Lived Music-Multi-dimensional Musical Experience - Implications For Music Education
Lived Music-Multi-dimensional Musical Experience - Implications For Music Education
Lived Music-Multi-dimensional Musical Experience - Implications For Music Education
12, 1124-1134
DA VID
PUBLISHING
Within the field of music education, there is a need of approaching the holistic view of musical experience from different angles. Therefore, the aim of this article is to investigate the phenomenon of multi-dimensional musical experience from a life-world-phenomenological perspective and indicate its benefits to music education. The analysis is informed by Dufrennes philosophical writings regarding the phenomenology of aesthetic experience and also draws on Merleau-Ponty, Heidegger, interpreted by Benson and Ford, together with Schutz. These philosophers provide tools for understanding musical experience from a bodily, existential, and sociological perspective, and their complementary ideas about being and learning can be applied to musical experience in the first case and secondly its influences for music educational praxis. Firstly, the concept of lived music is defined through a discussion of dimensions of musical experience; the phenomenology of aesthetic experience; the use of several senses; the heard and the hear-able; apperception; and musical dwelling. Then, the sharing of experience in musical dwelling and its relevance to the concept of imagination is highlighted. I will also emphasize the importance of the view of human beings as holistic bodily subjects. Finally, the article includes a discussion regarding the implications of a life-world-phenomenological view of musical experience to music education. Keywords: Holistic musical experience, musical dwelling, music education
1. Prologue
From the diary of a singer:
Recently, I participated in a small vocal ensemble. A newly created constellation of six people, who had never met before, were about to practice together a few times and then perform Baroque music along with a well-established baroque orchestra in Stockholm. We were all musically educated with a great deal of experience of choir singing but with very little experience of performing baroque music. In the last days before we met, each one of us had striven to learn our parts by reading the music. At the first rehearsal, one of the orchestra members, the cellist, was present. We sat in a circle together with the cellist who was assigned to lead the rehearsal and began to play one of the pieces. After just a few bars he stopped the music and said: Is it OK if I say something about baroque music straight away? The important aspects are rhythm, dynamics, and diction. If we concentrate on doing this together, the timbre will be much better as well. Make the ends of the phrases short and make room for others. Listen to each other, and to me. I might build on something that you do, and vice versa. He really loved to play (in a double sense) this kind of music, and he was playing with us. Let us take just the four bars to get the right feeling. At times, he would jump up, cello in hand, and yell: Did you feel it? That is, you did it together now! During the rehearsal, he also kept stressing that perfect intonation and correct notes were less important: what was important was taking initiative, being daring, and making music together. It was important to be there, to be Cecilia Ferm Thorgersen, Ph.D., Professor in Music Education, Department of Arts, Communication, and Education, Lulea University of Technology, Sweden; main research fields: Aesthetic Communication Based on Phenomenological Philosophy, Music Teacher Education, and Assessment of Music Knowledge. Email: cefe@ltu.se.
1125
present, to listen, to make and feel the music, to learn and feel the baroque genre, to use our musical knowledge and experience in a new setting, and to come close to a shared sense of when it worked. I could have stayed there forever.
2. Introduction
When interacting in the musical world, we experience and learn to handle form, depth, timbre, pitch, linearity, harmonies, rhythm, and movement in specific genres, contexts or styles (Alerby and Ferm 2005, 177-186; Ford 2010). Aspects of music are not exclusively musical, or artistic, but connected to living in the world in general (Merleau-Ponty 1960/2000). The combination of the aspects, how they sound and how they can be experienced, constitutes music as an aesthetic object. We experience music through our senses on a structural, emotional, tensional, existential, bodily, and acoustic level at the same time (Nielsen 1997; Varky 2009, 33-48). Depending on our directedness or focus of attention, in turn influenced by a variety of forces, some dimensions are foregrounded, and others are in the background. The musical world in which we interact is inter-subjective. In musical experience, we are always intertwined with other human beings through perception, expression, or both. As bodily beings, we try to make the world meaningful and manageable. Musical experience can be seen as every-day, non-obligatory, artistic, and personal ways of being in the world (Ferm Thorgersen 2009, 167-184; Langeveld 1987, 5-10). Hence, musical experience seems to be a complicated multi-dimensional phenomenon, existing in a changing social world, in which people create meaning though interaction. It is a big challenge for music education research to shed light on and offer an understanding of all the dimensions of musical experience. Nevertheless it is necessary to accept the challenge if we want research to contribute to expanding the range of fruitful possibilities for future actions and future decisions (Bowman 2005, 153-168). If educational research in music avoids the existential, bodily, emotional, or aesthetic aspects of musical experience, it will hamper future imaginations of how music education can be organised. We need to approach the holistic view of musical experience from different angles, and this article is my contribution: the aim is to investigate the phenomenon of multi-dimensional musical experience from a life-world-phenomenological perspective and indicate its benefits to music