1) The document discusses the concept of "interpassivity" where people delegate or outsource their own enjoyment and feelings to other people or devices rather than experiencing them directly.
2) It provides examples like canned laughter in sitcoms laughing on behalf of viewers, and the Greek chorus experiencing emotions for audience members. This shows how intimate feelings can have an "objective" external existence.
3) The concept of interpassivity suggests there are artworks that already include their own viewing and reception, relieving audiences of any necessary activity or passivity. Viewers may prefer to be replaced than experience their own emotions.
1) The document discusses the concept of "interpassivity" where people delegate or outsource their own enjoyment and feelings to other people or devices rather than experiencing them directly.
2) It provides examples like canned laughter in sitcoms laughing on behalf of viewers, and the Greek chorus experiencing emotions for audience members. This shows how intimate feelings can have an "objective" external existence.
3) The concept of interpassivity suggests there are artworks that already include their own viewing and reception, relieving audiences of any necessary activity or passivity. Viewers may prefer to be replaced than experience their own emotions.
Original Description:
Re-published, with permission, from Verso Books by Critical-Theory.com
1) The document discusses the concept of "interpassivity" where people delegate or outsource their own enjoyment and feelings to other people or devices rather than experiencing them directly.
2) It provides examples like canned laughter in sitcoms laughing on behalf of viewers, and the Greek chorus experiencing emotions for audience members. This shows how intimate feelings can have an "objective" external existence.
3) The concept of interpassivity suggests there are artworks that already include their own viewing and reception, relieving audiences of any necessary activity or passivity. Viewers may prefer to be replaced than experience their own emotions.
1) The document discusses the concept of "interpassivity" where people delegate or outsource their own enjoyment and feelings to other people or devices rather than experiencing them directly.
2) It provides examples like canned laughter in sitcoms laughing on behalf of viewers, and the Greek chorus experiencing emotions for audience members. This shows how intimate feelings can have an "objective" external existence.
3) The concept of interpassivity suggests there are artworks that already include their own viewing and reception, relieving audiences of any necessary activity or passivity. Viewers may prefer to be replaced than experience their own emotions.
and the Objective Illusion Te problem of illusions without owners becomes apparent through interpassivity a diferent, equally paradoxical issue. When dealing with people who display the tendency to delegate their own enjoyment to other people or to an apparatus, we are here unsuspectingly confronted with the fact that people enact illusions dramatically, with great precision, without noticing in the slightest that they are doing so. It is obvious that they know better, but they behave contrary to this knowledge in compliance with illusions of which they are not even aware. Tey produce imaginations without any image. Te method that interpassive subjects employ in their fight from enjoyment thereby leads us to the trail of imaginations without owners. In what follows, my aim is to reconstruct as succinctly as possible the opening that leads from the method of interpassivity to illusions without subjects, without delving into the complex and intricate questions posed by the motives for the interpassive subjects behaviour. 1 I therefore refrain from lending plausibility to all of the individual theses that further examples might possibly provide, and, at every tenet of the argument, focus only on the one key example leading directly to the subsequent theoretical assump- tion. Tis reconstruction appears useful not only because all cases of interpassivity are examples of illusions without owners, but also because the concept of interpassivity contains a useful analytical tool that can be applied in subsequent chapters with reference to other phenomena. How to Amuse Oneself Objectively At the beginning of the 1990s, when the art world was dominated by a seemingly omnipresent discourse about interactivity, Slavoj iek made an extremely astute comment that was a signifcant break from the discourse. He maintained that television sitcoms using canned 1 See also the many contributions concerned with this problem in Pfaller, Interpassivitt. 