Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

Between Zero and One: On The Unknown Knowns: Professor Simon Biggs, Edinburgh College of Art, September 2010

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 8

Between zero and one: on the unknown knowns

Professor Simon Biggs, Edinburgh College of Art, September 2010




"There are known knowns. These are things we know that we know. There are
known unknowns. That is to say, there are things that we now know we don!t
know. But there are also unknown unknowns. These are things we do not know
we don!t know."
Donald Rumsfeld

This infamous comment of February 12, 2002, by US Secretary of State for Defence
Donald Rumsfeld, concerning the lack of evidence linking Iraq's government to the
supply of terrorist groups with weapons of mass destruction, was widely ridiculed at
the time and, since 2002, has been referenced widely as evidence of the lunacy,
paranoia and sheer stupidity of the Bush era executive. Amongst many other
"accolades" it received the Plain English Campaign's 2003 Foot in Mouth Award.
Slavoj Zizek felt subsequently compelled to respond to Rumsfeld's apparently bizarre
logic. In his riposte in The Guardian, Zizek suggested that Rumsfeld had overlooked
something;

"What he forgot to add was the crucial fourth term: the "unknown knowns",
things we don't know that we know - which is precisely the Freudian
unconscious. If Rumsfeld thought that the main dangers in the confrontation
with Iraq were the "unknown unknowns", the threats from Saddam we did not
even suspect, the Abu Ghraib scandal shows where the main dangers actually
are in the "unknown knowns", the disavowed beliefs, suppositions and obscene
practices we pretend not to know about, even though they form the background
of our public values. To unearth these "unknown knowns" is the task of an
intellectual." (Zizek 2005)

Putting aside Zizek's particular, if probably reasonable, interpretation of Rumsfeld's
statement as evidence of a paranoid Freudian subconscious at work within the US
defence system, whilst accepting his assertion that the territory of the "unknown
known" is an appropriate frontier for intellectual inquiry, Rumsfeld's knowledge matrix
could be regarded as evidence of an, admittedly inadvertent, subtle appreciation of
epistemology. The implication of this matrix is that knowledge can exist in a variable
and uncertain state and yet still function as useable and applicable knowledge upon
which action can be based.

As Zizek has observed, one thing that is evident in Rumsfeld's Boolean matrix is that
one possible form of (un)knowing is absent from its logical array, the "unknown
knowns" - things we don't know that we know. This form of knowing is often referred
to as tacit and has become a popular subject of inquiry in the arts and other practice
based activities where knowledge of techniques, methods and relationships are often
accepted a priori, as being embedded in the skill-sets and processes of certain
practices learned through the careful rehearsal and subsequent adjustment of
acquired ability.

David Pye (1968) distinguishes between two modes of workmanship which might be
employed to evidence how tacit knowledge can evolve and be applied. Pye identifies
the "workmanship of risk" and the "workmanship of certainty". Quoting Elizabeth
Hallam and Tim Ingold (2007) on Pye, "In the workmanship of risk the quality of the
outcome depends at every moment on the exercise of care, judgment and dexterity.
The practitioner has continually to make fine adjustments to keep on course, in
response to the sensitive monitoring of the conditions of the task as it unfolds". By
contrast the workmanship of certainty "proceeds by the way of a pre-planned series
of operations, each of which is mechanically constrained to the extent that the result
is predetermined and outside the operative's control". However, Hallam and Ingold
problematise this duality, noting earlier in the same text that "life is unscriptable" and
"cannot be codified", for the world is not a fixed but fluid phenomenon. Thus, in
practice, the workmanship of certainty is never fully realised as no system or set of
phenomena is so predetermined and known that we can complete a task in respect
of it whilst on auto-pilot. All of our activities are, to some degree, creative and engage
the real-time evaluative processes inherent to tacit knowledge. In this sense tacit
knowledge and the creative impulse are not the preserve of those engaged in the
creative arts but are aspects of life, both extraordinary and quotidian.

When creative practitioners find themselves working within an academic knowledge
economy of qualified and quantified knowledge they are often required to submit to
the same measures of rigor and transparency as their colleagues in more
conventional academic subjects. Key in this is the principle that knowledge is of most
value when it has been rendered open and transparent to critical evaluation by
others. In order to achieve this it is required that knowledge be inscribed in a manner
that ensures the means by which it was arrived at is qualifiable and quantifiable by
others. The larger part of contemporary academic research infrastructure is
dedicated to this evaluative process.

However, as some have observed, perhaps most acutely Stephen Scrivener (at a
conference convened here at Hertfordshire in 2002), the requirements of academia
and those of the creative arts are not so readily reconcilable. Scrivener asks why
"has knowledge become such a hot topic? At least part of the answer can be found in
the very idea of research, which is generally understood as an original investigation
undertaken in order to gain knowledge and understanding" (Scrivener 2002). As
Scrivener points out, if the creative arts are to function within an academic
epistemology then art, when undertaken as research, "must contribute to
knowledge". However, is the primary objective of creative practice to achieve a
contribution to knowledge? Conventionally the answer to this question would be in
the negative. Arts practitioners have not been historically required to develop or
propose new knowledge. The creative practitioner's role has generally been quite
distinct to this.

