Rist BasilsNeoPlatonism
Rist BasilsNeoPlatonism
Rist BasilsNeoPlatonism
John M. Rist"
University of Toronto
A.
INTRODUCTION
138
JOHN M. RIST
1 P. Hadot and P. Henry, Marius Victorinus: Traites tlufologiques sur Ia Trinite (Paris
1960); P. Hadot, Porphyre et Victorinus (Paris 1969).
2 P. Courcelle, "Plotin et s. Ambroise," RPh 76 (1950) 29-56; idem, Recherches sur les
Coll{essions des. Augustin (Paris 1950) pp. 93-138; A. So!ignac, "Nouveaux paralleles
entre s. Ambroise et Plotin, Le 'De Jacob et vita beata' et le llepi euoatf1ovia,; (Enn. 1.4),"
A Ph 20 (1956) 148-156; L. Taormina, "Sant'Ambrogio e Plotino," MSLC 4 (1953) 41-85;
P. Hadot, "Platon et Plotin dans 3 sermons des. Ambroise: REL 34 (1956) 202-220; P.
Courcelle, "Nouveaux aspects du platonisme chez s. Ambroise," REL 34 (1956) 220-226;
idem, "Anti-Christian Arguments and Christian Platonism: from Arnobius to St
Ambrose," in The C01l/1ict Between Paganism and Christianity in the Fourth Cemury, ed.
A. Momigliano (Oxford 1965) pp. 151-192; idem, Recherches sur les "Coll{essions" des.
Augustin (Paris 1968) pp. 311-382; G. Madec, Ambroise et Ia phi/osophie (Paris 1974).
Exaggeration has inevitably set in: P. Courcelle, "Ambroise et Calcidius," in Recherches
sur s. Ambroise (Paris 1973) pp. 17-24.
3 Cf. Plotinus' attitude to Longinus (Porphyry, Vita Plot. 14) and his conversion of
Porphyry from a historically accurate account of the Forms (which he had learned from
Longinus) to his own version (Vita Plot. 18, with A. H. Armstrong, "The Background of
the Doctrine That the Intelligibles are not Outside the Intellect'," in Les Sources de Plotin
(Geneva 1960) pp. 391-425.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
139
a of the soul with the One and the claims made by him and on
to have experienced such union in his own person; 5 his
acceptance of a Neopythagorean tradition associated with
of Moderatus and Eudorus that led to his postulating a first
which is to be identified not as Nous but rather as the One. 6 Such
no means won universal approval; even those who genuinely
of Plotinus as their master took him seriously enough to accept
as that of a follower of Plato, and therefore frequently go back to
to Plato himself rather than to his pupil, for their inspiration.
ma~ observe, this tendency to revert to the source is particularly
among those who were less professional philosophers than
wishing to employ from time to time, and on their own terms,
philosophical ideas; and such people are particularly visible
the Christians.
more basic points: to be influenced by a man's philosophy one
him directly or to have access to his work indirectly either
other written documents or through oral sources. Porphyry's
Plotinus, the edition which we know today as the Enneads,
round about 301 AD. If, therefore, we find allusions to Plotinus'
works before 30 I, we must assume either an earlier edition,
"''""""'-'u of individual works, or an oral tradition. That there was
of oral tradition must be regarded as almost certain in view of
of Plotinus' pupils and their spread over the Mediterranean
JArn"'r" himself went to Sicily at least once, and Amelius retired
in Syria before Plotinus' death. 7 We should therefore consider
of the earliest diffusion of Neoplatonism, the Platonism of
and his philosophical successors, in two stages: the spread of
ideas before about 30 I, and their spread after 301. Both stages,
the latter, are indissolubly linked with, and complicated
spread of the knowledge of the works of Porphyry himself as well
of Plotinus in their various versions.
Enn. 4.8.8.1.
1.6.7 .2-3: 6.7 .40.2: 6.9.4.1.15 f.: 6.9.9.47 ff.: and possibly 4.8.1.1 ff.: Porphyry.
Plot. 23.
6
Pl For Plotinus' background on this matter see especially J. M. Dillon. The Middle
. a:onists (London/Ithaca 1977) pp. 115-135. 344-351.
Porphyry. Vita Plot. 2.
140
JOHN M. RIST
B.
PRELIMINARY OBSERVATIONS.
270-301
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
141
th 'Gocs 43.1 (ed. Mras) lv; T. D. Barnes, "Sossianus Hierocles and the Antecedents of
e reat Persecution'," HarvClassPhil 80 (] 976) 240.
142
JOHN M. RIST
that his work, especially the fifteen books Against the Christians, was Well
known in Christian circles even before the year 300, and indeed rebutted
in Christian texts which we have in our possession. There is, of course, no
doubt that Porphyry had published a large variety of material, including
presumably the influential De regressu animae, before 300; what we are
concerned with, however, is whether Christian writers made use of any
material derived from Porphyry which is obviously Neoplatonic, rather
than more strictly Platonic or Middle Platonic in content. For, in the
absence of such material, evidence for the knowledge and use of Porphyry
(as distinct from Porphyry's sources) is lacking. In practical terms our
enquiries must boil down to the following questions: the date of the
undoubted responses to Porphyry's Against the Christians by Methodius
and Eusebius of Caesarea as well as the date of Against the Christians
itself; the supposed references to Porphyry in Arnobius of Sicca's
Adversus Nationes; the sources of Lactantius' anti-Christian opponent
Hierocles; and the nature of the Platonic material in Calcidius'
Commentary on the Timaeus. Calcidius in particular, if properly
understood, will help us to appreciate why it is not Neoplatonism, either
that of Porphyry or of Plotinus, which is the dominant mode of Platonism
either in the East or in the West either before the appearance ofEusebius'
Praeparatio, or in the period that follows: the period of the Emperor
Constantine's Address to the Assembly qf the Saints, of the early writings
of Athanasius and of the Council of Nicaea. The Praeparatio, we shall
argue, is to be treated as a case apart, and an important one, but, as an
additional witness to our discussion of the "early Athanasian" period of
Christian intellectual history, we shall also invoke a rather neglected
pagan Platonist of late third-century Alexandria: Alexander of Lycopolis,
author of an extant treatise against the dualist theses of Mani.
i. Observations on the Date qf Porphyry's Against the Christians
First of all we are faced with the matter of the date of the work Against
the Christians. Until recently the dominant view was that it was written
under Claudius Gothicus or Aurelian, 14 but as T. D. Barnes has observed,
this depends on deducing, from the statement of Eusebius that Porphyry
wrote Against the Christians in Sicily, 15 that he must have written it
during his known visit to Sicily between 268 and the early 270s. As
14
For Aurelian see A. Cameron, "The Date of Porphyry's xara xpuntavwv," CQ 18
(1967) 384.
15
Hist. eccl. 6.19.2.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
143
Or. 18.178.
17
'
a:
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
145
146
JOHN M. RIST
as. well; and he would have written it long e~oug? befo~e this for its
existence to have penetrated to the less than maJor City of Sicca in North
Africa. The parallels adduced by Courcelle, however, are all vague and
imprecise. None of them is a doctrine which must be particular)
associated with Porphyry (or for that matter with Plotinus), though it
certainly true that Porphyry and Plotinus may (or did) accept some ~
them as part ofthe general deposit of religious/philosophical debris Which
they inherited. In particular one might suppose that the notion of the viri
novi concerning the pure impeccable soul might have Neoplatonic
associations, but if so Plotinus, as the fount of the doctrine of the upper
soul which remains above the level of sin and ordinary sociallife, 31 would
be the more likely source. However, such doctrines of a pure soul in some
version or other are commonplace among a wide spectrum of philosophers and theologians from the Plato of Republic x to the obscene
Carpocrates and his new-style agapeistic Christians32 -with all sorts of
other in betwe.ens. In fact, so far from there being good reason to suppose
that Arnobius is attacking Porphyry (or even Plotinus), there are good
reasons to think that he is not.
Arnobius indicates in book 1 that he will name his adversaries, 33 and in
book n he does so. As we have seen, they are Hermetists, Platonists and
novi viri. Had he meant Porphyry, why should he not have said so? He is
not, in fact, very clear on the "authorities" of these novi viri, but he does
mention Plato again, 34 and, as we have seen, he makes earlier reference to
Plato, Numenius and Cronius. The influence of the latter two, both on
Porphyry himself and on others of this period such as Calcidius, is
established beyond reasonable doubt. Since Arnobius names them, is it
too much to suppose that he read them: that they, not the unnamed
Porphyry, are the sources of the eclectic positions happily identified as
eclectic by Festugiere?
A further pointer in the same direction is provided if we revert to the
role in anti-Christian polemic of Apollonius of Tyana. We have already
noticed that, according to Eusebius, Sossianus Hierocles was the first to
offer a detailed comparison between Apollonius and Jesus, a task later
attempted by Porphyry. Interestingly, however, Arnobius also knows of
Apollonius and refers to him. Some would infer the influence of
Porphyry. That, however, is most unlikely. Apollonius is allowed no
31
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
147
ial importance, which he surely would have had if Arnobius had had
spec hyry's treatment in mind. Instead he is merely mentioned among a
por? ty of run-of-the-mill magicians like Zoroaster and Julian the
~:~~daean. 35 Arnobius knows nothing of Porphyry's attitude to Apol~us of Tyana- which while having admittedly no direct bearing on
lo:lDe regressu certainly confirms his ignorance of the (ex hypothesi notth t-written) Against the Christians.
ye NoW if the arguments which Arnobius directs against influential
ponents of Christianity are not directed against the author of Against the
~ristians. it seems implausible that they are directed against the author of
the De regressu or any other Porphyrian text, for these works alone
hardly qualify Porphyry as a major opponent of Christianity. At the same
time, it would be more than merely implausible to suppose that when
dealing with the so-called "positive teachings" of the viri novi Arnobius is
thinking of Porphyry's De regressu, while when considering the negative
attitudes of these same no vi viri to Christianity he is referring to someone
.else.
ii. Porphyry and Victorinus
For lengthy comment on Firmicus Maternus' use of Porphyry, seeP. Henry, P/otin
(Louvain 1934) pp. 25-43. Henry believed that Firmicus knows the Life of
and parts of the Enneads, especially Ennead 3.1. That he knows the Life seems
it is probabiy, as Henry argued against Oppermann, the only written source of his
ofPlotinus' death in the Mathesis (8.1.1), datable to between 335 and 337. Neither
detailed descriptions of Plotinus' leprosy, nor other information at his disposal
the appearance of comets) need imply a second written source. (That comets were
to be seen at somewhere near the right time seems clear. See Ho Peng Yoke,
1""'"'"''m and Mediaeval Observations of Comets and Novae in Chinese Sources," in
in Astronomy, ed. A. Beer (Oxford 1962) 5: !57.
'. 'ab Although we may leave aside Henry's vague and quite unconvincing suggestions
. a clear reference to Ennead
. OUtHFirm.reus, know Iedge o f Enn. !. 4 and 1.6, he also clarms
131
e thmks that the phrase "in quadam parte orationis suae" must refer directly to
148
JOHN M. RIST
Plotinus. But this does not follow. Knowledge of the end of chapter 15 of the Life would
be sufficient to explain the rhetorical comment in the Mathesis, which, as Henry himself
admits, is hard to attach to specific texts in Enn. 3.1.
Firmicus' remarks in the Mathesis are those of the "religious" man observing (with
some relish) the fate of a great figure, Plotinus, who paid too little respect to astrology and
stellar destiny. He is probably more interested in Porphyry, perhaps on the trivial grounds
that he can be claimed as in some sense Sicilian. He uses the phrase noster Porphyrius
which has plausibly been taken to refer to a claim of this sort, and we may note that the
commentators on Aristotle suggest that Porphyry's lsagoge was written in Sicily (see J.
Bidez, Vie de Porphyre [Ghent 1913] pp. 58-59); Augustine too calls Porphyry "Sicilian"
We cons. evang. 1.15.23; Retract. 2.31). (For discussion, with some scepticism, Hadot,
Porphyre et Victorinus, p. 84.) Later (AD 347), when Firmicus has turned Christian,
Porphyry's Philosophy from Oracles is denounced (De err. prof. ref. 13.4); that is to be
expected, but there is no evidence that Firmicus gave (or was capable of giving) Porphyry
serious philosophical attention. The condemned and now notoriously anti-Christian
Porphyry is a "bad hat." Denunciation need not entail attention.
37
See the Henry-Hadot edition, csEL 83: 28-61.
38
Augustine, Co11f 7.13.
39 Cf. Aug., De vita beata 4 with the reading Plotini, Henry, Pfotin et /'Occident, pp.
82 ff.; C. acad. 2.5; 3.41.
40
See (at last) the firm statements of R. J. O'Connell, St. Augustine's Early Theory Q{
Man. AD 386-.~91 (Cambridge, Mass. 1968) and his damning assessment (pp. 20 ff.) of the
work of W. Theiler, Porpl!yrios und Augustin (Halle 1933); R. Beutler, "Porphyrios,"
RECA 22~(1953) 275-313, esp. 301-312; P. Courcelle, Recl1erches sur fes CO!l{essions
(Paris 1956) pp. 157-167 and others.
41
The best case for Porphyrian influence on the early Augustine is made by J. J.
