Pr.-K. vol. i. 5 193, 240. The transfer of land by fine and recovery in England and the statute of enrolments has some resemblance to the transfer by judicial act of continental law.
thekenwesen)
s.
;

364.

Sec. 532-635.]

ACQUISITION OP OWNERSHIP.
is

257

tered transfer

to

be preferred to an unregistered one^.

The subject of registration has been much discussed in England during the last thirty years, and more than one
attempt to establish a system of registration has been made
without
success.

The doubts and complications which

sur-

round

titles to

land in England are so appalling that Parlia-

ment has never yet dared to make registration compulsory, and many persons think that until titles have been simplified
it

never will ^1
535. Whilst, however, in England

we have no

record of the

history of transactions relating to the ownership of land in

the public archives, that record


to of

is

generally found to exist

some extent

in

certain

documents which every owner


almost
universal
length,

land possesses.

It

is

the

custom to

narrate in private

documents, at great

and with
affect the

very frequent repetition, the history of transactions relating


to landed property
;

and many other events which


and

ownership besides actual transfers are there stated, such as

mortgages,

trusts, marriages, deaths,

so forth.

All the

documents containing this narrative are carefully preserved,

and form what are and unless


either

called the

'

title

deeds

'

of the property

this narrative is

tolerably complete,

and can be

handed over

to the purchaser or rendered otherwise

accessible to him,

it is

scarcely possible to take land into the

market at
is

all

^.

And

the protection afforded by this practice Use


is

of

in

some respects analogous to that which


Claimants

afforded in as a pro-

other countries by registration.

who do

not appear ^^^^.

upon

this private record are not absolutely excluded.

Neverof

cliasers.

theless, if after the

most thorough and careful examination


of great skill

this record
1

by persons

and experience, there be

Report on Registration of Title, 1857, p. 15 ; Second Report of Real Property Commissioners, p. 35. ' See the provisions of the Land Transfer Acts of 1875 and 1897 on this subject. The latter act has only been applied to a very small area, and
there does not seem to be any probability of its being extended. ' An owner who brought his land to market without deeds would be

looked upon with suspicion


p. 438.

Sugden, Vendors and Purchasers, 14th

ed.,

258
still

ACQUISITION OF OWNEESHIP,
any claim
to or

[Chap. XII.

upon the property which, has not been


will, at least if

discovered

by the purchaserj he

he has actually
it.

got into possession, very probably be protected against

But
buy

if

he has, or might have had by due dibgenee, what

is

called notice of the claim,


off

he must give up the property or

the claimant.

536.

On

the other hand, the very act of bringing together


all in

every transaction relating to land and placing them

a lump under the eye of the proposed transferee

is

in one

respect a positive disadvantage, at least in England.

For in

England the transactions


so

of landowners with their land are

numerous and complicated, the powers of disposition are so


involves

wide, and the interests in land are so various, that even with

a complete history of the property before you,

it

a very long, troublesome, and expensive inquiry to ascertain

whether as a result of
transferor

all

these

numerous transactions the


title

has

or has

not a good
proposes.

to

deal with the

property in the
transactions

way he

There are

many
to

of these

which

have

long
;

ago

ceased

have

any

operation upon the property

but of course a careful person

will desire to assure himself that this is the case,


is

and

this

a very costly operation.

of this quasi-registration in

The small advantages, therefore, England are balanced by serious

disadvantages.

537.

The matter

is

mixed up with the complications


Suppose

arising out of the

competing systems of law and equity.

This I can best illustrate by an example.


to sell his land to

agrees
:

but does not execute a conveyance


sell

and
does
:

he afterwards agrees to
execute a conveyance to
C.

the same land to


is

C and
But

the legal owner of the land

and
been
will,

mtist sue

for his breach of contract.


:

has

all

along the equitable owner

this equitable

ownership

however, be annihilated upon the conveyance being made

to C, provided that

C was

not aware of the sale to B.

If

was aware
and the

of the sale to

B
is

then

Cs

ownership

is

annihilated,

real

ownership

maintained in B.

Hence the

Sec. 536-538.]

ACQUISITION OP OWNERSHIP.

259

very ignorance of
tection
1.

C may

be that which furnishes his pro-

538. It will be seen from what I have said in the last three

Notice.

paragraphs that the doctrine of notice plays a very important


part in the transfer of ownership of land.
is

This doctrine

founded, no doubt, on a perfectly correct and just principle.

For some purposes and to some extent the apparent owner


of property

must be treated

as the real owner,

and whilst

our law allows almost unlimited freedom in the creation


of rights over things,

and has almost wholly abolished

or

declined to adopt the rules which require that the creation of

such rights should be completed by some public and


it is

notorious act,

only natural that

it

should protect those

who have

purchased in good faith from persons


all

who

are

believed to be, and have

the appearance of being, owners.


that other

But purchasers who know when they purchase


claim to this protection and the law does not give

persons lay claim to the property have not the same moral
it

to them.

From But it has been

this point of

view the doctrine of notice

is

defensible.

carried to a very great length in the English


It has

Court of Chancery.

of late years been applied to


;

equitable claims on personal estate


faith or diligence has

and the question of good


into the background^.
is

somewhat receded

The main
been

objection to the doctrine of notice

that

it

has Cannot be

so interpreted

by the

courts as to have been brought into defined,

a condition in which we find technicality combined with cumbrousness and extreme indefiniteness.
signifies

It

no longer merely
this,

knowledge.

It

means something more than

but

Hence the endeavours used by conveyancers to 'keep off' from their transactions which might give rise to troublesome inquiries. Sometimes vendors protect themselves by special stipulations against the necessity of satisfying these inquiries, and recent legislation has facilitated
1

title

the obtaining this protection.


2 See the judgment of Lord Macnaghten in the case of Ward against Buncombe, Law Reports, Appeal Cases, 1893, p. 383. One of the strangest ideas ever broached was that by the equitable doctrine of notice the trustees of property became a sort of register of the claims against the
'

'

property

ib. p.

393.
S

260

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.
tell.

[Chap. XII.

what more no man can


notice in law.

It

is

described sometimes as con-

structive notice; sometimes as implied notice; sometimes as

An

experienced conveyancer could, indeed, in


fair guess

most

eases,

make a very

whether the Courts of

Chancery would treat a thing as notice or not.

But

for

a private person to attempt to form an opinion upon this point

would be highly dangerous, and the attempt


as to Great exinvestigat-

to instruct people

what

notice

is

by giving a description
i.

of

it

has been
transto be

given Up as hopeless

actions relating to landed property in

The consequence is that all England have


of

ing

title,

conducted

by

several

sets

very highly

qualified,
;

and

therefore of course also very highly paid experts

and the

most

difiicult

and

intricate inquiries

have to be made on every

occasion that any such transaction takes place.

The enormous
alienation of

expense

and cumbrousness

of

such transactions no doubt

operate very extensively as a check

upon the

landed property ^Difficultto

539. I do not profess that this

is

at all a complete stateis

law of
transfer,

ment

of the

law of England on this subject, which


;

of

extraordinary complication
large licence

partly on account of the very


it

allowed to

owners of property in loading

with

trusts,

and in making posthumous and substitutional


;

disiDOsitions of it

partly because our law has not been

made
least,

on any plan, and has been allowed, to some extent at


to

grow out

of selfishness

and caprice ; but

chiefly

on account

of the conflict (not yet at

an end) between courts of law


recognising one person as

and of equity

one

set of courts

owner, the other set of courts recognising another person


as owner, of the

same property at the same time, and under


;

the same circumstances

and each

set of courts persistently

Sugden, Vendors and Purchasers, p. 781, 14th ed. The recent acts relating to the conveyance of land have prepared the way for an extensive simplification of the law, but that simplification remains still to be made. The scheme of the framers of these acts seems to be to make the law easier to work upon the old principles a considerable boon, no doubt but all that is required cannot be obtained by working upon the old lines, and merely improving the old machinery.
^ ^
: ;

Sec. 539-54I-]

ACQUISITION OP OWNERSHIP.
:

261
for

keeping out of view that which the other recognises

which reason no proposition about the transfer


to

of ownership
aflEirmed

can be stated very accurately, and at the same time


be generally true.

But what

have said

may

serve

to give the student

some notion of the point


dealt with

of view

from

which the matter


540. It
is

is

by English lawyers.
Bills of

observable that whilst the English law has not

adopted any general system of registration in respect of


land, the possession
registration
is

of

sales

of

personal property,
is

not taken by the transferee,


is,

necessary.

when The

registration

however, necessary in this

case,

not in order

that the ownership

may

pass to the transferee, but in order

to prevent the transferee being

deprived of the ownership

which he has acquired.

This annulment of the transferee's

ownership can only be demanded on behalf of the creditors


of

an insolvent transferor

the principle of the act being that


is

a transfer made under such circumstances

not void, but

presumably fraudulent.
541.

The

effect

of the

omission of the formality

is,

Eflfect

of

think, in this case clear.

The ownership
it is

is

in the transferee oftbrmali*'^^-

without registration, and


is

not affected until the transfer


there are other cases in which
is

impeached by a

creditor.

But

it is

doubtful whether a formality, which

clearly neces-

sary to

make a

title

unimpeachable,

is

also to

be considered
the ownership

as a condition

which must be

fulfilled before
it will

can pass.

doubt of this kind has,

be remembered,
;

arisen with regard to tradition under French law

and the
to

same doubt has arisen in Germany with regard

the

position of persons who, from no fault of their own, have

not got their names upon the register, but have got into
possession
^.

In England a person to

whom

complete

conveyance had not been made, but who was entitled to

demand
in
this,

it,

would be looked upon as equitable owner, which

in all essential particulars differs only

from legal ownership

that
1

it

is

liable

to

be defeated by a subsequent
d. Pr.-E. vol.
i.

See Dernbui-g, Lehrb.

240.

262

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.

[Chap. XII.

purchaser for valuable consideration without notice

who has
of transis

got the legal


Rules as to
transfers,

estate.
is

542. There

a set of rules affecting the

mode

ferring ownership and other rights over things which

based

upon a principle

distinct

from that of securing publicity,


These are rules which
litigation

but which also works to that end.


are

primarily intended to

prevent

by securing

facility of proof.

Every

transfer of ownership in the nature

of a sale or gift, involves a contract

which

may
is

be coin-

cident with

the transfer of ownership, but


it

very often
sale

separated from

by an

interval of time.
less frequently,

Moreover a

very frequently, and a gift


plicated
transaction.

may

be a com-

The exact extent


reserved,

of

the ownership
;

transferred very often has to be scrupulously defined

certain

jura

in

re
is

are

frequently

and the transaction


is

generally

not a mere transfer of a simple right, but

accompanied by covenants, agreements, and conditions be-

tween the

parties,

giving

rise to

a variety of rights in

rem

and

in

personam.

Unless, therefore, the sale be of articles of


is

immediate consumption, the possession of which


transferred,

at once

and the

price paid, the terms of the contract

may

come

into question

some considerable time


regard, therefore, to

after

it

has been

When

concluded.

Having

the fallibility of

necessary, oral

testimony as to past transactions, the parties to the

transfer are in

many

cases required

by the law

to put their

intentions into writing, so as to avoid the endless disputes,

and even fraud and perjury, which would inevitably


important transactions were entrusted
witnesses.
to

arise if

the

memory

of

Thus the Statute

of

Frauds in England, as a
all

general rule, requires a writing in

transactions relating

to land, or to goods valued at over ten pounds.


it is

In Prussia

required in all contracts of the value of seven pounds


all

ten shillings 1; in France in


six

contracts

of the value of

pounds
'

^.

But
;

as soon as a transaction has been recorded


i. tit.

Fifty thalers

Allgeraeines Landreoht, Part


fifty francs
;

v. sect. 131.

One hundred and

Code

Civil, art. 1341.

Sec. 542-544-]

ACQUISITION OF OWNERSHIP.

263

in writing
if it

it is

much more
of

likely to

become notorious than


writing

had passed by word


Sometimes

mouth

only.

543.
also

other

solemnities

besides

but other
ties be^^'^.^^

intended to secure facility of proof have been made


'

necessary to an efiEectual
contains

sale.

The Prench

law, for example,


.

writing.

some very minute and irksome


signing and
of writing

provisions

as

to

the form of

drawing up contracts^.

And
it

before the art

was

as

well

known

as

is

noWj instead of a writing some other formalities were in


use in order to

make

the intention clear^ and to impress

the transaction on the

memory
the

of

the parties the

such as
of

shaking

of

hands, nodding

head,

repetition
so

certain formulae, giving of earnest money, and

forth.

Some

of these forms
is

still

linger in the habits of the people.


Diatinc-

644. There

an important distinction between the two


which I have above referred
to.

classes of ceremonies

For
class,

t^gen^'

whereas omission of ceremonies of the first-mentioned

'^

such as delivery or registration, usually only affects


validity of the transaction as regards third parties

proof and the other


is

that

to say, it affects only the transfer of the ownership or right

in rem, but not the creation of the obligation or right in

personam.

the omission
This
is

of those of the last-mentioned class

affects the validity of it as regards the parties to the trans-

action

itself.

a consequence of the
Facility of proof
is

political origin of

the two sets of rules.

as

much

required

between

the actual parties to the transaction as


:

where third

parties are concerned


parties,

whereas publicity only concerns third

and the

rules

which ensure

it

therefore only
It
is

come

into play

when

third parties

come forward.

for this

reason that the two sets of ceremonies must be kept apart.

In point of

fact,

however,

all

the rules as to solemnities do

co-operate in enforcing both the objects mentioned above;


all of

them tend

to

make

the transaction public

all of

them

assist in facilitating proof.


1

Loi du 25 Tent, an

xi. sect.

Roger et
^

Soel,

Codes et

lois usuelles,
sect. 80.

p. 5.J4.

Bluhme, Encyclopadie,

CHAPTEE

XIII.

ON PRESCRIPTION.
Acquisition of rights by time.
if

545. In nearly every system of law


a person has been in
possession of

it

is

recognised that,

things or in

the

enjoyment of a jus in re aliena for a considerable time, defects


in his title or in his

manner

of acquiring ownership are cured.


;

Sometimes

all
:

these defects are cured

at other times

some of

them only
others.

and some defects are more quickly cured than


to be found in

How
justified.

546. The justification of this institution

is

the inconvenience and hardship of disturbing a possession

which has been long enjoyed,

Roman
law.

547. In the

Roman law we
It

find at a very early date this


called usiis or nsucapio.

principle acknowledged.

was there
it

By

the law of the Twelve Tables

was ordered,

'

usus au'

ctoritas fundi biennium, ceterarum

rerum annuus

esto.'

Usus '

here signifies possession, and


acquire ownership of a thing

'

rem usu capere ' signifies to by possession '. In the early

Roman

law ownership was acquired after two years in the

case of land; and in one year in other cases.


this effect the possession

But to have must have been acquired on a justa


English lawyer would translate
also

causa, which, I
'

think, an
right,'

under colour of
:

and the possessor must

have were

acted bona fide


defects in the
as

so that really the only defects cured

manner

of acquiring ownership

defects of form,

we

say,

and not defects of substance ^.

^ The principle by which under some systems of law ownership is made in the case of moveables to follow possession independently of usucapio (supra, s. 507 sqq.) was, I believe, unknown to the Roman law. As a general statement this is, I believe, true; but there was in
'^

certain special cases usucapio

which cured the graver defects


'

of title,

and

which, on that account, was called

lucrativa.'

ON PRESCRIPTION.
548. The rules of

265

Roman law

relating to the acquisition of Eecast by

ownership by prescription varied from time to time.

They
it,

were recast by Justinian, and in

this process, or soon after


it
is

a change of name was efEected which


understand, but to explain which I must
of

important to

first

go a

little

out

my way

to notice another institution.

549. Side by side with the usucapio, and at


closely connected

many

points Rules of
J'n'^Ro^^an
l^"^-

with

it,

was a

rule

which simply said that


it

persons

who sought

the protection of the law must seek

within a certain prescribed period after the cause of complaint

had

arisen.

There were

many

cases

in

which a person
it

against

whom
it

a claim was asserted could meet

by simply
of

saying that

was asserted too

late.

This
'

plea

the

defendant was called by the

Roman
all

lawyers

praescriptio.'

The

first

general rule requiring


is

actions to be brought

within a specified time

found in the Theodosian Code,


it

which

fixes the

time at thirty years, but


^.

existed in par-

ticular cases

long before that time

550. It

is

plain that a plea that the claim

is

asserted too Effect of


^"

late (praescriptio) effects

some
If

of the objects

which are more ^;^

fully attained

by

usucapio.

has got into the possession


to recover the property, it

of the property of , and


will

S seeks

answer just as

well, in order to repel


late, as to

, to say that he
is

has made his claim too


transferred to
possession
difference
is

say that his ownership

by

lapse of time.

But

if

were out of

and the thing had got

into the possession of

C the

between usucapio and a simple plea that the action


late

brought too

becomes at once apparent.

If there has
is

been usucapio
to him.

can successfully sue C, but the plea

useless

551. It appears however that in


strictly speaking, could only

many

cases a person

who. Change
^^t^

in

have had the benefit of the plea

^pre-

that a suit against


too late,
'

him

to recover the property

was brought

scnption.

was allowed by the


4. 14.

prsetor to recover the property

Cod. Theod.
i.

Cod. Just.

vii. 39. 3.

Demburg,
d.

Syst. d. Preuss. Pr.s.

Eechts, vol.

163

Windsclieid, Lehrb.

Pandektenrechts,

105.

266

ON PRESCRIPTION.

[Chap. XIII.
it.

from a third person who had got possession of


tically, in all these eases

Prac-

the praetor gave to the party

who

had the plea the

benefit of usucapio,

though the ownership


between these two

thus given was only bonitary and not quiritary ownership.

But Justinian abolished the


possessor in a

distinction

kinds of ownership, and he also gave the ownership to the

good many cases where previously he would

only have had as a defence the plea that the action was

brought too late; and partly perhaps for this reason, and
partly also because there

was some confusion

as to the true

nature of the two institutions, the term usucapio was dropped


out of use by writers on the

Roman law

subsequent to the
This

Code, and the term prescription was applied to both.

has been continued down to the present day.

Thus
is

in France

and
to

Italy,

whether a

man

claims that ownership

transferred

him by

possession,

or whether he
is

defends himself
late,

on
said

the ground that the action


to rely on prescription.

brought too

he

is

In Germany the acquisition of ownercalled 'Ersitzung,^

ship

by
'

possession

is

and the bar to the


pre-

action

Verjahrung.^

We

use in

England the terms


latter.

scription for the former

and limitation for the

And

inasmuch as the two things are really different have the two names.
PreacripEnglisli

it is

better to

552. In England the word 'prescription'' (as defined by

Lord Coke)
scription

signifies

the acquisition of

title

by length

of

^^-

time and enjoyment.


of

This would serve as a general de-

usucapio,

but nevertheless we shall see that

the prescription of English law differs in some important


particulars

from both the usucapio of the


later.

earlier

Roman law

and the prescription of the


553.

As

regards the effect of time upon the right, there are

three positions to consider.

A right may either be transferred


if

by

possession, or
it

by non-claun,
denuded of
its

may may be
it

be barred by non-claim, and

barred

either extinguished altogether, or only

ordinary legal protection.


1

So at

least it is con-

Co. Litt. 113 b.

Sec. 552-555-]

ON PRESCRIPTION.
and many disputes have arisen
as to

267

sidered

by

jurists^

which

view in a given ease ought to be taken ^.


is

The

difference

not unimportant

for a right
is

may

be useful for some purIf,

poses, even

where

it

not enforceable by action.

for

example, the owner out of possession gets back peacefully into


possession,

and

his ownership has


is

been in the meantime transIf his

ferred

by

prescription, he

in possession wrongfully.

ownership has only been extinguished he


sion wrongfully,

may

not be in posses-

and he may be

in possession as owner,

though

possibly not of his old ownership.

If his former ownership

were not extinct, but only his action, he would be restored to


his old ownership with all the rights attaching thereto.

654. Nearly

all

English lawyers, led by Blackstone, lay

it Prescrip-

down
is

as a general rule that the acquisition of the ownership pjjg^ ^^

of land

by prescription
it is

is

unknown

to the English

law ^.

This

^^'^'^

not the language of either Littleton or Lord Coke, and I do


correct.

not think

No doubt the

form
:

of English legisla-

tion has generally been to bar the action

and the principle

of acquisition of ownership in land by possession has nowhere

been directly affirmed.


to

But such

acquisition appears always

have been, and

still

to be, possible.

555. The early method of legislation on the subject thus described by Lord Hale ^
:

The
'

is

Early
tion.

use was in England

to limit certain notable times within the compass of

which

those titles which


accrue.

men

designed to be relieved upon must

Thus

it

was done in the time of Henry III by the


8, at

Statute of Merton, cap.

which time the limitation in


I,

a writ of right was from the time of king Henry


that statute it
for
assizes
is

and by

reduced to the time of king Henry II, and

of mort d^ancestor they were thereby reduced

from the
assizes

last return of

king John out of Ireland, and for


a prima transfretatione regis in
this

of novel
. .

disseisin
.

Normanniam.
'

And

time
AUgem.
p. 12a.

of

limitation

was

also

See Unger, System


Blackstone,

d. Osterr. vol.
ii.

Pr.-R, vol.

ii.

p. 435.

2 2

Comm.

p. 264.

History of the

Common Law,

268

ON PRESCRIPTION.
Westm. I.
cap.

[Chap. XIII.

afterwards^ by the statutes of


cap. 2j 46, reduced unto a

39 and Westm. II.


1.'

narrow

scantlet^ the writ of right

being limited to the


Modern
'*"

first

coronation of king Richard

556. This practice of renewing from time to time the


periods of limitation for the recovery of land

fn

was afterwards

discontinued, and a general period of twenty years was fixed by the 32 Hen. VIII^ c. 2, and 21 Jac. I, c. 16. The law was amended by the 3 & 4 Will. IV^ c. 27, and the period was reduced to twelve years by 37 & 38 Vict. c. 57.
Possession

557.

Now

to understand the position of a person in posis

denceof
title.

session of land under these statutes it

necessary to bear in
title.

mind that
This
is

possession itself

is

presumptive evidence of

certainly so in English law.


itself

And
him

this presumption

would of

alone be sufficient both to protect the pos-

sessor against intruders,

and

to enable

to recover against
possession, were

any person who wrongfully deprived him of


it

not that

it

can be turned against himself.


else

For

if it

can
still,

be shown that some one


the presumption

was

in possession earlier

may

be that that person was the owner, and

this presumption the second possessor can only

meet by show-

ing that the ownership has really passed to himself ^.


Operation
of statutes.

558. But here the statutes come in and greatly assist the
party

who

has been long enough in possession to get the


Suppose, for example, that

benefit of them.

is

the owner

of land, of which

gets into possession and remains in pos-

session for twelve years,

and after that C gets into possession.

1 See and compare Doe v. Carter, Queen's Bench Reports, vol. ix. p. 863, and Doe v. Barnard, ib. vol. xiii. p. 945. See also Doe o. Cooke, Bingham's Reports, vol. vii. p. 346. Whatever may have been the case once, I think that in modern times possession of land is in itself merely evidence of title, the vchole effect of vrhich is done away with as between two rival claimants as soon as one of them shows that he was in prior possession. Of course even this gives the advantage of the presumption to a casual possessor, and this under some circumstances would be a temptation to lawlessness. But the casual possessor of land is in modern England a very rare person. In turbulent times and where law is weak it is necessary to give special protection to possession as against wrongdoers apart from title, as in India in the present day. See Code
'
'

of Criminal Procedui-e, chap.

xii.

Sec. 556-560.J

ON PRESCRIPTION.
can ask to have his
title
if

269

If

sues

C he

presumed as against
sets

C from

his prior possession.

And

up the

still

prior

possession of

he will be met by the statutes of limitation.


of limitation, after the necessary-

For the modern statutes


period has

elapsed, certainly extinguish A's title.

That

is

a settled point of English law.


fore,

The

title of

cannot, there-

be set up against B, and B's


is

title will

be impregnable.

559. This
years.

the case of one

man

[B) holding for twelve


property,

If several persons in succession hold the

then also after the lapse of twelve years A's


extinguished.

title will

be

But whether the person

actually in posses-

sion has an impregnable title would depend


stances.

upon circum-

If a period of twelve years could be

made up by
descent, will,
^-

successive possessors succeeding each other

by

or

conveyance, the last of such persons would be secure

No

presumption would

arise

from any previous possession

which would injure him.


necessary period
is

The doubtful case is where the made up by a succession of persons who

are strangers to each other, no one of for twelve years. to say

whom

has himself held


it is

This

is

a very rare case, and

not easy
setting

how

it is

provided for by English law.

But

aside this doubtful case, the statement that there can be


acquisition of ownership of land

no

by

prescription in English

law can hardly be maintained.


560.
subject
are

From the peculiar way in which has grown up m England certain

the law on this Bona fides


restrictions

which

causa,

elsewhere placed upon the acquisition of ownership


It
is

by

possession are neglected in the English law.

a general

rule of jurisprudence that neither bona fides nor justa causa

when the defendant pleads limitation as a bar But it is also a general rule of jurisprudence that when it is asserted that a title has been gained by prescription, then the judge ought to see how the party got
are in question to

an

action.

into

possession,

and ought not to allow a

title

to be acit

quired
1

dishonestly, or, at least,


v.

he ought not to allow

to be

See the case of Asher

Whiteloek,

Law

Eep., Q. B., vol.

i.

p. i.

270
acquired so soon.

ON PRESCBIPTION.
But

[Chap. XIII.

in the English law this distinction has

been to a great extent overlooked, probably because


not kept clearly distinct the principle of limitation
actions are barred,
titles are acquired.

we have
by which by which

and the

principle of prescription

Preacrip-

561.

As

regards moveables the question whether and

when

plie/to

the ownership of

them

is

transferred

by

prescription very

'^?"

seldom
all

arises, because,

whatever

may

be the form of action,

that the owner of moveables can, except in very rare eases,


is

obtain,

compensation for his

loss,

and not the goods


is

themselves in specie.

And this

claim for compensation


arise in

very

soon barred.
party to

The question might

practice if the

whom

the goods originally belonged got back into

possession, after all his remedies for the recovery of the goods

or their value
to decide

had been and

barred.

It

would then be necessary


the

whether his ownership had been extinguished, as in


it

the case of landj

would be somewhat strange

if

courts were to hold that the ownership of moveable property

remained,
of land

when under analogous circumstances


If
it

the ownership

was extinguished.

were considered that the


still

ownership of moveables was extinguished, there might


be a question,
cally this

who has

acquired the ownership

Practieffect of

would come back to the question of the


title,

possession as affording presumption of


case of land, possession of moveables
is

for, as in

the

presumptive evidence

of
Presorip-

title.

562. The acquisition by prescription of jura in re has, in

*^ English law, got into considerable confusion. pliedTo jura re quently, whenever questions arise upon this topic

Conseof law,

judges find themselves in serious


has, I think, arisen

difiiculties.

This confusion

from the principles which govern prescrip-

tion proper not having been distinguished

from the

principles

which govern another


also apply the

institution to

which English lawyers

kept

distinct.

name of prescription, but which ought to be The English law of prescription as applied

to the acquisition of jura in re aliena, besides covering the

Sec. 561-564.]

ON PRESCRIPTION
for a

271
definite

acquisition

by enjoyment

certain

time^ also

comprehends the acquisition by enjoyment from time immemorial.


cases

Now
distinct

the
:

principles

of acquisition

in the

two

are

and I

shall endeavour to

explain the

distinction.

563.

The

immemorial
present day

is it

...
It

acquisition of rights

by enjoyment from time Enjoymentfrom .. a principle of very wide application. At the time im' is by no means confined to the acquisition of
.

Ai

'

'

jura in re aliena.

is

even applied in public law.

Savigny
^.

gives an instance of this from the history of England

For

a considerable period after the Revolution of 1688

many

conscientious persons felt doubts as to the legality of the

existing government.

But before the death

of the last of the

Stuarts in 1806 those doubts had ceased.

This could not be

because the existing government had gained a right

by

ordinary prescription, for there could be none in such a case.

The
'

principle

which operated was that of acquisition by


is

time immemorial/ which

thus stated by Savigny

'When

a condition of things has lasted so long that the present


generation never

knew any

other,

and

their forefathers

knew
and

no

other,
is

then
so

it

must be assumed that

this condition of

things

bound up with the

convictions, feelings,

interests of the nation that it cannot be disturbed.'

Savigny

considers that in the

Roman law

the principle of time im-

memorial applied only to three kinds of rights viae vicinales; rights connected with the prevention of floods; and rights
connected with the supply of water.
it

He

seems to think that

was

as being matters of public concern that the principle of


rights.

time immemorial was applied to these


the

The notion

of

Roman

lawyers seems to have been that in regard to


if

a thing 'cujus memoriam vetustas excedit,'

the public

were interested in

it,

they ought to treat the case in the


it ^.

same way as
564.

if

a lex had authorised

As

regards the length of time which would be con- Length

sidered time
'

immemorial the common expression


d.

is

'

cujus con- requh-ed.

Savigny, Syst.

L. Pr.-R.

195.

lb. 196.

272
trarii

ON PRESCRIPTION.
non exstat memoria
^.'

[Chap. XIII.

The

'

contrarii

memoria seems
'

to

mean a
is

recollection of the time

when no such

right existed.

If there
right
is

memoria

of this,

any presumption

in favour of the

excluded.

And

the result of two passages in the


if

Digest upon the subject appears to be, that

any person
their

comes forward and can say, either from his own recollection
or from the information of others speaking
recollection, that the

from

own

thing was at one time

illegal,

the pre-

sumption will be excluded.


than
Presumption of
legal origin.

But more

ancient information
sufficient
".

this as to

any

illegality

would not be

565. There have not been wanting persons


that between acquisition

who

consider

by

prescription
is

and acquisition by

enjoyment from time immemorial there


of principle
:

no

real distinction
is

that the root of the acquisition in both cases


;

the long enjoyment


defects

and that

if

time immemorial cures any

which prescription does

not, that is only because in

the former case the enjoyment has lasted longer.

The

other
is

view

is,

that in the case of time immemorial there

no

acquisition of right, but only presumption in favour of the

legal origin of a right

which has been long enjoyed *.


is

The

two views

are entirely distinct, and the difference

of great

practical importance.

For

if

there be an assumption of a

legal origin, that assumption

may

be rebutted by the party

opposing the claim bringing evidence to show that the as-

sumption
Comparison

is

unfounded.

between
English

566. If we consider the English law we shall find that an English lawyer when he speaks of prescription is nearly

and

Eoman
law.

always thinking only of the acquisition of jura in re aliena, and having in his mind rights of this kind he frequently says
that our rules of prescription are derived from the
It has indeed been said, that the

Roman
'

law.

law of England as cited by


civil

Lord Coke from Bracton exactly agrees with the


1

law *,'

Savigny, Syst.

198.

An
(p).

equivalent, though

more general expression,

is 'vetustas,' ig6,
" *

note

and 206 ad Gale on Easements, p. 122.


lb. 199 (p. 517)

fin.

lb. 206.

Sec. 565-567.1

ON PRESCRIPTION.

273

by which
I

is

probably meant the Corpus Juris Romani as


it.

understood by the commentators upon

But

to this extent

am

unable to go.

I doubt whether the present law of

England on

this subject can be identified


;

with that laid down


is

by Bracton

or that laid

down by Bracton with what

called

the civil law.

I must

first

remark that Lord Coke, in the

passage referred to, misquotes Bracton.


acquisition of things incorporeal words

He

applies to the

which Bracton ex-

pressly limits to the discussion of the acquisition of things


corporeal
;

the acquisition of rights over things incorporeal

being reserved by Bracton for the following chapter, which


contains nothing directly bearing upon the subject of prescription
^.

Bracton, indeed, as far as I can discover, nowhere

treats directly of the acquisition

by

prescription of rights

other than ownership, except in the single case of

common

of

pasture

to

which passage Lord Coke


^-

also refers,

but which

again he does not correctly quote

567. Moreover, neither as regards corporeal things, nor as

regards incorporeal things


it,

(so far as

he treats of them), would

I believe, be safe to affirm that Bracton's rules of pre-

scription are identical, either with the strict

Roman

law, or

with any modification of

it,

which

may

at

any time have been

known

as civil law.

As

regards corporeal things, Bracton

ignores the distinction, so important in the

Roman
it,

law, and

never lost sight of by the commentators upon


possession which
is

between

founded on a just

title

and possession

^ Coke upon Littleton, fol. 113 b. The passage of Bracton to which Lord Coke refers is in book ii. chap. xxii. fol. 51 b. The words are, Dictum est in precedentibus, qualiter rerum corporalium dominia ex
'

titulo et justa causa acquirendi transferuntur per traditionem.

Nunc

autem dioendum qualiter transferuntur

sine titulo et traditione per

usueaptionem scilicet per longam, continuam, et pacificam possessionem, ex diuturno tempore et sine traditione.' The discussion relating to the acquisition of things incorporeal commences (as he tells us) in chapter xxiii. I have not overlooked the passage at the end of chapter xxii., where
Bracton undoubtedly speaks of easements, but only of their possession, which he certainly does not say will confer a title, and rather implies the contrai-y (' ita quod taliter utens sine brevi et judicio ejici non poterit '). 2 Bracton, book iv. chap, xxxviii. fol. 222 b.

274

ON PRESCRIPTION.
is

[Chap. XIII.

which

notj

contenting himself with the far less compre-

hensive requirements^ that the possession must be continuous

and peaceful^and

As

regards the acquisition of

incorporeal

things, the Rules of


times^

Roman law

varied so greatly at different

so greatly also in reference to different kinds of

rights, that

any general statement of identity would be most

Upon the cardinal point just referred to, I very much doubt whether here again Braeton did not rather reverse
hazardous.

than follow the


to in

Roman

law.

I doubt whether he

was prepared
not explicit

admit the acquisition by prescription of incorporeal things

any

ease without just title


:

^-

At any

rate he

is

on the point
case)

whereas the

Roman law

did (as an exceptional


special

admit such acquisition in respect of certain


^
;

rights

and the modern English law,


It
is

as

shaU show
it

presently, admits it generally.

therefore incorrect, as

seems to me, to identify the English law of prescription with


the rules laid

down by Braeton,

or the rules laid


or civil law.

down by
between

Braeton with those of the


Littleton's visw of

Roman

568.

If

we

desire to see clearly the connexion

time im- the Roman law and the English law in the matter of memorial, prescription as applied to jura in re aliena, we must, I think,

go
'

to a writer

who was
fol.

of far greater authority


51 b.

than Braeton *

Book

ii.

chap. xxii.

See the passage quoted above.


titulo et traditione,

He

says

expressly that ownership

may

be acquired sine

which he

opposes to ra
^

titulo el

justd causa.
;

I do not state this positively


to,

but

it is

remarkable that in the passage

above referred

where he speaks of the acquisition


he
says,
'

common

of pasture,

of the right of item [acquiritur] ex longo usu sine con-

stitutione [not sine titulo] cum pacifica possessione [not per pacifieam possessionem] continua et non interrupts,, ex scientiS. negligentia et patientia dominorum, non dice ballivorum, quia pro traditione accipiuntur.' I take Bracton's meaning to be this: 'Common of pasture is

acquired without any express intention to transfer

it

(see

Dii'ksen,

Manuale Latinitatis, s. v. Constitutio) by reason of long enjoyment coupled with quiet possession, continuous and uninterrupted, on account of the knowledge, negligence and endurance of the owners not of his

bailififs,

because these things stand in the place of delivery.' Reports in the time of James the First, p. 142.)
'

(See Croke's

Digest,
S. 170.

Book

viii. art. 5. sect. 10.

Coke's translation

is

as follows

But

they have said that

Sec. 568, 569.J

ON PRESCRIPTION.

275

Littleton while discoursing' of tenure in burgage goes off to

a discussion of customs^ and from that to a discussion of


prescription.

He

says that

title

by time immemorial and by by time immemorial


de pre-

prescription are all one in law, but he seems to have been in

doubt whether a
at

man

could

make a
il

title

common law
:

done thus

and he

states the opinion that this could be

'

lis ont dit

que

y auxy un auter

title

scription que fuit a la

common

ley devant aseun estatute de

limitation de briefe, &e.; et ceo fuit, lou

un custome, ou un
ont
dit,

usage, ou auter chose, ad este use de temps dont memorie des

homes ne curt a
le

le contrarie.
title

Et

ils

que

il

est
II

prove per
dirra

pleder

un

de prescription de custome.
este

que

tiel

custome ad

use de tempore cujus conexistit et ceo est

trarium memoria

hominum non
le

autant a
vie

dire quant tiel matter est plede que nul

home adonque en

ad oye otcun proofe a


a
le contrary.'

contrary ne avoit ascun conusans

This passage clearly has reference to the time

immemorial of the

Roman

law, and

it is

applied

by Littleton

to all sorts of rights (custome ou usage ou auter chose).

569.

Now

the doubt which

is

here expressed by Littleton, Remarks

and which he does not

resolve, as to

whether in his time

"l^^-J^:^'

the party in possession could set up enjoyment from time im-

memorial at common law,


resolved that in

is

of

no

interest.

It has long been

many

cases

he can do
this

so^:

Three things,

however,

are

remarkable

in

passage

(i)

Littleton

identifies prescription

and enjoyment from time immemorial;


title;

{%)
(3)

he says nothing about the presumption of a legal


he assumes that,
is also

if

there

is

any right arising out

of enjoy-

there
before

another

title of

prescription that was at the

any statute of limitation of writs, &c., and that a custom, or usage, or other thing hath been used for time whereof mind of man runneth not to the contrary. And they have said that this is proved by the pleading, where a man will plead a title of prescription of
custom.

common law it was when

He

shall

say that such custom hath

whereof the memory of

man runneth

been used from time not to the contrary, that is as

much
alive

as to say, when such a matter is pleaded, that no man then hath heard any proof to the contrary, nor hath no knowledge to the

contrary.
'

See the quotations in Viner's Abridgment, Prescription (M).

T 3

276

ON PRESCRIPTION.
at

[Chap. XIII.

ment from time immemorial

common
i.e.

\&w,

it is

the time

immemorial of the Roman law^


the contrary/ and that

'that no

man

then alive

hath heard proof to the contrary nor hath any knowledge to


it

has nothing to do with the reign of

Richard the
Modifica-

First.

570. The passage I have quoted from Littleton's Tenures


I believe, the key of the English law on the subject

Littleton's contains,
'^'''"'-

of prescription as
aliena.

applied to the acquisition of jura in re


lawyers,

The

English

following

Littleton,

have

adopted time immemorial as the basis of their law.

They

have also

(in this

respect not following Littleton, but very

likely acting with logical consistency) adopted the principle

that time immemorial


affords a

is

not a mode of acquisition but only

presumption of legal origin.

And

if

they had

adhered to the view that time


Littleton described
it,
it,

immemorial was such as

and as the

Roman

lawyers understood

there would have been no inconsiderable protection to the

party

who had been

in long enjoyment of a right


still

when

it

was

attacked.

There would

have been the danger that the

presumption of a legal origin might be rebutted, but this

would not be easy, and the immemorial


"

full benefit of

the presumption
so

would be acquired within a reasonable time,

long as

'

time

meant

'

within the recollection of those living,

and what they had heard from others speaking from their

own
the

recollection.'

571. This protection, however,

was greatly weakened by


in

suggestion which finds, I believe, no countenance

the earlier writers, that even

when applying

the

it must be held that nothing was beyond the which had happened since the time of Richard the Firsts Only a right which had existed as long as this, was considered

common law memory of man

to

be

entitled

to

the

presumption that

it

had a legal
long as this

origin;

and to prove that a right had existed


difiicult.

so

was extremely

I have not been able to discover


first

when

it

was that the judges


'

attached this meaning to

Viner's Abridgment, Prescription (M).

Sec. 570-573-J
'

ON PRESCRIPTION.
It

277

time immemorial/
it,

was impossible

in strictness to mainassisted

tain

and

later

on we

find that the judges

the

person in possession by admitting a presumption that a right

which had been enjoyed for a considerable period had been enjoyed from the i Ric. I, and they did what they could to
enforce this presumption^ but like
all

presumptions of the
it

kind

it

was

liable to be defeated,

and

in this case

was very

often easily defeated.

For example, if a man claimed a right of


his claim
it

way

to a house,

and he rested

upon proof that

it

had

been enjoyed for one hundred years,

would be defeated by

showing that the house

itself

had not existed for more than

two hundred
572. It
is,

years.

I think, certain that at one time this defective

Insuffi-

protection was the only protection afforded by English law to teetionf

persons

not

who had been in long enjoyment of rights, but could ^iig^'sl^ show how they came into existence. It was obviously
it

not only a very slender protection, but


as the time
First

was dwindling away,


therefore, to seek for

which had elapsed since the reign of Richard the


It

became longer.

was necessary,

some better means of


573.

protection.
ascertain, it

As

far as I can

seems to have been Modern

thought that any alteration

in the period of time

immemorial

^^^^

'

must be made by the

legislature.

It

was suggested by one


of

writer that as the time

for bringing a writ

right

was

limited to sixty years, time immemorial ought to be limited


to sixty years also
it
^.

The suggestion was

a good one as far as

went, but the hint was not taken by the legislature.

The
right

judges accordingly hit upon a

new plan. About


tell juries

the end of the

eighteenth century they began to

that

when a

had been enjoyed for twenty years they ought to presume from
that alone, without any inquiry as to whether the right had
lasted

from time immemorial, that there had been a modern


'^

lost grant.'

Of

course juries ought to presume this,

if

they
this

really believed that such a grant


is

had been made: but

not at

all

what the judges meant.


1

They meant the jury

See Viner's Abridgment, ubi supra.

278
to find that there
existence or no.

ON PRESCRIPTION.
was such a grant, whether they

[Chap. XIII.
believed in its

The object was laudable, but it was a most unsatisfactory method of accomplishing it. It was asking the jury to find an obvious untruth. It was, however, more
successful than one could expect,

and

juries generally did as

they were

told.

If they did not, the judges

had the courage


set aside the

I
Prescription Act.

ought perhaps to say the effrontery

to

verdict as against the evidence'^.

574.

On

the top of this clumsy, though not altogether


contrivance,
c.

ineffectual

came the Prescription Act, the

&

3 William IV.

71.

The
:

object of that act

is

declared

to be to shorten the period of prescription.

Strictly speaking

what

it

does

is

this

it

makes the presumption


an enjoyment of twenty

of a
years.

legal origin conclusive after

It does not

make the

prescription of the English


it

law any-

thing different from what

was

before.

It does not do

away with the presumption


even apply to
all

of a legal origin.

Nor

does

it

kinds of jura in re aliena, but only to

those mentioned in the act.

The
lost

protection of other rights

remains as before, and juries are

still

often gravely asked to

presume that grants have been


to have existed.

which no one believes ever

To what
oasea the act applies.

575.

The language
is

of the act has been severely criticised,


ill-worded, but if
effectual, for

and
it

it

certainly

somewhat obscure and


its

can be got to operate

operation

is

the

presumption of a legal origin would cure defects of every


description.

It

is,

therefore, of the first importance to con-

sider
effect

exactly
of the

when
act

the presumption

is

to

be made.
is,

The
that

combined with the previous law

^ See the observations on this practice in the First Report of the Keal Property Commissioners, p. 51. The judgment of Lord Bowen in Dalton V. Angus, Law Eep. Appeal Cases, vol. vi. p. 740, seems to open the

prospect of putting the presumption into a more reasonable shape. He suggests that it is no longer necessary for a jury to find that there was a modern grant which has been lost, but that it will be sufficient if they

enjoyment which had lasted twenty years had its origin in circumstances sufficient in law or in equity to create the right, without saying what those circumstances were.
find that the

Sec. 574-577.]