9781781681756 On the Pleasure Principle in Culture (034I) final pass.indd 15 15/04/2014 08:54:55 16 on the pleasure principle in culture laughter are actually laughing at their own jokes and funny situations on behalf of the viewers. According to iek, viewers can be perfectly amused without having to follow the content of the sitcoms, and even without having to laugh: Why this laughter? Te frst possible answer that it serves to remind us when to laugh is interesting enough, because it simply implies that laughter is a matter of duty and not of some spontaneous feeling; but this answer is not suf cient because we do not usually laugh. Te only correct answer would be that the Other embodied in the television set is relieving us even of our duty to laugh is laughing instead of us. So even if, tired from a hard days stupid work, all evening we did nothing but gaze drowsily into the television screen, we can say aferwards that, objectively, through the medium of the other, we had a really good time. 2 iek here illustrates a Lacanian thesis about the role of the chorus in Greek tragedy. In a passage that has rarely been treated by commenta- tors, Lacan developed a unique perspective: Next then in a tragedy, there is a Chorus. And what is a Chorus? You will be told that its you yourselves. Or perhaps that it isnt you. But thats not the point. Means are involved here, emotional means. In my view, the Chorus is people who are moved. Terefore, look closely before telling yourself that emotions are engaged in this purifcation. Tey are engaged, along with others, when at the end they have to be pacifed by some artifce or other. But that doesnt mean to say that they are directly engaged . . . Your emotions are taken charge of by the healthy order displayed on the stage. Te Chorus takes care of them. Te emotional commentary is done for you . . . Terefore, you dont have to worry; even if you dont feel anything, the Chorus will feel in your stead. Why afer all can one not imagine that the efect on you may be achieved, at least a small dose of it, even if you didnt tremble that much? To be honest, Im not sure if the spectator ever trembles that much. 3 2 Slavoj iek, Te Sublime Object of Ideology (London/New York: Verso, 1989), p. 35. 3 Jacques Lacan, Te Ethics of Psychoanalysis 19591960, Seminar VII (New York: W.W. Norton & Co., 1992), p. 252. 9781781681756 On the Pleasure Principle in Culture (034I) final pass.indd 16 15/04/2014 08:54:55 interpassivity 17 From these seemingly paradoxical examples canned laughter and the Greek chorus (in Lacans interpretation) iek drew the conclu- sion that our supposedly most intimate feelings can be transferred or delegated to others. Our feelings and convictions are therefore not internal, but rather can lead an external, objective existence: a televi- sion sitcom can laugh for me; weepers can mourn in my place; a Tibetan prayer wheel can pray for me; 4 and a mythical being, such as the renowned ordinary man in the street, can take my place and be convinced of things that I cannot take seriously. 5 Te respective attitude or conviction is realized through these external agents. As iek states, the wheel itself is praying for me, instead of me or, more precisely, I myself am praying through the medium of the wheel. Te beauty of it is that in my psychological interior I can think about whatever I want, I can yield to the most dirty and obscene fantasies, and it does not matter because to use a good old Stalinist expression what- ever I am thinking, objectively I am praying. 6 Interpassivity: Do-It-All Artworks that Even Include Their Own Reception ieks contemplations on canned laughter and the Greek chorus make it possible to derive another conclusion relevant for art theory: apparently, there are artworks that already contain their own viewing and reception. And there are viewers who want it that way. It seems that they would prefer to be replaced than to feel their own laughter, their own fear, or their own sympathy. Tese are thus artworks and viewers who present us with exactly the opposite of what the theory of interactivity so persistently preaches. Whereas interactivity entails shifing a part of the artistic production (activity) from the artwork to the viewer, here the opposite occurs: the viewing (passivity) is shifed from the viewer to the artwork. I have decided to call this type of displacement interpassivity. Interactive art attempts to activate its viewers: in interactive art, viewers are not only required to view the artwork, but also to 4 For more on these examples, see iek, Sublime Object of Ideology, pp. 335. 5 See iek, Die Substitution, p. 14. 6 iek, Sublime Object of Ideology, p. 34. 9781781681756 On the Pleasure Principle in Culture (034I) final pass.indd 17 15/04/2014 08:54:55 18 on the pleasure principle in culture participate in its production. For interpassive artworks, however, the opposite seems to be the case: viewers are not required to participate; moreover, they are not even required to view. Te work is there, completely fnished not only completely produced, but completely consumed as well. Contained within such works is not simply the necessary activity, but also the requisite passivity. Interpassive art absolves viewers of any necessary activity whatsoever, and also of their passivity. Tey can now be even more passive than passive. Deprived even of their passivity, they end up in the uncanny hereafer of their couch-potato existence. From Arts Self-Viewing to Delegated Enjoyment in General Te discovery that the sitcoms canned laughter and the Greek trage- dys chorus present examples of self-viewing artworks, and can therefore be understood as cases of interpassivity, allows us to draw a further conclusion. Here, what is delegated is the reception of art including the enjoyment of art. Interpassivity comprises delegated enjoyment. Not only can laughing at a sitcom be lef to others, but also the act of watching television: rather than watching our favourite shows, we can record them and never watch the recording. It is as though the recorder has already watched for us. Tis opens up an entire series of everyday interpassive phenomena: Is it mere coinci- dence that travellers immediately hold a camera up to their eyes for protection when looking at a monument? Might it even be possible to say that they go so far as to place their friends, to whom they will later show the snapshots of their vacation, between themselves and the pictures that the camera takes? Isnt the utterly common statement How interesting! a downright negation in the Freudian sense? Doesnt it really mean: Tat doesnt interest me in the slightest! And isnt there an entire genre of interesting books (with titles such as Te Etruscans) that show up in shops just before Christmas: books that no one ever reads, but everyone gets as gifs? And in electronic media, isnt there a steady stream of new forms of actors and avatars constantly turning up in place of people for example, in chat rooms, on Facebook, Twitter, and other second lives? 