O'Meara in "Porphyry's Philosophy from Oracles in Eusebius's Preparatio evangelica and
Augustine's Dialogues ofCassiciacum,"Reci!Aug 6 (1969) 103-139, esp. 122-131.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
149
150
JOHN M. RIST
should be noted that Origen already uses rExvo2oyia to refer to "professional" Greek logic
(perhaps predominantly Stoic), but the Stoic/ Aristotelian distinction had faded by the 4th
century. (Origen, C. Celsum 3.39; cf. Sextus Empiricus, Pyrr. hypot. 2.205.)
4s Socrates, Hist. eccl. 1.9.30-31 (H. G. Opitz, Urkunden zur Geschichte des
arianischen .weites 318-328 [Berlin 1934], Urkunde J3); Gelasius, Hist. eccl. 2.36.
49
See A. Harnack, Geschichte der altchristlichen Literatur, 2 (Leipzig !898) 564 f.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
151
Barnes. "Porphyry," p. 441, points to the great importance of the absence from
of any mention of Porphyry's attack on the authenticity of
s... book of Daniel or of the date of its composition. The Eel. proph. seems to date from
~on after 300.
>.$1 F
?r Julian the "modern" master is larnblichus, Or. 4 046A).
52
VItae soph. 457.
53
Augustine, De Civ. Dei 10.32.
uu'"""'~ Ec/ogae prophetir:ae
152
JOHN M. RIST
Latin text is, as I have stated, the work of Calcidius on the Timaeus
Fortunately this need not occupy much of our time, for in addition to th~
massive text and commentary of J. H. Waszink, 54 we have, following
upon various detailed studies by Waszink's pupils and continuators,ss an~
eminently sane and convincing reappraisal of the problems surrounding
Calcidius' sources from John Dillon. 56 It only remains to conftrm, and
occasionally but not, I think, uninterestingly to enlarge on Dillon's
exposition.
There is no need to discuss at any length the reasons why, until
W aszink, it was generally assumed that the Ossius to whom Calcidius'
work is dedicated, is to be identified, following certain indications in a
number of the manuscripts, with Ossius, bishop of Corduba, ecclesiastiCal
adviser of the emperor from his conversion (and doubtless before) until
some time after the Council of Nicaea. One family of manuscripts has it
that Calcidius was Ossius' deacon. Waszink and others dismiss this
evidence. If Calcidius were a deacon of Ossius of Corduba, he would have
rated a mention by Isidore of Seville (560-630) whose policy it is to boast
of Spanish writers whenever possible. Rather, says Waszink, Ossius may
be an imperial official known of in Milan about 395 57 - or he may be
someone else. Waszink's arguments, as Dillon has shown, are inadequate,
and Dillon's case can be backed up with fresh evidence.
First of all, although it is true that Isidore frequently boasts of Spanish
writers and also that he uses Calcidius' commentary, 58 all that can be
concluded from this is that he may not have known the identity of the
author. But Isidore may also have known of a deacon of Ossius and also
of the name Calcidius as that of the author of the commentary without
identifying the two. To Waszink's second point, that the language of
Calcidius has many features in common with that of late fourth-century
or even later writers, Dillon rightly replies that this is inconclusive:
Calcidius could, but need not, be late fourth century: that is, he might
54 Timaett$ a Ca/cidio trans/at us commentarioque in.~trucftls. Plato Latinus 4 (London/
Leiden 1962).
ss J. C. M. van Winden. Calcidius on Matter: His Doctrine and Sources (Leiden 1959):
J. den Boeft. Ca/cidius on Fate: His Doctrine and Sources (Leiden 1970).
56
Dillon. The Middle P/ato11ists. pp. 401-408.
57 Timaeus a Calcidio. p. xvi. Implausible developments of a Milanese Calcidius are
available: Courcelle. Recherches sur S. Ambroise. pp. 17-24.
58
J. Fontaine. Isidore de Seville et Ia culture classique dans f'Espagne Wi.~igotfliqile
(Paris 1959) p. 658. Dillon. Middle P/atonists. p. 402 seems to suggest that Isidore did not
know the commemary. but Fontaine's texts seem decisive against this: and perhaps all
Dillon means is that Isidore did not know that Calcidius of Corduba wrote the
commentary.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
153
siblY be put into the late fourth century did not the kind of Platonism
pla~dvocates make this unlikely. And Dillon is again right to point out
be t were is nothing peculiarly . Neoplatonic, that is, redolent of the
~atonism of Plotinus and Porphyry (let alone lamblichus) to be found in
~ ~cidius. The sum total of Calcidius' Platonism could be derived from
: ddle Platonic writers, particularly from Numenius. In fact, as W aszink
.~self admits, Calcidius' main sources are the Peripatetic Adrastus and
\ne other writer whose views are very like the Platonism of Numes~us.s9 Dillon himself hesitantly proposes Cronius - we recall him as
nutnoritative among Arnobius' viri novi- as this Platonic source,60 and
~ronius is regillarly mentioned in company with Numenius. 61
There is a further item of information which may help to strengthen
tbis identification. According to Calcidius, Plato did not believe in the
transmigration of human souls into animal bodies. 62 This thesis, argued in
different ways by Porphyry and Iamblichus but not held by Plotinus,
migbt seem to point to a post-Plotinian influence (i.e., that of Porphyry)
:on the text ofCalcidius; 63 but interestingly enough there is just one writer
tbe Platonic/Pythagorean tradition before Plotinus who seems to have
. it: none other than Cronius, in his book On Reincarnation. 64 Cronius,
should add, though little more than a name to us, was regularly read in
of Plotinus and was an influence in the education of Origen. 65
11
Timaeu.5 a Calcidio, pp. xxxv-cvi. Henry and Schwyzer's Index testium (P/otini
3: 422) lists two parallels between Calcidius and Plotinus, 4.5.1.29"32 =ch. 237 and
1112 = ch. 294. Both are too general to indicate derivation.
Dillon, The Middle Platonists, p. 407.
Porphyry, Vita Plot. 14; Iamblichus. De an. (Wachsmuth. pp. 375.12 ff.; 380.6 ff.);
Hist. eccl. 6.19.8. Since Waszink, the most interesting attempt to insist that
Cronius and others are mediated through Porphyry is that of J. den Boeft,
on Fate (l.eiden 1970); idem Calcidius on Demons (l.eiden 1977). But for
chapters 176, 177 and 188, the influence of Middle Platonism, especially Ps.De .falo. is adequate explanation. The account of fate given by Calcidius has
necessarily Plotinian or Porphyrian. nor, as den Boeft interestingly admits. is the
term "One" used in Calcidius' commentary, even in these chapters. As for
den Boeft himself admits it is unlikely that Porphyry "has denied the system
(p. 53). Exactly; this is an unnecessary hypothesis. Middle Platonic exegesis of
Epinomis will account both for Porphyry and for Calcidius.
2
1 f In Tim. 42c, ch. 196.
63
For Iamblichus and Porphyry see Nemesius of Emesa, De IWI. hom. 2. Matthaei,
[ 117 This text may seem ambiguous in the case of Porphyry (who is wrongly held to
'tavour. transmigration by Wallis, Neop/ato11ism, p. 113), but that Porphyry rejected
~ansm~gration into animal bodies is confirmed by Augustine, De Civ. Dei 10.30, and
eneas of Gaza. Po 85: 893. In general see H. Dorrie. "Kontroversen urn die
See!;nwanderung im Kaiserzeitlichen Platonismus." Hermes 85 (1957) 414-435.
Nemesius, De nat. hom. 2, Matthaei, p. 117.
65
Porphyry, Vila Plot. 14; Eusebius; Hist. eccl. 6.19.8.
154
JOHN M. RIST
The lack of any clear evidence for Neoplatonic rather than Mictcti
Platonic influence on Calcidius is obviously important for the dating ofhe
lS
work. Advocates of a later date than the early years of the fourth century
and indeed many advocates of an early fourth-century date as well, hav'
no difficulty in admitting that there is much of Numenius (or Cronius) t e
be found in Calcidius, but claim that this is all mediated throug~
Porphyry's commentary on the Timaeus. 66 It is hard to disprove this, sine
there is no doubt that in his commentary on the Timaeus Porphyry
good use of Numenius; however, the claim is made implausible by the
fact that not only does Calcidius not name Porphyry - perhaps, in view
of the ban, he may have feared to do so! - but much more importantly
that he quotes nothing that is peculiarly Porphyrian or even Plotinian. To
which we must add that whereas Porphyry commented on the whole of
Timaeus, with frequent resort to allegorization, Calcidius is selective and
neglects allegorical interpretation altogether. 67
If we can argue that Calcidius knows no Plotinus and no Porphyry, the
task of dating him to the later part of the fourth century, after Victorious,
becomes far more difficult. The nearer Calcidius is in time to Porphyry,
the less likely he is to have used him. And a date between 324 and the
time of Victorious is, as I have already observed, not the most suitable
period for a Christian to flaunt knowledge of Porphyry's commentary,
even anonymously. But in fact there is a further reason for thinking that
the work was written even before 324, before Christians were accorded
legal recognition
and therefore, incidentally, before bishops obtained
official status in the Roman Empire: Calcidius dedicates his work to
Ossius, but without giving his Christian patron official recognizance, a
neglect hardly likely after 324.68 If Ossius were an imperial official, as
W aszink proposed, the omission of his title becomes additionally bizarre.
Of course, we could still say that Ossius is not an imperial official of the
380s, and indeed that he lived at a time when it would have been
imprudent or unwise to identify him further, that is, before 324, yet that
though named Ossius, he is not Bishop Ossius of Corduba. But then
merely to elaborate such a justification is to highlight its implausibility. All
in all it can safely be concluded (a) that Calcidius' work falls into the early
part of the fourth century, (b) that it is dedicated to Ossius, bishop of
rnau:
66
Thus van Winden. Calcidius, p. 247. He realizes that Calcidius "represents a pre
Plotinian style in the evolution of Platonic thinking," but still prefers unnecessarilY to
introduce Porphyry as an intermediary.
67
Dillon, The Middle Platonists, p. 403.
6
s I owe this point to T. D. Barnes.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
155
69
156
JOHN M. RIST
;n
;:t
73
Numenius, rr. II, 12, 15, 16, Des Places. Plotinus, we should observe, is prepared to
speak of a .~econd god, but not of a first, probably because "first god" might suggest a
Numenian (or other) nous. In his early 6.9 (chronologically no. 9) he allows "first Nature"
(6.9.7.16) and "that (ekeinos) God" (6.9.11.28). Cf. J. M. Rist, 'Theos and the One in Some
Texts of Plotinus," MS 24 (1962) 169-180, though I now think that Plotinus is already
more unwilling to be Numenian than I suggested then. Christ as "second God" is to be
found in Origen. C. Celsum 5.39, 6.61, 7.57. (Numenius is mentioned in 5.38.)
14
Porphyry, Vita Plot. 3.
75 Vila Plot. 14.
76
Vita Plot. 17.
77 Vita Plot. 3.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONJSM"
157
., Elnoc. [81].
PG
I.
Ambrose, De .fide 3.15 (Opitz, Urkunde 21, p. 42). Arius himself specifically rejected
as Manichaean in his letter to Alexander; for Arius it suggested that the Son is a
the Father (Opitz, Urkunde 6, p. 12). Similarly in his Thalia (Athanasius, De
15). Philostorgius, Hist. ecc/. I. 7, claims (possibly correctly) that Ossius and
ct"'"'~>anoer had decided to insert the ofJoouaw, before the Council opened. Philostorgius
.. oes not say, however, that Ossius and Alexander presented to the assembly a ready-made
~~ed ~hat included the homoousios, as claimed by V. C. de Ciercq, Ossius qf Cordova
~:hmgton 1954) p. 257.
See Eusebius' own words in a letter to his congregation (Socrates, Hist. eccl. 1.8).
158
JOHN M. RIST
association with the emperor at Nicaea makes its omission in the Orau011
to the Assembly qf the Saints the more striking; while the history of its
appearance at Nicaea renders its absence in 321 intelligible.
(b) The relationship between the first and second gods is that they are
two substances (ouaiat) with a single perfection. This is certainly
Christianized Platonism in that "subordinationist" ideas have been
expurgated in part, but the Origenist two substances remains81 and the
emperor remains Platonic enough to add, in phraseology surely un.
acceptable after Nicaea, or even after Antioch, that the existence
(hyparxis) of the second god comes from the first. The Council of Antioch
avoids the ambiguous hyparxis and prefers to speak of the Son's being the
image of the Father in all things and of the Father's substance
(hypostasis). 82 Nicaea too seems to have treated ousia and hypostasis as
synonomous, professing one ousia,83 but to have avoided hyparxis,
perhaps as too dangerously associated with and tainted by philosophical
assocations. To speak of the Son's having his hyparxis from the Father
might, in an Arian context, easily be misread. As for the "two substances"
(ouaiat), Ossius found that too unacceptable in Eusebius and Narcissus at
Nicaea itself.
(c) In the last sentence of his analysis of those parts of Plato which he
finds sound, Constantine observes approvingly that "the Father of all
things would be rightly held to be the father of his own Logos." Though
in peaceful times again this kind of deduction might seem harmless, in
times of Arian controversy it might well seem to place the Son too close to
the Father's creation- an Arian thesis clearly denounced at Antioch84 and indeed suggest that he is a creature.
