Dagfinn Follesdal - Analytic Philosophy
Dagfinn Follesdal - Analytic Philosophy
Dagfinn Follesdal - Analytic Philosophy
ordinary
language
C O N T IN E N T A L PH IL O SO PH Y
pheno
menology
existent
ialism
herm en
eutics
structural
ism
deconstructm sm
neoThom ism
neoMarxism
DAGFINN F0LLESDAL
such a way that it fits the great variety of philosophers who are
normally called analytic. In this article I shall do the latter.
Doctrines, Problems, Approaches
Some philosophical currents, such as phenomenology, are deter
mined by their perspectives or doctrines. A phenomenologist is
someone who has distinctive views about intentionality and other
related topics. Neo-Thomists, neo-Kantians, neo-Marxists, etc.,
are equally characterized by their views. This does not hold, how
ever, for hermeneutics, which is defined rather by its range of
problems. Hermeneutics is concerned with questions of understand
ing, and with the interpretation of texts and other manifestations
of the hum an mind, to speak with Dilthey. It only engages the
many other problems of philosophy in so far as the latter are
connected with understanding and interpretation. But as regards
their views, the various proponents of hermeneutics differ sharply.
Even at this stage, therefore, it is apparent that the standard
classification of the main currents of contemporary philosophy
conflates two distinct principles of classification: doctrines and
problems. Furtherm ore, the tradition with which we are concerned,
analytic philosophy, cannot even be characterized by reference to
either doctrines or problems. Analytical philosophers discuss a
variety of philosophical problems, and they hold utterly different
views about these problems. I know of no philosophical view which
is shared by all or even most analytic philosophers, at least not of a
view which is not completely trivial. In my view, what distinguishes
analytic philosophy is rather a particular way of approaching
philosophical problems, although, as we have seen, this approach
must not be identified with a specific method of analyzing
philosophical concepts. But in what does this distinctive approach
consists? This is the question that will occupy us now, and it is not
an easy one.
Genetic affiliation: schools
But before we turn to this question, let us first note that by now we
have encountered three different principles of classification:
according to doctrines, according to problems, and according to ways o f
approaching them. We jum p from the one to the next and to the
third, as in the Chinese encyclopedia, and without a unifying
principle of classification. For any classification, this is a serious
ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY
DAGFINN F0IXESDAL
teachers and pupils, but because they tackle the same problems.
In my view, analytic philosophy creates even more serious
problems than hermeneutics and existentialism for the view that
the main currents of philosophy consist of schools of thought. Take
as an example Bernard Bolzano.
In my view, Bolzano, born in 1781, was an outstanding analytic
philosopher. Early in the nineteenth century he anticipated many
central ideas of Frege, C arnap, Tarski, Quine and others, and
tackled them in an exemplary fashion. It is with good reason,
therefore, that Anders Wedberg starts the last volume of his history
of philosophy, the presentation of contemporary philosophy, with a
chapter on Bolzano.5 Then follow Frege, Russell, Moore, and the
other philosophers of our century. To say that Bolzano is an
analytic philosopher cannot mean that Frege, Russell, Moore and
other analytic philosophers are pupils of Bolzano. Frege does not
mention Bolzano, and seems not to have known of him at all. It is
not improbable that some of Bolzanos impulses reached him via
intermediaries. But to back the genetic thesis that Bolzano exerted
a decisive influence on Frege, one would have to believe in the
migration of souls: Frege was born in 1848, the year of Bolzanos
death (however, Bolzano died six weeks after Freges birth).