7 7 See Mathias Fuchs, Disembodied Online in Pfaller, Interpassivitt, pp. 338. 9781781681756 On the Pleasure Principle in Culture (034I) final pass.indd 18 15/04/2014 08:54:55 interpassivity 19 In addition to the artistic aspect of the matter delegated view- ing there is also a more general, economic aspect namely, delegated consumption. Interpassivity can be understood as every movement that shifs the consumption of a product from the consumer to a dele- gated consumption agency. Tis type of consumption agency can be either already contained in the product (such as the canned laughter in the sitcom) or added to the product (such as a recording device in a television set). Te role of this agency is embodied by persons, machines, animals, plants, and so on (which then function as inter- passive media). Consumers who tend towards this delegation of their pleasure are identifed as interpassive subjects. Te theory of interactivity has assumed a highly questionable conceptual classifcation, with artistic production and activity on the one hand, and art reception and passivity on the other. Yet, from the more general, economic perspective, it is now possible to speak on frmer ground of activity and passivity: production is activity; consumption, however, is passivity. Whether a process is active or passive depends on whether something consumable is produced or consumed. If we regard interpassivity as delegated enjoyment, then it is necessary to change the questions that are posed along ieks path of investigation the inquiry into the possibility of delegating convic- tions, feelings, and so on. Tis change also enables a consideration of ieks examples from a new perspective: the delegation of convic- tions and feelings creates special cases of the general principle of delegated enjoyment that we have now been able to identify. Te fact that Tibetan belief can be delegated to a prayer wheel, for example, is just as much an example of delegated or substituted consumption as the delegation of Christian belief to a burning candle representing a Catholic. Te so-called comforts of religion are the consumable elements. Worshippers consume them on a regular basis, thus the producers of religion must constantly produce them. Te producers of Christian belief, for example, also conceive of this belief as just such a consumer item, and charge for its consumption in the form of a church tax or tithes. In the interpassive case, the prayer wheel and the candle consume the commodity of religion in place of the worshippers. What we are dealing with here is not merely substituted belief, feeling or thought, but, rather, substituted consumption or enjoyment. 9781781681756 On the Pleasure Principle in Culture (034I) final pass.indd 19 15/04/2014 08:54:55 20 on the pleasure principle in culture Whereas ieks thesis states: feelings and convictions can exist externally, our double thesis states: 1. Tere are artworks that view themselves; and 2. there are consumers who want to be replaced by something that consumes in their place. Fortunately, there is strong support in the art world for these apparently utterly paradoxical considerations. Not only in philosophy, but also in art, people have begun to discover the varieties of delegated consumption. A series of contemporary artistic works thematize common interpassive phenomena: artists engaged in so-called service art, for example, ofer to take the viewers place at a rendezvous, or trash their cars, or corre- spond with their acquaintances. 8
Numerous artworks also include in their form the possibility of whether to avoid or engage with interpassive reception. Jenny Holz- ers text installations, for example, seem to repeat the methods of the Tibetan prayer wheel. Holzers aesthetic principle comprises creating such a strong presence for texts in a public space that it has become seemingly unnecessary to read them. Te texts themselves, their truisms, also seem to correspond with that principle they appear to be no ones truths, meant for no one in particular. For an audience that has grown weary of reading, they bring a pleasant moment of relief. Interpassivity thus builds a formal principle of contemporary art. It is the cause of its specifc aesthetic efects. From this perspective, it becomes possible to gain a general understanding of the massive emergence of texts within the fne arts in recent decades. Why are theoretical texts presented on the walls of exhibitions, in videos, installations or performances, and not in books? 9 Do the fne arts, with their love of theory, serve as the last aid for a culture that as Marshall McLuhan concluded has reached the fnal stages of its reading ability? (Similar to the way in which the prayer wheel stood at the beginning stages of literacy?) 