Scrupulous analysis of the Oration to the Assembly qf the Saints might
provide further evidence; sufficient is available for our present purpose,
which is a limited one: to argue that, written in 321, this document gives
81
Cf. Origen. De ora/. 15: i!7:cpo,; Jca7:' ouaiav. For the absence of homoousios in Origen,
see R. P. C. Hanson, "Did Origen apply the word homoousios to the Son?'' in t"pektasis,
Melanges Patristiques offerts au Card. J. Danielou (Paris 1972) pp. 339-347. Origen's
formula is 8uo 'zi1 U'TioiJ'tcitm 7rp6.yf.1.ara iiv 8e 'zi1 of.i.ovolfl xai 'zi1 rauroTI)r. roiJ {iouk/jf.l.aro,; (C.
Celsum 8.12).
82
A Greek version (of E. Schwartz) is to be found in Opitz, Urkunde 18. There is a
suspicious (to the orthodox) use of the verb u7r6.pxstv to be found in Arius' Thalia (see note
79 above); cf. letter ofEusebius ofCaesarea (Opitz, Urkunde 3); for Arius' use of unrjpgs see
G. C. Stead, "The Platonism of Arius," JT/zS 15 (1964) 26.
83 Cf. Eusebius, C. Marcellum 1.4.39, GCS 26: 5-10. Socrates tells us that when in
Alexandria Ossius began to investigate the terms ousia and hypostasis (}list. eccl. 3.7).
84
Opitz, Urkunde 18, pp. 38-39.
159
.~usebius
~~~' ~blished his Chronicle in about 303, but the references to Porphyry may
~ . ~i~nlY occur in the second edition (after 326). 86 He apparently did not know
~~.
s polemic when he wrote the Contra Hieroclem (ca. 303). 87 His
attack was probably in the rapidly compiled though lengthy Against
later we have the Ecclesiastical History where Porphyry is
and, above all, our present concern, the Praeparatio evangelica,
its extensive use both of Porphyry and of Plotinus. Even from the
however, we cannot discover exactly what Porphyry and
Eusebius had read, and beyond that where he obtained his
Of course he had access to the library at Caesarea, presumably
back in some form to the time of Origen, and developed perhaps by
and certainly by Eusebius' master Pamphilus, the martyr and
defender of Origen. What Porphyry do we find in the
? The following works are named: De statuis, 90 Philosophy
Oracles, Recitatio philologica, Against the Christians, Letter to
nebo, De abstinentia, On the Soul in Reply to Boethus. 91
From the writings of Porphyry as we know them in Eusebius we
construct Porphyry's own metaphysical system, or even the major
of it in so far as those lines are Neoplatonic. If we had to describe
metaphysics from Eusebius, we should fail, and fail worse
~
85
160
JOHN M. RlST
of
(a) Praep. ev. 11.21.1 (543o) and Enn. 1.1.8.9-10. This is an allusion
in Plotinus to Numenius' doctrine of nous. Eusebius himself quotes
Numenius On the Soul directly, 95 not through the intermediary of
Plotinus.
(b) Praep. ev. 1 I.l8.14 (538c) and Enn. 5.9.5.28. Again Eusebius
quotes Numenius' On the Soul directly. It is not even clear that Plotinus is
alluding to Numenius here. Only the word vof.to8f:rTJ~ might suggest it.
Originally Henry and Schwyzer did not propose it as Numenian. Their
restraint may well have been proper.
(c) Praep. ev. 15.6.15 (802o) and Enn. 2.1.1.2. Here Eusebius is
quoting not Numenius96 but Atticus97 as p. 342. Again there is no
question of Eusebius' use of the Enneads.
(d) Praep. ev. 15.7.7 (804c ff.) and Enn. 2.5.3.18. Another confusion
(this time on the fifth body) in Henry and Schwyzer. On p. 343 we are
rightly referred to Atticus98 which Eusebius indeed quotes; on p. 424 we
92 For the best brief reconstruction see P. Hadot, "La metaphysique de Porphyre," in
Entretiens Hardt 12. Porpl!yre (Geneva 1966) pp. 125-164 with A. C. Lloyd in Tile
Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Mediaeval Philosophy (Cambridge 1967)
pp. 287-293 and Wallis, Neoplatonism, pp. ll0-ll8.
93
Opera Plotini, 3: 424.
94
Henry, Etats, p. ISS.
95
Fr. 2 (ed. Des Places). fr. 11 (ed. Leemans).
96
As Henry-Schwyz;er, 3: 424.
97
Fr. 4. 87 (ed. Baudry).
98
Fr. 5, 66-69 (ed. Baudry).
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
161
co;
ev. 11.18 (538c 7-8) and Enn. 5.4 (title). In the Etats 101
aeP
that Eusebius quotes from Numenius' flepl -roiJ nwr; &no
al1:iou -co &!.mpov - which sounds rather like the title of
. .4 _ and thinks Eusebius may have Plotinus in mind: first
chapter 18 of Eusebi~s is located between two other chapters ( 1.6
where Plotinus IS quoted; and second because 5.4 IS
number 7 and 5.1 is number I 0. Eustochius, he thinks,
OUJ,.,v-
in chronological order; hence Eusebius, using that
from one treatise to the next.
and Schwyzer have abandoned all this speculation in
of Plotinus.
the results of the discussion thus far: Eusebius, as
has only read the two treatises of Plotinus which so far
that is, Enneads 4. 7 (in book 15 of the Praeparatio) and
1). It is, therefore, to this material that we must now turn,
if we are to make any suggestions about the influence of
,..,,,"'"'" and (importantly) on the Christian tradition which
fact: Eusebius cites only two of Plotinus'. tracts. The
immediately arises is where did he get his knowledge of
as it from Porphyry's edition of the Enneads? If it was,
to assert that that edition was at least obtainable in the
tt<>rr"""'"'"' by about 317 and that (presumably) the library at
)SSe:sse:d a copy. Or was it from what has been claimed to be
Eustochius, in which case we may have to deduce that only
writings.of Plotinus were readily available in about 317 a comparatively small number? Or, as has sometimes been
does Eusebius' text go back to the apparently good copies of
:
16!
P. ISS.
162
JOHN M. RIST
102
103
Henry, Recherches.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
163
164
JOHN M. RIST
from the treatises in the hands of Amelius or from a copy of these or from
some other source such as Longinus. Ameli us, we recall, had a good deal
but not all, of Plotinus, and Eusebius knew the writings of Amelius, or a~
least his comments on John's Gospel. 105 Perhaps the school of Amelius did
indeed affect the Christian community at Caesarea, either in the time of
Pamphilus or in that of Eusebius himself. This seems to be at least the
likeliest alternative.
There is, perhaps, a further text which may be considered at this point.
The Aristotelian commentator Elias preserves what he calls a quotation
from a single book of Plotinus On Voluntary Death; 106 Henry and
Schwyzer print it after the treatise On Suicide. 107 Westerink has argued
strongly that this material, to which parallels can be found in other late
Neoplatonic sources, 108 derives in the first place either from Proclus'
commentary on the Enneads or from a commentary on Plato's Phaedo.
That may be true, but the source of the material would still be Plotinus
himself; and if so, presumably not from Porphyry's edition. That we have
non-Porphyrian Plotinus was argued by Henry, 109 and presumably we
have to agree. The choices are Porphyrian Plotinus, which it is probably
not (unless by chance all our manuscripts of the Enneads and the
archetype are defective as in 4. 7 .8 5); or non-Plotinus, which is possible but
which there is no good reason to suppose; or Plotinus from some other
source. That other source could be Eustochius, but why should it be, since
all we know of his "edition" is that it included Ennead 4.4? More likely
the origin of the material again is Apamea, latter-day home of Amelius. Or
if not that, Longinus.
But we should recall that Amelius did not publish an edition of
Plotinus; he had a collection of material. So there is no reason to suppose
that all his material reached Eusebius. In fact Eusebius may well have
known little if any more than the two treatises of Plotinus which he
quotes. We shall have to bear this possibility in mind as we consider the
more general matter of the dissemination of Plotinus' text among
Christian communities in the fourth century. And where better to start
than in Alexandria, the most important of the Eastern sees and long a
105 On Amelius see Praep. ev. 11.18.26. Cf. H. Dorrie, "Une exegese neoplatonicienne
du Prologue de J'Evangile deS. Jean (Amelius chez Eusebe, Prep. r!v. II, 19.1-4)," in
Epektasis. pp. 75-87; though Dorrie's speculation on the sources of Augustine, De Civ. Dei
10.29 is suspect.
106
Prof. Phil. 6, ed. Busse, CAG 18: 15.23-16.2.
107
Enn. 1.9.
108
L G. Westerink, "Elias und P1otin," BZ 57 (1964) 26-32.
109
"Vers Ia reconstitution de J'enseignement oral de P1otin," BAB 23 (1937) 337.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
165
PAGAN ALEXANDRIA,
270-325
But we find nothing. Already in Plotin et l'Occident 110 Henry had pointed
to the comparatively slight influence of Plotinus in the East during the
fourth century, though, as we have already shown, he may have misstated his position in detail. Plotinus himself, ~f course, wrote nothing
before leaving Alexandria. Of his fellow-pupils with Ammonius, Origen
and Erennius, we know comparatively little, 111 but it is certain that Origen
followed Middle Platonic metaphysics in making an intellect the first
principle of reality and in identifying that intellect not with the One
"beyond Being" but with Being itself. 112 Longinus too, who had attended
the lectures of Ammonius and Origen in Alexandria113 and who later
taught in Athens and Palmyra, probably took a similar position, 114 despite
his having a detailed knowledge of Plotinus' work and a great admiration
for its author. I leave the matter of Origen the Christian aside for the
moment. At the time ofPlotinus' death, therefore, it would be reasonable
to assume that the Middle Platonism of Origen and Longinus was still
dominant in Alexandria; and it was to remain so for more than a century
at least.
We have a further important piece of evidence for late third century
the treatise in which Alexander of Lycopolis criticizes the
...... c.. ..,u.u of Mani, recently translated into English and commented by Van
der Horst and Mansfeld. !IS Alexander seems to have been a professional
active in a philosophical school, 116 teaching in Alexandria not
uo P. 15.
Porphyry, Vita Plot. 3, 14, 20. The fragments of Origen have been collected by K.
Origenes der Neuplatoniker (Munich 1962). Weber's speculations about Origen
Ammonius are unreliable: I should prefer to call Origen a Middle Platonist despite his
cf. Dillon, The Middle P/atonists, p. 382. His notion of a first principle is probably the
!li{SIUbjectofthe work The King is the Sole Creator, for which see below and Porphyry, Vita
3.
112
Proclus, In Plat. Thea/. 2.4, ed. Portus pp. 87 f. (Weber fr. 7).
113
Vita Plot. 20.
114
Proclus, In Tim. 1. 332.24 (ed. Diehl); cf. Armstrong, "The Background," p. 393.
15
(
~ P. W. Van der Horst and J. Mansfeld, An Alexandrian Platonist against Dualism
LLeiden .1974). They have used Brinkmann's 1895 edition of the Greek text, Alexandri
Ycopo/uani contra Manic/wei opiniones disputatio. For what follows see especially Van
de r Horst and Mansfeld pp. 6-4 7.
116
'
Ed. Brinkmann, p. 8.14, ch. 5; Vander Horst-Mansfeld, p. 58.
166
JOHN M. RIST
much before the year 300, though Van der Horst and Mansfeld misle
in calling him a Neoplatonist. 117 His awareness of and concern Wi~~
Manichaeism is of great interest: he regards it as a Christian heresy l!s
apparently sharing common ground on the matter with Arius and
giving us important evidence about an intellectual concern of both paga ~
and Christians in Alexandria around 300.
ns
Alexander is not a Neoplatonist; rather his theories bear a marked
similarity with those of the pagan Origen, 119 in particular in that he POsits
a first principle which is not a Plotinian One but an intellect - a fact
which should not surprise us since Origen apparently wrote a major work
entitled The King is the Sole Creator some time between 260 and 265, in
the reign of Gallien us, 120 that is, when he was quite old and familiar With
the views of Plotinus. 121 Alexander may even have heard Origen lecture in
Alexandria when he himself was young. Beyond doubt the influence of
Origen as an Alexandrian master lasted for the best part of two centuries:
he is cited by Hierocles (early fifth century) as a mainstream Platonist
carrying on the influence of Ammonius Saccas. Hierocles lists the series of
masters as Ammonius, Plotinus, Origen, Porphyry, Iamblichus and his
successors. 122
Alexander talks of hypostases, 123 and makes Nous supreme, but he does
not call it One even though it is in some senee "beyond Being." 124 The
word "hypostasis" is not a regular Middle Platonic term; its philosophical
importance derives particularly from Plotinus and Porphyry, but its use
by Alexander need not indicate influence from these sources. We should
thu
P. 10.
Alexander. ed. Brinkmann ch. 2. Vander Horst-Mansfeld p. 52. For corroboration
of this view see A. Henrichs and L. Koenen, "Ein griechischer Mani-Codex," ZP 5
(1970) 97-216. esp. 140. For Arius see Opitz, Urkunde 6; 6!1oouut01; is attributed to Mani.
119
Van der Horst-Mansfeld evoke Ammonius (Saccas) here (pp. 8-9), .though justly
criticizing Theiler's "reconstruction" of Ammonius and his principle for doing so (i.e ..
where Porphyry differs from Plotinus he goes back to Ammonius!l. I should prefer to say
even less about Ammonius than Van der Horst-Mansfeld, while a fortiori rejecting W.
