Robert Rosen How Are Organisms Different
Robert Rosen How Are Organisms Different
Robert Rosen How Are Organisms Different
Q is the initial state
Y is the set of outputs
is the output map
It has been said that this algorithmic character is restricted to sequential machines. I now will show that this is an
illusion. A machine is a machine. Now can we describe a "parallel machine" as anything different?
DEFINITION: Parallel Machine: PM = (X
0
, Q, , q
0
,Y, )
Where
X
0
is the set of inputs
Q is the set of states
: Q x X
0
Q is the dynamics
q
0
Q is the initial state
Y is the set of outputs
is the output map
Is there anything missing from this formulation? No, there is really none. The reason that they are the same in
actuality is quite simple, it is always possible to simulate a parallel machine with a sequential machine. It is true that
the symbols X and Q stand for different sets and that if Q is the set of states for the system it contains a subset, N
which is the states of all the nodes in the parallel system. (In an ANN these would be the neurons). More
importantly, the rules or algorithms behind the mapping , , are very different in the two examples.
What is of particular interest is the mapping representing the dynamics of the machine. Even if we allow final cause
into the picture, there is a paucity of entailment in the system. This will always be true in machines. In fact, if we try
to answer "why?" for each aspect of the machine we can only finally answer by going outside the machine. This
route leads to an infinite regression if continued. It is interesting that one way to end the process of nested
entailments is to invoke some notion of deity.
2.2.3 The (M,R) system as a relational model of the organism
The History of relational models goes back to a seminal paper by Nicholas Rashevsky wherein he made a radical
change in his approach to living systems (Rashevsky, 1954). After pioneering most of the mechanistic models we
know about today, including reaction-diffusion systems and artificial neural networks as far back as the 1930s, he
took stock of what he had learned and realized that he was not any closer to understanding what living systems were
all about. He then decided to take an entirely new direction. His goal was to keep the organization of the living
system while basically throwing out the physics. His tool for this was topology.
From the examples mentioned above it is inescapable that Rashevsky's desire to capture the contribution of
organization was key to understanding living systems. There are many ways of expressing this , none of which are
totally adequate due to the totality with which the Newtonian Paradigm made mechanism everything and clouded
the real structure of the modeling relation. The essence is in the idea that organization can not be preserved during
reductionist analysis. The concept of analytic models that do not reduce to synthetic models captures this formally.
The task then is to formulate an analytic model of the organism that captures the organization even if it must
sacrifice the physics. For this task, category theory is the method Rosen saw as capable of doing exactly what he
wanted. He applied category theory to the (M,R) system to answer the question of why an organism was different
from a machine. The presentation that follows will not be concerned with the fine points of category theory, but will
focus on the representation of the mappings as they develop as answers to the question "why?'. The fundamental
idea is that each mapping represents the input/output relations in an abstract block diagram. The first step is a single
input/output diagram to represent "metabolism" as a mapping f taking inputs in A to outputs in B, f:A B. This is
about as abstract a way there is to represent metabolism. In fact the symbols here can represent an infinite number of
different schemes all of which have in common the mere taking inputs to outputs. Thus the symbolism has more to
say about the organization of the organism rather than its mechanisms. Also, the symbolism as mere syntax, without
the rich semantics attached to it, is rather meaningless. Notice also that the symbolism could represent any
input/output relation. That is why it must carry with it certain semantics to fit the situation we are addressing here.
A, the set of inputs, is being replaced from the environment as well as having certain members leave to the
environment, but that need not be made explicit. What is missing is information about causality. A is clearly the
material cause of B and f the efficient cause of B. In the sense of these causes, f is unentailed. We know the
organism is repairing itself continuously, so that in the organism f is entailed by something. Again semantics is the
key to making the syntax meaningful. Let us therefore represent that by use of a second mapping, : B f. Now
we have as the efficient cause of f and B as its material cause. Call this second mapping the representation of
repair in the system. This implies that among the products of metabolism are the materials necessary to keep the
system maintained due to turn over of its components. What this simple symbolism connotes is truly profound. The
system is in a constant turnover. Part of the turnover is the causal basis for the system's self repair. The system can
be symbolized as follows:
The broken lined arrows represent material causation and the solid arrows represent efficient cause. If we note that f
has the meaning H (A,B) , namely some relation on the Cartesian product of sets A and B,
this can also be written as :
f
A B H(A,B).
(A relation as used here is merely a subset of all the possible (A, B) with A coming from set a and B coming from
set B.)