education. In the following, I intend to examine musical experience as a multidimensional phenomenon of being through a life-world-phenomenological perspective. The analysis is informed by Dufrennes (1953/1973; 1954, 401-410) philosophical writings regarding the phenomenology of aesthetic experience and also draws on Merleau-Ponty (1960/2000; 1962; 1968; 2004), Heidegger (1987), interpreted by Benson (2003), and Ford (2010), together with Schutz (1964/1999). These philosophers provide tools for understanding musical experience as a multidimensional phenomenon. Maurice Merleau-Ponty contributes the view of human beings as bodily perceptive and expressive subjects, Martin Heidegger1 represents a more existential approach, and Schutz a more sociological one, and their complementary ideas about being and learning can be applied to musical experience in the first case and secondly its influences for music educational praxis. Firstly, I will define the concept of lived music from a life-world-phenomenological perspective by discussing the dimensions of musical experience, the phenomenology of aesthetic experience, the use of several senses, the heard and the hear-able, apperception and musical dwelling. Then, I will highlight the sharing of experience in musical dwelling and its relevance to the concept of imagination. I will also emphasise the importance of the view of human beings as holistic bodily subjects. Finally, I will discuss the implications of a life-world-phenomenological view of musical experience to music education. Throughout the article, I will
1126
relate to the introductory anecdote to exemplify different aspects of the phenomenon of musical experience.
1127
finally present in a virtual knowledge of the affective meaning which the aesthetic object evokes. For, if the affective quality that informs the object at its very core is not in some sense already known by it, the spectator would be incapable of recognizing it, and would remain indifferent or blind (or death) to the object; in fact certain works are never understood by certain publics (Dufrenne 1954, 407). Merleau-Ponty (2004) makes the same conclusions using the foreign language metaphor, and comparing it to a work of art. If a human being does not know a language very well, she cannot understand the nuances, as she has not made it her own, and does not use it as a tool to understand the world. As regards any language, it is learnt while being developed through the use of it within specific cultures, genres, and styles (Ford 2010; Merleau-Ponty 1953/1973). In perceiving the work, human beings are not concerned with the matter as such, Dufrenne argues, but attention is instead directed towards the works matter insofar as it has been transformed into particular forms constituted by colours, tunes, or sculpted stone. Humans are then no longer concerned with its matter per se, but with what Dufrenne calls the sensuous (le sensible). The sensuous is defined as what the matter becomes when perceived aesthetically, in other words, the being of a sensuous thing is realized only in perception. The aesthetic object can be defined as a coalescence of sensuous elements (Dufrenne 1953/1973, 13). According to Dufrenne, meaning possible to perceive in interaction with an art work is not transcendental, nor nonexistent; it is immanent in the sensuous, being its very organization (Dufrenne 1953/1973, 12). Merlau-Ponty (2004) states that (aesthetic) meaning is constituted where the elements approach each other in the flow of expression; in the gaps between the elements in expression, we combine the elements in conscious ways and create meaning. We perceive our own expression and compare it with our intentions and agreed aesthetic ideas through the sensuous. According to Dufrenne (1953/1973), the subject must be active to complete the aesthetic object through three stages of being, which together allow the perceiver to respond to the depth of the aesthetic objectto its expressed worldthrough feeling, as mentioned above. The three phases are presence, representation and imagination, and finally reflection and feeling. Representation and imagination are activities that demands, presence, and are in turn required to make feelings and reflection possible. All together the three phases are needed to constitute aesthetic experience. The very height of aesthetic perception is found in the feeling which reveals the expressiveness of the work (Dufrenne 1953/1973, 42). This feeling is always someones feeling, as Dufrenne maintains. It is not disembodied or impersonal, but is the expression of the depth of a human subject. The perceiver becomes present in the aesthetic object as well. Through feelings she engages herself in the expressed world. Dufrenne underlines that depth in an aesthetic feeling is to be measured in terms of what it discovers in the object. On the other hand, Dufrenne underlines, the depth of the aesthetic object concerns its ability to surprise and demand habits; to offer new relations to and views of the world. The act of aesthetic experience is in other words an act of reconciliation of the object and the subject, reciprocity of two depths (Dufrenne 1953/1973, 48); the depth of the expressed world and the depth of the beholder of this world. The sensuous is an act common to the person who feels and to what is felt (Dufrenne 1953/1973, 48). The sensitive dimension of the world constitutes its expressed world; and functions as its guiding principle (Yates 2006). Man and world belong to the larger unity of being. It is obvious in the example in the beginning of the text that the participators are present as they use representations and imagination to create a shared picture of the work, and the cellist encouraged feelings and reflections. The cellist has a specific role in the group, which includes both power and responsibility. He shares his experiences and thoughts about Baroque music, but he also creates an environment where all participants are encouraged to take part in the
1128
three phases of aesthetic experience in the process of making music together. He is open for the expressions of the participants and opens himself as well.
