Pauley PDF
Pauley PDF
Pauley PDF
Theodicy
John Pauley
Simpson College
The details of evil will sink any attempt at theodicy. But details of evil are usually- or even
necessarily- lost in the abstract discussions of evil in philosophical texts. Hence this essay looks at
the details of tragic fiction, specifically in some stories by Faulkner. The initial analysis endeavors
to show that fiction gets us closer to the reality of agency than philosophy and so it then gets
us closer to the reality of the evils that haunt both individuals and cultures (the two cannot
be adequately separated). Finally, the details of the evil analyzed reveal that human beings
are actually capable of a self-destruction that annihilates the very grounds of human agency
and identity: Faulkners tragic fiction reveals that self-destruction is written into the necessary
components of agency and identity.
Introduction
Hume, in his relentless discussion of the problem of evil, implies
that any theodicy is rendered impotent in the face of an adequate description
of evil.1 Freud implies something similar in many places, although he does
not care much for the details of the topic.2 There is considerable promise
in this approach but philosophical description of the evils of the world
generally collapse into a quasi-abstract discussion of the categories of evil;
in other words, the old saw account of natural and moral evil. Hence,
philosophical descriptions of evil in the world tend to lose existential grit
and, in the process, that horrifying urgency that real evil engenders.
Hume also implies and then directly states that the poet has a better
handle on the details and at least in this case the clich is right: the
devil is in the details.3 It is not surprising that Dostoevskys bit on child
torture from the Brothers Karamazov is included in many philosophical
anthologies. For the most part, I think its inclusion has more to do with
what philosophers would call providing examples instead of providing
arguments. Hume is right that the poet has a better handle on the details
but the poet also might have better arguments in the form of descriptions.
In this essay, I will argue that fiction provides better reasons for rejecting
any theodicy than does philosophy: this is for the simple reason that great
fiction necessarily keeps us closer to human reality in the world than is
possible in philosophy.
Janus Head, 12(1), Copyright 2011 by Trivium Publications, Pittsburgh, PA
All rights reserved.
Printed in the United States of America
are correct, and they do demand more detail, then it will follow that the
conditions of fiction are also the same as the conditions of human agency.
If this conclusion is true then it will have to follow that fiction writers are
the best describers of the human condition within the world.
Snopes Being Snopes
Contingency is necessarily written into any narrative because it is an
inescapable aspect of human reality. Frequently, the notion of contingency
is understood as external to the agent: unpredictable events in nature
and society. Certainly this is one central component of contingency
and it helps to make up any mature version of what it is to be human
in the world. Contingency, however, is also internal to the agent; our
intentions for ourselves and others are disrupted by aspects hidden from
ourselves. Insofar as knowledge of ourselves is opaque we can be driven by
psychological features that we do not understand and if we did understand
all of those features we would be fundamentally different sorts of beings.
Symmetrically, it is impossible to construct any narrative of a human life
that proceeds on the basis of a full and transparent self-knowledge. If
narrative is the form of self-knowledge, then interpretation is the method
of self-knowledge. And since no interpretation can ever be complete, it
follows that a full and transparent self-knowledge is impossible in both
human life and fiction.
In a narrative, the world and characters unfold in ways both predictable
and unpredictable, but what is unpredictable is distinct from what is
implausible. Internal aspects of a character that are opaque to that character
leave traces in the world. What that character will be led to do on the basis
of those hidden internal aspects is related to additional contingencies. The
more a narrative synthesizes the unpredictable with the plausible, the more
it grinds down into human reality. Abner Snopes in Faulkners story Barn
Burning is an exemplar case to examine in relation to the above points.5
There is no question that he is burdened by a resentment and envy that
is beyond both his control and his understanding and unfortunately (for
himself and others) that resentment and envy are let loose on the world.
As Snopes sets out one evening to torch Major De Spains barn (the
Plantation owner, in essence the master), the story pulsates with his
incredible determination. The reader cannot help but to get the sense
that Snopes literally could not do otherwise. For Snopes to stop, sit
and heavily seasoned, it appears, with hatred and this is the result of an
ongoing cultural meta-story. Everyone in this culture (more or less) has
a place and not just due to some series of historical accidents or causes.