ON PEESCEIPTION.
is

279

the presumption

to be

made, whenever the right claimed

has been actually enjoyed without interruption for a period


of twenty years,

by a person 'claiming right thereto/ and

who
'

alleges

and can prove that the enjoyment has been

as of right/

576. In order to understand what


pressions
'

is
'

meant by the ex-

Quasi posre.

claiming right thereto

'

and

as of right/ which jm-^ in

are the expressions used

by the

act to qualify the enjoyment,

we must

first

consider a

question which I deferred in a


is

former chapter, namely, what

the

general conception of

the enjoyment or quasi-possession of a jus in re which

we

have in view, when we are contemplating the legal


of that condition
^ ?

results

577. This

is

a matter which has been very fully discussed

by Savigny
already so

in his Treatise

on Possession, to which I have

frequently referred^

Savigny

considers

that

the conception of the quasi-possession or enjoyment of an


incorporeal thing
is

analogous in

all

respects to the con- Analogy

ception of the possession of a

corporeal thing;

of which gjon of coi-

conception it is an extension ^. Thus, in order that there PT^' ^ ' things. may be quasi-possession of an easement, it is not necessary
that the right should be actually exercised
it is
*,

any more than


contact, in.

necessary that there should be

corporal

order to constitute possession of a thing corporeally existent.

The
it

physical possibility of exercising or enjoying the ease-

ment, coupled with the determination to exercise and enjoy

on one's own behalf, constitutes quasi-possession, just as


Neither the physical

a similar combination of physical and mental elements constitutes possession

of land or goods.

possibility of enjoyment, nor the actual enjoyment, will alone


^

What

Supra, sect. 396. follows is chiefly a paraphrase of parts of sect. 46 of the Treatise

on Possession. But, in order to make it more easy of comprehension, I have occasionally amplified Savigny's Teiy condensed expressions, and
' Supra, sect. 391 sqq. two or three illustrations. The phrase 'actually enjoyed' occurs in the 2 & 3 William IV, o. 71, but it is obvious that an easement may be enjoyed even when it is not

inserted
*

being exercised.

280
constitute

ON PRESCRIPTION.
quasi-possession.
like to

[Chap. XIII.

may walk
visits

across your

land

whenever I

pay you a

or to transact business
still

with you at your house, but I


session of

am

not in quasi-pos-

any easement

in the nature of a

way

across your

land.

In walking across your land I


all

am

only using the

means, which

owners of houses provide for their friends


of obtaining ready access to
:

and neighbours,
sion
feel

them

as occa-

may

require

should you lock the gate, I should not

that I had anything to

complain

of,

and should not


expression

attempt to force
of
it

my way
that
is

in.

To use the exact


should be

Savigny, to
is

constitute quasi-possession of an

easement,

not

sufficient
it

there

an exercise or
it

enjoyment of

which

merely de facto, or accidental,


;

must be

as of right {tanqiiam suo jure)

and there must be

not only the permission, but the submission (patientia) of


the person upon whose land the
enjoyed.
So, on

easement
if

is

exercised or

the

other hand,
field,

my

neighbour grants

me

way

across his

and consequently removes from

his gate a lock

which has hitherto prevented


that the road
is

my

using

it,

and informs

me

at

my

service, I

am

just

as completely in possession of the as


if,

way by such a ceremony,


walked along the

in assertion of

my

right, I actually

road in question.
Positive
tive ease-

578. In the case of positive easements, that

is

to

say,

easements which
neighbour's
land,

consist

in
is

doing
not

something

upon your
in deter-

ments.

there

much

difficulty

mining whether or no the circumstances constitute quasipossession of

them

and the distinction above pointed out


de facio
exercise

between

the

mere

or

enjoyment,

and

exercise or

enjoyment as of right, has always been recogtolerable


clearness.
is,

nised

with

But the
from
doing

quasi-possession

of negative easements, that in

of easements

which consist
something

your neighbour

his land

of
is

on which the easement that he should not build


passage of light
difficult
is

abstaining

so as to obstruct the

the most frequent

example

far

more

to

comprehend, and

has

Sec. 578, 579.]

ON PEESCRIPTION.

281

not been so well understood.


quasi-possession
points out,
first,

Savigny has discussed the

of negative

easements very fully, and be


carefully distinguish between

that
right

we must
itself,

acquiring
session

the

and acquiring the quasi-pos-

of the

easement, which

may

be

with or without

the right; just as

we may

acquire possession of land with

or without acquiring the right to possession, or ownership.

For acquiring the right a simple grant

is

sufficient

but

suppose two strangers to be adjoining owners,


of

how

does one

them get
579.

into quasi-possession of negative easements over


?

the land of the other

That

is

the question to be solved.


of the possession Enjoy-

One
is

case of acquisition (he says)


is

of this kind of easement


act,

undisputed; namely,
is

when

the

^f

i.igjit

which

opposed to the servitude,

actually attempted

by the owner

of the servient land, but prevented;

whether

by the simple protest of the owner of the dominant land, by force, or by the decree of a court of justice. As, for
instance, if I claim as

an easement the uninterrupted flow


in

of a stream issuing
clearly be

from a spring
of
it, if,

your land, I should

in possession
it

upon your damming up


or if I myself
;

the stream before

left

your land, I complained to you,


it;

and you thereupon re-opened


order of
court,

cut the

dam, which act you did not resent


that
it

or if I obtained

an

should be

re-opened.
is

Where no

such actual attempt to do the act, which


easement,
is

opposed to the

made and

prevented, some persons have main-

tained that, in order to put the owner of the dominant land


in possession of the easement, a pretence

must be made by

the owner of the servient land of doing the act opposed to

the easement

as, for

instance, a pretence of

damming up
earth

the stream by throwing in a few

shovelfuls of

to

be followed by formal opposition on the part of the dominant

owner, and that again by a pretended submission on the


part of the servient owner.

Savigny protests strongly, as

he always does, against this sort of symbolical action, which

he considers as unsuitable to the idea of possession, as

it

282
is

ON PEESCEIPTION.

[Chap. XIII.

undoubtedly unknown in practice.

Others hold an exactly

opposite opinion, which

Savigny himself at one time shared

maintaining, that the simple omission by the servient owner


to do

any act opposed to the enjoyment of the easement,


it ^.

puts the dominant owner in possession of


at once to the conclusion,

But

this leads

which Savigny, with good reason,

declares to be nothing less than monstrous, that every land-

owner
which
as

is

in legal possession,

and

entitled to all the advantages

result

from such possession, of numberless easements,


his

against

all

neighbours

so that,
is,

for instance, the

moment a man
to,

builds a house, he
of,

not of course entitled


were) on the

but in possession

and

(as it

road to
all

acquire

by enjoyment, an easement which prevents


that

his

neighbours from building within a certain distance of him.

The

error of the latter opinion consists in this


is

it loses

sight of that which

so important,

when we

are considering
;

what
that

constitutes quasi-possession in a legal sense


it is

namely,

founded, not upon every enjoyment or exercise of


exercise of

the easement, but only upon an enjoyment or


it

as of right

not upon the mere inaction of the other party,


[patietitia)

but on his submission

to

necessity.

Anything
is

which

establishes that the exercise or

enjoyment

of this

character,

and not merely de facto or accidental,

is sufficient is

to establish quasi-possession in a legal sense.

This

clear

enough

in the undisputed case

mentioned above, where there

has been an actual attempt to do the act opposed to the


easement, followed by a
protest submitted
to

or

enforced.

So, where the right itself has been granted, no

formal or

symbolical induction into the exercise or enjoyment of ease-

ment

is

necessary.

The

exercise or

enjoyment of the

ease-

ment and the

passiveness of the other party are now, not

^ I have not been able to refer to the earlier editions of Savigny's Treatise on Possession, but he states in a note to the subsequent editions, that he was at first one of those who thought that the mere inaction of

the servient owner put the dominant owner in possession, in a legal any negative servitude which the dominant owner de facto enjoyed. See p. 493.
sense, of

Sec. 580, 581.

ON PEESCEIPTION.

283

merely de facto or accidental, but directly referable to the


right,

which has been acquired by grant.


is

580. It
Tenterden,

certainly not a

little

remarkable that Lord

Coinoi-

who

has generally been supposed to have drawn expres-

the Prescription Act, and

who

does not usually evince any?^'^^^"


strict

very strong desire to adopt the

and accurate technical

tion Act.

language of the

Roman

law, should have chosen almost exactly

the expression which Savigny, against


after a considerable

much

opposition and

change in his own opinions, has fixed

upon, in order to characterise that kind- of enjoyment of a


right which leads to
its

acquisition.

I do not think there


is

can be any doubt that the Prescription Act

here identical

vnth the
either

Roman

law, from which the expression was borrowed


or

by Lord Tenterden,
before^.
is

some one of

his predecessors;

for, I think, the expression

had been used on the English

Bench

581. There

one

easement which the Prescription Act Easement

allows to be acquired in a different

ments ^.

This

is

the easement of
it

way from all other easelight. As to this easement


person

the act says that

may

be acquired by actual enjoyment claiming right

simply, the qualifying words 'by a


thereto' not being added.

There

is

no doubt that the in-

tention was to give to the mere de facto and accidental enjoy-

ment
cases

of light for
is

twenty years the benefit which in other

only conferred upon enjoyment as of right.

We

have seen

how

nearly the desire to render the enjoyment

of light under similar circumstances continuous and secure,


1 Lord Wensleydale treats the words of section 5, as of right,' as conveying the true meaning of the legislature. See the case of Bright against Walker, Crompton, Meeson and Eoscoe, Reports, vol. i. p. 219 ; Gale on Easements, p. 128. But the two phrases together show clearly that what
'

meant is tanquam sui juris. It might have been possible general in its terms, the words
is
'

to argue that, as section 5 of the act is as of right


'

'

in this section apply to the

easement of light as well as other easements. But, I thujk, it is agreed that these words in sect. 5 must be read as explanatory of the words claiming right thereto in sect. 3, and that they have no application to
' '

the easement of light.

284

ON PEESCEIPTION.

[Chap. XIII.

had perverted the interpretation of the Eoman law on the


general question of acquisition of negative servitudes
^.

The
that

obvious cause of the proneness to error on this point the ordinary law of prescription
is

isj

not suited to the circum;

stances of that particular easement

questions as to which

generally arise

where habitations are closely packed, and


special

where the respective parties stand to each other in

and exceptional

relations.

Most European
whilst

countries have

dealt with the subject in a

similarly exceptional

manner,

only this has been done avowedly;

we have caused
to
^-

a good deal of confusion by so long

struggle

meet

the difBculty by the application of general principles

But

all

necessity for straining the law for this purpose in

England
provision

is

avoided by the framers of the Prescription Act


case.

having made a special provision to meet this

The
one of

was at

first

rather misunderstood, but all difficulty


it

has disappeared since


this exceptional kind.

has been recognised that

it is

EnjoybcTpeace'-

582. English judges, besides requiring that enjoyment of

^^ easement in order to give


legal origin
I

rise

to the presumption of a
it

able

and

must be

as of right,

open.

have also held that


.

must
'

be peaceable and open.


are probably wise.

In requiring these conditions they


'

The words

peaceable

'

and

'

open

cor-

respond to two expressions of the

Roman

law, which required


I do not think

that possession should be nee vi nee clam.


^

Supra, section 579. - The distinctly exceptional character of this provision was, I believe, first pointed out by Mr. Justice Willes, in the case of Webb against Bird,

where the owner of a windmill claimed, as an easement appurtenant to his mill, the free and uuinten-upted passage of air. The case is reported in the tenth volume of the Common Bench Reports, New Series see pp. 284, 285, and exactly accords with the conclusions of Savigny as to
;

the acquisition of the possession of negative easements. Probably, however, the decision in Dalton against Angus, Law Eeports, Appeal Cases,
vol. vi. p. 740, is fatal to

any attempt to introduce the distinction between inaction and submission into the English law. But I cannot help feeling surprise that any one should maintain that it is reasonable or desirable
that

when my neighbour

away the

soil so as just to let his

right to excavate

my

me I should have to cut house fall down, on peril of losing my own land, should I find it necessary to do so.
builds a house near to

Sec. 582.]
it

ON PRESCRIPTION.
meaning

285

worth while for an English lawyer to examine very accuof these expressions in the

rately the

for this part of the

Eoman
made

law, though

it

Roman law, may have given


as a model, nor

a hint to our judges, has not served

them

do I think

it

could be

to do so without a radical

change

in our views as to prescription.

Expressions to the effect that

the enjoyment

is

to be open

and peaceable have long been


is

used by English lawyers, and this requirement


established.

now

well

But

it is

not to be found in the Prescription Act.

And

the judges, I venture to think, have gone entirely wrong,


it

in endeavouring to discover
or the analogous words struction of the act
'

in the words

'as

of right''

claiming right thereto.^

This con-

would lead to great confusion.


right with

We must

never forget Savigny's caution, not to confound the acquire-

ment

of

the

title
it

to
^ ;

the

the

acquirement of

the possession of

and I think
'

this caution is forgotten


"

when we

find these

words

as of right

interpreted, as
if

Lord
they

Wensleydale seems desirous to interpret them, as

meant ' rightfully 2.'


law with an act which

I do not think

it

has ever been doubted


in the English

that the acquisition of rights


is

may commence
;

a pure trespass

and that the enjoy-

ment may continue

to be a trespass until

by

prescription

it

has grown into a right.

It would have been impossible to


it

apply the statute to half the cases to which


applied, if such

has been

a trespasser could not in the view of the

English law enjoy as of right.

To exchange

the necessary

and

(if

may

use the expression) scientific interpretation of


"

the phrase 'as of right


suggests,

for that

which Lord Wensleydale

would throw the law into the greatest possible confusion; and it is a sufficient answer to the attempt to
use the language of the act for this purpose, to say that
it

has already been appropriated to another,


one.

and an

inconsistent

We

must, therefore, treat the conditions which require

'

Sav. Poss., sect. 46, p. 492.


vol.
i.

See the case in Crompton, Meeson and Eoscoe's Reports, Gale on Easements, p. 128.
^

p.

219

286

ON PRESCRIPTION.

[Chap. XIII.

the enjoyment to be peaceable and open as introduced npon


the authority of judicial decision
after
;

a stretch of power at which,


occasions,

what has happened on other


alarmed.

we need not be

very much
Condi-

It is desirable to observe that,

if

the view which I take

the quasi-possession of a right necessary o^ the general conception of


to acquisition of
^j^ ^j^g

nature of an easement, and of the conditions which are


the acquisition of the right, be correct, these con-

jura in re necessary to
ease-

ditions will apply not only to the easements specified in the

ments.

^^^ ^^^ ^^ ^|j easements,

and

also to all jura in re

which can

be acquired by prescription.
Derivative

583. I have explained above what

is

meant by

derivative

There may be derivative possession of a thing doernot"^ possession. induce belongs to another, or there may be derivative quasi-^yhich
prescription.
_

possession or enjoyment of a right over a thing which belongs


to another.

Thus,

if

the owner of Whiteacre grants to the


for a fixed

owner of Blackacre a right of way over Whiteacre


period of twenty years, the grantee by using the
full quasi-possession of

way

takes

the right, and enjoys

it

as of right.

He
also

can also during the twenty years assert his right against

the grantor, and under most systems of jurisprudence (perhaps

under our own) against

all

the world besides.

But he

cannot use this possession for the purpose of gaining the


benefit of the Prescription Act, or for

any other

like purpose.

The

true and only reason of this


is

is

that his possession, like

that of the pledgee,

derivative.

Benefits of the kind

we

are

now

considering are never conferred by derivative possession,

either in the

way

of true prescription or by

way

of

enjoyment
It
is

from time immemorial, or on any similar


desirable to observe that this
is

principle.

also

a wholly different case from

that

of

a person

who

enjoys

something merely under a

permission which

may

be at any
fails to

moment withdrawn.

Such

an enjoyment likewise
a thing by permission

produce the benefits we are

considering, but for a different reason.


is

person

who

enjoys

not in possession of the thing in


facto

a legal sense at

all.

The de

enjoyment produces no

Sec. 583, 584.]

ON PRESCRIPTION.
The tradesman who
for

287

legal results.

twenty years opens

my
an
of

gate and walks up to

my

door

is

never in possession of

easement in the nature of a right of way.


the

The grantee

way

in the case previously put


it,

is,

as I have said, in posso.

session of

and as of

right,

but only derivatively

Both,

therefore, are

excluded from prescription, but for entirely

different reasons.

Though,

therefore.

Lord Wensleydale was


case,

undoubtedly right when, in a well-known

he treated
of

both these

persons

as

excluded

from the

benefit
if

the

Prescription Act, he was, I think,


assert that they were both excluded

wrong

he meant to
principle.

upon the same

584. I

may

further illustrate

the general truth of the Excep-

prineiples above stated

by
in

referring to the cases in which

they have been really or apparently departed from.

Thus
of

where land
possession,

is

given

pledge,
statute

and the pledgee takes


the

by the English
in

ownership

the Pledgee
posses^^^'

of

pledgor

is

some

cases

extinguished, and he

can take

no proceedings to recover the land of which he has given

up

possession.

Practically also

the land

is

transferred to

the pledgee.
it

Now

the pledgee's possession being derivative,


stated,

ought never, according to the principles above

to operate in his favour.

But

possession which
so.

was once

derivative

may have
it is

ceased to be

If the pledgor has

not

manifested for a very long period any intention to


not unreasonable to presume that the

redeem the land,

pledgee has taken to the land in lieu of the debtj that he

has ceased to hold derivatively, and has determined to hold

on his own behalf.


not always do this;

We know

that a derivative possessor can-

he cannot change at will the character

of his possession from derivative possession to possession on


his

own

behalf as owner.

But

this is a special protection

given to persons

who

part with the possession of their pro:

perty to others, retaining the ownership

and there

is

ample

' See 3 & 4 William IV. chap, xxvii. section 28. This section describes the position of the pledgee as it really is, and not as it is called in our

clumsy law language.

288

ON PRESCRIPTION.
own

[Chap. XIII.

reason for not extending this protection to cases where persons


are so inactive in regard to their
interests as in the case

under consideration.
Tenancies

585. So in the provisions


at will

as to

what
The

are called tenancies

where
''f

and tenancies from year


it

to year,

where there has been


result of these pro-

^t

h*

^ payment of rent, or
visions
is,

has ceased.

ceased,

that a period of dispossession which eventually bars


title,
if

the remedy and extinguishes the


of the
first

commences

at the end

year of the tenancy, or

rent be paid, at the last

time when the rent was received.


tenant in such a ease would be

Now
is

the possession of a

at' least

derivative,

and perhaps
case, operate

representative; and, therefore, it

contrary to the rule we

have laid down, that the statute should, in any


for his benefit.

And we know how

jealously the English law

in most cases applies this rule to tenants

and refuses

to allow

that either a representative or a derivative possessor can change


possession which acknowledges the title of another into possession

which

is

adverse.

But by a

special provision a tenant

at will

who has

held for twenty years without payment of

rent and without giving


of his title
for the

any acknowledgment

to the

owner
and

may allege
let

that he has held during this period, not

owner who

him

into possession, but for himself,

claim the same benefit as any other holder for a similar period,

whose possession has been adverse ^Indian


scription.

586. Substantially the

same

principles

as

those

which

bave been adopted in the English law of prescription are


recognised in the Indian statutes.

The

period

which brings

the statute into


'

operation

is

in India

generally measured

See 3

(fc

William IV. chap,

xxvii. sections 7

It is convenient to continue the use of the

and 8. word adverse


'

'

to describe

the position of a person

whose possession

is

not derivative, notwith-

standing the somewhat unfortunate history of that word in English law. Prior to the passing of the statutes of William the Fourth, a doctrine of adverse possession had been set up which the ablest lawyers declared to

be unintelligible, and one of the main objects of these statutes was to sweep away this unintelligible doctrine. But there is no impropriety in now using the word 'adverse' in what appears to be its natural meaning.

Sect. 585-588.]

ON PRESCBIPTION.
wliieli is

289
'

from a date

described as that

when the

dispos-

session occurs ^'

No

suit

can generally be brought to recover


so

any property except within


English statute, but

many

years after that date.


is

No

further technical definition of this date


it is

given, as in the

obvious that the cases in which the

statute affects ownership are those in which there has been,

or

might

be, a dispute as to possession

and the position of

hostility thus implied requires that the party in possession

should hold, not

for,

but against the other ; should hold also


not consistently with the

as owner, and not derivatively;

ownership of the other, but adversely.

And,

if

a person has

been in possession, thus adversely, of land or moveables for the


necessary period, and the means of recovering
other person are taten away,
Council, though
it is it is

them by any

considered

by the Privy

not so expressed in the law, that the

ownership follows the possession^.

Thus we have in India

true prescriptive ownership of land, based not upon legislation

but upon judicial decision.


587. Certain rules relating to the acquisition by prescription
of rights

over land other than ownership have been

introduced into an act recently passed


lature.

by the Indian Legisis

These rules expressly provide that easements both

positive

and negative

may

be gained by enjoyment which

peaceable, and open,

and

as of right, but they

make

the dis-

tinction that the enjoyment of the easements of light


is

and

air

not required to be open ^

588. I do not think that the English law of prescription Suggested

will ever be put


is

upon a

satisfactory

i>

footmg

improyei-i ii iuntil the notion ment in


^^

got rid of that


is

all prescription

presumes a grant, and until

j^'^^

prescription
as a

recognised here, as on the continent of Europe,

means

of acquiring ownership.
fiction

This grant

is

only a
It does

fiction,

and the

here

is

not a useful one.

not indicate the principles to be applied.


'

The

relation of the

Act

ix.

of 1871, Sched.
vol. xi. p. 361.

2
'

See Moore's Indian Appeals,

The easement of

access of air is not mentioned in the English Pre-

scription Act, but it is so in the Indian Act (Act xv. of 1877).

290

ON PRESCRIPTION.
to the person

[Chap. XIII.

owner of the servient tenement


right over
is it

who has

the

it is

not really that of grantor and grantee, nor

analogous to that of grantor and grantee.

And though
in the

I think that fictions are useful

and may be defended


indefensible to place

hands of lawyers, I consider


before a jury.

it

them
to the

589. Probably the best thing that could

now happen
it

English law of prescription would be that


recast

should be wholly
first place,

by the

legislature,

acknowledging in the

in

the case of both ownership and jura in re aliena, that they


could be acquired

by

possession for a certain time

and that

the title so acquired was just as good by conveyance from the owner. This
course, be as of right,
sider

in all respects as a title

possession must, of

and

it

would

also

be necessary to con-

what

defects in the possession besides actual fraud should

stand in the

way

of acquisition.

And, at

this point,

it

is

probable that our law, especially as regards the acquisition


of land,

would require some substantial modification.

It is
all

hardly likely that on such a point


the rest of the world wrong.

we
if it

should be right and

And

were decided that some

defects in possession should be a bar to the ordinary prescription, a longer period

might be named

after

which even

this
^.

defective possession

might be considered

sufficient for a title

Time immemorial might, I


it

think, pass unnoticed.


it still

Not

that

would be thereby abolished ; for

might and would

give rise to a presumption of a legal origin, but only a pre-

sumption, of which the judge or jury (whichever had to decide


the question of fact) would form an opinion
'

^.

advanced as the ancient Hindoo law the recognised. The Mitacshara lawyers would allow a right to he gained in twenty years, but only if the party already held under a title which though defective was just. See Mitacshara, chap. 3, 3, Of the Effect of Possession. Jaganatha, a more recent
so little
title'

Even in a system

advantages of a 'just

are

which he reckons at sixty years, would give the ownership. What he says seems to imply that the period would be shortened in favour of a person holding under a just title. Book v. w. 395, 396. 2 Bentham (vol. i. of Collected Works, p. 327) has committed himself
quiet enjoyment without just
title

author, says that in three generations,

Sec. 589-591-1

ON PBESCEIPTION,

291

590. There are other rights besides ownership and jura in


re

ahena to which prescription can be appHed.


it

The Roman

law applied
to take
toll,

to marriage

and

it is

applied to such rights as

or hold a market.

I have selected ownership and

jnra in re alienS. for discussion because of their importance,

and because they best


as understood

illustrate

the principles of prescription

by English lawyers.

591. I follow the ordinary use of language,


that rights

when

I say
it

may

be gained or lost by lapse of time, but

must be borne Of course what


all

in

mind how
is

far that expression


is

is correct.

creates or destroys the right

the sovereign

authority alone, which


obligations
:

the source of

all

rights as well as of

and lapse

of time together with other circum-

stances are only the prearranged conditions which give rise to

ownership.

For instance, when a

man
is

gains by prescrip-

tion the right to take toU from all persons passing over a
certain bridge,

what

really happens

that, after he

has

collected toll for a certain

number of

years, the courts of law,

exercising delegated sovereign authority, will recognise his

right to

do

so.

But

generally, other circumstances

must
It

combine.

He must
If
it is

have collected the

toll as of right.

must not be on a bridge which forms part


a town.

of the street of

in a public thoroughfare the claimant in repair ;

must

show that he has always kept the bridge


ever else

or what-

may
we

be the restrictions which the sovereign authority

thinks

fit

to impose

on the acquisition

of the right.

When,

therefore,

say rights are gained or lost by lapse of time,

we

only use a convenient and compendious expression which


our attention on that part of the matter which

fixes

we wish

to bring into prominence.


to the opinion that no time

possession

is

dishonestly obtained.

however long ought to give a title where the His observations are rather rhetorical,

and

am

laying

down

not sure he has not lost sight of his so sweeping a proposition.

own

principle of utility in

V a

CHAPTEK

XIV.

liability'.
Primary
condaiy
duties.

592.

EvEEY person

is

under the law subject to a great


or to

variety of things.
fully

duties to do

abstain

from doing certain

The nature defined by the

of some of these duties has been care-

law, as for example in the case of the


his
child.

duties of a parent in regard to

In other cases

the law has not fully defined the duties to be performed, but

has left the definition of them in a measure to the parties concerned


:

as for example in the case of trustees, or the

directors of a railway

company.

In a third

class

of cases,

such as those duties which arise out of contract and other


ordinary transactions of daily
life, it
is

left

almost entirely

to the parties concerned to determine them as they please,

the law merely enforcing them.

593. These are


told

all

what

are called primary duties

we

are

what we
if
;

are to do without
is

any consideration of what


:

follows

the duty

not performed
is

that

we

are

told

separately

and forms what

called a secondary or sanction-

ing duty.
^ An Analysis of Criminal Liability has been published by Professor Clark (Cambridge, 1880), to which I refer the reader for a full and able

discussion of the principles here stated.

Mr.

J.

H. Wigmore has traced

in a series of interesting articles the gradual development of liability in

English law from the earliest stages, in which

it

was enough for the courts

that an act had been done which caused damage either wilfully or by misadventure (and these are scarcely distinguishable), down to the present
time,

when even

wilfulness

is

either desires or culpably disregards the consequences of his act.

not a ground of liability unless the doer See

Harvard Law Review,

vol. vii. pp. 315, 383, 441.

LIABILITY,

293

693 a. But there


no attempt
is

is also

a large number of eases in which Primary


to determine the primary always
<l'^Sned.

made by the law

duties, otherwise

than by determining what constitutes a


^.

breach of them, and what secondary duty follows thereon


534. It
is

quite possible that for practical purposes

it

may

come

to the

same thing whether the law determines the duty


it
:

or the breach of

and probably

if

the breach of duty were

defined in all cases as accurately as (say) the crime of theft in

the Indian Penal Code, there would be no reason to complain


of the obscurity of the law.

But

this is very far

from being Secondary


where the notiJways
dis- defined

the

case.

And

it is

precisely in that class of cases

primary duty to do or abstain from doing has not been


cussed,

and where lawyers have

fixed their attention

on the

breach of duty and the secondary or sanctioning duty which


arises thereon, that

we

find the greatest obscurity.

595. The word


of a person

'liability' is used to describe the condition Liability.

who has a duty


liability of

to perform, whether that

duty be

a primary one or a secondary or sanctioning one.

Thus we
duties of
:

speak of the
his trust
:

a trustee

to perform the
his

of a contractor

who

has broken his contract

to perform contract to pay damages.


'

of one

596.

We

frequently come actoss the expression

liability

Ex

con-

ex contractu.'

This

signifies the condition of

a person

who

is

under the primary duty to perform a contract.


do so he comes under another
to
liability

If he fails to

namely, under a duty


meet with
isExde'"*"

make

compensation.
expression

597. Another
'

we

frequently
is

liability

ex

delicto.'

Here the matter

taken up at a
the condition of

different stage.

This expression

signifies

a person who has already committed a breach of a primary


duty, and

who

is

under a duty to make compensation to the

party injured by his default.

598. The breach of duty


liability
still

itself
'

which gives

rise

to

the
for,

Torts,

ex delicto

is

called a
of,

tort.'

We

have no name

less

any description
'

the primary duty which has


sect. 1,53.

See supra,

294

LIABILITY.
It
is

[Ohap. XIV.

been violated.

not easy to say what breaches of duty

are comprehended under the word 'tort.'

The word

itself

conveys nothing more than that something is done which is But every breach of a legal duty is a legal legally wrong.

wrong, and there are


'tort'
is

many

such wrongs to which the word


call

never applied.

For example, we should never

a breach of contract a tort; nor a breach of duty by a trustee;

nor the omission of a person


toll.
is

who has used a


of

ferry to

pay the

Indeed I think

it

may

be said that the word 'tort' a primary duty,

never used to describe the breach

if

that duty has been itself described with

any degree

of

definiteness.
Civil injuries and

599. Liability
criminal liability.

is

not unfrequently divided into


liability is

civil

and

This classification of
in

not based

upon any
liability,

distinction

the nature of the two kinds of

but upon a difference in the tribunal in which the


is

party liable
party
is

proceeded against.

If the court where the


is

proceeded against be what

called a criminal court,


is

or court of criminal jurisdiction, the liability to be


criminal,

considered

and the breach


If the court

of

duty

is

called a

crime

or an offence.

in

which the proceedings are


of
civil

taken be a
liability
is is

civil

court, or court
civil,

jurisdiction, the

considered to be
civil injury.

and the breach of duty


then some difficulty

called

But
and

there are some courts which


is

exercise both jurisdictions,

and there

in distinguishing criminal

civil liability.

By

long habit

we have come

to consider certain kinds of personal violence,

certain breaches

of the

laws which protect property, and

certain kinds of fraud to be crimes.

But where there

is

no

such tradition,

as, for

example, in the case of the refusal


it

of a father to support his bastard child,

has been found

very
is

difficult to

determine whether or no the breach of duty

a crime.

and criminal

liability

The French law draws the line between civil by means of the Code. Civil injuries
which are dealt with by the Code

are those breaches of duty


Civil.

Offences are those breaches of duty which are dealt

'

Sec. 599, 6oo.j

LIABILITY.
Offences are divided into
'

295
crimes

with by the Code Penal.

(specially so-called), 'delits' (using in a narrower sense the

same word
injuries),

as
'

is

used to describe a certain class of


de pohce '
;

civil

and

contraventions

the latter class

containing a good

many

matters which

we should bring
division Origin of

under civU

liability.

600. Whilst too we

1.

between

......

civil injuries

,. /!;, and uncertain, distinction . and crimes fluctuating


1

find that in

modern times the

is

between
?^'^l'

we
at

observe that in the earlier stages of society,


all, it

was based on

entirely different notions

for all injuries both to

To exact person and property a payment in


'.

if it

existed

^"
,

juries and crimes,

money

to the person injured appears to


leffal liability

have been the

first

form of
idea of

for injuries to private persons alike in

Greece, in

Rome, and among the Teutonic tribes. The first criminal law, as distinguished from this, seems to

have grown out of the punishment by the sovereign authority


of offences directly against
itself.

And

the impulse to the

more general development


this last notion.

of criminal liability in later times

seems to have been due, in this country, to an extension of


It
is

supposed,
'

by rather an odd
'

fiction,

that by
his
'

every offence the


"

King's peace
it

is

disturbed,

and

dignity
it

offended.

And

was formerly necessary


;

in all

cases that

should be so stated in the indictment

not only

where

acts of violence

had been committed, but even where


on a Sunday.

the offence charged was such as obtaining goods by false


pretences, or selling ale

Modern

writers

still

attempt to preserve a somewhat similar notion, when they


tell

us that

civil injuries are

infringements of rights belonging

to individuals considered as individuals; whereas crimes are

breaches of public rights and duties belonging to the whole

community

^.

However, the examples given above

sufficiently

show that
'

this distinction is not adhered to.

Maine's Ancient Law, ch.

x.

Kemble's Saxons in England, Bk.


quoted in Broom's Com-

i.

ch. X.
'

Blackstone's Commentaries, vol. iv. p. 5

mentaries, p. 869 (ist ed.).

296

LIABILITY.

[Chap. XIV.

601. Sometimes the mental consciousness o part of the person

who

does the act appears to be

wrong on the made

the test of criminality.

We

are often told that in order to

commit a crime a person must have a guilty mind. No doubt too there has been a readiness to bring all acts, which
are in the general estimation of

mankind

wicked, within the

criminal law.
neither
is

But a very

slight experiment will

show that

this a test

distinguish civil injuries


Nature of
obliea-^" tions not

which has been consistently applied to from crimes ^

602. It must always be remembered that whatever names

we give

to dutieSj or to breaches of duties, or to the conse-

q^ences arising therefrom^ these names only refer to the


occasion on which the
duties

on the
theirraeation-

come

into

existence,

and

to

the mode in which they are enforced, and have nothing

whatever to do with the nature of the duty


is

itself,

which

the creature of the sovereign power.

For instance, the

duty I

am

under to abstain from acts which would interfere

vnth the enjoyment of your property


express contract between

you and me,

or

may arise upon an may depend, withCertain

out any contract, solely on your right of ownership.


rights with
their

corresponding duties do, iadeed, for the


certaia other rights with

most part

arise

upon contract;

their corresponding duties do, as it so happens, for the

most

part arise independently of contract.

Breaches also of duties


are,

which are the subject of

civil

procedure

as

a fact,

generally followed immediately

by consequences

of one kind

whilst breaches of duties which are the subject of criminal

procedure are, as a fact, generally followed immediately by

consequences of another kind.

But there

is

nothing in this

which

is

either necessary, or even constant.

There

is

hardly

any duty usually

arising
;

upon contract which might not


and a very large number of
arise partly

arise independently of it

rights,

with their corresponding duties,


1

upon

contract,

See Ru3sell on Crimes, vol.

i.,

will lie for neglecting to forward

whence it appears that an indictment an election writ (ch. xvii.), and for re(ch. xxxvii.).

moving a dead body, however innocently

Sec. 6oi, 602.]

LIABILITY.
;

297

and partly not

indeed,

we have

seen

how

the attempt to
creates

discriminate between duties

by the occasion which


So we

them has completely


the consequences of

failed.
all

shall see hereafter that

breaches of duty

are in a

great

measure ultimately the same, whether their consequences be


civilly or criminally pursued.

CHAPTER XV.
LIABILITY UPON CONTEACT.
Concepcontract

603. In order to understand liability upon contract


niust

we

try

and understand what

is

meant by a

contract.

Contracts clearly belong to that class of acts which give rise


to legal rights

and duties upon occasions when the

parties

themselves have agreed so to declare their intention.

The

declaration of intention does not create the rights or duties

that can only be done


is

by the sovereign authority, but


:

it

the occasion of their being created

and

it is

the very

object of the declaration that these rights and duties should


arise.

I have already

made some

general observations upon

declarations of intention which are, of course, applicable to

contracts

^.

604. In endeavouring to discover what


tract,^

is

meant by con'

I shall

make

use of the inquiry into the meaning of

the term contained in Savigny's System of

Modern Roman
is

Law ^,
Savigny's
of
0011-'

of
'

which the following

is

a paraphrase.
familiar to

605.
^^^'

The

idea of contract (says Savigny)

6ven to those who are strangers to the science of law.


it is

tract.

J3ut with lawyers


is

so frequently

brought into play, and

so indispensable

by reason of the frequency with which


it,

they have to apply

that one might expect from them an


it.

unusually clear and precise conception of

But

in this

we

are not a little disappointed.

606. 'I will try (he says) to show what a contract

is,

by the

analysis of a case

which no one can doubt

is

one

of true contract.
'

If

then with this view we consider the


'

Sect. 241.

Sect. 140.

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.


contract of sale, the
first

299
is

thing that strikes us

several
case,

persons in presence of each other.


as in most, there are precisely

In this particular
;

two persons

but, frequently,
is

as in a contract of partnership, the tain


;

number

quite uncer-

so that

we must adhere
must
all

to plurality in this general

and

indeterminate form, as a characteristic of contract.


several persons

These

have come to some determination,


for,

and

to

the

same determination;

so

long as there

is

any indetermination, or want


contract.

of agreement, there can be


;

no
is,

This agreement must also be disclosed

that

the wishes of each must be stated by, and to each, until


all are

known
'

for a resolution
vfill

which has been simply taken

and not
607.

disclosed

not serve as the basis of contract. not


neglect
to

Moreover,
is

we must
at.

observe the
to agree to

object which

aimed

If two

men were

assist each other reciprocally,

by example
it

or advice, in the

pursuit of virtue, science, or art,

would be a very odd use

of the term to call this a contract.

The

difference

between

such cases and the contract of


the type,
is

sale,

which we have

selected as

this
is

In the

latter,

the object which the parties


;

have in view

a legal relation

whereas in the former, the

objects are of quite another kind.

But simply

to say, that
is

the object which the parties to a contract have in view

a legal relation, does not go to the root of the distinction.

When

the judges of a court of law after a long discussion

agree upon a decree,


hitherto noted, and

we have every one


it is
is

of the characteristics

a legal relation that the decision

has in view; but yet there


the distinction
relation to
is,

no contract.

The bottom

of

that the judges have before them a legal


parties.

which they are no

In the case of a
parties

contract of sale the legal relation


plate
is

which the

contem-

their own.

608. 'These characteristics


following definition
persons
in
:

may be summed up
is

in the

A contract

the concurrence of several

a declaration of intention whereby their legal

relations are determined.'

300
English
definitions

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.

[Chap.

XV.

ofcontract.

.,, includes
^p

609. It will be observed that this definition o contract


not only those agreements

j_ij.t_
out

j.i-i which

are

a promise

(Jq^ qj. {;q

forbear from, some future act, but those also which

are

carried

simultaneously with the intention

of the

parties being declared.

English writers are not very clear

upon
in

this point.

While on the one hand they would seem


treat

practice

to

as

contracts

only those agreements

which

legally bind us to do, or to forbear, at

some future

time ; yet

we
all

find,

on the other hand, that in their definitions

of contract they generally take the widest possible ground,

rejecting

the

limitations

suggested

by Savigny, and

making, in

fact,

the two words 'contract' and 'agreement'

synonymous.
Distinc-

610.

From some

expressions

in passages

subsequent to

tween^
contract and per-

that which I have quoted, I gather that Savigny intended to


treat the performance of a contract as itself a contract. ^
if

Thus,

formanoe
tract.

I rightly understand him, he says that the agreement for


is

the sale and purchase of a house

one contract, and the

consequent delivery of possession by the vendor to the purchaser


is

another.
I venture
is

This,
to

with deference to so great


I think there
is

an
a

authority,

doubt.

here

confusion which

exceedingly

common between
^.

contract

and transfer

or conveyance, such as Austin has several times

pointed out in the course of his Lectures


611. Subject

to

this

modification

(and

for

our present

purpose

it is

.not

an important one) I think that Savigny's

analysis of contract
distinction

may
it,

safely be adopted.

The

essential

between

and the

definition current in those

countries which have adopted the

Code Napoleon,

is

this

Savigny defines contract


templation of the parties

solely with
:

reference to the con-

if

the parties intend to declare


calls
is

their legal rights inter se,

he

it

a contract

whether

or no
"

it

has the effect intended

not considered^.

The

See Lecture xiv. and the notes to Table II, pp. 387, 1005 (3rd ed.). ^ I gather this from the general tenor of Savigny's observations, and, I think, it is also implied in, though not expressly affirmed by, the definition.

Seo.6o9-6i4j

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.


it

301
of the essence
'

Code Napoleon^ on the other hand, makes


of the definition of contract that an
created.
'

obligation

is

thereby-

For instance,

if

I were to promise a voter ten

pounds for his vote, that would be a contract according to

Savigny
it

but, as no legal obligation would result

from

it,

would not be a contract according to the

definition of the

French Code.

The

definition of contract in the Italian

Code
effort English
defini-

nearly accords with that of Savigny's definition ^.


612. English lawyers have not
to define contract authoritatively.

made any very distinct

US a very careiul analysis and explanation or agreement, and


this is

1.

ij-

Several writers have given


^

j_T

tions of contract.

no doubt a useful step in understanding the nature of

contract.

But we have
so.

still

to ascertain

what agreements

are

contracts, for I believe every one admits that all agreements

are not
613.

Some

persons after having defined an agreement, go on

to teU us that a contract is

an agreement enforceable " at law^.


'

This, as I understand

it,

restricts the

word contract to those

agreements which the party making the promise can be compelled by law to perform. This is not unlike what is said by the French Code but it leaves the definition of contract very vague, because no guide whatever is given as to what agreements, or what classes of agreements, are enforceable at
:

law.

Moreover English lawyers do not hesitate to apply the


to agreements

word contract
614.

which are declared to be void

^-

The conception
all

of contract as set forth

by Savigny Advan:

does not solve


pears to

the diflSculties about contract


it calls

but

it

ap- Savigny's
dsfi'^i*iii-

me

to have this advantage, that

attention to
of.

a point which English lawyers have rather lost sight


It

reminds us that the agreement in order to become a

contract must be one in which the parties contemplate the


creation of a legal relation between themselves.
' Codice Civile, art. 1098. If we could find a, definition which would save us from the necessity of calling things contracts which were not conBut this has not been done. tracts, it would be convenient. ^ This is the language of the Indian Contract Act.

'

Order xix of the High Court, Eules 15 and

20.

302
Agreenofcalways
plate legal
a*'

LIABILITY UPON CONTEACT.


That there are agreements which
I think, abundantly clear.

[Chap.

XV.

615.

will be considered
is

not to be contracts because this legal relation


plated
.

not contem-

is,

Suppose^ for examplcj

that two friends


.

relation.

time and in a definite direction, no one would say that this


a contract, and yet
it is

B ...
and

agree to walk together at a definite


is

clearly

an agreement, and there

is

also

a consideration for the promise of each.


only reason,

The

reason,

and the
aware,

why

it is

not a contract

is,

as far as I

am

that the parties, presumably, do


relation.

not contemplate a legal

616. Another advantage of Savigny's definition of contract


is

that

it

clearly describes the true relation of the parties,

and

how
for
call

it arises.

It arises because there has been

between the
rights,

parties a transaction

having reference to their legal


special

which we have no
'

name, but which the Germans


call
'

Rechtsgeschaft,''

and the French

acte juridique.'

The
ment

expression

'enforceable agreement'

seems to

me

too

narrow.

There are cases in which parties come to an agree-

as to their legal relations,

which cannot be enforced

as

such, but
If, for

which nevertheless have important legal consequences.

example, an infant agrees to


:

make a

purchase, this
is

agreement cannot be enforced


ferred

but, if the property

trans-

and the

price paid, the transaction holds good.

This

is

because of the previous agreement, which has, therefore, im-

portant legal consequences, and


617. I

is

rightly called a contract.

have already said that I would keep clear the

distinction

between the fulfilment of a contract and the

contract

itself.

Nor do

I think there

is

any

difliculty in this.
sale

"When

after the parties

have agreed upon the terms of a

the buyer delivers the goods and the seller receives them, each

contemplates a change in his

own

legal position, but there

is

no new agreement.
transferred
individuals
is
is

The

transaction

by which the property

is

a legal one, but every legal transaction between

not a contract.
it

618.

But

may

be said that every sale

is

a contract, and

yet upon a sale for ready

money where

the goods are delivered.

Sec. 615-621.]

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.

303

immediately and the price paid, the transaction cannot be


separated into two parts, one of contract and the other of

conveyance, and that in this case, at any rate, contract and

conveyance are

identical.

But I do not think that

this is

necessarily the case.

Rather, I think, the words and gestures

used have served a double purpose; that of expressing an

agreement between the

parties,

and that
price.

of transferring the

ownership of the goods and the


619.

Upon

the whole, with the qualification that the


is

fulfil-

ment

of a contract

not

itself

a contract, I should accept

Savigny's view that every concurrent declaration of parties


as to their legal relations
is

a contract.
Difficulty

620.

contract

is

a manifestation of intention, and the

same

difficulty arises in contract as in all other manifestations taining

of intention

when

in case of dispute

we have

to ascertain

"*"t'-

what the
from
acts,

intention really was.