Theiler's excesses in his "Ammonios und Porphyrios," in Emretiens Hardt 12 Porphyre
(Geneva 1966). pp. 85-121 ( Umersuchungen zur am. Lit. [Berlin 1970] pp. 519-542).
120
Vita Plot. 3.
121
Origen heard Plotinus in Rome. presumably during Porphyry's time there (263-268
AD) (Vita Plot. 14).
122 Cf. Photius. Bibf. 214. 251 (ed. Henry), and J. M. Rist. "Hypatia," Phoenix 19
( 1965) 218. though the influence of Iamblichus is much greater than I then believed.
123
Brinkmann, pp. 24.18-19.
124 Brinkmann. p. 39.18; Plato. Rep. 509B. Cf. H. Dorrie. "Zum Ursprung d~r
neuplatonischen Hypostasenlehre," Hermes 82 0954) 331-342. and idem. "HypostasJs,
Wort und Bedeutungsgeschichte." NAG 0955) 35-92. Note the use of unouaut; in the
Tf1eaetetus Commentary. ed. Diels-Sohubart. col. 63.20, 68.3); and "Hypostasis." P 64
t17
118
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
167
that Alexander does not talk of three hypostases in the characupte. allY Plotinian manner exhibited by the title of Ennead 5.1: On the
teristlC
.. Hypostases. t2S
'hree Baste
Alexander's use of hypostases tells us that the word was by his time
nt in Alexandria, not that he got it from Porphyry or Plotinus; and
~u;re d we know that it was used there, perhaps particularly in the
10
~tian circles with which Alexander was familiar. A somewhat similar
~h~tion seems to exist in regard to his attitude to matter, very well
~t~urnented by Van der Horst and Mansfeld. Alexander believes that
0
atter derives from the first principle which, as we have seen, is Intellect
Ill a vieW similar to that advanced by certain Neopythagoreans, 126 but
, which cannot be found in Middle Platonism. The derivation of matter,
b.owever, was at the centre of controversy, as a well-known passage of the
heretical Hermogenes (criticized by Tertullian) makes clear. According to
Berrnogenes, God made things (a) out of Himself, or (b) de nihilo, or (c)
of something else. 127 The last is Hermogenes' view, and most Middle
would have agreed; the first (out of Himself) seems to be that of
, 128 though he wishes to understand this in some sort of nonsense (n:l erpEgij<; pivovro<; 7:0U 8t:oiJ unocmiUEl<; cluw). The clumsy
Iuu'"'"'1'"""' nature of this formulation should be compared with the
argument of Plotinus for a totally transcendent first principle
makes things and leaves them outside of itself. 129 Though
view has resemblances to Plotinus', as with the use of the
"hypostasis" itself, he can hardly have known Plotinus' own work
produced such confusion. Alexander's ~ti:vovro<; may be designed to
the First Principle from "movement," thus reminding us of
static first principle, 130 and contradicting Origen.
to the relation between matter and evil Alexander is simplistic.
wishes to argue both that matter is the last product deriving
from the One, and that it is evil in its effects, though not in
for in itself it is absolute non-being. And he does not find the
125
126
SUpposed.
168
JOHN M. RIST
reconciliation of the two aspects of his theory easy. 131 Porphyry's view is
in certain important respects close to that of Plotinus; for him too there is a
special sense in which matter is a "cause" of evil. 132 Alexander's solution
is simple: he nowhere connects matter with evil - conveniently enough
in a treatise against the Manichaeans - but leaves unanswered (as far as
we are informed) the question of the reason for the soul's fall. There is
nothing in his comments to suggest that he knew the more complex
Plotinian philosophical position, let alone that he rejected it.
Mansfeld, however, finds a close parallel between Alexander and
Porphyry in their rejection of the theory that the movement of matter is
random, 133 a Middle Platonic view used by Manito provide a definition of
matter itself. 134 Mansfeld points out that in attacking Mani Alexander is at
the same time attacking both Plato and a strong tradition in Middle
Platonism. 135 Does Porphyry argue similarly? Mansfeld finds the
"conceptual parallel striking," for Porphyry, according to Philoponus
'
argued against the Middle Platonists that Timaeus 30A and 53s suggest
that it is not unformed matter, but composites of form and matter which
are in confused motion. 136 But it is not clear from this what Porphyry
thought the "native state" of matter is, though in general one might say
that both Plotinus and Porphyry, in so far as they view matter as nonexistent, could hardly view it as in motion. Alexander, in contrast, does
not think of matter as non-existent at all. It does exist, though it is not a
body nor strictly an incorporeal, nor even an individual ho& rt). 137 Thus
though there may appear some similarity between Alexander and
Porphyry on matter, it is not sufficient to support the derivation of one
from the other. Alexander's version is simpler, showing not that he
rejected Porphyry, but more likely that he was ignorant of him.
What then are we to conclude? That Alexander is some kind of Middle
Platonist, probably considerably influenced by Origen and possibly
(though indeterminably) by Ammonius. As such he is a most important
testimony to the non-importance of Plotinus and Porphyry in later third-
13 1
Recently varied views on this topic are to be found in J. M. Rist, "Plotinus on
Matter and Evil," Phr011esis 6 (1961) 154-166: D. O'Brien. "Plotinus on Evil," Le
Neoplatonisme (Paris 1971) pp. 113-146: J. M. Rist. "Plotinus and Augustine on Evil," in
Plotino e il Neoplatollismo ill Oriente e in Occidente (Rome 1974) pp. 495-508.
m xaxoi Jj UA'rf (Sent. 30.2, ed. Mommert p. 16.6-7); Van der Horst-Mansfeld p. 20).
133 Vander Horst-Mansfeld, p. 21.
134
Ed. Brinkmann pp. 5.8, 10.5, 26.1.
m See Van der Horst-Mansfeld for references.
136
Philoponus, De aet. mundi 546.5-547.19 (ed. Rabe).
137
Ed. Brinkmann p. 10.19-20.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
169
Hierocles apud Photius, Bib/. 214, 251; In Car. A ur., ed. Mullach, p. 28.12-15; Rist,
ypatia," pp. 218-219. Wallis notes the importance of post-Porpl!yrian Platonism in
Jiierocles; we leap over Plotinus and Porphyry (Neoplatonism, p. 143).
139
\'(:;
On matter see Photius, Bib/. 251, 461A-B, ex nihilo according to Wallis (Neop(atonism, p. 143); also In Carm. A ur., Mullach p. 71.11.
140
.
Rist, "Hypatia," p. 216.
141
Ibid., p. 219. The most recent study ofHierocles, that of I. Hadot, Le probleme du
Neop/atonisme alexandrin: Hieroc/es et Simplicius (Paris 1978) has persuaded me of the
existence of far more Iamblichean elements than I had previously supposed, but I am not
convinced by the argument (pp. 115-116) that Hierocles must have taught that the One is
the supreme principle, even though he does not say this in our texts. It has been claimed
that Syrianus and Proclus too, though pupils of Plutarch, were perhaps more influenced
elsewhere - in their case by the Syrian school (see E. Evrard, "Le Maitre de Plutarque
d'Athenes," ACt [1960]398). Hierocles' own divergences from Plutarch would, of course,
be on different lines.
142
Synesius, Ep. 136.
170
JOHN M. RIST
already had one teacher, Origen, who though soaked in Plato could
1
come to replace Plato as an educational authority. Athanasius symbot so
an important decision of fourth century Christianity: in important resp~Zes
he became a greater than Origen, while at the same time joining Origencts
a founder-figure of the ever more autonomous Christian culture.
as
F.
ARIUS
143
Among other studies we may note the following: T. E. Pollard, "Logos and Son in
Origen, Arius and Athanasius," SP 2 (Berlin 1957) 282-287; idem, 'The Origins of
Arianism," JThS 9 (1958) 102-111; idem, "The Exegesis of Scripture and the Arian
Controversy," BJRL 41 (1959) 414-429; idem, Johannine Christianity and the Early
Church (Cambridge 1970); E. Boularand, L'heresie d'Arius et Ia ':foi" de Nicee (Paris
1972); these works emphasize the importance of Lucian of Antioch. The next group
represents those who emphasize primarily Alexandrian influences on Arius: M. Wiles,
"In Defence of Arius," JThS 13 (1962) 339-347; G. C. Stead, 'The Platonism of Arius,"
JThS 15 (1964) 16-31; L. W. Barnard, 'The Antecedents of Arius," VigChr 24 (1970) 172188.
For judicious mixing of sources see M. Simonetti, "Le origini dell'Arianesimo,"
RSLR 7 (1971) 317-330; H. I. Marrou, "L'Arianisme comme phenomt!me alexandrin."
CRAI (1973) 533-542.
144
Theodoret, Hist. eccl. 1.5.3, 11.7-8 (Opitz, Urkunde 1, p. 3).
145
So G. Bardy, Recherches sur S. Lucien d'Antioch et son ecole (Paris 1936) p. 194.
146
Pollard, Johannine Christianity, pp. 142 ff.
147
Philostorgius, Hist. eccl. 2.14, 3.15.
148
Epiphanius, Ancor. 33 (PG 43: 77).
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
171
rnple at Antioch) that not all the Lucianists were willing to go all the
ex:a with the blunt formulations of Arius.
warriUS probably admired Lucian for his scriptural exegesis, but he might
e found similar (though perhaps inferior) versions of the same kind of
}la~ook - at least in so far as it denied the validity of Origen's allegorical
ou thod -- at home in Alexandria, and in the person of Bishop Peter, 149 a
~etirn of the Great Persecution. Peter, admittedly himself not always
~~~ndlY to Arius, 150 may also have denounced Origen more generally as a
:ublemaker for his predecessors in the see of Alexandria. m
tr AriUS then is an Alexandrian, and could well have known something of
the pagan philosophy in Alexandria in his time. Scholars have detected
parallels between his account of the origin of the Son and the views of
Albinus and Atticus on the existence of time before the cosmos. 152 Like
Alexander of Lycopolis (and Athanasius) Arius worried about Manichaeism: homoousios sounded to him to smack of it, 153 and it was indeed
prominent enough, at least in Africa, to be denounced and penalized in a
rescript of the Emperor Diocletian in the 300s. 154 Yet beside his readings
Lucian, we may detect a variety of possible sources for Arius within the
tradition. Origen 155 and Theognostus 156 used the word x1:iap.a of
Dionysius of Alexandria clearly disliked homoousios as Sabellian
Christ a noiTJp.a. 157 Basil made it clear: Dionysius was one of the
of Arianism. 158 And there is also Pieri us, a clear subordinationist, 159
as an allegorizer admittedly distasteful to Arius. All in all there
little reason to go outside the purely Christian tradition, seasoned
172
JOHN M. RIST
160
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
173
dean metre, 165 points in the same direction. I should prefer, in fact, to
S~tak of the Cynics rather than of the Stoics; and if that is right it provides
thtnber evidence not of Arius' use of the positive philosophy of his day,
rurt
' .
f 't
bUt of his reJeCtton o 1 .
G.
174
JOHN M. RISf
It has been much debated why Athanasius wrote these treatises: they
purport to be aimed at pagans, but the "reader" is often assumed to be
Christian. F. L. Cross argued that they are primarily a theological exercise
set by Athanasius to himself, 170 a summary of what he has learned frotn
his teachers, whose books, he somewhat mysteriously tells us, he does not
have to' hand. 171 Naturally such a view, eminently attractive though it is
would be rendered more or less likely if we could be certain of the date of
composition. Traditionally this has been held to pre-date the Arian
controversy - since Arius is nowhere mentioned - but there have been
objectors, 172 most recently and powerfully Charles Kannengiesser. i73
Kannengiesser's best argument is that in those of Athanasius' Festal
Letters written before his exile of 335-336, there is no explicit connection
drawn between the rending of the body or robe of Christ and the
particular heresy of Arius; afterwards there is. Thus after 337, the death of
Constantine, argues Kannengiesser, Athanasius feels no inhibitions about
making the association; previously he avoided it for fear of offending the
emperor. Now in the De incarnatione (24) there is a reference to the same
topic, heresy and rending, but no explicit mention of Arius; for Kannengiesser, however, reference to him is implicit; hence the De incarnatione
appears to have been written at a time when Athanasius was deliberately
avoiding mention of Arius, such as during his exile; that is why, Kannengiesser adds, he had no books.
But Kannengiesser's argument is inadequate, depending as it does on
the dubious assertion of an allusion to Arius in chapter 24. While it
suggests that Athanasius might have written De incarnatione about 336, it
in no way compels us to believe that he actually did so. In fact, a
somewhat similar argument could be used to suggest that Athanasius
actually wrote the De incarnatione before about 324- under Licinius,
not Constantine. For in that year (or perhaps as early as 321) Alexander,
bishop of Alexandria and Athanasius' superior, sent out a circular letter174
in which he accuses the Arians, and Arius himself, of rending the robe of
Christ which the executioners did not divide. Now, it might be said, since
170
The Swdy Q( St. A thanasius (Oxford 1945) p. 14, followed by Meijering, OrthodoxY
and Platonism, p. 106.
111
C. Gentes I.
112 H. Berkhof thinks they are too mature to be this early (Kerkeliike Klassieken
[Wageningen 1949] p. 23); this is answered by Meijering, Orthodoxy, p. 109.
m "Le temoignage des Lettres Festales... ," RSR 52 (1964) 91-100, viewed with
suspicion by Pollard, Joflannine Christianity, p. 131 and followed (confusedly) by R. W.
