Emory 2009
Emory 2009
Emory 2009
Anton Friedrich Koch, Seminar in the spring semester 2009 at Emory University,
Department of Philosophy
20-Jan-09
Hello [Today is inauguration day, not only of your new president, but also my personal inauguration day as an academic teacher in the US etc.]
Subject matter: Hegels Science of Logic, a fascinating theory, but not well understood.
Today: Some preliminaries. Were going to start with a short look on Hegels immediate
predecessors Kant, Fichte and Schelling and on Hegels own earlier project in his Phenomenology of Spirit. (Were going to have a short break around 4:30, possibly after Kant, Fichte
and Schelling.)
But first of all let me say something about the overall character of Hegels philosophical
project, by way of a very short introduction.
-- -- -Short Introduction: The overall character of Hegels philosophical project
In the opening section of Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind, Wilfrid Sellars writes that
the framework of givenness
has been a common feature of most of the major systems of philosophy []. It has,
indeed, been so pervasive that few, if any, philosophers have been altogether free of it;
certainly not Kant, and, I would argue, not even Hegel, that great foe of immediacy.
(Sellars 1963: 127)
Now, what is the framework of givenness? It is a certain philosophical mood of thinking that
has generated a whole lot of different philosophical theories throughout the history of philosophy.
For example, according to Bertrand Russell, what is given is known by acquaintance, and
the rest is only known by description. Sense data, e.g., are given, i.e. known by acquaintance, but not only sense data; Russell thinks (or thought at one point in his long philosophical
career) that all kinds of universals are given as well. You just grasp them in a kind of intellectual intuition.
This is a well-known Platonic theme. Plato thought that ideas were given to reason and that
reason was passive in receiving them. But he also thought that this knowledge by acquaintance, of the ideas, could and should be transformed into knowledge by description in philosophy by the dialectical method. If an idea is grasped by reason (in a kind of intellectual intuition), then it may be discursively articulated in a dialectical process which leads to the definition of the idea. And conversely: if you are offered a definition of a certain idea, you will be
in a privileged position to grasp it in an act of knowledge by acquaintance.
So, for Plato, givenness is only a beginning, not the end. And in this sense he is not a wholehearted champion of givenness. What is given is there immediately. But only what is discursively articulated and conceptually mediated, is really understood and thus fully known.
2
If you are looking for a real champion of givenness, Hume will be a better example than
Plato. Humes sense impressions are paradigmatic entities to be given, and I will take opportunity more than once in the course of this seminar to explain what is going on in Hegels
Logic by relating it to the ontology and the epistemology of Humean sense impressions.
-- -- -Now, Sellars said that not even Hegel, that great foe of immediacy has been altogether
free of the framework of givenness. And indeed, Hegel opens his Logic with
being, pure being without any further determination,
and says of it that in its undetermined immediacy it is equal only to itself and also not unequal to something other, has no difference within it nor towards the outside (WdL I 66).
So, the Logic starts with pure being in its undetermined immediacy (whatever that may
mean).
But let me hasten to add if Hegel begins with undetermined immediacy, he does by no
means want to end up there. So, in his relationship towards immediacy and givenness he is
more like Plato (or Sellars) than like Hume (or Russell).
What is unique to Hegels approach is that he acknowledges the framework of immediacy
and the whole framework of competing metaphysical theories that go along with that immediacy as in some sense true without endorsing it as really true. Very sketchily, one might
present his overall view as follows.
Our pre-philosophical and pre-scientific everyday framework of perceiving, thinking and acting, which Sellars calls the manifest image of man-in-the-world, is unstable in at least two
respects.
(1) It is explanatorily unstable in that it has us ask more questions than can be answered using its conceptual resources. This is why we start developing scientific theories and postulating unobservable, purely theoretical entities like molecules, atoms, positrons, electrons etc.
Sellars has a lot of things to say about that process which, he thinks, will eventually lead us to
a conceptual stage in which we give up the manifest image and start thinking about the world
directly in terms of scientific theories. But of course, we are still very far from that.
(2) But the manifest image is logically (or categorially) unstable as well. It has us ask philosophical questions which it does not seem to give us the conceptual resources to answer. On
the contrary it leads us into paradoxes and antinomies of all kinds, like e.g. the paradoxes of
Zeno.
Nevertheless the manifest image is there to stay and cannot (I believe) be superseded with
some other be it scientific or metaphysical image. Its logical instability manifests itself in
our tendency to engage in (what Peter Strawson called) revisionary metaphysics.
Manifest image: our actual though incomplete conceptual structure, roughly Aristotelian/Strawsonian: the world consists of things and persons, changing in the
course of time.
Scientific image: our future complete conceptual structure: the world consists of what
future physics will then tell us it consists of. (Or so Sellars says.)
Metaphysical images: the various re-categorizations of reality offered by metaphysical
theories (revisionary metaphysics). (E.g. Spinoza: Reality is one singular infinite substance. Or Plato: Reality is the realm of super-sensible, eternal ideas.
Or Leibniz: Reality consists of non-denumerably many non-spatial, absolutely
simple substances called monads.)
3
But, if our manifest image is not only incomplete (inviting more Why-questions than it can
answer), but also logically unstable (inviting more What-questions, i.e. categorial questions than it can answer), revisionary metaphysics is logically unstable as well, and much
more so than the manifest image.
Revisionary metaphysics is a complex framework of competing categorial conceptions of
how things are in themselves and of how things are epistemically accessible to us, i.e. a
framework of competing ontologies and competing epistemologies.
Ideally, each metaphysical theory is centred on some basic categorial conception, e.g. the conception of things as bare particulars or the conception of things as bundles of universals or the
conception of reality as one singular infinite substance, etc. Those basic categorial conceptions turn out, in Hegels philosophy, to form a logical succession, starting from pure being
(pure immediacy) and leading on to more sophisticated categories.
In this series, each successor category negates, i.e. falsifies and in a sense annihilates, its
predecessor the perishing predecessor taking revenge, so to speak, by determining its successor. (Determination is thus the inverse of negation and, under the specific conditions of
symmetry, the same as negation, e.g. in the case of Etwas and Anderes, the Something and the
Other.) We will talk about that in due course.
The logical succession finally comes to a halt, or reaches a fixed point, but and this is the
nub of Hegels philosophy the fixed point turns out to be not one particular last and triumphant category, but gives way to the acknowledgment of the whole series which is, as Hegel
would say, sublated in the fixed point: in absolute knowing according to the Phenomenology
of Spirit, in the absolute idea according to the Science of Logic, and in absolute spirit according to the Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences.
Absolute knowing
the absolute idea
absolute spirit
PhenSp
SoL
EncPhil
(Well talk about the differences between theses fixed points; but not now.)
Hegel thus does not endorse one last and triumphant revisionary metaphysics!
He endorses the whole game of metaphysical or categorial forms in which no one particular
form is the final winner. When he says, in the preface to the Phenomenology, that the truth
is the whole, this is not a commitment to some queer ontological totalitarianism (as e.g.
Russell seems to have thought), it just means that the logical process the evolution of logical space does not privilege one particular metaphysical standpoint over the others.
Each metaphysical standpoint has to give way to a successor standpoint, thus paying the fine
for annihilating its own predecessor, as Anaximander taught; with the last giving way to and
sublating the whole logical process.
What is specific about the game of metaphysical forms, is that according to Hegel it is played
by reality itself and then replayed and completed by the various metaphysicians (who are,
of course, themselves part of that very same reality). Thus, the basic theorems of a metaphysical theory may well be true in the sense of corresponding to a certain stage in the development of logical space. But they should be treated as logically indexical sentences, accordingly, true at one point in the logical succession and false at others. If they are propounded
as logically eternal sentences, as they typically are in metaphysics, they turn out wrong, because the stage in the logical process they correctly depict is transitory.
Personally indexical sentences: true in the mouth of one speaker and false in the
mouths of others [I am Josef Ratzinger.]
4
Spatially indexical sentences: true at one place and false at others [Theres only rocks
and sand around.]
Temporally indexical sentences: true at one time and false at others [Caesar is
dead.]
Logically indexical sentences: true at one stage in the logical process (the evolution
of logical space) and false at others [The real is (at a given logical stage) one
infinite substance.]
[Metaphysical theorems are false as offered by metaphysics, i.e. as logically eternal
sentences, but may be true as logically indexical sentences.]
Hegel wants us to see through the game of metaphysical forms and to become aware of the
strength of the manifest image and the weakness of revisionary metaphysics.
The manifest image is, so to speak, our zero conceptual scheme: what is left over from the
logical construction and deconstruction of metaphysical forms. It is the corpus of mostly true
beliefs Donald Davidson had in mind, when he criticized the very idea of a (non-zero) conceptual scheme.
But in its logical instability the manifest image is inevitably under attack by revisionary metaphysics. Purely descriptive metaphysics therefore, as envisaged by Peter Strawson, will not
do. The manifest image has to be justified, i.e. defended against the revisionary attacks and
eo ipso purified from all the remains of (non-zero) conceptual schemes and embedded into a
new kind of philosophical thinking.
Hegel wants to do all of this by deliberately playing the metaphysical game until the end, reconstructing and deconstructing it at the same time. If in the end we see through the metaphysical process of competing conceptual schemes and competing forms of reality, we get
free to acquiesce in the zero structure we learned at our mothers knee a structure now
safely embedded into a stabilizing post-metaphysical philosophical theory (Hegels). Or thats
what Hegel wants to show.
-- -- -[Questions? Expectations? Common theoretical ground? My analytic heroes in the seventies and eighties were Quine, Sellars, Davidson, Strawson (also Rorty, Kripke, David Lewis,
Gareth Evans, and Carnap and Wittgenstein). And my continental heroes were first and
foremost Kant, then Plato, Aristotle, Hegel and Heidegger and Fichte. Is that enough common
ground for us?]
-- -- -Remarks on the theoretical setting
1781
1794/95
1795ff.
Kant, CPR
Fichte, Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre
Schellings various publications
1806/07
1812, 21832
1813
SoL I:
SoL II:
Sein (Being)
Wesen (Essence)
Objective
Logic
1816
SoL III:
Subjective Logic
5
SoL (Being, Essence, Notion)
Philosophy of Nature (mechanics, physics/chemistry, organic physics/biology)
Philosophy of Spirit (subjective Spirit, objective Spirit, absolute Spirit)
1. Kant
Aristotle taught that the fundamental determinations of being were designated by the forms
of predication, the schmata ts katgorias (Met. D 7, 1017a23). The predications is a
horse and is a man have different contents by which they designate different things (different concepts, different extensions, or what have you). But they have a common form: both
are sortal predications. And according to this common form they both designate substance.
And the predications is white and is musical, according to their common form, designate
quality. Etc.
ta schmata ts katgorias
The forms of predication
Kant criticizes that this procedure of finding the fundamental modes of being, i.e. the categories, is rather botanizing. And then: How shall one count forms of predication? Not surprisingly, according to Kant, Aristotles procedure turned out to be not very reliable and lead to a
mistaken list of the categories which included items that didnt belong there like place and
time and which lacked items which really do belong there like reality, negation, causality
and others.
So Kant proposes a new procedure, according to a principle. And his actual choice of principle turns out to be a coup by which he surpasses not only Aristotle but also, in a different respect, Hume.
Hume had shown that the concepts of substance and causality could not be explained and
justified empirically and he had concluded that they owed their respective contents to imagination and habit. Kant, by contrast, wants to justify them by deducing (or gaining) their contents from a sphere of knowledge that is as solid and secure as mathematics, viz. formal logic.
It is an irony of the history of philosophy that it was Aristotle who had developed logic into
the system of syllogistics. Kant thus wants to surpass Aristotle (on the categories) by using an
Aristotelian achievement. One only needs that was Kants thought to transpose the syllogistically relevant thought contents into another key and one will get the fundamental concepts of pure understanding or, ontologically speaking, the categories.
The relevant logical contents are expressed by certain syncategorematic expressions which
are essential for evaluating the formal correctness of syllogisms, like all and some, is
and not, if , then .. etc. Now Kants recipe for finding the categories is just this: Take
the syncategorematic logical contents and squeeze them into categorematic size, in other
words: take the logical constants, isolate their purely logical thought contents, and bring those
contents into conceptual form, i.e. into the form of (general) terms and you will have got
want you wanted: a set of concepts which you may call categories because they are (or purport to be) fundamental with respect to everything there is, and which you may as well call
concepts of pure understanding because there contents are purely logical.
Of course, this transposition of contents from the syncategorematic to the categorematic key
the metaphysical deduction of the categories is by no means a simple affair. But it turns
out simple in relation to what is yet to come, the so-called transcendental deduction.
For, even if the categories are but logical contents in the shape of terms, their objective validity isnt thereby vindicated yet.
6
Sure, it is true that we have to conceive of reality according to the categories (if the metaphysical deduction is right). And sure, what makes us conceive of reality in this way, is not
the brute power of habit, as Hume had thought, but the soft power of reason. Still, the soft
power of reason is one thing, and reality may quite well be another. We do not have any guarantee that reality behaves rationally and will continue to do so. All we have justified, up to
now (i.e. in the metaphysical deduction), is a rational faith that the real be well-behaved,
according to our lights. (Like, according to Kant, in practical philosophy one can justify a
rational faith in the existence of God and in the immortality of our souls.)
But wait a minute, a Strawsonian-minded philosopher might expostulate. We have shown
that we must conceive of reality by way of the categories. Call this a rational faith if you like.
But then look: reality does in fact behave as it should according to our rational faith. It offers
lots of cases of causality and substantiality; and whenever it seems to someone that it doesnt
do so on a particular occasion, we might as well tell that person: Try harder looking. But
nothing of that sort can be appealed to, regarding the questions of god and soul.
Well, that may be true, but Kant is rather demanding and exacting. And above all, he thinks
he has in fact found a way to prove the objective validity of the categories, a way i.e. to show
that our application of the categories to things and events in space and time isnt mere rational
faith enhanced empirically by the contingent behaviour of things and events, but that the real
is guaranteed to behave according to our categories. (We have a legal right, so to speak, of
expecting the real to behave according to our categories.)
Hume was completely right, Kant thinks, that one cannot detect categorial determinations of
things by sensuous receptivity. But on the other hand, our understanding does not intuit any
objects. Therefore we have to project (or read) the pure concepts of understanding into the
objects. And of course one must ask: Are we justified to do so?
Kant wants to answer this question in the affirmative. He wants to show in a transcendental
deduction that we project or read into the objects just as much as really lies in them just as
much as really and necessarily lies in all spatiotemporal objects, even though it is not perceivable by the senses. Everything spatiotemporal, of and by itself, has already adjusted itself
to our pure concepts of the understanding.
This is Kants Copernican turn. We dont need to adjust ourselves to the things in our
knowledge of their categorial determinations nor do we need to adjust things to our knowledge and thereby to distort them; but all things (in space and time) have by themselves adjusted themselves to our pure concepts. So we by no means do have to truncate or gerrymander things, as Nietzsche and Adorno suspected, when we subsume them under our concepts.i
Hegel didnt see this Kantian subtlety. He has Kant say that the categories are our addition to
the big cake of reality. Hegels Kant is, as he calls it, an adherent of subjective idealism. The
historical Kant however is not a subjective idealist, as I see it, even though he talks as if he
were one from time to time. But we may set questions of Kantian exegesis to one side and just
stress one point: that Hegel thought that Kants transcendental deduction was insufficient.
2. Fichte
Hegel thought that the metaphysical deduction was not sufficient either. Kant had reproached Aristotle that he was botanizing in giving his list of the categories. Now, Hegel
turns exactly this reproach critically against Kant himself.
The way for this critique had been prepared by Fichte, more precisely by Fichtes claim that
his Wissenschaftslehre (doctrine of knowledge or science) provided a foundation of logic of
the very logic Kant had taken for granted in giving his list of the categories. We might easily
7
think that this Fichtean claim is crazy. How can logic be in need of a foundation? What kind
of knowledge could be firmer than logic? And, secondly, how could it be possible to provide
a foundation for logic? Would not logic have to be presupposed as valid in giving a theoretical foundation for whatever type of knowledge?
But on closer inspection logic shows itself endangered by paradox. There are well-known
antinomies in set theory and in semantics which can be traced back to purely logical roots. I
am particularly thinking of the so-called Liar Paradox: What I say right now is not true, or:
This sentence is not tue, or:
(1)
Normally, of course, people would deny that this was a logical antinomy. Formerly, one
would have put the blame on the self-referential subject term of the sentence, claiming (like
Wittgenstein in the Tractatus) that no sentence could be its own subject. But, of course, there
is nothing wrong with the sentence:
This sentence has five words;
and, apart from that, Gdel has shown that any theory as strong as arithmetic is strong enough
to contain its own syntax. So, a sentence may very well have itself as its own subject matter.
Nowadays therefore people tend to put the blame on the predicate of the Liar: is true. But
the truth predicate is quite innocent as well, being nothing more, here, than part of a technical
device, which Quine once dubbed semantic ascent. [How do you accentuate ascent?]
In semantic ascent we talk about language, but that is pure lip service. In predicating truth (or
denying truth) of sentences we show that our heart is not with language, but with the world,
after all. When we say: The sentence snow is white is true, we are officially speaking
about an English sentence, but in reality we are saying something logically equivalent to the
simple sentence: Snow is white, which is a sentence about the world.
In cases like Snow is white is true, where we are predicating truth of single sentences,
semantic ascent is a trivial and superfluous manoeuvre; for we might as well simply say:
Snow is white. But there are cases, where semantic ascent becomes mandatory or necessary. Think for example of arithmetic, i.e. the infinite set of all arithmetical truths. You believe that all arithmetical theorems are true, but it would take you too much time, in fact an
infinite amount of time, to state them all one by one.
So you just say: Arithmetic is true, or you state the axioms of arithmetic and say something
like: These sentences and all sentences that logically follow from them are true. Here semantic ascent is mandatory.
Now, I claim that in the Liar the truth predicate occurs only as a technical device for the sake
of semantic ascent. The essence of the Liar is just that it is a sentence which is logically
equivalent to its own negation. And in this sense it just is its own negation:
n iff not-n
You cannot write down n in a finite language, because you would have to write down an infinite amount of negation signs (and brackets):
~(~(~()))
But there is no infinitely long sentence in a finite language. So, you use semantic ascent and
say This sentence is not true instead.
Now, if neither the self-referential subject term of the Liar nor its semantic predicate term is
the source of the antinomy, where does that source lie and where is it to be found?
8
There are three possible sources of paradox or antinomy in the Liar:
(1)
~ ((1) is true),
(i) the subject term (1) which is self-referential in that it refers to the sentence of which it is
part,
(ii) the predicate is true, which is a semantic predicate, in fact the truth predicate, and
(iii) the negation sign ~.
The subject term is harmless, as Gdel has shown. The predicate term is harmless too, just a
device of semantic ascent (or so I claim). So, the damage done rests with negation.
Parmenides said so, 2500 years ago, and I think he was right. If a language is strong enough
to include negation (and it wouldnt be a language otherwise), then it is strong enough to create paradoxical contents like the content of the Liar.
Discursive thinking as such, I would conclude with Parmenides, is inconsistent. (And Hegel
would applaud.) Well come back to that point in the course of our seminar over and over
again. For the time being suffice it to say that discursive thinking and with it logic is in trouble.
Fichte to return to his project set out to solve the problem in his Wissenschaftslehre. He
wanted to tell an encompassing story, based on logic of course, designed to justify logic from
within. With logic, we run into the inconsistency of the Liar, but with logic we can also think
of the principle of non-contradiction as a regulative ideal, still. Reason constitutes itself as
the norm of all thinking in an original act that Fichte calls the Tathandlung, i.e. an action
which is its own result.
I wont go into the details of Fichtes story. Its thrust is (as I said) that reason constitutes itself
as a norm of (and on) thinking by creating and then clinging to the principle of non-contradiction as a regulative principle: Wherever you run into a contradiction, dont remain there, shy
away from it, dont draw any consequences from it, put it into logical quarantine. In this way,
reason (or the absolute I) enforces itself, in the face of non-reason and contradiction.
Within that programme Fichte generated the principles of logic like the sentence of identity
((x) (x=x)), the principle of non-contradiction and the principle of sufficient reason, as well
as the categories quite systematically; and Hegel praised his procedure as truly speculative.
This is one side of Fichtes enterprise, the side of the metaphysical deduction. But there is
also the side of the transcendental deduction, which has to be taken care of; and Hegel
thinks that here Fichte is still far from a satisfactory solution. For Hegel, Fichte as well as
Kant counts as a supporter of subjective idealism; and this verdict seemed to be justified
by Fichte himself who claimed that his philosophy was but a doctrine of science (or knowledge), not a doctrine of reality as it was in itself.
Nevertheless, I think that Fichtes theory is grossly misinterpreted, if taken as a variety of
subjective idealism. The knowledge which is its subject matter is not the knowledge in our
heads, but the knowledge out there in the things, i.e. the phenomenality of things: that
through which they are epistemically accessible to us in perception, experience, and theory
building. And beyond their epistemic accessibility nothing determinate remains of things.
Fichtes doctrine of science thus does not allow for any hidden variables or parameters; it only
makes a conceptual distinction between the phenomenality of the real and the real itself. It
does not state or imply that the real is in some way hidden to us.
3. Schelling
9
According to realism, the real is independent of our beliefs about it. But then our most wellconsidered theories and beliefs could all be wrong. This is the well-known fundamental predicament of realism. Realism, if not counterbalanced by pragmatism or some other variety of
non-realism, leads to scepticism. If scepticism is to be avoided, if, that is, the real is to be
epistemically accessible, then it must be (and must be conceived as) essentially related to our
beliefs and as being in some sense belief-dependent.
But the belief-dependence of what is real must not be treated as total or absolute either. Otherwise the real would be turned into a mere subjective content of our beliefs. So we have to
beware not to get into the dilemma of unknowable things in themselves on the one hand and
purely subjective representational contents on the other.
This is a real dilemma for philosophy even today, the dilemma between metaphysical realism and pragmatist antirealism. Metaphysical realism postulates a belief-independent thing
in itself and thus turns the practice of truth claims (and of giving and asking for reasons for
truth claims) into a game of betting without the possibility to find out if one has betted correctly. Antirealism on the other hand loses reality as something objective and independent of
our cognitive practices.
One obvious way out of the dilemma would be to just fuse the objective and the subjective
and to say that what is real in the last analysis call it the Absolute, if you like is beyond the
divide of the subjective and the objective and thus beyond the divide of idealism and realism.
Of course, the Absolute, so conceived, must not be restricted to the status of posit of a philosophical theory. It must be epistemically accessible independently of philosophical theory
building, in a kind of intellectual intuition or, more precisely, an intellectual self-intuition.
Philosophy may help bring a person to the vantage point where this intellectual self-intuition
of the Absolute actualizes itself; but the possibility of such actualization must be there as
something independent of philosophical theory building, or else the identity of subject and
object would remain a theoretical posit.
Now, Hegel thinks that this desideratum is fulfilled in the philosophy of his friend Schelling.
Kant had taught that our understanding was discursive and that we could not intuit objects
intellectually. Fichte had assented to these teachings and added that nevertheless reason constitutes itself in an act of original self-intuition. So, according to Fichte, we do not have any
intellectual intuition of objects (just as Kant had taught), but we do have intellectual selfintuition of the rational I. But Hegel suspects that what is independently real, the Absolute, is
left out of the act of Fichtean intellectual self-intuition. He suspects that Fichtes absolute I
is just subjectivity writ large. Schelling does correct this mistake (or what Hegel thinks is a
mistake). For Schelling teaches that the other part of reality over and above human reason, the
ontological partner or playmate of reason, so to speak, the Object (with capital O), is included in the act of original intellectual self-intuition. Thus, the real and absolute self is the
original identity of subject and object. Therefore, Schelling calls his philosophy the philosophy of identity.
In other words, the Absolute exists as well in itself as for itself, exists both as the object
which is intuited intellectually and as the intuiting subject.
But if this approach manages to overcome, both subjective idealism and metaphysical realism,
and thus is the true philosophy in a nutshell, nevertheless we do now face the methodological problem to turn the intellectual self-intuition of the Absolute into a well-articulated philosophical theory. In other words, we must (Hegel thinks) leave the framework of givenness,
in which Schelling got stuck.
Of course, a philosopher such like Schelling may just dogmatically claim and assure us that
he, as the spokesperson of the Absolute, so to speak, is capable of diving into the intellectual
10
self-intuition of the Absolute and then inform us other people how it is like to be part of the
self-intuition of the Absolute. But what reasons could we other people have to believe him?
Schellings general claim would just be one among several competing basic philosophical
claims, and we could as well opt for one of those other claims (dogmatic realism for example).
In the Phenomenology of Spirit Hegel wants to do better than his friend (and then ex-friend,
because of this very fact). The true philosophy must acquire its adequate discursive form, it
must not be presented dogmatically and in the form of a report or narration of a philosophically privileged hero. Philosophical truth is in need of (and capable of) a scientific, discursive,
reason-giving exposition. But to this end (and for this sake) the fundamental intellectual selfintuition would itself have to become discursively articulated. I.e. the framework of givenness
would have to be overcome and left behind.
Platos philosophy could serve as a paradigm here. On the one hand, Plato believes in a kind
of intellectual intuition he calls nosis: a grasping of the Forms by reason. On the other hand,
what is grasped in nosis, the forms or ideas (ideai), is definable, which means that it can be
articulated discursively, albeit in a very specific form of discourse which Plato calls dialectic.
Hegel goes one step further still by postulating that nosis (or intellectual intuition) and dialectical articulation are one and the same thing. Hegelian dialectic thus is nothing but the
way in which the intellectual self-intuition of the Absolute is accomplished. So, we have here
a synthesis of intuition and discourse, one that Hegel calls speculation (which is the Latin
word for the Greek theria).
qewri/a, speculatio
11
So, for the time being, let us forget everything we ever heard about dialectic and let us understand by Hegels method something quite elementary and simple: the way he proceeds in
his theory building in the face of philosophical scepticism. Hegel proposes to the sceptic to
join him in a thoroughgoing examination of our knowledge claims or, more precisely, an examination of our philosophical knowledge claims or, still more precisely, of our basic claim
that in our states of consciousness (our mental acts and states) we are related to an objective
reality. This claim is made explicit in philosophy, but of course it is implicit in our pre-philosophical daily ways of thinking and acting.
Traditional philosophy has made explicit and tried to work out and justify this basic claim to
objectivity in various competing categorial forms. (Aristotle thought that the real was a plurality of finite substances, while Spinoza thought that it was the unique infinite substance, to
mention but two examples of traditional metaphysical conceptions, two examples of competing ontologies.)
-- -- -Let us now take a closer look on Hegels philosophical theory, first as developed in the Phenomenology of Spirit in 1806/07. In this work Hegel examines our claims to knowledge or,
more precisely, the various categorial forms our general claim can take that in our states of
consciousness we are related to what is real.
So the examination is not directed at ordinary truth claims of the kind Descartes was trying
to put into doubt, e.g. that we are presently feeling the warmth of the room we are sitting in
and or seeing a table right in front of us, etc.. But it is directed at philosophical or categorial
truth claims, which need not be put into doubt artificially and held in doubt by some mental
gymnastics like the Cartesian fiction of an evil demon, but which have in fact been moot ever
since antiquity and which are still moot and more so than ever after Kants attempt to set
metaphysics on the secure path of a science.
What Hegel means by consciousness is, very roughly speaking, perceptually informed intentionality as organized by our general claim to objective knowledge. That claim expresses our
pre-theoretical (but implicitly philosophical) conviction that the passing show is objectively
real, and it has, in metaphysical theory building, taken on different categorial forms. Metaphysics set itself the task of making explicit and evaluating candidate categorial forms of the
real, but it did not come up with a unique picture. Aristotle, for instance, thought that what
was real in the passing show was a manifold of finite substances, Spinoza thought that the real
was the one and only infinite substance, to mention but two examples of conflicting ontologies.
Now, Hegel does not want to do any botanizing with respect to the history of philosophy;
what he wants to do is to systematically deduce all categorial conceptions from next to nothing so that the sceptic may go along with him. For that reason he proposes the following procedure to the sceptic. First, look for a superlatively simple categorial conception of the passing show to start with, i.e. in Hegels terminology, look for a superlatively simple Ansich, or
in-itself. Hegel, in the first chapter of the Phenomenology, starts supernominalistically, with
the passing show conceived as a manifold of distinct individual entities as such.
Next, think of the general structure of consciousness. In our knowledge claims we hold that
the real is epistemically accessible to us. That means we all pre-theoretically hold the following implicitly philosophical view (which Hegel does not endorse, but wants to examine):
What is objectively real and thus independent of our various beliefs is nonetheless essentially
related to our beliefs and thus in a way dependent upon them. This view, which is close to
inconsistency, is the kernel of consciousness. Consciousness thus is essentially a (proto-philosophical) view or a theory, and a latently inconsistent one at that. Its general, abstract struc-
12
ture might therefore as well be called the contrast or opposition of consciousness (der Gegensatz des Bewutseins). In the introduction to the Phenomenology Hegel characterizes it in the
following way:
[Consciousness as the subject] distinguishes [] something from itself [the object] to
which it refers [or relates itself] at the same time, or, as this is usually expressed,
something is for it [for consciousness]; and the determined [i.e. dependent, co-variable] aspect of the referring or of the being of something for a consciousness is
knowledge [or, in the case of failure, the mere claim to knowledge]. But from this being for something other [the being of an object for consciousness, the epistemic accessibility of the object] we do distinguish the being in itself; what is [essentially] related
to knowledge is at the same time distinguished from knowledge and is posited as being
as well apart from the relation [to knowledge]. The side [or aspect] of this in-itself is
called truth [or we could say reality, if we preferred to reserve the word truth for
statements and beliefs; reality is so to speak truth in rebus].iv
Dressed in philosophical jargon this statement might look fraught with moot presuppositions.