8 See the artworks by Ruth Kaaserer, Astrid Benzer, Ronald Eckelt, Martin Kerschbaumsteiner, and San Keller; cf. for example, Kunstaktion Arbeit Teil1 ausgraben , documentary of an artistic action in 1998, posted on YouTube by interpassiv on Jan. 22, 2009, and Kunstaktion Arbeit Teil2 zuschuetten , documentary of an artistic action in 1998, posted on YouTube by interpassiv on Jan. 22, 2009; see also Pfaller, Interpassivitt, pp. 534. 9 See also Arthur C. Danto, Te Philosophical Disenfranchisement of Art (New York: Columbia University Press, 1986), pp. ixf. 9781781681756 On the Pleasure Principle in Culture (034I) final pass.indd 20 15/04/2014 08:54:55 interpassivity 21 Te steady growth in the ranks of art curators also seems to be an example of interpassivity. Dont they in fact view the curated art, replacing traditional viewers who have recently become scarce (for example, because they have been re-educated by the interactive instal- lations to become active artists)? And the numerous video installations in major exhibitions, whose length regularly surpasses (many times over) the time spent by even the most patient viewers arent they also self-viewing apparatuses, which in an interpassive way mediate to exhibition visitors the feeling of having seen something (and to non-visitors, the feeling of not having to see)? 10 Isnt there a peculiar conformity here, such that the viewers (who actually see only very little) perceive the situation that there is a lot to see, in such a way that it seems as though they have seen a lot? The Flight from Pleasure Te next question, then, is the following: Is it possible that interpassive subjects dont want their enjoyment? Tere is evidence for this assump- tion. ieks text, for example, reveals a mischievous pleasure derived from escaping, via canned laughter, the experience of being amused by television comedy. 11 Te remark by Klaus Heinrich that art collectors would most like to banish their collection to a safe, where they dont have to look at it also points in this direction. 12 And doesnt the popu- larity of interactive art prove that the art viewer only wants to create art, but does not want to view any or at least not anyone elses? An initial sof-core explanation of interpassivity hereby proves insuf cient: the delegation of enjoyment is applied not only in 10 See also Wolfgang Kemp, Echtmensch im Kosmodrom, in Die Zeit, 31 May 2000, p. 46. 11 Te Lacanian study of interpassivity repeatedly asks what happens to jouissance enjoyment, in Lacans sense in cases of represented pleasure. ieks mischievous pleasure at the success of his delegated laughter seems to ofer an answer to this question: the interpassive subjects joy at escaping enjoyment is jouissance. And is the expression mischievous pleasure not a precise counterpart to the likewise slightly devious connotations of the French term jouissance? See also Bruce Fink, A Clinical Introduction to Lacanian Psychoanalysis: Teory and Technique (Cambridge, MA/ London: Harvard University Press, 1997), p. 9: Te term jouissance nicely captures the notion of getting of by any means necessary, however clean or dirty. 12 See Klaus Heinrich, anfangen mit freud (Basel/Frankfurt am Main: Stroemfeld [Roter Stern], 1997), p. 55. 9781781681756 On the Pleasure Principle in Culture (034I) final pass.indd 21 15/04/2014 08:54:55 22 on the pleasure principle in culture situations where direct and personal enjoyment is impossible. Inter- passivity is not just a method of extended, indirect consumption that increases ones (necessarily limited) direct consumerist capaci- ties. Instead, we have to tackle a hard-core explanation straight on: interpassive subjects are actually feeing from their enjoyment. Tey even avoid it in those situations where personally experiencing it would be easy. Owners of recording devices, for example, watch less television once they have the recorder than they did when they owned only the television set. 13 And travellers, who are certainly capable of viewing scenic attractions themselves, hold a camera to their eyes as if by refex. Tis poses two fundamental questions. First, the reason for inter- passivity: Why dont people want to enjoy? And why do they choose the most complicated form of substitution instead of just leaving things be? Why are they so intent on someone else taking over the enjoyment that they dont want? Why do they undertake measures that work simultaneously for and against enjoyment? And second, how does this delegation work? What method do interpassive subjects use? What gives the represented subjects the feeling (or, more precisely, the ofen unconscious certainty) of being represented? How is it possible that they treat the televisions mechan- ical laughter as equivalent to their own laughter? What is the connection between that which is replaced and its replacement or delegate? Why dont we perceive the laughter of others as simply their laughter? And why is ones own not-laughing in no way understood as not-laughing, but instead as an efect of the successful delegation of laughter? It appears that these two fundamental issues are interde- pendent. Te issue of methods seems to provide a key for understanding the reasons for interpassivity. The Objective Illusion In order to track down the riddle of why interpassive people do not want their own enjoyment, frst we will investigate the methods they use for representation: What constitutes the interpassive subjects certainty that they are represented by something or someone else? In ieks examples the Tibetan prayer wheel, canned laughter, the 13 See also iek, Die Substitution, p. 21. 