Thomson in A thanasius: Contra Gemesl De lncarnatione (Oxford 1971) p. xxi.
174
Theodoret, Hist. eccl. 1.4 (Opitz, Urkunde 14).
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
175
the text of John 19 had been specifically and officially related to Arius
even by Alexander, the fact that this association is not mentioned in the De
incarnatione means that Athanasius was then ignorant of it, that is, that
the De incarnatione is prior to 324.
Kannengiesser's date, therefore, is no more than a possibility, and in
fact it is a possibility which has been proved to be mistaken, and that on
the basis of a text of Contra gentes cited by Kannengiesser himself. 175 In
chapter 9, Athanasius says that until recently, and perhaps even up to
now, the Senate at Rome has deified emperors. 176 According to Kannengiesser this must put Contra gentes between 324 (the death of Licinius)
and 339 (Athanasius' first visit to Rome itself). But that is incredible;
Athanasius certainly knew that, whatever honours were bestowed on
Constantine at his death, emperors were not deified between 324 and 339.
In fact, he is referring to the last known deification before the time of
Julian, either of Diocletian, as Eutropius says, 177 or, more likely, of
Maximian, as divus Maximianus on the coins attests. 178 The year is 318.
Plus or minus, that is the date of Contra gentes- De incarnatione. It is
thus indeed an early work, and in it we find the Middle Platonism that
Athanasius would have met, as we have seen, in the schools of
Alexandria, together with an opposition to heresies primarily viewed as
dualistic accounts of creation, such as Arius also seems to have
abhorred. 179 In other words heresy is viewed against a late third rather
than a fourth century background: it is Mani, not Arius.
Granted that 318 is the approximate date of the treatise Contra
gentes De incarnatione, we can allow ourselves to be impressed by the
implicitly non-Arian theology to be found there. This is not the place to
upon detailed discussion, but we can simply assert that already here
there is no trace of "subordinationist" theology of an Arian or an Origenist
type: let a single example suffice, the use by Athanasius of the phrase
dxwv arrapaAAaXTOG" 180 to describe the kind of likeness the Son has to the
Father. He did not drop this language in his Orationes contra Arianos, and
one can presume that he acquired it either from his theological teachers or
175
176
JOHN M. RIST
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
177
!s
186
178
JOHN M. RlST
CoNCLUDING REMARKS:
270-325
What has been exposed in this section is a sketch, but it is a sketch which
already embodies an important fact: intellectual life in Christian circles
was reformed in a number of fundamental respects during the period
which culminated in the Council of Nicaea. At that Council, a
190
SeeM. Aubineau, "Les ecrits des. Athanase sur 1a virginite," in his Recllercl!es
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
179
94
95
180
JOHN M. RIST
INTRODUCTION
B.
Traditionally Porphyry died about 305; I have argued that about 310 may
be more appropriate. Traditionally Iamblichus died about 325, 200 or
330; 201 we have no evidence that he survived beyond 319, 202 but he may
m Cf. Gregory of Nyssa. Ep. 13.4 (po 46: 1049A) with A. J. Festugiere. Antioc/Je
pai'enne et clm!tieune (Paris 1959) p. 409 and M. Aubineau, Gregoire de Nysse, Le Traite
de Ia virgiuite (Paris 1966) p.A5.
198
Gregory of Nazianzus, Or. 5.23.24; cf. Or. 43.22-23.
199 The town's culture is passed over quickly in modern works, such as those of Gallay
and Ruether on Gregory of Nazianzus.
200
J. Bidez. "Le philosophe Jamblique et son ecole," REG 32 (1919) 29-40. esp. p. 32.
201
G. Mau. RECA 9 (1916) 645.
202
SoT. D. Barnes. "A Correspondent oflamblichus," GrRoBySt 19 (1978) 99-106.
The correspondent is the Pseudo-Julian whose letters were once thought to be the
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
181
emperor's. Ep. 184 appears to be the latest of the letters and to be datable to 319. Some
time after that Sopater (at Licinius' court, it seems, according to Epp. 184 and 185) moved
to the court of Constantine, but after Licinius' death (Eunapius, Vitae Sop h. 462; Zosimus,
Hist. nova 2.40.3).
203
See H. D. Saffrey, "Abamon, pseudonyme de Jamblique," in Philomathes: Studies
and E~.mys in the Humanities in Memory qf Philip Mer/an, edd. R. B. Palmer and R.
Hamerton-Kelly (The Hague 1971) pp. 227-239 on the rivalry between Porphyry and
lamblichus.
204
So Dillon, lamb/ichus, pp. 9 ff.
205
h'
The odd mix is noticed by Wallis, Neoplatonism, p. 143, who apparently misses its
tstoncal significance and explains it exclusively in terms of Hierocles' dullness of wit.
182
JOHN M. RJST
PHILOSOPHY AT ATHENS,
250-355
206 See the edition of Proclus' Platonic Theology by H. D. Saffrey and L. G. Westerink,
I (Paris 1968) xliv.
207 A. A. Barb, "The Survival of Magic Arts," in The Co11flict, ed. A. Momigliano,
p. 115: Ammianus Marcellinus, xxix.i.42.
208
For Hierius, see Dillon, lambliclws, p. 14; Ammonius, In Anal. Pr. 31, 16.
20g Eunapius, Vitae soph. 469.
210
Saffrey-Westerink, Platonic Theology, 1: xlii.
211 For Theodorus, see Wallis, Neoplatonlsm, p. 95.
212 See G. Murray, Five Stages Q{ Greek Religion (London 1935) pp. 100 ff. for a
version of this. Dodds, in an additional note in Murray (reimpression 1946, p. 181) finds
P1otinian influence in many sections of Salh,1stius, but wisely does not attempt
documentation. For the neglect of the Neoplatonism available in Asia Minor by HilarY of
Poitiers when in exile there see H. D. Saffrey, "S. Hilaire et Ia Philosophie," in Hilaire et
son temps (Paris 1969), esp. pp. 251,255.
21 3 Dio Cassius 72.31.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
183
f the Academy, 214 though they need not have used the original site and
214
That earlier Platonists could (at Athens) be said to be "in the Academy" (per hap~
eta{Jhorically) is clear in the age of Plutarch (De E apud Delphos, 387 f.).
215
1. 6\ J. Lynch, Aristotle's School (Berkeley 1972) pp. 177-189 .
.H \ So Dillon, The Middle Platonists, p. 248, though Dillon notes that Eusebius (Chron.
i;238) does not speak of Atticus as head of the Academy, but simply as a Platonist.
17
/
"f'orphyry, Vita Plot. 15, 20; RECA. Suppl. 8 (1956) 853, s.v. Theodotus (19a), and
.?16\ 921 s.v. Eubulus 07<0. Athenian chair-holders made a habit of anti
nstoteljanism, e.g. Atticus.
211
184
JOHN M. RJST
222
Ibid., xlii.
223
Epp. 11-13.
Eunapius, V. Soph. 474.
224
225
226
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
185
D.
186
JOHN M. RJST
"Aetius," p, 558, n. l.
C. Eun. 2.404 (ed. Jaeger, 1: 344.13).
234
Dillon.lambliclws, p. 22; Proclus, In Crat., ed. Pasquali, p. 56.15.
m Didask. 6.
36
'
Iamblichus, De myst. 257-259. For Iamblichus' discussion see S. Gersh, From
lamblicflus to Eriugena (Leiden 1978) pp. 303-304. For Origen (and beyond) see Danietou.
"Eunome l'arien," p. 424,
233
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
187
231
See Wickham, "Aetius," p. 561, for references; also Vandenbussche, "La part de Ia
dialectique," p. 49, n. 1.
238
C. Eun. 1.9; PG 29: 532AB.
239
Wickham, "Aetius," p. 561; Gregory of Nyssa, C. Eun. 2.411.1, ed. Jaeger, I: 346.
z40 Wickham, "Aetius," p. 560.
241
Ibid., p. 56 Ln. I. Note Basil's reference to Chrysippus: C. Eun. 1.5; PG 29: 516a-c;
cf. Jerome, Comm. in Naum. proph. 2.15. (PL 25: 1269c).
188
JOHN M. RIST
them cited by Diogenes Laertius, 242 but this text derives from Diocles of
Magnesia, and perhaps ultimately from Chrysippus. Neither Diogenes nor
Chrysippus is likely to have influenced Eunomius directly. We should
note that the term epinoia itself does not occur in Diogenes. It does occur
however, in a passage of Sextus Empiricus, 243 which may or may not b~
of ultimately Stoic origin, but which appears in Sextus to be taken from an
utterance of Aenesidemus about Plato and Democritus. Here, we note
epinoia does occur, as do pygmies (but not giants) and centaurs. But th~
language is slightly different from that of Eunomius. Whereas Eunomius
has wvOc:a-u;, Sextus has buauvOc:att;; where Eunomius has aug1)a~t; Sextus
has rcapaug1)a~q. Even granted, therefore, that the doctrine is perhaps
ultimately Stoic, we may suggest that by the time of Sextus it was
commonplace
and it probably got into the books of the grammarians
and was there available for Eunomius. Such books, I suspect, are the
common source both for Eunomius' interest in the Cratylus and for his
"Stoic" language about epinoiai; even Danielou is well aware that they
also listed various theories of names, including the ~mystical" one
espoused by Eunomius.
Wickham has a further proposal about the origins of the Anomoean
theory of names, quite unconnected with the Stoics, which is very
attractive: namely that it was originally developed as a hermeneutical
principle for Biblical studies244 - Aetius was a pupil of the "Lucianisf'
Athanasius of Anazarbus - and that Aetius later applied it in general
theological debate. That, of course, is a suggestion pointing in exactly the
opposite direction to that of Danielou:
Danielou's theory about Neoplatonic influence on Eunornius has to be
rejected. Before leaving the matter, however, we may comment on a
historical question which encouraged Danielou to propose it. Aetius
seems to have enjoyed the favour of Julian's brother Gallus at Antioch;
and, apart from other visits to. Julian, he was sent by Gallus, according to
Philostorgius,245 on a mission to dissuade Julian from "Hellenism" in 351.
Hence, it might be supposed, Aetius enjoyed the favour of Julian and
might be influenced by the latter sufficiently at least to read the writings of
Julian's mentors, the post-Iamblichean Neoplatonists. A possible theory
indeed, it has no concrete evidence in its favour, and it is safe to discard it.
242
243
244
245
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
E.
189
190
JOHN M. RIST
CoNCLUSIONS:
325-355
INTRODUCTION
The survey which I have now completed brings us up to the time when
Basil was a student in Athens. Its general aims were as follows: to suggest
that the kind of Platonism to be found in the schools which Basil attended
at that period was largely of the Middle Platonic type, and that the
importance of the philosophical work of Plotinus and Porphyry was
minimal; to add that the only possible prominent variant on Middle
Platonism to be found in these schools was the more exotic tradition
stemming from Iamblichus - a tradition which was neglected or rejected
by Christians both at the theoretical level and soon, in the person of
Julian, at the political level also. Furthermore, that Basil's immediate
Christian predecessors and "authorities" were also brought up in what
may be broadly called the Middle Platonic tradition and not in the more
up-to-date philosophy of Plotinus and Porphyry. Hence one might argue a
priori that it is very unlikely that we would find more than limited use of
Plotinus and Porphyry, let alone Iamblichus, in Basil's own writings. Of
course, it could be objected that Basil could have become deeply versed in
the Plotinian tradition after his student days. Given the nature of his
career, that again might seem unlikely. It is my intention now. however,
to consider how far this a priori view of Basil's philosophical initiation
agrees with what we find in his writings. That investigation has some
thing of the charm, excitement, suspense and unexpected denouement of a
detective story.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
191
Let us begin with a survey of the Basilian material which scholars have
often connected with Plotinus. The first modern scholar to claim
significant influence of Plotinus on Basil was Jahn, 248 whose work has
been taken up and elaborated by Paul Henry in chapter 5 of Les Etats du
texte de Plotin. 249 Henry claims that Basil makes use of Plotinus as
follows:
in EGNaz. [2] he uses Enn. 5.1 and 6.9;
in the Hexaemeton he uses Enn. 1.6 and 2.8;
in the C. Eun. he uses 2.8 and 5.1;
in HFide [15] he uses 1.6, 5.1 and 6.9;
in De Spiritu Sancto he uses 1.6, 1.7, 2.9, 5.1, 5.8, 6.7 and 6.9;
in the De spiritu he uses 5.1.
To this list Danielou added a mention of Plotinian material in the De
baptismo, 250 though he gives no precise references to support his claim.
But by the time Henry (with H. R. Schwyzer) completed the Index
Testium of their text of Plotinus, 251 the list had shrunk again to read thus:
in the De spiritu Basil uses 5.1;
in the De Spiritu Sancto he refers to the title of 5.1;
in HFide [15] he uses 5.1 and 6.9.
The main reason for these more modest claims was the appearance of
Dehnhard's monograph entitled Das Problem der Abhiingigkeit des
von Plotin. 252 Dehnhard's basic thesis is that in the youthful De
(written about 360 ?) Basil indeed quotes Ennead 5.1, but that the
'"w.....,,.. material is "controlled" by Basil's use of various texts of Origen
Eusebius, as well as of the Creed of Gregory Thaumaturgus, the
of Cappadocia. Later on, argues Dehnhard, in 375, when Basil
to write the De Spiritu Sancto for Amphilochius of !conium, he
, among other sources, not on Plotinus, but on his own earlier De
, which itself, of course, depends substantially on Plotinus. In the
Spiritu Sancto, for Dehnhard, there is no direct influence of Plotinus.