Meta-stories provide the ultimate and transcendent explanation for why
the world is as it ought to be. No one can tell the meta-story exactly or
all it once because it has too many branched versions. But one crucial
aspect of all meta-stories is that they cannot withstand much in the way
of existential pressure. The aspect of vulnerability is due to the fact that
meta-stories are constructed from lived narrative and have absolutely no
connection to any other reality because there is no other reality (besides the
one we live). In other words, human beings know very well that historical
accident explains a lot about social roles and limits and that the metastory merely excuses the arbitrary nature of the roles and limits. At some
level, not too far away from our better selves, is the knowledge that the
meta-story is a story that we are telling ourselves. Symmetrically, the nave
version of free will and responsibility is told out of a need to cover for our
desperate lack of self-knowledge: this is one way that the meta-story of free
will functions. At least, however, the meta-story works on the surface of
things and, in the meta-story under consideration here, Snopes is at the
very bottom of the social world because he ought to be: he is white trash.
Snopes is not supposed to prosper; it is antithetical to the right order of
reality. Hatred can then be layered on top of envy due to impotence in the
face of what is accepted as a meta-norm.
Faulkner is not just vividly aware of the existence of the meta-story;
he is vividly aware of the way it distorts human life and, at the same time,
can be easily punctured. When punctured the response is an immense
violence and horror because to puncture the meta-story is to reveal the
ambiguity and uncertainty at the heart of sacred moral truths and codified
ontologically based social orders.
The truly unforgettable scene where Snopes wipes the shit off his boots
onto Major De Spains white French rug contains all that is needed to
create serious damage to the meta-story. On the one side the meta-story
has no ground whatsoever and on the other side it is very nearly impossible
to overcome (in day to day life). Symmetrically, Snopes is both doomed
and a serious danger to the social order (an element of the meta-story).
To be in the same room as De Spains wife-bursting in on a domestic
scene that is presupposed to be distant from his reality-is enough to make
every inherited truth precarious. Snopes presence is a moment in time
when things are just not the way that they ought to be but it did not take
much to produce this state of affairs. All that was needed was one near
lunatic straying from the path and this just opens the door to a myriad
of possibilities in how the slender meta-reality can be punctured. The fact
that this reality is slender and slight is what ironically explains the violent
reactions when it is threatened and given that it is threatened easily we can
expect violence often.
Meta-Story as Anti-Story
The way I am describing it, the meta-story is the anti-story. It imposes
an enormous force on the socio-historical development of human agency
and, in the process, distorts it. The anti-story is a ground and component
of tragedy in Faulkners work; we have already seen some of this with
Snopes. We come to know that Snopes has, in a way, seen through the
meta-story, but we can also see that he has to act out the meta-story (as the
role he has to play).
I need to emphasize here the manner in which the meta-story is the
anti-story. Narrative is, at the very least, a description and interpretation
of agency and agency is always imbedded in social and historical reality
(which is itself a narrative). The roles that are inevitably created through
society and history- that is, through relations and subtle forms of causalityare reified in the meta-story: so we have an addition to the considerable
pressure that already exists in the social/historical world for persons to take
up some role. Meta-stories always say or claim something about how this
world can be explained in relation to some other reality. Consequently,
the meta-story is not open for question. Insofar as narrative and so human
reality are shaped and constituted by directly lived reality, the world
of appearances, the meta-story destroys, inhibits, or distorts agency
necessarily.
As I remarked previously, we can feel Snopes resentment and envy; if
we add the idea of the meta-story as anti-story and if it is reasonable to
claim that Snopes has glimpsed the sheer made-up quality of the metastory, then we can conclude that he has a kind of meta-envy and metaresentment. He is caught in the absurd human trap of hating what he
wants to become. Another way of saying this is to realize that Snopes sees
through the meta-story as false but at the same time it has already formed
the center of his orientation. He has resentment concerning the necessity
Christianity is nothing more than the reversal of the causal arrow with
respect to how this meta-story is supposed to have originated and
continues to get new life. According to the champions of the meta-story,
the causal origin is in some supernatural event, the meaning of which
gets transmitted through history and yet somehow remains over and above
history (included are explanations for why some suffer). The possibility
presented in Light in August is that Christianity in any and all its forms- is
nothing more than a reification of various and dominant social wants and
patterns. Hence, once again we can expect that from certain perspectives
the meta-story is going to look ridiculous and indefensible: this is for the
simple reason that it so overtly supports the social realities in question.