But in fact Hegel here is trying to get rid of philosophical presuppositions and to ally with the
sceptic in saying something quite elementary. He just mentions and describes, but does not
endorse, the basic claim of consciousness, according to which the Ansich (the in-itself) of
what is real determines the Fr-es (the for-consciousness) of what is real. The Ansich is a
categorial conception of the real as it is in itself, thus an implicit proto-ontology produced by
consciousness. The Fr-es is a categorial conception of the real as it is epistemically accessible, thus an implicit proto-epistemology produced by consciousness. And consciousness, at its
most basic, is the claim that the Fr-es is (or at least ought to be) fully determined by the Ansich. Should, for example, the real in itself consist of many distinct particulars but be present
for consciousness as a plurality of universals, then consciousness in that specific form
would be categorially false, i.e. a piece of false philosophy. But if that is so, then poor consciousness! Its full success is bound to be its end, for as soon as the Fr-es takes on the categorial conception of the Ansich, there will be nothing left to ground the difference of role between the Ansich and the Fr-es which is of the essence of consciousness. Consciousness, we
begin to see, in its self-opposition or inconsistency, will have to sublate itself into some epistemic state beyond itself, a state which Hegel calls absolute knowing. But I am getting ahead
of my story and must now come back to the testing procedure that Hegel proposes to the sceptic.
-- -- --
13
27-Jan-09
We are presently talking about Hegels programme in the Phenomenology of Spirit, i.e. about
his method (in a very elementary sense of the word method), as it is sketched by him in the
introduction. Afterwards we will take a look into the first chapter, on sense-certainty, in
order to see how the method is supposed to work. (Then well turn to the Science of Logic, at
last.)
-- -- -I. Method according to the Introduction of the PhSp
Up to now, Hegel has offered us a superlatively simple
starting ontology: (the passing show as) distinct individuals
plus the
abstract structure of consciousness,
i.e. the difference of role between the Ansich and the Fr-es. That abstract structure, Hegel
thinks, functions like an input/output device for ontologies and epistemologies, or like a recursive function with the Ansich or proto-ontology as the independent variable and the
Fr-es or proto-epistemology as the dependent variable.
The structure may thus be put to service as a device for computing a Fr-es given a certain
Ansich. You put in a categorial conception as the Ansich (an ontology), and the device puts
out a categorial conception as the co-ordinated Fr-es (an epistemology), a conception which
ought to be, but by no means always is, the same categorial conception as the Ansich.
?
Ansich (proto-ontology)
Fr-es (proto-epistemology)
Thus Hegel (or we) need not evaluate a given proto-ontology from our external point of
view, by comparing it with our own favourite ontology. That would be dogmatism, and the
sceptic would be right to protest against such a testing procedure.
But instead of that: consciousness itself (as I said last week) is a kind of theory or, better still,
a kind of theoretician and can at least falsify, if not verify, its own claims. For consciousness
is defined by the claim that the Ansich determines the Fr-es according to its own categorial
form.
-- -- -I will soon give an example of how the computing device works, when I come to talk about
the first chapter of the Phenomenology. For the time being suffice it to say that in that chapter
Hegel shows that if you start the device by putting in a supernominalistic ontology of distinct individuals, the device will deliver as output a platonistic epistemology of universals
so that this first form or shape of consciousness, sense-certainty, is falsified. But how, from
there, is the testing procedure to go on?
Viewed from the internal standpoint of sense-certainty, it is the platonistic Fr-es which is
discredited by the nominalistic Ansich. But viewed from our external standpoint the failure
must be blamed on the independent variable, i.e. on the Ansich. It was the input of the nominalistic Ansich that produced the output of a platonistic Fr-es. Therefore the nominalistic
Ansich is discredited as well. We need a new Ansich as a new source and criterion for a new
Fr-es.
14
In Hegels words:
It thus occurs to consciousness that what it formerly took to be the in-itself is not in itself, or that it was in itself only for it [for consciousness]. So, when consciousness inspects its object and finds that its knowledge does not correspond to the object, the object itself does not stand the test either; or the criterion of the examination changes,
when that which was to be tested by it does not stand the examination; and the examination is not only an examination of knowledge, but also of the criterion for testing.v
Hence, the testing proceeds like this.
We let consciousness choose an Ansich (an ontology) and then wait and see what Fr-es
(what epistemology) is thereby determined. If the Fr-es consciousness comes up which differs categorially from the Ansich, then the operative shape of consciousness is falsified, and
consciousness must correct itself.
So, we let it choose a new Ansich. But we have to be careful not to fall into philosophical
botanizing at this point. What is needed is a unique candidate Ansich. And a unique candidate Ansich is what we have got, for consciousness has produced exactly one deviating categorial conception in the role of the Fr-es. It can thus try the old Fr-es as the new Ansich.
Hegel calls this change of role of the previous Fr-es a reversal of consciousness.vi Our
first input into the abstract structure of consciousness was an ontology of distinct individuals,
and the output was an epistemology of general traits. In a second attempt we must therefore
put into the structure an ontology of general traits, and the structure will yield some new
epistemology.
Hegel expects that consciousness will falsify itself in this procedure over and over again and
will thereby systematically generate and reject all possible ontologies and epistemologies,
until in the end it reaches a fixed point where input and output are identical. This fixed point
Hegel calls absolute knowing.
-- -- -Suppose that Hegel is right and that the input/output procedure does lead to a fixed point in
the event. Still, there might be launched at least two sceptical objections.
First, the testing procedure could have left out some categorial forms, and, second, the fixed
point as a shape of consciousness would still not be verified, but only not falsified. The first
problem is the problem of completeness, the second one is the problem of verification.
Ad (1). The problem of completeness will lose much of its bite, if in the course of the examination of consciousness it turns out that all categorial conceptions of the real which have been
developed in the history of philosophy are taken care of, up to the latest philosophy of Hegels
(or our) day, viz. Schellings system of identity, whose standpoint ought to be reached in the
fixed point. Hence, the exposition of the successive self-correction of consciousness should
turn out as an idealized reconstruction of the history of thought; and Hegel thinks that indeed
it does.
The burden of proof then lies with the sceptic who would have to come up with some categorial conception, either from the history of philosophy or of his own making, and show that
it was not taken care of in Hegels theory. (Perhaps we from our present day vantage point
could cite Frege and the methodological idea propagated by some of those who profited from
his work: to let a priori semantics play the role of a first philosophy, as something utterly new
that Hegel did not foresee.)
Ad (2). The second problem, the one of verification, may be posed thus. The exact correspondence of the Fr-es and the Ansich in the fixed point is only a necessary, not a sufficient
15
condition of the truth of consciousness. For even the last Ansich in the series is but a categorial conception devised by consciousness. And how are we to find out, whether it is the
objectively correct conception? Wouldnt we have to know quite independently what the true
Ansich was?
Hegel answers that the process of consciousness is self-fulfilling or, as Hegels German has
it, self-fulbringing scepticism (vollbringen in German means to accomplish).vii This
holds in two respects.
(a) First, each shape of consciousness occasions a specific sceptical doubt which forces the
process to go on and leave that shape behind. In this way philosophy-directed scepticism is
embedded in the Phenomenology of Spirit.
(b) Second, the categorial base of scepticism as such (i.e. as directed against knowledge
claims whatsoever, including ordinary ones) is itself generated, criticised and left behind as
one particular shape of consciousness in the process of examination.viii So at the fixed point
our knowledge will have to be informed by reality, if only for lack of viable alternatives.
(And again the burden of proof would lie with the sceptic.)
-- -- -But what now about the fixed point: what categorial conception could be its content? Since
the input/output game of consciousness is supposed to offer an idealized reconstruction of the
history of consciousness, Hegel must expect the fixed point to be reached historically in his
own time. It was reached, he thinks, in Schellings philosophy of identity. What then is most
characteristic of Schelling?
As Hegel sees it, Schelling has overcome subjective idealism and conceived the identity of
thinking subject and objective reality as an inarticulate and immediate intellectual intuition
in which the real is present to itself. In its total lack of structure, however, this intellectual
self-intuition resembles, as Hegel mockingly says, the night in which all cows are black.ix
But then the fixed point of the process of consciousness too must resemble the night in which
all cows are black. And this is the result we get, if we now ask in a more systematic vein
what the content of the fixed point must be.
In the fixed point being-in-itself and being-for-consciousness take on the same categorial
form. So they do not differ intrinsically any longer; only the abstract difference of their roles
is meant to last.
But this is impossible, an untenable postulate from the external standpoint of the theoretician.
Viewed from the inside, i.e. from the standpoint of consciousness, there is nothing left to
ground any difference of role. The duality of the Ansich and the Fr-es just collapses at the
fixed point, and so does the related duality of that which was to be in itself, viz. the object,
and that for which it was to be, viz. consciousness or the subject.
In-itself and for-consciousness, object and subject, all collapse into indifference. The structure of consciousness itself is lost in indifference and immediacy.
-- -- -So far, then, Schelling seems to be vindicated. But, of course, Hegel does not want to wind
up in complete immediacy, the night in which all cows are black. So he must claim that
something is different between his and Schellings philosophy and that the difference has to
do with the conceptual articulation of absolute knowing.
The fixed point, as was already said, does not give rise to some new form of scepticism. This
is so, because the fixed point is no particular shape of consciousness any more. As soon as
16
Fr-es and Ansich are congruent, consciousness is transformed into intellectual self-intuition. But this transformation can be looked upon in two different ways.
(a) On the one hand, absolute knowing is intellectual self-intuition, an inarticulate extensionless point which marks the boundary between the Phenomenology and the Science
of Logic.
(b) But if, on the other hand, absolute knowing marks this boundary, it will receive a rich
content from what is separated and at the same time linked by it. In this new perspective absolute knowing isnt just a limiting point, but the encompassing unity of (at
least) all previous shapes of consciousness and (perhaps also) all logical determinations which are still to come in the Logic.
All categorial forms are in it degraded to fluid moments of an evolving and ongoing totality.
Hegel tries to illustrate this by comparison with the organic process of a plant whose successive forms bud, blossom, fruit as he says
do not only differ, but also displace each other as incompatible with one another. But
their fluid nature at the same time turns them into moments of the organic unity in
which they not only do not militate against each other, but are one as necessary as the
other; and only this equal necessity constitutes the life of the whole.x
The actual whole, we read some lines later, is the result together with its coming about;
while the bare result is the corpse which has left the guiding tendency behind it.xi
That means Hegel does not want to supplant traditional metaphysics with a new one; his
new metaphysics if it can be called that consists in acknowledging the game of competing
metaphysical theories as the nature of our consciousness as well as of reality.
II. Sense-Certainty
To give an example of how consciousness works as an input/output device for categorial
forms, let me now make some remarks on the first chapter of the Phenomenology.
The simplest ontology, given the passing show, would seem to be an ontology of distinct
individuals spread out in space and time, and the simplest epistemology an epistemology of
immediate presence to consciousness. Hence, the nominalistic ontology of distinct individuals would go together well with an empiricist epistemology of sense impressions; in fact,
ontology and epistemology would coincide, for the impressions just would be the distinct individuals. That is the opening stage in the process of consciousness. Hegel calls it sensecertainty.
nominalistic ontology of distinct individuals
empiricist epistemology of sense impressions
Now, thinking and saying have propositional form: We refer to something and predicate
something of it.
Propositional form: reference and predication / truth and falsity
But if the individuals of sense-certainty are really distinct and dont have any common traits
(things with common traits would involve introducing a different ontology), then all we can
say about each of them is that it is or exists.
Referring to an individual, as Peter Strawson has shown, presupposes that we know some
individuating fact about it;xii but in the scenario of sense-certainty there are no individuating
facts, because each individual just is or exists, and this is all we can say. So we, acting for
17
sense-certainty, cannot refer to any one of the many individuals, since we cannot individuate
them in thought or in speech.
But if we cannot individuate them by description, maybe we can do so by ostension. Under
normal conditions of course we can. But under normal conditions our indexicals are suitably
backed up by descriptions (here, in this room, now, while it is raining, I, the man who is
presently raising his hand etc.).
In the stage of sense-certainty on the other hand we would have nothing with which to back
up our use of indexicals. Therefore, at that stage, we could not refer to individuals in thought
or in speech: we could only mean them in a very special sense of this word, in which Hegel
uses it to signify a cognitive attitude towards logically private objects, the very idea of which
was attacked by Wittgenstein in his private language argument.
LWs PLA: There cannot be a private language, i.e. a language about logically private objects.
The individuals of sense-certainty would indeed be such logically private objects, they would
be logically mine, if they did exist an insight Hegel expresses by the pun: What is mine, I
can only mean. [Was mein ist, kann ich nur meinen.]
-- -- -This, so far, is the scenario of sense-certainty as described from the external standpoint of
the philosopher or theoretician. Hegel next asks how the scenario would present itself from
the internal standpoint of sense-certainty, and then goes on to consider three variants of
sense-certainty, one realistic, the other idealistic and the last a kind of neutral monism.
three variants of sense-certainty: realism, idealism, neutral monism
He has got four terms to work with: the Ansich, the Fr-es, the object, and the subject. These
allow for a combinatorial approach in which the es of the Fr-es is always to be identified
with the subject, but in which the Ansich may be associated either, realistically and most
naturally, with the object, or, if that should fail, again with the subject, in the spirit of idealism. If that wont work either, the last resort will be to fuse object and subject in the spirit of
neutral monism.
Four terms: Ansich, Fr-es, subject (= es), object
(1) A = O
R
(2) A = S
I
(3) A = S = O
NM
But let us proceed step by step.
-- -- -First then let us put the object into the position of what is in itself, and let us ask, whether it
can occur in the subjects knowledge just like it is in itself.
It is posited to be one distinct individual among many in space and time, immediately given to
the subject. So it must be referred to by pure indexicals like here and now.
Therefore, it will exist for the subject as something here and now. But what are the senses
associated with these indexicals? Hegel antedates Castaeda, Perry and others by claiming
that the sense of an indexical cannot be reduced to a description.xiii
To show this he invites us to perform a little experiment. Take any old candidate reduction
for the sense of the indexical now. Maybe it is night at the moment and you come up with
the candidate at night. But you might as well have offered any other description you liked.
18
Next, write down your reduction thesis. If the thesis is true, it wont lose its truth by being
written down.
But notice that this holds only for eternal, non-indexical sentences. If you write down an
indexical sentence, that sentence may well change its truth value in the course of things. So
make sure you dont write down an indexical sentence like
Now it is night.
Write down a semantical or conceptual thesis instead, something like
The indexical now means at night. Or
The sense of now is the night. Or, as Hegel briefly puts it,
The now is the night.
This eternal sentence cannot change its truth value. But some hours later the night has gone,
the day has dawned, the sun also rises, and eventually it is high noon.
Now look at your sentence again: The indexical now means at night Are you still willing to believe it in the glittering sun? Of course not. But then, if you now think that the sentence is false, it must have been false all along, being an eternal sentence.
The point of this little thought experiment is that, no matter how hard you try, you wont find
a description which will do the job of the indexical now. If you want to grasp the sense of
now, you must abstract away from night and day, morning and evening, winter and summer etc. You must negate all these determinations, just to retain something completely general or universal; and the same holds true, mutatis mutandis, of the spatial adverb here.
The sense of a pure indexical involves maximal abstraction, i.e. negation of all concrete determinations, and thus maximal generality.
So the object of sense-certainty, which was meant to be a distinct individual and nothing
but a distinct individual among many, turns out to be for consciousness not as an individual,
given immediately, but as something mediated by negation and abstraction (not night, not
day, , not in England, not in Norway, ) and completely general.
-- -- -But sense certainty has yet another card to play and moves right on to its second stage. If the
object fails in the role of what is in itself, skip it and put the subject at its place. So, now,
what is real is me, the subject, the details of the passing show being floating accidents of
mine.
But now the problematic of the first stage reoccurs in a different shape. For in sense-certainty
I am present to myself only through the sense of the pure indexical I, whose sense is as
much mediated by negation and as general as the senses of here and now.
-- -- -This leads to the third and final stage of sense-certainty, in which the whole of it, not just
the object or the subject, is supposed to be what is in itself and given immediately.xiv The difference between subject and object is now well lost, and so are all remnants of discursiveness, propositionality, and of the possibility of falsehood and error.
We finally have arrived at a pre-propositional level of thinking or intuiting, where immediacy really reigns. At that level consciousness doesnt have impressions, but is an impression
or a quale, and a quale whose cognitive horizon does not extend beyond itself. So there is no
room for any form of generality any more. Immediacy and individuality seem to be reached at
last.
19
But if this scenario is still to count as a form of consciousness, the difference of role of the
Ansich and the Fr-es and thus the semantic duality of reference and predication must somehow be preserved even in this meagre context.
By fiat then let an impression as such have proto-propositional form and let it refer to what
is here and now, where here and now are defined by the impression itself, and let it predicate
immediate being of itself. This strange construction is the last resort in the attempt to vindicate sense-certainty.
But it is all in vain because of the continuous nature of space and time. There exists nothing
logically atomic in space and time; each real bit of spatio-temporal reality is extended and
thus a one in many. But then the problem of how to individuate each of the many parts of a
given bit of space-time, recurs and with it the problematic of the first stage of sense-certainty.
-- -- -The options for conceiving the real as a manifold of immediately given distinct individuals
are exhausted then and sense-certainty is definitely falsified. Its objects would be epistemically accessible not immediately and not as individuals, but via negation and as universals.
In the successor shape of consciousness, which Hegel calls perception, therefore the passing
show is now conceived as being in itself a manifold of perceptible universal traits. This will
lead to a dialectic of things as bare particulars and as bundles of properties, in the second
chapter. (But we shall now leave the PhSp.)
-- -- -III. The Science of Logic
So much for the Phenomenology, then. Hegels programme in the Logic may be viewed either in light of the Phenomenology or in its own self-sufficient light.
The Phenomenology offers as a starting point and as subject matter for the Logic its bare
result, i.e. absolute knowing in the inarticulate and immediate version. But it does not supply a method, the phenomenological method with its dependence on the duality of an Ansich
and a Fr-es being exhausted, nor any rich results to serve as axioms for the logical enterprise.
PhSp offers no method and no axioms for the SoL
So, to come into the Logic, we may as well, instead of accomplishing scepticism painstakingly in the manner of the Phenomenology, just postulate that scepticism be accomplished,
i.e. that everything (philosophical) be put into doubt. We will thereby achieve complete presuppositionlessness in the short way, by nothing more than our free decision to get into pure
thinking. (For the decision to think purely cf. what Hegel says in 78 of the Encyclopedia.)
The Logic then may be defined as the (unique) presuppositionless theory; and the working
hypothesis that there is such a thing as the presuppositionless theory is, to put it mildly, so
strong in fact on the very edge of inconsistency that it becomes surprisingly easy to formulate requirements that individuate the theory (step by step).
If we spurn the phenomenological guarantee that starting with absolute knowing qua immediate identity of thinking and reality will provide us with some worthy subject matter and
we may readily spurn that guarantee, because the Phenomenology doesnt tell us how to treat
that subject matter anyway then the Logic will have to find or to create its subject matter all
on its own.
20
-- -- -Here is a sketch of how that might work.
Obviously, the first theorem of the Logic must state a logical singularity and one that cannot
be effectively denied. For the sake of our working hypothesis (that pure thinking is possible),
we must therefore postulate a common factor which is part of what is stated in any statement
whatsoever, viz. veritative being as such or pure being the case.
A short glance at Wittgensteins Tractatus may serve to illustrate the point here. Wittgenstein also postulates that which all propositions, according to their nature, have in common
with one another, the general form of proposition (Tractatus, 5.47).
In a way that is quite congenial to the beginning of Hegels Logic, Wittgenstein characterizes
this common factor as the one logical constant and says that it is the essence of proposition
as well as the essence of the world (5.471, 5.4711). Again, he identifies the essence of proposition and the world with the logical form of picturing and also with the form of actuality
(2.18).
Apart from the one logical constant, Wittgenstein postulates simple objects (2.02) of various
logical forms (2.0233) which contain the possibility of all states of affairs (2.014) and which
form the substance of the world (2.021). Viewed in isolation, the objects are not actual, they
define the range of possibilities, i.e. logical space. What actualizes them is the form of actuality, according to which they hang one in another like the members of a chain (i.e. without
any logical cement) in the atomic fact (2.03).
Hence, the world the actual world is the totality of facts, not of things (1.1). Logical
space, the totality of possible worlds, on the other hand is the totality of things, plus the form
of actuality considered only in its role as logical form of picturing.
-- -- -In Hegel we get a somewhat different picture of the one logical constant and of logical space.
To put it bluntly, Hegel gives a dynamic picture and offers an evolution theory of logical
space. The logical constant, which he calls pure being, explodes in a kind of logical big
bang, called becoming, and thereby starts a pre-temporal, logical process, eventually culminating in a fixed point called the absolute idea.
What triggers the big bang is pure negativity which has contaminated pure being right from
the start. There are various ways to show this; for the present (preliminary) purpose I prefer to
hint at one of them which involves a bit of botanizing, but is particularly short and simple.
We all know that there is more to the real than pure being; so we need a logical operation
which leads us from there to something more determinate and articulate. In the context of a
presuppositionless theory we therefore need an operation which is the only candidate around,
and such is negation, being the only non-trivial one-place truth function.
-- -- --
21
03-Feb-09
Our (i.e. Hegels) working hypothesis is: There is exactly one presuppositionless theory.
A theory is a (non-empty) set of truth claims. Now, the working hypothesis itself must show
us the way to the first truth claim of the theory. Its content must be (1) without alternative
and (2) such that it cannot be effectively denied. We must therefore postulate a minimal,
invariant common factor of all truth claims whatsoever; and exactly that minimal factor will
be the content of our first theoretical truth claim.
The content of an arbitrary truth claim is some particular fact or being the case or veritative
being. The content of our presuppositionless truth claim therefore must be the fact itself
(Platonically speaking) or pure being the case or veritative being as such (pure) being, for
short.
An aside: We may distinguish at least four senses of the verb to be: (1) veritative being or
being the case, which arguably is the basic sense, (2) existential being (or existence for short),
(3) predicative being, and (4) being in the sense of identity:
(1) veritative being: attached to the whole sentence (it being the case that p)
(2) existential being: attached to the subject term (there being X, Xs existence)
(3) predicative being: attached to the predicate (being so and so)
(4) identity: attached to the identity predicate (being the so and so)
So, we start with veritative being as such (being simpliciter).
But notice: We do not know whether there is any such thing like a veritative being common
to the contents of all truth claims; we just must postulate it for the sake of our programme!
So, lets postulate it and see what it will be like.
In the best of all possible worlds well come up with exactly the same things that Hegel says
about (pure) being. So lets first have a look on what he says and then check, if we find out
those very same things.
Hegel starts with the one word sentence Being. This seems to be the formulation of the
theorem itself.
(1) Being is designed to state (mean) being.
Then, Hegel leans back and says quite a lot of things about being by way of what he later calls
external reflection (p. 110) . External reflection comes in different grades, i.e. it can be
more or less external: it may concern the nature of the Notion itself or be an external comparison (ibid.). But either way it is to be contrasted with that which is posited in a notion
and belongs in the developmental consideration of that notion, to its content (ibid. Millers
English is a bit confusing here, at least to me).
Now, it seems that strictly nothing is posited yet in pure being so that everything we can say
about it belongs to our external reflection. Otherwise Hegel would be paradigmatically inconsistent in what he says about being. Lets make a little list:
Being is
(1) expressed by the one word sentence Being,
(2) indeterminate,
(3) immediate,
(4) incomparable (equal only to itself, not unequal relatively another), homogeneous
(5) emptiness
(6) pure (i.e. empty) intuiting,
22
(7) pure (i.e. empty) thinking,
(8) nothing.
This is an impressive list of strong claims about being, and it is immediately clear that Hegel
would be talking rubbish, if what he said, were not meant as external reflection. For, if being
is indeterminate and empty, you cannot at the same time try to determine it by seven theorems
[(2) through (8)].
So, obviously, Hegel makes a distinction between what being is like
(a) for pure, presuppositionless thinking,
(b) for us (our background thinking).
Let us call these two levels (a) object logic and (b) background logic. The object logic is
pure thinking itself, the presuppositionless theory that we are after. The background logic is
our own theory of how a presuppositionless theory might be possible and how it would have
to look like.
-- -- -Let us now step back from Hegels text and see, if we can independently develop and justify
what he is doing and saying.
We may begin with the distinction of theoretical levels just sketched.
That distinction is an immediate consequence of our working hypothesis. As players of the
game of giving and asking for reasons we are just not able to propose a presuppositionless
theory, at least not on our own account. Whatever we propose is open to possible doubt or
negation. This is quite trivially so: Whatever content we propose is propositional and thus
subject to bivalence: It is proposed as true and may ipso facto be false. Such is the way of
objective truth claims.
Objectivity independence of claimed fact from act of claiming possibility of error
bivalence (T or F) propositionality (S-P-structure)
So, all we can do on behalf of a strictly presuppositionsless theory is to devise a fanciful
theoretician existing in a non-standard epistemic context who can entertain such an extreme
theory. So, within the Hegelian enterprise we have to distinguish an object theory from our
background theory, just as Hegel himself did.
The object theory is pure thinking strictly so-called, viz. the strictly presuppositionless theory
of our fanciful theoretician. The background theory is our (i.e. Hegels) own logical theory,
in which we have to try to lean on nothing (or little) more than our working hypothesis that
there is pure thinking. To repeat Hegels own words, the object theory is the internal development of the Notion itself, while the background theory is our external reflection. But
our external reflection must not be too external, if it is to qualify as the logical background
theory. It is part of the background theory, only if it concerns the nature of the Notion itself
and is not just an external comparison (SoL 110). (Hegels remarks to the main text are
mostly such external comparisons, e.g. with Parmenides, SoL 83, or Kant etc.).
OL: internal development of logical space
BL: our external reflections insofar as they concern the nature of logical space itself
(Remarks: external comparisons and the like)
-- -- -Now from here it is a short path to our points (1) through (8), especially to point (1).
If the object logic (= the presuppositionless theory) starts with a theorem that cannot be
denied in the strictest possible sense of can, then it cannot start with a theorem at all, be-
23
cause theorems have propositional form and are thus bivalent (true or false) and can be denied, doubted, negated. For any theorem whatsoever the possibility of error has been provided
for (to use a Wittgensteinian turn of phrase, from the Blue Book).
Thus the first content of the object logic cannot be propositional but must rather be like a
Humean sense impression, though of course not sensuous, but intellectual.
This gives us the one word sentence Being as an inadequate attempt to say, what cannot be
said, but only intuited in some way (viz. by intellectual intuition). So, we have justified the
Hegelian point (1).
And we have at the same time already made an important step towards the justification of
points (6) and (7), where being is equated with pure intuition and pure thinking respectively.
But let us proceed in due order.
So, what about indeterminacy? Well, sure, being has to be indeterminate (undetermined),
because we abstracted away from all determinations of specific truth claims in order to retain
nothing but the common factor of all of them, which must be extremely neutral and thus completely indeterminate. As soon as we said something determinate, we would have been making a choice and our saying what we said would not have been strictly without alternative and
without presupposition. So this is point (2) then.
(3) Immediacy. With immediacy we appeal to the framework of givenness. And this is just
what we should have expected, because what remains after abstracting from all determinations of truth claims the One Logical Constant (to use Wittgensteins turn of phrase) must
be taken up by thinking as something given. We saw point (1) that this content doesnt
have propositional form any more. Its a pre-propositional thought content, if such there
be, a content we can only know of by Russellian acquaintance, i.e. immediately.
-- -- -Excursus ad pre-propositional though contents or pre-propositional states of affairs,
urstates for short. Heres a little theory of urstates, meant as an idealized reconstruction of
the framework of givenness, thus as the reconstruction of something untenable.
Theory of urstates (TU):
(TU-0) Urstates are pre-propositional complete contents of perception or thought.
(TU-1) If an urstate is grasped (in perception or in thought), it is known with absolute
certainty (infallibility).
(TU-2) If a state of affairs is known with absolute certainty, it is an urstate.
(TU-3) What is known with absolute certainty, lies beyond bivalence and is true in a
non-contrastive sense of true: uni-valently true (so to speak).
(TU-4) Veritative and existential being is the same for urstates.
(TU-5) If an urstate is grasped, it does obtain (i.e. it is a fact: an urfact).
(TU-6) If an urstate obtains, it is grasped (urstates are self-intimating).
(TU-7) Propositional states of affairs exist in that they either obtain or do not obtain,
with respect to some object(s), i.e. as dependent entities. Urstates exist in that
they obtain, with respect to themselves, i.e. as independent entities.
(TU-8) Two main genera of urstates are conceivable (and have in fact been conceived
in the history of philosophy): sensuous urstates and intelligible urstates.
24
(TU-9) The being the undifferentiated obtaining and existing of an urstate is its
presence in the logical space of urstates. In the logical space of urstates nothing
can be hidden (there is no hidden obtaining-or-existing): In the logical space of
sensuous urstates there is nothing unperceived; in the logical space of intelligible urstates there is nothing unconceived (nothing unthought-of).
(TU-10) Sensuous urstates, if such there be, are logically private entities: Only the individual perceiving subject who grasps a sensuous urstate can know of it. (A
logical space of sensuous urstates is in each case the logically private sensorium of an individual perceiving subject.)
(TU-11) Intelligible urstates, if such there be, are logically public entities: They are
grasped by reason in general, in which the rational faculties of each individual
thinking subject take part, in some sense to be explained by further theorizing. (The logical space of intelligible urstates is a singulare-tantum: the totality
of that which can be known a priori by reason with absolute certainty.)
-- -- -As soon as you try to reconstruct the framework of givenness by an explicit theory, you will
realize its logical or conceptual instability which is normally disguised by surrounding theory
(think, e.g., of Hume for sensuous and of Plato for intelligible urstates). Hegel takes the
framework seriously he has to, given the working hypothesis and starts with one singular
superlative urstate for (non-discursive, intuitive) thinking, which he calls (pure) being. The
logical instability and inconsistency of positing such an urstate is what drives his theory to
further (ur-)states. So much for the immediacy of being.
(4) Being is incomparable (equal only to itself, not unequal relatively another) and homogeneous. This is easy enough. The One singular urstate being, in order to be without alternative
for thinking, has to be identical to the whole of logical space. But then it is incomparable. And
logical space cannot be in any way differentiated at this early stage of thinking. It must be
homogeneous (for lack of all determinations).