192
JOHN M. RIST
1. What is the significance, if any, of the fact that De sp. only uses 5.1?
2. Is the author of De sp. Basil, and if not, who is he?
3. Is Dehnhard's thesis correct that De Sp. S. 9 depends on De sp. for its
Plotinian material?
4. Can we now assert that there is no Plotinian influence in De Sp. S.
outside chapter 9 ?
5. Does Basil in De Sp. S. use Plotinus directly at all?
If these matters can be clarified, one can turn to the possibility of other
Neoplatonic influences on Basil, thence to the wider and more general
question of Basil's use of Plato and earlier Platonists.
B.
5.1
There is no reason to believe that the author of De sp. uses any text of
Plotinus other than Ennead. 5.1. There is, however, equally no immediate
reason to assume that he knew no other text of Plotinus than Ennead 5.1.
Now we have already observed that 5.1 is one of the two texts of Plotinus
which are used by Eusebius of Caesarea in his Praeparatio evange/ica. It
is therefore quite possible that, if the author of De sp. knows more
253
J. Gribomont, review of Dehnhard, RHE 60 (1965) 492; (also, idem, "lntransigencia e irenismo en S. Basilio," ETrin 9 [ 197 5] 240 n. 61).
254
J. Danielou, review of Dehnhard, p. 161.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
193
plotinus than Eusebius quotes, the source of De sp. is the same as that of
Eusebius, namely, in all probability, some non-Porphyrian version of the
work of Plotinus. Possibly, but not necessarily, the author of De sp.
obtained this material in the library at Caesarea. Later Christian writers
such as Cyril of Alexandria and Theodoret bear witness that 5.1 was an
unusually well-known and influential text of Plotinus.
C.
255
256
PG
32: 204A-B.
194
JOHN M. RIST
known as the Phi/ocalia be- and at about the same time- the author of
the Plotinian cento known as De spiritu?
The most we can safely conclude at this stage is that it is, to say the
least, strange that a man with the devotion to Ennead 5.1 displayed by the
author of De sp. should, if he be Basil, exhibit so little concern for Plotinus
in other, including nearly contemporary, writings. Let us turn therefore to
other kinds of evidence.
On the matter of the manuscripts the salient points have been assembled
elsewhere: 257 none of the manuscripts of Basil's C. Eun. which bear
witness only to the three authentic books provides a text of De sp., nor
does De sp. occur by itself. De sp. only appears as the last section of the
spurious fifth book C. Eun., frequently attributed to Didymus the Blind. 258
But even if this work is by Didymus, which may well be doubted, that
would seem to be little help for De sp. De sp. 's deep dependence on
Ennead 5.1 has no parallel in Didymus any more than it has in the author
of C. Eun. 4-5 or in Basil himself. There is, indeed, no particular reason to
think that the author of De sp. and the author of C. Eun. 4-5 are the same
person. Thus although in the manuscripts De sp. forms the end of C. Eun.
5, there is no internal explanation for this. It is quite reasonable to propose
that whoever first tacked C. Eun. 4-5 on to Basil's C. Eun. 1-3 brought in
De sp. at the same time. Hence the fact that books four and five of C. Eun.
are not by Basil does not carry the necessary implication that De sp. is
non-Basilian as well.
Why does Dehnhard still think that De sp. was written by Basil?
Perhaps partly because Timothy Aelurus (460-475) cites C. Eun. 4-5 as of
Basil, thus showing that the attribution was already current about 100
years after the composition of De sp. 259 Gribomont suggests that perhaps
Basil's executors found De sp. in Basil's desk along with the C. Eun. and
the spurious C. Eun. 4-5, and put the whole thing together. 260 But this,
though possible, is grasping at straws; all we have for certain is that within
a hundred years of Basil's death, knowing that Basil wrote about the Holy
Spirit and against Eunomius, someone added our books 4 and 5 against
Eunomius, as well as De sp., to the undoubtedly Basilian C. Eun. l-3.
2s7
195
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
196
JOHN M. RIST
s.
unoa-caact~
266
'BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
197
ben be says that this notion comes from "the wisdom of the world."
~ nrY is a little more hesitant, 268 but thinks that Basil has Neoplatonism
b~eflY in mind. But there is no reason to believe that the term itself is
~eoplatonic. Basil's opponents, as the entry una.piBtJ.'YJO'tr; in PGL suggests,
e most likely to be Anomoeans of some kind or another, whose source
araY be a work of Stoicism or Aristotelianism - we have discussed
~xvoA.oyia. already - but which is certainly not Neoplatonic. In fact we
~ave to admit we do not know the precise origin of the technical language
in tbis chapter: the only thing we do seem to know is that it is neither
Platonic nor Neoplatonic. I c~n see no evidence that the other supposed
parallels marked in Henry's Etats are parallels at all.
iii. De Sp. S. 18.44-45
68
I
269
Etats, p. 183.
Etats, p. 183.
21
For further reminders see Dillon, The Middle Platonists. pp. 367 ff.
271
Basile, p. 408.
212
6.9.1 I. etc.
2 3
p : ~ee E. Peterson, "Herkunft und Bedeutung der MONOJ: flPOJ: MONON-Forme! bei
lotJn, Phi!ologus 88 (1933) 30-41.
.
198
JOHN M. RIST
v. De Sp. S. 30.77
This passage tells us that those who confuse the persons (Sabellians) are
judaizing, those who oppose the natures (Arians) are paganizing: a
standard charge, as our discussion of 16.38 has already suggested. Pruche
wisely declines to follow Henry at this point; thus he sees no reference to
Plotinus in particular.
This brings us to the end of our discussion of texts of De Sp. S. outside
chapter 9, where Basil has sometimes been said to be using Plotinus. Our
conclusion must be that in these sections Basil does not use Plotinus via
De sp., nor does he obviously allude to any text of the Enneads either
directly or through the quotations in Eusebius. Our only hesitation is with
the title 1:pd~ a,pxtxal unoa1:aac:~ - and this, as we have seen, affords no
clear evidence for direct contact with Plotinus' text. More likely than that
Basil thought of Plotinus specifically, when he used the title, and nothing
more, of Ennead 5.1 in De Sp. S. 16 is that the phrase apxtxai unoanl.ac:t~,
perhaps coined originally by Plotinus, signified by Basil's time a wellknown and objectionable set of attitudes. It remains possible, of course,
that this is incorrect, and that Basil drew the title, and nothing more, from
~lotinus directly, or more probably from Plotinus in Eusebius'
Praeparatio evangelica.
I revert to De sp. If Basil wrote De sp., he knew more about Ennead 5.1
than he could find in Eusebius, and probably he knew the title of the
treatise directly as well as from Eusebius. Hence the likelihood of his
274
Perhaps we should note that Pruche (Basile, p. 413) finds Basil alluding with the
phrase 86y!-la fi~ /-lOvapxia~ to Dionysius of Rome (in Athanasius, De deer. 26), a possible
source we have already considered (note 266) for talk of three hypostases.
199
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
i. De Sp.
s.
276
217
200
JOHN M. RIST
similar remarks about the desire of the soul (aoxenp n68rp, apprrrrj; (n:opYfi,
etc.) which remind us, though not clearly enough to suggest immediate
derivation, of Ennead 1.6.7.13 ff., a section where Plotinus uses the verb
opcyopm of our desire for the good. So one could say that in De Sp. S. 9
Basil echoes his own hrear:pa.nr:at and not unreasonably associates it with a
well-known Aristotelian tag. Indeed Plotinus' phrase npot; who emar:pifpGV
m:lvr:a could itself, by Basil's time, have become well-known; thus the use
of it would not entail direct use of Plotinus even though the phrase is
plotinian. At this point we must suspend judgment: Dehnhard certainly
seems to neglect the possible importance of the coincidence of famous
phrases; we should not, however, overestimate its importance at this stage.
ii. De Sp. S. 9.22.25: &Ma 'wfJ; XOP1JYOV. ou n:poa8i;xatt; augaVOfJ-EVOV ...
Following Henry, 279 Pruche sees two clear parallels with the Enneads:280 'wfJ; xopwov echoes Ennead 6.9.9.49, while npoa{}f;xatt; a.ugavof-lt:vov depends on 6. 7. 41 .16-17. This is an important claim, if true. for it
may ensure Basil's direct use of two treatises of Plotinus other than 5.1.
But it is not to be believed lightly. For, if correct, it would imply that Basil
is consciously making the kind of use of Plotinian texts which. in view of
what everyone would have to say is his limited interest in Plotinus. would
need clear demonstration. Basil may have heard these phrases in general
discussions without knowing that they had any particular connection with
Plotinus; and if that is the explanation, it hardly encourages us to talk of
Plotinus' influence on Basil. Dehnhard proposes a possible solution:
xop'f}yov is to be compared with a section of De sp. ('wiJV napixu, r:pono; <ijq;
xopwia;)2 81 where Dehnhard finds the author of De sp. dependent on
other materiaL in this case. he thinks. the Creed Q{ Gregory Thaumaturgus. as well as on Ennead 5.1. 282 The word aytaa{-loiJ in De Sp. S. 9.22.26-.
27 might seem to confirm this; it is absent in all the Plotinian texts. but
present in Gregory Thaumaturgus and De Sp. S. 9, while De sp. has muq;
ayiouq; ayiouq; en:oirpe. So much, if so, for a direct quotation of Ennead 6. 9.
but a final word must await comment on Gregory Thaumaturgus. and
Dehnhard's case is weakened by the too general "parallels" he sees in the
following section. As for the phrase ou n:poa{}f;xatt; augaVOfJ-EVOV, it certainly
reminds us of Ennead 6. 7. but cannot be said to be derived from it in any
significant sense.
'w*
279
280
281
282
Etats, p. 179.
Pruche, Basile, p. 325.
Dehnhard, Das Problem, p. 52.
lbid . p. 8.
201
. v. De Sp. S. 9.23.24-25: iJ
EV BErjJ Ota{lOVi],
rarov rwv opExrwv, BEov yEvi:aBat.
iJ
Etats, p. 179.
Dehnhard, Das Problem, p. 53.
See C. F. H. Johnston, The Book of St. Basil the Great on the Holy Spirit (Oxford
1892) p. 54, n. 4; he offers many references.
284
285
202
JOHN M. RIST
But Henry wants to draw particular attention to Oeov yevtaOat. 286 This
must, he believes, be directly Plotinian: the source is the Oeov yev6fJvov of
6.9.9.59. It must be granted to Henry that the phrase is very striking, anct
that no exactly worded parallel has thus far been adduced. But we should
note that it is the two words alone for which a good case might be made
for direct derivation from Ennead 6.9; the rest could come from any
Platonic or Christian Platonic source, verbal or written. And it is
legitimate to wonder whether reference to the text of Plotinus is required
to account for so striking a phrase. We must allow that Basil may have
quoted Ennead 6.9 here, though so striking a phrase could have been
familiar to the learned or fairly learned while its origins were unknown to
the person using it. So we have to conclude not that Henry is right, anct
that we have an unambiguous use by Basil of Ennead 6.9, but that there is
a possible use of Plotinus in this passage. It is interesting that in the Index
testium of Henry-Schwyzer, volume 3, this reference no longer appears.
vi. Conclusion
What then are our conclusions about De Sp. S.? That it is possible, but
far from necessary or even likely, that Basil used Ennead 1.7 in
9.22.20 ff.; that it is even less likely that he used 2.9 and 5.1 in lines 39-40;
that it is more likely that he used 5.1 in section 23; that it is possible that
Oeov yevi:aOat in section 23 derives directly from Ennead 6. 9. And of Dehnhard's case that De Sp. S. 9 uses not Plotinus directly, but De sp. as a
source, only one dubious passage (9.23.25 ff.) remains. At least this much
of a positive nature may be concluded: that whereas in the remaining
chapters of De Sp. S. it is almost certain that there is no direct use of
Plotinus, or use of Plotinus via De sp., in chapter 9 the matter is in doubt.
Clearly this tells in favour of Dorries' thesis of a later composition of
chapter 9 - after the remaining chapters of De Sp. S. We may now
consider possible Plotinian influence on other texts of Basil outside De sp.
and De Sp. S.
F.
i. HFide {/5)2 87
In the Etats Henry288 suggested that the opening sections of HF;de [15]
(OeoiJ fJ.Ef1VfJ(10at ... ala0i}ae7:at) 289 are influenced by Ennead 5.1.1.1-33. But
286
Etats, p. 182. For 8wnoiTff1!t; see Nygren, Agape and Eros, p. 428.
464o-c.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
203
290
291
292
2)8E2.
Etats, p. I 76.
293
204
JOHN M. RIST
writes, sequentially, as follows: rrrm]v 'wf}t;, rrrrrilv voiJ, &.pxilv ovTo~. &.yaOou
ahlav, pi,av cPUXfJt;. Basil in the parallel passage, has the following: rpuaoo]
aya8on}t;, rraVTWV apxij, aiTia TOU elvat TO[~ OUatV, pi'a TWV 'WVTWV, 1!'rrfi!7:ijr;;
m
296
PG
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
205
anY "plotinian" material in HFide [15], 297 it is more likely that De sp. is the
intermediary than that Basil quotes Plotinus directly.