The obvious objection to the possibility here raised is the one that goes:
yes, that episode in Christian history is unfortunate (all that racism and
violence!), but it has nothing to do with the essence of the religion. Gradually,
Christianity would have to emerge from bigotry, dogmatism and outrageous
violence. This is an unfortunate response if only for the reason that no
one can possibly untangle Christianity from its social history anymore
than we can untangle the essence of a person from that persons social
history. One would like to say: Christianity is whatever it appears to be and
what it appears to be is strictly empirical/historical. This view concerning
how to understand the reality of Christianity is perfectly symmetrical
to Faulkners historical/social account of the human person. And these
points cut down to what I have been calling the center of orientation.
Christianity, as a meta-story, necessarily works against humanity-even as
it exerts positive moral influence- because it pretends to transcend history.
But the transcendence of history, as Faulkner always knows through the
construction of his characters, is the destruction of narrative and so human
agency. A world in which the notion of a transcendent order was never
even questioned would be an insane and perverse world.
An even not so careful reader of Light in August is bound to notice that
Christmas does seem to overtly reject Christianity and this sets up the
conclusion that Christianity cannot make up any part of the center of his
orientation. This conclusion does not follow from the premise. First, what
we end up rejecting might have already formed various features of our
thinking and experiencing, especially if what we reject is socially pervasive.
In fact, Christianity as a meta-story would be impotent and useless if it
really did transcend history (because inconceivable and so vacuous). Only
as it is taken up into social and historical life does it become anything at
all and then the categories that are formed from its social and historical
life can go everywhere. Given that Christianity is the worldview we can
expect that it has found its way deep into the very manner in which we
experience the world and our selves.
Truthfully, there is no way for Christmas to really separate out Christianity
from the racism that has determined his self-hatred: the very beginning
and end of his existence. Doc Hines and Percy Grimm are acting out the
dictates of the meta-story and all of it is related, in one way or another, to
Christianity. Certainly God is white and there is then no way to escape the
suffocating pervasiveness of the shadow of this God: an ironic version of
the awful saying that God is everywhere. So, wherever Christmas looks
he has to see himself as the object of suspicion, and the enemy of the
whole plan and pattern of reality. To join in with this plan is to voluntarily
destroy himself. There is no other way to make peace with the burden of his
enemies. In other words, that he is an enemy of reality is written into reality
and this is a result of the meta-story. As always with Faulkner, it is the sheer
fact that he has made it this long that is astonishing. And, what seems even
more astonishing, is that Christmas never turns himself completely over
to hatred; what is consistently the object of hatred- in the ways described
above- can never hate as much or as deeply.
Finally, with respect to the tragic story of Joe Christmas, there is a
ubiquitous element of all meta-stories: individuals get what they deserve.
Clearly, Faulkner is turning this notion on its head, but the novel is
drenched with this awful background theme and belief. Opposite views,
say that some people never get what they deserve or that what people
actually get has nothing to do with what they deserve, or finally that we
have no idea what it means for anyone to get what she deserves, are all
contradictory to the notion that the world is as it ought to be. As Faulkner
sees agency and identity so closely tied to history, the same will be true with
respect to whatever form of justice that is dished out. On this view, what
happens to people is always burdened by time and history. To be a person
who is, by definition, an enemy of all social reality (part of the meta-story)
in combination with the aspect of the meta-story that claims that all
people ultimately get what they deserve is a nightmare that cannot be fully
comprehended as a nightmare; that is, Christmas must think within the
same categories even as he suspects that such categories badly misrepresent
his own circumstance.