So far the system could easily represent a machine. The mapping was created to take care of the cause of f, so that
f is now entailed, but as a result a new lack of entailment is introduced. In any machine this would lead to an infinite
regression unless some outside agent was invoked as the cause. What Rosen did next was to see a way to bring
about a closure here in order to distinguish the organism from a machine. What he did has the same flavor as what
Newton accomplished when he saw that a formal description of particle motion was something that led to an infinite
recursion. He then formulated his second law of motion to deal with this. By assuming that there was a duality
between particle and environment, he assigned a "force" to the environment, which was dependent on particle
position and equal to the mass times the acceleration of the particle. Thus was born the equation of motion and most
importantly a closure was obtained! Rosen has accomplished something, which seems to be at least equivalently
meaningful in obtaining another kind of closure here. This closure, which forms a closed causal loop, is the reason
the organism differs from a machine.
By recognizing a role for "repair" in the organism, represented by the mapping , f became entailed. The next part
of the argument appears in a very abbreviated form in Life Itself. The basis for what appears there had been laid
down many years before and is summarized in another work (Rosen, 1972). There he said "The obvious idea of
iterating the construction we have used, and introducing repair components...leads to an infinite regress and is
useless. In biological cells, the problem is solved by making the repair components ...(self-) replicating."
This idea of self-replication of functional components (not parts) of the system is the key to the resolution of the
problem. It is important to fully understand this distinction. Function is distinct from structure. In complex systems
function is "spread" over the parts of the system in a manner which does not map 1:1 onto those parts. To capture
this essential property, Rosen utilized the functional component to represent this newly recognized reality within the
system. The functional components are the ontological embodiment of the non-fragmentable aspects of the system's
organization. They are defined by their context and have no necessary meaning outside that context. Thus, they
capture what is lost by reductionism. The idea that functional components have the same reality as the parts, if not
more, is very profound.
The fact that these functional components can also be self-replicating has a very nice mathematical realization that
can only be summarized here. The argument is as follows. Assume that the set of mappings H(A,B) have the
following property, namely that we can use the outputs to label the mappings. Then for each output, b in B we have
b*: H(A,B) B. Now imbed the set B into a set of mappings, namely H(H(A,B),B) so that b*(f) = f(a) for every
mapping f in the set H(A,B). What we are doing, in a very abstract way is assuming a certain structure in the system,
not unlike the way we characterize classes of biochemical reactions. The next structural requirement is that some of
the mappings among the class b* be invertable, that is if b*(f
1
) = b*(f
2
), then f
1 =
f
2 .
This
guarantees an inverse
mapping b*
-1
b*(f) = f for all f. Thus for every invertable mapping, there is a = b*
-1
with the property that :
H(A,B) H(B, H(A,B)). This mapping actually replicates the mapping !
In other words, with some simple structure among the mappings representing metabolism and repair, functional
components become self-replicating! Going back to the diagram, had we naively added the replication step it would
have left unentailed, for given that is really :f , that is that it is the efficient cause of and that f is the
material cause of ,
is left unentailed this time.
We have already established that a = b*
-1
, the inverse of b* : f B, so that the diagram can be redrawn,
The diagram is one in which every function is entailed by another function. Thus the infinite regress seen in the
machine does not exist and the question has been answered. Organisms are different from machines because they
are closed to efficient cause. As Robert Rosen stated it "A material system is an organism if, and only if, it is closed
to efficient causation. There is much that has been said in coming to this point and it is well worth summarizing.
2.2.4 What has been learned?
The closure of the relational diagram has a parallel significance with Newton's achievement of closure in his
dynamics. It establishes a category of objects called organisms that are clearly distinguishable from machines. This
distinction arose from a procedure, which did not reduce the system to its material parts, nor did it explicitly invoke
dynamics. In fact, the procedure, by necessity, treated processes and organization (mappings) as if they had the same
ontological reality as the material parts. Specifically, to recognize mappings in which the mappings f play the role of
material cause is to acknowledge a broader meaning for the notion of "material". Also, the concept of "replication"
here is new and broadens the meaning of that term as well. What is replicated is a functional component, not a
material part as such. It is necessary to recognize that the system of interest was complex, but that complexity alone
was not enough. Thus organisms are complex, but all complex things are not organisms. The nature of the organism
is that it possesses the kind of unity Maturana and Varela invoke for their autopoietic systems ( Maturana and
Varela, 1980). It would seem appropriate for this result to be incorporated in the discussion of autopoiesis.
It should be clear from this result that not only is it useful to recognize functional components as making up separate
tangible aspects of the system, but that it is necessary to do so. Once this idea becomes clear, it becomes possible to
look at complex systems in a new and meaningful way. Up until now, these ideas have been poorly understood and
the suggestion that there are non-material aspects to the system as important , if not more important, as the material
parts has often been looked upon as a form of mysticism. On the contrary, in order for science to be less mystical,
these aspects need to be given more consideration.