It appears that Russell did not know of Bolzano either, in spite of
the fact that Bolzano dealt at length not only with the philosophy of
logic and the philosophy of language, but also with other topics on
which Russell worked, such as the philosophy of Leibniz. Bolzano
remained generally unknown until the work of Heinrich Scholz, of
Kaila in Finland and of Wedberg and his pupils. U ntil recently, for
example, there was no entry on Bolzano in the Encyclopedia
Britannica. Only Husserl paid attention to Bolzano; he explicitly
thanks him in Logiscke Untersuchungen as well as in other works. If
the main currents of philosophy are schools, for which teacher/
pupil relations and actual influence are decisive, Bolzano must be
regarded as a phenomenologist. However, in his work one
encounters very little of the views about intentionality and related
themes that characterize phenomenology. Instead, all those who
have studied Bolzano have concluded that he is a typical analytic
philosopher. Great grandfather of analytic philosophy Dummett
called him, thereby claiming only a systematic connection, not a
genetic one.6
5 Anders Wedberg, A History o f Philosophy, Vol. 3: From Bolzano to Wittgenstein (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1984; Swedish ed. 1966).
6 Michael Dummett, The Roots o f Analytic Philosophy (London; Duckworth, 1993), p. 171.
ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY
r:
^
For this reason we are well advised to abandon the idea that the
classification of philosophical currents is a genetic classification of
philosophical schools. This may hold true of neo-Thomism, neoKantianism, neo-Marxism, etc., but hardly of any other currents.
^ Some currents, such as phenomenology, are characterized by
certain views or theses, others, like hermeneutics, by a particular
"range of problems. W hat we have here is a mixture of diverse
' criteria, but no common basis of classification, a situation similar to
that of the Chinese encyclopedia.
But analytic philosophy continues to demand our attention. We
have not yet established what it is. We have a few negative answers:
aiS&Iytic philosophy is not a school, one can be an analytic
^philosopher without having studied other analytic philosophers,
; aadT without in turn influencing other analytic philosophers.
i4&xceovtr, there is no philosophical view or method of conceptual
analysis which is shared by all or most analytic philosophers. But
w ia t can we say positively about analytic philosophy? I have already
mentioned that analytic philosophy appears to be characterized by
its way of approaching philosophical problems. The question is
f therefore: what characterizes this approach?
have alreay remarked that there are many analytic philosophers,
such as Quine, who do not fit the view of analytic philosophy as a
kind of conceptual analysis. It is true that analytic philosophers like
so investigate language. But philosophy of language is only part of
analytic philosophy. Analytic philosophers can be found in all
areas of philosophy, for example in epistemology, ethics, aesthetics,
ptutoiophy of mind and metaphysics. Moral philosophers like
Rawls' only rarely pronounce on language and the philosophy of
and yet they are analytic philosophers.
Br
h
DAGFINN F0LLJSSDAL
7 The Turning Point in Philosophy, in A .J. Ayer (ed.), logical Positivism (New York:
Free Press, 1959), p. 56. German original Die Wende der Philosophie, Erkemtnis 1 (1930/
31).
8 Loc. cit., p. 81.
9 Sceptical Essays (New York: Norton, 1928), pp. 69-70.
ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY
10
DAGFINN F0LLESDAL
ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY
1J
"
12
DAGFINN F0LLESDAL
Frege and Russell, fit well into this picture. Through the great
weight which they have given to argument they have contributed to
the philosophical enterprise insights into several general connec
tions, as well as detailed studies and distinctions. Yet, Moore and
W ittgenstein have also made im portant contributions. They give
little insight into general connections, but they have given
descriptions and drawn distinctions; moreover, they have detected
difficulties to which all attempts to provide a systematic philosophy
must be alive. Detecting difficulties is also an im portant contribution
to philosophy, indeed, a very im portant one.
Non-analytic philosophers
EC
ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY
13
14
DAGFINN F0LLESDAL
ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY
15
- .
**XYT1C
1
struc
tural
ism
decon
struct
ivism
neoThom ism
neoM arx
ism
ethics
n atur
alism
etc . . .
Hos
ier!
H ei
degger
mm
$ES&
.v u x .m c
v/r: .
<5
herm
eneu
tics
Sf,^
16
DAGFINN F0LLESDAL