2 3schmitter
2 3schmitter
2 3schmitter
and Is Not
Philippe C. Schmitter, Terry Lynn Karl
WHAT
...
DEMOCRACY
A N D IS N O T
IS
For
Journal of Democracy
76
these standards are met; indeed, some countries even consider them when
formulating foreign policy.2
What Democracy Is
Let us begin by broadly defining democracy and the generic concepts
that distinguish it as a unique system for organizing relations between
rulers and the ruled. We will then briefly review procedures, the rules
and arrangements that are needed if democracy is to endure. Finally, we
will discuss two operative principles that make democracy work. They
are not expressly included among the generic concepts or formal
procedures, but the prospect for democracy is grim if their underlying
conditioning effects are not present.
One of the major themes of this essay is that democracy does not
consist of a single unique set of institutions. There are many types of
democracy, and their diverse practices produce a similarly varied set of
effects. The specific form democracy takes is contingent upon a
country's socioeconomic conditions as well as its entrenched state
structures and policy practices.
Modern political democracy is a system of governance in which rulers
are held accountable for their actions in the public realm by citizens,
acting indirectly through the competition and cooperation of their elected
representatives. 3
A regime or system of governance is an ensemble of patterns that
determines the methods of access to the principal public offices; the
characteristics of the actors admitted to or excluded from such access;
the strategies that actors may use to gain access; and the rules that are
followed in the making of publicly binding decisions. To work properly,
the ensemble must be institutionalized that is to say, the various
patterns must be habitually known, practiced, and accepted by most, if
not all, actors. Increasingly, the preferred mechanism of
institutionalization is a written body of laws undergirded by a written
constitution, though many enduring political norms can have an informal,
prudential, or traditional basis. 4
For the sake of economy and comparison, these forms, characteristics,
and rules are usually bundled together and given a generic label.
Democratic is one; others are autocratic, authoritarian, despotic,
dictatorial, tyrannical, totalitarian, absolutist, traditional, monarchic,
oligarchic, plutocratic, aristocratic, and sultanistic) Each of these regime
forms may in turn be broken down into subtypes.
Like all regimes, democracies depend upon the presence of rulers,
persons who occupy specialized authority roles and can give legitimate
commands to others. What distinguishes democratic rulers from
nondemocratic ones are the norms that condition how the former come
to power and the practices that hold them accountable for their actions.
77
78
Journal of Democracy
79
required, but few would deny that democracy must involve some means
of aggregating the equal preferences of individuals.
A problem arises, however, when numbers meet intensities. What
happens when a properly assembled majority (especially a stable, selfperpetuating one) regularly makes decisions that harm some minority
(especially a threatened cultural or ethnic group)? In these circumstances,
successful democracies tend to qualify the central principle of majority
rule in order to protect minority rights. Such qualifications can take the
form of constitutional provisions that place certain matters beyond the
reach of majorities (bills of rights); requirements for concurrent majorities
in several different constituencies (confederalism); guarantees securing the
autonomy of local or regional governments against the demands of the
central authority (federalism); grand coalition governments that
incorporate all parties (consociationalism); or the negotiation of social
pacts between major social groups like business and labor
(neocorporatism). The most common and effective way of protecting
minorities, however, lies in the everyday operation of interest associations
and social movements. These reflect (some would say, amplify) the
different intensities of preference that exist in the population and bring
them to bear on democratically elected decision makers. Another way
of putting this intrinsic tension between numbers and intensities would
be to say that "in modern democracies, votes may be counted, but
influences alone are weighted."
Cooperation has always been a central feature of democracy. Actors
must voluntarily make collective decisions binding on the polity as a
whole. They must cooperate in order to compete. They must be capable
of acting collectively through parties, associations, and movements in
order to select candidates, articulate preferences, petition authorities, and
influence policies.