9781781681756 On the Pleasure Principle in Culture (034I) final pass.indd 22 15/04/2014 08:54:55 interpassivity 23 Greek chorus, mourners, and so on it soon becomes clear that one obvious answer can be eliminated: the certainty of delegation in no way has to do with a subjective illusion held by the person who delegates. Both the efect and that way it is achieved are usually not conscious acts on the part of the actors. As a rule, actors dont believe in the possibility of delegation, and they are not aware or, if so, only in a distorted way of the relief efect achieved through delegation. When Tibetan prayer-wheel users imagine something, then it is the opposite: namely, not being perfectly represented by the rotating prayer wheel. Teir illusion to remain with ieks example is that they were merely clinging to their obscene fantasies rather than pray- ing. In truth, however, as iek remarks, they have prayed objectively. Excessive video-recorder users, too, deceive themselves by falling back on general explanations about the actual benefts they gain from the recording. Tey really believe that they will watch the programmes at a later date, and dont even notice that they have already objectively seen them (and have already experienced complete relief at having done so). Interpassive subjects neither imagine the possibility of having a vicarious experience of their enjoyment, nor entertain the illusion of the success of their actions through a delegate even when such success is actually present. Te illusion is not theirs; instead, the interpassive subjects seem to not get it in a double sense: in full knowledge of the alleged unsuitability of an interpassive process, the actors nonetheless carry it out, and then actually obtain success- ful results from it yet once again conceal these results from themselves. Tus, it is not the interpassive subjects who imagine the possibil- ity of having a delegate they ofen dont even think of it. Tis representation is, instead, something that can only be described by the paradoxical-seeming concept of an objective illusion. Te illusion is objective for two reasons: (1) someone other than the practising actor has to believe in this illusion. Teory must therefore reconstruct this illusion and prove its efectiveness in the completed action against the ignorance and even amazed objection of the actors; and (2) this illusion of realized substitution for example, of a person by a record- ing device is not entirely untrue. In fact, video afcionados can realize a nearly television-free life on the basis of their recording 9781781681756 On the Pleasure Principle in Culture (034I) final pass.indd 23 15/04/2014 08:54:55 24 on the pleasure principle in culture activities. Even when they maintain the illusion of watching all of the recordings someday, this can easily be revealed as a subjective illu- sion. Ultimately, the recorder is permanently busy; the interpassive subjects, who in some cases have dedicated up to four machines per night to recording, never have a free machine available to watch what they have recorded. If they did watch, then they would be in danger of missing something in the current television schedule. We therefore have a phenomenon similar to Spinozas realization that we love something more when we hated it before. However, we cant intentionally increase our love by frst hating something, because then we would never be able to emerge from our hatred. 14 Te video afcionados seem to increase their love of television by having pre- recorded it. But now they never emerge from the recording process. For both of these reasons because of the non-subjective bearer of an illusion and the truth-content of that illusion it seems appropriate to speak of an objective illusion. From Objective Laughing to Television in Effigy Who, then, is the subject of this objectivity? Who believes in what the actors themselves dont even think about and, if confronted with, would consider senseless? A frst, obvious answer equates the interpassive subjects and their actions with the audience at hand. If, for example, I pay mourners to weep at a memorial ceremony, which I also attend, then the other participants in the ceremony can view this as my wailing. My own (albeit non-wailing) presence at the wail- ing makes this wailing my own. In a similar situation, when person A is present while person B makes a statement and person A accepts it without protest, person A is also considered by the others present as party to the opinion expressed by person B. In this case, the audience at hand would be the subject that is able to establish the objectivity of my interpassive wailing, my praying with the help of a prayer wheel, or my amusement attained with the aid of canned laughter. However, the example of the video recorder raises some pertinent issues related to this initial answer. Television viewers are apparently 14 See Benedictus de Spinoza, Ethics III, in On the Improvement of the Understanding, Te Ethics, Correspondence (New York: Dover Publications, 1955), pp. 15960. 9781781681756 On the Pleasure Principle in Culture (034I) final pass.indd 24 15/04/2014 08:54:55
HENRY BERGSON Premium Collection: Laughter, Time and Free Will, Creative Evolution, Dreams & Meaning of the War & Dreams (From the Renowned Nobel Prize Winning Author & Philosopher)