Straws On 1966 Review
Straws On 1966 Review
Straws On 1966 Review
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Oxford University Press, Scots Philosophical Association, University of St. Andrews are collaborating with
JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Philosophical Quarterly.
http://www.jstor.org
84
BOOK REVIEWS
emotivism and subjectivism are views about value sentences.) Ardal further thinks
that it is " natural " for a reflectivist to be a subjectivist and for an emotionist to be
an emotivist. Hume is thus held to be an emotionist and, less certainly, an emotivist.
Ardal, very usefully, suggests some reasons why Hume appears to be more of a subjectivist than he is. In the first place Hume was over-impressed by the analogy between virtue and vice and secondary qualities (or, at least, over-inclined to press it
as an argumentum ad hominem), despite his own attack on the received doctrine concerning secondary qualities in Treatise Book I, and despite the fact that he held virtue
and vice to be mind-dependent in a way secondary qualities are not. Secondly, the
distinction between having an emotion and judging that one has-the
distinction
over which both emotionism and reflectivism and emotivism and subjectivism divide
-is a vanishing one on Hume's theory of belief.
This is a good and useful book, which very well brings out the too often neglected
complexity, yet substantial consistency, of Hume's ethical thinking.
R. F. ATKINSON
The Bounds of Sense : An essay on Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. By P. F. STRAWSON.
(London: Methuen. 1966. Pp. 296. Price 35s).
The Kantian spirit of Strawson's Individuals doubtless encouraged in many of its
readers the hope that he would embark on a study of the first Critique. He has now
done so, and the book proves to be a stimulating, original and subtle account of this
work. The tasks of exposition and criticism are very different and it is a necessary
condition of success in such an enterprise that the reader should be in no doubt at
any given point which of the two is being undertaken. Strawson meets this requirement, but his text, with its uncompromisingly gritty style, makes quite severe demands
on any reader anxious to keep this essential distinction in the forefront of his mind.
In the first part of the book, 'The Metaphysics of Experience ', Strawson deals
with the Aesthetic, the Transcendental Deduction and the Analogies. In this section,
as throughout, Strawson is more sympathetic to Kant considered as an analyst of
the concept of a possible experience than as a transcendental metaphysician defending
the dubious doctrine of a timeless and supersensible reality. Strawson recognizes the
extremely close interconnection between these two aspects of the Kantian system but
maintains that the more modest Kantian thesis can be defended without leading one
to offensively (i.e., transcendent) metaphysical conclusions. Strawson has two main
grounds for this opinion. The first is what he calls Kant's "principle of significance ",
which is formulated as follows : " There can be no legitimate or even meaningful employment of ideas or concepts which does not relate them to empirical or experiential conditions of their application " (p. 16). Strawson frequently emphasizes the importance
of this principle not only in the context of Kant's thought but as an intrinsically valuable
philosophical insight because he regards it as forming part of " the framework of a
truly empiricist philosophy, freed, on the one hand, from the delusions of transcendent
metaphysics, on the other, from the classical empiricist obsession with the private
contents of consciousness" (p. 19). Strawson's second argument is perhaps more
controversial. He believes that Kant, to a serious degree, misunderstood the nature
of the task which he set himself in the first Critique because he had " no clear and
general conception of the synthetic a priori at all " (p. 43). If this is so, then of course
the problem of the Critique as formulated by Kant, viz. 'How are synthetic a priori
judgments possible ?' is scarcely intelligible. Strawson's discussion of this issue is
extremely brief and he is perhaps open to criticism for dismissing in cavalier fashion a
concept of such central importance for Kant. It is not even clear whether Strawson
thinks that Kant's failure to form a satisfactory concept of the synthetic a priori is
due to the fact that no one can do so because the concept is inherently unintelligible.
Strawson's own interpretation of the a priori he says is " relatively austere ", and
he characterizes it in terms of which the following is a fair sample : "To hold that the
unity of space 'and time was in this sense a priori would be to hold that it was an essential
element in any coherent conception of experience that we could form " (p. 65).
This view is doubtless austere in the sense that it involves fewer philosophical and
quasi-psychological assumptions than does Kant's own position, but it is hardly austere
from the point of view of clarity and logical rigour; as the reviewer in The Times
Literary Supplement has said, we would wish to know more about the definition of this
notion of coherence. It may also be added that an " essential element " cannot mean
" what iq deducible a priori from the concept of experience as such ", otherwise the
whole argument is in danger of collapsing into tautology with the consequent loss of
the essentially Kantian conception of transcendental justification.