(5) Emptiness. If being is a logical space devoid of determinations, it is an empty logical
space: pure indeterminateness and emptiness.
There is nothing to be intuited in it and nothing to be thought in it which brings us to points
(6) and (7) and their respective identifications:
Being = pure intuiting itself = empty thinking.
With urstates, three important distinctions are undercut:
(a) the distinction between intuiting and thinking (because discursive thinking is associated with propositionality),
(b) the distinction between object and subject (because objectivity is associated with
the possibility of error and therefore also with propositionality), and
(c) the difference between act and content (because the act would have to belong to
the subject and the content to the object).
Consequence: Our background logic seemed to be one step remote from being, because being
seemed to be the subject matter of the object logic, while the object logic seemed to be the
subject matter of the background logic. Now it turns out, that being and pure thinking (= the
object logic) just coincide. So, our background logic is the theory of both: of pure being and
ipso facto of pure thinking. Both are one and the same (at least at the beginning of the SoL).
-- -- --
25
Ad (8): Being is nothing. Taken in isolation, this may come as no surprise, after all that has
been said about being. What makes it non-trivial and challenging is that Hegel will go on to
say that being and nothing are absolutely distinct. But this claim will have to wait.
What is important for the moment is that Hegel wants to convey the thought that pure being is
contaminated with negativity right from the start. Why is that so?
I know of two independent reasons (one a bit an external reflection, which I already adumbrated the other day).
(i) There can be no doubt that there is more to logical space than just pure being (i.e. emptiness). Even if all there is (all distinctions we make), should turn out to be illusory, then still in
the mode of illusion there are (or seem to be) a lot of distinctions and determinations. Parmenides may be right for the realm of real being, but even he must acknowledge something
like a passing show, even if only in the mode of illusion (doxa).
Therefore it is trivial and thus no substantive presupposition at all to postulate (but its
really no big postulation) a kind of operation on pure being that will lead from there to somewhere else.
We found pure being by reflecting on truth claims: as the minimal neutral ingredient of each
and every truth claim, considered itself as a superlative truth claim. So what we need is a truth
operation or truth function, and a one-place truth function at that (there being no more than
one content given as a candidate operandum). By sheer combination (exhaustion of possibilities) we get four one-place truth functions:
p
T
F
f(p)
T
T
p
T
F
g(p)
T
F
p
T
F
h(p)
F
T
p
T
F
i(p)
F
F
If Being! is the first theorem of our OL, we are looking for a second theorem. But a theorem is a truth claim. So we cannot work with the truth function i( ), because it is the falsemaker and we dont (and cannot) want to say something false.
And we cannot work with function g( ), because it is the identity truth function which leads
us nowhere else and leaves everything as it is.
We cannot work with function f( ) either, because it is the truth maker, and we have already claimed Being! to be true. In fact, one could view the situation at the start of the SoL
as the result of having worked with the truth maker already (for to say something which is
beyond possible doubt one has to do exactly this: apply the truth maker to an arbitrary truth
claim).
So, the only candidate that survives and is thus without viable alternative is the truth function
h( ), i.e. negation.
-- -- -But now look what happens, if we apply negation to pure being. First of all, it cannot be
done, if negation, being made and known for propositions (i.e. propositional states of affairs) is not re-tailored to suit urstates.
But let us ignore this problematic for a while and pretend that we are working with regular
propositional theorems and regular propositional negation.
If we apply negation to our first theorem Being!, we get something like Not (being)!
and a problem (the exclamation marks are just reminders that we are here treating of claims,
i.e. sentence-like contents, not of things, i.e. term-like contents):
26
OL (object logic, pure thinking):
(0) Being!
(1) Not (being)!
The problem is this, or, more exactly, the first of (at least) two severe problems is this: Theorem (1) is the contradictory opposite of theorem (0); so OL is inconsistent.
To which we might reply: So, let OL be inconsistent; its not our own theory after all. Our
own theory is BL (the background logic) whose theorems state that pure being is indeterminate, immediate, incomparable etc. the above list. As long as BL is consistent, we are on the
(b)right side of life.
Well, yes and no. Yes, we could put the blame on OL and stand free. No, for then our project,
hardly begun, would all be in ruins: Pure thinking would be possible, yes, but only to lead into
inconsistency (and to remain there) after its very first thinking manoeuvre. So, we better
took care of OL, after all, and tried to mend its inconsistency in order to go on with it for a
while.
So, how can a sentence and its negation (its contradictory opposite) both be true? Only if they
are indexical sentences, i.e. sentences with varying truth value. There are, basically, spatially indexical sentences and temporally indexical sentences. In fact, most indexical sentences are both spatially and temporally indexical like It is raining (viz. here and now).
Now, we dont have any analogue of space for OL at the moment; but trivially we do have an
analogue of time: the succession of theorems (0) and (1) itself! This is a non- or pretemporal succession like the succession of the natural numbers. So the relevant indexicality
here is non temporal, but pre-temporal, purely logical indexicality.
So let us say: At logical point 0 theorem (0) is true: Being!. Then (a purely logical then),
at logical point 1, theorem (1) is true: Not (being)!
-- -- -Do we have solved our problem? Not yet. Remember: the content of Being! is the minimal
common content of whatever truth claim, thus even of its supposed contradictory opposite
Not (being)!. That means, that Being! is a logically eternal sentence (a sentence with
constant truth value) after all and that Not (being)! is self-contradictory and thus selffalsifying. It explicitly says Not (being)! and, like any old statement, implicitly says (i.e.
entails) Being!. Can it nonetheless be true in some sense and for a while (at least a very
short one)?
Yes, if we conceive it on the analogy of a certain subclass of temporally indexical sentences,
which might be called infinitesimally short term indexical sentences or just infinitesimal sentences, for short. An example of a temporally infinitesimal sentence is: The goal keeper
catches the ball, for as soon as he catches it, he will have caught it and be no longer catching
it. By contrast, The goal keeper holds the ball is temporally indexical (he wont hold it forever), but not infinitesimal (he may hold it for quite a while until the spectators begin to
whistle, and even longer).
And not only that; the act of catching is exactly of the desired logical form, at least if we
idealize a bit and think of the very moment, when the ball hits the skin of the hands (or the
surface of the gloves) of the goal keeper. The ball then, for an infinitesimal moment of time,
does and does not touch the skin of the goal keeper.
The principle of non-contradiction can be salvaged here, if we restrict it to (veritative) being and give it up for (veritative) becoming, i.e. for the very moment of change.
So, what weve got in OL is the following:
27
(0) Being! A logically eternal sentence, expressing (pure) being.
(1) Not (being)! A logically infinitesimal sentence, turning false instantaneously.
Therefore we get as a third OL-theorem:
(2) Not (not (being)!, equivalent to Being!, now as a logically indexical sentence.
What do sentences (1) and (2) express? Sentence (1) implicitly expresses being and explicitly
expresses the contradictory opposite thereof. It thus expresses a mixture of being and its
negative: becoming.
Sentence (2) then expresses the contradictory opposite of becoming, and again being, but now
it does so as a logically indexical sentence, i.e. it explicitly expresses non-eternal (but relatively stable) being. (Implicitly it expresses, like any old sentence, eternal being.) This relatively stable, but non-eternal being is called Dasein by Hegel (in Millers translation: determinate being).
-- -- -Now, theorem (0) drops out of the logical series and doesnt compete with the others any
more; it is implicit in all successor theorems, but cannot be stated (as a logically indexical
sentence) on its own.
The first theorem of OL thus turns out to be (1), the theorem of becoming. It expresses the
big logical bang with which logical space comes into existence and begins its evolution. Its
first relatively stable state is Dasein (determinate being), expressed by theorem (2).
-- -- -Further tasks for us: (A) to tailor negation for urstates-of-affairs, (B) to reconstruct Hegels
text (being becoming determinate being), (C) to say something about the alternative way
way (ii) in which negativity can be shown to be present in the logic right from the start.
Ad (A). It is of the essence of propositions (propositional states of affairs) that their obtaining is not the same as their existence. Any existing proposition may be grasped, e.g. the
proposition that Atlanta is the capital of North Carolina. But not any existing proposition need
obtain, as witness our example. If we grasp a proposition that does not obtain, we err. (Cf.
Platos theory of the possibility of error in the Sophistes.)
Now, if a proposition does not obtain there is always a related proposition which does: its
negation (contradictory opposite). So, as Aristotle noted, propositions come in pairs (in contradictory pairs), both members of which will exist and exactly one member of which will
obtain. This makes it easy, in fact trivial, for non-obtaining states of affairs to be sublated or
ideally there, in the realm of propositions: You can always think, consider, plan, imagine,
what is not the case.
This is different with urstates (pre-propositional states of affairs). For them obtaining and
existence are identical. So there cannot be (at least until further notice; but Hegel will work
hard to change this situation) negative urstates (negations of urstates, contradictory opposites
of urstates). To negate an urstate is (until further notice) to annihilate it, to erase it from
logical space.
Immediate consequence: As soon as we allow for the negation of urstates, logical space itself
must be conceived of as subject to change. So, we can independently see that we need logically indexical contents, as soon as negation of urstates is admitted as a logical operation. A
logic of urstates will have be an evolution theory of logical space. And so is Hegels SoL.
But if the negation of an urstate is its annihilation, there will be no sublating, idealizing,
positing, let alone mentally representing of urstates, at least not until further notice. This is
28
what makes Hegels theory of sublation so highly non-trivial. He manages to show how in
the evolution of logical space room is made for the sublation of urstates after all so that a negated, i.e. annihilated, urstate can still be present ideally (be represented, posited, sublated) in its successor urstate. (But this is a story for until later.)
Ad (B), Hegels text. We have hitherto reconstructed what Hegel says about being, and we
have introduced a second urstate called becoming (a mixture of being and negativity). But
we have so far said nothing about nothing (negativity).
We have introduced negation by way of external reflection. External reflection comes in
grades of externality. Ours has been quite external, at least by comparison with way (ii) of
introducing negativity, yet to be considered. So, how do we get to Hegels text from our comparatively external standpoint of reflection?
Well, from our standpoint pure negativity has to be interpolated between pure being and becoming as that which is responsible for the logical big bang of becoming given pure being.
But as the evolution of logical space starts with becoming, negativity cannot have been added
to pure being as a second principle at some logical point; it must have been there right from
the start, together with and separable from pure being. So pure being itself must have been
negativity after all, contrary to what we may have thought and intended, when we first postulated pure being.
This gives us BL-theorem (8): Being is nothing. (In the German original, nothing is capitalized here: Nichts, which means that Hegel at the end of A. Being is already equating
the purported urstate being with a purported urstate nothing and is not just saying Das Sein
ist nichts, Being is nothing, i.e. there is no such thing as being.)
But then we should expect that Hegel says much the same things about nothing in B. Nothing as he said about being in A. Being. And this is what we find, when looking at the text:
Nothing is [I numerate according to our list of BL-theorems about being]
(4) equality with itself,
(5) complete emptiness,
(2) absence of all determination and content
(6) empty intuiting,
(7) empty thought
(8*) pure being
If we compare this list with our list on pure being, according to which being was
(1) expressed by the one word sentence Being,
(2) indeterminate,
(3) immediate,
(4) incomparable (equal only to itself, not unequal relatively another), homogeneous
(5) emptiness
(6) pure (i.e. empty) intuiting,
(7) pure (i.e. empty) thinking,
(8) nothing,
we notice that, not amazingly, (1) is missing and (8) has been supplanted with (8*). But,
which seems to be more significant, (3) is missing as well. As pure negativity (or nothing) is
the principle of all operation and mediation, Hegel shies away from calling it immediate.
So far, the reconstruction of Hegels text from our considerations runs quite smooth. But we
may stumble, if we now turn to C. Becoming. First, Hegel reiterates (8) or (8*):
Pure being and pure nothing are, therefore, the same.
29
But then it gets difficult, and the difficulties seem to culminate in Hegels claim
that they [being and nothing] are not the same, that they are absolutely distinct.
Of course, if they are distinct at all, they must be absolutely distinct, because they cannot
share any determinations (like, say, a red cube and a red sphere), for want of determinations.
But why should they be distinct? And if they were, wouldnt we get a contradiction in our
very own theory (BL)? For BL would then seem to say both:
(8) B = N
(9) B N
Lets start with the first question: Why B N? Because otherwise, nothing (nichts) would
have happened, given pure being. We need nothing (das Nichts) as an explainer of becoming; so it must be different from being.
Second question: What about the contradiction of (8) and (9)? These cannot be theorems of
BL, otherwise BL would be inconsistent. So, (8) and (9) can only serve in a reductio ad absurdum of the existence of such urstates as pure being and pure nothing. But this then affects
our whole lists of BL-theorems about pure being and pure nothing: They are true only in the
modus irrealis, like physical theorems about mass points or punctiform events.
This result accords with Hegels text in so far as Hegel says that the difference of pure being
and pure nothing exists not in themselves, but in a third, in subjective opinion (SoL 92, end
of remark 2). This seems to be true as well of being and nothing themselves, because they are
but empty figments of thought (85, remark 1), which thus cannot be grasped in thought, but
only meant or opined.
And it accords with our own previous findings in so far as we let the logic, qua evolution
theory of logical space, start with becoming, thus relegating pure being (and pure nothing) to
the logical pre-history which cannot be grasped by pure OL-thinking, but only projected by
way of BL-theorizing.
Even if we grant logical urstates in general (which we do at least provisionally, for the sake
of our working hypothesis), pure being and pure nothing will not be among them.
-- -- -Ad (C), way (ii) of introducing negativity. We may now finally look at a second way of introducing negativity, a very short one, somewhat less external than the first one and closer to
what Hegel says himself.
If we abstract away from all distinctions between possible truth claims, then literally nothing
(nichts) will be left over, for every candidate left-over could in principle be made the content
of a separate truth claim and would then itself have to be subjected to our Grand Abstraction.
So really nothing (nichts) is left over. But we treat this zero left-over as something, when we
say that it is the logical urstate of pure being. We have thus reified nothing to the nothing
(nichts to das Nichts) and given it the name being. But not only the name; that would be too
simple, we could then identify being and nothing (B = N) and leave it at that and would not
get to their difference (B N). What really happened is that by reifying nothing (for the
sake of our working hypothesis) we decided to prefer a different kind of abstraction which
leaves over something neutral and affirmative, aptly called (pure) being, which must be
different from the reified zeroness called nothing. (Cf. Hegels remark 3, SoL 99f.)
This way of introducing negativity is more internal and shorter than the first one, but I only
accept it, because it is backed up with the first one.
30
10-Feb-09
Perhaps the second way can still be made a bit more convincing. The total abstraction from
all determinations surpasses its end and leaves literally nothing under the title (pure) being.
We will see that, if we try to restore the omitted determinations again. For it then will become
clear that nothing can be added to being.
As Aristotle saw and taught, being, to on, is not a genus. A genus is differentiated into subgenera and, lastly, species, by a (specific) differentia. This may be illustrated by way of comparison. Pure blue can be differentiated by adding, as a differentia, red or green and will then
be violet (reddish blue) or turquoise (greenish blue) respectively.
Now, trivially (i) only something which is (only an on) can be added to something and (ii)
nothing can differentiate itself (by being added to itself).
That is quite unproblematic in the case of colours, for (i) red (or green) is (exists) and (ii) is
not the same as blue. But it is problematic, nay, impossible, in the case of a purported genus
being. To differentiate being some being would have to be added to being as differentia other
than being itself; but that would presuppose the differentiation of being as accomplished
which it is the job of the differentia to explain. Put in a slightly different way: If we add being
to being, no differentiation will be done; and if we add a non-being no differentiation (in fact
nothing) will be done either.
Therefore being is no genus, says Aristotle, but possesses a primitive internal multiplicity that
lies still beyond the generic/specific distinction (to on legetai pollachs). Plato on the other
hand thinks that being is only one among several highest genera (megista gen), which are all
co-original and which may partake one at the other. So being may lend itself (i.e. being) to the
others and will receive their respective determinations in turn. Parmenides however said that
being cannot be differentiated, full stop, thus sacrificing the phenomena (of plurality and becoming), which Plato and Aristotle then tried to save against his verdict.
But we need not decide between Parmenides, Plato and Aristotle here, because Hegel offers a
different approach: If being is to be differentiated by being (and there is no alternative at the
starting-point of pure thinking), then it must at the same time be its own contradictory opposite: affirmative immediacy waiting to be differentiated on the one hand (therefore being
which is absolutely distinct from nothing) and pure differentiating negativity, called nothing,
on the other hand.
(By the way: The reductio ad absurdum of separate pure being and separate pure nothing
can be turned into a critique of the early Wittgensteins metaphysics of the One Logical Constant in the spirit of the later Wittgensteins own critique of the idea of general characteristics.)
-- -- -Last week, we have reconstructed Hegels text of A. Being, B. Nothing and C. Becoming. 1. Unity of Being and Nothing. We have now to look at 2. Moments of Becoming:
Coming-to-be and Ceasing-to-be and 3. Sublation of Becoming.
Becoming has two moments, i.e. sublated contents. So, here the story of sublation begins. It begins with two contents, being and nothing, which are there only qua sublated, never
qua self-subsistent contents (because becoming is the first logical content).
Becoming is (speaking apart from Hegel) something radically new over and against being and
cannot be reduced to it: Becoming is becoming-all-the-way-down. If becoming is a mixture of being and nothing, then each ingredient is itself a mixture of being and nothing and
so on ad infinitum.
31
In this way, becoming is a non-well-founded content. The SoL abounds with non-wellfounded contents. So, wed better take a look at non-well-foundation in time, by way of an
excursus.
-- -- -Non-well-founded Phenomena
The set theoretic axiom system ZFC leaves it open, whether or not there are non-well-founded
sets. If we add the foundation axiom, to get ZFFC, non-well-founded sets are excluded. A set
is well-founded, iff it has no infinite chain(s) in its membership ancestry, i.e. no chain like:
b a, c b, d c, e d,
In pure set theory (where there are no Urelemente, original members) each chain of membership ancestry will, in ZFFC, terminate in the empty set, 0, after a finite number of steps.
But Peter Aczel (in: Non-Well-Founded Sets, CSLI Lecture Notes 14, Stanford 1988) has
shown that if ZFC is consistent, then ZFC+AFA is consistent as well, where AFA is a certain
anti-foundation-axiom.
According to AFA there exists the unique set, , which is its own unit set:
= {}
Obviously, has an infinite chain of membership ancestry (, , , ).
There are all sorts of other non-well-founded sets as well, according to AFA, like the set
0* = {0*, 0},
but is the one and only set which is its own unit set. So it could be defined by this characteristic. But if you try to define it this way:
=df {}
Then the definition gets circular or, if you reiterate the definiens within itself, infinite:
= {} = {{}} = {{{}} = = {{{}}}
So if infinitely long sentences were possible, you could define simply by an infinity of pairs
of curly brackets.
-- -- -What Aczel has shown, at least to my complete satisfaction, is that nothing is inherently
wrong with the idea of Unfoundedness.
E.g. appearances in the Kantian sense are non-well-founded entities (maybe they are partially founded like the set 0*) in at least two respects, (i) mereologically and (ii) causally.
(Thats what the antinomies of pure reason are about). So (i) Leibniz ought not to have said
that spatial entities are phaenomena bene fundata, he should rather have said that they are
phaenomena non bene fundata, because you will never come to an end if you start dividing
the continuum, nor if you are looking for a sufficient cause of an event. (Thus the monads,
after infinitely many divisions, come essentially too late.) And (ii), pace Leibniz, the cosmological argument doesnt work; it only would, if you could start with phenomena which were
causally well-founded. (Thus the first cause, after infinitely many non-first causes, comes
essentially too late.)
The abstract concept of foundation, of which set theoretic concept of foundation is a
particularly well-understood species, is extremely important in first philosophy. (If we
philosophers had no other reasons for doing some set theory, this by itself would be a very
good and sufficient one.)
32
Now, non-well-foundedness is always linked to some operation or other, in set theory to the
(multigrade) set forming operation, {}, in mereology to the operation of forming the mereological sum, in the theory of causality to the operation of causation, and in the SoL to the (as
yet one-place) operation of negation.
The analogue of the set in negation theory would be the negation-of-itself:
= {} = {{}} = {{{}} = = {{{}}}
~() ~(~()) ~(~(~())) ~(~(~())) [One could drop the brackets]
The state of affairs here would be its own contradictory opposite, thus self-annihilating qua
urstate or self-falsifying qua propositional state.
A well known example of the propositional variant of is the Liar:
(1) (1) is not true.
The deep problem with cases of the negation-of-itself is that we cant negate them and be
free from their contradiction, as we can with p~p by saying ~(p~p). For then we would
be saying what they already, qua self-negations, say themselves, and would thus endorse them
and treat them as true after all and be committed to their inconsistency.
-- -- -Excursus (within the excursus):
Peter Aczel, Non-Well-Founded Sets. CSLI Lecture Notes 14. [Stanford] 1988.
The set theoretic axioms AFA1, AFA2 und AFA were introduced by Peter Aczel in his
work on non-well-founded sets. Aczel represents sets by accessible pointed graphs
(APGs). A graph consists of nodes and edges, where an edge is an ordered pair of
nodes:
The posterior node is called a child of the anterior node. A path is a finite or infinite
sequence of nodes which are related by edges:
...
A graph is pointed, if it has a special node called its point (a first or foremost node, intuitively speaking). A pointed graph is accessible, if for each of its nodes there is a
path leading to it from its point. A decoration is an assignment of sets to nodes such
that the children of a node are assigned the members of the set that is assigned to the
node. A picture of a set is an APG with a decoration in which the point of the APG is
assigned the (pictured) set. A well-founded graph, finally, has no infinite path.1
Aczel first shows that each well-founded graph has a unique decoration and that therefore each well-founded APG is the picture of a unique set. The simplest APG, e.g.,
consists of a node without children and is the picture of the empty set:
0/
An APG consisting of a single edge (i.e. two nodes) is the picture of the unit set of the
empty set (and so on):
{0/}
{{0/}}
It can further be shown that every set has a picture (which presupposes, of course, that
many paths, in fact infinitely and even non-denumerably many paths may spring from
a single node). Since there are non-well-founded graphs, an axiom is motivated by all
this which Aczel calls the anti-foundation axiom, AFA for short:
1
33
AFA: Every graph has a unique decoration
So, by that axiom, if a graph is an APG (i.e. accessible and pointed), then it is the picture of a unique, well-defined set. And if an APG is not well-founded, then so is the
set, whose picture it is.2 From AFA therefore it follows that there are non-wellfounded sets. The simplest example of the picture of a non-well-founded set would be
an APG whose sole edge leads from its point back to the point:
This APG is a picture of the set for which the following holds: = (x)(x={x}), i.e.
for which holds: ={}. That this APG has an infinite path is shown by its expansion
to an infinite tree::
. . .
Aczel points out that an analogous expansion of the equation = {} would issue
in an ill-defined infinite expression:3
= {{{...}}}
This is the analogue of the infinite expression ~(~(~())) which would be an illformed formulation of the Liar.
Non-well-founded sets are excluded from the set theoretic universe by the foundation
axiom, FA, which is usually added to the set theoretic axiom system of Zermelo and
Fraenkel, ZF, or to this axiom system plus the axiom of choice (AC), ZFC (=ZF +
AC). This addition provides us with the regular axiom system ZFFC (ZF + FA +
AC).
The foundation axiom says that all sets are [well-]founded. (I ignore differences between foundedness and well-foundedness for reasons of simplicity here.) A set is
[well-]founded, if each of its non-empty subsets has at least one member such that the
intersection of that member with the subset is empty:4
x is [well-]founded (y)(y 0/ y x (u)(uy yu = 0/ )).
Obviously, is non-[well-]founded, for the only non-empty subset of is itself,
and the only member of this subset, i.e. , is such that its intersection with is not
empty but is once again.
Since Peter Aczel has given a relative consistency prove for AFA, (i.e. has proved
that AFA is consistent, if ZFFC is), the question whether there are non-well-founded
sets must be decided by other means, e.g. by recourse to our deep set theoretic intuitions (if such there be) or by recourse to the utility of ZFFC or AFA respectively
within or without mathematics.
FA privileges certain APGs over some others: those that are well-founded. Only wellfounded APGs are to have unique decorations, only they are to be pictures of sets.
AFA on the other hand is totally egalitarian in spirit:
Every graph has a unique decoration,
from which it follows that every APG is the unique picture of a set and that there are
non-well-founded sets.5
2
Ibid., p. 5f.
Ibid., p. 6.
4
Cf. Heinz-Dieter Ebbinghaus, Einfhrung in die Mengenlehre, Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft,
1979 (second edition), p. 77 and pp. 127f.
5
Aczel, loc. cit., pp. 4-6.
3
34
We need not bother with questions of the existence of certain sets, for we are not intrinsically interested in set theory here. We may just note that neither the claim that
there are unit-sets-of-themselves nor the stronger claim that exactly one such unit-setof-itself, , exists, is inconsistent or absurd.
The difference between those two claims is important. AFA may be expressed as the
conjunction of two claims:
AFA1: Every graph has at least one decoration.
AFA2: every graph has at most one decoration.6
AFA1 leaves it open that there might be different unit-sets-of-themselves so that one
might have a set x and a set y with: x={x}, y={y} und xy. AFA, on the other hand,
permits us to define: =df (x)(x={x}). Given AFA, ist the unit-set-of-itself.
Of course, even then cannot be defined as the non-well-founded unit set; for the unit
set {0/*} is non-well-founded too. Only if we limit our universe to unit sets in the first
place (i.e. to graphs whose nodes have at most one child each), will be the only nonwell-founded (unit) set.
This is of some interest, because propositional negation is a one-place operation. For if
we want to make use of the set theoretic analogy for the SoL, then we may indeed
limit our attention to unit sets (at least until further notice). And if we side with AFA,
then we may say that the thought content that gets expressed in the Liar is the negation-of-itself and the unfounded (or not-well-founded) negation.
-- -- -In set theory, of course, if AFA had turned out inconsistent, one simply would have denied
it, i.e. one would have denied the existence of . One can always conceive of some entity and
go on to deny its existence. But one cannot conceive of some thought content and go on to
deny its existence, the esse of thought contents being their concipi posse. One can, if inconsistency threatens, deny the contents truth, its obtaining or being the case. So, (or the Liar),
as soon as conceived, is there to stay, only the question of its truth is open.
(Those who want to deny its existence qua graspable content betray themselves, by the way,
because they would not take any pains to deny its existence, if they hadnt grasped it all too
well. Since we understand the Liar, we some of us at least would like not to have understood it.)
And if we now go on and say that (or the Liar) is not true, we say what it says and thus
endorse it.
From which I draw the conclusion, saying: Yes, we are committed to inconsistency. Thinking by its very nature (not only contingently, from time to time, if we are careless) is inconsistent. (Parmenides had no chance in the first place: even extremely dulling down logical
space to one singular urstate wouldnt help; pure being already is inconsistent.) But we must
not go on now and draw the sceptical or cynical or playful conclusion that anything goes; for
thinking by its very nature (by rational fiat, by a Fichtean Tathandlung: the self-constitution of reason as a binding norm) ought to be consistent. Consistency then or, what comes to
the same thing, thinking is an infinite task (as Fichte but not Hegel would say). And the
law of non-contradiction (by rational fiat) is valid as a necessary regulative principle for
thinking: Wherever you get stuck in inconsistency, try to find a way out!
6
Ibid. p. 19.
35
Hegel seems to think that it is more than just a (necessary) regulative principle. It is regulative
along the way, but constitutive over there, where the logical saints go marching in: with the
Notion (or Concept, I dont know why Miller chose to translate Begriff as notion), especially with the notion having developed into the absolute idea. (Hegel is not very fond of
Fichtean oughts and endless striving; endless striving would be a case of bad infinity for
him. Ill have to say more on this topic later on.)
Anyway, we as thinking and speaking beings have to cope with essential inconsistency.
Logical space stands under the rational norm of non-contradiction, but it is by no means
easy to enforce that norm. Logical space is surrounded by logical jungle, a thicket impenetrable and dark, where inconsistency reigns and not only surrounded by jungle, but internally
affected by it, which means that jungle is always ready to take over right in the middle of logical space, if we get unwary. Rational thinking, therefore, is always a struggle.
We built up mathematics as a king of logical clean room, where we may feel comparatively
safe against inconsistency. But interestingly enough, we provably cannot prove that mathematics is consistent (Gdel). We may hope so, though. Therefore science tends to be formulated mathematically. Insofar as it can, we think we have a good insurance against the destructive influences of inconsistency.
Hegel, as I intimated, tends to think that more can be done and achieved on behalf of our logical safety, that the logical wilderness can be domesticated once and for all. Logical death
(self-destructive inconsistency) need not be feared and anxiously evaded, but can be overcome and turned into real life.
But in this all too Christian hope he may be wrong. A more pagan thinker like Heidegger
may be closer to the truth with his conception of clearing, Lichtung, where licht means
light in its old Germanic double sense: first, light in the sense of not heavy (German leicht),
and, secondly, light in the sense of not dark (German licht).
At the Lichtung, the heavy stuff of the jungle thicket trees, branches, leaves and all that is
made light (i.e. partly taken away), and then the light can shine in and start the play of light
and dark in which things can appear and which we call thinking-and-knowing. But all of a
sudden the dark and heavy forces (inconsistency writ large) may break through and take over,
at least for a while, even at the centre of the clearing (as, perhaps, in Nazi Germany). Or the
clearing as such may even get reabsorbed by jungle altogether. And then the game of thinking and knowing wont be played any more, though our species may well continue to live,
biologically, perhaps even mimicking the game of thinking and knowing in some funny way.
(Theres hardly any limit here on our fantasy for doing philosophy fiction.)
The irresolvable antinomy is the logical analogue of the biological or, better still, the anthropological phenomenon of death. But in fact, one should see it the other way round: death
is the anthropological concretization of the logical antinomy just as temporal succession is
the natural concretization of logical succession.
Now we can sort philosophers according to the stance they take towards logical death. Parmenides says its an illusion, in reality there is only spherical and homogeneous logical life.