But democracy's freedoms should also encourage citizens to deliberate
among themselves, to discover their common needs, and to resolve their
differences without relying on some supreme central authority. Classical
democracy emphasized these qualities, and they are by no means extinct,
despite repeated efforts by contemporary theorists to stress the analogy
with behavior in the economic marketplace and to reduce all of
democracy's operations to competitive interest maximization. Alexis de
Tocqueville best described the importance of independent groups for
democracy in his Democracy in America, a work which remains a major
source of inspiration for all those who persist in viewing democracy as
something more than a struggle for election and re-election among
competing candidates. 8
In contemporary political discourse, this phenomenon of cooperation
and deliberation via autonomous group activity goes under the rubric of
"civil society." The diverse units of social identity and interest, by
remaining independent of the state (and perhaps even of parties), not
80
Journal of Democracy
only can restrain the arbitrary actions of rulers, but can also contribute
to forming better citizens who are more aware of the preferences of
others, more self-confident in their actions, and more civic-minded in
their willingness to sacrifice for the common good. At its best, civil
society provides an intermediate layer of governance between the
individual and the state that is capable of resolving conflicts and
controlling the behavior of members without public coercion. Rather
than overloading decision makers with increased demands and making
the system ungovernable,9 a viable civil society can mitigate conflicts
and improve the quality of citizenship---without relying exclusively on
the privatism of the marketplace.
Representatives--whether directly or indirectly elected-----do most of the
real work in modem democracies. Most are professional politicians who
orient their careers around the desire to fill key offices. It is doubtful
that any democracy could survive without such people. The central
question, therefore, is not whether or not there will be a political elite
or even a professional political class, but how these representatives are
chosen and then held accountable for their actions.
As noted above, there are many channels of representation in modem
democracy. The electoral one, based on territorial constituencies, is the
most visible and public. It culminates in a parliament or a presidency
that is periodically accountable to the citizenry as a whole. Yet the sheer
growth of government (in large part as a byproduct of popular demand)
has increased the number, variety, and power of agencies charged with
making public decisions and not subject to elections. Around these
agencies there has developed a vast apparatus of specialized
representation based largely on functional interests, not territorial
constituencies. These interest associations, and not political parties, have
become the primary expression of civil society in most stable
democracies, supplemented by the more sporadic interventions of social
movements.
The new and fragile democracies that have sprung up since 1974
must live in "compressed time." They will not resemble the European
democracies of the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, and they
cannot expect to acquire the multiple channels of representation in
gradual historical progression as did most of their predecessors. A
bewildering array of parties, interests, and movements will all
simultaneously seek political influence in' them, creating challenges to the
polity that did not exist in earlier processes of democratization.
81
must be followed and civic rights must be respected. Any polity that
fails to impose such restrictions upon itself, that fails to follow the "rule
of law" with regard to its own procedures, should not be considered
democratic. These procedures alone do not define democracy, but their
presence is indispensable to its persistence. In essence, they are necessary
but not sufficient conditions for its existence.
Robert Dahl has offered the most generally accepted listing of what
he terms the "procedural minimal" conditions that must be present for
modem political democracy (or as he puts it, "polyarchy") to exist:
1) Control over government decisions about policy is constitutionally
vested in elected officials.
2) Elected officials are chosen in frequent and fairly conducted
elections in which coercion is comparatively uncommon.
3) Practically all adults have the fight to vote in the election of
officials.
4) Practically all adults have the fight to run for elective offices in
the government . . . .
5) Citizens have a fight to express themselves without the danger of
severe punishment on political matters broadly defined . . . .
6) Citizens have a fight to seek out alternative sources of information.
Moreover, altemative sources of information exist and are protected by
law.
7) . . . Citizens also have the fight to form relatively independent
associations or organizations, including independent political parties and
interest groups. ~~
These seven conditions seem to capture the essence of procedural
democracy for many theorists, but we propose to add two others. The
first might be thought of as a further refinement of item (1), while the
second might be called an implicit prior condition to all seven of the
above.
8) Popularly elected officials must be able to exercise their
constitutional powers without being subjected to overriding (albeit
informal) opposition from unelected officials. Democracy is in jeopardy
if military officers, entrenched civil servants, or state managers retain the
capacity to act independently of elected civilians or even veto decisions
made by the people's representatives. Without this additional caveat, the
militarized polities of contemporary Central America, where civilian
control over the military does not exist, might be classified by many
scholars as democracies, just as they have been (with the exception of
Sandinista Nicaragua) by U.S. policy makers. The caveat thus guards
against what we earlier called "electoralism"--the tendency to focus on
the holding of elections while ignoring other political realities.
9) The polity must be self-governing; it must be able to act
independently of constraints imposed by some other overarching political
system. Dahl and other contemporary democratic theorists probably took
82
Journal of Democracy
83
be respected. Not just any policy can be adopted there are conditions
that must be met, Democracy institutionalizes "normal," limited political
uncertainty. These boundaries vary from country to country.