We

can only infer intention

and whether we make

this inference

by the

aid of

artificial rules, or

without them, we shall inevitably in some


This
is

cases attribute intention wrongly.


is

difficulty

which

inherent in

all inquiries
is

into disputed facts.

In

acts of
if

which the very object

manifestation of intention,
is

the

parties are careful, the difficulty


stances, very great.

not, under ordinary circumin

But from the slovenly mode


from
themselves, great

which

Intention

parties to a contract, in the hurry of business or


ness, frequently express

careless- ^^ gon.

difficulties

often

*'^^<'*-

arise in ascertaining

what

legal relation the parties intended

to create.
621. It
is

with reference to this inquiry that

it is

said,

'the intention of the parties governs the contract.''


difficulty of ascertaining

But the

the

intention

still

remains.

The
is

person to
called,

whom the promise is made, or promisee, may say that he expected one thing, and the
that he intended another.
?

as he

promiser
is

may say
'

In which sense

the

promise to be taken
It
is

Paley discussing this question says

not the sense in which the promiser actually intended

it,

that always governs the interpretation of an equivocal

304

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.


;

[Chap.

XV.

promise

because, at that rate,

you miglit

excite expectations to satisfy.

which, you never meant, nor

would be obliged

Much

less

is

it

the sense in which the promisee actually

received the promise; for, according to that rule,

you might

be drawn into engagements you never designed to undertake.


It must, therefore, be the sense (for there
is

no other remain-

ing) in

which the promiser believed that the promisee accepted


^.'

his promise

Austin

^,

remarking on this passage of Paley,

says that

if this

rule be adopted, should the promiser misap-

prehend the sense in which the promisee accepted the promise,


either the promisee will be disappointed, or

he will get more


is

than he expects

and he suggests that the true guide


Paley's two
first

the

understanding of both parties.


are undoubtedly correct.

propositions

Austin's criticism, however, on what


is,

Paley considers as the only other possible alternative,


undoubtedly, sound.

as

But with the greatest


appears to

respect for so

high an authority,

it

me

that Austin, in his

own

suggestion, merely falls back on the old difficulty;


difiiculty

for the

only arises

when

the parties aver that they under-

stood the promise in different ways, which in every equivocal

promise

is,

of course, possible.
practical solution of the difiiculty
is,

How
tained in prac ice.

622.

The

I think,
is

simple enough.
(Jigtinction

Austin rightly points out that there

between the intention of the parties and the sense

of the promise,

and

it

is

the sense of the promise rather

than the intention of the parties which governs the contract.

Of

course the sense of the promise

may be

different to dif-

ferent persons;

the promiser

bear one sense, the promisee


another; and a stranger

may may

consider that his words

consider that they bear

may

consider that they bear a third.

But

the judge,

who has

to decide

what

legal obligation has

resulted from the transaction, determines


1

what the

sense

is.

iii. part i. chap. v. See Archbishop Whately's note, in which I find he arrives at the same conclusion as I do, namely, that the result of a promise may be different from what either party expected. ^ Lect. xxi., note, ad finem.

Paley, Moral Philosophy, book

Sec. 622, 623.]

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.

305

And
first

in doing this he

may

fairly use the assertions of the

parties themselves as a guide to his

own

conclusion.

Having

ascertained the terms in which the parties expressed

themselves, he

may

hear what each party says as to their

true interpretation, and

what each

respectively says he in-

tended by them; he

may

also consider

what

interpretation

would be put upon them by an uninterested man of ordinary


imderstanding.

He may

even go further, and consider the

surrounding circumstances, so far as they throw light upon


either the sense of the promise, or the intention of the pro-

miser, or the expectation of the promisee.

But

after all he
;

must put upon the words


intention.

his

own

interpretation

and from

the sense which he attaches to the words he must presume the

So that the current phrase 'the intention of


is

the parties governs the contract'


extent
;

really only true to this

that

it

governs the contract, where both parties are


intention

agreed what

the

was.

Where

there is a dis-

pute as to the intention, the contract, or rather the contractual


liability,
is

governed by the intention, as


all

it

is

presumed

from

that sense which, under

the

circum-

stances, the judge thinks

ought

fairly to be attached to the

promise.

623. For instance, suppose you wrote

me

a letter

offer-

ing to

buy 'my bay

horse,

if

warranted sound, for one


offer
;

hundred pounds,' and that I accepted the


I sent the horse to you with
fulfilment of the bargain.

whereupon

a written warranty as a
to dispute, whether

If

we were

the warranty I offered you was such a warranty as was


contemplated, the court would hear what you and I had
to say as to the

meaning
the

of the agreement,

and our
in
all

re-

spective intentions
bability decide,

and expectations; but would


sort

pro-

that

of warranty which
in such cases

I
;

was
that

bound to give was the usual warranty


being the warranty which a

man

of ordinary sense

and

understanding would expect under the circumstances.

And

whatever sense experienced persons usually attach to the word

: ;

306
'

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.


'

[Chap.

XV.
to

warranty

when dealing

in horses^ the court

would attach

it

in this ease,
to give,

and decide that that was the warranty I was


whatever protest you might make that that
to receive, or I

bound

was not what you expected


that was not

might make that

what

I intended to give.

624.
horse,

If,

indeed, after having agreed to purchase


to

my

hay

you wanted

make

out that your real intention was

to purchase

my

brown, the court would scarcely listen to you.

Suppose, however, that I have two


insisted that

bay

horses,

and you you

you had bought one, whilst I


other.

insisted that

had bought the


it

On
to

the words of the promise


discover whether
horses
;

itself

might be impossible

we
if

really in-

tended the same or different


which.
clear

and,

the

same,

But a very

little

further inquiry might possibly


It

up the whole matter.


horses, I

might turn out


to

that, of

my

two bay

had sent one

you

to

look at

that you had offered


horse,

me

seventy-five pounds for this

bay

and that I had insisted on having one


'

hundred
'

after which, your offer to purchase

hundred pounds was delivered.

my bay horse for one Now if nothing had ever


close

passed between us about the other horse, and your offer


of a hundred pounds
'

for

my

bay horse ' followed


all

upon

you would be considered to have bought that horse which had been sent to you for inspection. And the judge would come
that
to this conclusion, not because he
is

this negotiation, there

would be no doubt at

certain that this

was

what

I,

or

you,

or both

of us intended.

If

you

are a

person of high character for veracity, and you deny that this

was your

intention, the judge

would hesitate long before he


case

disbelieved

you.

But

in

this

the

doubt would

not

embarrass him.

He

concludes that no reasonable


to,

man would
fixes

suppose that any other horse was referred

and he

upon that horse accordingly.


625. This, I think,
is

the practical method which tribu-

nals adopt for deciding, in cases of dispute,


resulted

what

liability

has

from a

contract.

For this purpose they generally

Sec. 624-628.]

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.


interpretation-', which,

307
however,

adopt certain maxims of

generally conclude with a protest that these

maxims must

always yield to the evident intention of the parties.


is

What

here called the

'

evident intention of the parties

'

is

that pre-

sumed intention which, as I have said before, the judge takes from the interpretation, which interpretation may possibly conflict

with one or another of the generally accepted maxims

^.

626. I shall

now

discuss a very peculiar rule of English Consider-

law, which I shall have to examine at some length.

The

Enghsh law

says that there

is

no habUity upon a contract,


conditions

unless the contract fulfils one of two


either that it
is

namely,
it is
'

made upon a
seal.

'

consideration,' or that

contained in a deed under


627.

A contract,

we
is

are told,

is

made upon

'

consideration

What is
^*i"-

when some thing


by one party

done, forborne, suffered, or undertaken, consideris

at the request of another, which

made the

foundation of the promise of that other.

628. This rule about consideration

is

not recognised by any ConsiderIt


is euliar to
'^

other system of law in the modern or ancient world.

only recognised in England and in those countries which have j JJ^ It is not recognised in Scotland. derived it from England.

The

opinions of jurists may, therefore, be fairly said to be

divided as to the usefulness of the rule, and under these


^

See Chitty on Contracts, oh.


It is

i.

sect. 3. par. 4,

where these maxims are


for the interpretation of

collected.

common
;

to transfer the

maxims

and contracts from one to the other without very but I doubt whether the interpretation of these three classes of documents proceeds upon precisely the same principles. ^ Inasmuch as wherever the sense of the promise differs from the intention of the parties, or of one of them, there is not, strictly speaking, an agreement, it has been proposed to remodel the conception of contract, and leave out consensus altogether. This would entail a stupendous modification of legal language and I do not think it would lead to any Not only in contract but in the enormous number of satisfactory result. cases in which intention or knowledge enters into the grounds of liability there is a chance that the court may go wrong in ascertaining what passed in the mind of the person concerned. But that is no ground for as it is declining to treat the presumed intention as the real intention
wills, conveyances,

careful discrimination

'

'

in fact in the vast majority of cases.

X %

'

SOS

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.

[Chap. XV.

eireumstances one
of presumption.

may

criticise

the rule without being guilty

Meaning
of the rule,

629. In order to ascertain,

i possible,

what

is

the principle

on which the rule proceeds,


often occurs.

let

us take a simple case which

A father

says to his son that he will give If the father refuses to

him

a certain sum, say 1000.

fulfil this

promise the son cannot sue his father.

If the father writes


it, still

out the promise in the most formal manner and signs the son cannot sue the father.
to the
paid.

If the father afl&xes his seal


if

document then the son can sue him,

the

money is not

Such

is

the law of England.


it ?

Can a

rational explana-

tion be given of
Gratuitous promises.

630.

We

must be

careful not to confound the rules about

consideration with the rules relating to gratuitous promises.

gratuitous promise

is

obviously a transaction which the

law will regard with some suspicion.


reasons for jealousy in

There are the same


promises
as of

regard to

gratuitous

there are for jealousy in regard to gifts.

But then many

these reasons are as strong against gratuitous promises

made

in a deed under seal as they are against gratuitous promises

made

in writing without seal or

by

parol.

Accordingly we
legal result

find in English law special rules of gratuitous promises in every

whereby the

form are regulated. upon a

But the
different

rule as to consideration evidently proceeds


principle

from

this, for it says

nothing whatever about in-

validating the legal result of gratuitous proinises provided

they are made in a particular form.

How applied to deeds.

631.

The reason which

is

given

by English

lawyers,

why

the father should not be liable to be sued by the son in the

two

first

of the above cases,

and should be
'

liable to

be sued This

in the last, is that

the deed

imports consideration.''

points to an attempt to

make

it

appear that the English law

in all cases consistently requires a 'consideration^ in order

that a promise
is
is

may
way

be sued on.

Yet
'

it

is

obvious that this


consideration

only a pretence.

To say that a deed imports

only another

of saying that a promise under seal

may

: :

Sec. 629-635.]

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.


Moreover
if it

309

be sued on without consideration.

were of

importance to ascertain whether the deed were gratuitous, the


notion that a deed
disregarded.
'

imports consideration ' would be wholly

632. Again,

if

we

turn to promises not under seal


is

we

see Adequacy

that though a consideration


insisted

necessary, yet

it is

constantly inquired'
^'^**

on that no inquiry can be made as to the adequacy of


All that
is

the consideration.

necessary

is

a consideration in

form.

If

promises

a thousand pounds for nothing in


If he promises
it

return the promise cannot be sued on.

thousand pounds in return for a peppercorn

can be sued on.

Yet both these promises are gratuitous.


633. It
is

clear therefore that consideration has nothing

whatever to do with the question whether or no the promise


is

gratuitous.

A promise may

be purely gratuitous, and yet,

being based upon a merely nominal consideration,


rise to liability.

may

give

634.

What then
(a) that

is

the real explanation of these three things


is

(i) that

a contract under seal

enforceable without considerais

tion;

a contract not under seal

not enforceable

without consideration ; (3) that it is entirely indifferent whether the consideration be of any value or not ?
635.

The only
is

rational

and

consistent' explanation of these Suggested


is

three things

that the question

really one of form.

The

{^''^th"'

being under

seal or
it

not

is

as pure a matter of

form as can

be. 1'

And how

can

be a matter of substance to require as a con-

sideration that

which

may

be of absolutely no value?

of

course bearing in

mind that

these things have nothing to do

with the contract being gratuitous.


these things are both important.

As a matter of form The form of a deed is


is

a sure indication that the parties contemplated a legal relation


the form of a bargain, or giving a quid pro quo,
clusive,

not con-

but

it is, certainly,

useful as an indication that the


:

parties contemplated a legal relation

but no one would deny

that there are

many cases where a legal relation is contemplated,


is

in which, nevertheless, there

no consideration.


310

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.

[Chap.

XV.
to

636. Where^ therefore^ the English law seems to

me

have gone wrong

is

this

that which

is

a mere matter of form


is

has been used for a wrong purpose ; that which

only one out


it

of several possible indications has been used as if


sole test.

were the

Consequently the judges are every


difficulty
;

now and then

thrown into the greatest


results

they are either driven to

which are obviously, even

to themselves, unsatisfactory,

or they have to avoid these objectionable results

by reasoning

which would not be accepted under any other circumstances.


Promises

637. There

is,

for example, a class of cases not unfrequently

which a

man

is

occurring in which

A and _5 have made mutual promises. As is


is

aheady bound to
perform.

usual in such cases the promise on one side

the consideration
is

for the promise on the other, but a difficulty

raised

by

showing that what


already bound

has promised
to do.

is

something which he was


that there
is

by law

To the argument

a promise

by

B in

return for the promise

by A, and that the

court will not look into the adequacy of the consideration,

the judges, viewing the consideration as a condition of liability,


feel obliged to reply that

they

still

cannot acknowledge a con-

sideration

which

is

obvioudy worthless.

638.

As
:

a specimen of this class of cases I

may

take the

following

said to his

marry Z, that on
a
year.

his

nephew B^ who was engaged to marriage he would allow him ioo


difficulty in

There was no

construing this as a

promise by

^ to J
by

that he would marry


to

X if he
A

obtained the

annuity, and

5 that

if

he did so

would make him

the allowance stated.

Accordingly
paid.

did marry X, and for


died,

some time the annuity was


called

At length A

and

upon

A's.

executors to pay an instalment of the annuity

which had

fallen

due in ^^s

lifetime.

The executors refused


suit

to pay, denying the liability of A.

In the

which followed,

the decision turned upon whether there was any consideration


for the promise of A.

The mere promise of ^ to ^ that he would marry X, being a promise by B to do something to which he was already bound, was, in accordance with numerous
decisions, said to be not

a consideration

and the most

in-

Sec. 636-640.]

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.

311

genious suggestions were made to show


particular case have
simpler^

how

it

might

in this

become

so.

It

would have been much


facts, and, I

more in accordance with the

venture to

think,

more

reasonable, to hold that the case was one in

which

legal liability
liability

was

clearly contemplated

by the

parties,

and
an

ought therefore, for that reason, to be enforced^


set

639. Another

of cases, of which the following

is

Part con-

example, has been found equally embarrassing -.B at the


request of

handed him over a

letter,

by means
plaintiff.

of which

gained an action in which he was then

did not

promise anything to
to give

B at the time, but afterwards he promised


'

Ba

thousand pounds for letting him have the letter ^,


consideration
'

Of

course there was no


is

for his promise,

and

if

consideration

necessary the suit ought to have been dismissed,

which

it

was

not.

And

to dismiss the suit

would have been

so obviously unjust that very ingenious

arguments have been

produced in support of the decision.


convincing.

They

are

not very

Surely

it

would be only common sense in such

a case as this to hold that the parties intended to


legally binding contract,

make

and that they had done

so.

640. It has been said in reference to cases of this kind that


it is

not reasonable that one

man

should do another a kindness


for
it.

and then charge him a recompense

Nothing could be
he had of

more unreasonable

but nothing of the sort would be done in

any
his

case where the promiser

was made

liable because

own

consent undertaken a legal

liability.

If the handing

of the letter in the case I have referred to was a kindness,

probably the promise of


*

1000 might have been


v.

a kindness

The

case referred to is that of Shadwell

mon Bench
Anson on
p. 177.
^

Reports,

New

Series, vol. ix. p. 159.


;

Contracts, 7th ed. p. 90

Shadwell, reported in ComSee the observations in and in Pollock on Contracts, 5th ed.

The case
i.

is

that of Wilkinson

v.

Oliveira, reported in

Bingham's

New

The case seems generally to have been understood as I have stated it and this view of it is borne out by the pleadings as stated in the report. The argument, however, and the decision do not proceed entirely upon this ground. See Pollock on Contracts, 5th ed. Anson on Contracts, 7th ed. p. ^6. p. 169
Cases, vol.
p. 490.
: ;

312
also.

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT,


But the court thought otherwise
:

[Chap.

XV.

and I think pay

it will

be generally agreed that a

man ought

to

for a service per-

formed at his request^ and also that he ought to pay whatever


he has himself deliberately estimated as the value of the service.
641. There are

many

other cases in which promises have

been held to create

liability,
'

but in which
'

it

has been found


for ex-

very hard to discover a

consideration

promises,

ample, by a person of full age to pay a debt contracted during

infancy ; promises by a bankrupt to pay debts from which he

has been discharged

promises by a widow to pay debts con-

tracted during her marriage; promises to

pay debts barred by


in

the statute of limitations.

In

all

these cases a variety of

ingenious

suggestions have been

made

order to

make
simple

decisions square with the doctrine of consideration.

suggestion which explains

them

all is

that they were

all cases

in which the promiser himself intended to create


liability
^.

a legal

Contracts
^gjjt

642. Perhaps the boldest discovery of a


in

'

consideration

'

is

those

eases

where the court has enforced a gratuitous


It
'

promise to take charge of property.


in such cases a consideration because

is

said that there is

the owner's trusting

him with the goods


to a careful to understand
Oases in
there is no consideration.

is

a sufficient consideration to oblige

him

management.'

I give the words, I do not profess

them ^.
to cases in

643. If
denied

we now turn

which the

liability

has been
rest

we

shall find the reasoning

on which the decisions

equally

unsatisfactory.

Thus,

suppose

that A, as a pure

matter of business,
Promise
offer

offers to sell

goods to B, and expressly


till

agrees to let this offer remain open

the next day at the


the goods.
It has

open, same hour, and in the meantime not to

sell

been held that


has expired he
'

if
is

A nevertheless
not
liable,

sells

the goods before the time


is

because there

no consideration

See these cases collected and discussed in Anson on Contracts, and

ed. p. lo.
^

The words

are those of

no

less

a judge than Lord Holt, and they have

received repeated approbation.


189, 205, 207.

See Smith's Leading Cases, 7th ed. pp.


Sec. 641-645.]

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.


sell.

313

for the promise not to

Every

one, I think,

unsatisfactory nature of this conclusion.


perfectly unobjectionable,
one.

must feel the The arrangement is


an expensive

and in many
seal,

cases a very convenient


is

It

might be made under


affair, quite

but a deed

and troublesome
this.

unsuited for such a transaction as

The

parties clearly intended that the transaction should


result,

have a legal

and

it

would be far more satisfactory

if it

were enforced.
644.
:

T n "Lii ing A was guardian tor a minor, who had ready money was required for the management
.

representative case of another class

is

the followI y J

So-called

property, but
of
it,

moral consideration.

and for

the maintenance and education of the minor.

Accordingly the

guardian borrowed money on his

own

security.

When

the

minor came of age she promised to repay the money, but


soon afterwards she married, and then her husband,

who
it.

had had the

benefit of her property, promised to repay

Upon

this

promise the

husband was

sued-'.

There were

similar cases in

which the promise had been enforced, but

these cases were overruled;


sideration for the promise
lie
it

and because there was no conwas held that no action would


been regarded.
It was,

upon

it.

I have never been able to understand the satis-

faction with

which

this result has

no doubt, a triumph of the doctrine of consideration, but


a triumph gained at the clear expense of
justice.

Surely

it

might have been better


had
held, that
:

held, as in fact the previous cases


liability

an express undertaking of a

was

binding

not, however,

upon the stupid ground that a moral


to be enforced
2.

consideration supports a promise, but upon the ground that

liability

was intended and ought

645.
'

very curious result of the doctrine of consideration Account


stated.

See the case of Eastwood 1). Kenyon, reported in Adolphus and Ellis' Eeports, vol. xi. p. 446, oTerruling the decision of Sir James Mansfield in
v. Muggeridge, in Taunton's Reports, vol. v. p. 36. been suggested that Lord Mansfield formulated the doctrine that consideration vras only one of various modes by which it could be proved that the parties intended a contract (Anson on Contracts, 7th ed., I wish I could think so, but I have never found it in any decision p. 104).

the case of Lee


2

It has

of that

eminent judge.

314
is

LIABILITY UPON CONTBACT.


the following:

[Chap.

XV.

Supposing

that

and

B
:

having had

dealings together go over the account between them, and

agree to strike a balance at

agrees to pay that


this

500 as due to A sum upon request. B


But suppose that

and thereupon
to

is liable

if

he breaks

promise.

says he will

pay the money that day week.


promise because there
culous result (for
is,

is

not liable upon this


it.

is

no consideration for

This

ridi-

it is

impossible to describe

it

as otherwise)

I have

no doubt, a logical deduction from the English

rules

about consideration, and I have no doubt that the

exceedingly acute judges,

who

so

laid

down

the law, were

only actuated by the fear of letting the whole 'fabric of


consideration " fall to the ground

had they decided otherwise.

Now

what would have been the

result if instead of inquiring

whether there was a 'consideration' the judges had inquired


whether, in accordance with Savigny's definition, the parties

contemplated a transaction which would

create

liabiHty

The

result

would be that both promises would be considered


which might be sued
on.

as promises
result
Eeleaae of

And
'^-

this is the only

which accords with common sense

646. The last illustration I shall give of the unsatisfactory


nature of the doctrine of
'

consideration'

is

the perpetual and,

apparently at this moment, unsuccessful struggle to hold


persons bound

by a gratuitous promise
kind should,
of

to forgive a debt.

Promises

of
as

this
all

course,

be as jealously

watched
is

other gratuitous promises.

But

this object

not effected by saying, as the English law says, that a


it

debt, whilst

may

not be simply forgiven,


of a peppercorn^.

may be
The

discharged

by the handing over

true

way

to

deal with such cases would be to accept the inevitable conclusion that the parties to such a transaction

had in conto

templation their

legal

relations

and

to

aUow them

regulate these as they think proper, subject to any whole^

vol. of
"

The case referred to is that of Hopkins . Logan, reported in the 5th Meesou and Welsby's Reports, p. 241.
See Smith's Leading Cases, vol.
p. 197.
i.

p. 341,

and Pollock on Contracts,

3rd ed.

The absurdity

is

here admitted.

Sec. 64&-648.]

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.


against
gratuitous
disposal that

315

some

restrictions

may

be

found desirable^.
647.

The

result

which I have arrived at from a perusal of

Conolu-

the decisions of English judges upon the question of consideration is that it is impossible to apply it as a test of legal
liability

with consistency and with justice


test,

that

it

can only
:

properly be treated, not as a


indication, but

but as an indication

an

an indication

only,

amongst many

others, that

the parties entering into a transaction had in contemplation


their legal relations to each other
^.

648. The question, whether or no, notwithstanding the

Gratuit-

intention of the parties, the breach of a gratuitous promise misea.

should create any liability

is,

as I have said, a totally distinct

one

and

it is

obvious that in order to deal satisfactorily with

this question the notion that the

adequacy of the consideraIt

tion

is

not to be inquired into must be entirely discarded.

would be absurd when you are considering the


gifts to look

validity of

looo in return for a peppercorn otherwise than as a gift of iooo or to look upon the acceptance from a solvent man of 40 in lieu of 100 otherwise than as a gift of 60 ; or at the payment of %oos.
upon a promise
of
;

for a quarter of
gift of 160s.

wheat worth only

40*. otherwise

than as a

But by the
'

generality of the rule forbidding

judges to look into the adequacy of consideration, and by the


notion that a deed
'

imports ' consideration, the English law


which appears
to be con-

One

of the strange anomalies in English law

nected with the doctrine that a contract cannot be enforced without consideration is this that if I give a direction, whether by deed or not, that property of which I haTe a right to dispose shall be handed on to a person
:

I wish to benefit, that will be valid without any consideration but I attempt to give a security upon the same property, even by deed, and where there is no doubt whatever as to the animus donandi, that will not be valid without consideration. This certainly looks very like a frivolous technicality.' See Law Quarterly Eeview, vol. vii. p. 103. " It will probably be long before the doctrine propounded in the text
;

whom
if

'

will be accepted

by English

lav^yers.

am, however, glad to see that a

recent learned wi'iter agrees with me that the true function of consideration is ' evidence that a promise was intended to be binding.' Anson on Contracts, 7th ed. p. 104. This, to my mind, leads strongly to the conclusion that other indications of intention should not be shut out.

316

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.


gifts.

[Chap.

XV.

has obscured and confused the subject of


all

In almost

systems, in the

Roman

law-', in the Preussisches

Land-

Recht^, in the French Code CiviP, in the Italian Civil

Code *, even in the Mahommedan law


treated
actually
fully,

we

find the subject

and

for the

most part

satisfactorily.

Gifts

made

are under certain circumstances revocable or

void

gifts not yet

made can under


it

certain restrictions be en-

forced.

The English law, where

has dealt with gifts apart

from the question of consideration, has mixed them up with Thus if a husband being insolvent the question of fraud.
gives his
is

money

to his wife instead of to his creditors, this


:

obviously a transaction which ought to be set aside

and

it

may
still

be a fraud

it

would be

so, if

there were a secret under-

standing between the husband and wife that the


belong to the husband.

money should
set aside

But

it

ought

to

be

even

although there was a real transfer and no fraud.


gained by

An insolvent

ought not to be allowed to make either real gifts or pretended


ones
:

and nothing

is

'

presuming fraud.
'

Void and
contracts,

649. I have already

made some
"

observations

upon the

terms

'

void

'

and

'

voidable
is

as applied to legal transactions,

and the care that

necessary in distinguishing the various


are

modifications of the result of a transaction which


scribed

de-

by these terms ".


contract's.

This care

is

especially required in

the case of

650. The principal circumstances which modify the result


of a contract are defects of form, absence of consideration,
illegality, infancy, mistake, fraud, misrepresentation, duress,

and undue
Defects of form.

influence.

651. There has been a long pending discussion, not yet


closed, as to

whether contracts defective in form are to be

considered as void.
'

The

discussion has, I think, been com(Ledlie's Translation), p. 138.

See Sohm's Institutes of


Preuss. L.-R. Part
i.

Roman Law

'^

Tit. xi. 1037-1077.

"

Co. Civ. Ai-t. 893 sqq.

* Codice Civile, Art. 1050 seqq. Perron, Precis de Jurisprudence Musulmane, vol. v. pp. 64 sqq.

See supra, sect. 274.

Sec. 649-654-]

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.

317

plicated

by
'

its
is

not being clearly agreed in what sense the


to be used.

word

'

void

Many

persons

who deny

that

contracts defective in
to
say, that they are

form are

void, apparently only

mean
result.

not entirely devoid of legal

Other persons seem to mean when they assert that they


are void that they do not produce the legal result contemplated.

Of

course,

it

is

possible

that

the same contract

should be void in the last of these two senses and not so in the first. In fact I have little doubt that every contract
defective in point of form
senses
;

is

void in the last of these two


is

whereas a contract hardly ever


is

so in the

first.

652. There
is

another meaning in which the word 'void''


It
is

sometimes used as applied to contracts.


that

sometimes

said

a contract

is

void,

even when as between the


it, if

parties themselves

an action can be brought upon


it.

third

persons cannot acquire rights under

This

is

a peculiar

condition of things which sometimes occurs, but I do not


see

why

under such circumstances the contract should be

called void.

653.

What
is

I have
'

said

as

to

the uncertainty of the Nou-eom-

meaning
in form
arisen

of the term

void

'

as applied to contracts defective ^ith Sta'

well illustrated

by

certain discussions

which have

i?*'

j^

Frauds.

upon the Statute of Frauds.

In consequence of a
sect.

slight difference
sect.

between the language of

4 and that

of

17

it

has been said that contracts under

sect.

made void
654.
called
sect.
'

for a defect in form, whereas the very


sect. 17.

4 same defect

are not

makes void contracts under

But
void
'

is

there any sense in which a contract could be


sect.

under

17 for a defect of form and not under

4?

know
is

of none.

In the sense that the transaction


In the sense of
is

does not produce the liability which the parties contemplated

the contract

void under both sections.

producing no legal result whatever, the contract


either under sect. 17 or under sect. 4.
offers to
offer.
sell
is

not void
verbally

Thus, suppose

a horse for 50, and


falls

verbally accepts the


1 7,

This

a case which

within sect.

and the contract

318

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.

[Chap.

XV.

not being in writing does not render


if

A
is,

liable to

be sued by

he refuses to deliver the horse.


it

It

therefore,

undoubtedly

void in the sense that


templated.
says,
'

does not produce the liability con-

But suppose that

afterwards writes to
is

and

the horse you bought of

me

waiting in the stable for

you

to take

him away.'
sued.
it

This does not

make

new

contract,

but the contract originally made immediately becomes one upon

which

A may be

The

contract, therefore,

was

clearly not

void in the sense that 655.


of

has produced no legal result whatever.


sect. 4.

Now take
to

a case under
G.

promises

B by word

mouth
it is

pay the debt of


be
it

It is said that this is not void;


it is

that

a contract, although

not clothed in the necessary

form.

It

may
But

so.

That depends upon how you define a


which

contract.

certainly does not produce the result

the parties contemplated, namely, that the promise should be


enforceable against the promiser.

656. I do not say that the legal results of a defect of form

under the two sections are the same.


nothing.

As

to

that I say
'

The

decision in the

well-known case of

Leroux

v.

Brown
on

^,'

that a verbal contract

made

in France

may

be sued
sect. 17,

if it falls

within

sect.

4 and not

if it falls

within

may

or

may not

be correct ; but in either case the observations

which I have just made will hold good.


657. Absence of consideration renders a contract void in the sense that
liability
it

prevents the agreement from producing the

contemplated both as between the promiser and proas

misee,

and

between the promiser and any other persons.

658. Illegality also renders a contract void in this sense,


and, as far as possible, courts of law deprive an illegal contract of all legal results whatsoever.

Transfer of contractual
liability.

659. It

is

frequently said that a person

who

is

not a party

to the agreement

which

is

the basis of the contract cannot

incur any liability under the contract;

and that likewise a

person

who
'

is

not a party to the agreement cannot enforce

Reported in

Common Bench

Reports, vol.

xii. p. 801.

Sec. 655-663.J

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.


under
it.

319
is

any
to

liability

Of

course no one

who

not a party

an agreement can incur any

liability, or acquire

any right
not

to enforce a liability,

by reason
is

of his consent to that agreeit

ment.

If any liability

imposed upon him

must

be,

because of his consent to that agreement, but for some other


reason.

660. But a promise by


able

to jB is very often

enforce-

by

B
'

against C, and a promise

made by

to

is

very
is

often enforceable against I)

by

F.

And

if

this is

what

meant by

liability

under the

contract,''

the rule as above laid

down
in

is

subject to so

many

exceptions, that I hardly think it


all.

ought to appear as a

rule at

There are multitudes of cases

which the

heir, executor, administrator, or assignee of the

party to a contract

may

incur liability, or acquire a right to

enforce liability, under a contract to which he was no party.

661.

Much, no doubt,

will

depend upon what appears to


parties.

have been the intention of the

If the intention

was

that the liability should exist only as between the two original
parties to the contract it will not be extended.

662. It used to be said in somewhat barbarous language


that contracts are choses in action, and that choses in action
are not assignable at
able
in

common
that

law, but that they are assigncourts

equity.

Now

all

administer equity I
;

think that this

language might be well dropped

and that

the rule should be stated generally that the right and obligation under a contract are both assignable, unless
it

appears

that the parties to the contract intended otherwise.


will sometimes appear

This

by the words used and sometimes by

the nature of the transaction.

promise, for example, to

perform

personal services is one in

which the

liability

cannot

be transferred.
663. It has also been frequently said that to create
liability Offer

and
'

under a contract there

must be an
other.

offer

by one of the
is

parties ^nce^

and an acceptance by the


the same time liability

This I think

true.

At

may
it

be created by an
is

offer

and someThus,

thing which ensues upon

which

not an acceptance.

320
Reward
lost pro-

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.


offers

[Chap. XV.

if

a reward for the recovery of lost property, and

''^ho

has never heard of the offer restores the property, he


sue

perty.

may

on the promise.

I think, however, that though


is

sues on the promise there

no real contract, but only

what may be

called quasi-contract.
is

The reason

for calling it

a quasi-contract

that
if

and

JB are as nearly as possible in

the same position as

they had made a contract.

663
if it is

a.

Of

course

if

having heard of the

offer accepts it,

even though that acceptance be not at once communicated to A,

communicated before the


:

offer is revoked, there is

complete offer and acceptance


if

the case would be more difficult


it

the offer had been revoked before

was accepted, and the


_B,

revocation had not been communicated to

but I apprehend

that the true principle


is

is

that an uneommunicated revocation

no revocation at
664. There
is

all

'.

TJndisclosed principal

another case in which liability exists which

is is

certainly very like contractual liability, but in

which there
you.''
is

no

offer

and acceptance.
is

A says
j

to

.5,

'

I contract with
of C.
is

In truth
a

making the contract on behalf


a
liability

There

liability of

A to C, and of C to ^
C.

which

generally

called liability ex contractu.

between

A and

Not only
of

But nothing whatever has passed (to use the expression of Lord
it

Cairns), the

mind
^.

never rested on C, but

rested on

another person

Liabilityis a

665. The liability of the promiser to

fulfil his

promise

is

thing

object of ownership.

and

thmg and from

its

being capable of being bought and sold,


its

assigned and transferred like other things, and also from

having a money value,


ownership.

it

is

looked upon as the object of

Lumley
Gye.

u.

666. The view of liability that


object of ownership, that
it is

it is

a thing which

is

the

in fact property, leads natur-

ally to the conclusion that, like other property, it is protected

by the law which would damage it.


'

prohibits certain acts being done

which

This, I take
644 note.

it, is

the true explanation of


"

See supra,

sect.

See

746.

Sec. 663a-666.]

LIABILITY UPON CONTRACT.


versus

321

the case of

Lumley

Gye ^,

in

which the defendant was


a promise to

held liable for having^ with the intention to cause damage to


the plaintiff, induced a person

who had made

the plaintiff not to


plaintiff's

fulfil

it.

This was an injury to the

property

^-

Reported in Ellis and Blackburn's Reports, vol. ii. p. 216. It is because the liability or obligation is the object of ownership that contract is said to create a right in rem as well as a right in personam. See Anson on Contracts, 7th ed. p. 227.
'

"

CHAPTEE

XVI.

LIABILITY FOR TORT.


667. In the

same way as the examination of


an analysis of

liability

ex contractu involves an analysis of contract, so the examination of liability ex delicto involves


tort.

delict or

am
is

therefore brought face to face vpith that

most

difficult of all questions

What

is

a tort

Tort and

668. It

not necessary that tort and delict should be


expressions,
so.

exactly equivalent

but I think that they are


is,

understood to be

Liability for a tort

I think, con-

sidered to be equivalent to liability ex delicto, but the


'

word
"

tort '

is

more in common

use with us than the


is

word

'

delict.

rrench
of delict,

669.
there
is

On

the continent the word 'tort^

not used, but


'Delicts,^

in the

French Civil Code a chapter headed

which would lead us to suppose that we should


there fully defined.
All, however, that I
is

find delicts

am

able to infer

from what

is

there said

that a delict

is

an act of one

man

which causes damage to another, provided that the act be


done intentionally, negligently, or imprudently.
acts so done give rise to liability
is,

That some
but one
is,

no doubt,

true,

at least of the principal terms used in this description

as

I shall show presently, exceedingly vague, and

it is

certain

that

many
;

acts

which

this

description

would cover are not

delicts

nay more, that many


^.

acts so done do not give rise to

any
'

liability at all
clauses
are

The

as follows.

Art. 1382

'

Tout

fait

quelconque de

rhomme, qui
il

cause \ autrui

est arriv6 & le r^parer.'


qu'il a caus6,

un dommage, oblige celui par la faute duquel Art. 1383 Chacun est responsable du dom: '

mage

non seulement par son

gence, ou par son imprudence.'

fait, mais encore par sa negliSee Pothier, Introduction G6n6rale aux

Coutumes,

sect.

116; Traits des Obligations, sect. 116; and Les Codes

Annot^s de

Sirey, par R. Gilbert, Paris, 1859.

LIABILITY FOE TORT.


670. English lawyers have not yet
define torts
^,

323
to

made any attempt

and I therefore proceed

to

examine the phrases

common use among lawyers when they wish to give their reasons why liability ex delicto exists in some cases and not
in
in others
;

and

also the various terms

by which they describe

events which give rise to this liability, and by which they


distinguish events which do not give rise to
671.
torts
it.

We

generally find that those acts which are called


considered with reference to the obligation which
are,

when

results

from them

when

considered with reference to the

nature of the act

itself, called injuries;


'

and a good deal

is

made

of this

word injury/

as

if it,

in itself, told us a

good

Injury.

deal about the matter.

We are told over and


must be
that
it is
is

over again, that

in order that a

man
a

should be liable for any damage, on the


injury.

ground that
injury
?

it is

tort, there

But what

is

All

we know

of

it is

the infringement of

a right.
sense of

I believe also that injury

here used in the special

an infringement

of one or other of those rights

which

relate to property, or personal security, or reputation.

But

what
If

are those rights

I have never yet found

them

described.

we knew them, then we

should also

know

the duties and

obligations to which they correspond, and our difliculty would

be solved.
672.

When
we

something

more

definite

than

this

is

at- Qualifying

tempted,
is is

generally find that the act or omission, which

said to be

an injury,

is

qualified

by some adverb which


I find the

apparently intended to indicate that which constitutes the

required test of liability.

Amongst such adverbs


dishonestly,

following

fraudulently,

maliciously (avec pre-

' See however the recent discussions in Pollock on Torts, and Bigelow on Torts. I scarcely think the difficulty of arriving at a definition has been surmounted, but the labours of these two learned authors have contributed largely to a clearer understanding of tort. Sir Frederick PoUook,

Wrongs Bill for India, lays it down that 'every one commits a wrong who harms another by an act intended to cause harm.' But surely the law knows no such broad general principle. Evil-disposed persons can commit any amount of mischief with the most malicious intentions without any risk of coming within the reach of the law.
in his draft of a Civil

ya

324

LIABILITY FOR TORT.

[Chap. XVI.

meditation, avec de guet-a-pens), knowingly, intentionally,

wantonly, malignantly, rashly, negligently, wilfully, wickedly,


imprudently, and clumsily (par maladresse).

So

also I find

used such adverbs as forcibly, with a strong hand, violently


(avec
or in
violence
et

voies

de

fait),

riotously,

tumultuously,

large

numbers (par attroupement).


find such expressions

Again, for the


use of as wronginjuriously,

same purpose I
fully,

made

feloniously,
^.

unlawfully,

illegally,

and

unjustly

673. I have purposely selected these adverbs, as well from

the descriptions of those acts which are called crimes, as from


the descriptions of the similar acts which are called delicts
or torts, without
liability

any attempt

at discrimination.

For criminal
Criminal

and

civil hability

do not radically

differ.

liability generally

comprehends

civil liability also,

combined

with some additional element which, for our present purpose,


is

not of importance.
674. Considering these adverbs,
it

What
adverbs
express,

appears to

me

that they

may

be divided into three classes, which are indicated by the

^^(jer in

which I have enumerated them


which
are, apparently,

as follows

First, those

intended to express the


does the act.

condition of

mind

of the person

who

Secondly, those

which

are,

apparently,

not intended to

characterise the act simply as the occasion of liability, but

which are intended


aggravation

to express
is

what

is

commonly

called

an

that

to say, to

mark

the act as giving rise

to a special secondary or sanctioning obligation of a serious

kind.

Thirdly, those which are, apparently, intended to express

something, but really express nothing at

all

being only so

many different names for we are trying to discover.


675.
^

the very thing the nature of which

The terms

of the second class can be of

no assistance

adverbs also make their appearance in Codes, and other legislative productions, but I think they mostly originated vrith judges. At any rate I have been desirous to gather together every mark of liability that can claim authority, from whatever source it may proceed.

Many of these


Sec. 673-678.]

LIABILITY FOE. TORT.

325

to us here.

We

are considering not the nature of the conis liable,

sequences to which a party


at
all.

but whether he

is

Hable

The adverbs

of the first class, therefore, are those


liability.

from which we have to derive our conception of

Most
of

of the terms of the

first class

refer to the condition


liable at the point

mind

of the person sought to be

made

of time

when

his conduct is considered;

and two

of

them

'knowingly^ and 'intentionally"


tion.

only

describe that condi-

The

rest, or

most of the

rest,

combine with this purely


less

mental element an element of another kind: they more or

imply that the state of mind under consideration is, when tried by some standard which the person using the expression has in view, not what it ought to be. What this standard is it
is

not easy to discover, but

it is

something in the nature of

a moral standard.
676. In a former chapter^ I analysed as well as I was
able, the

mental attitude of the doer of an

act,

and the

relation of that attitude to the result.

As

I there showed,

man may

advert to the consequences of his acts, or he


If he adverts to them, he
;

not advert to them.


or
to

may may desire them

may

not desire them to happen

if

he does not desire them


:

happen he

may

still

expect

them mind

or stUl adverting to

them he may
terms

neither desire

them nor expect them.


are

677. These several states of

expressed

by the

intention, knowledge, advertence,

and inadvertence.
they accompany

678. Intention, knowledge, advertence, and inadvertence,

do not always give

rise to liability,

even

if

an act which causes damage.


to

If I do an act with the desire


if

harm

another, I shall only be liable

the law forbids


likely to

that act.

So

I do an act which I know to be

injure another.

And,

if

I advert to the consequences of


if

my
the

act without desiring or expecting them, or


to the consequences of

I do not advert
liable if

my

act, I shall

only be

occasion be one

upon which the law requires from me a

certain

degree of circumspection, which I have failed to exercise.


1

In

Chap. VI.

326

LIABILITY FOE. TORT.

[Chap. XVI.
is

the case of advertence this culpable want of circumspection


called rashness
;

in the case of inadvertence

it is

called heed-

lessness
Negligence.

^.

679. Bearing this in mind


adverbs above enumerated.

let

us revert to the

first class

of

Of

all these,

the adverb in most


v?ritten

common

use

is

'

negligently.'

Books have been

upon

negligence, and hundreds of reported cases are wholly taken

up with the

discussion of

it.

It

is,
it.

therefore, of the last

importance thoroughly to examine

How

op-

680^.

When

negligence expresses a state of the mind (for,


hereafter, it does not always express a state
all),

intention, as I shall

of the

show mind at

it is

opposed to intention; and


either of the

it

ex-

presses without distinction

two conditions of
with reference
act.

mind which I have


more generally the

called rashness
latter.

and heedlessness; but


an

It

is

also used

to the not doing as well as the doing of


is

Thus

it

said that death, ensuing in consequence of the malicious

omission of a duty, will be murder, but that death, ensuing


in consequence of the omission of a duty

which arose from

negligence, will

be

only

manslaughter

^.

By

malicious

omission

of a duty I understand to

be here meant, that

we omit to do an act which we are commanded to do, that we advert to the consequences of the omission, and that we expect these consequences to ensue, though not necessarily desiring those consequences, either as

an end, or as

means

to

an end.

By

negligent omission of a duty I under-

stand to be here meant, that

we omit

to do

an act which

we

are

consequences

commanded to do, either without adverting to the when we ought to have adverted to them
heedlessly

that
'

is,

or,

adverting to them, but expecting on


is,

insufficient
Supra,

groundsthat

rashly

that they

will not ensue.

sects. 226, 228.

^
'

Austin, Leot. xx. p. 444 (3rd ed.). See also supra, Chap. VI. The distinction between murder and manslaughter is thus drawn in

the case of the Queen against Hughes, by Lord Campbell delivering the considered judgment of five judges. See Dearsley and Bell's Crown Cases,
p. 249.
*

See infra,

sect. 686.