3. An application: Is the Gaia hypothesis sound?
The Gaia hypothesis asserts that earth and its surrounding atmosphere constitute a living organism
(Lovelock, 1979). Now that we have a clear-cut criterion for distinguishing organisms from simple
machines as well as from other complex systems, we should be able to classify the system. Let us assume
that the metabolism, m, of the earth consists of certain ongoing cycles including ecosystems, the water
cycle, and others, C, that are made from resources, R, which include sunlight, the atmosphere, and the
planet. As a relational diagram, this is, m: R C. Next, in order that m is entailed, we recognize a set of
natural processes that renew these metabolic processes from existing cycles when they are disrupted, n: C
m. At this point, n is unentailed. If another process, g, replicated the natural processes then a favorable
analogy with the example above by Rosen is obtained. In fact, the diagrams are the same with the
correspondences (A, R), (B, C), (f, m), ( , n), and (, G). Thus, by this criterion, the earth system, or Gaia,
is indeed an organism.
4. Some conclusions and the issue of fabrication
The question "what is life?" will probably never really be answered in that form. The reason is inbuilt in
epistemology. Such a question is inherently ill posed. Instead, we ask to distinguish life from not-life and, in
particular, the machine. The answer that presents itself is one we have recognized in other forms for years. We teach
the cell theory "Living cells arise from other living cells". Modern cloning experiments and other manipulations are
built on this notion and it seems to work well. Why not assemble a cell from its parts? The first response is usually
that it is too complicated. What Rosen showed is something else. The issue is not one of complication, but one of
complexity. Fabrication of complex systems is an entirely different project from the fabrication of a machine. This
has interesting implications when we contemplate the evolution of life.
1. Evolution of life is not the construction of a machine
In this age of molecular biology it is very tempting to see the mysteries of evolution of living organisms as the
evolution of some very complicated synthetic process. In fact, that notion is probably counter productive. A machine
needs a builder; it can not effect its own construction. Evolution is a process that defines itself as a system. This is
the idea captured in the concept of "component systems" (Kampis, 1991) and other related ideas. Rosen has laid a
nice foundation for this manner of thinking. As early as 1958 he began to imagine the way life has to come about.
As time progressed, the answer he saw was revolutionary. The machine oriented thinking of the Newtonian
paradigm was a distraction. The contemplation of mechanism after mechanism for the answer to the problem led
nowhere. The reason is clear, living things are not like machines at all. Machines are built from the bottom up out of
parts constructed to add to each other in a supportive way. It is tempting to look at a machine and glibly say that the
whole is more than the sum of the parts and think one has said something. Rosen simply asked, what is a sum of
parts? This led to the modeling relation, the identification of some formalism that would define that sum, and the
recognition that in every speculation about these matters models are involved. He then knew he had to understand
those models. This led to a clear definition of what a machine is and how a machine relates to its parts. Once that
was accomplished, it became obvious that living systems relate to their parts in entirely different ways. Evolution, as
does the mature organism, must be seen as the evolution of function in the form of functional components. What is
more, the functional components, because they are defined by the momentary context, are not permanent features in
an evolving system. To the extent that a developing system mimics its evolution the same is true for it. How can this
be realized? Rosen saw it in the abstract. He saw metabolism, repair, and replication. And there it is! The key to a
system evolving to become an organism is that it must reach some point where it achieves all three of these
functions. We have never designed a machine like this and for very good reason. We build machines to last. One of
the first and most crucial aspects of the evolving living system was its failure to last! It was in a condition of being
torn down as fast as it was being built up and this is what allowed it to evolve. Stability is the return to a condition
after being perturbed from it. How much more stable could something be than to have both its construction and
destruction under strict limits? Both construction and destruction are systems properties. The systematic tearing
down allows rebuilding, replication and evolution. The details we know, but the strategy was masked by the details.
Molecular biology is indeed an oxymoron. Biology is the study of life and life does not exist at the molecular level.
We do not know how far Rosen went down this path. In a radio interview he speaks of unpublished work and some
moral reservations about the responsibility he felt if he were to lead us further. It is clear from that strong conviction
that, in his own mind, he saw an answer.
4.2 The twenty first century
Science itself is a complex, evolving system. John Horgan, among others, has contemplated its end (Horgan, 1996).