1129
something completely new could encourage students, and even music teachers, to dare to discover the musical world more freely. Dufrenne claims that the task of the artist is to uncover, or discover, the phenomena in the world through creating works that can be presented to potential perceivers and made possible to experience aesthetically. Merleau-Ponty talks about making the invisible visible, in our case the unheard hear-able, and that is also what is expected to happen in Langevelds (1983) artistic way of experiencing the world. The visible or the hear-able is not used here in a physiological way, as in Frederick Pios (2007, 121-152) categories of musicality, but rather as capacity to experience aesthetically, as perceiver or creator. Music experienced aesthetically is what Pio defines as the un-heard, a way of being that includes the dimensions that are not directly connected to the acoustics of music. Merleau-Ponty (2004) writes about the unspoken, the quiet parts of a language, or forms of expression, the gaps, the meaning in-betweenor the spiritual vectors of an expression. Expression and perceiving which include those vectors is what I call a multi-dimensional experience of music. Here, perception and expression are valued equally; the artist is also a perceiver, and the beholder influences the musical, and aesthetic object. The experience also takes place in specific contexts to which the subjects bring different earlier experiences, just as in the introductory example.
1130
attempt simply to copy the work of Buxtehude would not have achieved. Dwelling does not take place in a vacuum, as I mentioned in the first part of the text. It happens in an inter-subjective setting similar to the one described in the introduction. The musicians were directed towards each other and to the music, and they arrived with different experiences of music, music making, choir singing, baroque interpretation and so forth. Therefore, the sharing of experience was crucial.
1131
Music as a form of expression has already been compared to and described as language in a broad sense, and language in a broad sense is created in as well as creates a context making inter-subjective meaning production possible (Merleau-Ponty 1960/2000; Alerby and Ferm 2005; Schutz 1964/1999). As bodily subjects, active in musical activities, we share streams of consciousness through common experiences (Schutz 1964/1999). In playing music together, we share both time and space, we communicate through and use several senses, share the music, values, and spirituality. It is also in the sharing of experience, where human express and perceive music, that the combinations of elements, and thereby gaps, are made accessible which make musical meaning-making and aesthetic experience possible. The musical elements are combined by and between the individual musicians. In the meeting, or sharing, between the performers and the composers, and the listener(s) stream of consciousness even more in-betweens or gaps are constituted. The frames of the context, the earlier experiences together with the expectations and imaginations of the involved individuals limit, or make multi-dimensional experience and meaning-making possible.
1132
Maybe musical dwelling can be seen as a phenomenological body where the participants are inter-related and work together as different organs with complementary skills and actions where all actions involve every participant (Stubley 1998, 93-105). The body is closely connected to the world through the life-worlds of the participants, their experiences, and expectations. The boundaries of the body are changing depending on the directedness of the body. When the vocal ensemble was to sing together with the orchestra, the boundaries of the body had to include both groups of living subjects. New common goals and imaginations had to be settled. Later when also the audience was included in the body, the process evolved and the imagination and meaning of dwelling changed. All participants constituting the new living body had to be present, open and engaged, all participants had to use representation and be imaginative to reach a common expression, all participants were able to connect to their feelings and let reflection connect them to their living in the worldthey were offered, and offered multidimensional musical experience in the rehearsal and performing settings.
1133
such as romanticism, hip-hop, new-age, or childrens rhymes. Finally, the fourth form of experience, the personal, should inspire to activities where students get the chance to find their own musical identities. For example, students could be encouraged to reflect upon music that they have been exposed to through their lives in different settings. They could have the chance to explore what musical preferences they have and how these have developed. Additionally they should get the possibility to think about the relations to music they imagine in their future lives. I hope this article provides some openings for further visions of how music education can offer students multi-dimensional musical experiencelived music. I also hope that the message of the text in one way or another will reach teachers, school-leaders, and people who write policy documents and inspire them to cross boundaries when it comes to creating spaces for multi-style musical experiences in educational institutions at all levels, such as ordinary schools, municipal culture schools, NGOs and higher education.
Note
1. For a more thorough discussion of Heideggers thoughts about being and art, based on his later works, see Thorgersen and Schwieler (2013).