Sec. 679-681.]

LIABILITY FOR TORT.

327

So again we

find it said in discussions about negligence, that


is

negligence alone

not a sufficient cause of action without

a breach of duty^, which I understand to mean that


consequences which

when

we

did not intend or

ensue upon an act or omission,

know then we are

to be likely
liable if

we

were heedless in disregarding those consequences, or rash


in the expectation that they

would not ensue.

Negligence

therefore, so far, seems to be only a general expression for

rashness and heedlessness.


681.
of the

But

in the latest

and most authoritative expositions


find quite a different
is

Later exof its

term negligence, we

meaning

attached to the term.

NegHgenee

declared to describe, *'s-

not the state of mind of the party who does or does not

do the act; not the absence from his mind of certain ideas

which might have led him into a


or inaction,

different course of action

which

state of

mind he might have


recalled

avoided,

and which

ideas he

might have

by a proper use
grounded

of his faculties

not

in short that

which I understand by
ill-

the word heedlessness; not, again, the hasty and


expectation that results will not follow,
to be expressed

which I understand

by rashness

but the absence of diligence,

and even
was able

of skill;

and moreover, not the absence of that


which

diligence, or skill,

which the party imder the circumstances

to exercise, but of that diligence, or skill,

under the circumstances the law requires.

So that whatever
not at

be the exact nature of the qualities to which we ascribe


these names, the conduct of the person
is
is

all

what

considered, but whether he has fulfilled a special obligation

' This is the language of Sir William Erie delivering the judgment of seven judges in the case of Button against Powles see Law Journal Keports, vol. xxxi. Queen's Bench, p. 191. Compare the observations of Sirey on the Code Civil ' Dans I'application de I'article 1382 et pour
; :

il faut se souvenir que la loi entend par la Taction de feire une chose qu'on n'avait pas le droit de faire.' It is curious to observe how regularly lawyers in every country, when pushed

savoir

quand

il

a fauU,

upon any of these terms, fall back upon the barren express what the law forbids qiiod non jure factum.
;

generality, that they

(See Digest,

Book

ix.

tit. 2. sect. g.

par. i.)


328

LIABILITY FOR TORT.


Thus
it is

[Cliap.

XVI.

which he has incurred.

said that the

'

action for

neghgence proceeds upon the idea of an obHgation towards


the plaintifE to use care, and a breach of that obligation to
the
plain tiB:''s
i.''

injury

And more
to

explicitly

still,

'a

person

who undertakes
must
exercise

do

some work for reward to

an

article,

the care of a skilled

workman;
care
is

and''
skill

not
as

his inadvertence, or even his neglect to use such


'

he possesses, but

the

absence of such

negligence.''

Modern
interpietations of
jg

682. It

is

obvious in these cases, particularly the

last,

which

the term
"ence.

a J & celebrated for the acuteness and iudge 6 ' accuracy of his legal perceptions, that the term negligence
lang'uag'e of &
'

^^

is

used to express something wholly independent of the conduct

of the person

whose act or omission


negligence consists,

is

under consideration.

The workman's
act he
is

not in heedlessness of the


consequences
is
;

doing or omitting, or of
all

its

not in his but in his


use,

omitting to use

the care of which he

capable

omitting to use the care

which a

skilled
it

workman would
It
is

whether he

is

himself capable of

or not.

simply the

omission to perform a positive duty, and in this particular


case a positive duty

which

arises

upon a

contract.

As

the

phrase

is,

the workman,
;

when he undertakes

the work,
skill of

spondet peritiam artis


his craft.

he promises to use the ordinary

683. The latter use of the term

'

negligence '

is

perfectly in

accordance with ordinary language.

We

constantly speak of

a person

who

breaks a positive duty as neglecting that duty,

intending thereby only to express that he has not performed


1

This

is

the language of Lord Penzance in his considered j udgment de-

Swan against The North British Australasian Company see Law Journal Reports, Ne'w Series, vol. xxxi. Exchequer, p. 437. The next quotation is from the judgment of Mr. Justice Willes, in the case of Grill against The General Iron Scre'w Colliery Company see Law Eeports, Common Pleas, vol. i. p. 612. Of course with a shifting term like negligence it would be possible to find it used in a variety of shades of meaning, but I have confined myself to the passages most frequently
livered in the case of
; ;
'

'

quoted in the current


negligence.

treatises, as

containing the accepted definitions of

Sec. 682-685.]

LIABILITY FOE TORT.

329

the act which he was bound to perform, without any regard


to the state of

mind which accompanied the non-performit is

ance.

And

as a question of terms

only necessary to be
it,

careful to avoid sliding, without perceiving

from

this

meanit,

ing of the word

'

negligence ' into that other meaning of


rashness or heedlessness
;

where

it

expresses

as

so

easily
dis-

happens when a word has several meanings not wholly


connected.

684. But then we must consider what


detinitions of negligence.

is

the result of these Neglito say that


fjjg y^l^j.

What

does

it tell us,

man

is liable

for negligence, in either of these senses of the ^^"^ "^ '


it
all.

word negligence
pose, just

As

no use appears to me, for our present pur- in ascer-

nothing at

There

may

exist a standard in the

liability,

breasts of our judges or jurors by which they can measure

whether a

man

has been rash or heedless

by which they can

ascertain whether he has exercised reasonable care, or the

care of a skilled

workman

but when does the law require us


It
is

to reach this standard and


requires definition.

when not ? To say that a man

this

duty which

is liable

for negligence,

and
law

to define negligence as the omission to do that


requires, only brings us

which the

back by a very circuitous route


said

to that

which we have above

ought to be the

first

step in

the inquiry

namely, what
as I

is

the duty which the law imposes

upon us ?
685.
class

Now,
cases

have already pointed out, in a very large


discussion

of

the

of liability turns

exclusively

upon
sions

the question, whether or no there has been negligence.


it is

If then

true that the word

'

negligence

'

in these discus-

means no more than the


it

authorities to
it is

which I have

referred represent

to

mean, then

obvious that this disis

cussion simply revolves in a

circle.

What

a tort?

The

breach of a duty.
gence.

What

constitutes such a breach? Negli?

What

is

negligence

The breach
^.

of a duty.

In this

way we
'

shall never arrive at a result

Bench,

In the recent case of Heaven against Pender, Law Reports, Queen's vol. xi. p. 509, an attempt has been made by Lord Esher to

330
Malice.

LIABILITY FOR TORT.


is

[Chap. XVI.

686. Malice
of use,

a term which seems to be rather going out

though

it

was

at one time very frequently used to exliability

press something

from which

might be

inferred.

It

points directly to the state of

mind

of the person,

and prob-

ably

it

originally expressed pretty nearly the


is^

same thing as

malevolence, that

the motive (in the estimation of the

speaker a bad one) which induces a party to act or abstain

from acting.
in the best

It has been thence transferred to intention,

and

known

definitions^ of
;

malice
it
is

it

is

scarcely dis-

tinguishable from intention


cases

but

applied, not only to

where the consequences of an act are desired as an end,

but where they are desired as means, and even to eases where
they are merely adverted to and expected, without being
desired at
all.

When

used in this extended sense, the badis

ness of the motive

which prompts the act

altogether lost
kill,

sight

of, for it is

obvious that a
to

man may

even desire to

as an end, or as

means

an end, or he may do an act which


without desiring to
kill,

he knows

to be likely to cause death,

from motives which are altogether good, and yet be guilty of


a crime.
Cases of patriotism, of excess in the use of the right
of self-defence, or in the exercise of power by constables and
other persons similarly situated, afford very frequent examples
of this kind.
Malice in

687.

The

difficulty of
'

obtaining a clear idea of what


is

is

meant by the term malice '


of the phrase
'

also greatly increased


If, for instance,

by the use

malice in

law.''

I erroneously
suspicions to

suspect

you

to be a thief,

and I communicate

my

construct a proposition
said that,

which would cover a large class of cases. It is whenever a person is in such a position with regard to another, that by the exercise of ordinary sense he would recognise that if he did not use ordinary care and skill he would cause danger to the property or person of the other, he is bound to use ordinary care and skill to avoid such danger. The attempt is not without merit, but the proposition is
too wide.
'94, p. 281.
'

See a case of Ponting

v.

Noakes,

Law

Reports, Queen's Bench,

See Russell on Crimes, by Greaves, 4th ed.,

vol.

i.

p.

688 note.

The

definition of a malicious act there given is 'a wrongful act done inten-

tionally without just or lawful excuse.'

Sec. 686-688.]

LIABILITY FOR TORT.

331

another, not in any


it likely

way

intending to injure you, or thinking


I,

that I shall injure you, but because

erroneously,

think
in

it

my

duty to do

so,

there can, of course, be no malice

any reasonable sense

of the word.
is
'

And

this is admitted in
fact.'

such cases by saying there


less

no malice in

Nevertheis

lawyers persist in such cases in saying that there

'malice in law.'

Obviously the state of the law which they


is

approve, and which they wish to apply,

that I should be

liable for the publication of statements injurious to the char-

acter of another, and that this obligation should be in no

way

dependent on

my

belief as to the truth of

my

statements, or

on

my desire
are

or expectation that you

may
still

be injured by them.

Nevertheless, the forms of procedure

assume the contrary


;

you

bound

to state that I acted maliciously

and after

it

has been most carefully inquired into and ascertained that


there was no malice in the matter, the judges
liable
still

hold

me
of

by

telling

me

that there was

'

malice in law.'

What,

course, this

really

means

is,

that there are circumstances

under which I

am

liable for false statements affecting


;

your

character independently of malice

but

it

would be far

better,

and save endless confusion,

if,

instead of seeking to do this

by

interposing the phantom called ' malice in law,' that no malice was necessary.
circuitous route
is

we said

plainly

To

arrive at our point

by

this

just as

if

the court, desiring to relieve


tell

a debtor from the obligation to pay a debt, were to


that he would be considered as having paid
creditor a cheque
it if

him
no

he sent his

drawn

in full

form upon

his bankers for

pounds, no shillings, and no pence.

meet with many other similar cases; thus we have legal or constructive fraud as distinguished from actual notice in law, or confraud a most embarrassing term
688.

We

other
^aTea'''^

structive notice, as distinguished

from actual

notice.

Any

one acquainted with the history of English law knows exactly

how

this has occurred.

To have

said that malice, or fraud, or Origin of

notice, were not necessary, in cases where they had been terms generally thought necessary, would have been too much like

332

LIABILITY FOR TORT.


For though
it
is,

[Chap. XVI.
as I

an avowed innovation.
limits, to
office

have shown

above, a duty imposed upon English judges, within certain

make new ever to avow

laws,
it.

it is

against the tradition of their


is
is

By

saying, therefore, that there

malice in law, or fraud in law, they pretend that there


malice, or fraud, or whatever else they

want

to get rid of,

when
Dis-

there

is

really
is

none at

all.

689. Dishonesty
legislation.

a word a good deal used in some modern

honesty.

As
in

far as I

am

able to discover, it signifies the

state of

mind

which a

man adverts

to the fact that he

is

com-

mitting a breach of the law and expects to gain something

by
Wantonness.

it

acting, as the

Roman
is

lawyers said, lucri

causa''-.

690. Wantonness

used, as far as I can gather, to express

those eases in which consequences are desired as an end, but

the motive to the act


revenge, or
lust,

is

not one of the ordinary passions of


;

or avarice, or the like

but rather

(as

the

phrase

is)

the love of mischief for mischief's sake.


liability,

Its use, as

an expression which characterises

has no doubt arisen

from the confusion between motives and intention, which we


have already noticed in the case of malice.
Fraud.

691. Fraud, though

it is

a term frequently used in such

way

as to suggest that

it is

a test of

liability,

has not, as

far as I

am

aware, been authoritatively defined.

Bentham ^,
embraces the

however,

who

generally took very considerable pains to ascer-

tain the precise

meaning

of terms, thinks that

it

idea of falsehood or mendacity.

And

I understand falsehood

to be the moral characteristic which, after

much

debate, has
liability for
it is

been decided to be necessary in order to constitute


fraud.
1

Nevertheless, say the books, to constitute fraud


definition of dishonesty in the
:

The

Sect. 24

'Whoever does anything with the intention of causing wrongful


'

Indian Penal Code

is as follows,

gain to one person or wrongful loss to another person is said to do that thing dishonestly.' Sect. 23, Wrongful gain is gain by unlawful means of property to which the person gaining is not legally entitled.' Sect. 24, 'Wrongful
loss is the loss
it is

legally entitled.'

by unlawful means of property I think it was an error

to
to

which the person losing


extend the definition of
vi. p.

dishonesty so as to
"

make it include the intentional causing of wrongful loss.


29s n.

See Bowring's edition of Collected Works, vol.

Sec. 689-692.]

LIABILITY FOE TORT.

333

not necessary to show that the parties making the assertion

knew
it

it

to be untrue; it is
it

enough that the person making


1.

did not believe

to be true

It

is

diflScult to

understand

a distinction founded on the difference between knowledge and


belief.

One

can easily understand a rash assertion^ assumed to

be true on insuiRcient grounds, or a heedless assertion, made

without considering at

all

whether

it is

true or notj and there

are not wanting indications that


assertions

of care in making may, under some circumstances, render a man liable.

want

But such statements


Moreover the
believing

could hardly be called false or mendacious.

distinction
is

which philosophers draw between


has said that knowis

and hiowing
Sir

very subtle, and by no means univer-

sally recognised.

WiUiam Hamilton
;

ledge

is

a certainty founded upon intuition, belief

a certainty

founded upon feeling

but James Mill applies the term belief


^.

to every species of conviction

692.

What

I think was intended

is

this

When
if

man

makes a
and

direct assertion,

he very often impliedly

also asserts

that he has, to the best of his ability, exercised his judgment,


believes the assertion to be true.
is

Thus,

I say

'

Mr.

has a good constitution,' there


fact concerning ^'s health,

here a direct statement of


also,

and

instance

if

the question were put to


life,

in many cases, as for me by an office about to

insure ^'s

an implied statement, that I have exercised

my

judgment

in the matter, and have

come

to that conclusion.
(i) if I
(a) if I
;

This implied statement will be mendacious,


given the matter any consideration at
sidered it
all;

have not
have conif

and not come

to

any conclusion

or (3)

I have

^ This is not the exact language of Lord Wensleydale, who wag the author of this distinction but the distinction is (as I understand it) made to turn, both in the original and in the quotations of it, upon the difference between knowledge and belief. See the judgment of Lord Wensleydale in the case of Taylor against Ashton, in Meeson and Welsby's Reports, vol. xi. p. 415 Smith's Leading Cases, sixth ed., vol. ii.
;
;

94 ; Addison on Torts, third ed. p. 828. ^ See James Mill's Analysis of the Human Mind, ed. i86g, p 343, note by J. S. Mill and An Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy,
p.
;

by

J. S. Mill,

chap.

v.

334
considered
it,

LIABILITY FOB TOBT.

[Chap. XYI.

and not come to that conclusion which

my state-

ment

involves.

693. Whilst discussing the various terms which have been


used to express
liability,

I will advert to

two phrases in
These

common

use,

which are sometimes placed in apparent oppoterms which we have been considering.

sition to the

two phrases express not quite the same thing, but things
nearly similar.

Thus

it

is

said

of

certain

acts

that the

question of liability is
Doing a
^

not one of negligence, but that a


;

man

does

them

at his peril

so also it is said in certain cases that


is

perif

he

is

liable,

not for fraud, but because there


first

a warranty.

What
is,

I take to be aimed at in the


is

of these

two phrases
forbid,

that there

some act which the law does not


is

some
to

act

from which there

no primary duty or obligation

abstain, but for which, if a


will be liable to

man

does

it

and harm ensues, he

make compensation.

For instance, a

man

is

said to accumulate water in a reservoir


peril
;

on his land at his


not unlawful for the
if

which apparently means that

it is

landowner to accumulate water in the reservoir, but


reservoir bursts

the

and the water

floods his neighbour's land,

he

must make him compensation ^.


this is the true

I have
;

some doubt whether


is

view of the law

and whether a man


is

not

generally prohibited from doing that which

in fact dangerous;

though of course
danger
not, it
till

it is

very often impossible to discover the


But, even
if

after the event has happened.


this

he

is

would only come to

that
is

as regards certain acts

the primary duty or obligation

not to abstain from them,


are

but only to compensate persons


It
is

who

damaged by them.
expressly under-

in this view that the

duty or obligation in the case above


is

put has been often compared to that which


taken by an insurer.
Warranty.

694.

warranty, properly speaking,

is

in form

an under-

taking that certain events will happen, or will not happen;


'

See the case of Eylauda against Fletcher,


iii.

Lords, vol.

p.

330
ii.

Law Reports, House of and that of Nichols against Marsland, Law Rep.,

Exch. Div.,

vol.

p. 4.

Sec. 693-6^8.]

LIABILITY POE TORT.


;

335
it is

have happened, or have not happened


their happening or not happening.

but

in reality

a promise to make compensation for the

loss occasioned

by
a

Such a warranty

is

contract

the obligation
;

is

one which arises on the agreement

of the parties

and such contracts are very often entered into

as ancillaiy, or supplemental to contracts of sale, or other

similar transactions.

But the word warranty '


'

is

not confined

exclusively to transactions which are properly called contracts.

Whenever

it is

incumbent upon a person, from any reason


warrant

whatever, to take upon himself the consequences, should a

statement which he makes not be true, he

is

said to

the truth of the statement; whether this duty or obligation

be imposed by contract between the parties, or in any other

manner.

And when

it is

said that a party

is liable

for a breach
is liable

of warranty, as distinguished from saying that he

for

a fraudulent representation, I understand


there
is

it

to be affirmed that

some primary obligation upon him, not only

to state

nothing except that which he believes to be true, but also to


take the consequences of stating anything which in fact
is

not true.

695. Hitherto

we have not got


of

very

far.

We

have got

some idea of the meaning

some of the terms used, but we


others,

have failed to get any very distinct meaning for

and

we have got no mark


696.

or quality

by which

liability

ex delicto

can be known, or distinguished.

Now

let

us look at the acts themselves which are


let

Qualities

called torts,

and

us see whether in that


or quality.

way

it is

possible designated
*'^'^-

to discover

any such mark

697. There are certain duties corresponding to rights in rem Trespass,

which we

call rights of

ownership.

Some

of these rights have

been enumerated and described.

Every

violation of a right of

ownership which causes damage gives

rise to

a liability to

make
is

compensation to the owner for the


tort.
.

damage

done, and

a
^.
Violation
,

..

698. There are certain other duties corresponding to rights of rights of

336
personal
sscuritv

LIABILITY FOE TORT.


call rights of personal security.

[Chap. XVI.

in

rem which we
rights

Some

of

these

have been enumerated and described.

Every,

violation of a right of personal security

which causes damage


for the

gives rise to a liability to done^ and


Defamais

make compensation

damage

a tort.

699. In the ease of statements which damage a man's


reputation
abstain
it is

difficult

to say

whether there

is

a duty to

from making them, corresponding

to a right that

they

make compensation for damage caused by them corresponding to a right to demand


should not be made, or only a duty to

such compensation.

It

would seem, however, that there

is,

at

any

rate, a general

duty to abstain from making defamatory

statements otherwise than by words spoken, and that the plea

which

is

allowed that the statement was true and that

it

was
is

for the public

good that the statement should be made

matter of special justification only.

man who makes

a
is

defamatory statement otherwise than by words spoken


liable to a criminal prosecution,
fication.

and he must prove

his justi-

Some

of the language
is

we

find in the books seems

also to

assume that there

a duty to abstain from

making
so is

any defamatory statements whatsoever, and that doing


prima facie a wrong which can only be
circumstances.
justified

under special
that such the
civil
is

Yet

it

would be

difficult to assert

a duty exists.
court

seems to

Upon the whole the practice me to support the view that

of

there

no

such duty as regards verbal statements.


plaintiff

It is true that the

can put the defendant on his defence in

many

eases

by simply showing that the unwritten defamatory statement


has been made.
this

But

this is because the plaintiff

having done
fact,
it is

can then claim the benefit of three presumptions of


charge
it

(i) that the

made

against

him

is false, (a)

that

malicious, (3) that

has caused him damage.


is

It seems clear

that
there

if
is

any one of these three presumptions


no evidence to supply
is

excluded, and
fail,
it

its place,

the plaintiff will

because his case

not made out.

As

regards the damage,

may

be only a rule of practice that actions will not be enter-

Sec. 699-701

LIABILITY FOR TORT.


But the
explained

337
require-

tained where no loss has been incurred.

ment

of malice

and

falsity

cannot be

in

this

way

^.

700.

Any

defamatoiy statement which was

false

and

malicious,

and caused damage, would be


is

called a tort.

701. There

in

law no general duty


is

to speak the truth. Mendaei-

That

is

to say, simply telling a lie

not the violation of any


level as ingratitude,

legal duty.

Mendacity stands on the same


It brings

down punishment on the offender, Nor is there any general duty to make compensation for damage caused by telling a lie. Thereor cowardice.

but not of the legal

sort.

fore, if

man were

to tell a lie

and thereby damage another,


liability.

he would not by this alone incur any

But

there

is

a duty to speak the truth on particular occasions and under


particular circumstances
;

or, at

any

rate, there are occasions

and circumstances when a man


for

is liable

to

make compensation
telling a
lie.

any damage that may be caused by

For
tells

example, a a
lie

man

will be liable to

make compensation
is it

if

he

to a person with

whom

he

transacting business, and


to be true,

that person, acting upon the statement believing


is if
it,

damaged thereby.
he
tells

So he will be
upon

liable to

make
it

compensation

lie

to a person intending that person to act act


it

upon
and

and that person does

believing

to be true,

^ See Odgers on Libel and Slander, p. 17, referring to Townshend on Slander and Libel, chap. iv. sect. 57 ; also pp. 169, 264. It seems clear that in an action of contract, if a breach of contract is proved and no

damage, the plaintiff


land, if the trespass

is

entitled to a verdict.

In an action

of trespass to
is

is

proved and no damage, the plaintiff

entitled to

a verdict,
tion,
tiff

if

the

title is also in question.

even

if

the words are spoken falsely

But in an action for defamaand maliciously, yet the plain-

will not get a verdict if there be no damage.

And

it is

this peculi-

arity which I understand to be referred to

that in the action of

by those writers who maintain defamation damage is the gist of the action. The
'

expression

'

gist of the action

is

rather vague.

It is certainly

not true

to say that, because the Courts require

both

damnum et injuria, therefore

without
is

damnum there

is

no breach of duty.

A trespass without damage

it may be ti-ue that the Courts in declaring that an action for breach of contract is maintainable without damage, and that an action for defamation is not so maintain-

certainly a breach of duty.

On

the other hand,

able, are acting inconsistently.

338

LIABILITY FOB TOUT.

[Chap. XVI.
telling a lie

incurs loss thereby.


these circumstances
Misrepresentation,
is

To

cause

damage by
in

under

called a tort.
is

702. Whether or no there


tractj a liability to

any

case, apart

from con-

make compensation

for

harm caused by
It
is,

misrepresentations which are false in fact but not mendacious,


is

a matter upon which lawyers have differed.


settled that in

however,
liability^.

now

English law there

is

no such

If there were such a liability the misrepresentation would be


called

tort.

703. There are some uses which a


of his property, because they cause

man is

forbidden to

make

damage

to his Neighbour.

Such a use

of a

man's property

is

called a nuisance.
is

What
all

uses of property are and


clearly stated.
Sic utere tuo.

what
is

are not nuisances


is

not at

Whatever

a nuisance

also

tort.

704. There are some cases in which

it is

said that

though

man by making

use of his property in a particular


if

commits no breach of the law, yet


it,

he does so
to

and causes damage thereby, he

is liable

way make use of make compen^.

sation.
Carriers and innkeepers.

An

act

which

so causes

damage

is

called a tort

705. Certain special duties are imposed by the law upon


particular persons or classes of persons, for example,

upon

innkeepers, and

common

carriers.

If
is

any person

is

by a breach
pensation.
Hetero-

of these duties there

a liability to

damaged make com-

An

act which thus causes

damage

is

called a tort.

706. There are


called torts,

many

other acts or omissions which are


is

geneous
cliaracter of torts.

but the above enumeration


are.

sufficient to

show

how

heterogeneous they

The only common


is

feature of

the torts enumerated that I can discover

that they are acts

forbidden by the law, which cause damage, and for which the

law requires compensation to be paid.


^

This

is

what I under-

vol. xiv. p. 337.

See the case of Peek against Derry, in Law Eeports, Appeal Cases, As a general principle the law here laid down is, no douht, right. But, nevertheless, there are many situations in which

is required, and where persons who make fiilse statements ought to compensate those who are misled, although there is no mendacity. But these are oases to be dealt with by the legislature. ^ See supra, sect. 693.

greater circumspection

Sec. 702-707.]

LIABILITY FOR TOUT.

339

stand to be meant

when

it is

said that in tort there

must be

damnum
law.

et injuria.

Injuria means, I suppose, a breach of the


is

The

jus of which the injuria

a violation

may be

either

a jus in rem, like a right of ownership, or a jus in personam,


like the right to

be compensated for a misrepresentation.

It

may

be a right that the act which causes the injury shall not
it

be done, or

may be

simply a right to compensation, in which

case the injuria consists in the refusal to

make compensation.
be found

But the combination


in every tort.
for
Still

of injuria

and

damnum must
we

we have

not found what

are looking

a mark which
it

will distinguish tort.

This combination,

though

is

universally present in torts, will not serve to

distinguish them.

We find

this

combination also in breaches


^.

of contract and in breaches of trust

707. There has been a disposition to

make blameworthiness
torts.

Blameness.

the connecting link between acts which are called


are,

There

no doubt,

many acts which


is

give rise to a liability to

make

compensation, and which are called torts, in which the conduct


of the doer of the act

estimated,

and

is

pronounced blame-

worthy.
this kind.

All cases of rashness and heedlessness are cases of

The conduct

of the person

upon

whom
is

it is

sought

to fasten liability is tried

by a standard which

furnished by

the experience of the judge as to what sort of conduct


reasonably be required.

may

The

occasions

upon which a person


in the

will be liable for rashness or heedlessness are chiefly occasions

on which he and other persons are brought into contact


exercise of their
:

others are
or

common rights as, for example, when he and using a common road; or a common conveyance;
invited other persons to
;

when he has
others

come

to his house, or
is

upon

his premises
;

or

when he

is

employing or

employed

by

or when he and others are engaged in a common

employment.
'

In these and other cases the law says

that, if

If there are any cases in which the courts allow an act to be complained of as a tort without damage, they are cases in which the real dispute is as to the existence of the right, and the action is allowed because,

strange to say, our law does not always afford any direct the question whether a right exists or no.

way

of trying

Z 2

340

LIABILITY FOR TORT.


is

[Chap. XVI.

damage

caused by a certain want of attention to consequences


in

which amounts to heedlessness, or by a want of caution


avoiding danger which amounts to rashnesSj
pensated.
it

must be com-

708. There might be some convenience in classing together

and enumerating the occasions on which a person would be


liable for rashness or heedlessness

by reason

of

some duty

east

upon him by the law to be circumspect j and


venient to keep separate the occasions

it

might be conarose

when the duty

upon a contract, and those when

it

arose without a contract


for the acts

and then we should want a name


liability

by which the

was

incurred,

which name would cover a portion of


called torts.

the acts which are


Specific acts and

now

709. Then

there are other cases in which, instead of leaving

forbearances.

the conduct of the person to be estimated by the tribunal

which decides upon the

liability,

the sovereign authority has


:

ordered certain precautions to be taken

as

when a
is

rule of the

road

is

laid

down

or a railway

company

directed to fence

in its

permanent way, or to use particular appliances for the

safety of passengers.
rest

And many
it is

of these cases,

no doubt,

upon the principle that

reasonable to require such

precautions,

and that the omission of them would be blameit

worthy.
class of

But

would be very
first,

difficult to

make

a separate

such cases;

because the reasons which lead to


all

such a
because

command may not be


it

of one kind

and secondly,

would not always be easy to say what these


of conduct as

reasons are.
Estimation of

710.

The estimation

an element of

liability is

conduct

of comparatively
^

modern

origin^.

The general

practice in

particular acts,

been suggested that the commands to make compensation for which are to be found in the Laws of Alfred, were arrived at by a process of specification from general rules. I can understand what
It has
is

meant when

it is

said that the


'

modern

'

rule of the road ' on land or at


'

sea is arrived at by a

process of specification

from a general rule

for-

bidding negligence. But that any rule in the Laws of Alfred should have been so arrived at seems to me unlikely. Is it not rather true that in those days the only conception was of a specific rule to do this or abstain from doing that ? See The Common Law, by Mr. Justice 0. W. Holmes, p. 1 1 3.

Sec. 708-711.]

LIABILITY FOE, TOET.

341

early times seems to have been to impose a liability to

make

and inten-

compensation for

specific acts done.

And

the mere doing of

modem
Pi'^ctice.

the act induced the liability, unless the party charged could
establish

some

justification.
'

Later on we

get the more

general expression

trespass/ behind

which

lay,

no doubt, the

conception of rights of ownership and of rights of personal


security. Still we have got no further than that an act was done which ought not to be done. Neither advertence to the

consequences of an act as distinguished from the act

itself,

nor

inadvertence to those consequences seems ever to have been

taken into consideration.

If it had been suggested that they ought to be considered, the answer, I think, would be that

the attitude of the mind as regards the consequences was


undiscoverable.

Probably the Courts of Chancery set the ex-

a,mple of considering the attitude of


act as regards the consequences, that

mind
is,

of the doer of

an

of inquiring whether
as,

he intended them, and also of estimating his conduct,


for

example, whether he had acted in good faith.

The

Common Law

Courts at length felt themselves obliged to

consider intention in matters of contract, and

by degrees got

also into the habit of submitting to juries questions of conduct,

and the
seems to

closeness

with which the intention, or the knowledge,


is

or the' conduct of the party

scrutinised in courts of justice

me

to be

upon the

increase.

711. It
effect of

must

also

be remembered, that whatever


liability in

may be

the All blame^re


'"'*^-

blameworthiness in inducing
that there are
to

some kinds ^^g

of
for

torts, it is certain

many

things called torts ^^

which a person

is liable

make

compensation, in which,

not only the element of blameworthiness, but even the element


of intention to do harm,
is

wholly absent.

If I do any

harm

whatever to your land, whether I do so advertently or inadvertently


is

of no importance.
is

The only question


it

is

whether

the trespass
to

my act. Nor is

possible to trace the liability

make compensation

in this case to blameworthiness.


is

What
it

lies

at the back of liability in this case

not blameworthiness

but ownership.

On

the other hand, I do not see

how

can

342

LIABILITY FOR TORT.


is

[Chap. XVI.

be asserted that there

noWj or ever was, a rule or principle


Is there

that mere blameworthiness gives rise to liability.

any general duty to abstain from acts which are malicious or negligeni;? or to make compensation for damage caused by
acts

which are malicious or negligent

I think none.

Many

times the law has said this thing or that thing shall not be

done maliciouslyj this thing or that thing shall not be done


negligently
;

that compensation shall be

made

for this or for

that malicious or negligent act.

But

it

has never said that


or^

nothing shall be done maliciously or negligently;

that

compensation shall be made for malicious and negligent acts


in general.
influence

However malignant may be the motives which


conduct; however disastrous
it,

my

may

be the con-

sequences which I expect to result from

I shall not be liable


;

unless I have transgressed certain limits

which
run

limits are

marked out by the


land.

law.

I have a fine spring of water on


it

my
the

For some years I have allowed

to

off in

direction of a neighbouring village^ the inhabitants of

which

have come to depend on

it

mainly for their supply of water.

From

the most malignant motives, and hoping and expecting

thereby to bring famine and sickness into the village, I

dam

up the stream

in that direction^

and turn

it

into another.

Am

I or

am

I not liable ?

The answer depends simply on


in other words,

whether the inhabitants of the village have by long enjoyment


or otherwise acquired a right to the water
;

whether I have come ixnder a special duty to abstain from any


act which deprives
right,

them

of

it.

If they have not acquired that


special duty, I

and I have not incurred that

am

not

answerable under the law.

If they have acquired that right,

then, however useless the stream

may be

to

them

though my
for
scientific

object was to supply another village which

was perishing

want
lages

of water;

though I

may

even have obtained a

opinion that the supply of water was suflicient for both vil-

shall still

be

liable.

712.

So in the questions which

so frequently arise

between

persons related to each other as master and servant.

The

Sec. 712-714.]

LIABILITY FOR TORT.

343

servant

may

be exposed by the master to great danger which


yet^ if the servant

might be avoided^
accident that

knew
is

of the dangerous

nature of the employment, the master

not liable for any


difficult,

may

happen.

Here

it

would be

on

moral grounds, to defend the conduct of the master in thus


exposing his servant to danger, even with his
and, as the master ex hypothesi

own

assent

knows
if

of the danger, he

must
them.

at least disregard the consequences,

he does not intend

What
law.

draws the
is

line is the master's

duty as defined

by the

It

not the legal duty of the master to preserve


risk in all cases
it
;

his servant

from
to

in

which

it

is

immoral
either

to expose

him

nor

is

the master

made

liable

because he expects, or because he

disregards,

the
it

conse-

quences of the exposure

the law simply makes

his

duty
risk,

to take certain precautions to preserve his servant

from

when the
does not.

risk is one of

which he knows but his servant

713. It seems to

me
'

impossible to escape from the con- Sugges*

elusion that the

word

torts

is

used in English law to cover


is

to the
^

a number of

acts,

having no quality which

at once

common

^^^^
'

and
the

distinctive.

In other words, I believe the

classification to

tort.

be a false one.

Upon what

intelligible

ground do we apply

damage done by trespass or by slander, or by fraud, and refuse to apply it to damage done by breach of Nor contract, or by breach of trust? I think upon none. assigning the name can I see any advantage whatever in

name

of tort to

'torts' to a

number

of acts which have nothing in

common
It

except what they share with other acts not so called.


certainly be desirable to cease calling
acts

would
all

by the name of torts which have acquired other distinctive names such

as

trespass, fraud, slander.

714. I suggested just


class

now

that

it

might be convenient
is

to
re-

together those cases in which circumspection

quired, and in which the particular degree of circumspection


is

left in

each case to the judge or jury to determine, and

possibly if this classification were

made

it

might be convenient

344
to call acts in

LIABILITY FOR TOET.

[Chap. XVI.

which liahihty was incurred through want of

this circumspection

by the name

of torts.

am

disposed to

think that these acts do possess


their being classed together

a quality which justifies

and which distinguishes them from


I

other acts giving

rise to liability.

am disposed to
when

think that
people are

the occasions

when they

arise are occasions

brought into contact with each other, as by living contiguously, or

by using the same conveyance or the same highway, or by the employment of, or by visiting, each other. These being the occasions, the conduct is estimated by the
judges or the jury, as the case
their experience^.

may

be, in accordance

with

714

a.

If this nomenclature were adopted

we

should then,

with the help of such terms as fraud, slander, and trespass,

have a tolerably useful and comprehensive

classification.

Of
It

course such a classification would be a very rough one.

does not, however, follow that

it

would be a

useless one.

am

inclined to be afraid of attempts at too

much
is

pre-

cision.

"What I have been chiefly arguing against

the

sort of

sham

definitions

and

distinctions of

which the books


left great
is

afford so

many examples.

There should, I think, be

latitude to the tribunals in deciding whether

where harm
resist

done, compensation should be given

and I would

the

tendency which

is,

I think, at present, too strong in England,

to let successive decisions

on such a point as this grow into

law. 715. I
of
'

tort

'

might even perhaps venture to suggest a definition which would adapt itself to these views. It might
'

be declared that

every person

who on any occasion

is

required

to use reasonable care

and omits

to use such reasonable care

commits a

tort.' The question whether or no the occasion was one requiring care ought not, I think, to be left to a jury

For a further discussion of these questions of conduct, and for a conwhether they are questions of fact or of law, I take leave to refer to an article in the Law Magazine and Review, 4th Ser. vol, ii.
sideration of
p. 311.

See. 7i4a-7i6.]

LIABILITY FOR TORT.


by the judge

345
in all cases

to determine, but should be decided

and

it

would probably be

inevitable,

and perhaps not undesirlaw would

able, that out of decisions on this point rules of

grow.
rules

But no attempt should be made to determine by legal the standard of conduct by which the reasonableness *
'

of the case is measured.

That question should be

left to

the

uneonttolled opinion of the jury, or of the judge, in cases

where he had no jury


716.

to assist him.

A somewhat novel principle of liability has been lately Liability


if

suggested, which,
tions.

favoured,

may grow

The

particular cases

which have occurred have been

to very large proper- aTbetween innocent

cases of fraud.

commits a fraud which damages

persons,

and

C,
is

who

are both innocent.

is,

of course, liable, but, as


is

frequently the case with fraudulent persons, he

insolvent.

Thereupon

B and
is

enter into a litigation in which the object

of the plaintiff
plaintiff fails to

to

throw the

loss

on the defendant.

The

show that there has been any must


where

dereliction of

duty on the part of the defendant; whereupon the court,


instead of saying that the loss
lie
it

has fallen,

proceeds to consider which of the two parties enabled

to

commit the
that person.

fraud, and to hold

that the loss

must

fall

on

The

liability is

not placed upon the ground of


If this principle were

misconduct, but of causation.

once

acknowledged, the door would be open to a very large extension of legal liability
^

^-

See the judgment of Chief Justicf Cockburn in the case of Babrooh

t).

Queen's Bench Div., vol. iv. p. 394. It was quite unnecessary in that case to call in aid any such doctrine see the case in appeal in vol. v. p. 284. The late learned Chief Justice seems to have thought that the right of an innocent purchaser to retain goods which he

larvon,

Law Rep.,

had bought, and of which he had obtained possession, from a person who had himself obtained them by fraud, also rested upon the principle that the original owner had enabled the seller to commit the fraud. I should doubt the correctness of this view. At any rate it is quite a modern view. Until recently the view was that the innocent purchaser was owner, this being a case in which the ownership followed the possession. See the case of Moyce v. Newington, Law Eep., Queen's Bench Div., vol. iv.
p. 35.

See also supra,

sect. 512.

CHAPTER

XVII.

GROUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.
Effect of

717.

In analysing the nature of an act and the manner


it

in

eonditions.

which

produces legal results I considered in a very general

^g^y jjQ^ these results were affected by certain abnormal


conditions of the party
sider a little

who

does the act.

I will

now

con-

more

particularly the effect of these conditions

upon that legal


Where
does not
arise.

result

which we

call liability.

718.

When

the abnormal conditions of the party

who

does

^^^

^^'^

^^^ such that the elements

which constitute

liability

are not all present, then, of course, that liability does not arise.

For example, when a

man by

reason of being drunk


is

fails to

discover that a shilling in his possession

obviously bad,

he cannot be guilty of uttering counterfeit

coin, because the

knowledge which
kind of
is

is

one of the elements of this particular

liability is

wanting.

In such a case drunkenness


is

not an excuse for crime, but the case


if

exactly the

same

as

the ignorance had arisen from the stupidity of the party


If the party
is

charged.

punished, he

is

not punished for

uttering counterfeit coin, a crime which he has not committed, but


for

drunkenness, or some other offence.


if

On
kills

the other hand,


his

a lunatic in a frenzy of passion


of

keeper,

aU the elements of the crime


if

murder are

present; and
arise,

the liability to capital punishment does not


liability to suffer
is

but only the modified

imprisonment

during the King's pleasure, the case


consideration.

one for our special

Where
liability
arises.

719.

cases

In the following observations I shall only deal with which the elements of liability are present, and
-1

GROUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.
the ordinary liability would
arise,

347
is

were

it

not that the case

treated as an exceptional one.

720. There are three ways in which the ordinary

liability

Ways

in

may
it

be affected.

It

may
;

either not arise at all


or,

or it

may

liability

arise in

a modified form

having arisen in

its

usual form,

^e'^'w

may

be

set aside or modified

by the order

of a court.
is

721. Cases in which the ordinary liability arises, but


seq^uently set aside or modified
also

sub-

when
geUsideor
modified,

by the order

of a court,

must
from

be kept apart.

They
doubt

are dealt with differently


is

those in which the ordinary liability


in
its

prevented or modified

inception.

No

all

these cases

might be governed

by the same or analogous rules; but, as a matter of fact, courts of justice, when they modify or set aside a liability which has
already arisen, exercise a large amount of discretion, guided to

some extent by the examples


and capable of being stated
the ordinary liability

of their predecessors as recorded

in the reports, but not governed


in

by

rules constantly observed

an abstract form.

I shall

therefore, for the present, confine myself to cases in which


is

prevented or modified in

its inception.

722.

The abnormal

conditions which I propose to discuss

are insanity, error, intoxication, infancy,

and

duress.
all disorders of Insanity.
little

723. Insanity

the intellect of a grave character

under which term I include has been


to
liability generally.

discussed

with reference

It
its

has been almost

always discussed with reference to


liability.

effect

on criminal

But
all

in the

main the

principles of liability are the


shall refer here to the
liability

same in

courts,

and therefore I

manner
724.

in

which the questions of the

of

insane

persons have been discussed in criminal courts.

The
it is

ideas current on the subject of

insanity have Modern


of
late

undergone very
Indeed

considerable

modifications

years.

only in recent times that the subject has received


it

anything like the consideration which

deserves.

Attention

was

first

drawn

to it

by the

horrible sufferings endured

by

insane

persons in

confinement.

It

apparently used to be

thought that every insane person, who had physical strength

348

GROUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.
liberty to use
it,

[Chap.

XVIL
of

and

was dangerous, and that the only way


forcible restraint.

rendering

him harmless was by

The

idea

seems to have been that insane persons were under some sort
of external impulse, which drove

them
It
is

to

commit

acts (as the


that,

phrase was) against their


rare

will.

now known

with

and temporary exceptions, insane persons are susceptible

much the same kind of influences as other persons. They can be made to feel the effects of discipline, and can
of very

appreciate, in a very considerable degree, the painfulness of

reproof and the pleasure of approbation.


that,
in

The consequence

is

the best asylums, the patients are seldom under

physical restraint.

How they
liability.

725.

This

discovery,

though

it

has

greatly

mitigated

^^^ sufferings of persons subject to this calamity, has un-

doubtedly opened a
to be decided,

new and

difficult inquiry,

whenever
is

it

has

whether or no the insane person

legally

responsible for his acts.

This mode of treatment clearly shows


intellectual

that the moral and


entirely effaced.

qualities

are

hardly ever

The insane have


it

in a great measure re-

covered their liberty, but with


least, their responsibility.

also they resume, in part at

Peculiar
of eiimi*^^

726. It
^^^^

may

be perhaps doubted, whether the recognition

responsibility

has

kept pace with

the

increasing

nal cases,

tendency to treat abnormal conduct as indicating some form


or other of mental disease. of insanity should It
is

also unfortunate that the

law

have been to so great a degree fashioned


in one particular class of criminal cases.
cases this defence is rarely set up.

upon the practice

For in ordinary criminal

The

effect of setting

up a plea
if

of insanity in answer to a

criminal charge, even

successful, is generally almost as

disastrous to the accused as if he were to admit his guilt.

Insanity

itself is

a stigma

and accused

persons, if found
indefinite

insane, are liable to be imprisoned for

an

time

whereas ordinary convicts are only imprisoned for a specified


period.

Hence

it

follows, that

few persons care

to set

up
is

the defence except in capital cases, in which this defence

Sec. 725-728.]

GROUNDS

01'

NON-LIABILITY.
;

349

frequently insisted upon, strenuously enough


for the

but even here^

most

part,

only in that class of cases, in which

murders have been committed under the influence of violent


passion, without

any attempt

at concealment,

and where any


is

other defence

is

therefore hopeless.

Now

this

just the

very class of cases in which the question of insanity presents


itself

under peculiar

diflBeulties.
is

The violent excitement under


itself

which the accused


so like

labouring produces an extravagance of


:

conduct very like that produced by insanity indeed anger


is

madness as to be proverbially

identified

with

it.

727.

