Civil Society
Civil Society
Civil Society
Introduction:
Civil society, dense network of groups, communities, networks, and ties that stand between the
individual and the modern state.
This modern definition of civil society has become a familiar component of the main strands of
contemporary liberal and democratic theorizing. In addition to its descriptive properties, the
terminology of civil society carries a litany of ethical and political aspirations and implications.
For some of its advocates, the achievement of an independent civil society is a necessary
precondition for a healthy democracy, and its relative absence or decline is often cited as both a
cause and an effect of various contemporary sociopolitical maladies.
The meaning and implications of the concept of civil society have been widely debated. As an
analytical framework for interpreting the social world, the idea that civil society should be
understood as, by definition, separated from and opposed to the operations of the state and
official public institutions has various disadvantages, not the least of which is that it inhibits
appreciation of the complex interrelationships between state and society. Equally, the notion
that the hugely diverse group life of Western capitalist societies promotes social values that are
separable from, and possibly opposed to, the market is hard to defend. The forms of combination
and association that typify civil societies in the West are typically affected and shaped by the
ideas, traditions, and values that also obtain in the economic sphere.
includes all organizations that occupy the 'social space' between the family and the state,
excluding political parties and firms. Some definitions of civil society also include certain
businesses, such as the media, private schools, and for-profit associations, while others exclude
them.
some states to orchestrate and occasionally manipulate civil society organizations for their own
ends.
Standing between and partially overlapping with these perspectives, there developed a different,
long-lasting
conception
in
the
thinking
of
some
of
the
major
theorists
of
the Scottishpolitical economy tradition of the 18th century, including Adam Smith and Francis
Hutcheson. In their view, civil society should be conceived as emerging from the intertwined
development of an independent commercial order, within which complex chains of
interdependence between predominantly self-seeking individuals proliferated, and the
development of an independent public sphere, where the common interests of society as a whole
could be pursued. The development of the notion of a public that is in possession of its own
opinion in relation to matters of common concern became an increasingly prevalent way of
thinking about civil society, particularly in connection with the emergence of forums and spaces
where the free exchange of opinions was observablenewspapers, coffeehouses, political
assemblies.
The German strands concern with the sources and importance of the ethical ends learned
through participation in the corporations of civil society reemerged in the work of a body of
American political scientists and theorists who came to view civil society organizations as sources
of the stocks of social capital and mutual reciprocity that a successful democracy is supposed to
require.
And, third, the Scottish conception was powerfully revived by left-inclined thinkers who hoped
to provide a more pluralist, and less statist, reformulation of a socialist ideology that was
experiencing a profound political recession among Western publics.
As the Canadian philosopher Charles Taylor observed, these and other influential ways of thinking
about civil society rested upon the twin assumptions that, in empirical terms, independent civil
societies did come into existence at various points from the 18th through the 20th century and
that their existence depends, in part, upon the separation of the concepts of state and society in
the Western political imagination. Neither of these assumptions is uncontentious. While there
clearly does exist a plethora of groups, communities, and associations in relative separation from
the state, the boundary between state and civil society in many countries is rarely as clear or firm
as the first assumption suggests. In various democracies, the state and other public authorities
succeeded in incorporating institutions and organizations from civil societyfor instance, trade
unions, environmental groups, and business associationsinto key networks of influence and
decision making. Equally, individual groups and even oppositional social movements often
expend considerable resources and energy attempting to interact with government officials,
elected politicians, and state bureaucracies. The notion that the statecivil society distinction
exists in all Western societies therefore requires considerable clarification and qualification in
empirical terms.
Likewise, the idea that a fundamental intellectual distinction between state and society
underpins the model of liberal democracy begs some rather large questions. Quite different
accounts of the distinction and interrelationship between society and the state guided some of
the major ideologies of the 19th and 20th centuries and sustained clashing theories about
politics, sovereignty, and social order. Above all, the idea that a portion of any societal complex
should be portioned off, endowed with ethical, even emancipatory, significance, and understood
as the fundamental opponent of political authority and institutional life looks increasingly
problematic in the early 21st century.
One of the most interesting and contentious manifestations of the terminology of civil society
arises from its increasingly common application to non-Western societies. Are supporters of civil
society in the West and in newly democratizing states throughout the world talking about the
same things when they invoke this term? Can a Western-derived term be usefully employed as a
framework for analyzing societies with forms of sociability and state-society relationships that
differ markedly from those of the West? Equally, the assumption of some Anglo-American theory
that a network of independent associations, cultural practices, and organizations is a necessary
feature of a stable democracy is open to considerable doubt when viewed from elsewhere in the
world (think, for instance, of East Asian countries that have many of the features of civil societies
but are not democratic in their political structures).
During the 1990s, in particular, many authors, politicians, and public authorities keen to find
solutions to some of the different kinds of problems facing developing countries seized upon civil
society as a kind of panacea. Relatedly, this term became a conceptual mainstay of academic
thinking about democratic transitions and a familiar part of the discourse of global institutions,
leading nongovernmental organizations, and Western governments. The ideological character
and political implications of such ideas have become increasingly clear over time. Such thinking
helped sustain various attempts to kick-start civil societies from above in different African
countries, for example, and simultaneously served to legitimize Western ideas about the kinds of
political structure and economic order appropriate for developing states. In philosophical terms,
applying civil society in this kind of way raises the profound question of whether it can be
removed from its status within the Western political imagination and applied in ways that are
appropriate for the indigenous developmental trajectories and political cultures of some of the
poorest countries in the world.
It is impossible to divest the notion of civil society of normative connotations. The concept
remains powerful, in part, because of its (often unstated) contrastive character. A civil society is