The parallels offered by Henry for Ennead 5.1.6 and HFide [15] are too
vague to need further discussion. 298 We have to settle for no direct and
onlY slight indirect "Neoplatonic" material in the HFide [15] as a whole.
ii. Epistula Gregorio sodali (EGNaz. [2})29 9
297
206
JOHN M. RIST
the Etats. And Basil's sources are said to be not only the plausible S.l, and
the less plausible 1.6, but, according to Henry, the downright unlikely 2.8.
Such indeed is the weight of tradition and blind respect for authority.
Ennead 2.8, as Bn!hier already realized when writing his Notice in the
Bude edition of Plotinus, is a school treatise: 307 it is concerned with the
question of why distant objects appear smaller. In it Plotinus discusses five
school views and gives his preference to one of them, that of Aristotle. Itis
likely that Plotinus himself is using a manual at this point, and if Plotinus,
why not Basil who, as we have already noted, is not averse to the use of
manuals. To defeat this reading of the situation very strong evidence
would be required, which Henry has not provided. First he cites the
(Porphyrian) title ofPlotinus' tract, the weakest evidence of all; and far
from even verbally identical with what is found in Basil's Hex. 6.9. He
then compares Basil's nt&ov ... noM with Plotinus' opwv .. no.Ua~. And
that is all from Ennead 2.8.1. Chapter 2 provides merely noA.u ... To opoc;
and f.ni TOiJ oupavoiJ, plus ol/;t~ ... EXTEGVOfl.Evrj, as though phrases of this SOrt
were not virtually unavoidable in discussion of so technical a topic.
Henry believes that Hex. 6.9 is very closely related to C. Eun. 3.6,
where two of the supposed echoes of Plotinus recur: opwv TE nafip.eytOwv
and later oupavoiJ! 308 c. Eun. also contains the phrase TO neptXEifl.EVOV awt.ta,
and for this Henry recalls Ennead S.I, as he did when he found the phrase
in De sp. We may note first that TO neptxdfl.evov awfi.a does not occur in the
Hexaemeron, only in C. Eun. 3.6 309 - which substantially, if not totally,
weakens the case for Plotinian influence on Hex. 6.9. As for C. Eun. 3.6,
Ennead 5.1 or De sp. might be the origin, as Dehnhard has argued. But for
the words To neptxdfi.evov awfl.a in isolation, or rather accompanied only by
opwv TE TCa{J.fl.EyeOwv and oupavoiJ (not from S.l or De sp.), only a scholar
would have avoided the obvious conclusion: they are a banality going
back to Aristotle. 310
We turn now to Henry's "parallel" between Hex. 2.7 and Ennead
1.6. 311 The situation is rather similar. Again there are a few, indeed
slightly more, verbal parallels between Plotinus and Basil. But, according
to Henry, it is not these which persuade him of Basil's use of Plotinus; it is
"I' allure de tout le passage et 1' ordre dans lequelles idees sont exposees."
307
Theiler (JJZ 41 [1941] 171) inevitably thinks of Porphyry, though he notices the
possibility of pre-Plotinian sources for Basil.
los For all this see Etats, p. 174.
309
See also Dehnhard, Das Problem, p. 62.
310
GA 764s30.
311
Etats, pp. 172-173.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
207
The first of these claims is subjective, and the second has no weight if it
looks as though we are dealing with traditional school doctrine. And that
is exactly what we have in this case. In Ennead 1.6.1 Plotinus refers to a
standard and especially Stoic view that the beauty of an object is to be
explained in terms of the symmetry of its parts. 312 Basil refers to the same
standard .view in his discussion, but he is particularly concerned with the
question of the beauty of light, of gold and the evening star (Plotinus has
gold, lightning and stars in general); and Basil's discussion is largely in
terms of the pleasurable impact of light during the process of vision, a
question with which Plotinus does not concern himself. It is only the
banal parts of the texts, those dealing with a communis opinio that Basil
and Plotinus have in common. Sucp. a communis opinio is Pt'lrfectly
adequate to explain the similarities of vocabulary. Courtonne observes
that both Basil and Plotinus are concerned about the beauty of "simples,"
that is, substances supposedly composed of similar parts, which, it is said,
are not accounted for in the Stoic theory. 313 But while Basil is thinking of
light and gold, of material objects, the whole point of Plotinus' treatment
is to move to the beauty of immaterial "simples." Furthermore, it should
be noted that whereas Plotinus, for philosophical reasons, rejects the
"symmetry" theory of beauty in toto, it is possible that Basil, confusedly,
ion1y rejects it for some (viz. "simple") bodies.
So much for Basil's use of Plotinus (as claimed by Henry and others) in
'theHexaemeron; and for that matter in Contra Eunomium as well. For I
i'can find no further evidence of his influence in either work.
G.
all the Basilian or putatively Basilian texts that we have considered, the
IniJlUeJnce of Plotinus, whether direct or indirect, can be detected with
sertainty only in De sp. and in De Sp. S. 9. De sp. certainly uses Ennead
.SJ while De Sp. S. 9 uses 5.1 independently of De sp. Furthermore, the
~emote possibility of Basil's use of 6.9, and even 1.7 and 2.9, cannot be
denied for De Sp. S. 9; perhaps further enquiry may bring one of these
,Possibilities a little nearer to probability. Of other Basilian texts it is just
Possible that Basil used De sp. in HFide [I 5]; it is rather less likely that he
used 5.1. Nor should we forget that Basil (though he apparently neglected
312
313
(svF
3: 279).
208
JOHN M. RIST
this source) could have known Plotinus through the passages of Enneads
4. 7 and 5.1 to be found in Eusebius. What then does all this tell us about
Basil's utilization of Plotinus '? First of all that De Sp. S. 9 shows that he
uses Ennead 5.1 directly - and that it is possible on the evidence so far
that this is the only Plotinian treatise he so uses. He makes no use of the
texts of 4. 7 he could have found in Eusebius. Now I have already
suggested, as a result of a consideration of the use of 5.1 by Eusebius
Cyril of Alexandria and Theodoret, that this treatise probably circulated
separately. That factor might also supply the clue to why Basil probably
knew very little Plotinus. If he read 5.1 in Porphyry's edition, or even in
that of Eustochius, he would presumably have read much more Plotinus
along with it. But Porphyry's account in his L(le of Plotinus makes it quite
clear that some of the treatises, especially the earlier ones- 5.1 is number
I 0 - were in circulation long before any complete edition of Plotinus
was published. For the sake of clarity I should mention that 6.9
immediately precedes 5.1: number 9 in Porphyry's collection; thus if Basil
knew 6.9 our general thesis would hardly be affected. 1.7 and 2.9 are
chronologically 54 and 33, so that if I was convinced that Basil knew
these two treatises, I should have further minor difficulties on my hands.
But I am not so convinced.
But the question of 6.9 affords us a good way to return to the still
unresolved problem of De sp. and of its author, for related to this question
is the matter of Basil's attitude to Plotinus in general. I have already
observed that Dehnhard finds the phrase 'w% xoprrrav in De Sp. S. 9.22.25
to be dependent not on Ennead 6.9.9.48, but on the Creed of Gregory
Thaumaturgus in De sp. Here we should also advert to our discussion of
the phrase Oeov yeveaOat in De Sp. S. 9.23, which, some say, derives
directly from Ennead 6.9.9.59. We held this claim to be still unproven,
though it is more plausible than the claim for 'wfj; xopr}yov, since this time
De sp. cannot be the source.
At this point. a definitive conclusion about the status of De sp. can be
delayed no longer. I have noted Gribomonfs doubts that it was actually
written by Basil and, in some measure, approved them. Let me pursue the
matter further in the light of the now complete analysis of "Plotinian"
material in Basil. Dehnhard's view of De sp. is that it is a document
composed by Basil on the basis of Ennead 5.1, the Creed of Gregory
Thaumaturgus, Origen and other sources. This interpretation of the
content of De sp. is largely accepted by Gribomont, but has recently been
challenged by Abramowski in an article in which she argues that the socalled "Creed of Gregory Thaumaturgus," so far from being a source for
Basil (or the author of De sp.), is rather to be regarded as itself in some
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
209
dependent on Basil. 314 If this were to prove correct, it might seem that
waY rima facie likelihood of Basil's being the author of De sp. would
~be pase: the De sp. would appear to be his blend of material later known
10
cr:e "Creed of Gregory Thaumaturgus" with Plotinus. For it is certain
as ~ the first ascription of the Creed that we know to Gregory
~:aumaturgus (together with the first publication of its full text) is made
b Gregory of Nyssa315 a.frer Basil's death. However, if Basil wrote De sp.,
ye have to credit him at some stage of his career with a degree of respect
;r Plotinus (at least for Ennead 5.1) which we might otherwise never
bave suspected.
Let us now inspect at least the major points of Abramowski's argument
tbat the "Creed" (if that is the proper rendering) of Gregory Thaumaturgus is dependent on Basil:
l. The first extant complete version of the "Creed" that we have is to be
found in Gregory of Nyssa, who is also the first to mention the
ascription of this material to Gregory Thaumaturgus. The date of
Gregory's L{fe qf Gregory in which this appears is uncertain, but it is
between 381 and 395.
166.
315
316
PG
46: 912o-913A.
317
C. P. Caspari, Alte und neue Que/len zur Geschichte des Taufsymbols und der
Giaubensrege/ (Christiania 1879) p. 27; contra Abramowski, "Das Bekenntnis," p. 150.
318
ENeoc. [204); ENeoc. cl. [207); ENeoc. pm. [210).
210
JOHN M. RIST
use in his own controversies. Behind which lies the more basic fact that at
the time of Gregory Thaumaturgus the question of the nature of the Holy
Spirit is not prominent. The great emphasis put on it in Gregory of
Nyssa's version of the "Creed of Gregory Thaumaturgus" is in itself
suspect; we may detect a late fourth rather than a late third-century hand
as the quotation by Gregory of Nazianzus might also naturally lead us~
suppose.
According to Dehnhard, Basil used the authentic "Creed of Gregory
Thaumaturgus" when composing De sp. Yet the evidence for such use is
thin indeed: it is little more than that the phrases CwiJ Cwvrwv alria, n7Jyi}
ayta, ayu'rrt]~ aytaa{J.oiJ XOP1JYO~ and nveiJ{J.a aytov, EX Oc:oiJ ri}v unapw iixov
xai &' uloiJ nsrp1JVo~ from the "Creed of Gregory Thaumaturgus"- in the
version, moreover, of Gregory of Nyssa- resemble certain phrases in De
sp. But since there is certainly much material in De sp. which derives
neither from Plotinus nor from Gregory Thaumaturgus, these few phrases
invite the alternative explanation: namely that they derive not from the
authentic "Creed of Gregory Thaumaturgus," but from the ideas, not
necessarily the pen, of Basil himself. What then is the truth about the
"Creed of Gregory Thaumaturgus"? Basically Abramowski is right: there
was such a "Creed" (iixOsat~); Basil refers to it in ENeoc. pm. [210]. He
apparently knows its content, though he makes no use of it- presumably
because it was related to third century problems and thus no help in his
Trinitarian dealings with Atarbius or anyone else in the fourth century.
The document which Gregory of Nyssa produced and which Dehnhard
claims as a source for Basil, is a reworking of the original "Creed" by
someone close to Basil; and as Abramowski points out, its material on the
Spirit seems to depend on the work of Basil himself.
Where then does this leave us with De sp.? The work is to be seen as a
cento composed ofPlotinus, Ennead 5.1, and various other texts of largely
Origenist provenance. It need not even come from a Cappadocian milieu,
though it probably does; what we know is that it appears at a time and
from a milieu where Plotinus, Origen and some Origenists were valued,
and where there was a serious concern with the theology of the Holy
Spirit, a concern which clothed itself in language later judged appropriate
to Gregory Thaumaturgus. As to date, it is just possibly used by Basil in
HFide [15], written after 370; and it is also just possibly a sourc.e of parts of
De Sp. S. 9.22 and 23, which were written no earlier than 375.
An important question remains: if Basil met De sp. only late in his life,
why should he take much interest in it, especially if many of the purely
theological ideas to be found there were his own? The time has come to
evaluate the basic thesis ofDehnhard: that Basil used De sp. in De Sp. S. 9.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
211
our own investigations have shown that any such use that he might have
:tnade is far less than Dehnhard supposed. Of the uses of De sp. by Basil
proposed by Dehnhard we are left, as we have seen, with a slight
possibility in one passage of HFide [15], and with De Sp. S. 9, 22 and 23.
Before closing this section of the discussion, therefore, we should return
to the problem of De sp. or Ennead 6.9.9 (and in particular the phrases
'~ xoprrrov [1.48] and 0Eov yEVOf1EVov [1.59D as possible sources for these
chapters of De Sp. S. 9. 0Eov YEVOf1EVov, we were earlier inclined to suggest,
is perhaps a commonplace, and the use by Basil in De Sp. S. 9.23.25 of
0Eov yEvf:aOat need not persuade us of direct Plotinian influence. But if it
were to look probable that Basil's twi'J; xoprrrov is directly Plotinian (from
6.9.9.48) we should have to reconsider.