The

question of liability in the case of insane persons Grounds

cannot be determined unless

we have
require

first clearly settled

in bilUy.

own minds the grounds Why do we imprison a man or


our
tion for

of liability in ordinary cases.

him

to

make compensaMainly I
Punishultimately
like.
is

damage which he has caused


is

to another ?

think in order to deter others from doing the

ment

of the deterrent kind

I think what

intended.

Punishment
is

in the shape of

awarding compensation

to the injured party

a very convenient form of proceeding,

because

it

substitutes the action of the party for the action

of the state,

and

satisfies

a general sense of propriety which

makes people
728.

in general willing to co-operate and assist in

enforcing the penalty.

Why then
?

not punish an insane

man ? Would

it

not

Why inI'^^'^'i^y-

be as effectual as a deterrent to punish an insane as to punish prevents a sane person

The answer given by Lord Coke


is

in

the

Third Part of his Institutes

that punishment inflicted upon

an insane person would


cruel as rather to

be so generally

deemed inhuman and

make men
is

desperate than to deter

them

from crime.

Possibly this

may

be true.

The
is

deterrent effect

of the criminal law


it is,

probably increased by the sentiment that


just.

on the whole, humane and

It

also not unlikely

which awarded a penalty to the actions of insane persons would be ineffectual, since no one either as a prosecutor or witness would assist in enforcing the penalty if he could
that a law

help

it.

S50
Essentials

GROUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.
In.

[Chap. XVIT.

729.

the majority of cases the non -liability of insane

generally

inc

persons cannot be rested on the absence of the elements which ^^*' constitute legal liability. It is indeed possible that a man^s
intellect

may

be so disordered, that he
his

may

altogether fail to

perceive the consequences of


or to
is

acts,

whether to himself

any other person.


so.

But

in the majority of cases this

not

All the essentials of legal liability will on excase.


is

amination be found to be present in nearly every


the furious

Even
refused

madman who

kills his

keeper because he

his liberty, conceives a

wish which prompts him to do a certain


accomplish the end which he has

act in order that he


in view.

may

He

intends his keeper's death as

means

to that end,

and every condition of the crime of murder


Mode
in

is fulfilled.

730. But whatever

may
is

be the true ground on which


it

question submitted ^e that


to jury.

^^

ezcuse of insanity

based,

cannot by any possibiHty


^
'

which the form of the inquiry assumes in criminal


.

cases

when

the accused person

is

alleged to be insane.

The

law requires that the question should be put to the jury


in to
this

singular form

had

the accused sufiicient reason

know

that he was doing an act that was

wrong ^
it is

What

gave

rise to this

form of putting the question

not very

easy to discover.

The capacity
at

wrong has hardly


test of insanity.
is

of distinguishing right from any period been accepted as a general

Probably this form of putting the question


(as already
is

due to the notion which

mentioned) lurks in

our criminal law, but which


is

never boldly asserted, and

sometimes emphatically denied, that the moral quality of

the act determines the liability to criminal punishment.

How

dealt

731. It

must be remembered, however, that

this question has

tliem.

always to be answered in criminal cases by a jury

a tribunal

which generally comes to the task without any previous training, and which is wholly incompetent to discuss with
' See the answer of all the judges, except Mr. Justice Maule, to questions put by the House of Lords, at the end of the answer to the second and third questions. These questions and the opinions of the judges thereon were printed by the House of Lords on June 19, 1848 ; they are to be found in most works on Criminal Law.

Sec. 729-732-]

GROUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.

351

nicety the very peculiar and difficult question wliich the law
requires to be placed before them.
really

Probably^ therefore^ what

happens

is

that, consciously or unconsciously, the jury

give their verdict according to their opinion upon a

much
cir-

more general question

namely,

whether, under

all

the

cumstances, the prisoner ought to be punished: and, where


their decisions are not distorted

by a

special dislike of the

punishment provided for the offence


capital eases), the result
is

(as

sometimes occurs in

perhaps as good as any to which,


it is

in the present state of science, at

possible to attain

^,

And

any

rate the decision of a jury has this negative advantage;

that, if unsatisfactory, it forms

no precedent; on the conit

trary, the

public condemnation which follows


least,

serves as

a guide and warning, for some time at


errors.

against similar

It would, however, be

somewhat

better, if the ques-

tion were submitted

by the judge to the jury

in a simpler

form, so that his

own remarks might

be more intelligible,
their determina-

and more

direct

upon the point upon which

tion actually turns.

732.
is

The

liability

upon a

contract,

when one

of the parties insanity

insane at the time of the supposed agreement,

may
is

arise ^f jjo^.

either, first,

where the party

is,

or secondly,

where he

not,
^'^^j^^Jg'^g"

capable of understanding the nature of the transaction. the


first

In

of these two eases there

liability; in the second there

may be true contractual may be liability quasi ex contractu.


valid

Apparently, however, English lawyers ignore this distinction,

and

insist

upon saying that insane persons can make a


like

any one else, however disordered their contract just intellect may be, upon the somewhat curious ground that no one is allowed to plead his own deficiency of intellect. But they
will not

admit any
if

liability

either contractual or quasi ex


liability

contractu

the party seeking to enforce the


:

knew

of the other's incapacity


for the supply of
^

except in the case of necessaries,


is

which the insane person

in all cases

See the somewhat similar observations of Lord Hale, Pleas of the


vol.
i.

Crown,

p. 33.

352
liable
^.

GROUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.
Of
course, however, i the insane

[Chap. XVII.
been, in

man had

any way overreached the Courts


to protect him.
Insanity

of Chancery

would interfere

733.

How

far a person v?ho is insane

would be held

liable,

of non-lia- i^ courts of civil procedure, for his acts or omissions indepen*'jj'*y

dently of contract,
find our

is

a matter on which one


silent.

is

surprised to

cases.

law-books nearly
rule,

Lord Hale

lays

down,
this

however, a sweeping
defence in such cases
sort,
Error.

which would entirely shut out


no

that

man
^.

can, in matters of this

plead his

own mental

deficiency

734. Error, in the shape of ignorance of the consequences


of

an

act, or

mistake as to the consequences which are likely


it

to arise, of necessity renders

impossible for a
;

or disregard those particular consequences

man to intend man so ignorant


conditions

cannot therefore

incur

any

liability

which involves such


the habiHty
?

intention or disregard.
of liability to be

But supposing the normal


error prevent

satisfied, will

from
Ignorance
defect of

arising, or cause it to arise in a modified


^

form

735. Blackstone

says that
house,

if

man

intending to

kill

^ thief in his
family, this

own
not

by mistake

kills

one of his own

the will,

is

a criminal

action.

But Blackstone's
and the

explanation of this

is

most extraordinary ; and to me, indeed,

altogether unintelligible.

He

says,

'

for here the will

deed acting separately, there

is

not that conjunction between

them which is necessary to form a criminal act.'' Nothing can show more strongly than this confusion in the mind of so
1

See the case of The Imperial Loan

Company
p. 599.

against Stone,

Law

Reports, Queen's
2

Bench

Div., 1892, vol.

i.

Even if this dictum of Lord Hale be would still be necessary to consider how far the elements which go to make up liability were present when the act was done because the existence of these is alleged by the plaintiff, and must be proved before the defendant is called upon for his defence. If the plaintiff failed in this proof, it would still have to be considered whether there was a liability to make compensation, quite independent of intention or negligence and perhaps what Lord Hale really means is that,
Pleas of the Crown, vol. ii. p. 16.
it

accepted to the fullest extent,

as in contract, there is such a liability.


"

Commentaries,

vol. iv. p. 27.

Sec. 733-738.]

GROUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.

'

353

eminent a writer the importance of the analysis undertaken

by Austin,
to

of the relation between the mental consciousness

of the actor

and the act done.

It

is

not very safe to attempt

assign a meaning to

such a phrase as 'the will and


it is
'

the deed acting separately,' but I suppose


of the erroneous expression so often

another form

met with, doing an act


by means
of motions of

against your
this

will.'

The
But

true view of the case I take to be


will,

Acts are produced by the


aim
it at

our bodily muscles.


is

this exertion of the will, or volition,

the result of an
pistol,

antecedent desire.

Thus, I take up

you, and

pull the trigger, because I desire

to kill you.

I desire to kill you, because I believe that you

are breaking into

my

house,

and I consider

it

necessary to kill

you

in order to protect myself and

my

family.

After I have

fired,

I find that you are a relative, coming to pay


visit.

me an
will.

unexpected

My

mistake as to your person has caused

me

to desire your death,

which

desire has acted

upon

my

The same mistake has


justified in killing

also led

me

to suppose that I

was

you in

self-defence.

736. There
is

is,

I think, no doubt that the case here put


is,

one of murder, that

that

all

the elements of murder are

present,

and

if

the liability to capital punishment does not

arise, it is

because of the abnormal condition of the person

who

fires

the shot.

Whether any other liability than that to capital punishment wiU arise depends upon the circumstances. If I were not justified in assuming you to be a thief if I were rash in drawing that inference, I might be guilty, though of
737.

a difEerent crime.

For rashness may be a ground of criminal


is

imputation, and then the ignorance which


that rashness cannot absolve me.

the result of

738. So asrain where my mistake is not either rash or Will not excuse an some cases. Thus suppose act otherheedless, I may yet be liable

I see in
trees,

my
it

neighbour's garden something moving in the


to be

]^'^f"""

which I believe

a wild, but harmless animal.


it
is

I examine

very carefully, and satisfy myself that

A a

354

GROUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.
I fire at
is
it,

[Chap. XVII.

a wild animal.

and

it

turns

out to be

my

neighbour himself, who

dangerously wounded by the shot.


Because, though
if all
still

Here I
mistake

am clearly liable; and why? may be a reasonable one, yet,

my

that I believed

to be true were true,

my

act

would

be a breach of

a primary duty, and the facts which I supposed to exist

would not justify


stone.

it.

But not

so in the case

put by Black-

In that

case, if all I believed to be true

were

true,

there

would be an excuse for what would otherwise be


There
is is is

a breach of a primary duty.


forbear from taking
life is
life,

a primary duty to

but there
There

an exception where
a primary duty not

taken in self-defence.

to fire

guns into

my

neighbour's garden, and no exception

where the object


liable to

fired at is

a wild animal.

am

therefore
positive

such consequences as are laid

down by the

law.

I should be liable for manslaughter in England, because


j

of the extremely sweeping definition of that crime

perhaps

under the Indian Penal Code I should not have committed


a crime, but I should be liable
Ignorance
in cases of contract,
civilly.

739.

The

effect
is

of

error

on the
;

liability

which

arises

upon contract
increased

more complicated
to its

and

this complication is

owing

having been the custom to consider

under this head


thereto.
Inquiry
shut out
inter ^r** tation.

several matters

which do not properly belong


the

740. I have

already adverted

to

mode which

is

generally adopted for ascertaining the intention of the par^ *^ in casc of dispute.

It has there been observed, that all

a tribunal can do, after deciding upon the evidence what

were the terms of the contract, after hearing the statements


of both parties as to

what each intended, and

after inquiring

into the
so far as

circumstances which

happened about that time,

they throw any light upon the intention


its

is

to

put upon the words

own

interpretation,

and from that


in arriving at

interpretation to presume the intention.


this

But

presumption judges
*

generally,

as

I observed,

follow

Supra, sect. 622 sqq.

Sec. 739-742.]

GROUNDS OF NON- LIABILITY.


;

355

certain rules of

such, for instance, as that the technical terms


in

law can never be used


and
so

any other than

their technical
their ordinary

sense, or ordinary
sense,

words in any other than


1.

forth

So that a

careless

man may

find

himself fixed with an obligation arising upon a contract,

which he did not intend, almost without having had an


opportunity of asserting his mistake;
excuse of error
is

and

practically the

thus very often shut out, upon grounds


principles

which stand apart from the general


that excuse depends.
741.

upon which

of the promise

But suppose the covat to have determined the sense and that the promiser i^en seeks to deny
ground of
surely
error.

Consensus
^^j. j^^

his liability on the

How

will the court <liet>o"so

deal with it?

Not

upon the ground


is

frequently

put forward that where there


in
is

error there is

no consensus

idem and no contract.

That, as I have just pointed out,

an antecedent question, the very question which arose in


'

the well-known case of the

Peerless.^

There

agreed to buy
'

and

agreed to

sell

a cargo of cotton to arrive

ex Peerless

from Bombay.'

There being two ships of that name then

on a voyage home from


cotton, this

Bombay and both being

laden with

was an accurate description of two difEerent cargoes


the sense of the promise ' ^

and there being no circumstances from which the court could


determine that in accordance with
either one or the other
'

was meant, the sense of the promise


Probably
one of the ships and the

remained undetermined, and there was no contract.


the plaintiff

may have meant


;

defendant the other


conclusive
;

but this alone would not have been

if

the court could have determined that, accord-

ing to the reasonable construction of the language used under


the circumstances, one or other was meant, there would have

been a contract in this sense.


742. Cases of this class are cases in which the parties

have failed to use language to which any certain

sense

can be attributed, and therefore there can be no contractual


'

Supra, sect. 238.

"

See supra,

sect. 63a.

A a 2


356
liability.

GROUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.
But
if

[Chap. XVII.

there has

been

a transaction

in

which
it,

one party has made a promise and the other has accepted

and the sense of the promise can be determined, then


question of consensus ad idem
is

all

at

an end.

The sense

of the

promise determined upon

may

not be what both the parties


this, as

or either of them expected, but

we have
Liability

seen, does

not prevent the contract from arising^.

upon the

promise in the sense attached to


the result contemplated.

it

will

be taken to be

This

is

best seen
is

by an example.

A bar

of metal which belongs to

lying before

and B.

B, asking no questions but relying on his own judgment,

and thinking
market

it is

gold, offers to purchase 'that bar'' at the

price of gold,

which

offer

accepts.

In fact the bar

contains a considerable

amount
If

of inferior metal, so

much

that

merchants would not even


the promise to purchase.

call it gold.

StUl

is

liable

on

when sued by
in
his

he said that

he made a mistake and thought the bar was a bar of pure gold,

which he knew that


Error in
courts of
_

had

possession

and which
to.

he had examined carefully, he would not be listened


rj^^_

j^

xLsedi

to be
_

said that

the question of error was '

Chancery, differently treated in courts of

Chancery and courts of Comso,

mon Law

and

if

that were really

now

that

all

courts

administer the same law, the only law which


to consider

we

should have

would be the law of the courts

of Chancery.

But

I think the special doctrines of the courts of Chancery only


affected the peculiar kind of relief granted

by that court
but that
It

doctrines
for

which assumed that the


special reason it

liability existed,

some

ought to be manipulated.

must

be remembered that courts of Chancery used only to deal

with contractual

liability

when the remedy

at

law was

in-

' Supra, sect. 621. No doubt it may be said that wherever one party contemplates one thing and the other party contemplates another, that is,

is no consensus in idem. If so, every kind would render true contractual liability impossible. In practice, however, as I have frequently pointed out, the consensus is not arrived at by considering what were the expectations of the parties, but by considering what is the sense of the promise.

in all cases of error, there


of error

Sec. 743, 744.]

GEOUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.

357

effectual

and in such

cases these courts have always reserved

to themselves a full discretion to determine whether under


all

the circumstances they would assist the


to his ordinary remedy.

plaintiff, or leave

him

No

doubt, in considering this

question^ the courts have sometimes been influenced

by the
rules

allegation that

the defendant was

asked to do something

which he did not expect, but I do not think that any


form^744. The

have been yet laid down which could be stated in an abstract

Roman law

contains some rules on the subject Error


referred to.

in

of error which

may, I think, be usefully


and lead

The

law.

distinctions taken are clear,

to satisfactory results.

They do not
rather clearer.
substantia,

greatly differ from the English law, but are

Error was divided into two kinds


error in corpore.

error in

and

Error in substantia was

a mistake as to some quality of the subject-matter in question,


as, for
it

example, thinking that a bar of metal was gold when


really brass.
It
is

was

assumed tbat the


is

parties are agreed

as to the thing

that there
The
in

no

error in corpore, but only

error in substantia.
valid,

juristic act, therefore, is complete,

and binding,

in accordance with the m&'sxm.falsa causa

non

nocet.

And

many

transactions, such as delivery of

property, pledge, loan, &e., the error in substantia

was quite
good faith

immaterial, but in the contract of

sale, letting

and hiring, and

some other cases in which

special considerations of

were applicable, the judge would consider whether the error

ought to modify the legal

liability^,

' See supra, sect. 721. Until recently the courts of Chancery were the only courts which could directly set aside or modify an existing contractual liability : so too they were the only courts which could order Courts of ordinary jurisdiction could specific performance of a contract,

increase or reduce the damages, or could let the defendant go practically

principle.

But they did this without any The result is that there is very little law in England as to the effect of error, and for the most part only examples to show how discretion
free

by awarding nominal damages.

should be exercised.

Sohm's Institutes of Roman Law (Ledlie's translation), which the above paragraph is taken almost verbatim.
2

p. 136,

from

358
Error in

GBOUNDS OF

NON-LIAJBILITY.

[Chap. XVII.

745.

French

nuUite

'

The French law seems to treat error as a 'cause de of the contract, and to make no distinction between
and
it is

error in substantia

error in corpore.

But I am
is

still

not
all,

quite sure whether


or one of

meant that there


is

no contract at

which the result

modified

^.

Cundy

v.

746. There are some cases in the English law reports in

Lindsay.

which the grounds


follow,

of the decision are


will examine.

somewhat

difficult to
^

and which I

Cundy
goods.

against Lindsay

was a

case in

which A, by fraudulently stating that he was X,


Co. to sell

induced

8f

him some

contract

was

accordingly concluded by

^^

Co.

with

in the

name

of

In fulfilment of

this contract _B Sf Co. delivered goods to A,

and

sold

them

to C,

an honest purchaser, who accordingly

obtained possession of them.

Whether under these circumhad passed


to

stances the ownership of the goods

C by deUvery

does not necessarily depend upon whether or no there was

a contract between

and
it

Sf Co.,

but in this case the House

of Lords thought that

did so depend, and decided that there


all
;

never was any contract at

which

is,

of course, very differ-

ent from saying that there was a contract, although one


affected

by
(

fraud.
Co.) 8f

The words

of

Lord Cairns

are

Of him
'

{A) they

never thought.

With him they never

in-

tended to deal.

Their minds never for an instant rested on

him

and

as between

mind which could

lead to

him and them there was no consensus of any agreement or contract whatever.^
class
it

These words are wide enough to cover a very much larger


of cases than that

under consideration

cases

in

which

had always previously been held that there was a contract which could be enforced. For example, if A had been wholly
' II n'y a point de conaenfcement valable, si le consentement n'a 6i6 douu6 que par erreur. L'erreur n'est une cause de nullity de la convention que lorsqu'elle tombe sur la substance meme de la chose qui en est I'objet. EUe n'est point une cause de nullity, lorsqu'elle ne tombe que sur la personne avec laquelle on a I'intention de contractor, k moins que la consideration de cette personne ne soit la cause principale de la convention.' Code Civil, Art. 1109, mo. With the last clause compare
' . .

the decision in Cundy against Lindsay. ^ Lav7 Reports, App. Cases, vol. iii. p. 459.

Sec. 745-748.]

GBOUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.

359

innocent of fraud, and

8c

Co.

had

still

made a mistake
it

about ^'s identity,

all

that Lord Cairns says in the passage

quoted would be just as true.

Yet I do not think

has been

generally said in English law that in such a case there would

be no contract.

There was a

definite person

with

whom

Sj-

Co.

were in correspondence.

If they erroneously assumed


error has been

that

was X, I do not think that such an

generally considered to preclude the possibility of the existence


of the contract
is,
^.

But

in

any case the ground of the decision


liability

not that because of error the

on the contract must

be set aside or modified, but that because of the error there

was no consensus such as would make a contract. 747. In the case of Boulton against Jones ^ A had ordered
goods of B.
executed
it.

This order
It

fell

into the

hands of C, and

was held that there was no contract between


it

and

C.

This seems obvious; and

seems to

me

to be

a very different case from one in which


to C, addressing

gives an order

him

as

B, when,

if

there were

no fraud,

there would, I imagine, be a good contract between


if

and C

accepted the order.

748. In the case of Smith against

Hughes * the defendant


oats of the plaintiff.

had agreed to buy a

specific parcel of

The defendant thought that these were


was aware that they were new.
oats did not affect his liability.
plaintiff

old oats

the plaintiff

It

was agreed that the


was
said that

erroneous opinion of the defendant as to the nature of the

But

it

if

the

had known

that the defendant in making the bargain


plaintiff

with him for oats acted on the assumption that the

was agreeing to

him old oats, then there was no contract by the defendant to buy new oats. This, however, is clearly
sell

not on the ground of error


error in

there being as

much
it

or as little

one case as the other.

Nor

is

so

put in the

' See the article of the French Code quoted above, from which it appears that under the French law an error as to the identity of the contracting party is in most cases immaterial.

" '

Reported in Hurlstone and Norman's Reports, Reported in the Law Reports, Queen's Bench,

vol.

ii.

p. 564.

vol. vi. p. 597.

360

GROUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.
I take
it tliat

[Chap. XVII.

judgment ^.
decision

both the actual decision and the


case

in the hypothetical

proceed upon

the

same

ground, namely, that under the circumstances the sense of


the promise in the
first

case

was

to accept

and pay

for the

specific parcel of oats

whether old or new, and that in the

second case the sense of the promise was to accept and pay
for old oats only,

749, The case of Conturier against Hastie

has nothing

whatever to do with

error.

It turned, as the

Lord Chancellor
of the promise.

Cran worth says in his judgment, entirely upon the construction of the contract, that
is,

upon the sense

The

plaintiff

had

sold to the defendants a cargo of corn,

described as being then on a certain ship on her voyage to

England.
sequence of
sold.

Before the date of the sale the cargo, in conits

having become heated, had been landed and

This was not

known

to either party.

The House

of

Lords thought that the intention of the parties was that


there should be no liability under the circumstances which

had occurred

^-

750. The perusal of these cases does not encourage

me

to

attempt to lay down any general rules on the subject of error


' Sir James Hannen says that in the case supposed the plaintiff would have been aware that the defendant apprehended the contract in a different sense to that in which he meant it, and he is thereby deprived of the right to insist that the defendant shall be bound by that which was the apparent and not the real bargain.' See p. 6io of the Report,
'

ubi supra.

Reported in House of Loyds Cases, vol. v. p. 673. These are not the words of the judgment, but this is what must have been meant. Of course it was admitted that the defendants intended
^ ^

buy something, and the plaintiff said that according to the sense of the promise what they sold and what the defendants bought was, 'not the cargo absolutely as a thing assumed to be in existence, but merely the
to

benefit of the expectation of its arrival,

contingency of
intelligible

its loss.'

and of the securities against the The cargo was insured, and this was quite an
of the contract ; though,

and not an unreasonable construction

as the court thought, not the right one.

The

case of Strickland against


it is

Turner (which

is

said to be like Conturier against Hastie, as

in

some
It is

respects) also turned entirely

upon the sense of the promise.


vii. p.

reported in Exchequer Reports, vol.

ao8.

Sec. 749-751.]

GROUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.
They show very
are its terms
?

361
clearly the
(i)

as affecting liability in contract.

importance of keeping separate the three questions^


there a contract
there
?

was

(a) if so,

what

and

(3) is

any reason why the

liability

on

it

should be annulled

The circumstance that one of the parties was under an error when the contract was being negotiated may
or modified ?

be an important consideration in determining whether or no


the contract exists
;

but

it

being once determined that every

error is not fatal to the existence of the contract, I think

the courts must be

left in

each case to decide whether or no,


contract
is

notwithstanding the
established.

error, the existence of the


is

The

consideration of this point

apt to slide over

to a consideration of the second question


of the promise ? because

what was the sense


is

when that

is

determined the question

of error as affecting the existence of the contract often becomes

immaterial.
case in

As

to the third question, I doubt if there

any

which

error has been successfully pleaded in answer to

an action on a contract, when the court has once determined that there was a contract and has ascertained its meaning.

The only

resource then left to the defendant

is

in
its

some

discretionary

power of the court either


This
is

to

hold

hand
is

or to set aside the transaction.


called equitable,

a power which

and

is is

not exercised under fixed rules.

751. Intoxication

a disordered state of the

intellect, Intoxica-

produced by eating or drinking something. Blackstone says it is rather an aggravation of the offence than an excuse for
criminal misbehaviour;

any man thus to


not an
intent,
shall

and that the law will not privilege one crime by another^.

suffer

The
is

Indian Penal Code says 2;

'In cases where an act done

offence, unless done with a particular

knowledge or

a person who does the act in a state of intoxication be liable to be dealt with, as if he had the same
if

knowledge as he would have had,

he had not been intoxi^

Commentaries, vol. iv. p. 26. I doubt whether the passage of Lord Coke to which Blackstone refers as an authority for this position, has been correctly understood by him. See First Pai-t of the Institutes, p. 247.

Sect. 86.

362

GKOUNDS OP NON-LIABILITY.

[Chap. XVII.

cated, unless the thing


istered without his

which intoxicated him was adminhis will/

knowledge and against

The
itself

Erroneous English rule


ofBiaek-^
stone.

is

intelligible,
it is

though the reasoning by which


Drunkenness in

Blackstone supports

worthless.

can hardly be said to be a crime under English


even
that
if it

Law ^

and

were,

it

is

simply begging the question to say,

when

man

pleads drunkenness, he thereby seeks to

privilege one crime


Eule of Indian Penal Code
obscure.

by another;
is

the whole question being,


or is not

whether or no that other act


Indian rule
quite
sure
is

a crime. I

The
not

very
is

difficult of

comprehension.
'

am

what

meant by

a particular knowledge or

intent/ but I suppose setting

fire to

a house

is

an

offence,

though not done with any particular knowledge or intent


yet
it is

not at

all likely

that intoxication was intended to be

an excuse in such a
counterfeit coin
is

ease.

On

the other hand, passing

clearly
;

an offence in which a particular


is

knowledge
spurious
;

is

necessary

namely, knowledge that the coin

and

therefore, a

drunken

man who

takes a counter-

feit coin,

which he would certainly have discovered to be

counterfeit if he

had been

sober,

and pays

it

away without
But

discovering

it,

might under

this provision
it

be convicted of

passing counterfeit coin knowing


this result seems very remarkable.

to be counterfeit.

True effect

752.

The

question,

how

far intoxication affects liability,


settled

ingthede- can never, I think, be


fence of in^^.X, things " toxication altogether the state of

satisfactorily

by presuming
really are.
.

are

different

from what they

If

mind which we
consideration

call knowledge or intention

nal cases,

is

essential to the breach of the

duty or obligation in quesbe,

tion,

the

first

will

whether or no the

drunkenness was such as to have prevented the possibility


of such a state of

mind.

It

is

perfectly consistent with

very great drunkenness that a

man

should

the consequences of his acts.


^

soldier

know and intend who after a day's

It is

an

offence punishable

chap.

vii. sect. 3.

by a fine of five shillings under 21 James I. But simple drunkenness, independently of any other

consideration, is very rarely, if ever, punished.

Sec. 752-754.]

GROUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.
of

363
his

hard drinking discharges his musket in the face


sergeant,
actj just

may know and

intend the consequences of

his

as well as the jealous lover


mistress.

who
it
is

stabs his rival

in the

arms of his

Indeed

hardly possible
sort

to preserve the physical capacity to execute this


crime,

of

without also retaining the low degree


is

of
if

intelli-

gence which
not the case;

necessary to the offence.


if

But,

that

is

the drunkenness

is

such that no offence


the
particular
offence
effect of

can

have been committed, or not


is

with which the person

charged;

then the true


spite

presuming knowledge or
is

intention, in

of

the facts,
is

to

able

make drunkenness itself an offence, which with a d^ree of punishment varying with
^-

punish-

the con-

sequences of the act done


753.
in

How
coiirt

far intoxication affects the liability of a


of

man,

lutoxica-

civU procedure, to

make compensation
in

damage
tion
liability.
is

done, has been

little discussed.

would be here
necessary

necessary as

.....
The same
the person
it,

for q^^j!"

distinc- '^^^^ ^^^'^ crimes

considering criminal and

If the liability be such that the state of

mind
mind.

^f go.
*'^*^*'

element of

it,

then

pleading

intoxication
If

may, or may
it,

not,

have that state of


like

he

has
is

then he

is

liable

any other person.


then,
if

If he
liable

so
all,

intoxicated that he cannot have

at

he

is

liable

because there

is

law, which

what they do when drunk, independently of any consideration of their state of mind when

makes men
they did
754.

liable

for

it.

In cases of contract, an intoxicated


this

man may,

or intoxicacontract.

may

not, have the degree of intelligence necessary to agree

upon the terms of a contract; and


of inquiry.

would be a matter
intervenes.

But here a

different

principle
it
;

man who

is

intoxicated generally shows

and there

is this

' It would appear from a passage in Lord Hale that some lawyers have thought that the formal cause of punishment ought to be the drunkenness, and not the crime committed under its influence. Pleas of the

Crown,

vol.

i.

p.

3a.

364

GROUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.
man who

[Chap. XVII.

exception to the law that contracts will be enforced, that

a contract made with a


not be enforced.

is

apparently drunk wiU

The sovereign

authority, for

good reasons,

has decided that people ought not to attempt to transact


business

with persons whose incapacity to exercise sound


is

judgment
Infancy.

thus apparent.
rules

755.

The

which govern the

liability of infants

and

minors have varied considerably in different countries.

They

have had their origin mainly, but not exclusively, in considerations of intellectual deficiency.

They have been founded


in-

sometimes on the necessity of subjecting young persons to


parental or other control;

sometimes on their physical


;

capacity to go through certain forms

and not unf requently


;

on their incapacity for sexual intercourse

but the most

prominent consideration has, of course, always been the absence of that knowledge and experience which
to
is

necessary

enable any one to

appreciate the

consequences of his

acts.

Traces of

all

these principles

Roman, the English, the But it is obvious that an inquiry


intellectual capacity

may be found in the Hindoo, and the Mahommedan Law.


into either physical or
difficult

would be both

and inconvenient
inquiry has been
certain fixed

and consequently, the necessity


to a great extent superseded,
rules as to liability, based simply

for this

by laying down

upon the age of the person

sought to be made
Criminal
cases.

liable.

756.

The

rules

vary somewhat in different countries, and


of

they also vary with reference to the nature


or obHgation

the duty

which

is

in question.

As

regards acts which

lead to penalties or forfeitures under criminal procedure, a


child cannot, under the Indian Penal Code^, be
until he has attained the age of seven years.

made

liable

Above seven

years and under twelve the child will not be Hable unless he

has attained

sufiicient

maturity of understanding to judge


This means

of the nature and consequences of his conduct.

that he will generally be considered not to have attained that


1

Sect. 83.

Sec. 755-758.]

GEOTJNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.

365
so.

condition;

but he

may
is

be shown to have done


same,

The
that

Law

of

England
is

substantially the

except

fourteen years

substituted for twelve.


is

The French Code


under sixteen years

provides that, wherever the accused


of age, there

must be an inquiry

into

what

is

called his

discernment ^.

As

regards those acts which are usually called torts or

delicts,

the consequences of which are liability to

make com-

pensation, or

some other obligation of a

civil

kind, they would

probably be dealt with upon the same principles as acts which


are punished criminally.

757.

As
is

regards contracts, the law

is

very favourable to

Contracts,

young

persons.

Up

to a certain age, which in

European
though

countries

usually fixed at twenty-one, they are not gene-

rally liable to obligations created

by way

of contract,

they can sometimes compel persons who have made promises to

them

to perform them.

But though the minor cannot by


specially appointed

his

own
his

act incur

any

obligation, there is generally

some person,
for

father or mother, or a person

the purpose, and

who

in this relation is called his guardian,


certain circumstances, valid contracts

who can make, under


on the minor's behalf.
full age,

Moreover, a minor, on attaining his


ratify, either expressly, or

may sometimes
age.

by acknow-

ledging their existence in any other way, contracts

him when under

minor may

also

generally
life.

made by make
In India

a valid contract to pay for the necessaries of

the same general principles apply to contracts


as in Europe.
at

made by minors
fixed
^-

The age

of majority

is

however there

eighteen for some purposes, and

at twenty-one for others

758.

We

now come
little

to another matter, upon which there Duress

has been no
of terms.

confusion,

owing

to the inconsiderate use

We

constantly hear people speak of a


discuss

man

doing

an act against his


of

will, and lawyers an act done against the will. But if we use language th the precision which is absolutely necessary in order
1

the validity

does not

t^e

wm.

Code P6nal, Art. 66.

See Act.

ix.

of 1875.

366
to

GEOUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.

[Chap. XVII.

deduce legal consequences, and revert to the

analysis

above given of the relation between the will and the act
(the only one

which appears

to

me

to be rational),

it

will be

at once apparent that to say that a

man

has done an act

against his will


into your
is

is

flat contradiction.

If I thrust a

gun
it

hand and
fire

force your finger on to the trigger,

who

the

against your will.


if

gun and not you. You do no act at


it

You do not do an
all.

act

On

the other hand,

I present

you a document for signature, and inform you


I shall

that unless you sign

blow your brains

out, pro-

ducing at the same time a


in earnest
;

pistol to convince

you that I
;

am
in

whereupon you take up the pen and sign

that case you sign in accordance with your will, and not

against

it.

What

I have operated upon


will.

is

not your

will,

but

the desires which influence your

I have never deprived

you, nor can I ever deprive you, of the power of freely

choosing whether to sign the paper or to be shot through


the head.
I put

Knowing

that you have a strong desire to

live,

you in a position

in which, in order that that desire

may be

accomplished, you must do an act which you otherwise

desired not to do. to the act

I might be mistaken.
so great that death

Your repugnance
preferable.

might be

would be

Many
virtue.

woman

has preferred death to yielding up her

759. This will be seen more clearly


case,

if

we compare

this

which most people would describe as an act done against

the will, with a case which would not be so described, but

which

will be

found on examination to stand on precisely the


I

same grounds.
enemy, who I
putting

am

a prisoner in the hands of a cruel

feel certain will take

an early opportunity of
chance of speaking to
if

me

to

death.

I have the

you, and promise you a thousand pounds

you

will carry

message to one of

my

friends,

who, I

feel sure, will

come to

my

aid

when he

learns

my

situation.

It

is

exceedingly

painful to

me

to

expend so large a sum of money, which

I can

ill

spare,

and I would gladly avoid doing

so.

But

Sec. 759-762.]

GROUNDS OP NON-LIABILITY.

367

I fear to lose

my

life,

and you

will not take less, so I sign

a promise to pay that amount.


this as

No

one would speak of

an act done against


will, in

my

willj

and yet the condition

of

my

this case, is precisely the

same

as that of

yours, in the former case.

In each case the


desire to live,

will is influenced

by

conflicting desires

the

and the

desire to

avoid an act;
accordingly.

the desire to live preponderates, and

we

act

760. Having removed this misconception,


the improper influence upon the desires, which
affects the liability

let
is

us see

how

called duress,

which

arises

out of an

act.

As

in all

other cases,
creates

it is

only by an examination of the law which

the primary obligation, that

we can
into

discover this.

Under what circumstances


what
rid of
is

does the law create obligations

upon contracts which have been entered


termed duress ?
761.

by persons under

great

many

eases of so-called duress

may be

got Real cases


of cluiTGSS

upon a very simple ground.

If a promise

the influence of duress be for the benefit of

made under the person who

asaground
ija^ijt'

has used the improper influence, this person will not be


allowed to enforce the promise, on the ground that no one

can be allowed to take advantage of his

own wrongful

act.

But there are undoubtedly cases in which a promise will not be enforced, though the promisee be wholly innocent. Thus
if

a friend of mine asked you to lend


I,

him a thousand pounds,


to

and
your

wishing his request to be granted, threatened to take


unless

life

you signed a promise

pay him the money,

the promise would not be enforced, although he and I were

not acting in concert.


762.

The

principles

upon which the sovereign authority

Eules

will refuse to enforce a promise in such cases

far as I

am

aware, been very exactly stated.

have not, as govern If a judge ^''^^^

has to decide such a ease he would generally consider a good


deal,

what under

all

the circumstances appeared to be just

and proper.
adopted.

Three rules

appear

however to

have been

First, the danger to be avoided must be of a

368

GROUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.
is,

[Chap. XVII.

serious kind, that

danger to

life,

or limb, or liberty, either

of the

person himself, or of his wife, or of his children.


of losing one's
is

Danger

good character, or of injury to one's


serious.

property,

not considered sufficiently

Nor

is

the

danger of being sued in

civil process, or of

being charged
serious

with a crime.
to justify the

Of

course I

mean not
person

sufficiently

non-performance of a promise made to an

innocent

person.

Should the

who

threatens

the

danger himself seek to enforce the promise, the case would,


as I have pointed out, be treated

on

different principles.

Secondly,

it

is

necessary that

the danger should be of

something which a person of ordinary constancy and firmness

may

fairly expect to

happen; and the act must be one

which a prudent man would do to avoid the danger.


Thirdly, the escape from the anticipated harm,

by making

the promise, must be suggested by some one other than the

promisor himself, and the act must be the direct consequence


of the suggestion.

763.

The

effects

of duress

upon criminal

liabiHty,

and

upon

civil liability

independently of the agreement of the


far as I

parties, has

never, as

am

aware, been discussed.

Cases of this kind are of rare occurrence, and are frequently


capable of being solved on other principles.
Use of
'

7e4_ In

discussing

the

effect

upon

his

liability
act,

of the

void.'

abnormal condition of the party who does the guarded myself against the use of the word
to
'

I have

void,' in order

prevent misconception.
act

There are
produce
the

cases,

no doubt, in
liability,

which the
even by

does

not

usual
it

or

itself

any

liability at all.

But

does not follow

from

this that the act is devoid of all legal results.

"We

have a very strong example of this in the case of infancy. The statute which protects infants in cases of contract uses
the strongest language upon this point.
It says that the
if
it

promise of the infant


to

is

absolutely void^, as

meant

make

it

a simple nullity.
'

But
C.

is
s. I.

it

so?

The infant

37

&

38 Vict.,

62,

Sec. 763-768.]
if

GEOUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.
is

369 defend

sued on the promise

put to his plea.


:

He may

himself

by

alleging his infancy

but

if

he does not specially

allege this defence he will be found to be liable.

bare

denial of the contract will not help him, as


if

it

certainly should

the transaction were a nullity ^.

765. Fraud
fore,

is

error produced

by mendacity.

It

is,

there- Fraud,

a particular case of

error.

But

it

requires

separate

consideration, because the effect of error


arises

on

liability

which

upon a contract
of

is

largely affected
it

by the

considera-

tion

whether or no

was created by a mendacious


sues

statement.

766. In contract,

if

upon a contract which

originated in an agreement induced

by

fraud,
into,

and
it

pleads
certain

simply that no

contract

was entered

is

that the court, even though the fraud appear, will hold that
there

was such a

liabiHty.

If

it,

pleads that he was induced

to agree

by fraud, and proves


judgment

the court will under certain

conditions give

in his favour.

But whether upon

the ground that there never was any contractual liability, or

upon the ground that

this contractual liability will be set aside


is

because of the fraud, it


767.

not always easy to determine.


is

As

far as the defendant

concerned, the result

is

the

same whether the court says there never was any


unconditionally removes that liability.
it

liability or

But

to other persons

may

be of enormous importance

this is well illustrated

by the case of Cundy against Lindsay which I have above


stated 2.

768. In

Cundy
it

against Lindsay the property had actually


dis-

been delivered, and (though this seems to have been


regarded)

was

quite possible to hold that


transferred, although

by the

delivery
of the

the ownership was

by reason

fraud no liability arose out of the contract which preceded


the delivery.
to

But take a

case

where

A by

fraud induces

agree to

sell

him a

house, and then C,


is

who

acts perfectly

honestly, before the conveyance


1

executed, agrees to purchase


'

Simpson on

Infants, p. 500.

Supra,

sect. 746.

Bb

370

GROUNDS OF NON-LIABILITY.
him the money.
It

the house from A, and pays

makes
If

all

the

difference whether the contract of

B to

carry out the purchase


it

was never

created^ or

whether

it

will be set aside.

was

created^ then

no court would

set it aside

without considering

the position of C, and

how he would be

affected

by the

order.

But

if

no

liability at all

was created by the

transaction, then

there would be no

room

for such a consideration as this.

If

were sued on the contract he would simply prove the non-

existence of his liability,

and

C would

be left to any remedy

he might have against .


769. The question whether fraud prevents the existence of
the contract, or whether
or for enforcing
it it is

a ground for not enforcing

it,

conditionally, or with

some modification,
fraud

is,

notwithstanding

its

importance, very often left in obscurity.

Many

writers

lay

down broadly

that

prevents the

consent of the party defrauded from being a real or sufficient


consent,

meaning thereby (apparently) that

it

prevents the
this is very

existence of an agreement.
rarely held to be the case.

But I think that

And
is

I observe that those who

deny the
denial.

reality of the consent,

do not always adhere to this

This contradiction

very apparent in the Indian


is

Contract Act, where after saying that where there


there
is

fraud
is

no

real consent it is said

little later

that there

in the

same ease not only an agreement but an enforceable


is,

one, that

'

contract

'

in the

language of the Code

^.

^ See sects. lo, 14, ig, and the definition of contract in word used in the Indian Contract Act is not 'real' but induced by fraud is said to be not free.

sect. 2 (h).
'free.'

The

Consent

CHAPTEE

XVIII.

SUCCESSION,
770.

Theke

are

few

institutions

of law whicli

can be Origin

of

fully understood

one time, or in

by considering them as they exist at any any one place. This is specially true of
is

cersron!""'

that head of law which

dealt with in this chapter,

and

I will therefore attempt to state


as to succession originated.

how

our present notions

771. I will first explain generally

what I mean by the Meaning


an
infinite sion!""^^'

term succession.
variety of rights
obligations.

Every member
and
is

of society has

subject to

an

infinite

variety of
;

He

has property in his


;

own

possession

he has

property in the possession of others


to other persons,

the law has bound

him

and has bound other persons to him; he

owes money
his

to some, others

owe money

to

him

he has of

own

accord entered into engagements of various kinds

with various persons, and bound various persons to himself

by

contracts;

many

of

these

obligations

on either side
with him

remain unperformed.
(so to

Thus a man

carries about

speak) a vast mass

or bundle of rights

and

obligations,

which are attached to himself, in the sense that they are


conceived as binding lum or belonging to 1dm.
or

This mass
lawyers
obli-

bundle

of rights

and

obligations

the

Roman

called a

man^s jus.

What

becomes of these rights and

whom they are attached? on whom do they devolve ? Do they also perish ? If not, That is determined by the law which I am about to consider
gations

when

the person dies to

the law of succession.


772. It
is

frequently said

that the law of succession


this portion of the

How

far

rests entirely

upon

fictions

and
B b a

law has

fictions.


372

SUCCESSION.

[CKap. XVIII.

accordingly had to sustain

many

attacks upon that

weak

side

which

all

institutions

based upon fictions present.

How

far the statement that the


fictions is true will

law of succession

is

based upon

appear

when we examine
conception

the conceptions

from which
Vniversitas
juris.

it

has been derived.


first

773.

The

main

which

underlies

the

modern law of

succession cannot be seized without a little

preliminary consideration of a term of the Civil Law^ which


contains the idea whence all our conceptions of succession
originally sprang,

though
becomes

it

has been to some extent de-

parted from.
solved
isj

I have already said that the problem to be


of

what
to

the

rights

and obligations
dies
;

which are attached to a person when that person


I have

and

now

explain that these rights and

obligations

have been frequently conceived, not separately, but as a


whole.

And

this

mass or bundle of rights and obligations


being conceived, and dealt with as

attaching to

man

a whole, it has been natural to give to it a name. The name given to it by the Civil lawyers was juris universitas. ' A Sir Henry Maine has thus explained this term ^
:

universitas juris

is

a collection of rights and duties united


their

by the

single

circumstance of

having
as It
it is

belonged at

one time to some one person.