However, creative practitioners work within and do develop their own knowledge
frameworks and to engage with the outcome of a creative process, whether as author
or reader, requires knowledge about the subject and its context as well as the artifact
and the relevant discourses of the culture the artifact is produced within. Thus, whilst
it might be the case that creative practice rarely engages the propositional character
of scientific knowledge production it nevertheless does depend upon, participate in
and represent a form of highly contextualised and shared critical knowledge.

On the other hand, as observed above, even the most rigorous of pursuits of
knowledge will involve a degree of tacit knowledge and intuition in its realisation.
Scientists, if they are to fulfill one of the key criteria of their activities, that of
originality, and whilst they might undertake their activities with extreme diligence to
documentation and critical reflection, would seem to need to engage the
"workmanship of risk". By definition they must go beyond the limits of their practice
and knowledge if they are to satisfy such a key objective and they can only do so
when they rely on processes of judgment and mental or technical dexterity that are
born of the long exercise of a set of skills such that they have become second nature.
In this sense the scientist, like the artisan, exercises tacit knowledge, almost
unconsciously, operating beyond the evaluative processes of scientific rigor. It is in
this condition that the eureka moment can unexpectedly emerge. Indeed, science
incorporates the unpredictable and improvisory into its fundamental methods, valuing
the unpredictable negative outcome as equal to the positive affirmation of a
hypothesis whilst appreciating that such an unpredictable outcome counters the
epistemologically foundational processes of conjecture and refutation. Artists and
scientists can thus be considered to share an interest in something more
fundamental than a particular form or method of knowing; that is, wonder. In this
context the artist Paul Klee's observation (Klee 1961) that artists and scientists often
start from the same source and arrive at the same destination, but do so via different
means, has particular resonance.

Charles Peirce argued that artists can arrive at choices through a hunch, a form of
reasoning he termed abductive (Peirce 1958). Within this epistemological model
elements of knowledge might be considered of uncertain status but nevertheless able
to be reasonably employed on the basis of an intuitive sense that something might be
so. The argument here is that what is the case for creative practitioners, in the
exercise of their pursuit of insight and affinity (a kind of knowing), is also the case for
those working within those domains concerned with the rigorous pursuit of
knowledge.

Peirce identified three methods of reasoning: deduction, induction and abduction. He
regarded all three as integral to the scientific method. Peirce suggested that scientific
method starts with abduction, an hypothesis where a conjecture is postulated,
seeking to explain a phenomenon. The method then proceeds to deduction where,
through a series of inferences, conclusions can be drawn from the provisional
hypothesis and further conclusions reached about other phenomena that must be so
if the hypothesis is true. Finally, the method proceeds to the stage of induction,
where experiments are carried out to test the provisional hypothesis by ascertaining
whether the deduced results do or do not obtain. Peirce did not regard this as a
strictly linear process as he proposed various feedback loops between such methods
so that various entry and exit points at the various stages could be employed, thus
allowing for a non-linear apprehension of knowledge creation. In this model
knowledge is often in a contingent and uncertain state but nevertheless the
methodological framework can be pursued and outcomes arrived at. Thus, as we
have already observed at the outset of this text, knowledge can exist in a variable
and uncertain state and yet still function as useable and applicable knowledge upon
which action can be based

Another example of reasoning that is less than black and white in its methods is
found in computing theory. The notion of fuzzy logic, derived from fuzzy set theory
(Zadeh 1965), has gained popularity in data analysis applications designed for
dealing with complex real-world data-sets. This is a method of algorithmically
modeling decision making processes where much of the data required to make a
choice is in an unknown state, neither a zero nor a one but something in-between.

Lofti Zadeh (1973) has argued that "the conventional quantitative techniques of
system analysis are intrinsically unsuited for dealing with humanistic systems or, for
that matter, any system whose complexity is comparable to that of humanistic
systems". He has postulated that "as the complexity of a system increases, our ability
to make precise and yet significant statements about its behavior diminishes until a
threshold is reached beyond which precision and significance ... become almost
mutually exclusive characteristics". He has suggested an approach to understanding
human thinking as a process not founded on the key elements of numbers but "labels
of fuzzy sets ... classes of objects in which the transition from membership to non-
membership is gradual rather than abrupt". Zadeh has proposed that human
reasoning is not binary, or even multi-valued, but a "logic of fuzzy truths, fuzzy
connectives, and fuzzy rules of inference". Whilst Zadeh's language is quite distinct
there are uncanny echoes of Peirce's theories at play in an approach to computing
that has become very influential in the areas of artificial intelligence and specifically in
language and voice recognition systems. It is therefore perhaps not surprising that
both Pierce, with his work on semiosis, and Zadeh, who proposes a linguistically
rather than numerically based system of logic, both can be seen to regard language
as key to understanding how knowledge is made and valued as a human activity.