Sutpen Creating Sutpen 8
There is a strong sense in which Snopes orbits Sutpen. All things considered,
Sutpen is a consolidation of multiple themes in the ongoing cultural
meta-story in which Snopes also participates in around the edges. Perhaps
most importantly, they share the original experience of their own radical
inferiority in this social world. Sutpen describes to General Compson his
humiliation, as a child, in being sent around to the back of the plantation
home. The social world is, however, underwritten by a meta-story and the
one prevalent theme, already seen with Snopes, is the reification of roles.
These roles have a cosmic stamp even as they are ambiguous. Hence to reach
his design Sutpen must take on the task of self-creation and this includes
both a magnificent will to power and core elements of self-annihilation.
Self-creation is another aspect of an emerging meta-story but it needs
two sorts of explanation. The first concerns how it is possible in any sense.
The second concerns how it can be achieved by an individual human being
in a particular circumstance. The answers to both questions are haunting
and finally empty. There really is no sense in which self-creation is possible
and so the identity of the person who endeavors to this feat is bound to
be haunting and empty (in some ways, profoundly inscrutable). Or, even
worse, the emptiness of the endeavor is necessarily perverse and radically
self-defeating.
In a previous section, I argued that meta-stories are written into the
nature of human consciousness. Self-creation is the greatest of the selfdefeating endeavors of consciousness and it also sits at the pinnacle of metastories. Insofar as the self can become an object of consciousness, insofar
as we can see ourselves as distinct from others, we can also see ourselves
as entirely free from history and society (this is all a matter of seeming).
An answer to our first question is then self-creation is possible (merely as a
self-deceived endeavor) through the very nature of self-consciousness. And
there exist certain social/historical conditions that can make the endeavor
urgent. In Sutpens case, the urgency hangs on and around the idea of
flourishing in the only way a person could flourish in his culture: to be a
member of the plantation class. A radical division in forms of life, within
societies, is often the ground of the envy/hatred complex and so finally the
ground of the urgent need for self-creation. The alternative for Sutpen is a
Snopes like existence. While there may be other possible alternatives, there
are no clear reasons for thinking that Sutpen sees these as possibilities and
there are no reasons for thinking that the range of possibilities are other
All of the above points can be seen as Sutpen tells his story, in parts, to
General Compson. As most people will do, Sutpen tells his story with an
authority that subtly dismisses the fact that all narrative is interpretation.
Sutpen differs from others according to the force and deliberateness in
which he asserts and then acts. The tidal wave of disaster that awaits
him is already present in his narrative. His attempts to deny the possible
consequences of his past are the result of already realized consequences of
his past that he is in the process of dismissing. In short, he has to deny
his identity to achieve his identity and this is the self-defeating truth of all
self-creation. I am entirely in control of what I am and what I become
is nothing more than the result of some historical circumstance where
the meta-story and ones place in it are exaggerated (a social, cultural, or
economic urgency bearing down on the human person). Sutpens own
undoing is ultimately the endeavor to deny the very possibility of having
an identity at all; he is, in the endeavor to self-create, a self annihilator.
In the above, I mentioned that the endeavor of self-creation is tied
closely to, or depends on, the will to power. The fact that human identity
necessarily depends on having a history and being, more or less, conscious
of that history also presents- at the same time- the possibility of flatly
denying that history shapes or determines anything at all. One might say
that this assertion is easily made; in fact, everyone makes it in some sense,
but only the Sutpens of the world act and behave as if it is really true.
And this requires an enormous will to power. Sutpen shoulders on into
the future with only his clean notion of the future as motive. His life
comes to resemble and finally encompass a venture of great proportions
and given that his possibility is already tied into the components of human
consciousness and hence human identity, his venture is also our ever
possible venture. Finally, however, Sutpen is a beautifully wrought tragic
figure who must meet a violent death due to his outrageous and all too
human recalcitrance to let go of his clean and shiny future. As he obliterates
connections to others, and so their humanity, he also obliterates his own
humanity and agency. His demise mirrors the demise of his tattered, tired,
and shabby culture.