It

is

were the legal


not formed by
It can only

clothing of some given individual.

grouping together any rights and


be constituted by taking
a particular person.
all

atiy duties.
all

the rights, and

the duties of

The

tie

which

so

connects a

number

of rights of property, rights of

way, rights of
obligations

legacies, duties

of

specific

performance, debts,

to

compensate

wrongs

which

so connects all these legal privileges and

duties together as to constitute


is

them a

universitas juris

no

the fact of their having attached to

some individual
is

capable of exercising them.


university of rights juris
is

Without

this fact there

and

duties.

The

expression universitas
is

not classical, but for the notion iurisprudence


'

Ancient Law,

first ed., p. ij8.

Sec. 773. '774-]

SUCCESSION.

373
nor
is

exclusively indebted to
to seize.

Roman law

it

at all difficult

under one conception the whole set of legal relations in which each one of us stands to the rest of the world. These, whatever be their
to collect

We

must endeavour

character and composition,


juris;

make up

together a wikersitas

and there
if it

is

but

little

danger of mistake in forming

the notion,
enter
into

we

are only careful to


as

remember that duties

much as rights. Our duties may overbalance our rights. A man may owe more than he is worth, and therefore if a money value is set on his collective legal relations he may be what is called insolvent. But for
quite
all

that the entire group of rights and duties which centres

in

him

is

not the

less

a juris

universitas.'
it

774. Another conception which, though


to

cannot be said Ownernallycof-'


Po''^*^-

belong to the

modem
is

law of succession, yet underlies that


It has

law in every part,

that of corporate ownership.


first

already been intimated^ that according to the

notion

^ Supra, sect. 326. I venture to retain this opinion notwithstanding the emphatic condemnation of it by two very learned persons in a recently published work (Pollock and Maitland, History of Early English Law, chap, vi.), and I do so for the following reasons. Family ownership, in the form in which it prevails in the greater part of India, may, I think,

Every member acquires his rights by there is no inheritance until partition there is no sense of the woi'd in which a single member can be said to be owner of more than a possibility of acquiring something. It is true that on a partition he would get a share, and what share could at any given moment be ascertained, but it changes constantly. Every birth and every death of a member of the family affects it. I am at a loss to see how, before partition, that makes him an individual owner of anything. The same is true of every member of a trading corporation. Further, if family ownership in India may be correctly described as corporate, there is little remaining doubt that corporate ownership is older than individual ownership. The conception of family ownership which prevails in one part of Lower Bengal, under which each member of the family is owner of his share, is generally admitted to be a modification of the more prevalent form. Individual ownership probably had its origin in separate acquisition. The reduction of a family by death or partition to a single person does not really introduce individual ownership. Such a person strongly resembles a corporation sole. His son at birth becomes co-owner with him. Of course these ideas in regard to ownership were not conceived by Hindoos in their abstract form nearly everything was
be correctly described as corporate.
:

birth alone

there

is

perpetual succession

374
of society, at

SUCCESSION.
any
rate according to the
first

[Chap. XVIII.

Aryan

notion,

ownership

in

general

was not individual, but corporate.

Property belonged not to an individual, or a determinate


set of individuals,

but to an aggregate of persons, such as

a family or
case in

tribe.

But such
difficulty

corporate ownership

is

just the

which the

about succession vanishes.

The

rights

and obligations are in

this case attached to the cor-

porate body, and the existence of the corporate body to which

the rights and obligations are attached

is

in no

way

affected

by the death 775. Nor Succession


rate^^

of individual
is

members

of the corporation.

this

view of succession confined to those an aggregate of indi-

Corporations which are composed of

owner-

viduals, such as [a family, or a municipality, or a trading

company.
poration
is

Precisely the

same takes place where the


single individual, or, as

corit

represented

by a
is

is

termed in English law,

a corporation sole ; such as the king,


idol.

the parson of a parish, or the priest {shehait) of a Hindoo


It
is

not the particular incumbent of the


is

office in

whom

the
it

property
is

vested,

and

to

vyhom the obligations attach j

the Crown, or the Church, or the Deity; or some abstrac-

tion of that kind, of


shehait
Transition
is ^

which the king, the parson

'^,

or the

only the representative.

776.
^'^'^

Now once having seized the

idea of a juris universitas

skinto sole

^ ^ corporation, especially of a corporation sole, there need

owner-

j^q^

be any difficulty about mastering the conception of succes-

sion.

There

is

a reasonable probability that the idea of in-

dividual succession

grew out

of the idea of corporate succession,


is

and, although the transition


to suppose that it
ceived.

considerable, there
one, or that
it

is

no reason

was a violent

was even per-

The corporate ownership

of the family no doubt con-

covered by the simple rule that the


inter se.
'

members of a family had no rights Compare also the passage of the Digest quoted atp.379in the note. So called because he is said vicem seu personam eccksiae gerere. Coke upon
;

Littleton, 300 a
^

Blackstone, Commentaries, vol.

i.

p. 384.

here refer generally to Maine's Ancient Law, chap, vi, where the early history of testamentary succession is most ably and learnedly
I

may

discussed.

Sec. 775-777.]

SUCCESSION.

375

tracted to the individual ownership of the father, not suddenly,

but gradually

and

so too

with succession.
representative

The father had


of

been the

sole

manager and
was
still

the family

whilst ownership

corporate; and whether one indi-

vidual succeeded another as owner or as

manager would not


familiar.

become apparent until long


ship

after rights of individual owner-

had become well established and

change

from corporate to individual

succession, therefore, like the

corresponding change from corporate to individual ownership,

would produce no external change of


sition

itself

and one tran-

would proceed as an unconscious development of the


There was,
it

other.

is

true, a

new

question to be solved,
it
;

but
if it

it is

very likely that nobody asked

and no

one, even

had been asked, would have doubted about the answer.


let

There was nothing to be done except to


before.

things go on as

The

old head of the family being dead, the

new

heads of families would take his place ;

whether as managers

on behalf of their respective families, or on their own behalf,

would make no external

difEerence.

It

was only

after the

notions of personal obligation and personal ownership had been fully established, that it would occur to any one to ask

how, when the person

is

dead, can the rights and obligations


his

which were attached to

person

continue?

Then only
necessary,

would the continuation of


heir

his existence in the person of his

come

to be

questioned;

and the doubt,

if

resolved

by

a iiction that the aneesto/s existence was con-

tinued in the person of the heir.


777. It appears to me, however, at least open to question, Continua-

whether the continuation of existence in the person of the


heir '

ex'utenoe
in j)6r90n of heir,

which we now

call

fiction,

was not
It
is

in earlier times ofanoestor

stated as a solemn physical truth.


to account for the broad

difiicult

otherwise
this

and general terms

in

which

continuation

is

appealed to as a fact;

not only

by Roman
seem

lawyers, but by lawyers of other countries.

The Hindoo
to

lawyers

when

discussing the rights of

succession

assert the

physical identity of father and son, and also of

376

SUCCESSION.
;

[Chap. XVIII.

fatter and daughter quite as strongly

and, whenever they

have to deal with a disputed question of succession, treat this


identity as a self-evident truth.

Thus Manu says:


is,

'The
is

son of a

man

is

even as himself, and as the son

such

the

How, then, if he have no son can any inherit but who is closely united with his own soul ? ' ^ Nay, even when dealing with the rights of a widow, the
daughter.
the daughter,

great contest as to her right of succession seems to have been


settled

by the observation that body


sui-vives.

'

Of him whose

wife

is

not

deceased, half the

How then
is

should another
'

take his property while half his person

alive ?

Similar

strong expressions of complete physical identity also occur


frequently in the Bible.

The legend
from

of

Eve having been


bones, and flesh

formed out of a

rib taken
'

Adam

the latter's exclama-

tion on seeing her, of

This

is

now bone

of

my

my

flesh

'
;

and the frequent assertion by blood relations

that they are to each other as bone of the bone, and flesh of

the

flesh,

even by those connected through females, are at

least very remarkable^.

778. Continuation of the existence of the ancestor in the

person of the heir

is, it

is true,

not the only ground of inthe Hindoo lawyers of the


is

heritance recognised.

Amongst

Bengal

school,

whose principal authority

a treatise called

the Dayabhaga, the notion that spiritual benefits are conferred

by the

heir

upon the ancestor enters largely


This notion
is

into

their

conception of succession.

based upon three

assumptions

(i) that the deceased is benefited

by

his wealth

being expended on the performance of


(2) that it will
^

certain ceremonies

be so expended;

(3)

that the extent of the

Chap.

ix.

verse 130.
xi. sect, i,

Dayabhaga, chap.
perhaps,
is

verse

2.
i.

But the
sect. 3,

strongest passage of
:
'

all,

in the Mitacshara, chap.

verse to

The woman's

property goes to her daughters because portions of her abound in her

female children
of

him abound
'

in his

and the father's estate goes male children.'


;

to his sons because portions

Genesis

Chronicles

out of

Judges ix. 2 2 Samuel v. 1, xix. 12, 13 14 In Genesis xv. 4 it is said, He that shall come forth thine own bowels shall be thine heir.'
ii.

23, xxix.
j..

xi.

'

Sec. 778, 779.J

SUCCESSION.

377

benefit depends

on the relationship of the deceased to the


the ceremonies.

person

who performs
of

The

last

determines

the order

succession.

The second was,

of course, only
to leave

applicable to the scanty wealth

men

formerly used
still

behind them, and though the ceremonies are

performed

somewhat
all

lavishly,

they do not now necessarily absorb nearly


It
is

the accumulated property of the deceased.

not imall

probable

that the

original

practice

was to apply

the

available wealth of the family to the performance of family

ceremonies and the perpetuation of family sacra

and thus
profit-

what was
has
still

originally a

mere family duty has become a

able right.

Though from a

legal point of view the


it

duty
it

now dwindled

into a fiction,

was once

real;

and
^

supplies a not unjust rule of inheritance, based mainly


of males to females
is

upon propinquity and a preference


779.

But

in the Mitacshara, which


is

supposed to be older
'^,

than the Dayabhaga, and


right of succession
is

of far wider authority

the

nowhere placed upon the ground of

spiritual benefits conferred.


his propositions for the

The author

of this treatise rests

most part upon the bare rule of proone class

pinquity;
oblations
(goiraja)

and though he recognises the offering of funeral


as

a distinctive mark of
others,

of

relations

and perhaps of

he does not treat this as an

essential condition.

He

has apparently heard of the notion

but rejects

it;

as well as the

more general assumption that


^.

accumulated wealth can only be used for religious purposes


This
is

probably the reason

why the

author of the Dayabhaga


spiritual benefits at

discusses

and defends the doctrine of


I

such great length.

may

observe that the authors of both

treatises consider the little that the

Code of
*-

Manu

says upon

the subject favourable to their views 1 See Dayabhaga, chap. xi. sects. 5 and 6.
' '

Colebrooke's

Law

of Inheritance, Preface, pp. iv.


ii.

and

xii.

See Mitacshara, chap.


sect,
i,

sect. 3, verse 4,

and

sect. 5,

verse

and

compare

* See Manu, See also Mitacshara, chap.

verse 14, with verses 22, 23. chap. ix. verse 186 sqq., and compare verses 106
ii.

sect. 3, verses 3

and 4

and 142. and Dayabhaga,

chap. xi. sect. 5, verse 6 sqq.

378

SUCCESSION.

[Chap. XVIII.

Law

of

780. The law of succession as developed under the cominfluence

in^lndTa!" bined

of

Brahminical law and

the decisions

of

English judges in India presents


able interest. as the

many

features of remark-

Starting,

apparently, from the same

point

law of Europe, namely the corporate ownership of

families,

and

asserting, as I

have already shown, quite as

strongly the physical unity of kindred, the Hindoo law of


succession

down

to the

present day

is

still

in

close con-

nexion with the law of the family.

In the west, even in

ancient Rome, on the death of the head of the family each

new family, and there were as new families as the deceased left sons surviving him. many But this was not the case in India in earlier times, nor is
son became the head of a
it so

even now.

Throughout India the death of the father


If he were

leaves the

family single and intact.

sole

owner, his heirs become either corporate or joint owners of


his property,

and

so

remain until a distinct act of separation


is

takes place

and the feeling

rather against than in favour

of such a separation. of

If the father was himself a


all

member
the

a joint

family,

his

descendants are so too;

property before and after his death being held in common.

So long

as the family remains united there is

common
is

purse into which, and

out

of

which, everything
the

paid,

without any account being taken of


tributions or expenses;

individual

con-

the fund

itself,

and the expenditure

from

it,

being under the control of the family, generally

represented

the

by a manager. This is so even in Bengal, where members of the family are the individual owners of their
Individual rights are dormant.
It
is

shares.
collision

only in case of

between the members of the family, leading to


that any
it

disruption,

question

as

to

individual

rights

arises;

and then

first

becomes really important whether

the members are joint owners or a corporation.


therefore,

The change,
ownerit

from corporate

ownership to

individual
is

ship has been a very slow one in India, and

not even

yet

complete.

It

is

still

denied in

some parts of India


Sec. 780, 781.]

SUCCESSION.

379
dispose
is

that
and,

the

individual
if

members
This

can

of

anything
give

even

they can, a partition


disposition.

necessary to

effect to

the

explains the curious place

that

We

of succession occupies under Hindoo law. Europe have long been accustomed always to deal with the law of succession as connected with the rupture

the law

in

of the family

by death

the Hindoo lawyers deal with

it

as connected with the rupture of

the family by partition.

It

might be

said that there is in fact no

succession, but
treatises

only a law of partition.

Hindoo law of The two great


are of
inheritance,
is

which Colebrooke
said to

has translated, and which

commonly
really deal

contain the

Hindoo law

with a subject for which the Sanscrit term

dayabliaga;

and
to

this, as

the

authors of both treatises are


inheritance,

most careful

explain, means, not

but the

partition of wealth^.

781. Probably the oldest form of succession, though

it is Division

based upon a X^-^^ ^ division of the family into groups of male agnates, each group groups.

now

almost completely effaced,

is

that which

is

consisting of a

man and

his

descendants, and each group

having been, originally, a corporation.

The whole

family,

and any portion of the family whose


a

lines of descent

meet in

common

ancestor, forms a group of that kind.

Thus, suppose

the following diagram be taken to represent the male agnates


of a family:

Dayabhaga, chap.

i.

w.

1-5

Mitacshara, chap.

i.

sect,

i,

vv. 1-6.

Lassalle has pointed out the difference between the (so-called) intestate

succession of the early

German law and

the intestate succession of Kome.

very remarkable similarity between his description of the German law and the Hindoo law as it appears in the Mitacshara. See Compare Syst. d. Erworb. Eechts, vol. ii. Part ii, especially pp. 583 aqq. In suis heredibus evidentius also the following remarkable passage apparet continuationem dominii eo rem perducere, ut nulla videatur hereditas fuisse, quasi olim hi domini essent, qui etiam vivo patre quoItaque non hereditatem percipere dammodo domini existiraantur. . videntur, sed magis liberam bonorum administrationem consequuntur.' Dig. 28, 2, II. This looks as if there were traces at Kome of a system

There

is

a.

'

similar to that of the Hindoos

and early Germans.

!80

Sec. 782-786.]

SUCCESSION.
of persons forming the group
is

381
disregarded.

The number The


1)

distance of the individual from the

common

ancestor
if

is

disregarded.

Thus, on a partition the individual T,

and

weredead, would get as much as the whole group B.


784. It
is

useless to speculate as to the causes

which led

to

this

method of

partition,

which does not to our eyes appear

very equitable.
extensive

But I do not doubt that it has had a very effect upon the rules of inheritance. The Hindoo law
which governs
sought
If a Hindoo dies leaving

of inheritance coincides generally with the law

the partition of family property.

property which

is

exclusively his

own, the heir

is

amongst the male agnates

of the family according to a rule

very similar to that which regulates partition.


succeed each other, the nearest group taking

The groups
Thus,
if

first.

were to die leaving separate property,


If

his sons,

Y and

X,

would succeed.

P had no

sons the group

G would

succeed.

If there were no representatives of the group G, the group

would succeed, and failing

this

group

also,

the group A.

785. In one part of India, in the valley of the Lower

Ganges, the rights of the descendants have been, as in ancient

Rome, absorbed by the


without sons,
ceeding,

ancestor, so that

on the death of

were

if G were alive, instead of the group G sucG would take the whole. If G were dead and Q, Here ownership has alive, Q would take the whole.

lost its corporate character.

786.

The

classification

of

heirs into

groups appears in Mahomlaw.

a very striking manner a

in the

Mahommedan

When law of inl^entance.

Mahommedan
But

dies, then, according to the express directions

of the Koran, certain persons are to receive shares of the

property.

these shares do

not generally exhaust the


is

property, and the succession to the residue


certain rules

governed by

which are not

to be

found in the Koran, but


These rules obviously

which the Koran does not supersede.


represent the old Arabian custom

of succession.

The persons
satisfied, are

who

succeed to the residue, after the sharers are

the male agnates, and with one modification the classes o male

382

SUCCESSION.

[Chap. XVIII.

agnates succeed each other in the same order as in the Hindoo


law.

Only

here, again^

where the family system no longer

prevails, the descendants are excluded


Parentenuiig.

by a living

ancestor.

787.

The same

classification of

the heirs into groups of

persons descended from a single ancestor, and the use


it

made

of

in the determination of the heirs,

was well known

to the

ancient

German

law,

and

it still

survives in the Austrian Code.

Germans

call this classification of

the heirs parentelen-ordnung

or lineal-ordnung'.
it

The Austrians have, however, extended


but to a single
pair^.

to females

and cognates, and the modern code of Austria


conclusion to which these observations appear to

traces the descent not to a single ancestor

788.
lead
is

The

that the rules of intestate succession of an heir to the

individual property of the deceased

grew out of the

rules

which

governed the rights of co-owners upon a partition of the


family property.

As the family system

disappeared, the rights

of the descendants have been absorbed

by the

living ancestor,
alterations to
inequitable.
is

and there have been many interpolations and


obviate results which to

modern eyes appear


co-heirs per capita
little
is

Thus

it

may

be said generally that the modern tendency

to give the inheritance to


stirpes
:

and not per

though I think there can be

doubt that the

division per stirpes is the older rule division of the heirs into groups

and

connected with the

which I have been endeavourdealt with the origin of the

ing to describe. 'b


Teetamencession,

789. So far
conception
of

we have only
intestate
;

succession.

But

there

exists

also

testamentary succession
the person to succeed
will

that

is

to say, succession in

which

is

determined by a declaration of the


This,

of

the deceased person.


fiction
;

Savigny^

says,

rests

How far
on
fiction.

Upon a

the fiction being that the deceased person

Continues to act beyond the period of his

own

death.

If the

See Holtzendorff' s Encyelopadie,

s.

v.

Parentelen-Oi'dnung

Uuger,

Syst. d. Allgem. Oesterr. Priv.-Eechts, vol. vi. p. 134.


'
'

The Shiah Mahommedaus have made a similar extension. Syst. des heutigen ROmischen Eechts, vol. i. p. 131, sect. 57.

Sec. 18^-)8g.l

SUCCESSION.

383
fiction,

testainentary power
as this, to

was

really

due to such a strange

which no physical conception ever corresponded, we could only wonder at it. By a metaphor it may be said that
' ;

man being dead yet speaketh ' but the words of a dead man can hardly create binding obligations. Nor do I know
a
of

any foundation

for the statement that


^.

any such

fiction

was

the origin of testamentary law

All the testamentary power

in the world can be traced either to the


distinct legislative enactment.

Roman law

or to

know
was

of

any such

fiction ?

But did the Roman law really The authority for a Roman will
and sweeping maxim

itself to

be found, either in the express assent of a body

having

legislative powers, or in the broad

legislatively declared in the T welve Tables that every

man might
and con-

dispose of his property as he liked


trivances of

^.

The

shifts

Roman, lawyers were, not to obtain the testamenwhich were imposed upon
whatin the

tary power, which they had got, but to get rid of the forms

and

restrictions

all alienations

soever,

whether testamentary or

iniei- vivos,

and which

case of testaments were felt to be peculiarly irksome.

This

was done by a variety of methods, none of which, however,


as far as I

am

aware, depend upon the fiction of enforcing


It

obedience to a dead man's commands.


expression
Perhaps
figuratively describes
it is

may

be that this
place

what

actually takes
is

in the following

way

that the fiction

traced to the

by Modestinus (Digest, Book xxxi. sect. 36) that this in the Institutes (Book ii. tit. 20, a legacy is a gift left by will sect, i) is changed into 'a legacy is a kind of gift left by a person deceased and this has been again transformed into a will is a gift by a person deceased.' It has been pointed out by Windscheid (Lehrbuch des Pandekten-Rechts, sect. 623, note 2) that the word gift is not used in the passage of the Digest above quoted in its proper sense and both the etymology and history of legatum indicate a totally different origin.

Eoman
'

law.

It is said

'

'

'

'

'

See Smith's Dictionary of Antiquities, s. v. Moreover the history of the that the formalities necessary to a transaction of gift were got rid of, not by the fiction that one of the parties to the transaction

Eoman law shows

was a dead man, but by special exemption of this particular transaction from the ordinary rules. See Savigny, Syst. d. heut. KOm. Rechts, vol. iv. pp. 21 and 424 vol. iii. p. 206. " Uti legassit super pecunid tuteldve suae rei ita jus esto TJlpiani Fragmenta, See Maine's Ancient Law, first ed., pp. 201, 202. tit. II, 14.
; ;

384

SUCCESSION,
:

[Chap. XVIII.
is

under modern testamentary law


notion that
it is

and there

also

a vulgar

a sacred duty to yield implicit obedience to


It
is

the wishes o the dead.

further extremely probable


it

that this notion, fostered, as no doubt

was,

if

not created,
the

by the Church,
latitude

in

some measure accounts


allowed
to

for

great

sometimes

testamentary

dispositions.

But

this is not the authority


:

on which testamentary disposiit is historically

tion rests derived.

nor

is it

the origin from which

790. It
steps

is

not necessary for

me

to trace here the successive

by which the Roman lawyers tardily arrived at the notion that a will in the modern sense of the term could be

made
to

that

is

to say, that a

man

could dispose of his property

whom

he pleased, and in whatever

way he
It
is

pleased,

by means

of intentions formed in his lifetime, but which remained until


his death both secret

and revocable \

however remark-

able that towards the end of the last century the true history
of succession, both intestate
Origin of
SUCC6S310I1
iiicor-

and testamentary, seems to have


Blackstone ^,

been almost wholly forgotten and ignored.

who

was thoroughly acquainted with the


suggest
times and in

ideas current in his day,

Stat

d b

speaks of succession as a contrivance which would naturally


itself at all all countries to
if (as

Black-

remedy the

inconvenience which would occur,

he considers would

otherwise be the case) the property of a deceased owner became


vacant, and could be seized upon
treats intestate succession as a

by the

first

comer

and he

supplementary contrivance in

order to meet particular cases of neglect or disability on the


part of the deceased owner.
Effects of

791. This

is,

of course,

mere

idle speculation

but

it

was

India"

^^ current view

when

Blackstone's treatise was published.

Nor has it been without important practical consequences. When we began to administer the law in India, we did in
fact
^

come

in contact with a people


is

amongst

whom

true wills

The reader
vii.

referred for this information to Maine's Ancient


vol.

Law,

chaps, vi,
'

Commentaries,

ii.

pp. lo, 12, 489.

It is not easy to reconcile all

that Blackstone says upon the subject.

Sec. 790-792.]

SUCCESSION.
;

385
strict

were as yet unknown


adherence to their

but who, in spite of their usual


laws, were

own

by no means unwilling
to read the

to

acquire this important extension of the rights of the existing


generation.
It
is

very curious

now

arguments

by which the testamentary right was supported and opposed. All through the discussion testamentary dispositions of property are treated as
if

they stood exactly upon the same


inter vivos;

grounds as gifts of property

and the whole

dis-

cussion turns upon the question whether such alienations are


allowed.

The

distinction between alienating property


it

by

gift Distinca

during

life,

and disposing of

by a

gift

which operates after tween

death, seems to have been wholly ignored.


assertion
is,

that wills must be looked upon as


:

The constant gifts made in

'^ij|

?'*

'oi'oos.

contemplation of death

without any inquiry as to whether

made in the way valid by the Hindoo


gifts

in

which

wills are generally


if

made were

law, even

the greatest latitude of

alienation were

allowed to living persons.

This defective
considered
it

reasoning could have deceived no one

who had
real cause

from the right point of view

and the

why it

gained

acceptance must have been the then inherent notion that wills

were so natural an expedient that the recognition of them was


almost a matter of course,
established.

when

the right of alienation was

792.

Many

years later the validity of a Hindoo will was Identity

again questioned before the Privy Council.

Wills had then

g(.jji

gome-

been in use in India upwards


expressly recognised
this, it

of seventy years,
legislature^-

by the

and had been *j^g^ ^^ Notwithstanding

appears to have been thought necessary, perhaps in

order to disavow innovation, again to protest that a testa-

mentary disposition did not


gift
^.

differ in principle

from an ordinary

pretence was even


of 1799, sections

made
i, 2.

of testing the validity of

^
'

Regulation

5,

See the case reported in the Bengal Law Reports, vol. ix. p. 377. The passages to which I refer are at pages 397, 398. The Judicial Committee of the Privy Council there describe a will as a disposition of property to
'

take effect
'

upon the death

of the donor '


is,

and say that such a disposition

though revocable in his lifetime

until revocation, a continuous act of

C C

SUCCESSION.

386

[Chap. XVIII.

the gift in that particular case^

law

of gifts.
ergo,

To a

gift it

was

by the analogy of the said there must be a


is

actual
living

donee
but

a gift to a person unborn

invalid.

Surely with

equal force

it

might have been


ergo,

said, to

a gift there must be


is

wrong y

^ living donor
as
is

a gift by a dead
is

man
gift

void.

If,

again,

there said, the law of wUls

simply a development of

the law of gifts,


it

by carrying on the

up

to death,

why

is

that the donatio mortis causa has been developed as a distinct

transaction? and

how have

the formalities which are neces-

sary to this form of donation come to be dispensed with in


wills ?

The whole law


intention
is

as to donationes mortis causa

is

based

upon the supposition


tion of

that, generally, a

mere one-sided

declara-

by the owner

of property,

upon which

and disad- nothing


ously.

done, effects nothing.

The
if

donatio mortis causa

would be an impossible halting-place


been a development of the law of

the law of wills had the sense that one

gifts, in

may

be inferred logically from the other.

793.

Nor do

I see how,

if wills

are to be conceived as gifts

by the deceased not made

in his lifetime, they can be defended

against the imputation of absurdity.

They can always then


'

be attacked as Mirabeau attacked them.


difference,'

There

is

as

much
life.

he

said,

'

between what a

man

does during his hf

and what he does after death as between death and

What

is

a testament

It

is

the expression of the will of a

man
no

who has no

longer any will, respecting property which


:

is

longer his property

it is

the action of a "man no longer

accountable for his actions to


gift

mankind

it

is

an absurdity,
If I understand

up

to the

moment

of death

and does then

operate.'

the reasoning rightly it is meant, not only that the act should be continuous until death, but that it must be continued until at least one

and so Savigny evidently thought supra, sect. 784. then a will is still a transaction inter mws, and the difficulty about getting rid of the rules which regulate such transactions is not avoided. Of course making a will to be a gift by a deceased man was not necessary to the view the Privy Council were seeking to establish as to the limitations upon the testamentary power. In fact those limitations come out all the stronger the more we look at a will as a special
after

moment

death
so,

If this be not

transaction standing

by

itself.

Sec. 793-795-]

SUCCESSION.

387

and an absurdity ought not to have the force of law ^' From the point of view taken these observations are unanswerable.

The testamentary power carefully guarded and


not be an absurdity
;

restrained

may

but

it

would be

so if it were, as

Mirabeau

views

and as Savigny and some English lawyers have represented it, nothing more than a dead man's expression of desire. The real answer to all such objections is that, politiitj

cally,

the power of testamentary disposition

rests, like

every

other institution of law, on habit and convenience, backed

by

authority; historically,

it

has grown, like other law, partly

out of the expressly declared will of the supreme power, partly


out of judicial decision, and partly out of custom.

794. Having

now

given some idea of the methods by which Succession


jand!'^"

the problem of succession was originally solved, I proceed to


consider the legal conceptions which
it

at present involves

and I wiU
795. It

first
is

deal with the succession to moveables.

not necessary to attempt here a complete history Obscurity

of the English law of succession to moveables.


is

involved in considerable obscurity, and

is,

That history of English in fact, the history ^^^


one time in

of a very long

and very severe


part,

contest.

In this contest the


at

Church took a very active

and succeeded

obtaining, together with some pecuniary advantage, considerable influence over the law applicable to succession, as well as

some share in

its

administration.

Hence the English law

of succession in the case of moveables has been in a great

measure based upon the


generally adhered.

Roman

law, to which the Church

And though

the principles of this law

have been freely modified by the temporal courts, which have


' Bulwer's Historical Characters, vol. i. p. 114, Mirabeau was probably thinking of Leibnitz, who had said, Testamenta vero mero jure nullius essent moment! nisi anima esset immortalis, sed quia mortui revera adhuo
'

viviint, ideo

cipiendi sunt ut procuratores in

manent domini rerum, quos vero heredes reliquerunt, conrem suam.' Leibnitz, Nova Methodus

Jurisprudentiae, Pars specialis, sect. 29 ; vol. iv. part iii. p. 187, Geneva It is curious to see how readily people sometimes set aside ed. 1768.

what they are pleased


to

to call

'

mei-um

jus,'

and the

shifts

they are put to

supply

its place.

C C 3

388

SUCCESSION.

[Chap. XVIII.
all

long since re-established their exclusive jurisdiction in


points of real importance,
it
still

remains the best

way

of

considering the English law of succession to moveables to


treat it as
Succession

an offshoot of the Roman law.


of the salient principles of the

796.

One

Roman law

of

man law

'

succession (as will be readily understood after the observations

umversaL J Jjave

made upon

its

origin) was, that the succession dealt

with was a universal ne.

What

passed directly from the

deceased to his heir or heirs was the whole aggregate of his


rights

and

obligations.

Every

heir took either the whole or


half, a third,

a share of that aggregate


case

a fourth, as the

might be

and

it

was an absolute

rule of

Roman law
and every

that this devolution should be complete, immediate, and unconditional.

No

device could get rid of this rule,

scheme for securing to particular individuals particular portions of the |)roperty, or for carrying out particular wishes

of the deceased,

had

to be

framed with

strict caution

not

to violate this principle.

direct to the legatee, but the thing bequeathed


heir,

Thus a legacy could not be given went to the


it.

from

whom

the legatee could claim

So

if

man
and

desired that

any portion

of his property should be held

enjoyed in a special
portion from the

manner, he could not separate that


stock, but could only lay his heir

common
is

under the obligation to carry out his wishes.


Partly so

797. This view

partly adhered to in the English law.

the case

of ^^

*^^ death of a person the whole of his moveable property


eti

moveables.

passes
if

bloc to his

executors

if

he die

testate, to the ordinary


liable for the

he die intestate ;

and the same persons are


been somewhat

debts of the deceased.


principle has

Indeed, under the English law, the


respect

in one

unreasonably

extended ; I ought perhaps to say, distorted.


relations of

Even the blood


testate,
directly,

an intestate, or the universal legatee of a

do not, under the English law, take his property

but

only indirectly through the executor or administrator.

This

can only have been because the Church thrust


the deceased person and
his
successors,

itself

between

and

insisted

upon

Sec. 796-800.]

SUCCESSION.
administration
its

389
estate

treating the

of

the

as

in

all

cases

dependent upon

own

authority, exercised

through the

administrator or executor, as the ease might be.


for this there

Of

course

was no authority

in

Roman
if

law.
paiti-

798. Under the English law there cannot even be a partition No


of the inheritance
:

the representatives,

there be several, can- allowed,

not be made owners of shares, but must be together one single

owner of the whole


were several
heirs,

whereas, under the

Roman
own

law,

if

there
is

each was owner of his


respect the

share.

There

a good reason
followed.

why in this

Roman law has


and we

not been
diffi-

separation of the inheritance must lead to

culties about the administration of the estate,

find that
testa-

in countries

which have adopted the Roman law, the

mentary

heirs are frequently placed under the control of a

single person.

799. It follows, of course, from what has been

now

said.

No

privity

that between the heir, or the legatee, and the deceased there deceased
is,

under the English law, in the case of moveables, no privity

^'^^ ^^"^

whatsoever.

At the

death, neither the heir

nor the legatee


;

of move-

has a right to claim any portion of the moveable estate


are not liable for anything
to the deceased.
;

they

they do not in any way succeed


of their right consists in

The whole The

this

to call

upon those who are administering the

estate to proceed

according to law.

nearest approach to an exception to

this principle is in the case of the legacy of a specific thing;


if

the executor appointed

by the

will

have assented to a legacy

of this description, the thing belongs at once to the legatee.

In

all

other cases the only remedy

is

by an

action for the

administration of the estate.

800. It was an immediate deduction from the Roman idea of succession that the heirs, whether of a testate or of an intestate person, were Hable to pay all the debts and fulfil all
the v?ord 'heir' to designate the person vfho is entitled moveable property of an intestate. As pointed out there is in England, properly speaking, no hereditary infra (sect. 805), succession to moveable estate, but I am obliged to find some designation
^

Liability
to debts
'^'^^^'^

^^^

I use

beneficially to the

for the person

who

really gets the benefit of it.

390

SUCCESSION.

[Chap. XVIII.

Eoman

the obligations of the deceased

whom

they represented.

The

succession being a universal one, there

was no distinction

between the assertion of a claim and the submission to a


liability.

Consequently, under the

Roman law an
on the

heir

might

find himself in

very serious position ;

that he had more to


estate were greater

pay than to

receive ; that the claims

thian the assets.

Upon

this

ground he was allowed a reasonhe was personally

able time to reflect and decide, whether or no he would accept

the inheritance.

Having once done

so,

bound by every obligation of the deceased which was not by its nature incapable of being transferred from one person to
another.

This led to great inconvenience

first,

on account of

the delay which took place whilst inquiries wer being made,

and secondly, on account

of the frequency

with which inheirs.

heritances of doubtful solvency were refused


order to avoid this inconvenience,
Benefit of
torv"^''^'''^'
'

by the

In

what has been known


if

as the

benefit of the inventory

'

was introduced by a constitution


in compliance

^ Justinian ^.

with certain

The provision was that, forms, and within a certain


by the
heir,

time, a complete

inventory of the property of the deceased was


in the proper office
entirely separate

made and

filed

and

this property

was kept

from the property of the


which the
wre

heir himself, then

the heir could claim exemption from liability for any claims
of the deceased
assets
insufficient to satisfy.

The

heir,

however, had to give notice before he entered upon


;

the property that he intended to claim this exemption

and he

forfeited his protection, if he did not deal with the property

honestly for the benefit of

all parties

concerned.

This

is,

in

substance, the general law at the present day throughout the

continent of Europe.
Liability

801. In England the liability to the debts of the deceased

and adTr'for'^^' debts.

person has got somewhat displaced from

its

natural coincidence

^^^^ ^^ reception of the assets of the

estate.

The

legatees

and next of kin having no direct connection with the deceased,


and not being
his representatives,
'

have nothing to do with his

Cod. Just. Book

vi. tit. 30, sect. 2a.

Sec. 8oi, 802.]

SUCCESSION.
which
falls entirely

391

debts, the liability to

on the intermediate

functionary, the executor or administrator.

Nor

is

the posiheir,

tion of either of these identical with that of the

Roman
source
^.

although our law

is

clearly traceable to a

Roman

It

seems that originally an inventory was required from the


executor or administrator in every case before he was put in
possession of the property ; and
it

was considered a matter

of

course that he got the

'

benefit of the inventory,' without the

necessity of his putting in

any

special claim to

it.

But graduor

ally the practice of putting in

an inventory

fell into disuse,

dwindled into a mere form


originally been conditional
this

whereas the benefit which had

faithful performance of duty was nevertheless retained ^. So that without furnishall,

upon the

ing any inventory at

executors and administrators are

now

exempt from

all

personal HabiHty except for the due administra:

tion of the estate

and they only become personally


'

liable if
is

they violate or neglect their duty, and are guilty of what


called

a devastavit, or

wasting the

assets,''

in

which case they

must answer out of

their

own

pocket ; not however even then


or

for the whole claim, but for

what they had,

might have had,


law, like- Under Ko-

of the property of the deceased ^

802. Another essential principle of the

Roman

wise dependent upon the idea of personal succession, was, that naewtTf there was no interval or breach at the deai;h of the deceased, teirneces-

but the heirs at once stepped into his shoes.

It

was the

sary to sucoes'

same idea as
dies.'

is

expressed in our

maxim

that

'

the king never

On

the other hand, however, the consent of the heir


:

was necessary to the vesting of the inheritance


1

until the

Williams on Executors, sixth

ed., p.

912; compare Erskine's Institutes


it is

of the
2

Laws

of Scotland,

Book

iii. tit.

9, sect. 41.

There has however always been a tendency, and

just

now perhaps

a growing one, to treat the 'estate' itself as liable to the debts; making the estate a sort of juristical person and it would not be difficult to bring
;

Kecently where a testator died having an interest in an uncompleted contract. Sir William James spoke of his estate as being ' a co-contractor ' in the business. Law Reports, Chancery Appeals,

our law into this view.

vol. ix. p. 343.


'

Williams on Executors, sixth

ed., p. 658.

392
inheritance

SUCCESSION.
had been accepted
it

[Chap. XVIII.

did not belong to the heir.

There wasj therefore^ a


fact
:

conflict

between the theory and the

there

was a space

of time, very often a considerable one,

during which, whatever the theory might be, the inheritance


did in fact belong to no one.
but his

This difficulty was partly got


is

over

by

the doctrine of

'

relation back,'' as it

called

that

is

lat^dtock. * ^^7> t^^ heir, though he was not really heir before he accepted, yet, when he accepted, was treated exactly as if he

had succeeded immediately on the death of the owner. was vacant, which might give
which no
ing this
fiction
rise to practical

Still

the difficulty remained, that in the interval the inheritance


inconveniences
of meet-

could remedy.

The common method

difficulty

was by the appointment of a person for the

intermediate custody and


Acceptexecutor

management

of the property

^.

803. The state of the English law upon this matter

is

somewhat peculiar.

We frequently find it laid down positively,


title directly '

also neces- ^-^^^ sary.

^^ executor derives his

from the

will

that

the property vests in

him from the moment


is

of the testator's
title,

death
the
is

and that the probate

only evidence of

and not

title itself.

That

to

some

extent, however, this statement


fiction, is

not the assertion of an actual fact, but of a legal

evident, I think,

from the following considerations:


an executor derives

It

is

perfectly true that

his title directly

from an

the will in this sense, that the inheritance passes immediately


to the executor

from the

testator,

and

not, as in the case of

administrator or a legatee, through another person.


true that the only use of probate
is

It

is

also

to satisfy a rule of evidence,

and that the grant of probate confers no right whatever.

But
the

still

the property does not, in fact, vest in the executor at


of death.

moment

As under

the

Roman
is

law,

it

does not

vest until some act has been done,

which

equivalent to an

acceptance of the inheritance, and the commonest

mode

of

* See an interesting discussion of the maxim le mort saisit le vif,' by which continental nations have bridged OTor the interval between the deceased and his heir, in Lassalle'a Syst. des Erworbenen-Rechts, vol. ii.
'

part

2.

Sec. 803-805.]

SUCCESSION.

393

acceptance

is

the application for probate, though any interestate is sufficient for that purpose.
title

meddling with the

804. If this were not the correct view of the position of an His
executor, another position taken

by English lawyers would be


tell

\,l^_

wholly unintelligible.

The same authors who


title,

us that the
of death,

inheritance vests in the executor at the

moment

speak of the relation back of the

of the executor

from

probate to the death of the testator^.

The only

possible
is,

explanation which I can conceive of this language

that

when the

executor,

by applying

for probate, unequivocally


is

accepts the inheritance, the inheritance

then assumed to
If
it

have vested in him at the death of the


back at

testator.

had

already really vested in him, then there could be no relation


all.

So

also the distinction that, if the first executor

die after proving the will, the inheritance passes on to his executor, but if he die without having proved the will, it

passes to the ordinary


to

who must grant

administration, seems

me

only capable of explanation upon the assumption, that

the inheritance had never vested in the executor


expressed his assent
this

who had not

by applying

for probate.

It

may

be that

assumption was not always quite


;

correct, as

Lord Holt
fact, in dis-

pointed out ^

but the only error would be one of

regarding
probate.

all

other acceptance than that by application for


principle of

The

law upon which the ordinary acted

in granting administration, namely, that the inheritance had

never vested in the executor

who had not

accepted,
It
is

was upon

correct, and has always been acknowledged.

also

the same principle that

if

an executor renounce, and adminis-

tration be granted, no assent or assignment

by the renouncing

executor

is

necessary.

805. The relationship between the deceased person and his No heir to executor is wholly different from that between the deceased ^optrty^
person and his administrator.

The executor

is

the heir of the

fj^^^^

See also the language of ' Broom's Commentaries, first ed., p. 616. Lord Denman, Adolphus and Ellis' Reports, vol. x. p. 212. ' Salkeld's Eeports, vol. i. p. 308; Williams on Executors, pp. 245, 282.

394
deceased
;

SUCCESSION.
the inheritance passes to him directly
;

[Chap. XVIII.

and he
it

repre-

sents the deceased.

Strange as

it

may

seem^ yet

is

true

thatj in contemplation of our law, a person

who

dies intestate

has (strictly speaking)


It passes

no heirs of his moveable property.


his property passed to
:

Down

to the year

1857

an

ecclesiastical

ordinary,

functionary called the ordinary


the Court of Probate ^.

now

it

passes to the Judge of

There

is

no necessity to enter here into

the inquiry

how

the very peculiar view came to be taken, that

the property of persons dying intestate vested in the ordinary


especially in a country not
astical authority.

always prone to submit to


its

ecclesi-

It

no doubt had

advantages.

In

all

probability,

no other person would have shown any respect

whatever for the rights of others, which the ordinaries always


did to some extent; though
resistance that
it

was not without considerable


call

what we should

the obvious rights of the

kindred of the deceased and of claimants upon the estate were


fully recognised.
Ordinary,
'

806. The English law has, however, been brought round


^'^

trolled.

^ reasonable condition, not by altogether expunging the


leaves no heirs, but
I,

idea that an intestate person


trolling

by conc.

the ordinary.

The 13 Edward

statute i,

19,

directed the ordinary to

pay the debts of the deceased, which

plain duty

it

appears that the Church was disposed to neglect.

But the most important changes were introduced by the 31 Edward III, statute i, c. 11. Prior to that statute it had
been customary for the ordinary to appoint an
officer of his

own

to administer the property of the deceased.

The person

was a mere agent of the ordinary, subject to the usual rules of agency ; and of course possessing only such
so appointed

powers as the ordinary chose to give him.


of

The

statute

Edward
:

III,
(i)

however, contained three very important


it

provisions

compelled the ordinary to depute, not

any person he
the estate
right
;

chose, but the nearest of kin to administer

(a) it

gave to the persons


to

so

deputed the same


their
19.

as the

executors have
'

sue

in

own names

21

&

2a Vict. chap, xov, sect.

Sec. 806-808.]

SUCCESSION.
which
right,

395
strange
so

to recover debts due to the deceased,


to say, the ordinary never

had;

(3)

it

made the persons

deputed liable to be sued in their own names for the debts


of the deceased.

is

807. This statute was also interpreted to imply, though it Property not expressly so said, that the property of the deceased
in the administrator in the
it

f^ ^jje^"*"

became vested
executor ; and

same way as in the

adminis-

would have been

also a legitimate inference,

as well as one which would greatly have simplified the law,


if,

having

so far assimilated the position of


it

an executor to
represented

that of an administrator,
administrator, like
deceased,

had been further held that the


directly

the

executor,

the

and that

his title

the intestate person's

commenced from the moment of death. This, however, was not done.
still

The administrator was


of the ordinary
1

looked upon as only an

'

officer

But he

is

1,'

though

in

what
,
.

sense he could

still

be so theVent'*
con-''^*!' ordinary,

called it is difficult to say.:


,

for the ordinary


.

had no

trol,

or next to none, over his appointment j

and he held
Never-

rights which

the ordinary was unable to confer.

theless, the doctrine is still

adhered to that administrators

derive their title solely from the grant of the administration


to

them by the ordinary

although, to remedy glaring in-

justice,

administrators are sometimes dealt with in special

cases as if their title also related back to the death of the

deceased.