Main stream philosophers would say that we can safely avoid it, if we take pains to lean on
mathematics and to be careful in our thinking quite in general. Both, they and Parmenides
exclude logical death from logical space, but Parmenides is more radical in that he excludes
negativity as such, which he rightly acknowledges as the source of the problem.
Then there is Hegel, who doesnt want death to be excluded from life, nor negativity and inconsistency from logical space. Death is no taboo for him, one could say. But his Christian
roots let him be over-optimistic. Good Friday (which saw the death of God, the death of reason in total antinomy) is to be superseded with Easter, with resurrection. So, logical death has
36
a function: Let it in to logical space and have it do some useful theoretical work. But in the
event, when the work is done, it will be become superfluous and be overcome.
According to Hegel, what drives the logical evolution is the principle of non-contradiction
after all, conceived of (in our background theory) as a regulative principle or one which is
constitutive not of the interim stages of the logical process, but only of its encompassing result, the absolute idea. For in fact, inconsistencies occur throughout the logical process,
though they ought not to.
When Graham Priest, the main advocate of paraconsistent logic (which rejects the ex contradictione quodlibet), reclaims Hegel as an ally in dialetheismxv the even stronger view
that there are true contradictions this holds true only with a considerable grain of salt. The
theorems of a metaphysical theory may be true in the sense of corresponding to a stage in the
development of logical space. Likewise contradictions may be true in the sense of corresponding to an instability or a change in logical space (as witness the infinitesimal urstate of becoming). But their truth is transitory because what they correspond to is transitory as well.
Dialetheism can perhaps be characterized as the view that even (logical) death is still a form
of life. But this is not Hegels position.
Finally, there is the stance of Heidegger and, perhaps, Heraclitus before him, which on this
particular question, I am very much inclined to take up myself. Logical death is not avoidable
(pace Parmenides and the main stream), nor can it be overcome in the logical event (pace
Hegel), nor is it a form of logical life (pace dialetheism), nor is it an excuse for letting anything go (pace Rorty and Feyerabend): we usually dont commit suicide just because we
know that we must die anyway, some day. So we ought not to commit logical suicide either,
though we know that the antinomy will take over in the long run.
-- -- -Returning now to Hegelian becoming I must start with a confession. The fact that logical
non-well-foundedness is linked to the operation of negation had hitherto blinded me to the
non-well-foundedness of becoming.
Becoming seemed to be a case of well-founded negation after all, being that which would be
expressed by the two word logically indexical (and in fact infinitesimally indexical) sentence
Not (being)!. Here we seem to have some given, immediate operandum, viz. being, where
negation can operate on. (Cf. the unit set of the empty set in pure set theory: {0}.) Therefore, I
always had treated of the other of itself (SoL 118) as the first clear-cut case of a non-wellfounded logical content (a non-well-founded logical urstate).
But when I prepared this class last week and read Hegels text on the moments of becoming,
not in the seductive familiarity of my mother tongue this time, but in a foreign language in
which humdrum matters may appear in a new and unusual light (or shine), all of a sudden it
occurred to me (what should have been obvious all the time): Becoming is non-well-founded
(Hegel comes very close to saying it explicitly!) and therefore comes close to being a form or
variant of the negation-of-itself.
Becoming is non-well-founded in that its ingredients (non-self-subsistent ingredients, called
moments by Hegel), being and nothing, are, in it, not simple being and nothing any more,
but again cases of becoming, called coming-to-be and ceasing-to-be. So, according to Hegels
text, becoming is becoming all the endless! way down, and therefore not well-founded.
But is it, more specifically, a non-well-founded negation? Not yet. Its expression was introduced as self-contradictory, saying (i) explicitly Not (being)!, and (ii) Being! by implication. So we have to negate it (Not(not(being))!), and then everything is fine for a while.
37
But the result, determinate being, or d-being for short, is again inconsistent, and so becoming
will in the event be seen to be a version of the negation-of-itself after all.
Certainly, if we were to model becoming on a non-well-founded set, we would rather choose
0* than , because it seems that becoming includes both: immediate being as an analogue of
the ur-set 0, and negativity, ~ (), as an analogue of the set-building operation, {}, running free. Therefore, it seems, becoming is more like {0, 0*}, i.e. 0*, than like {}, i.e. . So
becoming is both: (i) the opposite of being and, ipso facto, (ii) the opposite of itself and its
essential negativity.
-- -- -We handled this very first variant of by pleading infinitesimal validity: We shrunk, that is
to say, the content becoming to a punctiform shape, to the punctiform starting event of the
evolution of logical space. So, the rest of the history of logical space will be the negative (the
contradictory opposite) of becoming.
But wait: isnt becoming its own negative? And isnt therefore the rest of the history of logical space, qua negative of becoming, becoming again? So it seems. And this betrays our solution, our way out of the inconsistency of becoming, as very provisional and temporary.
Indeed, the SoL will be a little like one of those annoying action movies, where the hero,
hardly escaped from one drastic danger, always runs into a new variant of that self-same danger again. We thought the bad guy was happily dead, but no, here he is again, and his big fat
wonder-gun is not yet rotten either. And so, instead of being presented with a nice new adventure of the hero, the audience has to go through it all over again. And again. And again.
But the provisional nature of each purported way out of the great inconsistency which reigns
the whole thing right from the start is what creates logical, categorial, philosophical structure. The SoL lives by it.
And of course, if the process of pure thinking is the evolution of logical space, then what succeeds the big bang of infinitesimal becoming must be a case of becoming too (only non-infinitesimal this time), it must be becoming-itself expanded to a whole logical history.
So Dasein or d-being (short for determinate being), expressed by the logically indexical
three word sentence Not (not (being)!, with all its relative stability, will eventually turn out
to be a sort of becoming as well (viz. as alteration).
-- -- -Chapter 2: Determinate Being (Dasein)
The chapter on d-being is divided in three sub-chapters (or passages):
A. D-being as such
B. Something and other, finitude
C. Qualitative infinity
The first passage is again divided in three sub-passages:
(a) D-being in general
(b) Quality
(c) Something
You can see here, how the various categorial titles recur at different levels. Not only does dbeing recur at three levels (chapter, passage, sub-passage), but also quality is not only the
title of sub-passage 2.A.(b), but also of the whole section one of the logic of being: Determinateness (Quality). In any case, d-being and quality go closely together (even though being-
38
for-self in chapter 3 also falls under the heading quality still). Well have to be aware of
this fact in what follows.
-- -- -But first some remarks about Millers translation, at the transition from becoming to being.
(1) tollendum est Octavium, p. 107, seems to me to be nonsensical. You may either report the Ciceronian pun in indirect speech: that Octavius is to be endured/lifted up (in
triumph), or in direct speech: Octavius is to be endured/lifted up. In the first case
you would have the a.c.i. of Hegels original: tollendum esse Octavium, in the second
case you would have: tollendus est Octavius. (But maybe one can construe Millers
phrase thus: it is to be endured/lifted up [whom?] Octavius. I am not a Latinist.)
(2) In Millers translation, p. 107, bottom, Hegels claim that the technical language of
philosophy employs Latin terms for reflected determinations does not seem wellmotivated, because in English both terms, sublate (sufferre, suffero, sustuli, sublatum) and moment are Latin, while in the original German aufheben is Germanic
(cf. heave up), while Moment is Latin. Hegel is alluding to that contrast. (It seems
to me that English didnt have the ambition to create a domestic philosophical terminology, it just took over the Greco-Latin one. No Meister Eckhart, Christian Wolff,
Martin Heidegger.)
(3) The beginning of chapter 2 is hard to render, and particularly so, if one decides to
translate Dasein as determinate being. For Hegel says: Dasein is determinate being [esse, Sein] which would give the tautology: Determinate being is determinate
being and then goes on to say: its determinateness is determinateness which is [being, existing determinateness], quality. Through its quality, something [must be italicized, Hegel has capital E in Etwas] is [fill in: contrasted] against an other [italicized], [and] is alterable [Hegels otherable, vernderlich, cannot be reproduced in
English, there being no English verb to other sth.] and finite; [and is] negatively determined not only against an other but also plainly-and-simply in itself.
My version would be something like this: Being-there is determinate being, its determinateness is determinateness which is, or quality. Through its quality, something is
contrasted against an other, and is alterable [turnable-into-an-other] and finite; and
negatively determined not only against an other but also just in itself.
-- -- -The being being expressed by Not (not (being)! is determinate in that it is one of exactly
two items which determine each other, there being nothing else outside them to do the determining: becoming as the logical predecessor of d-being and d-being as the logical successor
of becoming. Becoming negates (and annihilates) itself and is ipso facto negated, annihilated
and succeeded by becoming certainly a somewhat strange scenario.
But we have to distinguish between OL and BL. In OL, i.e. pure thinking proper, there is
(or should I say there becomes?) only becoming, which instantaneously annihilates itself, and
thats all. Thereby pure thinking stumbles into a new logical urstate, without being able to
notice this transition. Pure thinking itself was becoming and is now d-being. We in BL know
that d-being is the successor of becoming, but in OL becoming has totally vanished and dbeing is like the starter, totally immediate.
For us, in BL, d-being is the other, the contradictory opposite, of becoming. But it is the victorious urstate in that opposition. The loser, becoming, negated/annihilated by d-being, takes
revenge, so to speak, by at least determining the winner. So determinateness is the inverse
39
of negatedness. This determinateness is as such invisible in OL, but d-being as seen in OL
is de facto determinate, even though OL does not (yet!) leave any room for making a distinction between d-being and its determinacy. Therefore the determinacy of d-being is its quality,
and d-being is (at that early stage) in OL identical with its quality. It is therefore what philosophers nowadays use to call a quale, though not one among many possible sensory qualia,
but the unique logical quale.
If x has quality Q, then x may in principle lose Q and gain Q instead. A green tomato may
turn red, while ripening (and by ripening; it is kind of funny, by the way, that the German
variant of while, spelled weil, has lost its temporal sense and gained a completely causal
sense; thus weil reifend would mean because of ripening). But a quale cannot lose its (defining) quality; it does not have but is its quality; when the quality vanishes, so does the quale
itself. This holds for sensory qualia, and it holds as well for the purely logical quale d-being.
-- -- -Now, we in BL see that becoming is sublated in d-being: d-being would not be the logical
urstate it is, if it werent the victorious annihilator of becoming. For us therefore d-being
shows a trace of becoming. Becoming is what makes d-being determinate after all and which
therefore defines it as the unique logical quale that it is. But this is not yet posited (not yet set
or put: gesetzt), i.e. not yet visible at the OL level.
At the OL level d-being appears as a first, as a starting-point for the ensuing development. It
is first Hegel goes on to say in the one-sided determination of being; the other determination, nothing, will likewise display itself and in contrast to it [i.e. to the first one, gegen
jene]. (p. 109 bottom)
So, this will be the development of d-being: its negativity, at first hidden at the OL level, i.e.
not yet posited, will make its presence more and more felt at the OL level, gradually, step by
step. But look: The argument must not proceed in the short way! We must not reason like this:
We know more about d-being than is visible at the OL level; so lets enrich the OL level in
order that it might catch up to our vantage point. This would be cheating, according to
Hegels austere lights. We have to wait and see if the OL level catches up all on its own.
What we know at the BL level is that pure thinking at the OL level will have two variants of
d-being or (which comes to the same thing) of its determinateness or quality, without being
able to distinguish between them. Pure thinking will either sink into variant A and, sunk in A,
know nothing of variant B, or vice versa. But then the two variants are one and the same for
pure thinking (it can make no difference between them); there is only one seemingly affirmative and immediate urstate d-being for pure thinking, though, in fact (and for us), there are
two variants of that urstate, one affirmative and the other negative.
D-being is the unique logical quale. Its variants therefore affect its quality, which is thus either positive or negative, either reality or negation (in the sense of privation, stersis). In
Hegels words (SoL 111):
Quality, taken in the distinct character of being, is reality, as burdened [or afflicted:
behaftet] with a negative [with a case of negating, Verneinung] it is negation in
general, likewise a quality, but one which counts as a deficiency, and which further on
is determined as limit [Grenze], limitation [Schranke].
So we have the following logical structure: d-being, identical with (its) determinacy, which
therefore is (its) quality and which in this identity is reality.
As long as identity reigns, we thus have:
d-being = determinacy = quality = reality.
40
But we in BL know that identity (and immediacy, being) is not the one and only ruler. There
is negativity (difference) there as well. And when negativity reigns, we will get a distinction
between d-being and determinacy and ipso facto (!) a distinction within quality between reality (positive quality) and negation (negative quality):
d-being determinacy; quality (qua reality) negation.
-- -- -This is a very old and venerable logical structure, arguably detected by Empedocles. Empedocles countenances (a) four material and (b) two kinetic principles of the universe:
(a) earth, water, air, fire [the four elements]
(b) love (philia) and hate/strife (neikos)
Now, the kinetic principles operate on the material ones, bringing them together (love) and
asunder (hate) periodically. Thus, the cosmic process is cyclic or periodic, a succession of
periods of love (where unity is growing) and periods of hate (where diversity is growing).
But love and hate affect their own relationship as well. When love is at its peak, we have
complete unity and perfect harmony, so there is nothing left to unite, which makes love collapse (or at least weaken) so that hate can grow again. When hate is at its peak on the other
hand, love and hate must be in a perfect equilibrium, i.e. equally strong, and then the balance
tips to the other side again (the one of love).
So we get a somewhat paradoxical result: When love wins, there is nothing but love (and at
the same time neither love nor hate any more); and when hate wins, love is exactly as strong
as hate. So, love is in a way the monarchic and hate the democratic principle. (Cf. the
well-known paradox that in a democracy the foes of democracy must have equal rights, and
esp. the right to express and defend their views.)
More abstractly, one can talk of identity and difference (non-identity) instead of love and
hate, and say the following: When identity reigns, identity and non-identity are identical;
when non-identity reigns, they are non-identical. This is true in a way of d-being as well:
When (d-)being reigns, d-being and determinacy (and at the same time reality and negation)
are one affirmative quale. When determinacy reigns, d-being and determinacy (and at the
same time reality and negation) negatively fall apart in difference.
-- -- -In (a) Determinate Being in General Hegel had portrayed d-being as unitary and affirmative: as in the form of being (110), in (b) Quality (111) Hegel had stressed the side of
negativity, difference: the articulation of d-being. In (c) Something he now stresses the side
of identity and unity again. This order is supposed to represent what is happening at the level
of pure thinking: d-being splits and reunites. Qua reunited it is called a d-being (Daseiendes) and something (Etwas).
But why should that be so?
We saw (in BL) that pure being is no possible content of thought, not even a possible urstate,
because it just cannot be purified from its original contamination with negativity. The first
thing to happen in the evolution of logical space is therefore becoming and the first thing to
be there is being-there (Dasein) or d-being.
But if we have to relegate the logical start with pure being (and the transition, via nothing, to
becoming) to a fictitious logical pre-history, then the affirmative being which we have to
project retrospectively beyond the infinitesimal becoming was already d-being.
41
17-Feb-09
D-being comes in two varieties, one affirmative (being as reality) and one negative (being as
negation). Or, more precisely, d-being comes in one singular variety from the standpoint of
the affirmative variety, and it comes in two different varieties from the standpoint of the negative variety. This, as it were, half-hearted duality is the duality of duality and non-duality
and at the same time the unity of unity and non-unity (or identity of identity and non-identity,
cf. Empedocles: love/strife of love and strife). And it is duality enough for reality and negation to qualify as real successors of (or as real logical starters instead of) the fictitious
urstates being and nothing. After all, pure being and pure nothing were supposed to be one
and the same urstate (B=N) from one standpoint (the one of being) and two distinct urstates
(B
N) from the other standpoint (the one of nothing), as well.
And as the conflict of the opposing standpoints was solved by infinitesimal becoming in the
fictitious pre-history, so it will be in the real history of the evolution of logical space.
Since the negative variety of d-being is as original as the affirmative one, this latter one can
always be seen as the outcome of a becoming that took place with respect to d-being. Becoming, as a transition from d-being to d-being, is then called alteration, and its two sides or
terms are called something (a d-being, Daseiendes) and the other.
So instead of the original series
pure being [+ nothing]
becoming
d-being
Dasein in general
[Or: Dasein + dist.
distinction in it
sublation of dist.
Note how peculiar becoming qua alteration is: it leads from A to A (not from A to non-A).
(But such is the concept of alteration: what alters in one respect remains the same in another.)
New scenario: The sublatedness of the distinction is determinate beings own determinateness; it is thus being-within-self [Insichsein, esse in se, cf. Spinoza: substantia est, quod
in se est et per se concipitur]; das Dasein ist Daseiendes, Etwas. (115)
Something is the first negation of negation, as simple self-relation in the form of being.
(115, middle) Not yet: negation-of-itself, but double negation (cf. Not (not (being)!).
(Double negation is not idle, something happens in it: self-individualization. See below.)
Something is double negation not only for us (as was d-being in general), but also for pure
thinking. In something self-mediation is present and posited (116, top), therefore its esse
is in se esse, it therefore is the beginning of the subject (115, bottom), i.e. of self-individualization. (In grasping the content something, pure thinking has to mediate itself.)
Next series (116, bottom):
Something
alteration
Note: In something, mediation with self is posited (116, top) vs. [something] is not yet posited as mediating and mediated (116, bottom). (It will be posited as such in the other itself.)
Note: But to begin with, something alters only in its Notion; it is not yet posited as mediating
and mediated [through alteration and the sublation of alterity]. In its Notion: in its BL definition. When an OL urstate will have further developed so that it (i.e. its successor) now contains what its BL definition contained, then it has altered and is not the same urstate any more,
42
but a new one with a new BL definition (Notion). So the logical urstates are always running
behind their respective Notions (BL definitions).
Only in the Notion (or Concept) itself, what is posited will have caught up with the BL
definition. (The Notion is, at the same time, its own Notion, cf. 578 t., 582, ll. 13ff.)
B. Finitude
With something, d-being has begun to dissociate from logical space; and with something and
an other, logical space has split. (But pure thinking does not see the splitting yet; it is either
sunk into the one side or into the other. It is bifurcated itself in the splitting of logical space.
With the category of limit, though, pure thinking will catch up to our vantage point. But then
the splitting will be internalized to the finite something.)
What further categories are here developed? We already have:
(being, nothing,) becoming, determinate being, determinateness, quality, reality, negation, something (= a d-being), being-within-self, alteration, other
We shall get (as the categories of finitude):
The other (of) itself, self-identical something, being-for-other, being-in-itself, determination, constitution, limit, finite (= finite something), limitation (= transcended, negated limit), ought (= negatively affected in-itself or determination)
Note: These categories are here not developed as some basic general concepts, true of things
(as e.g. in Kant), but in and for pure thinking: as pure entities on their own account, logical
urstates.
Survey of Hegels text:
(a) Something and an Other (117-122)
[Finitude for us, in BL]
The other of itself (118) as self-identical something (119 t.); being-for-other (119),
being-in-itself (119) [not: being-within-self, cf. 115; Ansichsein vs. Insichsein]
1.1 Something and other are both somethings.
1.2 Each is equally an other (cf. alius alium and alter alterum).
1.3 The other is (therefore, 118) to be taken as isolated, abstractly, as the other of itself. The other (of) itself comes in two variants: it (i) negates itself, alters itself (118
b.) and (ii) is posited as reflected into itself with sublation of the otherness, as the
with-itself-identical something (119 t.). (And now the something is posited as mediating and mediated, 116 b.)
According to (i) the other of itself is a variant of the urstate [with: ~()]. And
(ii) portrays one of two results of the self-negation of , the affirmative one. (We can
represent the affirmative one as resulting from a trick: if we put the negation signs together in pairs, then the unfounded negation will turn into the unfounded affirmation:
~ ~(~ ~(~ ~())). But the trick shows at the same time its own one-sidedness, because
the number of infinite negation signs is not even.
2. Being-for-other and being-in-itself constitute the two moments of the something.
There are here present two pairs of determinations: 1. Something and other, 2. Beingfor-other and being in-itself. (119) [Logical space is divided between two inhabitants,
and each of them has being-in-itself from its own standpoint and mere being-for-other
from the others standpoint.]
43
3. Somethings being-in-itself as identical with its being-for-other is its determination. [See below.]
(b) Determination, Constitution and Limit (122-129)
44
() Limitation and the Ought (131-133/136)
To get ahead (with the perishing of the perishing) we must detect some (new) structure
within the finite, some moments of the finite. The quality of the finite (i.e. itself) is
its limit. So this is what gets negated in finites self-negation.
Thus, the finite has as moments itself qua negated (called limitation) and itself qua
negating (called the ought).
Somethings own limit thus posited by it as a negative which is at the same time essential, is not merely limit as such, but limitation. (132 t.) The in-itself as the negative relation to its limit [], to itself as limitation, is the ought. (Ibid.) Limitation is
the limit as transcended (negated). Determination has become an ought, limit has become a limitation. But now further, the finite as the ought transcends its limitation (133), but only as the ought [not as the is].
() Transition of the Finite into the Infinite (136-7)
The finite in its self-contradiction ceases to be, but in its ceasing-to-be reaches its determination (its better self, so to speak, but this better self is only): another finite,
and so on to infinity. That is to be taken quite literally, for in the other finite, the finite only unites with itself, and in this affirmative being reaches the other not of
it(self) qua particular finite but of the finite as such: the infinite. Logical space, filled
by the finite (or a finite), would always have to alter, because the finite would give
way to a new finite over and over again, each finite in the infinite sequence being (i)
the negation of and (ii) identical to its negated predecessor. So, each item in the sequence is negated (by its successor), none comes away unnegated. Therefore the
whole infinite sequence as such is negated as well, by an inifinitely-many-place operation of negation: [f0, ~ f0 (= f1), ~ f1 (= f2), ~ f2 (= f3), ]. The result of this infinitely-many-place negation, (), is the infinite.
The logical space of the simple infinite (of the infinite in its simple Notion, SoL 137) is the
paradoxical process (the standing flow) in which each finite negates itself and thereby creates
another self-negating finite: an infinite series of identical finites (of finite logical spaces). That
(paradoxical) flow doesnt jerk, it is completely continuous, and so doesnt even flow either.
Therefore the infinite is being and becoming at the same time (SoL 137, in fact, it is posited
as such, says Hegel). And it is self-relation (viz. originally the finites self-relation: the finite
itself becomes the infinite, by its own nature, 138) and indeterminate (ibid.), there being nothing (else) to do the determining. Still, it is (qua affirmative) the negation of the finite as such
(of all infinitely many particular finites at once, now and ipso facto in eternity).
-- -- -Let us survey the way from the first, simple something via the self-identical something to the
finite something, or finite, for short.
For the simple something, the other was completely invisible. The self-identical something
(the affirmative result of the other of itself) is at least negatively related to the other. It may
be compared to a Cartesian solipsist (CS), if this is a person who has read and now believes
the first two Meditations, but not the four following ones.
CS says to his other: I think, therefore I exist and am possessing being-in-itself as a thinking
substance; you instead are only a content of my representations, and your being is only beingfor-other, viz. being for me. [But we in BL see that the other is a CS as well.]
The simple something was (in OL, for itself, i.e. for pure thinking, not for BL) the whole of
logical space. The identical something, CS, is (for himself, i.e. in OL, not in BL) the soloist
filling all of logical space. (We in BL know s/he is not a soloist; we know there are two pre-
45
tenders in perfect symmetry.) That is a first step on the way to recognizing the other, a step
characterized by the distinction between being-in-itself and being-for-other.
In the second step, the pretender vacates a bit of logical space as irrelevant for herself/himself. This step is characterized by the pair of terms determination and constitution. The
region in logical space that the pretender left free he deems irrelevant for himself. He thinks
he is related to this region only externally, through his constitution. And the other pretender
does the same. Each pretender (each CS) now concedes that the other possesses being-in-itself
as well and that s/he her/himself possesses a being-for-other in so far as s/he is represented by
the other. But they are still sceptical or agnostic as to the existence of the other: s/he is a kind
of thing-in-itself; all one can know of him/her concerns his/her being-for-other, which is now
called constitution. (But is there really an in-itself behind the constitution? I dont know,
and it cannot bother me.)
But in the third and last step, something experiences itself (if we may go on personalizing it
for the sake of illustration) as inseparably connected to its other in and through their common
limit. Now the splitting of logical space is completely reconstructed at the OL level. But at
the same time the splitting breaks down, because the limited something and the limited other
are now in perfect symmetry and therefore indiscernibly one and the same finite.
-- -- -And then comes the logical development of the finite leading (via limitation and ought) to the
infinite.
-- -- -
46
24-Feb-09
The finite, by its own negativity, transcends itself and becomes infinite. But this transcending
cannot be conceived of as a logical (quasi- or pre-temporal) succession any more, because the
finite as such already consumes all of logical time (pre-time) in its dialectic of ought and
limitation. So we get an infinite series of finite urstates:
f0,
f0,
f0,
~ f0 (= f1),
~ f0,
f1,
~ f1 (= f2),
~ ~ f0,
f2,
~ f2 (= f3),
~ ~ ~ f0,
f3,
Nowhere, i.e. at no particular point, in that infinite series will the infinite be found. Or contrariwise: it is everywhere in that series (not beyond, but already there, present).
No member of the series comes away unnegated (each having a successor by which it is negated), so one can as well negate the whole series, by the very negativity of each of its members, and thereby make explicit, what is going on anyway:
[f0, ~ f0, ~ ~ f0, ~ ~ ~ f0, ]
The outer negation sign here only expresses the implicit negativity of the infinite series
of finites. (It is no alien force, 138 m., but the own negativity of the finite that makes it become infinite.)
-- -- -Excursus. The Logic can be interpreted as a critical reconstruction of metaphysics. How can
we do this at the present stage?
We have to interpret the logical urstates as fundamental predicates (categories) of the passing show that got lost with the Phenomenology. So, first of all, we have to bring the passing
(spatiotemporal) show back in again. The critical metaphysical question then is this: What is
the spatiotemporal show in the last analysis, i.e. in its deep ontological structure?
A metaphysic of finitude would answer: A manifold of finite items and would then have
to specify the items ontologically: Are they, basically, things and persons (Aristotle, Strawson)? Or are they pure processes (Sellarss metaphysics of ) or pure sets (Quines brave new
ontology) or the theoretical entities that current physics postulates (a very optimistic version
of scientific realism)? Or are they Heideggerian items (Zeug, Dasein, Gegenstnde, Bestand)?
But these further specifications are not yet at issue at the present stage of the evolution of
logical space. What is at issue is only the question, whether the passing show consists of finite
items in the last analysis. Hegel, from the standpoint of the Logic, would of course say: No.
The items of the passing show are not finite in the last analysis; nothing is. The infinite is not
beyond the passing show, but already present in it, here and now, as the own negativity of the
finite items turned upon itself. (Or something like that. Well get to know more about his
standpoint as the argument proceeds.)
-- -- -But back to our logical urstate infinity. How is the outer negation (in [f0, f1, f2, ]) to be
interpreted? We can hitherto conceive of three models among which to choose (with two of
them having already been operative before):
(i)
(ii)
(iii)
But not (i): because the logical succession is already needed within the negated series itself.
47
(iii) would be fine; but (ii) would be bad, because with otherness the infinite would be the
other of the finite, and both would again share logical space as did something and an other.
So, we would be back in finitude after all.
But up till now we just dont have a model of pure sublation. We know sublation only in
combination with (i) or (ii), i.e. either (i) as BL sublation (e.g. becoming was BL sublated in
d-being) or (ii) as sublation which is contaminated by otherness and thus by finitude: If A is
sublated in B, then at the same time A persists in logical space as the other of B (and vice
versa), in mutual qualitative negation.
What we need is neither qualitative, mutual sublatedness (something in the other and vice
versa) nor successive or BL sublatedness (becoming in d-being) but pure sublatedness, nonsuccessive and at the same time devoid of an accompanying qualitative negation. This pure
sublatedness Hegel calls ideality. But we are still far from that.
On the contrary, in operating on each of the infinitely many finites at a time, the infinitelymany-place negation, , collects the finites into a new urstate finitude as such which
gets negated in and by the infinite. Thus turns into ~ (one place negation) back again; in
Hegels words: [T]he immediate being of the infinite resuscitates the being of its negation, of
the finite again which at first seemed to have vanished in the infinite (138f.).
But note that this new urstate is there only as negated, never as self-subsistent, thus never as
an obtaining urstate:
[f0, ~ f0, ~ ~ f0, ~ ~ ~ f0, ],
a fact which may be seen as a BL hint in the direction of pure sublatedness, i.e. ideality.
But we must not force pure thinking and talk it into catching up with our BL knowledge. Pure
thinking must proceed at its own quiet pace.
-- -- -So, let it fall back into finitude (thus lending some kind of self-substistence to [f0, f1, f2, ]
after all)! Its logical space is then split between the infinite and the finite, the limit between
the two being the negativity that separates them ( or ~ respectively).
But something is different now than in the former case of the finite something with its limit:
the perfect symmetry that prevailed between both sides then is now lost or, more precisely,
disturbed by enrichment of content. There is more to each side than just being the negative of
the other (cf. The right hand side is where the thumb is left): One is the negative or opposite
of the self-destructive finite, the other is the negative or opposite of infinity.
So pure thinking cannot be lost in any one of them any more (as if each were as good as the
other), but has to oscillate between them (in order to get them both) and is in fact the very
oscillation between them, thus creating an infinite alternation:
, f, i, f, i, f, i,
In the case of the finite (and its dialectic of ought and limitation) there was no real progress
in the sequence of finites, because in each progressive step nothing was reached than the same
old finite again. Thus continuity reigned over discretion. But now we have an alternating
determination of the finite and the infinite (138) and thus a real progress (with discrete
steps) into infinity.
-- -- -Some notes. (1) What is the logical (pre-)time of this infinite progression? Since pure
thinking has fallen back into finitude, its pre-time is the old finite pre-time once again, newly
filled now. In the progression, i and f behave as ought and limitation against each other.)