Constitutional guarantees of property, privacy, expression, and other
rights are a part of this, but the most effective boundaries are generated
by competition among interest groups and cooperation within civil
society. Whatever the rhetoric (and some polities appear to offer their
citizens more dramatic alternatives than others), once the rules of
contingent consent have been agreed upon, the actual variation is likely
to stay within a predictable and generally accepted range.
This emphasis on operative guidelines contrasts with a highly
persistent,
but
misleading
theme
in
recent
literature
on
democracymnamely, the emphasis upon "civic culture." The principles
we have suggested here rest on rules of prudence, not on deeply
ingrained habits of tolerance, moderation, mutual respect, fair play,
readiness to compromise, or trust in public authorities. Waiting for such
habits to sink deep and lasting roots implies a very slow process of
regime consolidation---one that takes generations--and it would probably
condemn most contemporary experiences ex hypothesi to failure. Our
assertion is that contingent consent and bounded uncertainty can emerge
from the interaction between antagonistic and mutually suspicious actors
and that the far more benevolent and ingrained norms of a civic culture
are better thought of as a product and not a producer of democracy.
H o w Democracies Differ
Several concepts have been deliberately excluded from our generic
definition of democracy, despite the fact that they have been frequently
associated with it in both everyday practice and scholarly work. They
are, nevertheless, especially important when it comes to distinguishing
subtypes of democracy. Since no single set of actual institutions,
practices, or values embodies democracy, polities moving away from
authoritarian rule can mix different components to produce different
democracies. It is important to recognize that these do not define points
along a single continuum of improving performance, but a matrix of
potential combinations that are differently democratic.
1) Consensus: All citizens may not agree on the substantive goals of
political action or on the role of the state (although if they did, it would
certainly make governing democracies much easier).
2) Participation: All citizens may not take an active and equal part
in politics, although it must be legally possible for them to do so.
3) Access: Rulers may not weigh equally the preferences of all who
come before them, although citizenship implies that individuals and
groups should have an equal opportunity to express their preferences if
they choose to do so.
84
Journal of Democracy
85
86
Journal of Democracy
87
88
Journal of Democracy
legal codes that offer no guarantee of reliable practice. On paper, Stalin's 1936
constitution for the USSR was a virtual model of democratic rights and entitlements.
5. For the most valiant attempt to make some sense out of this thicket of distinctions,
see Juan Linz, "Totalitarian and Authoritarian Regimes" in Handbook of Political Science,
eds. Fred I. Greenstein and Nelson W. Polsby (Reading, Mass.: Addision Wesley, 1975),
175-411.
6. "Publius" (Alexander Hamilton, John Jay, and James Madison), The Federalist
Papers (New York: Anchor Books, 1961). The quote is from Number 10.
7. See Terry Karl, "Imposing Consent? Electoralism versus Democratization in E1
Salvador," in Elections and Democratization in Latin America, 1980-1985, eds. Paul Drake
and Eduardo Silva (San Diego: Center for Iberian and Latin American Studies, Center for
US/Mexican Studies, University of California, San Diego, 1986), 9-36.
8. Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, 2 vols. (New York: Vintage Books,
1945).
9. This fear of overloaded government and the imminent collapse of democracy is well
reflected in the work of Samuel P. Huntington during the 1970s. See especially Michel
Crozier, Samuel P. Huntington, and Joji Watanuki, The Crisis of Democracy (New York:
New York University Press, 1975). For Huntington's (revised) thoughts about the prospects
for democracy, see his "Will More Countries Become Democratic?," Political Science"
Quarterly 99 (Summer 1984): 193-218.
10. Robert Dahl, Dilemmas of Pluralist Democracy (New Haven: Yale University Press,
1982), 11.
11. Robert Dahl, After the Revolution: Authority in a Good Society (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1970).
12. See Juan Linz, "The Perils of Presidentialism," Journal of Democracy 1 (Winter
1990): 51-69, and the ensuing discussion by Donald Horowitz, Seymour Martin Lipset, and
Juan Linz in Journal of Democracy 1 (Fall 1990): 73-91.
13. Terry Lynn Karl, "Dilemmas of Democratization in Latin America," Comparative
Politics 23 (October 1990): 1-23.
14. Otto Kirchheimer, "Conf'ming Conditions and Revolutionary Breakthroughs,"
American Political Science Review 59 (1965): 964-974.