808. The result of the statute of Edward III being to Adminisgive the inheritance entirely to the administrator, and no g^naUy liabilities being imposed upon him except to pay the debts took the
of the deceased, the right to the grant of administration in himself.
""

a solvent estate was one of very great value

for the person

who, as next of kin, was


the statute took for his
proceeds of the estate
'

entitled to the administration

under

own

benefit the whole of the surplus

^-

This was certainly an unsatisfactory


ii. p.

Blaekstone's Commentaries, vol.

496

sixth ed., p. 388.


agent,
'

The view is absolutely erroneous. how could he be the owner of the property ?
ed., p. 1372.

Williams on Executors, If he were only an

Williams on Executors, sixth

396
result.

SUCCESSION.
Prior to the statute,

[Chap. XVIII.
estate

when the

was administered
in prac-

by the Church, the widow and children had always


tice, if

not by absolute right, got each their pars rationahilis,


third

a half or a

according

to

circumstances^

Now

all

went
Origin of
traTiMi^of

to a single relative, and others for

whom

it

was a duty

to

provide would thus frequently be left penniless.

The

Church, which had always fought strenuously for the rights


q
^j^g

bonds.

widow and

children,

and had succeeded

in establish-

ing their rights to some extent, naturally enough made an

attempt to prevent this disastrous result of

the

statute.

The ordinaries began to take bonds from administrators as to how they would administer the estate, by which bonds a This, provision for the widow and the children was secured.
however, the Courts of
tion, as it
Statute of
^'

Common Law
^.

prohibited as a usurpa-

probably was

809. But at length the Statute of Distributions


t'oned the practice, and

sanc-

tionr

even made

it

compulsory on the

ordinary, in every case, to take a


to exhibit
(if

bond from the administrator


which

an account to the ordinary showing the surplus

any) after the assets were collected and debts paid ;

surplus the ordinary

was directed to

distribute

amongst the

next of kin, according to the rules therein laid down.


Weakness
clesiasti-"

810. Considering the pretensions which the Church had


successfully put forward, statutes in
fied,

and the language

of

the various

cal Courts,

which those pretensions, whilst they were modirecognised to a considerable extent,


all
it

were
to

still

would

seem

have been almost inevitable that

matters con-

nected with the administration of the moveable property of


deceased
persons,

both

testamentary and

intestate,

would

have fallen into the hands of the Ecclesiastical Court.


this

But
Bench

has not been the case.

The Court

of King^s

has always prohibited the Ecclesiastical Courts, whenever


'

Williams on Executors, sixth

ed., p.

387

Maine, Ancient Law,

first

ed., p. 244.
^

Williams on Executors, sixth


ii.

ed., p.

1372

Blackstone's Commentaries,

vol.
^

p. 515.
(fe

22

23 Charles II, chap.

i.

Sec. 809-813.]

SUCCESSION.

397

any attempt was made by the latter to exercise functions which it thought it was better able to exercise itself:
and even without these prohibitions there was always the
fatal

defect in the procedure of

the Ecclesiastical

Courts,

that they had no process by which to enforce their judg-

ments^.

They had
it

possessed such

a process, and a very


less

formidable one

was at one time, being nothing

than

excommunication.

They
j

possess in
it is

name

the power of ex-

communication

still

but

a threat, and a threat only


all its terrors.

and as a threat

it

has lost nearly

It

is true,

as

Blackstone says, that to prevent these courts falling completely


into contempt the

common law

lent a supporting

hand

to

their otherwise tottering authority.

It would, however, be

perhaps more correct to say that they were handed over to


the tender mercies of a jealous rival,

who

only assisted them

at the price of their complete submission.


811. I

now

pass to the consideration of the law of succession Succession


find the

to

immoveable property, and we


812.

change of ideas to be moveable


property,
entirely

very great indeed.

The law of England has not only drawn the distinction

between moveable and immoveable property differently from f^om sueother countries in Europe, but it has made that distinction cession to ' '
_

moveable.

wider.

In no other country do we find two perfectly


This

distinct

bodies of law governing the succession to the two different


sorts of property.
is,

however, the case in England.

In

considering the law

of succession to immoveable property


;

we

must begin

entirely de novo

not a word that


is

is

said about

the succession to moveable property


able property, and
vice versa.

applicable to

immoveis

The whole conception


from being able

dif-

ferent from beginning to end. 813. Moreover, whilst

we

are far

to trace Testamen-

the law of succession in the case of moveables with clearness positions

in the deepest obscurity.


.

and continuity, in the case of immoveables its history is buried fj^^^^y A few isolated conclusions are all not
,
.

that have been arrived at by mquirers.


'

,rni
'

The

primitive (jcrman

/-x

allowed,

Blackstone's Commentaries, vol.

ili.

pp. loi, 102.

398
or
allodial

SUCCESSION.
property/ says
Sir

[Chap. XVIII.
'is

Henry Maine,
is it

strictly

reserved to the kindred;


disposed of
alienated

not only
it is

incapable of being

by testament but

scarcely capable of being


^.'

by conveyance
same

inter vivos

All property, however,

even

all

landed property, was not allodial ; and to property not


strictness does not extend
;

allodial the

and there are

also

indications that the rules applicable to non-allodial land were

gradually extended to

all lands.

These rules were the

result

of successive importations

from the Roman law which, com-

bined with certain barbarian ideas, formed the feudal system^.

Out
for

of this

emerged the law of landed property, the actual


at

state of

which in England
earlier

any one time cannot be described

any period
it

than the time of Henry II.

At about
all

that time

may

be said to have become settled law, that


;

land descended to the eldest son

and to the son of the


;

eldest

son, if the eldest son died in the lifetime of his father

that

in default of direct descendants collaterals


representatives
;

came

in,

and their

that during his lifetime the owner might


his purchased lands,

dispose in

some cases of

and of a portion

(not the whole) of those which

came

to

that he had no power to dispose of lands


Introduc"

him by descent ; but by wiU ^.'

814. Testamentary dispositions of landed property, like so

many

other considerable alterations in our law, were intro-

duced by the invention of uses.


trace the

I do not propose here to


further than to

history of that invention


its

point

out

that

origin

is

not (as has been

supposed) to be

found in the
as the

Roman

law, either in the fideicommissum, or,

name might seem to indicate, in the usus. I have elsewhere * shown what the Roman usus really was, and that
'

Ancient Law,

first

quotes this curious old


'

Bluhme ed., p. 198. German rhyme


:

(Encyclopadie, sect. 513)

Wer
Syn

seelig will sterben,

Schall laten vererben


allodi

Gut

Ant' nachst gesippt Blut.'


"
= *

Maine's Ancient Law,


Supra,
sect. 305, 393.

first ed., p. 296.


ii.

Reeves' History of the English Law, chap.

; ;

Sec. 814, 815.]


it it

SUCCESSION.
equity.

399

had nothing to do with


is

The fideicommissum was,


it

true, in a certain sense

an equitable obligation, but

did not produce what English lawyers call a use, or trust


estate.

The person upon whom the

fiduciary

relation

was

imposed was not bound, like an English trustee, to hold the


thing for the use or benefit of another ;

on the contrary, he
;

was bound
he

to

hand over the thing


and
it

itself

from which time

lost all control over it,

belonged absolutely to the


originally intended.

person for whose benefit

it

was

In

all

systems of law fiduciary relations are well known and understood


;

other systems of law also exhibit the peculiarity of


set of rules applicable to such relations.

a special

But the

relation of trustee

and

cestuique trust as
is

understood in the

English Courts of Chancery


in the world, except where

unknown

in

any other system


it,

we have
as
it

introduced

namely, in

America, in the English Colonies, and perhaps in India.


815.

However anomalous
it

was, the use, as an equit- Devise

of

the use.

able right distinct

from the land, was successfully established


as far as I can see,

and moreover
there
is

was assumed, though,

nothing to warrant the assumption, that this was

an

interest with

which only the Court of Chancery, and not


could deal
;

the Courts of

Common Law,
it

and

further, that

in dealing with

the Courts of Chancery were not bound

by the ordinary
mentary

rules relating to landed property.

Of

course

this easily led to the contrivance

by which the right

of testa-

disposition

over land was

substantially exercised.

The land was conveyed to what was called a fcofEee to uses who at common law was the absolute owner. The uses
were then declared in a
will,

and the Court of Chancery

compelled the feoffee to carry out the intention. The statute of Henry VII, though unsuccessful as an attempt to put

an end

to uses,

was considered

to

have put a stop

to this

mode

of disposition; but almost immediately afterwards an

express enactment conferred an absolute right of alienation,

both testamentary and

inter vivos,

upon

all

owners of land,

with exceptions which have since become

insignificant.

;:

400
Devise of

SUCCESSION.

[Chap. XVIII.

816. This being the origin of wills of immoveable property,

ed as a
species of

^^^ ^^^
and

statute

which created them

so treating

them, they

conveyance.

^gj-e very naturally looked j j

upon only r j

as one

form of alienation

in fact such wills have generally been considered in the

English law merely as a species of conveyance;

difEering

from an ordinary conveyance only in the solemnities which

accompany
struction

their execution^

and in some minor

rules of con-

which the nature of the transaction suggests.


is

It

must not be supposed, however, that there


has provided that a

here any fiction

about carrying out the wishes of a dead man.

The

statute

gift, secret, revocable, conditional,

and

unaccompanied by any of the forms necessary to a transfer


inter vivos, shall

be valid

and

this,

though contrary

to general

principles, of course the legislature

was perfectly competent

to do
Intestate
to laud,

2.

817.

In the case of land the degrees of consanguinity

are calculated not according to the rules of the

Roman,

or

as

it is

usually called, the Civil

Law,

as

it

is

in succession

to moveables, but according to the rules of the

Canon

Law ^
is

of which peculiarity I have never yet seen

any explanation.
that

The

difference

between the two modes of computation


or Civil

whilst the

Roman

Law

counts the number of degrees

in both lines from the deceased person through the

common
in

ancestor to the heir, the

Canon Law counts the degrees


furthest

one line only from the


to the heir, whichever
' '

common

ancestor to the deceased, or


off.

is

For instance,
find

my first
fiction

32

Henry VIII,

chap.

i.

I have no doubt, however, that

many

persons

still

any

acceptable which will disguise the arbitrary origin of rights of succession


I

suppose because legislation on this subject appears to trench upon the

sacred principle of non-interference with rights over property.

I do not imagine that eminent lawyers would be seriously embarrassed by such scruples, but they sometimes feign a respect for them in argument, as in the case mentioned above (supra, sect. 557). And quite recently a very learned Judge delivering judgment in the House of Lords, supported his conclusions by the very curious suggestion that the Statute of Distributions, was nothing more than the making of a will by the legislature for the intestate. Law Eeports, Eng. and Ir., App., vol. vii. p. 66.
^

Blackstone, Commentaries, vol.

ii.

p. 206.

Sec. 816-818.]

SUCCESSION.

401

cousin

is

related to

me

in the fourth degree under the

Roman

or Civil

Law, but

in the second degree under the

Canon Law.

The

other two peculiarities, namely the entire exclusion of

the ascending line and of the brothers of the half-blood, have

both been removed by statute ^-

The

difEerence in the

mode
Liability of heirs of land to

of calculating the degrees however stUl remains.

818. Nothing marks more clearly the wide difference be-

tween the ideas of succession as applied to moveables and

as applied to immoveables than the difference in the law as g^^geslw The to the liability of heirs for the debts of the deceased.
strict

notions

of personal

representation and continuance

which are involved

in the conception of succession carried

this liability to the very utmost,

making the
modified

heir in

some
apply-

cases even personally liable for the debts of the deceased.


This, as

we know, our own law has


is

when

ing the conception of succession to moveable


the modification
just

estate,

and

and reasonable.

This conception of

succession and strict personal representation has never been

applied

by us

at

aU

to

immoveable property.

Still

it

is

difficult to

account for the views which English lawyers at

one time seem to have entertained as to the entire freedom from liability of those who have inherited land. It has
indeed been said that in very ancient times the heir of land

was

liable for the

unpaid debts of his ancestor, and that

the narrower rule which


the time of Edward
I,

we

find laid

down by Britton
if

in

that the heir of land was liable

the

deceased had specially bound

him by

the deed under which

"This the debt was due, was a restriction due to feudaHsm seems, however, to be mere conjecture, and no feudal reason

can be assigned for the exception made in favour of debtors, when the heir was specially bound. It must be remembered,
moreover, that in the period which immediately preceded the reign of Edward I, lands were not available even to the
creditors of

''

a living

man

at all;

and I should rather be

& 4 William IV, chap. 106. Williams on Real Property, seventh


3

ed., p. 74.

Bd

402

SUCCESSION.

disposed to consider the rule laid


struction of the statute of

down by Britton as a conEdward I ^ in favour of creditors,


by
will

than as a restriction on their rights,


and
of

819. Consistently with the idea that a devise

under

the statute was an alienation of the land,


creditors of the testator

it

was held that the


devisee.

had no claim against the

820. Gradually, though very slowly, the principle has been


established

by express

legislative provision that the heir is

liable for the debts of

the deceased, whether he takes under

a wiU or by intestacy.
'

13

Edward

I, stat. i,

chap. xix.

CHAPTEE

XIX.

SANCTIONS AND REMEDIES.


821. I
tionSj

HAVE

hitherto considered law, and the duties, obliga- Relation

and

liability

which

arise out of law, only

from one point

of view

sanctions

as the

machinery by which a

political

"ghts. society is ^""^

governed.

It

is

true that I have adverted to the division

of duties into those


relative

which are absolute and those which are


but I was desirous not to complicate

and I have spoken of the right which corresponds


duty
:

to the relative

further a discussion already sufficiently complex

by remarking

then upon
connote.

another distinct order of ideas

which these terms

822.
is

As a

general principle the point of view above taken Laws

are

the only true one in this sense


justifies

namely, that

it

is

the only

fo^ the

one which

the existence of laws at

all.

No

one ^?^?

creates or enforces duties

nowadays

for the benefit of indi- viduals


society at
'^""S*-

viduals, or classes of individuals,

but for the benefit of the

community
conferring

at large.

If any modern law has the aspect of


class of society alone,

new advantages on one


it

we

may

be sure that

has been adopted only on account of the

indirect advantages

which

it is

alleged will be derived from it

by the remainder. 823. Of course when I

assert this, I do not

mean

to say This

is

not

that a conviction of their utility was the original moving g^Uy true, cause of the introduction of proportion of existing laws;
existence long before
all,

or even of

any very large


them came
into

for

many

of

any such

ideas as those to

which I now

advert were started in the countries where they

now

prevail.

Nor

do I doubt that there are everywhere to be found persons

Dd a

404
wh.0, in their

SANCTIONS

AND REMEDIES.
certain

[Chap. XIX.

own minds,

are persuaded that they have


privileges,

an an

hereditary and indefeasible right to


interference with

which on considerations of

utility

would be

immoral and absurd.

But no one avows

this;

and we need

only look to the debates of legislative bodies, or to the published declarations of the rulers in every state, to see that the

only principle on which they pretend to govern, the only

ground on which they expect that their subjects


to obey
society

will consent
political

in other words, the only means by which a that can in modern times be kept together
is

the

object of government should be, or at least should profess to


be, the happiness
It is true
all

and prosperity
is

of the people at large.

824. In this respect there


duties

no distinction between those


absolute.

laws

which are

relative

and those which are

The

whether
create abrelative

j^^ ^^ ownership, for example, which comprises a great variety


of relative duties, is supposed to exist as completely for the
benefit of society at large, as the

law of treason, or the bribery

"

^^'

laws.

The law of ownership


and luxuries of
it

is

said to encourage industry

and and

commerce, to promote an increase in the production of the


necessaries
so forth.
it

life

and

in their distribution,

If

could be

shown not

to possess these advantages

would gradually disappear, or be modified.


this, or denies it ;

Nobody
are prone

really

doubts

only whilst some

men

from

time to time to renew the test of

utility,

and to try

this as

well as other institutions by this standard with great care>

other

men

are, or profess to be, so

convinced of

its excellence,

that they are impatient of any inquiry about the matter.


Apparent
tiontothis
of ^vil^'^^

825. It

may

possibly be suggested that this,

is

hardly in

accordance with what


'^^ * widely stated.

we

see

around
it is

us, or that it is at

any

For while

true that some breaches

procedure, of the

law of Ownership are considered as ofBences against For instance,


property, he
if

society at large, others evidently are not so.

man

steals or mischievously destroys

my

may

be prosecuted and punished in the King's name at the public


expense
;

but

if

man

injures
this'

my property

by negligence, no

one dreams of treating

as a matter of public concern;

Sec. 824-828.]

SANCTIONS

AND EBMEDIES.
him
or not as I like
;

405

am

left to

proceed against
it is

and

if

I do

proceed against him,

not to punish him, but to recover


I must
if

compensation for the injury which I have sustained.

take the whole trouble and risk of this upon myself, and
I

am

satisfied, there is
is,

an end of the matter.

826. There

no doubt, this apparent inconsistency between

the proceedings of courts of civil and courts of criminal


jurisdiction.

"Whilst in criminal courts


its

we

see plainly before

us the breach of law followed by

appropriate punishment,

which deters others from breaking the law by warning them


that they too will incur the like consequences
other words, operates as a sanction
;

which,
we

in

in civil courts
redress,

find
is

that the

only thing thought of


is

is

and there

apparently nothing which


at
all.

intended to operate as a sanction

827. I do not think however

it

will be difficult, without

How

this

going minutely into an

historical inquiry as to the origin of contodic-

legal tribunals, to discover

whence
civil

this apparent divergence *'"

^^^

between the functions of

and criminal courts

arose

moved,

and hence

to infer that it is only apparent,


all

and that the

real

functions of

courts are the same

namely, the enforcement


civil Ketalia-

of obedience to the

commands

of the sovereign authority.

828. Prior to any distinction between criminal and

proeedure, prior even to legal procedure of any kind, there

seems to have arisen everywhere the notion of retaliation;

upon the wrong-doer exactly in Breach proportion to the wrong he has inflicted upon you.
that
is,

of inflicting

an

evil

'

for breach

eye for eye

tooth for tooth,' says the Mosaic


rupit aut os

Law

^.

'

Si quis

membrum

fregit

talione

proximus
^.

cognatus ulciscatur,' says the

Law of

the Twelve Tables

And

the earliest customs of


similar principles.

all
is

Teutonic nations were based on


obviously punishment, and not
sanction;

This

redress;

it

is

the direct appHcation of a


in the

and

would operate precisely

manner which Austin

considers

See Leviticus xxiv. so. See the article


Talio in

'

Smith's Diet, of Greek and

Boman

Antiquities.

406

SANCTIONS

AND REMEDIES.

[Chap. XIX.

a sanction to operate in enforcing an obligation in


jurisprudence
Substitution for it
^.

modem

829. Retaliation, however, though

it is

punishment and not

ofa money redress, was undoubtedly looked upon as some satisfaction to paymen ^^ party injured, and this may very likely have suggested,
.

when a

fixed

money payment was

substituted for the

talio,

or

equivalent injury inflicted on the wrong-doer, that the

money
all

should be paid to the sufferer.

This obviously answered

the purposes of a sanction, loss of

money being an

evil

which

persons are generally anxious to avoid; nor any the less so

because

it is

paid to a particular person, and not, as

money

payments used directly as sanctions now generally


the public treasury.

are, into

Modern
1(1 f^s

830. There

is still

a considerable step, no doubt, from this to

^ Or

compensa- Our
tion.

modem

ideas of compensation.

Thus, under the laws of

Alfred, for the loss of a forefinger the compensation


at fifteen shillings in all cases.

was

fixed

In a

suit
it

brought against

a railway company for a similar injury,


case according to the pecuniary loss

would vary in every


sufferer

which the

might
is

be supposed to have incurred in consequence.

And
still

there

no doubt the ideas of compensation have made a prodigious


advance, even within the last few years
'

^
;

but

no one,

"

See supra, seotiou 192. See the general view of the subject of damages in the treatise on that

by Mr. Sedgwick, where the authorities are collected with much industry and research. The earliest declaration of the rule, that the damages are to be measured by the injury sustained, is quoted from Lord Holt (see p. 29). But I think the notion of calculating the compensation
subject
for a personal injury

for the injury,

upon an estimate of what money the sufferer, but might have earned, is of still later origin. It may possibly be doubted whether these notions about compensation will be very long lived. The cases in which damages are most liberally awarded are those where the defendant is a large public company. But a company has it in its power to exclude its liability in almost all cases by express stipulation, or, by raising its prices, to cast back the burden, in a great measure, upon the general body of its customers. At present the doctrine seems to affect even international relations. The Americans claimed 2,ooo,oooZ. sterling, on account of damages sustained by reason of our alleged breach of neutrality. The Germans have obtained compensation on an equally large scale for what they assume to be a wrong done to themselves by the

Sec.

829-832.J

SANCTIONS

AND EEMBDIES.
Anglo-Saxon Law, just
of the
'

407

I thinkj would doubt that they have grown gradually out of


the
'

'

were ' and


'

'

hot

'

of the

as the

were

or

'

hot '

itself
is

grew out

feud

V
it is Specific

831.

But

there

another point of view in which

necessary to consider the action of legal tribunals in enforcing ^f^t^gf the law, which will be best brought out by an illustration, duties and

wound be inflicted, or valuable property be damaged, a great, possibly an irreparable injury has been inflicted, but
If a
all

tions.

that the law can do in such cases


of example,

is

to inflict punishis

ment by way
keep

and

to

compel such redress as

possible in the shape of compensation.

But

if

I wrongfully

my

neighbour out of possession of his property, then

the law can do

much more than merely compel me


It can actually restore
right.

to

make
and

compensation.

my
is

neighbour to the
redress

enjoyment of his

Here again, however,

punishment go hand in hand.


to the owner,

The law

put in motion to

take the property by force from the wrong-doer and restore


it

and at the same time he


for the

is

directed to

pay
loss

sum
832.

of

money

damage caused by the temporary

of possession, and for the costs of the proceedings.

From the

habit of obedience to the law which generresort to such extreme measures


it

ally prevails

amongst men, a

as have been just described is rarely necessary, nevertheless


is this

which

is

contemplated under our law as the ultimate

result, in all cases

where the injury in question

is

the wrongful

detention of land.

Forcible transfer of the possession of things

other than land has not been generally thought necessary under

our law, even where such transfer

is

possible ; but this


is,

is

only

upon the assumption that the

limit of the injury

except in

very rare cases, the present money value of the

article detained,

French nation in declaring war. Claims not less extensive have been before, by the strong hand but I thinJi that it is new to place such claims on a quasi-legal ground. ' See Kemble's Anglo-Saxons, book i. chap, x., and the Laws of Alfred, Bot ' is the name given to the compensation ordered to be paid 43, 44. in case of a wound which when life was taken was called were.' The right of private warfare to revenge an injury was called feud.'

made

'

'

'

408

SANCTIONS AND REMEDIES.


it

[Chap. XIX.

and that
even

may

therefore be covered
true, it
is

by compensation ^.

But

if this

assumption be

must be remembered that


no
redress, if the person

an order to pay compensation


ordered to pay be insolvent.
Specific

833. Duties, the performance of which


said to be specifically enforced j

is

thus secured, are

ance.

and there are many others


class

which may be
mentioned.

so dealt

with besides those of the


is

above

Where

there

a dispute about the

title to specific

things, whether land or moveables, which are at the

moment

in the possession of neither party, but of a third person holding as the representative of, or derivatively from, the true owner,

the right of the true owner

may

often be specifically enforced

by declaring it, and requiring

this third person

(who generally,

not being interested in the .dispute, will be ready to obey)


to

acknowledge the right of ownership as declared ^.

So

also

a very large number of duties either are primarily to pay money,


or are such that

a breach of them results in a duty to pay

money ; and

all

such duties are in their nature capable of being

specifically enforced,

by the property
is

of the debtor,

if

he has

any, being seized and sold, and the proceeds being handed over
to the creditor;

which

invariably done should the debtor

delay or refuse to pay the money, after he has been ordered by a court of law to do
so.

So again, through the power which


every kind, rights
;

every court has over duties of

may

be

transferred from one person to another

and where the duty

which

it is

desired to enforce

be done, whether the

make this transfer, this can party obliged to make it consents or no,
is

to

and therefore without

resort to the pressure

of a sanction.

Thus

if

owe you money which

am

ready to pay, and you

owe the same sum


'

to a third person, the court can secure the

performance of your duty by simply annulling these two


See supra,
It
is

sect. 51a.

sometimes said that,

when an

officer of

a court executes a con-

veyance in the name of another person who has been ordered to convey, but who refuses to do so, the obligation to convey is thereby specifically enforced. But this, I think, is hardly correct. The order of the court is amply sufficient to pass the ownership without any conveyance and the document executed by the ofSoer is only convenient evidence of title.
;

Sec. 833-836.]

SANCTIONS AND REMEDIES,


of the

409

duties

and creating a new one


;

same kind between


is

me

and your creditor

or, as

the transaction
so correctly,

generally described,

though I think not quite


the debt.

by simply transferring

834. Probably also the idea of rendering further breaches


of the law to a great extent physically impossible, and so

securing a sort of rude specified performance,

is

to

some

extent involved in transportation, and in the modern practice


of substituting long terms of imprisonment, with comparatively

mild treatment, for shorter and sharper sufBering.


835. The more
direct enforcement

of
is,

duties, so

far as

why the
^

matters of
of

civil

procedure are concerned,

like the procuring

^''giy"!

compensation, left entirely to the control of the party procedure

injured,

and there are many circumstances which combine to

tual.

render this

mode
an

of proceeding effectual.

There

is

no better

way

of securing obedience to the law than to give to private


interest in enforcing
it.

individuals

That

interest

is

given

at once in all cases of relative duty,

by giving

to the party

who

has the right corresponding thereto means, either of

enforcing the right, or of obtaining redress


infringed.

when the

right

is

He

at once not only becomes the public prosecutor,


risk,

but takes upon himself the whole trouble,


prosecution.

and expense

of

And

this

method

is

found so

effectual, that so

far as concerns all those violations of right which

come within

the denomination of civil injuries, the State


itself entirely of

is

able to relieve

the trouble of enforcing obedience to the law,


officers to

beyond the appointing proper


the civil courts.

perform the duties of

836.

The injury

to the individual, therefore,


is

though

it is

never the cause of the action of a court of law,


of
it.

the occasion
cases

And

in matters of civU procedure

and a few other

it is

not only the occasion of the action, but the exact measure

of

it.

The whole

ostensible object of the proceedings


is

from

beginning to end in those cases

not punishment, but redress,


redress alone

and they are fashioned upon the hypothesis that


is

the object.

410
Secondary
right as
tiorTof" claim for

SANCTIONS From
'^^

AND REMEDIES.

[Chap. XIX.

837.

this point of view, therefore, to

have a right

does not only express the condition of a person towards ^ ^^^J ^^^
(j^ty

whom
that

^ performed, as

it

would

if violations of
;

were only punished and not redressed

hut

it

expresses

the condition of a person

who can put

in motion the whole


object.
If, for

machinery of courts of law to obtain a private

instance, injuries to property were followed only by a fine

payable to the Crown, or by imprisonment, the compound right

which we

call

ownership would

still exist,

but

it

would have

no legal importance independently of the duties and obligations to

which

it is

corresponds

but when the owner of the compensation for the


aspect.

property injured

also enabled to claim

injury, the right assumes a

new and important

It

is

no longer the mere correlative of the primary duties commanding us to abstain from acts injurious to the property of others;
it has, as

the foundation of a claim for redress, an altogether

independent existence, correlative to an obligation to

make

amends on the part


Imperfect

of the delinquent

^.

838. It

is

obvious enough that none of the consequences of


it

a breach of the law will render

certain that the

command

which contains the law

will

be obeyed.

wrong-doer, or compel him to

make

redress,

we punish the we only warn him


If
repetition of

and others
the wrong.
or
if

in a significant

manner against a

If

by a

transfer of rights

we

fulfil

an obligation,
powerless

by the use

of physical force

we

render a

man

to repeat

an injury, we have only rendered ourselves secure

in

an individual case; and we must trust to the example

to deter others
'

from doing the

like.

Nothing, therefore, can


with a private object

It

is,

I apprehend, this combination of a public

which determines the apportionment of costs in oiyil proceedings. They are borne partly by the public, for the same reason that costs in criminal proceedings are so borne entirely. But I do not see exactly on what principle Bentham (vol. ii. p. 112) would require the government to take upon
itself

the whole burden of costs in civil proceedings. If so, all notion of giving redress would have to be abandoned, for it is not a duty incumbent upon a government to procure redress for individuals ; no government has ever assumed any such function and to charge upon the public the duty of performing it could hardly be justified. The action of the law would thus be confined to enforcing penalties.
;

Sec. 837-839-]

SANCTIONS

AND EEMEDIES.

411

be more inappropriate than the expression by which some laws


are distinguished as perfect^

and others as imperfect. All laws

are imperfect in the

sense that

we cannot be

sure

that

they wiU be obeyed by those on

whom
is

they are imposed.

On

the other hand, a law which has no sanction of any kind,


either legal or moral, if that
is

what

meant,

is

a thing that

I confess myself unable to conceive.

Again, a moral law, or


is

a law accompanied by a sanction which


a legal tribunal (which
is

not enforced by

also

sometimes said to be what


is

the term

is
is

intended to express),
enforced.
set

no more imperfect than

one which

If

we

consider the very rare cases in


legal sanctions,

which the sanctions


gations,

by the law, or

come

into competition with the sanctions of so-called imperfect obli-

which are the sanctions


called

set

by

society,
is, if

and which are


look to cases
conflicts
it

commonly

moral sanctions

that

we

where the conduct required of us by the law


that which
is

with

expected of us by our neighbours,

would be

obviously untrue to imply that the moral sanctions were, as

compared with the legal ones, imperfect. There are many men
who, upon deHberate
of those with
choice, in order to gain the approbation

whom

they are accustomed to associate, would

leave unpaid their debts to a tradesman rather than their

wagers on a horserace. But

this is in reality a

wholly distorted

view of the subject

the sanctions set by law do for the most

part not conflict, but concur with moral sanctions; and every
political society

depends for
It

its
is

existence in a great measure


this

upon

this

concurrence.

concurrence which has

enabled the law to impose sanctions which are sometimes


so light as scarcely to be perceptible.

Nothing indeed can be


slightness of legal

more striking than to contrast the habit of obedience to law


which prevails in most countries with the
sanctions

that

is,

with the smallness both in quantity and

intensity of the suffering which the law inflicts in cases of


disobedience.

839. Sanctions are divided into the two following kinds,

diate

and

412
ultimate
sanctions,
j^

SANCTIONS AND REMEDIES.

[Chap. XIX.

Frequently, indeed most frequently, disobedience to the law

^^^j followed in the

first

instance

by the imposition

of

a fresh duty.

I have disobeyed the law

by not attending as
street, or
is

a juror when summoned, by driving carelessly in the

by not
I

fulfilling

my

contract

the result in each case


of money.

that

am

ordered to pay a
is

sum

The duty

to

pay

the

money

a secondary or sanctioning one, inasmuch as

it exists
is

for the sake of enforcing a primary duty.

But

it

only a duty, and requires therefore a further sanction to


it, if it

enforce

be disobeyed.

840. Sanctions which consist merely in liability to a duty,


that
is,

which

result

from a command

to a

man

to do someif

thing, under pain of incurring certain further consequences

he do not, I will

call intermediate sanctions.

Sanctions which

consist not of liability to a duty, but of liability to


evil

some other

which

it

is

supposed the party would be desirous to

avoid, I will call ultimate sanctions.


Ultimate
the same
for civil
''"d
'

841.

The ultimate

sanctions of all primary duties, whether


is

the breach of
^}ia,t
is

them be what

usually called a civil injury, or

usually called a crime, are the

same.

They

are

of three kinds

crimes.

and

forfeiture.
;

i.also

bodily pain ...


;

including death, imprisonment,

This division of sanctions


itself
is

..

is

not scientifically

correct

for

imprisonment

a kind of bodily pain,


it
:

and

an instrument

for

inflicting

though

it

is

generally something more

loss

of

liberty being regarded

by most men

as an evil, independently of any bodily suffering.


is,

The

division
;

however, convenient.
consist in the simple

Forfeiture

is

of

two
or

kinds

it

may
him

annulment of
it

all

some of those rights which the party has, or


in depriving

may

consist

of all or

some of those rights which are in


and transferring them to another.

their nature transferable,

Whether the
Applicasanctions by courts

right be

simply annulled, or transferred to

another, the sanction consists in the forfeiture only.

842. The application of sanctions has varied considerably


^^ different times, but there
^jjg
is

a good deal of similarity in

yiews which prevail at present in regard to them in most

Sec. 840-843.]

SANCTIONS AND REMEDIES.


in
courts

413
civil

civilised

countries, especially

of civil procedure, of

These courts, shaping their proceedings^ as they ostensibly do,


for the sole purpose of giving redress to the party injured,

always select that form of sanction which will best accomplish


that purpose
to
:

sometimes they order the party delinquent


;

make compensation in money sometimes, where the wrong done is the keeping the rightful claimant out of possession,

they restore the possession, using force

if

necessary

for the purpose ; sometimes they proceed

by way

of restitution

that
duties,

is

to say, creating, destroying, or transferring rights,

and obligations, for the purpose

of putting the parties

as nearly as possible in the

same
first

position as if the
cases,

wrong

had not been done.

In the

two of these

keeping

only the sanction in view, and disregarding the remedy,

we

should find that the order of the court results in the


is,

imposition of an obligation, that

the application of an
is,

intermediate sanction, or in forfeiture, that


tion

the applicarestitution

of an ultimate

sanction.

The

process

of

consists partly of the imposition of

an ultimate sanction in

the shape of forfeiture, and partly of the specific enforcement


of obligations.

Courts of

civil

procedure never, in the

first

instance, apply

the ultimate sanction of imprisonment, and they have no

power

to inflict bodily pain in

simple detention.
largely curtailed in

any other form than that of Even this power has recently been very England by what is called the abolition of

imprisonment for

debt-*.

843. I have already said that the only sanction of


duties to
is

many

Slightnes3
tjong
?*"gg'''

the liability to

make amends
;

for the

damage caused

an individual by

their breach

and in a very large number


of a

of such cases the only form in which compensation can be

given

is

by an order

for the

payment

sum

of

money by

See the statute 32 & 33 Victoria, chap. Ixii, by which the imprisonfor debt in purely civil matters is wholly done away with, except in cases where the court, being satisfied that the debtor has means to pay, makes a special order for payment, which the debtor disobeys.
'

ment

414

SANCTIONS

AND EEMEDIES.
But

[Chap. XIX.

the delinquent to the party injured.

since the passing of

the last-mentioned act, no person, except in very special cases,

can be arrested or imprisoned for making default in the pay-

ment

of a

sum

of money.

For
is

all this class

of cases, therefore,

the only ultimate sanction

forfeiture.

Moreover, forfeiture,

when resorted to as an ultimate sanction of an order to pay money by way of compensation, has always been confined by
us to the forfeiture of such rights as
so as to produce the

may

be seized and

sold,

money and

satisfy this secondary duty.

And

it is

not an unimportant reflection that

we thus
;

arrive at

an ultimate sanction of a very limited kind


entirely depends

and one which

on the possession by the delinquent of rights

of a particular nature.
there
Applicasanctions
nal^corts
is

In other words, as against a pauper


all.

no sanction at

844.

When

the breach of the primary duty

is

the subject
offence,

of Criminal procedure,
^^
^^

and

is

called

a crime, or an

Customary to apply the ultimate sanction at once, by


accompanied by some kind of physical

ordering the guilty person to suffer death, or imprisonment,


either alone or
in-

convenience, such as whipping or hard labour.

Sometimes,

however, an alternative
ultimate
sanction

is

still

left

of escaping from the


of

by the payment
;

sum
cases

of money,

which

is

then usually called a fine

and in

which are

of a mixed character, neither decidedly civil nor decidedly


criminal, a fine
is

generally imposed as an alternative inter-

mediate sanction.
In India.

845. In India sanctions are substantially the same as in

England, except that imprisonment for debt


under conditions which make
that
In other
countries.
it is

still

exists

but

it

so onerous to the creditor,

very

little

resorted to.
civil

846. The courts of

procedure in the United States

and in France
the same.
cases

also proceed

upon

principles almost precisely

in both countries, in that very large class of where the proceedings result in an order for the payof

And

ment

money by way

of compensation,

it

has been found

possible to dispense with the ultimate sanction of imprison-

Sec. 844-847-]

SA2JCTI0NS

AND EEMBDIES.

415

ment, and to rely entirely on the apparently slender sanction


of forfeiture
^.

847. If

we

consider the general tendency of

modern

legis- Tendency
legisia-

lation in regard to sanctions,

we

perceive,

on the one hand,

that our ideas on the subject of compensation for injuries

*^-

have rapidly developed.

But, concurrently,

we

observe that

in the absence of certain characteristics, which are generally


also the characteristics of crime, such as fraud or intentional

wrong, the ultimate sanction of imprisonment has in


matters almost disappeared.

civil

Moreover, whilst

we

are con-

tinually enlarging the field of crime,

we

are at the

same time
all

endeavouring to mitigate the sufferings of punishment in


respects except their duration.

am

also inclined to think

that (possibly as a result of these changes) the disgrace of

a criminal conviction, which

is

an important part of the

punishment, has diminished, especially in certain cases


for example, as the conviction of directors of a

such,
for

company

fraud.

We

are perhaps approaching a considerable readjust-

ment
'

of the respective domains of civil

and criminal law.

chap.
sions

See Powell's Analysis of American Law, Philadelphia, 1870, Book iii. ix. sect. 3, and the Loi de 22 Juin, 1870, in the Collection des Lois,

Tol. Ixvii. p. 165,

where there is a very interesting account of the discuswhich preceded the abolition of imprisonment for debt in France.

CHAPTER

XX.

PROCEDURE.
Procedure
is

848. Peoceduee
of courts of law.

is

the term used to express the action

the

action of courts of law.

Courts of law are persons or bodies of

persons delegated

by the sovereign authority


tacitly,

to

perform

the function of enforcing the duties and obligations which

have been created


in the
Parts of the proceeding

or

expressly,

by

this

authority

form of law.

849. I have already pointed out

how

this function gener-

ally divides itself into the several parts of ascertaining the

penal or
remedial.

precise nature of the duties

which have been imposed by the which of these

sovereign authority

of further ascertaining

have been broken


to the breach.

and of applying the sanction appropriate


though
this

I have further pointed out that


is

penal function

the only one for which courts of law exist,


it

they do in fact perform


ing a function which

in

some cases by ostensibly


;

exercis-

is

merely remedial

the court taking

action ostensibly, not for the purpose of punishing disobedi-

ence to the law, but for the purpose of giving redress


Civil

^.

and

850. This cardinal difference between the ostensible functions of courts of

criminal
courts.

law corresponds generally, but not exactly,


of

with

the

distinction

courts

into

courts

of

civil

and

courts of criminal procedure.


of all courts
is

Though the ultimate

object

the same, the civil court generally professes


inflict

only to give redress, and the criminal court only to

punishment.
851.

The general scheme

of procedure in each court also

corresponds with the general object which each professes to


See Chapter XIX.

PROCEDURE.
pursue.
plaint
is

417

In the

civil

court the person


suffered
is

who makes

the com-

the party

who has
litis,

hy the breach

of the law.

He

is

also

dominus

and

responsible for the conduct of

the proceedings, and in a great measure for the expenses of

them, inasmuch as they are treated as though they were carried

on entirely for his

benefit.
settle

He may abandon them


the
dispute
privately,

at
if

any
he

moment,
thinks
it
fit.

or

he

may

On

the other hand, in the criminal court, though

has been the custom in England hitherto to trust the

conduct of prosecutions to some extent to private individuals,


the prosecutor
is

in no

way

responsible for, nor has he control

over, the proceedings.

852. It

is

a general rule that courts of law will not


is

move

Suits will
rally
lie^'

unless some duty or obligation


assert rights

broken.

Very

often parties

which they do not

as yet wish to exercise, or^"'''"^'

repudiate obligations which they are not at the

moment
1

upon to perform.

And

so disputes arise without any wrong


:

,^

called tionswifchoutwrong.

having actually taken place


desirous,

and very often come

parties

are

from reasons

of convenience, to

into court

and

get their rights declared at once without waiting for the

expected breach.

No

doubt there

may

be strong reasons of

convenience in favour of such a course.

The

intention to do
if it

an act would, in a vast majority of cases, be abandoned,

was known
if it

to be illegal

or,

what comes

to the

same thing,

was known that a court of law would treat it as illegal. The consideration which counterbalances these reasons of convenience is the fear that too much opportunity might be
o-iven to persons of litigious character to bring useless

and

vexatious suits against their neighbours, and thus the number And since the burden of suits would be greatly multiplied.

and expense of
solely

litigation always fall to

some extent on the

public at large, this burden and expense cannot be increased

with reference to considerations of private convenience.

The

rule therefore, is generally adhered to, that there

must

be some actual wrong done before the court will set itself in motion. An exception is, however, generally made where
E e

418
there
is

PROCEDURE.

[Chap.

XX.

a reasonable and well-grounded expectation that

a breach of duty or obligation will be committed^ and that

no proper redress can be had^


indeed, one class of cases in

if it

does take place.


in

There

is,

England

which parties are

allowed to come and ask simply for the opinion of the court

upon

their rights

and duties

but this privilege

is

confined

to trustees, who, to

by
cast

a peculiarity of our law,

may
it

always

some extent

upon the court the duty which has


This being
so,
is

been undertaken by themselves.


economical to allow

more

them

to consult the court, as it were,

and

to require the court to give

them

its

advice

for a refusal

might only
Com853.
of

result in

a far greater burden.

The

respective

schemes of procedure are fashioned

ment

according to these views.


to set the court in

In

all

courts the party

who

seeks

1^^'^'^^'

motion has, except in very special cases

such as are mentioned above, to

make a statement which,


is

whether

it

be called a complaint, an indictment, a charge,


bill

a demand, a

of complaint, a plaint, or a declaration,

in

fact an assertion that a

wrong has been committed j including


a claim for redress.
This
of
is

also generally, in the civil courts,


is

invariable

and there

also invariably a defined

mode
is

bringing before the court the person whose conduct


plained of, in order that his answer
is

com-

may

be heard.

But there
the com-

a good deal of variety, and some peculiarity, in the modes

of doing this. plaint


is

Sometimes the party against


is
is

whom

made

summoned

that

is,
;

he receives a notice that

his attendance

required in court
is

sometimes he

is

arrested

and brought there; sometimes he


in court
;

required actually to appear

sometimes only to put in his answer or defence.


to the exact time of
of.

Moreover the practice varies as

the statement of the particular wrong complained


times
it is

making Some-

other party to

made simultaneously with the first summons to the come into court and answer it. Sometimes the
first,

summons
made

into court takes place

and the complaint

is

afterwards.

And

these varieties are to be found not

only in different countries, but in the same.

For some crimes.

Sec.

853]

PBOCEDURE.

419

both in England and in India, a party

may

be arrested and

brought into

eoiirt;

in others the proceedings can only com-

appearance.

mence by a summonSj followed by a warrant in ease of nonIn England, in what used to be called the

Appear*'^^"

Common Law

Courts of

civil procedure,
first

the theory was that

nothing could be done in the

instance beyond biinging

the party complained against into court, and that no further


proceedings were possible, until this had been accomplished.

And though
so

the rigour of this rule

is

now

relaxed,

it is still

much

respected, that the appearance (as it is called) of the


is

defendant

always feigned to have taken place, even when


it.

the proceedings go on without

When

both parties have

appeared, or are supposed to have appeared, they


respective statements answering
till

make

their

and replying

to each other

both sides have nothing more to say.

In the Court of
complain
;

Chancery, on the other hand, the plaintiff has always com-

menced proceedings by
the same time requiring

stating

what he had

to

of,

and delivering a copy of the statement

to the defendant

at

him

to appear

and answer

it.