It is possible, indeed likely given the large class of potential signs, that what is the
case for language is also the case for images. The image is a powerful means for
determining and describing classes of things. The image can be simultaneously
concise and general, precise but vague, in its status. This is perhaps the poetic
property of all signs, regardless of the sign system to which they belong; the
polyvalence of the sign exhibiting the fuzzy and uncertain characteristics of things
that both Peirce and Zadeh explore and thus able to sustain multiple states and sets
of relations with other things. This would seem to be the natural territory of the artist
and poet and thus we can suggest that if what Zadeh proposes is a system of
knowledge then what creative practitioners routinely do, as they play with the
indeterminate multilayered and dimensioned relations in the elements of their
creative work, is a form of knowledge creation as well, not only in the sense of
exercising a tacit knowledge associated with their skill-set, as observed in the
observations of Pye, but through the essaying of a knowledge-representation which
evidences Pierces three key elements of reasoning - abduction, induction and
deduction - in the dynamics of the interplay of the components of the creative work.

This returns us to Hallam and Ingold's conception of improvisation, not only as a form
of creativity but a form of problem solving, where the creative practitioner is
constantly adjusting their activity as they pursue their "workmanship of risk". This
might be regarded as the exercise of the abductive and fuzzy in practice. Through
this approach we might consider a humanist reformulation of Heisenberg's
uncertainty principle (Heisenberg 1927), proposing that the more precisely one thing
is known then the less precisely the other be known.

Perhaps we can consider whether there is value in seeking to determine what the
"unknown knowns" might be and in what sense they are, and remain, unknown? In
attempting to shift the register of our logical knowledge matrix, in order to render the
"unknown known" a "known known", the intrinsic value of this form of knowing might
be compromised. In uncertainty knowledge can be considered to retain a certain
value. Indeed, the uncertain might be regarded as of a very particular value that only
this particular kind of knowledge can contain. Thus, in contrast to the conclusion
drawn in Zizek's re-reading of Rumsfeld, if we do seek to erase the "unknown
knowns" and replace them with the "known knowns" we, arguably, risk losing a way
of knowing that could be of significant value. Without wishing to support a false social
dichotomy, implicit in Zizek's proposal, that the task of the intellectual is to "unearth
the "unknown knowns"", perhaps the task of the artist is to nurture the imminent seed
that is the "unknown known"?

However, if we accept this then the problem emerges that we risk indulging the
romantic ideal of the artist as one with a capacity to access a form of proto-
knowledge which might be compromised if we hold its source up to the light of critical
analysis. The resolution to this problem is, however, not a question of epistemology
but ontology, for we now need to ask what, in this context, the artist might be? If we
choose to employ a model of the artist founded upon the ideal of the solitary genius,
whose creativity is a function of, and finds value in, its difference to the body of
society, then the problem becomes intractable. However, if instead we accept
Ingold's proposition of creative practice as a pervasive and defining quality of
communities and societies, where the foundational creative act is the making of
people through the dynamic inter-relations of people, we can then regard the
performative value of individual instances of creative practice as emblematic of those
processes.

This arguably allows us to more fully appreciate the contribution of the individual
creative act, or its outcome, whilst recognising that its value is a function of the
social, not something established in oppositional isolation to it. Such an
understanding has echoes of Michel Foucault's conception of knowledge as a
pervasive social quality, as he outlined in his foundational work addressing discipline
(1975) and sexuality (1976). This is an economy of knowledge where all members of
society are implicit in the creation, and destruction, of value. In this context the value
of the "unknown known" can be regarded as politically significant and perhaps this
suggests why Rumsfeld did not, or could not, consider the full range of possibilities in
his incomplete knowledge matrix. To have done so would have required Rumsfeld to
accept the social value of the "unknown known", a pervasive and tacit route to
knowledge that stands in contradistinction to the top-down and centrally determined
models of knowledge he would most likely be comfortable with. In this respect Zizek
is correct to propose that it is the "unknown knowns" that form the background to our
values and that these should be subject to critical evaluation if we are to avoid
forever repeating ourselves.


references:

Foucault, M (1975), Discipline and Punish: the Birth of the Prison, Random House, New York

Foucault, M (1976), The History of Sexuality Vol. 1: The Will to Knowledge, Penguin, London

Hallam, E & Ingold, T (2007), Creativity and Cultural Improvisation, Berg, Oxford

Heisenberg, W (1927), Quantum Theory and Measurement, translated by J. A. Wheeler and
H. Zurek, Princeton University Press, 1983

Klee, P (1961), Paul Klee Notebooks, edited by Jurg Spiller, Witternborn, New York

Peirce, C (1958), Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Harvard University Press,
Cambridge Mass.

Pye, D (1968), The Nature and Art of Workmanship, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
UK

Scrivener, S (2002), The art object does not embody a form of knowledge: Working Papers in
Art and Design 2, Retrieved 13.05.2008 from URL
http://www.herts.ac.uk/artdes/research/papers/wpades/vol2/scrivenerfull.html.

Zadeh, L (1965), Fuzzy Sets, in Information and Computation v8 n3, Elsevier, Amsterdam

Zadeh, L (1973), Outline of a New Approach to the Analysis of Complex Systems and
Decision Processes, IEEE Transactions on Systems, Man and Cybernetics, v3 n1, USA

Zizek, S (2005), The Empty Wheelbarrow, The Guardian, February 19, London

You might also like