48
(2) We have already had occasion to watch pure thinking in its oscillation between its alternating determinations. First, we studied the transition of the finite into the infinite (136),
then, we studied the resuscitating of the being of the finite (138f.). Pure thinking is caught in
exactly these two acts, forever, or so it seems.
(3) The infinity of the progress itself is the same spurious infinity (142 m.) as the infinity of
one of its two members.
(4) The logic here has deduced the paradigm of all infinite progresses.
-- -- -Hegel text on infinity has three passages, which Hegel summarizes thus (137):
The infinite is:
(a) in its simple determination, affirmative as negation of the finite
(b) but thus it is in alternating determination with the finite, and is the abstract, one-sided
infinite
(c) the self-sublation of this infinite and of the finite, as a single process this is the true
or genuine infinite.
We have already talked about (a) and (b). So, what about (c) Affirmative Infinity (143ff.)?
It is self-sublation (of i and f) as a (single) process, thus becoming, thus both (i) an encompassing, concrete unity of being and negativity and (ii) infinitesimal [but can the true infinite
be infinitesimal?], thus transition: to infinite being, called being-for-self.
Can the true infinite be infinitesimal? Yes, qua becoming; but not qua being. Qua becoming
it is the transition to infinite being (being-for-self). So the infinite is both, becoming and being. This explains one of the puzzling things about Hegels text, viz. the fact that he (deliberately?) blurs the distinction between true infinity and being-for-self in what he says about
infinity. (This blurring the distinction has a solid foundation in infinity and being-for-self.)
Cf. 148, bottom 149, line 1 (This determination of the true infinite [] present before
us.), especially:
The infinite [], like its two moments [i.e. i and f], is essentially only as a becoming, but
now a becoming further determined in its moments. And:
This infinite, as the consummated return to self [als In-sich-Zurckgekehrtsein], the relation
of itself to itself, is being [], viz. (which Hegel does not say here) being-for-self.
-- -- -The transition of becoming to d-being [Dasein] was as a real change (at least prima facie):
d-being was the stable negative of unstable becoming. The transition of infinity qua becoming to being-for-self [Frsichsein] seems to be a transition just from instability to stability,
without change of underlying urstate.
That means that the quality of the underlying urstates remains the same. This quality is ideality (pure sublatedness). See p. 150 (Transition):
Ideality can be called the quality of infinity; but it is essentially the process of becoming, and
hence a transition like that of becoming in determinate being which is now to be indicated.
[]
So, it is all already there, the transition needs only to be indicated, not to be argued for any
more. With (a) ideality as the quality of the infinite (and being-for-self as well) and (b) infin-
49
ity qua (transition to) stable being, we have already reached being-for-self, which is therefore nothing more and nothing less than truly infinite being (cf. 157, first sentence of ch. 3).
Some notes:
(1) The genuine infinite is the fundamental concept of philosophy (Enc. 95, end).
(2) The proposition that the finite is ideal [ideell] constitutes idealism. [] Every philosophy is essentially an idealism []. (154f.) (Thus, there cannot be a genuine
metaphysics of finitude, after all; or so Hegel says. What then about, e.g., Heidegger?)
(3) So, being-for-self is already a bit of THE NOTION in the area of immediate being.
(Theres always a bit of heaven in a disaster area, Hugh Romney, Woodstock, NY,
1969.)
All (at least a lot) seems to hinge on the concept of ideality (pure sublatedness). Its high time
we took a closer look.
-- -- -There was no ideality in the sphere of finite d-being. The problem with neatly fitting together
being and negativity in that sphere was that it could not be done. Sure, negativity would, as
negation-of-itself (cf. the other of itself), lead to an affirmative result from time to time, which
could then be wedded to being (in the case of the other of itself this led to the self-identical
something). But the union was never complete because of a structural bifurcation in the negation-of-itself: it had an affirmative result, to be united with being, and it had a purely negative result that didnt join the union (but took a rebel stand, outside): endless alteration, and as
well the other over there, beyond the line in bifurcated logical space.
Only in becoming was the unity of being and negativity concrete and total; i.e. only there,
no abstraction was made from the splitting force of negativity; becoming had it all and was
therefore self-contradictory, self-destructive, infinitesimal, giving way to one-sided, abstract
d-being. (Infinity qua becoming will give way to stable being as well, being-for-self, but being-for-self is not the opposite of infinity but, on the contrary, infinite being.)
In d-being, then, sublation was never pure and total. What existed sublated, as a moment, had
at the same time a self-subsistent being on the other side of the line. (This is the point of
Hegels frequent talk of qualitative negation.)
Now, in the case of the finite something (something with a limit), qualitative negation is
turned upon itself, once again, but is now finally in for yielding a unique result (not two of
them) and thus a new kind of quality (viz. ideality) which can be wedded to being without
remainder.
Therefore the new kind of quality, taken affirmatively, i.e. with the stress on being, and then
called reality (in a higher sense, 149 m.), is identical with the new kind of quality, taken
negatively, i.e. with the stress on negation, and then called ideality full stop. (In the sphere
of d-being, reality and negation were identical only from the standpoint of reality, not from
the standpoint of negation.)
So Hegel can say: It is not the finite which is real, but the infinite (149), and: ideal being
[das Ideelle] is the finite as it is in the true infinite [] (149f.). That might suggest a difference between reality in the higher sense and ideality. But in the true infinite, the infinite and
the finite are dynamically united (as becoming), and therefore Hegel can also say: Ideality
can be called the quality of infinity (150) and forget about reality in the higher sense from
then on. Being-for-self is sheer ideality, the self-relation of the sublating 163 b./m.) no
talk of higher reality any more.
50
Note: In being-for-self there is no hard (real) fringe containing a soft (ideal) interior (e.g. a
person of bones and flesh harbouring a mental software), but its all soft: The sublated is sublated not in an unsublated but in a sublated, viz. in itself.
-- -- -But if this is our next theoretical destination, then how do we get there? How do we get
there, given the alternating determination of the finite and the infinite in the infinite progress?
Hegel says: In this alternating determination of the finite and the infinite from one to the
other and back again, their truth is already implicitly present, and all that is required is to take
up what is before us. This [constant] transition [] constitutes the external realization of the
Notion [viz. of the true infinite]. For the infinite progress is the (external, one-sided)
unity of the finite and the infinite but the elimination, too, of this one-sided determination must lie in the externalization of the Notion [of infinity] now before us. (143)
So Hegels recipe for finding the notion of the true infinite is simply: Watch the infinite
progress of the alternating determination of the finite and the infinite!
So, if we watch it, what do we see?
(1) That f and i hang together in the alternation (qua infinite progress).
(2) That f and i are separated in the progress (qua alternation).
This gives us two modes of consideration (143f.):
(1) i and f taken in connection,
(2) i and f taken in separation.
Interestingly enough, both modes yield the same result (144 m.): viz. the connection (or
unity) of i and f, which is thus dominant (their separation being recessive, so to speak).
The separation is the unity of i and f from the standpoint of f, the connection is the unity
of i and f from the standpoint of i. But this seems pretty much old news, so far: the same old
relation we found between love and strife, being and non-being, identity and difference, etc.
However, Hegel goes on to say: [] each [!] is [] in its own self the unity [!] of both; thus
we have two [!] such unities [not one unity and one duality]. The common element [of both
unities], the unity [] as unity, posits them [] as negated, since each is supposed to be what
it is [and thus self-subsistent] in its distinction from the other; in their unity, therefore, they
lose their qualitative nature [!] (144 b.)
The important news is: The finite is also unity of f and i. So, either way (from the standpoint
of f as well as from the standpoint of i), f and i lose their self-subsistence and thus their qualitative nature. There remains no hard separation in which they could retain their qualitative
nature against one another.
But we have to exhaust all possibilities of consideration in order to make sure that no possibility is left over in which negativity will outlast sublation and remain there in qualitative
style.
So far, then, we have reflected on the common element of both unities, on unity as such. But
further, since [] they are also taken to be taken as distinct [otherwise they would not be two
different moments of their unity], the unity [] which each of these moments is, is differently
determined in each of them. (145 t.) What happens if we take their different determinations
explicitly into account?
51
Well, finitude is only as a transcending of itself; it therefore contains infinity, the other of
itself. Similarly, infinity is only as a transcending of the finite; it therefore essentially contains
its other and is, consequently, in its own self the other of itself. (145f.)
Note: Hegel must not argue from the nomenclature, e.g. Since the infinite is conceived as
the in- or non-finite, ! That would be cheating. The nomenclature has to follow the conceptual content, and it is the content, from which we must argue.
That the finite leads to the infinite, right by itself, seems pretty clear; that was the transition
to the infinite. But why has the infinite in its own self the other of itself, i.e. the finite? Because it just cannot be conceived immediately, like d-being in general. Pure thinking has to
grasp the infinite through the inherent negativity of the finite.
-- -- -Reflecting now in particular on the infinite progress, Hegel points out that i and f are in the
progress as this movement in which each returns to itself through its negation; they are only
as mediation within themselves []. They are thus a result []. (147)
In the progress, f goes together with itself through i, and i goes together with itself through f.
But not only that: what we get is only one single result here, not two separate ones; for if
even f is self-mediation, the progress must be thought as infinite in both directions, and in this
two-way-infinity, [i]t is [] a matter of complete indifference which is taken as the beginning; and thus the difference which occasioned the double result disappears of itself. (148 t.)
What then lasts of the difference between i and f? The difference of the double meaning
which both have (148):
The finite is
(1) only the finite over against the infinite,
(2) the finite and at the same time the infinite opposed to it.
The infinite is
(1) exclusively the infinite and as such the spurious infinite,
(2) the infinite in which i and f are only moments.
Thus, the infinite, qua becoming, deposes (degrades, lowers) itself to being only one of its
determinations and then to go together with itself again and become the true infinite. (148)
The straight line of the infinite progress is thereby bent back into itself and becomes a circle.
(149)
-- -- -Cf. becoming, pure and simple:
Becoming is Being+Nothing. Being in becoming is BN (ceasing-to-be), nothing in becoming
is NB (coming-to-be).
The true infinite is I+F. I in the true infinite is IF, F in the true infinite is FI.
Disanalogy: The whole of the true infinite is aptly called according to one of its moments: the
(true) infinite; while the whole of becoming could not be called (true) being (but was inifinitesimal becoming, only followed by being again).
-- -- --
52
3-Mar-09
Being-for-self
Four related terms (plus a fifth: Dasein, d-being):
Ansichsein
Frsichsein
being-in-itself
being-for-self
Sein-fr-Anderes
Sein-fr-Eines
being-for-other
being-for-one
53
And even that easy transition doesnt really belong to A.c), but is developed in full only in
B.a). So, the whole of section A seems to be theoretically idle.
Ad A.a) D-being and being-for-self:
In being-for-self, the difference between being and determinateness or negation is posited
and equalized (157 m.). That much we know. (Determinateness has been totally integrated
into being.) And this we know as well: As already mentioned, being-for-self is infinity which
has collapsed into simple being (158 b.).
(At the beginning of the logic, concrete becoming had collapsed into abstract, simple being,
called d-being, as well. But d-being was the opposite of becoming, while being-for-self is the
same as the infinite, i.e. it has the same quality: ideality.)
In so far as determinateness and negation are present in being-for-self, it is (trivially, one
might say) as well d-being (i.e. stable unity of being and negativity), but its determinateness
is bent back into the infinite unity of being-for-self as a moment (an ideal being), called
being-for-one (159 t.).
Ad A.b) Being-for-One:
The finite is present in the infinite as an ideal being: as such it has only being-for-one. But
we already know that the infinite is not a hard fringe around a soft core but soft through and
through. There is going to be a hard, in fact extremely hard, urstate, called one, in the sphere
of being-for-self, shortly. But not yet; as yet, there is only one ideality of that, for which or in
which there is supposed to be a determination as moment, and of that which is supposed to be
a moment in it. (159 m.)
To be for self and to be for one are therefore not different meanings [or sides] of ideality,
but are essential, inseparable moments of it. (160 t.)
Being-for-self can be represented by the infinite formula ~(~(~())). But many logical
urstates can, e.g. the other-of-itself and (as we shall see) essence. So, it all depends on how
the formula has to be interpreted at each different stage in the evolution of logical space.
Excursus:
In the case of the other-of-itself, (i) ~ stands for qualitative negation (which separates something and an other in logical space), and (ii) the affirmative variant of the
negation-of-itself (i.e. affirmation of itself) is here to be interpreted as affirmative
something. But there remains a negative variant as well, expressing permanent alteration and standing therefore an other.
In the case of essence, as we shall see, we dont have recourse anymore to some form
of immediate being in order to interpret the affirmative variant of the negation-ofitself. Here, negation is pure and absolute (not only self-related).
But there remains a negative variant as well. The affirmative variant identity and
the negative variant difference shine one into the other, as Hegel will say. (Each
seems to be the whole of essence and has the other and itself as its moments. They are,
as it were, two different sites of identical essence: You look at essence one way and it
looks back as identity; you look at it the other way and it looks back as difference.)
So, in the sphere of essence, ~ stands for shine, illusion, for the sealing off of pure
thinking from any putative object. (In essence, pure thinking shines only within itself.)
54
Note: In German shine, spelled Schein (verb: scheinen), means
(1) the same as in English (Sonnenschein, Mondschein, cf. Scheinwerfer,
i.e. shine thrower, for a headlight, spotlight, flood light),
(2) certificate showing or proving something (e.g. that you may drive a car:
Fhrerschein, that you attended a seminar: Seminarschein, that you were
sick and couldnt go to work: Krankenschein),
(3) appearance, illusion (cf. this item from the Prussian catalogue of virtues:
Mehr sein als scheinen!).
In being-for-self, ~ stands for pure sublation, i.e. ideality. The affirmative and the negative variant of the negation-of-itself are totally integrated with each other and at the same time
with being. Being is thus infinite being. And Being-for-self is self-related ideality.
Ad A.c) The One:
Since there is only one ideality of being-for-self and its moment (being-for-one), being-forself is the simple unity of both: itself and its moment. There is nothing, so to speak, in being-for-self to fund (pay for) a duality of it and its moment. So it collapses into immediacy,
the internal mediation breaks down. Being-for-self is thus a being-for-self, and [] the
wholly abstract limit of itself the one. (163)
The one as limit is abstract and self-related, because it has got no concrete sides (like something and other) whose limit it could be. Thus, the soft ideality of being-for-self has turned
into the hard reality of the one. [For a fuller treatment, see B.a)]
-- -- -That was the easy part of the chapter on being-for-self. Now come the difficulties, as Hegel
himself remarks, for: The moments which constitute the Notion of the one as a being-for-self
[its BL definition] fall asunder in the development. They are: (163 b.)
(1)
(2)
(3)
(4)
(5)
(6)
negation in general [B.a.) The One in its own self: there is nothing in it],
two negations [B.b) The One and the Void],
two that are therefore the same [B.c) Many Ones: sheer duality and plurality],
sheer opposites [C.a) Exclusion of the One: The ones are all on a par],
self-relation, identity as such [C.b) The one One of Attraction: indiscernibility],
relation which is negative and yet to its own self [C.c) / Transition to quantity].
The main and fundamental inconsistency of being-for-self is its violation of the principle of
the identity of indiscernibles (which is a theorem of second order predicate logic):
(Id.Ind.)
Since the conditional in the opposite direction (the indiscernibility of what is identical) is relatively unproblematic, we can strengthen (Id.Ind.) to get what may be called Leibnizs Law:
(LL)
which can be used to define identity in second order predicate logic. (So, identity and its ilk,
like difference, and the number predicates, twoness, threeness etc., all supervene on regular
or ground floor predicates. Hegel calls them determinations of reflection.)
But the many ones, being one exactly like the others, do violate (Id.Ind.) and (LL) and are
thus forming an inconsistent and instable urstate.
That is the foundation of the difficult part, which comes next: sections B and (above all) C.
-- -- --
55
Being-for-self is the third to (i) simple being und (ii) d-being: their synthesis (but we
wanted to forget about dialectics). In fact, determinateness is now bent back upon itself, and
in this sense d-being is indeed integrated into simple being.
Being-for-self: being as negation-of-itself, with negation understood as sublation
Now, self-sublation makes for softness (ideality), and being makes for hardness (reality,
now in the higher sense).
(And here reality in the higher sense may have its only interesting scene, after all.)
The ideality of being-for-self as a totality [viz. its of moments, i.e. of itself and its only moment: itself again] thus reverts, in the first place, to reality and that too in its most fixed, abstract form, as the one. (164 m.)
In the unity of hard being and soft self-sublation, that is, self-sublation has no chance of unfolding its internal structure, but gets compressed to absolute, amorphous density: the one.
But this is not the end of the (logical) story.
Ad B.a) The One in its own self:
The one simply is, it is unalterable, beyond d-being 164 b.).
Even Hegel or we, in our BL, do not define the one as the other (opposite, negative) of something else (as we did with d-being). We define it as the totality self-sublation and at the same
time as simple being. I.e., we dont use former logical urstates for its definition (as we used
becoming for the definition of d-being), pure being and sublation being no urstates but a mere
projection and an operation respectively. One could even say: If you want to know what simple being is, dont look at pure being (which is a logical fiction) but a being-for-self as collapsed into the one (in which collapse all difference and manifoldness has vanished, 165
t.).
D-being qua something was de facto within-self; we detected that. But here, with the one, its
being-within-self is posited (165 t.), i.e. part of its very definition.
As not being determined by some other, the one is the whole of logical space. But since all
difference and manifoldness have vanished from this logical space, there is nothing in it, it is
empty: the void.
The inconsistency of being-for-self begins to make its presence felt: The one is (i) withinitself (in sich); but then (ii) nothing, thus not even itself, is (with)in it. (In its being-withinitself it is pure negativity, but on the other hand it is simple being; and we already know: B=N
and BN!)
Ad B.b) The One and the Void:
But B=N and BN do not fall apart here, as two conflicting relations between B and N, but
are one and the same (thus paradoxical) relation in the unity of the one, because the one does
not tolerate two different relations (or any difference) within itself. But then, in its paradoxical
character, the one has to project the difference outside itself. So, the nothing as the void is
outside it. (165 m.)
New situation: Being-for-self determined in this manner as the one and the void has again
acquired a determinate being. (165 b.) Logical space has regained an articulate structure: It
is all empty with only the one in it.
(Hegel in a remark explains that this is the core of metaphysical atomism.)
56
In d-being we had: Integrated negativity vs. disintegrated negativity.
Here we have:
Integrated negativity vs. integrated negativity
(thus disintegration and d-being again).
Ad B.c) Many Ones: [First and Second] Repulsion:
1st stage of the d-being of being-for-self:
2nd stage:
Because of BN, we have here the one and there the void. But because of B=N we have
as well here the one and there the one; in Hegels words:
As essentially self-relation, the other [we are here talking of the ones d-being] is not
indeterminate negation as the void, but is likewise a one. The one is consequently a
becoming of many ones.
Strictly, however, this is not really a becoming, for becoming is a transition of being
into nothing: the one on the other hand becomes only one. (167 b.)
And: The negative relation of the one to itself is repulsion. (168 t.)
-- -- -Next, a first and a second repulsion have to be distinguished.
First it might seem, as if the one, by repelling itself from itself, posited and generated the
many ones (as perfect clones of itself). But if what is putatively created in repulsion really is
another indistinguishable one, then that new one repels itself from itself just like the first one.
Therefore, secondly, the repulsion is mutual or reciprocal between the many ones. It thus (cf.
C.a) will turn out to be exclusion: each one presupposes the many ones and excludes them
from itself.
Notes: (1) Thus plurality [sc. of the many ones] appears not as an otherness, but as a determination completely external to the one. (168 b./m.)
Plurality is in fact (quite independently of Hegels Logic) no variant of otherness in that it
cannot be defined in terms of identity and negation and quantification (like duality, triality,
etc.). Cf.:
there are exactly two F iffdf
there is an x such that Fx; and there is a y such that Fy; and xy; and for every z, if Fz,
then either z=x or z=y.
(2) According to Aristotle, a genus is differentiated into species by a differentia (i.e. otherness), and a species is pluralified into individuals, and these are two totally different ways
of going from unity to diversity: (i) form something to an other, (ii) from one to many.
(There really are pace Plato no genera according to Aristotle, but there are species and
individuals, and both come pretty close to the same thing: essential forms. But then, we have
a riddle of individuation which must be solved. The logic of being-for-self offers a way of
solving it to present day Aristotelians: the form/species repels itself from itself to many individual forms and collects them back again into the unity of the species, when the individuals
die the process of the species.)
Ad C.a) Exclusion of the One:
Next, the second repulsion is explicitly characterized as exclusion. But we in BL see that all
the ones are indistinguishable, thus identical: one One. And this is so as well on the level of
57
OL, for: to our external comparison as relating the ones there corresponds in OL the relation
of repulsion itself (the ones are related by it). But if (and in so far as) the ones are related at
all, they turn out to be identical, because they are indistinguishable). This OL movement toward their identity is attraction. In the one affirmative unity of attraction the many ones are
ideal (their reality is repulsion qua exclusion, which is presupposed by attraction).
Ad B.b) The one One of Attraction:
Repulsion is only the ought-to-be of ideality. In attraction, however, ideality is realized
(173 m.), but only for the many ones [and for us in BL], not yet for the one One of attraction
itself [and for pure thinking in OL]. The many ones do not in their ideality return into themselves but have this ideality in another one (174 t.) [and thus only for us].
But the one One of attraction does not sublate them [the many ones] abstractly, i.e. purely
negatively (positively only for us, in BL): Since it contains repulsion in its determination
[i.e. presupposes it], this latter at the same time preserves the ones as many in it (174 m.).
(But isnt then the one One already quantity, which is the (non-abstract) sublation of the
ones? Not yet; in quantity even the one One of attraction will be sublated.)
Ad B.c) The Relation of Repulsion and Attraction:
To show this, Hegel has to show not only that repulsion does not start from an immediate,
self-subsistent one but also that attraction does not lead to a self-subsistent one.
At first repulsion and attraction stand apart from one another; but they are as well essentially connected with each other (174 b.). We have the one (and the void); so repulsion seems
to come first, and then attraction (which presupposes repulsion) comes to the many as an
other (175 t.). But in fact, attraction is in repulsion itself (175 m./t.); otherwise repulsion
(exclusion) would break down at its own success: the many ones would just fly up and away.
So we have a mutual presupposition of repulsion and attraction. But each is also self-mediation (175 b.) and thus presupposes itself. Second Repulsion presupposes itself qua first repulsion; the being of the many ones is repulsion itself. Attraction idealizes the many ones; but
the ones are unalterable, so their ideality must already have been there.
So self-presupposition and presupposition of the other go together in repulsion and attraction.
The result of this dialectic of repulsion and attraction is the process which posits and contains it throughout only as sublated (177 b.). This process then collapses, qua becoming, into
the simple immediacy which is quantity, in which therefore being-for-self (which started as
self-sublation and reverted to reality) is sublated. (Quantity is sublated being-for-self, 187
t.; and continuity and discreteness are attraction and repulsion sublated in quantity; quantity
starts in the form of continuity because of its immediacy.)
But was not the one One (of attraction) already the realized ideality and thus sublatedness
(174) of the ones? Yes, but only of the many ones, it was not yet its own ideality.
-- -- -In d-being, there was alteration: A became B, i.e. something became an other (A vanished
and became B, 178 t.).
In being-for-self, there was no alteration: the one was unalterable (164 b.). The otherness
was wholly internalized (itself a being-for-self, 178 m.).
In quantity, being-for-self (unalterability) and being-for-other (alteration) are the same (185).
A becomes B and remains A nonetheless (i.e. it alters, and remains the same).
58
17-Mar 09
Basically, in the Logic of being we have two ingredients to work with:
(1) immediacy: being;
(2) negativity: mediation, relation, negation, determinateness.
Pure immediacy, i.e. pure being, has turned out to be a logical fiction. So whenever we have
immediacy, there will also be a little bit of mediation in it (cf. d-being and reality).
Since we have no pure immediacy to start with, mediation will never be all well-founded but
always contain a little bit of self-relation, i.e. of self-relation of the negative (164 m/t) or
self-related negation (165, l. 3).
The purely immediate would (per impossibile) be being, but being cannot be purely immediate. So the logical mark of being is not pure immediacy, but consistency (non-contradiction)
and therefore stability, rest (stable, affirmative self-mediation, if such there can be; a promising candidate was infinity qua being, i.e. being-for-self but it turned into the One).
The logical mark of negativity is inconsistency (self-contradiction) and therefore instability,
unrest.
Now, the One does not just have a little bit of self-related negation (at its outer rim, say) but is
self-related negation (164, 165), though not concrete self-negation with distinguishable moments, but abstract self-negation, sheer negativity, nothing. On the other hand, it is being-forself, thus infinite being, thus an (at first) promising candidate for stable, affirmative selfmediation: being.
The One is, as it were, a perfect superposition of pure being and pure nothing. Taken in
isolation, each of these was a logical fiction; taken together as moments of a third, they were
ways of becoming: ceasing-to-be and coming-to-be; but taken together as two self-subsistent
urstates superposed and fused into one new urstate, they are the One.
Thus, the One inherits stability from being and self-mediation from negativity. Its problem is
that its stability doesnt come from its self-relation, nor does its self-relation come from its
stability. Stability and self-relation (being and nothing) are only glued together, super-closely.
In its stability and self-mediation the One is unalterable. Nothing can happen to it. But in its
internal inconsistency, qua self-negation, it cannot be at rest either. So, quite a lot will happen,
but it wont touch the One in its own self but only what goes on around it, so to speak.
-- -- -Now, here is the logical core of the concept of the void, not yet spatial: We call something
void or empty, if nothing is in it (e.g. a bottle, a pot). The void (as a singularity) therefore is
affirmative logical space with nothing (no urstates, propositions, whatever) in it. The void
therefore may be defined as the quality of the perfect superposition of being and abstract
negativity. The void is thus the quality of the one in its immediacy. (165 m.) The one is the
void as the abstract relation of the negation to itself. (ibid.) For short: the one is the void.
However, next step, the void as the nothing is absolutely distinct from the simple immediacy, the also affirmative being of the one [remember that negativity and affirmative being are
only glued together], and since they stand in one and the same relation, namely, that of the
one [are glued together after all], their difference is posited [i.e. belongs to their BL definition and surely it does, if according to the BL definition the one is the superposition of two
different urstates], but as distinct from the affirmative being of the one, the nothing as the void
is outside it (165).
59
There is no room for any distinction within the one, just as there is no chance of any alteration of the one.
The metaphor of being and nothing as glued together in the One may be helpful here to illustrate what is going on. The One (affirmative being) is glued together with its quality, the void
(abstract negativity); but then only glued together, so they are still different. But as the one
can harbour no distinction, its own quality (qua distinct from it) must be outside it. So we
have the one and the void and therefore d-being again (165 m/b).
The moments of being-for-self: viz. itself and being-for-one (that had collapsed into the
One), are now revitalized, but as external to themselves (165 b): the One as the successor
of being-for-self and the void as the successor of being-for-one. Both are the same unity of
being and negativity, only differently accentuated, just as quality was in d-being: as reality
and as negativity, respectively. But here quality as such is negatively accentuated and projected outside the urstate One itself. (In this separation of an urstate from its quality, the next
logical stage, quantity, may already be foreshadowed.)
But the One and its quality (ideality, moment, negativity, ) are glued together. So what is
projected outside is still the whole thing: the quality has taken its qualified with it. The void is
still the One, as the One is still the void.
So, in the structure of d-being (the One and the void) no real alteration has taken place, when
the One became the void. The One became the One, outside itself. What is left from the void
is just the idea of an outside: the difference between the One and the One is totally external to
them, intrinsically they are the same, one is only just outside the other.
But then, the second One behaves just like the first One: it alters itself into another intrinsically identical One etc. for the third, fourth, fifth One as well. And even the first and second
keep on altering in this way. So, we get many Ones in the logical space which had been
empty, the void, before. The thought content of the void can now be reinterpreted as that into
which the many Ones multiply themselves by the adumbrated alteration which really is no
alteration and which Hegel calls repulsion.
-- -- -For subsection C. Repulsion and Attraction, see above. Here, I shall try to sketch only the
main ideas and then go on to main Section Two: Magnitude (Quantity).
-- -- -As the many Ones are all internally identical, there is no privileged first One as the unique
source of the general repulsion. So, the repulsion is mutual between any two Ones and is thus
(mutual and general) exclusion.
Exclusion is second repulsion, while first repulsion seemed to have a privileged One as its
source. But, of course, something like first repulsion is still needed; otherwise there would not
be many Ones to exclude each other, in the first place. (So, second always presupposes first
repulsion as something that must have happened in an a priori past, as it were)
Next, Hegel introduces attraction as counterbalancing repulsion, the basis of attraction being the intrinsic identity of the many Ones. And they are identical even considered extrinsically, because in the void there are no particular landmarks to create different external (quasispatial) properties. (So, there is no Onek closer to landmark k than Onek+1.) Therefore, they are
in fact, all identical as well; and this identity appears at the OL level (i.e. for pure thinking)
as their mutual and general attraction into the one One of attraction.
But repulsion/exclusion is still operative as well, and Hegel shows that attraction and exclusion presuppose each other (as well as each itself). Pure thinking at the OL level just is the
60
ongoing process of repulsion and attraction of the many Ones. And what Hegel must show for
the transition to quantity to be accomplished, is that pure thinking rises above what it is (repulsion and attraction of the Ones) and makes what it is (and then: was) its new content. This
new content is the one One of attraction, accomplished in such a way that its internal structure of repulsion and attraction is positively sublated, i.e. preserved. So, the one One is not
as internally unstructured as each of the many Ones.
The theoretical work that Hegel has to invest here is to show how pure thinking can leap up
so to speak from only repelling and attracting the many Ones, to our BL vantage point. For
us, the process of repulsion and attraction is already the one One, but (as yet) only as a regular
propositional state of affairs in our BL, not as an OL urstate to be grasped by pure thinking.
-- -- -A leap up (of pure thinking) of the required kind occurs at different stages in the logical development. It occurred for the first time in the transition from the infinite progress (the unity
of the finite and the infinite for us) to true infinity (their unity for pure thinking). It will occur
again in the transition from measure (the unity of quality and quantity for us) to essence
(their unity in which all of being is reduced to absolute shine for pure thinking).