And

the rule requiring the defendant to appear, before the case

could proceed further, then applied, as in the


Courts, but was avoided by the same
indirect methods which were
fiction.

Common Law
The
cm-iously

at one time in use both in Courts

of

Common Law and

in Courts of Chancery, for compelling

a defendant

to take the step of appearing in court,


it,

and some

expressions which are used regarding

seem

to point to

something voluntary in the submission of the defendant to the


jurisdiction of the court.

This

is

analogous to what has been


considers the
legis actio

pointed out by Sir

most ancient

Henry Maine in what he judicial proceeding known to us

the

sacramenti of the Romans, where the form of the proceeding

appears to treat the judge rather as a private arbitrator

chosen by the parties than as a public


in

officer of justice.

But

modern times
significance^.

this appearance of voluntary submission has

no

See Maine's Ancient

Law (first

ed.), p. 375.

Under the

last

new rules

E e a

420
854. It
is

PEOCEDURE,

[Chap.

XX.

impossible here to do more than point out the

leading characteristics of the procedure^

by which the complaint


this subject, called

of one side and the defence of the other are submitted to the

judgment

of the tribunal.

The

rules

upon

by us the

rules of pleading, are generally elaborate,


artificial,

and very

often highly

and even capricious ; but I

will notice

one or two leading distinctions of principle in the practice of


different coui-ts respecting
Pleadings.
it.

855. In every dispute the two principal questions to be

law and
fact,

determined
exist

are, (i)

what

are the duties


(a)
^ '
.

and obligations which


.

civil cases.

parties ? between the ^


?

have they, or any of them,

been broken
of course

The

first

of these questions depends ultimately


it

upon the law, but proximately


will arise;

may

depend on

whether certain events have happened, on the happening of

which duties and obligations


or a marriage solemnised.

such, for instance,


or a will executed;

as whether a contract has been

made;

certain events have happened.

The second depends on whether Hence in every case which


fact

comes into court the questions to be determined resolve themselves into questions of

law and questions of

and

it is

the object of the rules of pleading in English courts, and

analogous rules in
precise
to be

all

other courts, to put into a more or less

form the various questions of law and fact which have


^.

determined

856. The difficulty of understanding the procedure in the

English courts, where the


arises

trial

takes place before a jury,

from the very wide

difference

which prevails between


it.

the theory and the practice based upon

Theoretically the

parties to a suit heard before a jury are required to

work out
but

the questions of law and questions of fact into distinct issues,


as they are called
;

and though at the present day


as these questions

this is

imperfectly done,
(those of 1883) a

j-et,

have to be decided by

summons may

in simple eases contain a statement of the


of
it is

claim,
'

then dispensed with. have shown above that the socalled questions of fact sometimes involve questions of conduct, but these fall within the province of the jury (see supra, sect. 25).
I follow here the usual language. I

and any further statement

Sec. 854-857.]

PROCEDUKE,
issues

421
issues

different tribunals

fact

by the jury

of law by the court and of one would suppose that to whatever extent
The judge^ one would
think,
to completely separate, and then to decide the

this has not

been done before^ the deficiency must necessarily

be supplied at the hearing.

would have

first

questions of law ; after which he would ask the jury to give


their opinion
this is done.

on the

facts.
it is

To a very

considerable extent

But then
facts are so

only done in a verbal address


;

to the jury of

which there

is

no regular record

the observa-

tions

on the

mingled with the directions on the


difiicult to distinguish

law, that

it is
is

sometimes very

them

and what
judge lays
is,

more important

still,

there

is

no regular mode

of ascertaining whether or no the jury acceiDt the law as the


it

down; because the ordinary form


^.

of finding

not on specific questions, but for the

plaintiff, or for
it

the

defendant, in general terms

Indeed, were

considered

necessary to keep the functions of the court and the jury

as completely severed in practice as they are in theory, the


proceedings at a trial at Nisi Prius would have to undergo

a veiy

considerable change.

I even think

it

very doubtful

whether with such a severance of functions the jury system


could be as successfully worked as
it is

at present.

The

present success of that system depends almost entirely on the


friendly co-operation and mutual good understanding between

the court and the jury, which have been, in England, so


liappily established
:

and these

it

would be extremely

difiicult

to presei-ve, if such discussions as to their respective duties

were admitted as would be necessary to keep each within the


strict limits of its

own
little

particular functions.

857.

very

observation of

what
is

passes daily in

courts of justice will

show that there

a similar indistinct-

' The jury cannot be compelled to find particular facts, or even to find the affirmative, or negative, on particular issues, though they are generally But it has been alvyays recognised as their vpilling to do so, if requested. undoubted privilege to decline finding any other than a general verdict,

and they have been knovpn to exercise it. See a case reported in the third volume of Adolphus and Ellis' Reports, p. 506.

422
iiess

PKOCEDUEE.
in the
line

[Chap.

XX.

drawn between law and

fact In the pro-

ceedings

subsequent to the verdict of the jury,

when the
it

tribunal, whilst professing to keep within

the province of

pure law, really enters into


impossible to call legal
is
:

considerations which

seems

as, for instance,

whether a verdict
a legal

against the weight of the evidence.


is

And though

form
think
is

given
is

to another frequent consideration

whether there
it is

any evidence

to suppoi-t

namely, the verdict yet I


what
^-

impossible to doubt that under this form


considered
is,

really very often

whether the jury have

drawn the right inference from the


In erimi-

facts laid before


is

them

858. In criminal cases no attempt

made

to separate

the questions of law and fact prior to the hearing;

and

though the functions of judge and jury are in criminal cases


theoretically separated, there
is still

the same absence of

alt

security that this separation should be practically observed

and the
one,
is

result in a criminal trial,

in reality arrived at rather


trial,

even more than in a civil by a co-operation of judge

and jury throughout the


exercise of

than by the simultaneous

two

entirely independent functions.


is

In courts
eery.

859. The proceedings where there


deal simpler.

no jury are a good

There

it is

not necessary to separate the issues

of law and fact.

The
is

parties are not required to

make

this

separation at

any stage of the pleadings antecedent to the


nothing in the nature of the proceedings
it

hearing, and there


at the hearing

which renders

then necessary, inasmuch

as the presiding judges decide both


ously.

law and fact simultaneis

And

in practice the separation

only so far

made
and

as

is

found to be convenient for understanding the

case,

so far as the judges

may make
courts,

it,

when

in conformity with

the tradition of the

they disclose to the litigants

their reasons in detail for arriving at this conclusion.

In India and other


countries,

860. The provisions of the Indian Code of Civil Procedure


,
.

on this subject are very peculiar and stringent.

They

re-

quire that the judge should settle the questions of law


*

and

Supra, sect. 25.

Sec. 858-861.

PEOCEDUEE.

423

fact

upon whicli the

parties are at issue in every case before

the hearing commences.

The French Code

requires no settle-

ment

of issueSj but there are very strict rules

which require

that the judgment should contain a specific statement of the points of law and of fact which have arisen, with the deter-

mination of each.

The requirements
Law,

of the Italian Code,

and

I believe also of the Spanish

are similar.

Of
is

all

these

methods, that provided for by the Indian Code


laborious and complete.
issue

the most

It contemplates that every possible

which can

arise should
is

be raised prospectively

much

greater bm-den than

thrown upon a judge by the French


duty has been found so onerous
it.

Code,

who

has only to declare what issues have actually come


;

into dispute

and

in fact this

that the courts in India have almost universally neglected

And
that
far,

it

appears, from the rules recently

made by

the judges in

England, that English lawyers have come to the conclusion,


it

may

be safely

left to

the discretion of the court

how

and when, and with what and that

precision, the issues shall be

ascertained;

so far as this has to be done, it should

be done,

if possible,

by agreement

of the parties^.

But the

rules are silent

upon the question of separating the findings on


it

these several issues, so that


of not doing so, as
it

may be

inferred that the practice


is

at present exists in England,

not

disapproved.

861

^.

It

is

not possible yet to form any judgment as to

how

the modern system of allowing an infinite variety of

questions to be tossed in disorder before the court will answer

the ends of justice.

One thing

is

certain, that this disorder

must be reduced
object of all
'

to order at

some point

in the trial.

rules of pleading,' as they are called,

The was to

produce that order.

As a

learned

German

Jurist has pointed

out in some very practical and sensible observations upon


legal procedure generally, no part of that procedure has been

spoken of with greater contempt by mankind at large than


'

What
iii.

follows has appeared in an article in the

Law

Magazine, N.S.

vol.

p. 393.

424
rules of pleading.

PROCEDURE.
The term
'

[Chap.
'

XX.

special pleading

has become

a bye-word in the English language^ and the whole system


has been swept
these rules
it is

away

as worthless.

Yet the objects which


desirable^

had in view were not only

but such as

absolutely necessary to secure.

Unless a judge contents

himself with simply saying that he decides in favom- of

one party or the other (and practically no judge can do

this),

he must break up the complex contentions of the parties into


the various simple questions which are involved.

To

the

performance of this task modern procedure for the most part


affords no assistance

whatever

it is

left entirely to

the in-

tellectual capacity of the judge,

with such assistance as the

parties

through their counsel choose to render him^.

In

the early

Roman

procedure, the judges being laymen, and

there being but scanty opportunity of obtaining legal assist-

ance for the court, there was a rigorous rule of

'

one suit

one question,' binding both upon the plaintiff and the defendant.

Our

rules of pleading,
difficulties

though never quite

so strict,

did remove

many

out of the

way

of the judges
difficulties

by bringing out the


are

issues to be tried.

These

now

let loose

upon the

court.

It

may

be that the rules

of pleading were, on the whole, an impediment to the administration of justice. It

may

be that they had become distorted,


in view.

and sometimes defeated the very object they had

But the
judges
is

object was a useful one, and the burden laid

upon

enhanced by their

abolition.
(as

It

is

frequently taken
called) the

for granted that


of pleading

by simplifying

it is

rules

you have

relieved the parties of a merely useless

legal technicality.

When

you have allowed the

plaintiff to
all his

lay before the court in his

own language
way

the tale of

wrongs, and have permitted the defendant to state not only


all

that he has to say in

of reply, but to bring all his


is

countercharges, a triumph of simplicity

supposed to have
this as a certainty.

been achieved. It
It

is

too soon to count

upon

may
'

turn out that the investigation


See lliering, Geist.
d.

is

only

made more

Rom.

Rechts., part

iii.

p. 15 sqq.

Sec. 862, 863.J

PROCEDURE.
difficult.

425
is

costly

and more

It

may

be that the whole case


:

never before the court at any one time

that the aspect

of a case constantly changes in the course of the investigation

and that, on the whole, with a greater expenditure of money, time, and labour, a satis:
:

that appeals are increased

factory result

is less

seldom obtained.

862.

When
is

the ease has been heard and the decision Decree


is

given, the result, so far as the judgment


claratory,
,.

not merely de- ^edara^'''


*''y ^"^

to impose either

an ultimate or an intermediate

sanction.

In

civil cases this will generally

form,

be an intermediate

sanction only, and, for the reasons explained above, generally

an order to make compensation or restitution. But though the courts lay down as a general rule that they will not move unless there has been some wrong committed,
in the form of

the real object of

many

suits is not to

compel redress, either

in the shape of compensation or in the shape of restitution.

The
is

real dispute is as to the rights of the respective parties,

and a declaration on
frequently well

this point

having been once procured,

it

known
what

to all concerned in the litigation


is

that every one will do

required, either

from motives of

honesty, or because the means of compulsion are sufficiently

proximate and certain to make

it

useless further to resist.

For
is

this reason

we

constantly find that the result of litigation

a mere declaration.

863. Again, wherever

it is possible,

the Court of Chancery,


redress

Eestitu^"'

which alone

lias

power to do

so,

gives

by way

of

restitution rather than

by way of compensation.
all parties as

Now

the

principle of restitution
duties,

is,

as far as possible, to treat the rights,

and obligations of
having been
all

being at that moment,

and

as

along, such as they would have been,


to interfere with them.

had nothing taken place


a sale of property
is if
is

Thus, when

is set

aside on account of fraud, every effort

made

to

put the parties precisely in the same position as

the fraud had not taken place.


declared void.

The fraudulent conveyance


is

The property

treated as never having

ceased to belong to the party

who was induced by

the fraud

426
to part with
it.

PROCEDUBE.
All the profits are declared to belong- to

him, and so forth.

The court only resorts to a money payment by way of compensation when it is compelled to do so. But it would not always be easy to say whether, in very
strictness,

the court in making a decree of this kind, was

depriving the defendant of a right, or merely declaring the


existing rights of the plaintiff
;

that

is

to say,

whether

it

was

applying an ultimate sanction, or not applying a sanction at


all.

Nor

is

there

any reason in

practice for distinguishing

between the performance of these operations.


it

On the contrary,

rather serves as a guide to the measure of relief, to keep up


it

the idea (even though

be

fictitious)

that the rights of the


have, therefore, another
is

parties are only being declared.

We

reason

why

in form, at

any

rate,

the final decree in a suit

often only declaratory.

INDEX
N.B.
The numbers in
the

Index

refer to the Sections.


his

Austin,

explanation

of custom,

Absolutely void, meaning


n.

of,

274 and

Act, is an event viewed as under human

analysis must be intended, consequences need not be tended, no from mental condition without, dependent on mental
of, ib.

control, 214.

his view of case law, 98. his explanation of error of law and 269. J. Mill's estimation on intention in promise, 621.
fact,

18 sqq.

S.

of, 1 7 .

219.

Austrian

Law of

Succession, 787.
B.

of,

in-

220. legal result

232. legal result of, condition, 233. in the law, 235.

Bailee, consideration for contract 642 ; possession of, 388.

of,

Benefit of Inventory, Soo.

Bentham

refers everything to public

Acte juridique, 235. Actio in rem and Keal Action compared, 129.

opinion, 119 n.
his

contempt for lawyers, 194.

Bills of Sale, 540.

Action through an intermediary,


246.

Administration of intestate's estate,


806, 807.

Adverse
585
.

possession,
246.

meaning

of,

Agency, law

of, not derived from law, 251.

Roman

Agent and Messenger,


tween, 253. Alienation, restrictions

difference be-

a condition of personality, 132. Blackstone, hij view of reports, would limit human law by divine, no. gives no account of 198 nor of breaches of duty, his explanation of error of law and 269. observations on 735. how explained by, 751. on the origin of 790.
91.
duties,
ib.
;

Birth, what constitutes, 132, 133.

fact,

his

error,

intoxication,

wills,

on,

330

n.,

Blamevrorthiness not a
tort, 707, 711.

criterion of

334right of, not universal, 516. what consent necessary to, 517. should be certain and notorious, 519. Allodial property, succession to, 813.

Bona

fides as applied to prescription, 560.


747.

Boulton against Jones,

Alluvion and Diluvion, 490. America. See United States.


Analogies,
100.

Braoton, his authority as a lawyer, 89. on prescription, 566. Brahmins, influence of, on Hindoo
law, 83.

competition

of

opposite,

Burn
of law by, 77. continuation of by heir,

against Carvalho, 479.


C.

Analogy, extension
Ancestor,
777-

Canon
817.
of,

law, rules of inheritance


92.

in,

Anoona against Kogers, 388. Angus against Dalton, 581 n. Animals ferae naturae, capture

Appearance, hovr
27.

361.

acquisition of ownership
853. far necessary,
ib.

of,

483.

Arrangement of Iiaw, 291. Ashford against Thornton,

case

of,

advantages basis of authority characteristics 98. Austin's view 98. Paley's view 100. distinction between, and law derived
of, ih.
of,

Case law, English,

93.

of,

of,

of,

from commentaries, 103.

Austin, his view of declaratory and

Chancery, creation

repealing laws, 6. distinguished law from morality,


criticisms of, 14 sqq. his explanation of laws judges, 18 sqq.

1 2.

made by

477 how error treated procedure in courts

of equitable ownership in, 335. court of, mortgage of moveables in,


in, 743.
of,

859.

428

INDEX.
Contract,
132.
offer and acceptance how far necessary to, 663. with agent of undisclosed principal,

Child, en ventre sa mfere, not a person,

Church, part taken by, in


794, 806, 808.

succession,

664.
liability on, is

Civil

and Criminal Procedure have


object, 825.

same

Civil Injuries and Crimes, distinction between, 599. Civil Liability, 599. Civil Procedure, application of sanc-

by courts of, S42. Civil Sanctions ultimately same


tions

may be owned, 665. 665. how affected by insanity, 732. of error on, 739. of intoxication 753. of infancy on, 757. whether prevented by fraud,
effect
effect
effect

a thing,

on,

it is

as

766.

criminal, 841.

See Manu. Codes, early, 69. Coercion, evil of, 52. Coke, his views on prescription, 566.

Code of Manu.

Colonies, subordinate legislation in, 63. Combat, judges presided over, 2^. Commands, what, are laws, 5. Commentaries, as a source of law,

treated as a person, 136. notion in early family,

Conturier against Hastie, 749. Convalescence, 278. Copyright, ownership of, 323. Corporation. See Juristical Person.
of,

145. ownership
sole,

137.

of,

324.

and case law,


856.
100.

loi.

Cour de Cassation, authority of, 78 n. Crimes and Civil Injuries, distinction

difference between,

04.
of,

Common Law, procedure in courts

between, 599.

Competition of opposite Analogies,


Condition, of persons, meaning
of,

Criminal and Civil Procedure have same object, 825. Criminal cases, procedure in, 858.
of
of,

estimation standard

168, 176. Conduct, rules of, not law, 1 7 e. as enforced by courts of equity, 20. as enforced by courts of law, 2i.
of,

Code, vagueness expressions used in draft 211 599. procedure, application of sanctions
n.

liability,

sanctions
civil,

by courts

710.

of, 844. ultimately the 841.

same

as

of,

714a, 715.

Cundy against Lindsay,


Custom, explanation
effect

746, 768.

Confusion of ownership, 495. Consent, of heir to succession, 802. Consequences of Acts need not be
intended, 220.

antecedent to law, given to by courts, early reports are evidence


79.
T>.

of, 18.

ib. of,

peculiar English law, 628.by, 627. not applied deeds, 631. need not be adequate, 632.
is

Consideration, what
to to

meant

as a source of law in England,

90.
ib.

true meaning of requirement, 635. past service, 639. contract of bailment, 642. moral, 644.
fur for

Damnum

Construction, rules of, 240. Contract, English definitions


612.

et injuria, 699 n. Debts, liability of heirs for, 818. Declaration, suits will not lie for, without wrong, 852. Declaratory degrees, 863. Decrees, often only declaratory, 862.

of,

609,

Deed, does not require


631. early conception
of,

consideration,

and conveyance, difference between, 234. 610, 617. Defamation, 699. Savigiiy's analysis 604, 619. Delegation of Sovereignty, 62. a manifestation intention, Delict. intention how ascertained, 621. 620. FrenchSee Tort. 669. definition consideration necessary 626. Delivery, when necessary to transfer See Consideration. of ownership, 519. void and voidable, 649. error of Heineccius as 522 on, of defects of form, 651. error of Serjeant Manning as non-compliance with statute of reasons why not now necessary, 523. frauds, 652. important to ownership, 525. transfer 660. on sale of land, 529.
of,
is

of

of,

for,

to,

n.

effect

to, ib.

still

of,

INDEX.
Derivative possession does not produce prescription, 583. Detinue, nature of action of, 511. De Tooqueville's view of American
Constitution, 34.

429

Equity, why it precedes legislation, 122. is ex post facto and concrete, ib.

in India, 124.

Error,

Blackstone's

explanation

of,

Dishonesty, meaning

of,

689.
dif-

Divine Lav, how conceived by

not always enforced, but a source law, no. human law not limited by, and human, not generally use made by lawyers
109.
is

ferent nations, 106.


of

ih.

in con-

flict,

113.

of,

115.

Drunkenness,

See Intoxication.
will, 758.

744 Savigny's views as 270. as to private 277. as application of law, 272. of on 734
to,

261, 269. in criminal cases, 263. of law and fact, 265. how treated in Chancery, 268, 739, Austin's explanation of, 269. how regarded in Eoman law, 269,

rights,

to

Duress, 254, 758.


as

does not destroy the a ground 761. Duties, what they created by sovereign power, must be cannot be imposed by sovereign body on negative, and 182. and primary and secondary, not generally expressed, 196, 593 not stated by Blackstone,
of non-liability,
are, 147.

how treated in French Code,


Estate, conception
330of,

effect

liability,

sqq.

745. in English law,

Events,

151.

how described, 208.


Execution and judicial powers, Executor, consent of, 803.
48.

207.

specific, 153.
itself,

154.

relation back of
Fact, error
of,

title of, 804.

positive relative

181.

absolute,
clearly

F.
265.

183, 592.

See Error of law


of,

198.

and law, separation of issues 856. jury interference of judges


in
cases,

and

fact.

in questions

of,

857.
sort of corporation,
.
of,

E.

Family, anciently a

are a kind400. 401. are jura 418. the must be between, and prendre, 419. appurtenant and 421. take potwater, 422. without 424. perpetual, cause 425. of support, 426. correspond 427. ofUght, 581.
of servitudes, in re aliens,
servient res difference
gross,

Basements,

137. 774 ^ ownership, 326, 774


ib.

Father and Son, physical identity


Perss naturse, animals,
capture

land,

profits-k-

of,

ownership
Feudal

361.

to

profit,

of,

restrictions on,

to duties to forbear, 430.

Enjoyment

as of right of easement,

578. must be peaceable and open, 583.

chief not a relation of importance of 340. not a 341. not analogous service 341.
characteristic of, i5. contract, ib.
it,

of, 4S3. relation, unsuited to times, 343. tenure, nature of, 338. in England, ib.

modern

political

juristic relation,

services

peculiar, ib.

in India,

Equal Freedom,
59.

principle

of,

Equality, cannot be promoted


is

51, 53. by law,

a good thing Equitable ownership, 335. anomalous, 336. nothing Eoman law,
in
itself, ib.

not cause of modern evils of ownership, 343. Fidei oommissum, not like equitable ownership, 336.

Feudalism

Fiducia, 439, 448.

Forbearance, 231.

Equity,

ib. like it in original conception of English,

Force involved
law, 17 a.

in the conception

of

why

120.
it

has become rigid, 121. explanation of Sir H. Maine, 121. due to difference in conception of
law,
ib.

Forfeiture of ownership, 499. France, imprisonment for debt


846.

in,

Fraud, 273. meaning of, 6gi.

430
Fraud,

INDEX.
as

whether

ground of
it

non-liability, 765. prevents a contract, 766


of,
effect

Imprisonment for debt,

Frauds, Statute

of non-

in England, 284. in other countries, 845, 846.

compliance with, 652.

Imputation of intention or knowin contract,

Prse consent, meaning

of,

in the Indian Penal Code, 265


In personam, rights, In rem, rights, 164.
164.

ledge, 264.

w.

Free government,

cliaraotenstics of,

31exists in

England, 36.

Freedom, principle of equal, 51* French Code, punishment of judge by,


for refusing to decide, 26. prohibits judge from making law, ib. declares sovereignty of people, 38 n. rule of, as to delivery, 528. definition of contract in, 611.
definition
delict in, 669.
in,

Inadvertence, 227. Incorporeal things, quasi possession


of, 391.

of how error treated


French
lawryers,

745*
.

French. Constitution, 38

opinions of, as to restrictions on ownership, 328 n.

equity 124. procedure 860, imprisonment debt 845. Indian wills, history 791. Penal Code on intoxication, 751. Infancy, 273, 755. in criminal 756. in contracts, 757.
in, in,

India, subordinate legislation

in, 63.

for

in,

of,

cases,

G.

Government, bad
58.

Gift, transfer by, 515. better than none,


fiction of, in prescription, 565,

modern ideas concerning, 724. how 725.


it

Inheritance. See Succession. Injury, meaning of, 671, Insanity, 273, 723.
affects liability,

Grant,

Insinuatlo, 529. Intention, 217.

569, 588.

Gratuitous promises, 630, 64S.

H.
Harrison, Frederic, as
conception of law, 17
to
a.

force

in

Heedlessness, 228. Heiueocius, on delivery


522
n.

of

chattels,

manifestations 241. formal and informal, 242. express and 243. to break the law, immaterial crime, 263. necessary to possession, 366. in contract how ascertained, 621, imputation 624.
of,

tacit,

in

of,

Heir,

continuation
of,

of

ancestor

by,

Interpretation, different kinds extension of law by, 75.

of,

consent
liability

777-

of,

to succession, 802. to debts of ancestor,

Hindoo

800, 818. lavf , development of, 83. Brahminical influence upon, 46. of succession, 780. widow, estate of, 332. wUl, explanation of, by Privy Council,

usual one, accepted, rules 625. Intoxication, 751. how explained by Blackstone, 751. Indian Penal Code on, 751, on contract, 753.
81.
of,

72.

effect of,

Inventions, ownership of, 323. Inventory, benefit of, 800.

792.

Hirer, possession by, 3S0. Hopkins against Logan, 645.

Judge-made law, forbidden altogether

Hypotheoa,

444.

and to some extent by French Code,

by Justinian, 78
78)1.

., 92,

Ignorance,

not a defect of wUl, 735. Blackstone's observations on, on contract, 739effect of,

260, 734.

Set Error.
ib.

forbidden in Prussia, 93. not a usurpation,


97,

Judges, frequently act without law,

presided over combats,


Judicial

25, 27. 29, 201.

27.

Ihering, criticisms of Savigny's views on possession, 384. Immoveables, owner can follow, 505. succession to, 811. See Succession. Imperfect laws, 838.

function, exercise of, by sovereign, 95. Jura in re, prescription as applied to, 562. possession of, 576.

INDEX.
Jurisdiction of courts, how
luntary, 853. Juristic act, 235.
far vo-

431

Law, Hindoo, how developed, 83. Mahommedan, development of,


early,

Juristical persons, 138. T need not consist of persons,

opinions continental lawyers, opinions English lawyers, through Jury, how with interference of judges with proceedings 856.
1

how created,
of
of

ih.

39.

140.

ib.

act

it

representatives, 141. insanity, 730. deals verdicts


before,

of,

857.

Jus in re

aliens, as opposed in ownership, 316. Justa causa, as applied to prescription, 560.

K. King's peace, 600.

imputation

Knowledge,

222.
of,

264.

of Europe, generally personal, became under influence of feudalism, 87. books, printing of 89 idea posterior that of judicial derived from commentaries, loi. inadequate expression 193. cannot be expressed by laymen, 194. expression not necessary to administration of 201. very in Statute Book, 202. and error See Error 265. of law and fact. arrangement 291. public and private, 292. of persons, things, and procedure, 296. not primarily made redress, 822, perfect and imperfect, 838.
84.
territorial

early,

n.

of,

to

decision, 95,

of,

of,

justice,

little

fact,

of,

of,

for

Lawyers,
Iiand, ownership
.

of, alleged to be indefensible, 52. feudal ownership of, 338. possession of, how acquired, 355

delivery on sale

how

retained, 357
of,

how

lost,

364.

529.

in early times not alienable, 516. prescription as applied to, 554.

law, 194. Bentham's contempt 194. are necessary,


ib.

inflaence of, 81 ; mainly a popular one, ib. reforms in the law due to, ib. how far responsible for expression of
for,

erroneous,

Xiandowner,

latitude allowed to

in

England, 333.

Leases, for long terms of years, 333, Lee against Muggeridge, 20. Legal expressions, importance of obtaining accurate, 210.

Larceny, how
387-

possession regarded in,

simplified, 387 a. Xjassalle, his principle of realisation of

how law might be

Legal fraud, objection


212.

to use of term,

Legal proceedings, commencement


of,

what commands declaratory, conception not dependent on any moral theory, which do not proceed from sovereign authority, element of in conception 17 made by judges, Austin's explanaciety, 2.
are, 5.
t

the will, 55. Iiatifundia, 443. Law^, general conception of, i, 9. part of conception of political so-

853.

Legal relations, creation, extinction, and transfer of, 203, Legal remedies, ancient forms of, 27.
49. what oau be done by, objects subordinate, why preceded by Equity, 122. Legislators, judge-made law, tendency of modern as to sanctions,
57.
of, ib,

Legislation,

is

based on

utility,

6.

of,

62.

13.

dislike

78.

10.

force

of,

847.

a.

Leibnitz, bases wills on immortality of soul, 793 n.

27,201. sources See Source of law. development in early times, 69 by interpretation, extension by interpretation, 75
25,
of,

and

tion ot, 18. fact, division into, 25. not necessary to action of judges,
60.

Lex

of,

71.

of,

by analogy,

77.

includes primary and595. secondary duties, 596. how out of contract and 596 sqq. and criminal, 599. breach of contract, 603. See Tort. 667.
far it arises
delict,
civil

Talionis, 828. Liability, what it means,

for

for tort,

432

INDEX.
472. how viewed at common law, 473. attempt of Lord Mansfield improve the common law English law might be 476.
to
of,
of,

Liability, as between innocent per-

Mortgage,

sons, 716. set aside or modified, 721. Lien, difference between, and Pledge,

467.

simplified,

Life, estate

for, peculiarity of,

330.

Light, easement of, 581. Limitation, 550, Littleton, identifies time immemorial with prescription, 568. Lost grant, presumption of, 573. Lost property, finding of, 485. Lumley against Gye, 666.

475 "> 481. Mortgagee, can always sell, 472. Mosaic law of retaliation, 828.

Motive, 216.

Moveable and immoveable things,


129.

Moveables, possession of, how acquired,


358
362.
;

how

retained, 360

how

lost,

M.

Mahommedan
84.
difiScuIties

law, development
of, ib.

of,

in way influence of Roman law of 786.


succession,

on,

ih.

Maine, Sir Henry,

his

remarks on

Malice, meaning in law, meaning

Austin, 14 sqq. his account of equity, 120.


of,

686. of, 687.'

Manifestations of intention, 241. See Intention. Manning, on delivery of chattels, 5^2 n. Mansfield, Lord, his attempt to improve common law of mortgage,
476.

how ownership follows, 504. servitudes not attached 407. pledge in court of chancery, 477. owner cannot recover in 505 ownership transferred by recovery of value, of recovering, 512. biUs of 540. prescription as applied 561. no heir in English law, 805. pass ordinary, succession 797, 805. See Succesfar
to,
of,

of,

specie,

of,

ib.

difi&culty

sale,
to,

to,

to

ib.

to,

sion.

N.
Nature, law of, n6. Negligence, meaning
of,

recognition of83 custom function of king judge on 777.


;

Manu,

code

of,

antiquity

of, 83.

in, 83.
in, 93.

as

succession,

Measurements of time, 280. Mendacity alone not a tort, 701. Mental condition, produces no

legal

result without act, 232. how ascertained, 237. rules for ascertaining, 238.

duress

how opposed to intention, 680. latest meaning 681. Non-liability, grounds 717. insanity as ground 723. error as ground 734. intoxication as ground 751. infancy as ground 755.
of,

of,

679.

of,

of,

of,

of,

as ground Notary, 531.


of,

of,

758.

Mental reservation, effect of, 257. Messenger and agent, difference between, 253. Mill, J. S., his estimation of Austin, 17 n. Mirabeau, attack upon wills, 793. Misrepresentation, apart from contract,

Notice, doctrine

538.

0.

Occupancy,

acquisition of ownership by, 48.1Official reporters, appointment of, 91.


is,

how

far actionable, 702.

Mistake, 260.

See Error.
287, 290.

derived from experience, n6.


Moral theory, none
ception of law,

Montb, lunar and calendar, Moral consideration, 644. Moral law, 116.

involved in con-

1 3.

Morality,

distinction between, and law, 12. rules of, enforced by courts, 20, 21. not always thereby made rules of law, 23.

317. of aright, 321. Ownership, what meant by, 307. absolute, 310. not an aggregate of 314. rights are distributed, 315. of a corporation, 324. of family, 326. conditional, attempts to 327, 328. up, separation of into 328. separation of legal and equitable, of335inventions and copyright, 323.
is

Owner, who

rights,

of,

tie

estates,

INDEX.
Ownership,
of land, alleged to be indefensible, 52 ; in England, how far feudal, 338. Troplong's observations as to tying up, 328 . power to sell detached from, 334. evils of modem, not due to feudalism,
constitutes,

433

343 what 344. importance knowing, right of zemindars Bengal, not altered by pledge, 453. how acquired, 482. by occupancy 483. acquisition of property, 485. of whales and sturgeons by crown, 486. of treasure-trove, 487. of produce and animals, 489. of land by alluvion and 490. sea-shore, 491. confusion 495. things the 496. by of moveables, how 499. posof to accessions, in
ib. ib.

can pledge over, 450. 384. has a real right or jus in 469. nature of 470. ownership when gained by, 584. Pledgees, priority among, 463. subsequent, rights 465.
re,
it,

Pledgee, possession by,

of,

Pledgor, use and

foundation
India,

belong to, 454. Political society, characteristics of, 3.


profits
of,

45.

346.

Positive law and morals, distinction between, 12. Possession, of land by tenants in
346. Savigny's Treatise on, 347. Pollock and Wright on, physical idea 348, 353. legal idea 349. legal consequences contact not necessary 351. of land, how acquired, 353. how 355 retained, 357 how 364. of moveables, how acquired, 358 how retained, how 364. of wild animals, 360 361. how by intrusion, 365. mental element 366. transfer of detention without, 367 by change of mind, 368. how change of mind ascertained, 370. through a representative, 371
ib.
of, of, of,

of res nullius,
lost

of,

of trees

to,

diluvion,

of

lost,

of,

of

loss of,

affixed to soil, forfeiture, far it follows

lost,

lost

504; transferred by recovery of value, 505 ; or by change of possession, 507 history of the law relating to, 508 following up,
session,
; ;

in,

5" transfer by delivery when necessary solemnities required 542 corporate, succession grew out
of,

gift

or

sale,

515;

is

to, 519.

real not fictitious, 372

conditions

for transfer of,

774-

of, ib.

P.

Paley, his view of case law, 100. on intention in promise, 621.

Parentelen-ordnung,

787.

Peril, doing a thing at one's, 693. Perpetua caiisa, 410, 425. Personal law, in Europe, 87. Personal security, violation of, 698.

Persons, what are, 132. Persons, things, and procedure, law


of,

296.
125.

Persons and things,


Pignus, 441.
Plaint, 853.

involuntary, 458. extinguishment 461. difference between, and of moveables, whether necessary unauthorised 467. 468.
of,

Pleadings, 855. Pledge. See Security. ownership not altered by, 453.

of Infants and 378. 375. 380. in what cases constituted, 381. of pledgee, and tenant, Ihering's views on, 384. English law as 387. how regarded in larceny, of incorporeal things, 391. of 394. modern extension idea 394. only one person a time, 397. of co-owners, 399. whether necessary a pledge moveables, 467' of moveables, how ownership 504. precariousness of without, 526. as evidence 556. of jus 576. derivative, prescription not based on,
lunatics,
this is

necessary for,

derivative,

hirer,

ib.

to,

ib.

servitudes,

of

of,

in, at

to

of

far

follows,

title

of title,

in re,

583.

Potwater, right to take, 422.


467.

lien,

Power

to sell detached from ownerin pledge, 447.


of,

possession

to,

importance of

ship, 334.

sale of,

Praerogativa Begis, statute

486.

434
Prescription, 545.
of,

INDEX.
Beal action and actio in rem compared, 129.

Koman law 547. change in meaning of term, 552. in English law, as applied to land, 554. early legislation as 555. modern legislation as 556. bona and justa causa, 560. as applied to moveables, 561. as applied to jura in 562. time immemorial, 563. presumption of legal origin, 65. comparison of English and Boman law, 566. Bracton's views on, 566. Littleton's views on, 568 identifies time immemorial with, 568. based on modem grant, 573. Act, 574, 580. not based on derivative possession, 583 Indian law 586. steps necessary to improve law
ib.

Beal and personal

origin of

things, 129. this division, ib.


dififer-

Beal right and right in rem,

to,

to,

fides

of pledgee, 468. 167 Beal security, search nature 471.


of, ib.,

ence between,

.
after, 447.

re,

Bechtsgeschaft, 235. Eedress, not primary object of law,


822.

Eegistration, 529. on the continent of Europe, 529 sqq. in England, 534.

Eelation back of title

lost

Blackstone's view patent of James I


371-

of heir, 802. sqq. Beports, character of early, 90.

Bemedies, 821

of,

when they became authoritative,


of,

91. as to, ib.

ib.

of,

Bepresentative, possession

through,

of,

588.

Presumption of legal Primary duties, 183,

origin, 565.

592.

Principal, undisclosed, contract with agent of, 664. Priority among pledgees, 463. Private and public law, 292.

substitution of money payment 829. substitution of redress 830.


for,

Bes nullius, occupancy Eestitution, 275, 863. Betaliation, 828.

483.

for,

Bevrard
663.

for recovery of lost property,


it is,

Privy Council, explanation


'

of

Hindoo

will by, 792.


courts, differ-

ence between, 850. remarks on modern, 861.


Profits-&,-preudre, 400.

Procedure, 848 sqq. in civil and criminal

149. corresponds to duty, cannot exist without duty, duty may without,
1

Bight, what

50.

ib.

See Ease-

must be cannot belong


155-

exist

ib.

specific, 153.

to sovereign

body,

on, 429. correspond to duty to forbear, 430. Property. See Ownership. rights require to be
restrictions
of,

ments.

tested, 56.
it

need have no 160. must belong to a determinate person, 161. as foundation claim for redress,
object,
of

Property, grounds on which


defended, 56.

may be

837-

Eight in rem,

Public and private law, 292. Public opinion Tribunal, Bentham's,


119
.

difference between, and real right, 167 n. Bights, are incorporeal things, 128. of persons and things an erroneous

Q.

in rem and in personam, 164.


Bivers, ownership of bed

classification, 163.

Quasi possession of incorporeal things,

391of jus in re, 576.

Eoman law^, how

Quidquid plantatur solo solo


496.

cedit,

K.

Bashness,

226.

Batication, 276.

Batio

legis,

how

it aff'eote

interpreta-

86. displaced barbarian laws, influence resisted in England, attempts to introduce in England replaced how error treated by custom, 90. 744.
88.
of,

of, 494. developed, 82. general adoption of, in Europe, 85. not disturbed by barbarian invaders,

89.

it, ih.

it,

tion, 73.

Byot,

legal position

of,

346.

INDEX.
Sovereign, not independent,
also
87.
S.

435

unauthorised, pledge, 468. by, 515. 540. Sanctions, 821 821. ultimate and intermediate, 839. are ultimately the same, 841
of

Sale,power of, importance of, In pledge, 447 ; how exercised, 456.


transfer

bills of,

sqq,

relation of, to rights,


all

originally judge, 95. delegation of by, body cannot impose duties on 154 cannot have Sovereignty, conception of Austin's view 14 sqq. not capable of limitation by law, not even by express convention, 32.
judicial office 96.
rights, 155.
of, 9.

itself,

criticism

of,

31.

tendency of modern legislation as


842.
of,

to,

weakness
Savigny,

delegation
831.

practical limitations
of,

in United States, 32.

of,

36,
of,

40, 62.

843.

Specific performance, enforcement

his explanation of interpreta-

tion, 72. his explanation of error of


fact, 269.
it

Spencer, Mr. Herbert,


law and

Treatise on Possession, use of by the author, 347. Ihering's 384. analysis contract, 604, 612,616. Frauds, 653. Sea-shore, ownership Subordinate legislatures, 491. limited powers delegation 66. Secondary duties, 592. Security, the main object of law, Substitution, meaning in French preservation involves law, 330. meaning of term, 431. of law Succession, English law derived from Roman, meaning of term, 771. 770. how based on 772. 434 grew out of corporate ownership, not from best 435. statement of Roman law 437, 774 based on physical identity ancestor search given by power 447, 449. and 777 or on English law 466. 447. in India, 780. in courts of common law, 467. by groups, 786, 787Service, nature 430. in English law aniversal as Servitudes, possession 394. positive and negative, 404. moveables, 797 immoveables, 811. correspond a duty 405. early law, 813. and personal, 405, degrees of consanguinity, 817. not attached moveables, 407. Mahommedan law 786. 408. Austrian law perpetua causa 410 testamentary, 789. a condition 41 how founded on must be carea condition
his
ib.

his

criticisms of, of
of,

his principle of equal freedom, 51, 53. Status, meaning of, 168, 176. as opposed to contract, 178, 180. law of, 300. Statute of Distributions, 809. 62.

183,

of

of,

57.

of,

of,

sacrifice, ih.

origin

of,

of,

far

fictions,

sources,

of,

real,

after,

of

of sale,

heir,

of,

spiritual benefits, J'jS.

of,

of,

to

to

to forbear,

to

praedial

to

origin of,

of,

praedial,

of,
;

of, ih.

vicinity

of,

utility

of, ib.

fully exercised, 413 ; could not be transferred, 414 ; urban and rural, 415 J restricted number of, 416. personal, not restricted,!!). Sliifting use, a device to prevent alienation, 330 n.

origin as founded by Blackstone, 790. on death, in England, 794.


of,

far

fiction, ib.

Sic utere tuo, 704.

Sidgwiok, Professor, maintains


ciple of utility, 54.

prin-

obscurity English law, part taken by Church, 806, 808. Roman law, universal, consent of executor necessary 803. consent of heir necessary 802.
of
ih.
ib.,

in

796.

to,

to,

Slavery, conception of, 178 n. Smith against Hughes, 748. Social compact, theory of, 46. Source of law, what is meant by, 60.

Suits, none without wrong actually done, 852. Support, easement of, 426.

Supreme Court, powers


States, 34.

of,

in United
as evi-

legislation, primary, 61.


to

Sovereign, acquiescence

of,

equivalent

Surrounding oJroumstanoes,
dence of intention, 244.

command,

IQ.

436
T.

INDEX.
United
States, peculiar constitution 32 sqq. imprisonment for debt in, 846.
of,

Taoking, 455. Tenant, feudal, owned a jus in


b.

re aliena,

339 possession by, 384, 388 at ownership when gained


will,

Universitas juris, meaning of, 773. Uses, applied to wills, 814. not identical with fidei commissa,

by,

585-

814. devise
48.

of,

815.

Tenure, meaning
Territorial

of,

338

b.
1 26.

Usus,not like equitable ownership, 336.


Utility, basis of authority to make laws,

Law,

87.

origin of this division,


Tilings, law
296.
of,

Things, corporeal and incorporeal, moveable and immoveable, 129. real and personal, ib.
ih.

persons and procedure,


of,

284. Time immemorial, 563. Littleton with prescription, 568. of English law peculiar way of measuring, 571.
difference of,
identifies

Time, measurements

280.

the only guide to attempts to substitute other49. prin may serve as a pretext arbitrary power, 119. principle on public opinion,
legislation,

ciples for, ib.

for

of, rests

119.

basis

of prescription,

Vi clam et precario, 582. Viability, how far necessary to constitute person, 133.

Title, investigation of, 538.

Void, meaning of, 764. Void and Voidable, 274.

Title-deeds, their use as a protection

contracts, 649.
27.

not defined English law, 670. meaning of negligence 679.


-

to purchasers, 535. Tort, liability for, 598, 667. and delict are equivalent, 668. in
in,

W.
"Wager of battle, how
related to law,
of,

heterogeneous nature

negligence how opposed to intention, 680. latest meaning of negligence, 681.


of,

Wantonness, meaning

690.
n.

Ward

against Duncombe, 538 "Warranty, 694.


"Will, realisation
of,

707. distinction between, and inter blameworthiness not a criterion vivos, 791. 707,711. Wills, not known may depend on estimation of con- Leibnitz's view to Hindoos, 79T. 793 duct, 710. Wrong, no without, 852. definition 713, 715.
gift
of,

55.

of,

suit lies

of,

Transfer of contract, 660.


Treasure-trove, 487. Trespass, 697. Twelve Tables, law of retaliation
828.

in,

altered by act

Tear, commencement of, 289. of George II, Tear Books, nature of reports
Z.

289. in, 90.

U.

Undisclosed principal,
agent
of,

contract with

Zemindars, ownership
346-

of,

in Bengal,

664.

THE END.

Oxford

Printed at the Clarendon Press by

Hoeace Hakt, M.A.

You might also like