Works Cited
Adams, Harry. Merleau-Ponty and the Advent of Meaning: From Consummat Reciprocity to Ambiguous Reversibility. Continental Philosophy Review 34.2 (2001): 203-24. Alerby, Eva, and Cecilia Ferm Thorgersen. Learning MusicEmbodied Experience in the Life World. Philosophy of Music Education Review 13.2 (2005): 177-86. Benson, Bruce Ellis. The Improvisation of Musical Dialologue. Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 2003. Bowman, Wayne. The Limits and Grounds of Musical Praxialism. Praxial Music Education: Reflections and Dialogues. Ed. David Elliott. Oxford: Oxford UP, 2005. ---. More Inquiring Minds, More Cogent Questions, More Provisional Answers: The Need to Theorize Music Educationand Its Research. Music Education Research 7.2 (July 2005): 153-68. Bowman, Wayne, and Kimberly Powell. The Body in the State of Music. International Handbook of Research in Arts Education. Ed. Laura Bresler. Dordrecht: Springer, 2007. Dufrenne, Michel. The Phenomenology of Aesthetic Experience. Evanston: Northwestern UP, 1953/1973. ---. Intentionality and Aesthetics. Man and World 11.3-4 (1954): 401-10. Elam, Katarina. Vardagsestetik, Sinneserfarenhet Och Den Kulturella Kroppen (Everyday Aesthetics, Sensible Experience, and the Cultural Body). Paper Presented at ACSIS National Research Conference for Culture Studies, Norrkping. June 13th-15th, 2005. Ferm Thorgersen, Cecilia. msesidig Nyfikenhet Och RespektFenomenologisk Didaktik Som Utgangspunkt Fr Musikundervisning i Grundskolans Lgre Aldrar (Mutual Curiosity and RespectPhenomenological Didaktik as a Starting-Point for Music Education in Primary Schools). Nordic Research in Music Education 11 (2009): 167-84. ---. Openness and AwarenessRoles and Demands for Music Teachers. Music Education Research 8.2 (2006): 237-50. ---. Quality Holistic Learning in Musikdidaktik From a Student PerspectiveWhere, When and How Does it Occur? Visions of Research in Music Education 15 (2010): 35. Ferm Thorgersen, Cecilia, and Elias Schwieler. Translating the Impossible. Language, Learning and Art. In press. 2013. Ferm Thorgersen, Cecilia, and Ketil Andr Thorgersen. Impetus, Imagination and Shared Experience in Aesthetic Communication. Paper Presented at Workshop at INPE. 11, Kyoto, Japan. Aug. 8th-12th, 2008. Ford, Charles. Musical Presence: Towards a New Philosophy of Music. Contemporary Aesthetics 8. 2010. <http://www. contempaesthetics.org/newvolume/pages/journal.php>
1134
Giorgi, Amedeo. A Phenomenological Perspective on Some Phenomenographic Results of Learning. Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 30.2 (Fall 1999): 68-96. Heidegger, Martin. Konstverkets Ursprung (The Origin of the Work of Art). Gteborg: Daidalos, 1987. Langeveld, Martin. Reflections on Phenomenology and Pedagogy. Phenomenology and Pedagogy 1.1 (1983): 5-10. Manen, Max van. Researching Lived Experience. Ontario: U of Western Ontario P, 1997. Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. yet Og Anden (The Eye and the Spirit). Oslo: Pax forlag, 1960/2000. ---. Phenomenology of Perception. London: Routledge, 1962. ---. The Visible and the Invisible. Evanstown: Northwestern UP, 1968. ---. Lovtal Till Filosofin. Esser i Urval (Eulogy to philosophy. Chosen essays). Stockholm: Brutus stlings frlag, 2004. Nielsen, Frede Viggo. Almen Musikdidaktik (General Musikdidaktik). Copenhagen: Akademisk forlag, 1997. Pio, Frederic. Om Det Uhrte. Bidrag Till Musikalitetsdannelsens Faenomaenologi (About the Non-Heard. A Contribution to the Phenomenology of Music Education). Nordic Research in Music Education 9 (2007): 121-52. Schtz, Alfred. Den Sociala Vrldens Fenomenologi (Phenomenology of the Social world). Gteborg: Daidalos, 1964/1999. Stubley, Ellinor. Being in the Body, Being in the Sound: A Tale of Modulating Identities and Lost Potential. Journal of Aesthetic Education 32.4 (1998): 93-105. Varky, ivind. The Role of Music in Music Education Research. Nordic Research in Music Education 11 (2009): 33-48. Yates, Christopher. A Phenomenological Aesthetics of Cinematic Worlds. Contemporary Aestheics. 2006. Yorks, Lyle, and Elizabeth Kasl. Toward a Theory and Practice for Whole-Person Learning: Reconceptualizing Experience and the Role of Affect. Adult Education Quarterly 53.3 (2002): 176-92.