Here, as soon as pure thinking grasps the urstate the one One of attraction, it passes on to
quantity. Or, more precisely, the one One of Attraction then collapses into the immediacy of
quantity as did the infinite into the stable and infinite being-for-self.
To show that pure thinking grasps the one One, Hegel has to show that in the process of repulsion and attraction no single aspect remains unsublated (as he had shown that in the infinite progress no aspect, neither the finite nor the infinite, remained unsublated).
Let us suppose that has been done and move on to quantity:
The process in which the One is self-subsistent neither qua starting point nor qua result, but
only present qua sublated, in the instability of its moments, is the collapse, or rather goingtogether-with-itself, into simple immediacy. This being [being: because it is immediacy], in
the determination it has now acquired, is quantity. (177 b).
-- -- -Quantity is the determinateness which has become indifferent to being [] (185 t) Who
is (actively) indifferent toward whom? Being toward quantity (cf. the German original: dem
Sein gleichgltig: Sein does not care or bother about its quantity). Hegel goes on: [] a
limit which is [] no limit, being-for-self which is absolutely identical with being-for-other
a repulsion of the many ones which is directly the non-repulsion, the continuity of them.
We have to try to understand these characterizations.
(1) Being does not care about (its) determinateness. It is no quale anymore; determinateness (i.e. quantity) may vary, being will stay the same. (Enc 99: Quantity is the
pure being in which determinateness is posited no longer as one with the being itself,
but as sublated or indifferent.)
(2) Quantity is a limit which is no limit.
(3) Being-for-self is absolutely identical with being-for-other.
(4) Quantity (qua sublated being-for-self) is a repulsion which is non-repulsion, continuity. Continuity thus is attraction, but attraction as sublated in a new urstate.
In d-being, alteration (becoming an other than itself) was what happened to something. In
being-for-self, there was (at first) no alteration and no other anymore. Now, in quantity, alteration is staying-oneself: The coming-out-of-self here is no turning into ones opposite, but
61
is as such a perennial self-production of unity, a perpetual becoming-other which is selfidentical (189 m). Quantity is, so to speak, soft repulsion: a creative flowing away of itself, an uninterrupted continuity (188 t), it is (cf. Spinoza) infinita, unica et indivisibilis
(189).
In being-for-self, the many ones were (as such) a violation of the identity of indiscernibles
(IdInd). In quantity, this is still so, but at the same time (IdInd) enforces its validity. So, basically, quantity is the contradiction of (IdInd) and Non-(IdInd): The many ones are still many,
but at the same time one and the same. Cf. p 190 m/t: Quantity is plurality as simple [!] unity
[not as an aggregate or a mereological sum]; its Notion is that each of the many is the same
as every other.
Thus, in quantity, repulsion and attraction are not different movements any more, but their
unity is now explicit: repulsion as such is attractive and attraction as such repulsive.
-- -- -Examples of pure quantity: space, time, matter, light, the ego (185f.)
-- -- -Chapter 1. Quantity
A. Pure Quantity
B. Continuous and Discrete Magnitude
C. Limitation of Quantity
We have talked about pure quantity (A), and we have mentioned attraction and repulsion in
quantity, thus continuous and discrete magnitude (B). In quantity qua (immediate) unity, attraction (thus continuity) is dominant first: continuous magnitude (199 b). But repulsion is
there as well, so quantity is as well discrete magnitude. Hegel does not make much argumentative ado about this transition (cf. 200 t). He just says that each moment of quantity is as
well the whole of it (200).
The Encyclopedia may be of some help here, 100: Continuous and discrete quantity are not
species of but perspectives on (aspects of) quantity: The same whole is at one time posited
under one of its determinations and the other time under the other. And this, if taken in oscillation, gives the antinomy of infinite divisibility (Kants second antinomy of pure reason).
Discrete quantity might be considered the logical core of set or class (cf. 200 m). (Remember that set theory was invented and developed by Georg Cantor for the sake of infinity; finite
sets are rather trivial. So, discrete quantity qua the logical core of set may still be infinita,
unica et indivisibilis.)
Next, Hegel goes from quantity to quantum: quantity with a limit, and this happens again
without much argumentative effort in C. Limitation of Quantity: In the duality of continuous and discrete quantity, quantity as such is limited; so both undergo transition into quanta,
but not in two sorts of quanta, but into quantum as such (201 b).
-- -- -Chapter 2. Quantum
A. Number
B. Extensive and Intensive Quantum
C. Quantitative Infinity
According to the classical conception of number (cf. Aristotles discussion of various conceptions in Met. MN), each number is a unit of units (a one of ones).
62
And Hegel assents: The One is the element or medium of number, and that in two respects
(cf. one of ones): according to discreteness as amount (of units), according to continuity
as unit(y) or oneness.
Frege has criticized the classical conception exactly on the ground that it violated (IdInd) and
has analyzed numbers as properties of concepts instead. E.g. the number two is the common
property of all concepts which have exactly two instances. This sounds circular, but the circle
can be eliminated:
Concept c has exactly two instances iff
(x)(y)(x, y fall under c, and xy, and (z)(if z falls under c, then z=x or z=y))
That may be fine for the purposes of mathematics as that particular region of our thinking
which is posited as free of contradiction.
Nevertheless mathematics springs from inconsistency (in a process of logical emancipation
this much may be conceded to Frege), and the logical source of mathematics (here: of number theory) may be captured well by the classical conception and its (anyway critical) reconstruction in Hegels logic. (Thus, there is here no real conflict between Hegel and Frege,
though Frege would no doubt believe so.)
-- -- -So, number is amount and unit. This gives the kinds of arithmetical operation: addition,
multiplication and raising to square power. Uniting units is number formation (numbering,
counting, SoL 206); uniting (counting) numbers is addition; uniting (counting) numbers of
equal amount (which thus can serve as units) is multiplication, uniting numbers of equal
amount as many times as the amount contains units (so that amount and unit are here equal) is
raising to square power.
-- -- -B. Extensive and Intensive Quantum
(a) Their difference
(b) [Their] Identity []
(c) Alteration of Quantum
Ad (a):
One could perhaps say (Hegel doesnt but gives other examples) that extensive and intensive
quantum are the aspects of cardinality and ordinality. With natural numbers, there is no difference in extension (only in intension) between cardinals (which measure the size of finite
sets) and ordinals (which give the order type of finite well-ordered sets). We get the same
infinite sequence in both cases: 0, 1, 2, 3,
Finite cardinal and finite ordinal numbers are different only in their Notion (intension). The
cardinals are encompassing, they have their individual determinations (numbers of units)
within themselves; e.g. the cardinal 3 is the unit(y) of three units. The ordinals, on the other
hand, have their determinations outside themselves; e.g. the ordinal 3 is the ordinal which has
exactly three predecessors (0, 1, 2).
Beyond finitude, with infinite sets, cardinals and ordinals even part in extension. There is exactly one cardinal of the size of the set of natural numbers, called Aleph0, but there are infinitely many ordinals of that size (Aleph0, Aleph0+1, +2, +3, ).
One can see here a bit of the strength of Hegels Logic. Hegel didnt know anything about set
theory. Nevertheless his logic laid bare a pivotal distinction of set theory, which Hegel then
63
interpreted along more commonplace lines as a distinction of (a) normal natural number and
(b) degree.
-- -- -The cardinal number or extensive quantum is determined by what (i.e. by how many) it comprises or encompasses. So, it is within itself discrete, a plurality which has no being distinct
from its limit, nor is the limit external to it. Quantum thus [] is extensive magnitude. (217)
[Continuity and discreteness are determinations of quantity as such, while [e]xtensive and
intensive magnitudes are determinatenesses of the quantitative limit itself (217).]
But the many in the defining limit of a given cardinal number are all alike, all the same.
Consequently the limit of quantum [] passes over into simple determinateness. In this simple determination of the limit, quantum is intensive magnitude; and the limit [] is now also
thus posited as unitary degree. (218)
(b) Identity of Extensive and Intensive Magnitude
But equally, intensive magnitude has its defining amount, which is therefore within it (in a
sense). (The twenty predecessors of the ordinal 20 have to be united in one unity in order to
define 20.) Thus, intensive magnitude passes over into extensive magnitude again, and both
are in fact identical.
Identical through the negation of difference: That was the defining trait of a d-being or something. Therefore: With this identity, the qualitative something makes its appearance, as a
kind of substrate of quantum. Something is a quantum (221).
(c) Alteration of Quantum
With d-being and something alteration is back again. At the same time, the quantum is infinite qua successor of the one and of being-for-self. So it repels itself from itself. Repulsion
and alteration therefore go hand in hand with the quantum; it is now the express character of
quantum to impel itself beyond itself and to become an other (225 m). But the other is no
longer indiscernible form it, but greater or smaller. The quantum consists in undergoing increase or decrease (225 m), as an infinite progress in both directions (the greater and the
smaller): in counting and in dividing the continuum.
-- -- -In the Encyclopedia we find a slightly different disposition of the section on quantity:
a. Pure Quantity
b. Quantum
c. Degree
In degree (or intensive magnitude), Hegel says there ( 104), the notion of quantum is posited: What we knew about quantum in our BL is now visible for pure thinking in OL. We
knew the contradiction of quantum: that its many units are at the same time indiscernible and
therefore one and the same. In the degree their oneness reigns, but their plurality is also present: in the external neighbourhood of the degree (the plurality of an ordinal n consisting in
the n predecessors of n).
Now it is characteristic for degree that its very internality is its externality and vice versa. In
pure quantity being was indifferent toward its determinateness (which was thus quantity).
Now the affirmative side (being) and the negative side (determinateness) are fused:
Degree is indifferent toward degree (i.e. itself).
64
Degree is exactly what it is not and doesnt even care! It is self-determined (every ordinal
is what it is without any help of its friends, i.e. the other ordinals), but its self-determination
is completely external and foreign to it.
This paves a short way to measure for the encyclopaedic logic (EncL) in 104-106:
We know from SoL that quantum is something, therefore alterable and finite. We know
(from EncL and SoL) that intensive quantum (degree) is indifferent toward itself.
Qua finite something the quantum alters, and qua degree it is indifferent to this alteration and
always stays the same: quantum. In EncL 104 Hegel says:
In this contradiction: that the independent (i.e. being-for-self) indifferent limit is absolute externality, the infinite quantitative progress is posited an immediacy which
immediately veers round into its opposite, into mediatedness (the passing beyond the
quantum just posited), and vice versa.
Number is a thought, but thought as a being which is completely external to itself. []
The quantitative infinite progress goes to infinity in both directions: toward the infinitely
large in counting and toward the infinitely small (the infinitesimal) in dividing the continuum. And it never reaches its beyond, i.e. quality as such.
But in fact we have here already a union of quantity and quality: To have its own internality
(being-for-self) in sheer externality is already quality: the quality of quantum.
In Hegels word (EncL 105, translated by W. Wallace, with my commentaries):
That the Quantum in its independent character [in its being-for-self determinateness] is
external to itself, is what constitutes its quality. In this externality it is itself and referred connectively [related] to itself. There is a union in it of externality, i.e. the quantitative, and of independency (Being-for-self), the qualitative. The Quantum when
explicitly put [i.e. posited] thus in its own self, is the Quantitative Ratio [or quantitative relation: Verhltnis], a mode of being [a determinateness] which, while in its
Exponent [as exponent of the ratio/relation], it is an immediate quantum [cf. p in the
function:
x = py], is also mediation, viz. the reference [relation, Beziehung] of some one
quantum to another, forming the two sides of the ratio. But the two quanta are not
reckoned at their immediate value: their value is only in this relation.
And 106 says:
The two sides of the ratio are still immediate quanta: and the qualitative and quantitative characteristics [determination(s)] still external to one another. But in their truth,
seeing that the quantitative itself in its externality is relation to self, or seeing that the
independence [being-for-self] and the indifference of the character [of determinateness] are combined [united], it is Measure.
-- -- --
65
24-Mar 09
It is good to be clear on some basic conceptual tools with which Hegel operates.
The distinction between in itself (in principle) and posited is closely related to the distinction between determinateness and determination.
The determination of an entity (here: of a logical urstate) is so to speak the determinacy of its
in-itself (and as such the opposite of the entitys outer constitution). It is that which is a yet
hidden at the OL level (like the oak tree in the acorn), but is already in for becoming visible.
When it becomes visible at the OL level, it gets posited, which means that the (former) determination becomes (the new) determinateness or (in still other terms) that the notion of the
entity in question becomes realized and acquires Dasein (being-there, i.e. existence of the
type of the logic of being, called d-being). It is now there for pure thinking at the OL level.
The aspects of the in-itself of a given logical entity (urstate) which are stated in its BL definition are its determinations (in the plural now, if there are, as usual, more than one aspect). As
long as the logical process goes on (and is still underway to its final fixed point), when an
urstate, u, gets posited, a new urstate, u, arises as its successor, with the determination of u
being the determinateness of u.
Here is an example:
But with the positing of quantum in conformity with its Notion [sc. in the ratio of
powers], it has undergone transition into another determination [therefore into another
in-itself, expressed by another BL definition]; or, as we may also express it, its determination is now also a determinateness, what quantum is in principle [in itself, an
sich] it is now also in reality. (SoL 323 m/t)
Quantum was number and, more specifically, ordinal number or intensive magnitude, degree, and degree was by definition indifferent to (and for) itself, was exactly
what it was not (and didnt even care). It was self-determined (thus an instance of being-for-self), but its self-determination was completely foreign and external to it.
Now, in the ratio of powers the externality of the degree is internalized; here the
quantum in its otherness is identical with itself (SoL 322 m/t).
An ordinal (a degree) is what it is considered in isolation, but in its outer being-there
(d-being) it is determined by the set of its predecessors (the other degrees). In the ratio
of powers, y= x2, quantum itself determines its other by which in turn it is determined.
(or so Hegel says. Well come back to this shortly.)
-- -- -Now, in the minor Logic (EncL), the doctrine of essence begins thus:
Essence is the Notion as posited Notion [].
Essence is (the) Notion, even posited Notion? How can that be true? Isnt essence just that:
essence?
Well, even (pure) being is already the Notion, not yet the posited Notion though, but only the
Notion in itself (in principle, an sich). Here is the reason why:
Nothing [a nice ambiguity] is posited in pure being. If something [again an ambiguity, but not a nice one, because we are here not talking about the logical urstate something] were posited in it, if being had a (concrete, non-abstracting) BL definition, if it
could be really thought instead of meant only, then it would (per impossibile) have
to have a logical predecessor at the OL level and would be determination of that
66
predecessor, while the predecessor in turn would be realized in and with being, i.e.
would have its being-there (d-being) in pure being (surely an absurd scenario).
Now, pure being is meant to be all of logical space, thus the absolutely infinite, unconditioned and free, to quote Hegels opening claim about the pure Notion (SoL
601). Therefore, pure being is already the Notion in principle (in itself: still totally
hidden and implicit).
We learned: In and with essence, Notion is posited. That means that the aspects of our BL
definition of Notion (i.e. of the Notion of the Notion, i.e. the determinations of the Notion) are
already there at the OL level, but not yet united into a single thought or single logical urstate.
Thus Hegel continues (EncL 112):
[Essence is the Notion as posited Notion], the determinations are in (the) Essence only
relative ones [W. Wallace: correlatives], not yet [as] absolutely reflected in themselves
[but still reflected in their respective other]; therefore the Notion is not yet as for-self.
Essence, which is Being coming into mediation with itself through the negativity of itself [the grinding mill running free, grinding what is already ground, without original
input], is the relation to itself, only in so far [and because of this restriction other than
in the case of the Notion] as the relation is relation to an other, this other however being immediately not as something which is, but as something which is posited and mediated.
What does that mean? In essence the determinations of the Notion are present, but only as
correlatives, not as united into one thought. Their correlation is not d-being, however, but
one side, the side of the other, is not there (d-being-ly), but only posited and mediated
(sublated). (Being posited is in fact the essence-logical successor of the being-logical beingthere or d-being, i.e. Gesetztsein is the successor of Dasein.)
This is true, in the first instance, of the other of essence: being, which is in (the) Essence
only as shine, not as a real other. But it is true as well of the internal structure of essence.
(In fact, there is no opposition here in the first place: Essence is the shining in itself and
thus creates, posits, the determinations of that shining: the essentialities or determinations
of reflection.) The determinations of reflection come in pairs, first as identity and difference. Now, each of these two essentialities purports to be the whole of essence, and each includes the other as its moment, each in turn shines into the other one.
So, identity is in itself (in principle, an sich) as well difference, and vice versa. But they
dont come around to form one unitary urstate of essence. Or when they finally do, in the
urstate (the essentiality) contradiction, their union is the extremely unhappy one of posited
inconsistency and geht zu Grunde, literally: goes (falls) to ground, i.e. perishes (the German
zugrunde gehen fits together well with what results from that perishing: the ground, as the
last one of the essentialities, 444 m).
-- -- -But what now about the Notion? (We started talking about it and should say one more word
in order not to remain totally cryptic, although it is not our present subject matter.)
With the notion the fixed point of the logical development is reached, at least in principle.
That means that OL content and BL content now finally coincide (at least in principle) and
that our BL definition of the Notion is represented in the Notion itself or that the Notion is as
well the Notion of the Notion. On the other hand, as Hegel says, the Notion is as yet only the
Notion of the Notion, not yet its full (self-)realization, this latter being be the absolute idea
with which the logic actually ends.
A quick way to give (or summarize) the BL definition of the Notion is this (SoL 578 t):
67
The progressive determination of substance [the concluding essence-logical urstate] necessitated by its own nature [i.e. substance itself necessitates its progressive determination], is the positing of what is in and for itself. [Substance in this positing becomes as
well subject.] Now the Notion is [and here comes the quick definition] that absolute unity
of being and reflection [i.e. being and essence, being and positedness] in which being is in
and for itself only in so far as it is no less reflection or positedness, and positedness is no
less being that is in and for itself. This abstract result [the quick and short definition of the
Notion] is elucidated by the exposition of its concrete genesis; that exposition [the real
definition of the Notion: the logic of substance, and in the last analysis the whole of the
logic of being and the logic of essence] contains the nature of the Notion whose treatment
it must have preceded.
What pure thinking does in grasping the Notion (i.e. the positing of the Notion) must be
part of (in fact all of) the content (i.e. the being in and for itself) of the Notion. Nothing is
hidden anymore in the Notion, it is totally transparent for itself (for the pure thinking which
it itself is). There is no opaque grinding mill (opaque negativity) anymore. The mill so to
speak now results from its own grinding activity. It is the ground output of its own activity.
In and with essence, the negative existed only as negated (no simple immediacy anymore).
The mill of negation ran free, using as input only its own output, but it still had being in and
for itself which was not yet as well posited (the mill was simply there, grinding; though no
original, immediate corn was there to be ground).
In and with the Notion, negativity as such exists only as negated. The mill of negation now is
posited as well, i.e. it is itself the product of its own grinding (negating). But if negativity as
such is now only as negated, it will have lost its sting (the sting of antinomy and self-destruction) and be domesticated. Alls well that ends well.
-- -- -From quantity to essence through measure
We know from SoL that quantum is something, therefore alterable and finite. We know
(from EncL and SoL) that intensive quantum (degree) is indifferent toward itself.
Qua finite something the quantum alters, and qua degree it is indifferent to this alteration
and always stays the same: quantum. In EncL 104 Hegel says:
In this contradiction: that the independent (i.e. being-for-self) indifferent limit is absolute externality, the infinite quantitative progress is posited an immediacy which
immediately veers round into its opposite, into mediatedness (the passing beyond the
quantum just posited), and vice versa.
Number is a thought, but thought as a being which is completely external to itself. []
The quantitative infinite progress goes to infinity in both directions: toward the infinitely
large in counting and toward the infinitely small (the infinitesimal) in dividing the continuum. And it never reaches its beyond, i.e. quality as such.
That is an interesting point. The beyond of the quantitative infinite progress could nowadays
be thought of, prima facie, as a transfinite number. So, Aleph0 is the smallest non-finite cardinal number and the smallest non-finite ordinal number (limit number). But if set theory
thus might be taken to have shown that the beyond of the quantitative progress is still a quantum, it has on the other hand shown as well that in reality this is not the case, because the
progress just continues in the transfinite. The true beyond, in which the progress would have
come to a halt, can only be quality.
68
And in fact we have here already a union of quantity and quality: To have its own internality
(being-for-self) in sheer externality is already quality: the quality of quantum.
In Hegels word (EncL 105, translated by W. Wallace, with my commentaries):
That the Quantum in its independent character [in its being-for-self determinateness] is
external to itself, is what constitutes its quality. In this externality it is itself and referred connectively [related] to itself. There is a union in it of externality, i.e. the quantitative, and of independency (Being-for-self), the qualitative. The Quantum when
explicitly put [i.e. posited] thus in its own self, is the Quantitative Ratio [or quantitative relation: Verhltnis], a mode of being [a determinateness] which, while in its
Exponent [as exponent of the ratio/relation], it is an immediate quantum [cf. p in the
function: x = py], is also mediation, viz. the reference [relation, Beziehung] of
some one quantum to another, forming the two sides of the ratio. But the two quanta
are not reckoned at their immediate value: their value is only in this relation.
And 106 says:
The two sides of the ratio are still immediate quanta: and the qualitative and quantitative characteristics [determination(s)] still external to one another. But in their truth,
seeing that the quantitative itself in its externality is relation to self, or seeing that the
independence [being-for-self] and the indifference of the character [of determinateness] are combined [united], it is Measure.
I wont go through the details of the three variants of quantitative ratio:
the direct ratio
the indirect ratio
the ratio of powers
y = px
y = 1/x
y = x2
Suffice it to say that in the ratio of powers the quantum, x, determines itself: x times x, in its
own externality. So Hegel can say:
But in the ratio of powers, quantum is present in the difference as its own difference
from itself. [It is not only different from itself but is now itself its very difference from
itself!] The externality of the determinateness is [has always been] the quality of quantum and this externality is now posited in conformity with the Notion of quantum, as
the latters own self-determining, as its relation to its own self, as its quality. (SoL
323 t)
The point is that the externality as such has at last turned out as the internality, i.e. as the quality, of quantum.
-- -- -Pure thinking at the OL level has now gone full circle: from quality to quantity and back to
quality. From one inconsistency to another and back to the first. From the frying pan into the
fire and back into the frying pan. And this could go on forever in a new infinite progress.
What will happen next is that the circle, which is there for us, in BL, and in which pure thinking is caught at the OL level, will have to become a unitary OL urstate for pure thinking itself.
But first, this new unitary urstate is there for pure thinking only as the immediate unity of
quality and quantity in which its inconsistency is well hidden: this is measure. (Abstractly
expressed, in measure quality and quantity are united. SoL 327 t. At first, as an immediate
measure it is an immediate quantum, hence just some specific quantum or other; equally immediate is the quality belonging to it, some specific quality or other. 333)
69
In the Minor Logic, measure is treated very briefly. First, we have immediate measure, a
quantum to which a quality is attached (e.g. a foot, for measuring length).
To this immediate unity of quality and quantity there corresponds the immediacy of their
difference (for, of course, they are different as well): We get specific quantum which is a
rule one might even say: a rule of thumb: we know roughly how large a garden must be in
order to be neither just a patch or bed nor a whole park, but a garden, justly so-called. The
(specific) quantum qua bare quantum may be diminished or increased without measure
thereby being set aside or the rule being violated. Thus, you may turn part of your garden into
a car port or buy your neighbours garden and add it to your own without thereby ceasing to
have a garden. But of course, if you go on diminishing or increasing the area of your garden,
you will finally wind up with a patch or a park respectively.
Beyond the measure we will hit upon the measureless. But the measureless of x is the measure of y. Thus, the measureless of your garden may be the measure of your park. This selfabrogation and restoration of measure in the measureless (EncL 109) can be imagined as
an infinite progress, an infinite nodal line of measure relations (SoL 366) again. (In nature,
each nodal line will of course be finite, cf. e.g. the two nodes at 32F and 212F, as regards
the aggregate state of water.)
The immediacy of the unity of quantity and quality is now sublated (EncL 110): But
measure shows itself as sublating itself into the measureless. However, on the other hand it is
only going together with itself in the measureless, which is the negation of measure but itself
unity of quantity and quality.
This then is the point at which pure thinking at the OL level catches up with our BL thinking
in uniting quantity and quality into one dynamic, self-mediated urstate. The oscillation between quantity and quality which threatened as an infinite progress for us (in BL) is now present, as an oscillation between the specific measure and the measureless, at the OL level. So,
again we have here a transition of the kind we know from the case of the infinite progress of
the finite and the bad infinite into the true infinite. In Hegels words ( 111):
The infinite, which is affirmation as a negation of negation, now has quality and quantity
as its factors [sides] instead of the more abstract factors [sides], being and nothing, something and other etc.
Measure thus gets aligned with becoming, alteration, the infinite, as a dynamic unity of two
factors each of which is inconsistent and gives way to its counterpart.
But there is here no way anymore for a collapse into a stable, affirmative unity. The whole
sphere of being is now compressed into a single urstate being, which is a substrate of two
states (purely external qualities), quality and quantity, both of which are self-destructive and,
through the negation of every determinateness of being, turn being into absolute indifference, a purely negative and inconsistent simple unity (SoL 375).
Being was abstract indifference at the beginning of the logic qua result of our abstracting
from all possible differences. Now this same indifference is reached as a result of beings own
abstracting from all internal differences in its internal inconsistency. This is why the indifference is now called absolute: it is internal to being itself, self-induced.
And there is no way here to save the situation by pleading indexicality. This move has been
used up with becoming and alteration and has in the event turned out not to be of lasting success. So, the inconsistency is there to stay, forever, destroying all internal structure. The enterprise of the presuppositionless theory has finally ended in shipwreck. So whole logic of
being is sublated in shipwreck (called absolute indifference)! Or so it seems.
-- -- --
70
Now, what remains of the logic of being is absolute negativity, negation without any affirmative, immediate input. This result is merely the product of the external reflection of the
subjective thinker (SoL 384 t), and if that were all, our project would indeed be in ruins.
But of course Hegel wants to turn that result into something helpful which we can work with.
Pure thinking itself must somehow come into the position of rising above its shipwreck and of
making its shipwreck its new content.
But I think that at the end of the logic of being, there is no other way than that the theoretician intervenes and sets the derailed logical train on the tracks again or, better still, finds
new tracks to continue the journey. That is what makes the transition from being to essence
such a big thing after all.
-- -- -Considerations at the end of the tracks of being:
(1) Being was to be grasped by thinking, in an act of pure intellectual intuition, as something immediately given. We now see that being is everlasting self-destruction without any profile (structure, determination, distinction, difference). Thus, we in BL may
conceive of a negation of being, stipulating at the same time that it is not of its (i.e. beings) ilk. We must be careful, for being itself is already the negation (and destruction)
of being, so we must devise something sufficiently new.
(2) So the new urstate which is to negate being might be conceived as an urstate which is
not graspable as something immediately given by pure thinking but as hiding behind
the immediately graspable. What is hiding behind the phenomena as something deeper
and more real, is usually called their essence. Thus, the essence of manifest water is a
theoretical (and as such unobservable) entity called H2O.
(3) So, we might dub the looked for new logical urstate essence and stipulate (i) that it
is the negation of being as a whole, but (ii) a new, essence-like, hitherto unknown
kind of negation, and (iii) nonetheless a negation that arises out of the antinomy of
being itself (and not totally unconnected to it), so that pure thinking will be somehow
be able to get from the tracks of being onto the tracks of essence.
(4) Now, if we dubbed the unknown other of antinomious being essence, then being
will be non-essence, or the unessential. But of course, we dont want the new urstate
essence to fall back into the relation of something and an other. At first it does, for
lack of profile of the new negation, and thus we get the opposition of the essential and
the unessential. This is the beginning of the logic of essence (chapter 1, on shine,
section A, pp. 394-5).
(5) But we know that the opposition of the essential and the unessential cannot be it; its
content (essence) does not fit into its form (d-being). Of course, we could go deeper
into the logic of being: Had not the infinite fallen back into the opposition of something and an other as well, and had the solution not been idealization, i.e. the sublation of the finite and the bad infinite and then the transition to being-for-self. But in
being-for-self, the urstate and its sublated moment, i.e. being-for self and being-forone, were identical, and we dont want to be essence and antinomious being to be
identical. That would be a fixation of the antinomy. (And besides we know that beingfor-self will lead through quantity and measure into the antinomy anyway.)
(6) So, we need something totally new. The new urstate essence lies behind or well hidden within antinomious being which in turn is no real other for essence but only its
null and invalid foreground. We in BL must sever the pure thinking of antinomious
being from any (objective) truth claim. But what remains of a content of thinking if
71
severed from objective truth claims is called a mere seeming, mere appearance, or, as
I shall say in order to mimick Hegels German, a mere shine. So, we have at least a
name for what has remained of being, in relation to the new urstate essence: shine
(illusory being in Millers translation, but shine need not be illusory, it may as well
be treated for what it is, and then no illusion is attached to it).
(7) So, being in its everlasting antinomy is shine, and its global negation is essence. Shine
in its total invalidity and nullity cannot stand in any real opposition to essence. It is
strictly nothing (writ small) in relation to essence. All there is to it must somehow
come from essence itself. (So there is a sense in which shine is identical with essence
after all, but we must be careful not to say that shine is essence, full stop; nothing
could be further from the truth.)
(8) So, pure thinking grasps shine but it must mean something else (but care must be
taken not to interpret this along the lines of d-being) behind shine, called essence.
Thus, pure thinking goes representational! Shine is a sign, a sma, in Greek. The
dimension of semantics is thus opened up before our very eyes. (But Hegel does not
comment on it; the importance of semantics for first philosophy became clear only
decades later, with Frege, Russell and Wittgenstein.)
(9) In shine, pure thinking is totally closed within itself and severed from any real urstate.