BOOK REVIEWS
85
86
BOOK REVIEWS
of a figure. The impossibility arises not from the concept in itself but in connection
with its construction in space, that is, from the conditions of space and of its determination " (A 221).
C. K. GRANT
Die Kantkritik des jungen Hegel. By INGTRAUD G6OLAND. (Frankfurt am Main:
Vittorio Klostermann. 1966. Pp. x + 251. Price paper DM 18.55).
The authoress is an Assistant to Professor W. Brocker in Kiel. In the Preface which
he contributes to her book he says it is a well-known fact that Hegel adopted Fichte's
interpretation of Kant and that this was a topsy-turvy one. Thus when Hegel claimed
that his philosophy was the destination to which Kant and Fichte blazed the trail,
he was right about Fichte but wrong about Kant. "The real Kant has basically remained unknown to Hegel, so that a real discussion between Kant and Hegel is a task
left to us ". This book is a contribution to this task.
The authoress is learned and she has done her best to establish difficult propositions,
but she has not the gift of style, and her book is hard reading. She professedly confines
herself to the " young " Hegel, by which she means the Hegel of the Jugendschriften,
the Jena essays, and the Phenomenology. She does, however, draw on the Logic, the
Encyclopaedia, and the History of Philosophy. It may therefore be a pity that she did
not deal simply with all those passages in Hegel's works where he is explicitly expounding Kant, or differing from him, or criticizing him. The major part of her book deals
with the Phenomenology in which Kant is occasionally alluded to by implication, though
never by name, and in which the adjective 'Kantian' occurs but twice.
As may be expected, the authoress can draw attention to several places where
Hegel's criticism of Kant, or difference from him (between these attitudes she does
not distinguish), demand a verdict in Kant's favour. I quote only three examples:
(i) In the Jena Logic Hegel's criticism of Kant on cause and effect ignores Kant's schematism and his association of this category with time. (ii) Hegel's criticism of the
well-known " otherwise there would be no deposits " in K.p. V. takes no account of
what follows. Kant's expression of his point may be unfortunate, but his meaning is
that if there are deposits, then they involve binding obligations, and this is immune
from Hegel's criticism. This point against Hegel is put more clearly and more succinctly in J. Maier's Hegel's Criticism of Kant, which is not included in the authoress's
bibliography. (iii) Hegel has not grasped Kant's doctrine of the Kingdom of Ends
which is expounded in the Grundlegung, and the authoress can quote many passages
from that work to confute things said in the Phenomenology. It has always seemed
strange to me that Hegel never mentions or even seems to have been acquainted with
the Grundlegung. It appeared when he was still a schoolboy and he may have regarded
it as superseded by K.p. V.
That Hegel was misled by Fichte does not appear to be proved. If both these
philosophers misinterpreted Kant, they did so independently. Hegel read Kant at
Tiibingen, and he had twice studied K.p. V. before he ever read Fichte (the evidence
is clear in his correspondence with Schelling and Holderlin). His acceptance of K.p. V.
is writ large in the earlier Jugendschriften; his admiration of Kant's book on religion
is clear in a letter of 1794. By 1800, however, he had come to believe that beyond
Kant's Moralitdt there was a higher moral sphere, which later he was to call Sittlichkeit.
Consequently in some of his criticisms of Kant's ethics, he was standing on ground
that was not Kant's.
I suggest that an understanding and evaluation of the young Hegel's criticism of
Kant depends on answering a question which the authoress does not raise, namely:
How did the enthusiastic Kantian of 1794 become a critic of Kant by 1800 ? My answer
would attach far more importance to his study of religion, history, and Greek philosophy
than to the supposed influence of Fichte, Holderlin, and Schelling.
To suppose that Hegel, influenced by Fichte, misunderstood Kant is like supposing
(as has happened) that a twentieth century critic can understand Plato better than
Aristotle did. Hegel was steeped in Kant : Kant, he said, was his education. He revered
Kant as the founder of German philosophy, a master whom Hegel's contemporaries
were ignoring. Many, he said, would think his numerous references to Kant superfluous,
but he persisted because, in his view, for all his difference from his master, Kant was
the Bahnbrecher.
Of course Hegel's presuppositions and standpoint were not Kant's. He thought
that Fichte had "completed"
the Critical Philosophy. Kant thought differently.
Thus it is not surprising that Professor Br6cker should say that there was no real
conversation between Kant and Hegel. C. Stommel said the same in a Halle Dissertation in 1876. He is quoted in Wyneken's Hegels Kritik Kants (1898), but that is not
in the authoress's bibliography either.
T. M. KNOx