Dehnhard, of course, invokes De sp. 15: ~wi}v rr:apiXEt, 1:p6rr:o; 7:ij;
xopTJyim;, 319 phrases which he thought were dependent on aytaaf.WU
xopTJy6;, etc., from the "Creed of Gregory Thaumaturgus"; and we
allowed that the appearance of aywa11oiJ (present in "Gregory Thaumaturgus" and reflected by m); aylou; ayiou; irr:olrpE in De sp.) might confirm
this. But Gregory Thaumaturgus can now be left aside, and our question
reformulated thus: does the presence of aytaaf1oiJ in De Sp. S. 9 make it
certain that De Sp. S. 9's ~wij; xoprrrov derives not from the Enneads
(xoprrro; tiJ..rJOtvij; ~wij;, 6.9.9.49-50), but from De sp., although De sp. has
the less close 1:porr:o; 1:ij; xoprrrla;? It certainly does not; indeed we know
that in De Sp. S. 9 Basil used Ennead 5.1 directly, and it is possible that he
used 6.9.9 as well. The possibility is slightly increased by his use in the
same chapter of the phrase 0Eov yEviaOat, though we have tried to dismiss
this as commonplace. Furthermore, if De sp. is not a source of De Sp. S. 9,
evidence for its use by Basil has all but evaporated (only a slight possibility
remains for HFide [15]), and with it Dehnhard's thesis.
I conclude that before 37 5 Basil had come across parts of Enneads 5.1
and 4.7 in Eusebius, but he took no interest in them; by 375 or later,
when he wrote De Sp. S. 9, he knew Ennead 5.1 directly, and possibly
also 6.9. I have already noted that 5.1 is number 10 and 6.9 number 9 in
Porphyry's chronological list. I do not, of course, conclude that Basil used
Porphyry's complete edition of the Enneads. The fascinating problem
remains, to which I shall return: can we account for Basil's interest in at
least a little Plotinus in 375, but not before? To this question may be
added a second: is Basil's belated interest in Plotinus in any way related to
the appearance of De sp.?
319
JOHN M. RIST
212
H.
320
See H. Dorrie, "Gregors Theologie auf dem Hintergrunde der neuplatonischen
Metaphysik," in Gregor von Nyssa und die Philosophie, edd. H. Dorrie eta!. (Leiden 1976)
p. 29.
321 BZ 41 (1941) 171.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
213
and was thus indirectly more responsible for Basil's (and others') use of
Neoplatonic ideas about the return of the souL But often j:he ideas are not
even purely Neoplatonic, but generally of the Platonic tradition, as Justin
Martyr already knew; and it should be added that because Porphyry
perhaps over-emphasized the notion of the return of the soul (in De regressu) in a possibly unplotinian fashion, that fact of that emphasis is insufficient to establish Porphyry as a source whenever such material is
found in other writers.
Basil's second letter is, in my view, an excellent example of how
"platonically," even "neoplatonically," a Christian can talk, without
giving the scholar any reason to believe that he is necessarily following
anY Neoplatonic source, or possibly any particular source at all. There is
nothing of the "platonic" or "ascetic" tradition found there which a
careful reading of Origen could not have provided, particularly to a man
who presumably read a number of the works of Plato himself when he
was a student. Certainly there are "platonic" ideas here; certainly there are
"Stoic" ideas here: that is, ideas with which contemporary Platonists or
Stoics (if any) might concur. But to invoke Porphyry, or even Plotinus, for
that matter, is to mistake the spirit of the age. Put Epictetus, Origen and
Numenius together (exempli gratia) and you have no need here of
Plotinus or Porphyry.
It might seem a pointless exercise to go through the unsatisfactory
attempts of Theiler to read Porphyry into Basil; one wishes that it
were. But it is necessary because the assumption "if not Plotinus, then
Porphyry," can reappear in strange guises. In particular one should
beware of an attempt to see in Porphyry's exaggerated version of Plotinus'
personal asceticism a mode of neo-Platonism more attractive and
therefore more influential on Basil. Here, for example, is E. F. Osborn
discussing a passage of Porphyry: 322 "Plato chose an unhealthy part of
Athens as the place for his Academy. The philosopher meditating on
death despises luxury and lives free from want on a slender diet. 'For he
who in this way mortifies the body will obtain all possible good through
self-sufficiency and be made like the divine. The worship of the supreme
God can employ neither material sacrifice nor verbal utterance
only
silent contemplation is appropriate. This is the kind of Platonism which
Basil knows and understands." 323
322
214
JOHN M. RIST
Certainly Basil knew and understood it, but he did not need Porphyry
to tell him about it. Much of it had been in Platonism since the Phaedo
and the mixture of Platonic and Pythagorean asceticism (as in Numenius)
easily pre-dates Plotinus. What seems to have misled Osborn
and he is
quoted only exempli gratia
is the belief that Porphyry's version of these
Platonic themes is not only different from Plotinus', but that it could not
predate him. Such a belief largely derives from the overemphasis on the
titles and context of Porphyry's De regressu ani mae and De abstinentia as
indicating a novel and unplotinian morality. Doubtless Porphyry
emphasized bodily asceticism more than Plotinus (though he may not
have practised it more); in this he reverted to earlier strains of Platonism
and Pythagoreanism: it is thus misleading for Osborn to say that Basil's
Platonism is more dependent on Porphyry than on Plotinus. It could in
these matters be dependent on neither. Perhaps the passage on the
unhealthy locale of the Academy tipped the scales in Porphyry's favour.
Basil quotes it in Ad adolescentes 9. 81. But Basil had been to Athens and
the theme is commonplace; it also occurs in Aelian's Varia Historia 9.10,
a source, among others, for Basil's Hexaemeron.
Such legendary material may be particularly liable to mislead. Also in
Ad adolescentes is to be found a story about a companion of Pythagoras
named Cleinias. The story itself is also extant in Iamblichus' Life qf
Pythagoras. 324 Hence, says a modern editor, 325 it is possible that Basil
knew Iamblichus' work. But the name Cleinias is not given by Iamblichus, and a common source for Iamblichus and Basil is the more likely
explanation, for even if Basil could have read lamblichus, he would have
had to read the same material elsewhere to find the name.
We have suggested both in this section and at an earlier stage of our
discussion that the influence of Porphyry on Basil is likely to have been
abstinelltia, but he believes that to be the case. Amand is also followed by P. Courcelle,
"Gregoire de Nysse, lecteur de Porphyre," REG 80 (1967) 406.
324 On Iamblichus' sources in general see E. Rohde, "Die Quellen des Iamblichus in
seiner Biographie des Pythagoras," RhM 27 0872) 23-61; also A. J. Festugiere, "Sur une
nouvelle edition de 'De Vita Pythagorica' de Jamblique," REG 50 (1937) 470-494.
Festugiere observes (p. 471) that the direct sources of Iamblichus are the Neopythagoreans
Apollonius. Nicomachus, Moderatus.
325 N. G. Wilson, St. Basil on the Value of Greek Literature (London 1975) p. 59 on
7.47-53. Wilson seems to follow R. Reitzenstein C.Der Athanasius Werk iiber das Leben
des Antonius [Heidelberg 1914]) in thinking that Athanasius too knew the Life of
Pythagoras when he wrote the life of St. Antony. One must admit that this is possible, but
Iamblichus' sources might seem more plausible than Iamblichus himself.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
215
J.
In 375, as we have seen, Basil knows Ennead 5.1 and possibly 6.9. In
addition, we assume that he knew some of 5.1 long before 375- though
he did not use it - by reason of his acquaintance with Eusebius' Praeparatlo evangelica, which quotes 5.1 and 4.7 extensively. 4.7 is also an
early work of Plotinus (number 2), so it adds nothing surprising to our
view of the circulation of Plotinian treatises separately. We notice that it is
the early treatises of Plotinus which first appear in the Christian Fathers.
We have already observed Cyril of Alexandria's use of 5.1 and of 5.1
alone. Have we any external evidence as to why Basil might have become
interested in Neoplatonic material not in his student days, but towards the
end of his life? To this, two further witnesses might be called: Gregory of
Nazianzus and Gregory of Nyssa, and although this is not the place to
touch extensively on the influence of Neoplatonism in these authors, a
few observations may further our immediate aim to understand the
development of Basil.
In fact we do not need to say much of Gregory of Nazianzus. Although
he has a certain knowledge of Greek philosophy, especially of Plato, his
general attitude is often critical or hostile. And his knowledge is largely
Jimited to the earlier teachers, Pythagoras, Plato, Aristotle (an artificial
thinker with poor notions about Providence), the Stoics and Cynics, and
the Epicureans; all of these he suggests are worthy of attack and
.refutation. 326 But he offers no similar comment on contemporary or more
contemporary teachers. His knowledge of Plotinus appears to be
slight, and of no real help to us at present. Henry and Schwyzer claim that
one of his poems he echoes Ennead 5.2.1, 327 a claim which I am
.u~'u.'"'" to deny or at least think doubtful. More plausible, however, is
their suggestion that in his Third Theological Oration he refers to lines 8
~nd 9 of the same chapter. 328 Here Gregory actually says that he is citing
one of the Greek philosophers who spoke of an urci:pxuaw of goodness and
of goodness overflowing like a mixing bowl. And Plotinus does write of
the One, olav urcsppUYJ xai TO um:prc'kijps(.; avroiJ 1CGTCOiYJ'X.Eli aMo. Not too close,
one might suppose; but Gregory says that this occurs in a writing "On the
326
321
328
216
JOHN M. RIST
First Cause and the Second." This is not Porphyry's name of the treatise
5.2, but we note that Gregory's title is rather nearer the version found in
the Arabic, 329 where the essay is called "The First Cause and the Things
that originate from it. " 330 So it may be argued that Gregory does quote
Ennead 5.2 here, but not in Porphyry's edition. And that makes his use of
Plotinus in the Poem slightly more likely. But in the end all this helps us
but little with Basil. The third Theological Oration was delivered after
Basil's death while Gregory was at Constantinople, at the Church of the
Anastasis; and the poem was almost certainly composed after he had
retired from the Capital in 381. Neither composition tells us anything
which might clarify Basil's position in 375. The most natural interpretation of Gregory of Nazianzus' use of Ennead 5.2, not in Porphyry's
edition, is that he came across it, prol::>ably alone or with only a few other
Plotinian essays, when he was in Constantinople. We note that 5.2 is
number 11 in Porphyry's chronological list. Basil, as we have seen, knows
5.1 (number 10) and perhaps 6.9 (number 9).
Let us turn to our second witness, Gregory of Nyssa. In fact we have to
treat of only one text, since the De virginitate is probably the only major
work of Gregory's to have been composed before Basil's death in 379.
Dehnhard suggested that Basil was directly influenced by his younger
brother, 331 an idea which has not been welcomed, 332 since it is generally
held- perhaps unjustly- that Basil failed to recognize young Gregory's
talents. In favour of Dehnhard's proposal it might be argued that Basil's
view of Gregory was at least sufficiently high to secure his promotion to
the dignity of bishop. Basil had hopes- in which he was disappointedthat Gregory would be an effective ally in the ecclesiastical struggles in
which he, Basil, was engaged. It was also, apparently, at Basil's suggestion
that Gregory set about .writing the De virginitate - which implies that
Basil's opinion of his theological qualities was considerable.
Nonetheless, I have no wish to endorse Dehnhard's thesis, that the De
virginitate is a source for Basil's De Spiritu Sancto. We are more aware
than was Dehnhard of the chronological problems surrounding the date
of the De virginitate itself. As Gribomont has observed, 333 the
329
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
217
334
335
So Gribomont, "Le panegyrique," p. 250; Basil, EGNys. [58], PG 32: 408a; Courtonne, I: 145.6-7.
336
For J. Danielou, see his communication, "Gregoire de Nysse et Plotin" (resume), in
Actes du ve congr. de /'Ass. Dude (Paris 1954) pp. 259-262, and his review of Dehnhard,
Pp. 158-160. See also D. Bahis, Metousia Theou (Rome 1966) p. 63.
218
JOHN M. RIST
m The question arises whether Gregory used Porphyry's edition. In view of his
limited knowledge of Plotinus in De virginitate, I should incline to deny it. Possible
evidence for his use of it is offered by Courcelle, who argues, in "Gregoire de Nysse,
lecteur de Porphyre," pp. 404-405, that in chapter 23 of De virginitate, Gregory uses the
response of Apollo to the question of Amelius about Plotinus quoted by Porphyry in the
Vita Plotini (ch. 22). The argument is less than compelling: Courcelle's "parallels" are all of
commonplace material in such contexts; and in any case the reply of Apollo was
presumably known to others besides Porphyry.
338 Henry <.Etats, p. 168) thought that the phrase /'O'IJ7:EUouawv yuvatxwv in De sp. (ed.
Dehnhard, p. 8, 1.23) for Plotinus' wv yeyo'f}7:Euxowv (Enn. 5.1.2.13) indicates the
monastic preoccupations of the young Basil (ca. 360). It might equally well indicate the
comparatively youthful fervour of the anti-matrimonial Gregory of the De virginitafe.
BASIL'S "NEOPLATONISM"
J.
219
EPILOGUE
339
L P. Sheldon-Williams, in The Cambridge History, ed. A. H. Armstrong, p. 446;
compare alsop. 442.
340
EEust. [223] 2, PG 32: 824A; cf. Spidlik, Sophiologie, p. 146. I am, in fact, inclined to
date the Ad adolescentes to the period of Basil's teaching in Caesarea, after his return from
Athens.
220
JOHN M. RIST
341
Or. 31.5; but this must be juxtaposed with texts which emphasize faith (Or. 28.28, etc.).