The window it is trying to look through is here in fact a mirror. It gets reflected to itself, and thats it. Want some more metaphors? Here we go. If pure thinking could
walk, in shine it would persistently stumble over its own feet. In shine, it is completely
entangled with itself. There is no transcending to any outside, to the real and objective (not: any more, but: not yet, because in the sphere of being, we were still completely beyond the duality of the subjective and the objective; now this duality announces itself from far away, but that is all for the time being).
(10)
Shine is not essence, shine points to (signifies, designates) essence as to its
hidden source. Shine is the shining of itself within itself of (the otherwise hidden)
essence.
(11)
Again we may employ our formula for the negation-of-itself: ~(~(~())),
and at the analogy with non-well-founded sets, especially with the unit set of itself,
, which is such that thus = {} = {{}} = {{{}}}. This formula is now to be
interpreted without any reference to immediate being. It now stands not only for selfrelated negation but also for absolute negation. That means we dont use any immediate clue for interpreting it anymore.
(12)
Nevertheless, we can interpret the outer negation sign as standing for the negation of shine, thus:
essence ~(~(~())) ~(shine).
But then shine has the same internal structure as essence and is indeed identified with
essence, save the fact that it gets negated one more time, by essence. Thus, essence
negates itself and is called essence qua negating and shine qua negated by us in
our external BL reflection. Surely an inconsistent situation again.
(13)
The inconsistency of essence is, of course, vital for any logical progress. On
the other hand, it must not be so overwhelming as to block any progress. It will be
posited in the essentiality (determination of reflection) of contradiction. But first it
should stay in the background. We come from the open inconsistency of being and
need a way out of inconsistency (not a way in).
(14)
So we do two things. (i) We say that essence is not cognitively accessible for
pure thinking (yet) and all pure thinking has is shine, which is indeed inconsistent, be-
72
ing that which is left over from being. This makes room for a little bit of logical structure of shine after all, to be considered in sections B. Illusory Being and C. Reflection.
(15)
(ii) We then do what we always do with the formula of self-negation: take its
negation signs in pairs to get self-affirmation and then add (to correct this onesidedness) the formula once again, but this time as it were with an uneven number of
negation signs, so that one outer negation is left over. This gives us the formulae
[unfounded affirmation] and ~[unfounded affirmation] respectively as two
equally valid formulae of essence.
(16)
The first formula depicts essence as identity, the second formula depicts essence as the negative thereof, difference. Identity and difference are called essentialities or determinations of reflection by Hegel, but first and foremost each of them is
the whole of essence. They are determinations of reflection only in so far as each
shines in the other one, thereby betraying its own one-sideness. Qua determinations
of reflection they articulate the logical structure of shine (the topic of chapter 1, sections B and C).
-- -- -Our next task will be to say something about the internal structure of shine (positing, external and determining reflection) and then something about the determinations of reflection
(identity, difference, contradiction and ground).
-- -- --
73
31-Mar 09
Rough program for the rest of the semester
7-Apr 09
14-Apr 09
21-Apr 09 (?)
28-Apr 09
74
Sein
Nichts
Werden
Positives (Identitt) Negatives (Differenz) Grund
Dasein
Existenz
That is a bit amazing. Either the Logic of essence is paralleled to the entire logic of
being; then we would have: (1) quality/reflection, (2) quantity/appearance, (3) measure/actuality. Or we have a parallel here between the logic of quality and the logic of
essence: (1) being etc./reflection, (2) finite d-being/existence & appearance, (3) infinity & being-for-self/actuality.
-- -- -Chapter 1
A
B
C
Shine
The Essential and the Unessential [already treated, shortly]
Shine
Reflection, (a) positing, (b) external, (c) determining reflection
[Shine] is the same thing as reflection; but it is reflection as immediate, while reflection is
shine made foreign or estranged from its immediacy (399 m; therefore we use homely
Saxon shine and foreign Latin reflection respectively).
How then are we to understand shine/reflection? It is what comes back from a surface onto
which some light shine. (So, shine may go two ways: to and from the surface, while reflection
comes only one way. But as shine is supposed to be the same as reflection, we are presumably
supposed to abstract from its to-direction as well.)
[Shine] is all that remains from the sphere of being. (395 b) Shine is the immediate successor of the unessential: the unessential stripped of its being. Note regarding the method: To
come into the sphere of essence, one has to start working with essence-fallen-back-into-dbeing: the essential and the unessential. So, the unessential, the putative other of essence,
minus being is shine.
Shine is reflected immediacy (396 t): only there in the coming back from (nothing).
There is no immediate surface (no other) from which it could come back; shine is the nonself-subsistent which is only in its negation. (ibid.) Hegel says that shine is the phenomenon of scepticism and that the Appearance of idealism, too, is such an immediacy, which is
not a something or a thing (ibid).
This immediacy then is not present in shine, but only presupposed as a side that is independent of essence (397 m/t). But shine is nothing apart from essence, and so, in fact, the moments of shine are thus the moments of essence itself. (397 b) Shine is to be fully internalized to essence itself. As such it is reflection.
-- -- -The metaphor of the mill grinding (running) free, without input, but generating an output
nonetheless which can ex post be presupposed as the original (but in fact: imaginary) input, is
becoming relevant now, with the operation of the mill standing for the operation of negation:
Becoming in essence is the movement of nothing to nothing, and so back to itself. [] Being
[in the sphere of essence] is only as the movement of nothing to nothing, and as such it is essence; and the latter [] is this movement [as absolute shine itself], pure negativity, outside
of which there is nothing for it to negate but which negates only its own negative, which latter
is only in this negating. (400 t) That means that essence qua operation (becoming, transition) is absolute shine, creating or, better, positing what is getting negated in the act of negation itself. This pure absolute reflection that is the movement from nothing to nothing determines itself further. (Ibid.) It is positing, external and determining reflection.
75
-- -- -Positing, in the course of the logic, was the making explicit (or giving d-being to) what was
there in itself, in principle, implicitly. Now this diachronic logical movement (BL movement)
is turned into an OL content as positing reflection.
Positing is not stipulating, postulating, inventing, creating. Positing has to be true to the
facts, it is bound by what is there already, in itself. The acorn cannot be posited into a palm
tree, nor the coconut into an oak tree.
According to colour realism (Qualia aint in the head, Michael Tye), colours are a physical
reality, something like surface reflectances. So, a pink ice cube is pink even if stored in the
dark of a freezer. But it is pink there only in itself (or in principle); the pink is not posited in
the freezer. It gets posited in and by (day) light. Daylight is true to the colour facts: pink
things look pink and green things look green (etc.) in daylight.
So, the real, i.e. phenomenal, visible, pink is there only in the coming back (in the reflection) of the light from the in-principle-pink surface (white light goes to the in-principle-pink
surface, and pink light comes back from it).The important thing to see is that phenomenal
colours are there (have being-there, Dasein, d-being) only in their being posited. So, being
posited, positedness, is the (essence-logical) successor and equivalent of (being-logical) dbeing. In the sphere of essence, positedness corresponds to determinate being. (406 m/t)
Determinate being is merely posited being or positedness; this is the proposition of essence
about determinate being. (406 m, positedness is the middle term between d-being and essence.)
But here, in the interchange of the negative with itself, we have the absolute reflection of
essence (400 m), not the relative reflection of light form some surface. Essence, that is, is
reflecting surface, light source, and reflected light all in one. So, in the absolute reflection of
essence, even that from which the (seemingly relative) reflection comes back has to be posited, but posited as an in itself (i.e. as not posited). This positing or setting (Setzen) which is
a setting as not set is a fore-out-setting (Voraussetzen, the German word for presuppose):
pre-positing, i.e. presupposing.
The positing reflection of essence is thus a presupposing (401 m), a positing as not posited.
But to what fact(s) could one still be true in positing the in-itself? (And nevertheless, e.g., in
Kants transcendental philosophy the thing in itself gets posited.) The only fact around, in the
absolute reflection of essence, to be true to is absolute negation: the mill of negation running
free. The grinding of this mill is the positing of the output (the ground corn, i.e. the negated
being) which is as it should be; but (which is highly strange) it is ipso facto as well the positing of the input, more specifically, the positing of the input as not posited (but as given as an
in-itself).
-- -- External reflection would be reflection with respect to the in-itself; it could therefore not
truly reach its subject matter (the in-itself) in positing this or that. But if the absolute reflection of essence posits its own input as not-posited, then by that very same token it is turned
into external reflection with respect to that input as an in-itself.
This is (by the way) how we pre-theoretically interpret perception: as mere receptivity which
leaves the things perceived (received) as they are, i.e. we conceive perception as external
reflection (and only on closer theoretical inspection do we begin to conceive it as a positing of
what is there in principle). More generally speaking, external reflection is the totality of our
cognitive acts and states standing over against the object to be cognized. So, we have the infinite reflection of subjectivity on one side and the thing in itself on the other side, the latter
76
the immediate and the former the reflection-into-self which stands over against it (403;
cf. the whole page):
This external reflection is the syllogism in which there are two extremes, the immediate and reflection-into-self; the middle term of the syllogism is the connection of the
two, the determinate immediate [the thing in itself as cognized, determined, determinate], so that one part of the middle term, immediacy, belongs only to one of the extremes, determinateness or negation, belongs only to the other extreme. (403) [So,
there really is no valid syllogism here to be found, but rather a quaternio terminorum:
Banks are for sitting. Wachovia is a bank. So, Wachovia is for sitting. Subjectivity
wont come together with the thing in itself, because there is no unique middle term to
unite them.]
But a closer consideration of the action of external reflection shows it to be secondly,
a positing of the immediate [that is so in the absolute negation which is essence: the
immediate input into the operation of negation has to be posited, otherwise it would
not be there at all], which consequently becomes the negative or determinate [it gets
negated, qua input, and is the other of the output]; but external reflection is immediately also the sublating of this its positing; for it presupposes the immediate [positing
reflection, we know, is presupposing reflection]; in negating [the input] it is the negating of this its negating [the input is as well there to stay and in fact the same as the
output]. [And so the in-itself and external reflection come together after all:] But in doing so it is immediately equally a positing, a sublating of the immediate negatively related to it [in the phenomenal colours the seen surface is not immediate anymore but
interferes with vision, vision has sublated the immediate in it], and this immediate
from which it seemed to start as from something alien [the surface as such is alien to
vision], is only in this its beginning [the surface qua phenomenally coloured is only in
the reflection of light from it to the eye]. In this way, the immediate is not only in itself
[in principle, for us in BL] [] identical with reflection, but this identicalness is posited. [] The fact is, therefore, that external reflection is not external, but is no less
the immanent reflection of immediacy itself; in other words, the outcome [or output]
of positing reflection is essence in and for itself. Reflection is thus determining reflection. [Essence is the input and the output of absolute negation.] (403f.)
-- -- -As determining reflection, subjectivity, thinking, reason is seen as powerful: as the internal
movement of the thing in itself (better: the absolute; cf. the saying, in the introduction to the
Phenomenology, that the absolute wants to be with us.) What we in our external BL reflection did, when we went from being to essence, must be seen as the internal movement of essence itself (cf. 405f.).
I said that pure being, at the frontline of essence, grasps only shine, but that it must mean
something else, essence, which is hidden and thus gets only signified (not grasped), but
which cannot really be something else (the essential over against the unessential shine) either.
Now, shine is reflection, and pure thinking qua grasping shine, is the act of reflecting. In its
reflecting it has to posit essence as its referent, but it remains external to its referent, thus
external reflection. But all of logical space is now essence; so there is nothing here but essence. Therefore, reflection, even the external reflection (in which shine only signifies essence
which remains hidden), must be the internal movement of essence itself, thus internal, determining reflection. And the aspects of this reflection must be aspects or moments of essence
itself: essentialities or determinations of reflection.
77
Reflection first is positing: making visible what is there implicitly, but (naively conceived as)
making visible what is already there in itself in exactly the same manner (cf. nave colour realism), thus presupposing (positing as not posited) what is posited. But then reflection is in
fact external, not reaching its object (the phase of scepticism that follows nave realism). But
with the absolute negation (of essence) input and output are the same (and still two): One and
the same reflection repels itself from itself (406 b) and is there on both sides, the side of the
input and the side of the output. This is called absolute presupposing (ibid.), because the
presupposed is in no way other than the presupposing.
Consequently, positedness is, as such, negation [privation, lack of reality, negatedness]; but,
as presupposed, it is [not only the negated input, but] also reflected into itself. Positedness is
thus a determination of reflection. (Ibid.) Negated and at the same time reflected into itself,
thus affirmed-by-itself: that is the repulsion of reflection from itself, into two determinations of reflection, which are the same and yet one the negative of the other. Each of them is
reflected into itself, thus the whole of essence, and each has the other as its identical! opposite.
By virtue of this reflection-into-self the determinations of reflection appear as free essentialities floating in the void without attracting or repelling one another. (407 m) We have here
only the original repulsion (but it is not there to stay, when it has done its work). Each of
them, qua posited by the other, is at the same time sublated, but qua reflected into self, both
are self-subsistent and are infinite self-relation (408).
-- -- -These essentialities are identity and difference, to begin with. (In A. Identity, pp. 411f., it
seems that Miller has got the disposition wrong: one 2. (411) too many! Remark 1 ends at
412 b., and then comes Nr. 2. of the main text, including the transition to difference (413),
which would otherwise be part of remark 1.)
In fact, Nr. 2 on p. 412 is extremely important: This identity is [] essence itself, not yet a
determination of it, reflection in its entirety, not a distinct moment of it. As absolute negation
it is the negation that immediately negates itself [] Etc. What is present, therefore, is selfrelated, reflected difference, or pure, absolute difference. (413) And only now do we have
two determinations of reflection and two images of essence as a whole.
-- -- --
78
7-Apr 09
Today: The logic of essence in a survey.
Essence, at first, qua pure reflection, is identity, according to the formula ~~(~~(~~())),
where negation is bent back into affirmation: unfounded and therefore absolute affirmation.
The affirmation is mediated through double negation, therefore identity includes negation and
is in principle as well negation. So, it has its negative difference as its moment, as well
as itself. [The infinite formula of identity includes itself (many times) as well as the formula
of difference (again many times), which is the same formula with only the imaginary difference that the number of negation signs is imagined as uneven.]
Difference, on the other hand, includes identity and itself as its moments and is, like identity,
the whole of essence, qua absolute difference.
Identity and difference are usually defined as second floor predicates with respect to first floor
predicates: x = y iff (f)(fx iff fy) (with the predicate variable f ranging over first floor
predicates). But here, in the logic of essence, they get an absolute, i.e. totally unfounded expression. Reflection is pure and absolute, not guided by first floor predicates (i.e. not guided
by the logic of being anymore).
We, in BL, see that essence is identity as well as difference. Pure thinking at the OL level
either conceives of essence as identity or, alternatively, as difference. But the situation has
changed since the logic of being, especially of d-being. When pure thinking grasped something, it at the same time negated and sublated the other, which, though, persisted outside of
this act of pure thinking in the logical space of d-being (for us, in BL). Pure thinking never
had the whole, dichotomous logical space of d-being in view but was always lost in one side
of it. The nearest it came to having it all in view was in grasping the limit and then the finite
(i.e. the something with its limit). But the limit wasnt concrete dichotomous logical space but
at best represented it. Now, in grasping identity, pure thinking (i) negates and sublates
(posits) difference and (ii) at the same time presupposes (pre-posits) it, as a self-subsistent urstate (and vice versa: in grasping difference it presupposes identity).
We see now why it might have been important that Hegel first talked about reflection (positing and presupposing, external, determining). In the sphere of essence, pure thinking has acquired a new relationship to logical urstates: it can grasp them as before, but not only that, it
can as well presuppose them, ungrasped. This is a major step towards propositionality already, for propositions can be presupposed (without being explicitly grasped) as well. (But the
difference between affirming and only grasping a proposition or between grasping a true and
grasping a false proposition has not yet been provided for.)
-- -- -LE 30 (EncL):
Essence as Ground of Existence
--a. The Pure Determinations of Reflection
) Identity
) Difference
LE 13 (SoL):
79
b. Existence
c. The Thing
(We have talked about identity and absolute difference. Next comes diversity.)
-- -- -With positedness, presupposition, difference not only a prerequisite of propositionality is
realized, but (not surprisingly) at the same time a prerequisite the objectivity/subjectivity
distinction. (There is something over there, different from this my act of positing it.)
In the sphere of being, determinations were qualitative, but though quality was rooted in relation and negation, the relation was not grasped by pure thinking. Now, in the sphere of essence, pure thinking grasps negation (and determination) qua relation, difference, positedness, mediatedness. The determinations of reflection are (as such) reflected into themselves
and thus not merely dependent determinations as in the sphere of being, but at the same time
self-subsistent, and presupposed as such.
In diversity, this becomes obvious (posited, I would say, but Hegel does not say so). Identity includes itself and difference as its moments, but as these moments are as well reflected
into themselves and therefore self-subsistent, identity falls as well apart (SoL 418 m) into its
moments and pure thinking grasps the dichotomous logical space which comes out of this
falling apart as a new form of difference, viz. diversity. Its parts are, of course, identity and
difference (i.e. diversity itself), which can now be compared, not only by us in BL, but (inarticulately) by pure thinking in OL (which just is their comparison). As compared, they are
either like or unlike each other (either equal or unequal). So, likeness and unlikeness are the
posited version of diversity which in turn is their in-itself base (as the phenomenal colours are
the posited version of physical surface reflectances which provide their in-itself base).
But the indifferent sides of diversity are just as much simply and solely moments of one
negative unity, called opposition (421 b). Likeness and unlikeness, reflected (from their
positedness) into themselves, are the determinations of opposition (424 m): the positive and
the negative. Taken (i) together as well as taken (ii) in isolation in their respective selfsubsistence, these are (and each of them is, EncL 120) the posited contradiction (SoL
431 b).
Now, the inconsistency of essence (i.e. of absolute negation) has finally taken over logical
space. Again, all structure is demolished, as the sides of the contradiction fall (or, in German,
go) to the ground. Essence now is explicitly was it has been all the time: the unity (and
totality) of essence in its dual shape, with identity and difference as its two aspects; and so
the inconsistency, which was suppressed in the separation of these aspects, is back again.
The ground is the unity of identity and difference [] It is essence posited as totality.
(EncL 121). The formula of absolute negation, ~~~, finally taken at face value in its
strict inconsistency, is thus the formula of the ground a black hole (and at the same time
whole or totality oh, the unsung speculative power of the English language!), in which all
structure is crunched. So the logic of reflection ends in a black hole, called ground, and
gives way to black hole logic.
For, surprisingly, there is some structure in a black hole as well, quite a lot of structure according to LE 13, though very little structure (or none at all) according to LE 30. Not only the
logic of hylomorphism: essence as (a) form, (b) form and matter, (c) form and content, but
also parts of the logic of modality and causality are put into the 1813 ground chapter, while
in 1830 ground is only that from which existence arises, as a new form of being: In the
ground, essence has sublated difference and mediation and thus restored immediacy or being.
But the essence-like being, existence, is mediated through the sublation of mediation (EncL
122).
80
Existence existent = thing. Cf. Dasein Daseiendes = Etwas // Frsichsein Frsichseiendes = Eins // Existenz Existierendes = Ding.
With respect to the category (the reflexive, essential category) of thing, Hegel then develops the following subject matters (according to LE 30):
Existence is the immediate unity of reflection-into-self and reflection-into-another, therefore an indefinite manifold of existents, which are reflected into themselves, but at the same
time are shining into one another and constituting a world of mutual dependencies, of
grounds and grounded(s), where the grounds are themselves existents (EncL 123).
But since each existent at the same time contains its dependencies at (or on or within) itself
and is reflected into itself as ground, it is a thing. (Thing is the Germanic word for (i) the
assembly of the free to decide public matters, then (ii) for the matters or affairs to be talked
about, (iii) then for any more or less substantive item whatsoever; cf. Heidegger on thing. A
thing essentially does some assembling.) (124)
A thing therefore has its reflection-into-another at (on, within) itself: its properties, which
in turn have their reflection-into-self at/on/within the thing ( 125). But qua existents (though
not things, properties thus weaken the equation of existents and things a bit) even the properties are unities of reflection-into-self and reflection-into-another, therefore they are on the
other hand as well freed from their allegiance to the thing and are abstract determinatenesses:
matters ( 128). [Here the concept of matter(s) enters the scene. More about it later.]
So here we find the dialectic of things qua bare particulars having (not being) properties
and then of things qua bundles of free, self-subsistent universals (matters), which was previously developed in chapter 2, on perception, of the Phenomenology (chapter 1, on sense
certainty, seems to correspond to the whole logic of being, chapter 3, on the understanding, to
the section appearance, and chapter 4, on self-consciousness, to the logic of the notion
very roughly speaking). This dialectic will eventually ( 130) lead to the self-sublation within
itself of the thing, by which it is degraded to appearance.
On the way to this self-sublation, Hegel in LE 30 develops the logic of hylomorphism (which
he had put in the chapter on ground in 1813): The matters got together into the One matter
(prime matter), 128, and the thing then falls apart into matter and form, 129, which leads
to the contradiction within the thing which in turn leads to the aforementioned self-sublation.
[More on matter and form below.]
-- -- -Section Two (or B): Appearance
The thing as such is neutral with respect to the question: Appearance or reality/in-itself? So,
in the Phenomenology, the thing is the object of simple perception which just takes in the
perceptible universals. Now with appearance, we get the distinction between the inner and the
outer and therefore a job for the understanding which is: to penetrate to the unperceivable
inside of or behind things, to the forces that are at work in the perceivable processes. Thus
Platonic forms as well as the modern conception of laws of force and mass are treated in
chapter 3 of the Phenomenology under the heading Force and Understanding. (But, of
course, we are here not in the Phenomenology; we are in the Logic, and so consciousness and
its cognitive faculties are not our subject matter.)
What gets treated in the present section are: a. The World of Appearance, b. Content and
Form, c. The (Essential) Relation.
Matter, in the context of hylomorphism, was responsible for the subsistence of things and
was the totality of the thing no less than the form was that totality ( 129). Now, in the context
81
of appearance, matter is sublated and only one of the determinations of form: The appearances dont subsist in the full sense anymore but are dependent aspects of an (open, I would
like to add, and unfounded) totality: the world of appearance ( 132).
In LE 13, Hegel discusses appearance under the three headings The Law of Appearance
(A), The World of Appearance and the World-in-itself (B), Dissolution of Appearance
(C). In LE 30, the relation of content and form takes the place of these subject matters: It is
the form which, qua content (and content in turn is as well form), is the law of appearance
( 133). (I still postpone the treatment of matter, form and content one more time.)
-- -- -Only for appearances, not for things in themselves, can there be laws of nature. Naturalism
tends to be insincere on this point. E.g. as against the navet of present day creationists the
naturalist will rightly point out that the forms of life we observe on earth are fully explainable
by a (mathematically necessary) statistical trend, given the fundamental biological or,
should biology be reducible to physics, physical laws.
But now let a (nave, pre-critical) metaphysician enter the scene, addressing the naturalist:
Oh, what happened to you? Remember last week when I tried to convince you that there are,
and must be, natural laws, i.e. modalities in rebus? You just wouldnt believe it and kept insisting that its all just regularities with no modal force whatsoever. And today you are talking to this funny guy who thinks that God is permanently interfering with nature, and though
he has not produced a single convincing argument, you convert to my metaphysical position?
And the creationist chimes in: How absurd to believe there are, or even could be, laws of
nature! I am totally in line with what my friend, the naturalist, seems to have said to you on
this issue last week. Its just regularities. But of course, the regularities we observe stand in
need of explanation and the only candidate explanation around is that they are freely willed
by God. If He decided, gravity would be done away with at this very moment. The metaphysician will laugh and turn away: Oh, I see the both of you guys are perfect partners in discussion; you really deserve each other!
But the metaphysician is in for a chilly shower, he as well. Turning around, he runs into an
adherent of critical (i.e. transcendental) philosophy who happened to overhear his little discussion with the naturalist and the creationist. But didnt you once tell me, he asks, that
things at least the real and substantial elements of things exist in themselves? How, then,
can they be essentially related and bound together by laws? If anything is a distinct entity,
then, clearly, a thing in itself is.
What will Hegel say? He will point out that the transcendentalist is right in so far as laws (of
nature) go together with appearances and appearances only. But he will add that the naturalist, the metaphysician and the transcendentalist are all doing bad metaphysics or, more to the
point, that reality itself is doing bad metaphysics in developing different logical layers which
then find their spokesmen in the naturalist, the metaphysician and the transcendentalist respectively. (And the creationist? Is he into mad metaphysics? If so, his position could, with a
little help of some sophisticated metaphysical friends, be easily turned into a metaphysical
theory which meets professional standards, i.e. into another piece of bad metaphysics.)
-- -- -Matter, Form, Content, Absolute Form
The (essential) relation is characterized by the identity of what stands in it. In LE 13, we have
the duplication of the world as world of appearance and world in itself (which mirror each
other perfectly), and in LE 30, we have content (the world qua manifold of appearances) and
82
form (the world qua unitary law of appearance) as the identical material to be distributed to
the two sides of the essential relation.
Now, in order better to understand what is going on in the essential relation, let us go back
and survey the logical development of form, first in its relation to matter and then in its relation to content.
Matter is introduced (in EncL) with respect to the thing, in the plural first: the properties,
bound in the thing, are as well self-subsistent matters (and are, by the way, treated as such in
contemporary theories of universals) out of which the thing consists, they are its subsistence
( 127). Plurality is characteristic in the realm of existence: The existents are indefinitely
many ( 123), and the thing has indefinitely many properties, which in turn are many matters.
The singular corresponding to this plural is the said subsistence of the thing: the numerous
matters coalesce into the one matter (128). We need plurality and singularity, and if the
matters are all there is to a thing, they have to provide for singularity. The differences that
ground and found plurality are then attributable to another element, over against matter: form.
Existence
Existence
is matter.
is form.
This then is hylomorphism: the thing consists of matter and form, the matter being its subsistence, the form being responsible for all its distinctions and determinations. (So, each is the
totality of thinghood, in its respective way.)
But hylomorphism has to deal with a regress of matter that gets stopped by Aristotle with socalled prime matter, which is wholly indeterminate: potentially everything and actually nothing. But then prime matter as such can never be found anywhere, and everything we can ever
deal with is form. It is only Vorstellung (imagination, representation) and the understanding which try to fix matter before it vanishes into form, e.g. by relying on the thought content
of pure quantity as an example of matter (cf. above, ad quantitatem).
The thing, qua both: matter and form, in the vanishing of matter sublates itself into appearance. That is, hylomorphism is an instable ontology which has an inbuilt logical tendency
towards conceiving things as appearances.
With appearances, we have a primacy of form over matter: The subsistence of an appearance is sublated and is only one moment of form ( 132). [Thus, prime matter is present here
only as the spectre of the thing in itself, if at all.] Form, as the principle of plurality, develops
(posits) appearance into a whole world of appearance, to an outside one another which is
not yet space (but, of course, a logical source or core of space).
But subsistence of things (i.e. appearances) now being a moment of form, form is as well content [(pre)formed matter, so to speak] which develops into the law of appearance ( 133). The
law qua content is form reflected-into-self (form as unified); the form over against the content is reflected-into-other: outer form (form as diverse and as the source of diversity, of
contingent determinations). The world seen under the perspective of law can then be called
the world-in-itself, to be detected by (physical) science (cf. Sellarss scientific realism).
This world of appearance whose content (inner form) is the law (a finite set of fundamental
physical equations, lets say) and whose (outer) form is outer diversity (the contingent initial
conditions of the world which are inherited by later times from earlier times according to the
fundamental equations) is still free (devoid) of subjectivity and propositionality. (These go
together naturally subjects being those entities that make truth claims and truth claims being
those entities that are propositional.) But the world of appearance is pre-propositional in the
sense of being already underway to propositionality and subjectivity.
83
We needed the conception of content, because matter tended to vanish and only form was left
and we therefore needed to reproduce the form-matter-distinction within (thus absolute) form
itself. This gave us (absolute) form qua form-and-content. Form as opposed to content is
relative, one-sided form (as the bad infinite was the relative, one-sided infinite). But content
and relative form transform themselves into each other in a reciprocal revulsion ( 133),
just as the finite and the bad infinite did. And so the reflected finitude ( 132) of the world
of appearance gives way to the reflected infinity of absolute form, which is in principle there
now but which will be posited in the absolute relation ( 133) of substantiality ( 151).
But first there comes the essential relation (whole/parts, force/expression, inner/outer) and
only then the absolute relation (actuality going into the relation of necessity in substance). In
the absolute relation the relative, essential relation will be sublated into absolute identity: substance as such. It is instructive to compare substance with the law (the world-in-itself) and the
accidents with the world of appearance:
Content is substance qua substance, (outer, relative) form is substance qua accidents. These,
the accidents are no additions to substance from the outside, but are substance itself. (We first
have to speak of substance in the singular: it is the whole logical space, as in Spinozas metaphysics.) Substantiality is the absolute revulsion of form and content into one another (
151), thus absolute form.
Now the important difference is that law and outer appearances (content and outer form) are
still foreign to one another, while substance is itself the totality of accidents, their absolute
negativity (i.e. their own, not a foreign negativity) and absolute power ( 151). If the logic
ended with the outer appearances and their law, then it would be the task of physics to really
come up with a final law (final set of basic equations, a world formula or definite theory
of everything).
But then, two basic questions would forever remain open as intractable: (1) Why that law?
(2) Why those initial conditions? Ex hypothesi, physics would have to leave those questions
not only open but even unaddressed.
Substance now is supposed to hold the (indirect) answers to the two questions, since it is the
revulsion of the law and the initial conditions into one another! They kind of explain each
other in their revulsion, not in a vicious circle though, but in a circle whose vicious darkness
or opacity is in for illumination and transparency, as soon as (blind) necessity will be transformed into (rational) freedom and ipso facto substance into the Notion.
Thus, physics must always continue in laying bare successor fundamental equations of the
ones it had found in an infinite progress (bad infinity). Meanwhile on the logical level the
stage of the world of appearance and its law is left behind. And so the bad infinity of physical
successor theories is left behind as well.