Interestingly, as he does that, he also mocks the many definitions of "complexity" and also only briefly mentions
Robert Rosen as some "Canadian scientist", never mentioning his contributions to the topic he presents himself as
expert in. On the other hand, Rosen wrote optimistically about the future of science (Rosen, 1996). His optimism
was based on a direction for science that Horgan and many others rule out. Their bias is based on a strict adherence
to a science of method rather than a science of content. Rosen saw that a science of content had its boundaries
beyond our sight due to the newness of the ideas that sharpened his vision. There is more to life than that which a
science of method allows access to. Human experience tells us that quite clearly. Rosen, with great skill, developed
his tools from within the science of method. He used them to expose the limits and then break them down.
There is a lot being said in other circles about science and its role in the quest for knowledge in the future. For
example, one brand of postmodern thought (Lyotard, 1979) recognizes an ongoing conflict between science and
narrative as ways of knowing. These different realms may be in the process of becoming more complimentary as the
development of these new ideas progresses. It is interesting that some writers have their feet planted in both arenas
as they forge ahead (Hayles, 1995).
Rosen was ahead of his time when seen from that perspective. His work is difficult to master because it asks the
learner to change directions. Often unlearning and relearning is necessary. It is easy to look at the above diagrams
and dismiss them without understanding the immense semantic richness they carry with them. The ability to make
that change makes it easy to continue to change. Is that not what evolution is all about?
5. References
Arbib, M. and E. G. Manes. 1975. Arrows, Structures, and Functors: The Categorical Imperative. New York:
Academic Press. pp 93-106.
Dress, W. 1998. "A Bayesian approach to extracting meaning from system behavior
1998 IEEE International Conference on Systems, Man, and Cybernetics. IEEE Press, pp. 2243-48.
Dress, W. 1999. Epistemology and Rosen's Modeling Relation. This Publication.
Fischler, M. A. and O. Firschein. 1987. Intelligence: The eye, the brain, and the computer. Reading:Addison
Wesley.
Hayles, N. K. 1995. "Narratives of evolution and the evolution of narratives". in Cooperation and Conflict in
General evolutionary processes. (J. L. Casti and A. Karlqvist, eds.). New York: Wiley. pp113-132.
Horgan, J. 1996. The end of science:facing the limits of science in the twilight of the scientific age. New York:
Broadway Books.
Kampis, G. 1991. Self-Modifying Systems in Biology and Cognitive Science: A New Framework for Dynamics,
Information and Complexity. New York: Pergamon Press.
Lovelock, J. 1979. Gaia: A new look at life on earth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lyotard, J.-F. 1979. The postmodern condition: A report on knowledge.Minneapolis: The University of Minnesota
Press.
Maturana, H. R. and F. J. Varela. 1980. Autopoieses and cognition: The realization of the living. Dordrecht: D.
Reidel.
Mikulecky, D. C. 1993. Applications of network thermodynamics to problems in biomedical engineering. New
York: New York University Press.
Mikulecky, D. C. 1994."n-ports: what are they good for?" Special Issue: Modeling Complex Biological Systems,
Math. And Comp. Modeling. Vol. 19: 99-118.
Mikulecky, D. C. and M. Thellier. 1993. "Determining transient kinetic behavior of complex multi-enzyme systems
by use of network thermodynamics. C. R. Acad. Sci. III. Vol. 316(12): 1399-1403.
Peusner, L. 1970. The principles of network thermodynamics: theory and biophysical applications. Ph. D. Thesis.
Harvard University. (reprinted by Entropy Limited, Lincoln, MA, 1987)
Peusner, L. 1986. Studies in network thermodynamics. Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Prideaux, J. 1996. "Feed-forward activation in a theoretical first-order biochemical pathway which contains an
anticipatory model. Acta Biotheoretica. Vol. 44:219-233.
Rashevsky, N.1954. "Topology and life: In search of general mathematical principles in biology and sociology".
Bull.Math. Biophys. Vol.16: 317-348.
Rosen, R., Some relational cell models: The metabolism-repair systems, in Foundations of Mathematical Biology,
Volume II, R. Rosen, ed. Academic Press, NY, 1972.
Rosen, R. 1978. Fundamentals of Measurement and representation of Natural Systems. New York :North-Holland
Rosen, R. 1985.Anticipatory Systems: Philosophical, Mathematical & Methodological
Foundations, New York: Pergamon Press.
Rosen, R. 1991.Life Itself: A Comprehensive Inquiry into the Nature, Origin, and Fabrication of
Life. New York: Columbia University Press.
Rosen, R. 1996. "On the limits of Scientific knowledge" in Boundaries and barriers:on the limits to scientific
knowledge. (J. L. Casti and A. Karlqvist, eds.). Reading: Addison-Wesley. pp199-214.