Again, we know in our more sober moments that all aspects of selfcreation are part of a meta-story. The relationships between self-creation
as meta-story and Christianity as meta-story are multiple and varied;
in fact, the manner in which they intersect and are tied together could
present a whole sociological standpoint on America. Obviously, however,
been occurring to and within that character. And it is not just the suicide
of an individual. It is the suicide of the species because it is the denial
or annihilation of what is constitutive of agency. To dwell in the past,
especially one that is in tatters or never really existed (as imagined) or
to yearn for the past, always betrays a profound sorrow and misgiving
about that past. At its fever pitch it is the recognition, however inchoate,
that whatever transpired in the past is already enough to destroy the
possibility of a future (from within that peculiar consciousness). What is
worth remembering, which is itself a condition for having a memory at
all, is inconsistent with a future; clearly, this is Quentins circumstance.
The limits of action are bound by the imaginative conception of what
is not just possible but worthy of being actual for that agent. Quentins
idealized past, together with the recognition that it is not an ideal past,
creates the ground for a sorrow that leads to self-annihilation. One might
say the same is true of his culture, the background and possibility of his
own particular past.
Human beings are, of course, agents; that is, our lives are intentional and
meaningful in relation to a temporal background (a history). Agency, as
far as we can hope to understand it, is necessarily historical and forward
looking. A history is what allows for the creation of agency. What I did
yesterday and the day before is the only way to understand what I did
at all and those things that I did are what constitute the elements of
my current and future self. (One should also be warned concerning the
search for the origin of the self: this is meta-nonsense.) The future is also
analytically contained in agency as to do x is first to have some sense of
intentionality and this is to have wants, desires, and so forth, all which
presuppose a future. The future is therefore constitutive of being, our
normative ontology (as well as a finite limit to that future) and it is also
constitutive of the possibility of consciousness. The human agent does not
just live through time. The human agent experiences himself or herself as
having a past and having a future as constitutive of having being in the world.
I said in the above that what is worth remembering is a condition
of memory. In other words, what is worthy of remembering has to be
present for memory to take hold and become formative in consciousness.
At the overtly conscious level what and how we remember is structured
and conditioned by what we understand as valuable or non-valuable about
our history and our possible future states. Quentin can no longer recover
what is precisely or unambiguously valuable about his past in relation to
what is possible for his future. Identity is then jeopardized because the
connection between past, present, and future is jeopardized. Insofar as what
is valuable has come through a social world, a background and context, we
come to realize that identity is precariously built on normative relations
to others and their histories. This is where the structure of narrative in
literature reveals what philosophy treats mostly as an abstraction. Locke
found the condition of identity in memory or the stream of consciousness,
a connection between parts of consciousness (memory), but what he failed to
realize is that memory analytically contains what is worth remembering:
in short, it contains character. This is what Faulkner does realize and this
is the key component of how one form of tragedy is possible: the tragedy
of the walking dead.
But it is not just value and valuing that makes human identity possible.
Identity also determines and is determined (back) by the nature of
memories. And here we can take another step into the depths of Quentins
tragedy. To say that value and valuing make memory possible is too general;
we might say that it is the how and why of our memories that really allow
for memory to even begin. We never just remember in any deliberate
sense; there is always a how and why to acts of remembering that are as
much ingrained in the nature of the person as they are in the nature of
society. This how and why of remembering constitutes the character of
both persons and societies.
Quentin has come to remember in ways- the how and why of his
remembering- that are inconsistent with the possibility of a future. His
suicide is then written into his remembering. His suicide is then written
into his past. And here we must come face to face with a horrifying
reality. Agency can be destroyed from within its own components. The
possibility and reality of our sinning, the Christian human nature since
the fall and the key to unlocking all related theodicies cannot unlock this
horrifying reality. Quentin has not gone astray or failed to hear the call
of righteousness, nor does he have some tragic flaw as some method to
tragedy; he has, instead, lost the grounds for being a person.
In the second section of The Sound and The Fury, we are confronted
with the activity of a mind more so than any series of events that would
constitute an external narrative. From the internal narrative, we see that
Quentin has come to occupy the jagged edges of reality. The reason is not
hard to find. His overall desperation has led him to comprehend time as
an object instead of a condition of life. As such Quentin does not seem