-- -- -Next we have to look at the essential relation [passage (c), after (a) the world of appearance
and (b) content and form; 135-141] What has happened up to this point is in SoL, at the
opening of Section Three, Actuality (SoL 529), summarized by Hegel in the following way:
Actuality is the unity of essence and Existence; in it formless essence and unstable
Appearance, or mere subsistence devoid of all determination [i.e. prime matter] and
unstable manifoldness [the form, pace Plato and Aristotle, is here not considered as
stable], have their truth. Existence is indeed the immediacy which has proceeded from
ground, but form is as yet not posited in it [so it was wise to relocate the discussion of
form from the chapter on ground to a later part in LE 30]. In determining and forming
itself it [i.e. Existence] is Appearance; and when this subsistence which is determined
84
only as reflection-into-an-other [a world of many appearances] is developed further
into reflection-into-self [the law, the world in itself], it becomes two worlds, two totalities of the content, one of which is determined as reflected into itself [the world in itself], the other as reflected into an other [the world of appearance]. But the essential
relation [our next topic] exhibits [or is, stellt dar] their form relation [the content is
one and the same anyway, so there is no content relation; only according to the form
do we have two sides and thus a relation] [].
This essential relation (exhibiting the form relation of both worlds) is, first, the relation of
whole and parts, second of force and its expression, and third of outer and inner.
The whole is its parts (consists of its parts); the force is totally present in its expression, and
the inner is totally expressed at the outside.
The whole being its parts is an idea relevant in modern ontology from Leibniz to Russell and
the early Wittgenstein. Corporeal substance, according to Leibniz, is compound, and what is
compound must (according to all three of them) consist of simple parts. But (as Kants treatment of the antinomies shows) the conception of simple parts has its pitfalls, to say the least,
which Hegel is referring to in his remark on infinite divisibility (SoL 517f.) as well as in the
note/remark to EncL 136.
The third relation (inner/outer) is particularly interesting for discussions of the ontological and
epistemic status of inner mental states and acts. If their outer expressions in behaviour were
only contingently related to them, then there could be logically private items and therefore a
logically private language in which a person could talk to herself about her logically private
mental states and acts.
But as Wittgenstein some 120 years later, Hegel insists that the inner is necessarily (essentially) capable of getting fully expressed in outer behaviour. (There cannot be a great poet, full
of ingenious poems, who by unfavourable contingent facts always comes up with only poor
outer expressions of his inner poems.) The outer is the same content as the inner (EncL
139), and as regards the form, the inner and the outer are absolutely, i.e. emptily opposed; so
what is only inner is as well only outer, and vice versa ( 140).
141: The empty abstractions through [or by means of] which the one identical content is
forced [or supposed] to be still in the relation sublate themselves in the immediate transition
the one in the other; the content itself is nothing else but their identity. Through the expression
of force the inner is posited [put in the technical sense of positing] into existence; this positing is the mediating through empty abstractions; [therefore] it [the mediating] vanishes within
itself to the immediacy in which the inner and outer are identical in and for themselves and
their difference is determined as only positedness. This identity is actuality.
-- -- --
85
14-Apr 09
We are presently talking about the logic of essence in a short survey and have arrived at the
beginning of Section Three: Actuality.
According to our program, I will first complete the little survey (I) and then say something
about the absolute (II) and about the Notion (III).
(I) Survey Completed
The section about actuality in LE 13 contains (1) a chapter on the absolute and its (absolute)
attribute and its mode, with a remark on Spinoza and Leibniz, (2) a chapter entitled actuality, containing the logic of the modalities (actuality, possibility, contingency, necessity
relative and absolute, real and formal) and (3) a chapter on the absolute relation, containing
the logic the categories of relation (Kant), i.e. substance, causality and reciprocity.
In LE 30, Hegel starts with modality outright:
Actuality is the unity, become immediate, of essence and existence, the inner and the
outer. The expression [exteriorization] of the actual is the actual itself [] ( 142).
This is a rather high conception of the actual, which may lend some plausibility to Hegels
otherwise bewildering, infamous claim (in the introduction to the Philosophy of Right) that
the actual is rational (reason-like) and the rational is actual. There are many things in nature and in society, quite actual in a lower sense, that are not rational at all.
The lower sense of actuality is given in 144, with recourse to possibility:
But the actual in its distinction from possibility (which is reflection-into-self) is itself
only [i.e. one-sided-ly] the outer concrete, the inessential immediate. [] In this
value, of a mere possibility, the actual is a contingent/accidental, and conversely the
possible is mere accident/chance itself.
First, in 143, possibility is split from actuality as actualitys minor self, so to speak. If the
difference of the inner and the outer is re-enacted with respect to actuality, then possibility
stands for the inner (and is abstract and unessential essentiality, 143) and lower actuality (the contingently actual, the accidental) stands for the outer, while actuality (in the higher
sense) is it all:
Actuality in the full sense comprises (but not as a mere sum, it sublates as well) (a) the inner
abstract and unessential essentiality which is possibility and (b) the outer contingently actual
which is the accidental.
[The accidental, das Zufllige is the contingently actual, while the contingent (as such) is
usually defined as what is possible but not necessary, so that it cuts through the actual and the
non-actual.]
By the way: Interesting and theoretically important are Hegels remarks on possibility and
consistency (freedom of contradiction) in 143. How do we know what is possible? Well,
what is inconsistent is impossible. But what is positively possible? A standard thesis is:
What is consistent is possible. This is Hegels reaction to the standard thesis: Well, then
everything is possible, because everything can be made consistent by abstraction; and everything is impossible as well, because prior to abstraction everything is inconsistent. This
means that the question of consistency and inconsistency is the question whether we abstract
away from contradiction or not. (I think that this is basically right.)
-- -- --
86
Since actuality comprises both, possibility and accidentality (contingent actuality), the latter
are its moments ( 145). Now, Hegel says something very remarkable with respect to the
modalities, viz. that Kant may have been right to call possibility (and thus perhaps accidentality as well) a modality, because it is a mere mode or manner, but that actuality (in the full
sense) and necessity arent modalities in this sense.
So he would have to say that the usual inter-definability of possibility and necessity is a
superficial phenomenon:
(p ~~p // p ~~p).
There may be such a merely modal concept of necessity, but it clearly is not the real thing.
And he seems to be right, which can be shown quite independently of his own arguments.
Lets take a short look on some conceptions of actuality. According to David Lewiss indexical theory of actuality there is nothing intrinsically special to actuality; its just that everybody calls their own world the actual one, because this is exactly what actual means (says
Lewis).
A more substantive, less relativistic, conception of actuality would be Leibnizs theory: that
there are (in a sense) all the possible worlds, but only qua contents of Gods intellect (each
internally consistent but each inconsistent with any other, so that at most one of them may be
actual); and then there is the best of these which as such is the content of Gods morally perfect will and thus the object of His omnipotent agency. Thats what makes it actual, because
that is what actual means. (Actual means: what the omniscient, omnipotent and morally
perfect being freely chooses to create.)
But then one could reason with Leibniz against Leibniz: If there is no independent meaning
of actual according to which our world is guaranteed to be the actual one (i.e. if actual
just means created by God), then it is highly improbable that our world is the actual one, because it does by no means seem to be the best of all possible worlds. (That is, we must be
merely possible substances in Gods intellect then.)
The point is that actuality lies outside the sphere of the modally inter-definable concepts of
possibility, contingency and (weak, i.e. modal) necessity. So, one might do weak modal
logic without any appeal to actuality: The possible holds in some worlds, the contingent holds
in some worlds but not in some others, and the necessary holds in all worlds and no word
about actuality!
Something totally new enters the scene, as soon as one world is declared to be actual, in a
non-relative (absolute) sense. This, strictly speaking, goes far beyond the theory of modality.
Then even the mere modalities get a new complexion. For now, the necessary is as well actual, so it rises (infinitely!) in ontological status. And even much of the possible now is actual
as well (though this does not seem to affect possibility as such).
Anyway, if we did not already learn it from Leibniz or from David Lewis (somewhat malgr
lui) we could learn from Hegel that the theory of actuality (and strong necessity) and the
usual theory of the modalities (including weak necessity) are two pairs of boots (as one
says in German). Hegel therefore does not bother to go into the usual theory of the modalities
at all, but starts with actuality and treats the mere modalities more or less as abstractions from
actuality. What interests him, are actuality and necessity in the strong sense.
-- -- -Necessity brings life to actuality, so to speak, a moment of activity (though we have not yet
reached subjectivity): activity as the self-movement of (absolute) form ( 147). Actuality is
the immediate unity of the inner and the outer, necessity is their living, active (mediating)
87
unity. We have the totality of conditions for a certain fact (a Sache, i.e. a state of logical
space), and then the activity of form transforms the conditions into the fact. It is one and the
same content anyway; what is important is only the transferring or transforming. (If all the
individually necessary and collectively sufficient conditions of a possible state of affairs are
given, then that state will obtain as a fact. That is, the conditions will be transformed by the
activity of form, without anything further happening, into that state.)
The one content (identical in the conditions and the fact) stands for being, the activity of
form stands for reflection, i.e. essence. We have here being plus (at the same time) reflection, and this is what is characteristic of necessity: The necessary is because it is.
This may sound vacuous; but there is a real transformation here at work, from the totality of
the conditions to the fact itself. Spinozas concept of causa sui may be interpreted either in a
deflationary or in an inflationary way: either as meaning that which simply has no causal mediation (and whose necessity might therefore be as well called contingency) or as meaning
that whose real causal mediation lies in itself. Hegel obviously opts for the inflationary interpretation: Necessity is exactly that inner structure which turns substance into a causa sui.
(Here one sees that David Lewiss theory of the modalities is not a real substantive theory,
but just a nice and tidy representation of (some of) our modal intuitions. What is so specific
about the necessary that it is the case in all worlds? The theory doesnt tell. It couldnt. The
necessary just happens to be the case in all worlds (so to speak). But then it is contingent as
well, according to what we normally mean by contingent. And we could now go on and
consider super-worlds, logical galaxies, as we might call them, and so on up in an infinite
progress, as with the (finite and transfinite) cardinals.
-- -- -Substance according to Spinoza, is in itself and can be conceived through itself, and it has (as
parts/expressions of its essence) attributes (through which it is conceived) and modes (which
are its more or less contingent outer). Spinoza then proves that the singular infinite substance
is as well causa sui, which means, according to the definition of the latter, that its essence
includes its existence.(This is somewhat neutral between the inflationary and the deflationary
conception of causa sui.)
Now Hegel (1) brings the causa sui character closer to the definition of substance and makes
it part and parcel of its very substantiality, and (2) interprets it inflationarily. Thus substantiality is indeed a relation: the one absolute relation (which gives Hegel the opportunity to
go with Kants table of the categories, where substance, causality and reciprocity are listed as
the categories of relation).
Thus substance is the (absolute) relation
(1) between it qua substance and it qua totality of its accidents; then
(2) between it qua powerful first and original cause [Ur-Sache] and it qua effect, thus
between it and it as between two substances, one active, the other passive; finally
(3) between two substances who in their interaction create equal status among themselves, because the active one is like the passive one except for its very activity; it can
therefore have an effect on the passive one only in turning it into the active one and
then vice versa. Thus, the indiscernibility and thus identity of (active and passive)
substance is here actively posited by substance itself in pure reciprocity this act of
self-positing being nothing other than
the Notion!
88
(II) The Absolute
The chapter on the absolute is a kind of short version of the two chapters that follow (on actuality and the absolute relation), leading, as they do as well, from the unity of the inner and
the outer all the way to the Notion.
What is important on that way is that our external BL reflection on the absolute gets fully
interiorized, and in the end, in the logical urstate of reciprocity, everything we did and
thought at the BL level is done and thought by pure thinking on the OL level itself. In the
chapter on the absolute this process of interiorizing is considered under the heading of exposition: the absolute gets exposed, first by what we say about it, then by itself. Our reflection cannot posit or determine anything in the absolute, so our exposition must in the last
analysis be the self-exposition of the absolute and only a display [or showing] of what it is
(530 m/b), called as well manifestation.
In the manifestation nothing gets done to what is manifested (nothing is posited, i.e. made
visible, or determined in it). Or the positing here makes visible what is already visible (so to
speak). Hegels absolute has the structure of Spinozas substance:
It has, first, an attribute, which is what is conceivable of it: the whole content of the absolute, which is the totality which previously appeared [in the technical sense] as a world
(SoL 533 m/b), therefore this content (it itself) as shown in its self-exposition, which latter is
its form, or form-activity).
And it secondly has a mode, which is its externality (viz. at first as an object of our thinking about it), but then more specifically its externality posited as externality (SoL 535 t).
We have here a structure close to what Fichte says about the absolute and our knowledge or
concept(ion) of it in his later versions of the doctrine of knowledge: There is the absolute on
the one side and our conception of it on the other side. What unites them as their middle term
is called the attribute (of the absolute) by Hegel. The extremes to this middle term, of
course, are the absolute itself and its mode (SoL 534f.). So, the mode thats we, our conception of the absolute, first and pre-theoretically in our manifest image of the world (of appearance), and then in our BL (i.e. in exactly that which is being said by Hegel and interpreted
here by me), which is the negative as negative, the reflection which is external to the absolute (535 t). But BL goes far beyond the manifest image and conceives of its own externality.
So Hegel goes on (ibid.):
But mode, the externality of the absolute, is not merely this [the manifest image], but
externality posited as externality [in our BL] []. Therefore it is in the mode that the
absolute is in fact first posited as absolute identity [of the inner and the outer, of the
absolute as such and its reflection]; it is what it is, namely identity-with-self, only as
self-related negativity [our good old friend, ~(~(~())), again], as a reflective
movement [Scheinen] that is posited as reflective movement [Scheinen].
But if shining is made visible as shining (if shining is shining as shining), if the externality of
the absolute qua content of our thinking and thus our thinking as well is made visible as external, then this self-cancellation of our conception (to speak with Fichte) comes to the selfexposition or the manifestation of the absolute. Thus, Hegel can say:
Accordingly the true meaning of mode is that it is the absolutes own reflective movement, a determining; but a determining which would make it not an other but only that
which it already is [i.e. the determining here is completely cognitive, in no way manipulative anymore], [thus this determining is] the transparent externality which is the
manifestation of itself, a movement out of itself [and into our seemingly external reflection], but such that this being-outwards [Sein-nach-Auen] is equally inwardness
89
itself and therefore [now comes what is in fact shorthand for the definition of the Notion] a positing that is not merely positedness, but absolute being. (SoL 535f.)
Think of the phenomenal colours again as posited by perception given their physical bases
(some surface reflectances). Here we have merely positedness, as regards the phenomenal.
But in the unique case of the absolute, what is posited is already there as absolute being or (as
Hegel later says, with an eye on the notion) what is in and for itself. In the Notion, being-inand-for-self is identical with positedness, and such is the absolute in its self-exposition (or
manifestation) as well.
So Hegel can go on (SoL 536 t/m):
When therefore a content of the exposition is asked for, what then does the absolute
manifest? the answer must be that the distinction between form and content is simply
dissolved in the absolute. Or the content of the absolute is just this, to manifest itself.
The absolute is the absolute form which [] is absolute content. The content, therefore, is only this exposition itself.
As this movement of exposition [], the absolute is manifestation not of an inner, nor
over against an other, but it is only as the absolute manifestation of itself for itself. As
such it is []
[] actuality, Hegel says in LE 13; but he might as well and more accurately have said
the Notion.
-- -- -(III) The Notion
The absolute manifestation of itself for itself this then is the Notion. It is officially reached
at the end of LE 13 under C. Reciprocity. Last week I talked about Heraclitus as the (probable) discoverer of the conception of a relationship of reciprocity (Wechselverhltnis, RR
for short). What stands in a(n) RR are distinct entities which are nonetheless related essentially or internally. In a set of chess figures one can neatly separate the aspect of distinctness
from the aspect of essential relatedness: Qua pieces of wood the black king and the white
queen are distinct, qua abstract roles they are internally related and at root identical in so far
as both belong into the identity of the game of chess. Because of this separability of distinctness and essential relatedness, chess is not a real RR.
In a real RR, those aspects cannot be separated. What seem to be distinct entities through and
through, in a real RR, nevertheless are essentially related through and through at the same
time. So, a(n) RR is latently characterized by an inconsistency. It is a harmonious tension, to
speak with Heraclitus. Its identity is hidden inwardly and manifests itself outwardly only as
a set of modalized relations, e.g. as causality. (Remember that Hume was right in saying
that distinct entities could not stand in necessary relations; but he was wrong in trying to devise a deflationary account of causality. Causality betrays the aspect of non-distinctness of the
entities which stand in causal and thus necessary relations.)
Now, Hegel is totally in line with the conception of a(n) RR, when he says:
Necessity is [] inner identity; causality is the manifestation of this []. (SoL 570 m)
But now wait a minute! Manifestation is a term that points beyond the sphere of necessity
and merely inner identity. Causality may normally be kept within this sphere, but if we watch
closely enough and follow causality all the way to what Hegel calls reciprocity, we see that it
points beyond it and that it in fact manifests necessity and inner identity, thus turning necessity into freedom and ipso facto inner identity (which is at the same time only outer identity:
a system of outer relations, and in both ways opaque identity) into transparent identity.
90
So to complete the above quotation:
[Necessity is inner identity; causality is the manifestation of this], in which its illusory
show of substantial otherness [of two distinct substances, an active and a passive one]
has sublated itself and necessity is raised to freedom. []
In reciprocity, therefore, necessity and causality have vanished; they contain both, immediate identity [which is not yet manifested and thus only inner identity, showing itself outwardly] as connexion and relation, and the absolute substantiality [i.e. distinctness] of the different sides, hence the absolute contingency [no necessary relation between distinct entities] of them; the original unity of substantial difference, and therefore absolute contradiction. (SoL 570)
So, Hegel does not accept the conception of a(n) RR as a last word about logical space, he
wants to leave the Heraclitean opacity behind and attain to Parmenidean transparency.
Reciprocity thus is both: the end of opacity and necessity (inner identity) and its absolute
contradiction and the beginning of transparency and freedom, of the absolute manifestation
of itself for itself which is the Notion.
There is a mistranslation at 571, lines 2-3:
This inwardness [of inner necessity] or this in-itself, [not: sublates, but:] is sublated by
the movement of causality [causality itself, in its reciprocity, is what generates the
Notion, although at its own cost, by sublating as well itself and vanishing], with the result that the substantiality [real distinction] of the sides standing in relation is lost, and
necessity unveils itself [viz. as freedom]. Necessity does not become freedom by vanishing, but only because its still inner identity [Heraclitus] is manifested [Parmenides]
[]. Conversely, at the same time, contingency [the distinctness of both sides] becomes freedom, for the sides of necessity, which have the shape of independent, free
actualities [] are now posited as an identity [by reciprocal causality] [].
[We should read the last paragraph of LE 13, SoL 571 b.]
Now at last we have reached the mill that constitutes itself in its grinding: a relation (or form)
that is identical to each of its relata (its content) and is thereby defined. So, we are no longer
dependent upon a given meaning of not (taken over from the propositional calculus and
adapted to the setting of the SoL), but we can now quite conversely define negativity as
the relationality (the relational aspect) of the relation between itself and itself (the Notion).
This new negativity is not destructive anymore, but has both sides of itself, one the negative
of the other, stand in perfect harmony or even identity. Under the aspect of identity, the identity-of-itself-and-itself is the universal: negativity which is self-identical.
But, of course, negativity as well differentiates and thus determines (in a new, transparent,
constructive way) each side, which on the other are identical. This self-identity (self-relation)
which is negative (self-identical negativity with the stress on negativity) is the individual.
Lastly, the simple identity of the universal and the individual is particularity. In other words,
the universal qua individual (and thus potentially in relation to other individual universals) is
the particular. (What would be the non-simple, i.e. the active, self-mediating identity of
the universal and the individual? Presumably the Notion as such.)
The universal, the particular and the individual are three totalities which are one and the
same reflection (571 b).
-- -- -In the introduction the logic of the Notion (The Notion in General), the Notion is likened to
the I of transcendental apperception.
91
Let us first look at the Notion of the Notion, as given on p. 582.
Next, Hegel goes on to ask if this Notion of the Notion is in accord with what others have said
about the notion (582f.) and then (584 t) refers to Kant as a positive example. We should read
that as well (at least till the end of p. 583).
-- -- --
92
24-Apr 09
We are presently talking about the section Subjectivity of the subjective logic, i.e. the
doctrine of the Notion: The Notion / The Judgment / The Syllogism.
Chapter 1, The Notion, contains, as Hegel remarks at the beginning of chapter 2 (The
Judgment) more a subjective reflection or subjective abstraction (623), i.e. one in our BL.
This is a kind of luxury here, not necessary, for:
[] the Notion is itself this abstractive process, the opposing of its determinations is
its own determining activity. The Judgment is this positing of the determinate Notions
by the Notion itself. (Ibid.)
So, the real theoretical work in the logic of the Notion (LN) begins with chapter 2.
Here are some even more subjective reflections on the Notion.
-- -- -Aristotle is opposed to Plato with regard of the ontological status of the universal. According to Plato, the universal is real, even the truly real (onts on), and it is active and living (see
The Sophist).
But Aristotle reasons like that (end of Met. Z): If the universal, say animal, were real, then it
would be possible to run into it: So, here is the ANIMAL itself, as a tode ti. But how many
legs does it have? Humans essentially have two legs, horses essentially have four legs and
snakes essentially have none at all. So, the animal itself will (essentially, but it is all essence
in the forms/ideas anyway) exactly two and exactly four and exactly none legs a contradiction.
In fact, therefore, the universal is like matter: an indeterminate determinable, and in fact is
matter, though not regular, sensible matter, but hyl not, intelligible matter (Met. H 6).
But then the species is not a true universal at all. You can run into a species as a tode ti: if you
run into one of its individual members. The individual and its species have all essential properties in common, so there is no (essential) difference in thinkable content between a species
and its individuals. Therefore the double meaning of eidos, meaning (a) species and (b)
(essential individual) form, is no conceptual handicap at all, quite the contrary: it is an exact
conceptual tool.
Aristotelian forms/ideas thus are all immanent and specific. There are no generic (and no
transcendent) Aristotelian forms/ideas. Platonic forms/ideas on the other hand come in all
grades of generality, from specific forms up to the megista gene. But this, as Aristotle sees,
leads to contradiction. Plato would not deny that, but would say that the art of dialectics, as
the philosophers method, is made to deal with that contradiction.
Now, Hegel is in fact trying to reconcile Aristotle and Plato on this fundamental point. He
conceives the forms/ideas (i.e. the Notion) as immanent, pace Plato, but at the same time he
conceives the universal (the generic universal) as real, pace Aristotle, and takes over from
Plato the art of dialectics as the way to handle the immanent negativity of the Notion.
The horse and the snake are both animals, different from each other but not from the animal.
They are animal all over and nothing but animal. This is the universals shining to the inside.
But the universal is shining to the outside (SoL 606 m/b) as well: It has a place in a hierarchy
of universals (qua individual universal, i.e. qua particular).
From Hegel point of view, Aristotle brings particularity (species-hood) too close to individuality, and Plato brings it too close to universality (generality). For Aristotle all forms are
individual forms and ipso facto specific forms, and that leaves him with a deep problem of
93
individuation (within a species). An Aristotelian form must be like a Hegelian One, repelling
itself to many Ones. What is universal (general, allgemein), on the other hand, is not real,
not substantial, according to Aristotle.
Plato, in Hegels view, wrongly posits a gulf between the individuals and the (specific and
generic) forms, hence between the individual on the one side and the particular and the universal in the other. But all three of them belong together as the self-subsistent moments of the
Notion.
Universality, particularity, and individuality are, taken in the abstract, the same as
identity, difference, and ground. But the universal is the self-identical, with the express
qualification, that it simultaneously contains the particular and the individual. Again,
the particular is the different or the [determinacy, Wallace says:] specific character,
but with the qualification that it is in itself universal and is an individual. Similarly the
individual must be understood to be a subject or [grounding, foundation, Wallace
says:] substratum which involves [contains] the genus and species in itself and [is itself substantial]. (Enc. 164)
In the realm of plurality (which starts with the judgment), where we find many individuals,
particulars and universals, one can easily see how they all fit together:
Each individual is as well particular (specific, as witness Aristotle) and universal: Socrates is
a human being and an animal.
Each particular is one individual particular among many, and it is universal (comprising
many individuals, and, pace Aristotle, divisible into sub-particulars.)
Each universal is one individual universal among many, and it has its place, as a particular, in
the hierarchy of universals. So e.g., animal is a particular corporeal substance.
In the realm of singularity, i.e. with the Notion qua all of logical space, these relations are not
so easily understood. The one and only Notion or Concept is all three of them: i, p, u, like the
one and only essence was identity, difference and ground. But now it is explicit in each of the
moments that the Notion is all three of them.
In its universality the Notion/Concept is in free equality with itself in its determinacy. (The
universal goes through its differences). In its particularity the universal continues serenely equal to itself. In its individuality the Notion qua universal a particular is reflected
into itself which negative self-unity has complete and original determinateness, without
any loss to its self-identity or universality. (Enc. 163)
-- -- -But where does this complete and original determinateness come from? Out of itself. In the
sphere of being, we had being as the immediately given common factor of all truth claims
whatsoever, plus negation, as adapted from the propositional calculus. This was not much, but
enough for creating all the various contents of the logic of being.
In the sphere of essence only negation was left as a possible given source of content, and it
turned out enough as well and productive of (essential) being. Now, with the Notion, nothing
is left as a given source of content, and even that is supposed to be enough to create content.
The Notion is definable as the (one and only) self-creating content. Or, alternatively, as absolute form which as such creates (and is) its own content. In its creating it is mediation, relation. So it is relation between itself and itself. So we may define the Notion as well as the (one
and only) relation which relates itself to itself.
Now we need not appeal to the propositional calculus any longer in order to get a sense of
negation. Negation can be defined as that which makes the Notion a relation, its relational
94
aspect. And the other, positive aspect of logical space, called being, is that which is responsible for there being relata (or terms) of the relation. But in fact, terms and relation are
one and the same: this is meant by the Notions universality (self-identity). Nevertheless,
negation is present in the Notion, thus creating determinateness, which in the Notion is (its)
particularity (the first negation). But the negation is self-related (as it was already qua essence), and this self-relation of negation is the Notions individuality (the second negation or
the negation of the negation).
In short: The Notion has the structure [r1 R r2], with r1 = r2 = R = [r1 R r2]
The identity of both relata constitutes its universality.
The difference of the relata, qua terms of a relation, constitutes particularity.
The non-well-foundedness (i.e. self-relation) of R constitutes individuality.
First, the Notion is to be taken in its universality (as essence was in its identity), as the simple
whole of logical space. But it is shining towards its outside, like the sun, say (Platos likeness of the source of logical space). So, we have logical space shining constantly beyond itself. But this cannot be. What we in fact have, is a logical space more encompassing than we
first thought: one in which the universal is only a particular, and its other, the particular
itself is right there to its side.
So, logical space, U, comprises U and P. Thereby U itself is only a particular. We have here
coordination and subordination at a time: The universal notion in its shining to the outside
is coordinated to the particular notion; but at the same time the latter is subordinated to the
universal notion in the hierarchy of generality.
But of course, the particular universal and the Particular are as well both particulars. So they
are both subordinated to the Particular as well, which thus is there common universal.
This is the total manifestation of one in the other. We just cannot fix their difference.
-- -- -And it is lastly all bent back into the individual, which is (a) the whole of universal logical
space, but as well (b) the loss of the Notion:
But individuality is not only the return of the Notion into itself, but immediately its
loss. Through individuality [] it becomes external to itself and enters into actuality.
(SoL 621 t)
The individual, therefore, as self-related negativity is the immediate identity of the
negative with itself; it is a being-for-self. (Ibid. m)
The first individuality is notion-like: transparent and free. The second individuality is thinglike or one-like (a being-for-self): negativity turned opaquely on itself. This opaque negativity
splits the Notion into two parts which are vaguely called subject and predicate and whose
unity, the judgment, is affected by immediate being as a kind of cement, the copula is.
It is the element of Individuality which first explicitly differentiates the elements of
the notion [etc., see Enc. 165]
So, this then is the judgment.
-- -- -It is important to see that Hegel makes a distinction between the sentence (or proposition,
Satz) and the judgment (Urteil), between sentential form and judgmental form (Enc.
167). Judgmental form is predicative form: S is P.
Modern predicate logic (MPL) and traditional formal logic (TFL) differ on that point. MPL
tries to capture as much as possible of sentential form (there are more formally valid infer-
95
ences than formally valid syllogisms after all), predication just being restricted to the most
basic level of the sentence. TFL on the other hand casts all (categorical) sentences into predicative form, adding quantity to any subject and quality to any predicate. (Cf., on these
issues, Fred Sommers, The Logic of Natural Language.)
Now Hegel is (of course) loyal to TFL, but sees that it does not capture the logic of natural
language as it stands, which he comments with a so much the worse for natural language (I
am overstating the case). Fred Sommers on the other hand tries to enrich TFL up to a point
where it equals MPL in expressive strength and may be used to reconstruct the logic of natural language at the same time (while MPL tends to regiment not to lay bare the logical form
of natural language, according to Sommers).
-- -- -Now the individual, qua the lost Notion, being a one (out of many ones), comes as many individuals in the realm of judgment. Judgment here is not to be taken subjectively, as an
act of ours, but neutrally, as objective/subjective: All things are [i.e. each thing is] a judgment (Enc. 167). Each thing is an individual with a universal nature, or a universal individualized (ibid.). This of course is the reason why we can make subjective judgments
about them without thereby doing violence to them (as Nietzsche and Adorno feared).
But if things are judgments, doesnt that amount to a Tractarian ontology of facts? No, says
Hegel, for the predicate is ideal (!) in the subject ( 170) and has no self-subsistent being at
all. Nevertheless, qua judgments things are finite, because judgment is not only union but as
well articulation and separation: of a things Dasein (d-being) from its universal nature, of its
body from its soul ( 168).
-- -- -In his exposition of the judgment, Hegel follows Kants list of the types of judgment. This
creates a certain quandary. Kant has four times three different types of judgment, while Hegel
regularly gives us three of each whatsoever. He helps himself with a little trick: Essence, as
the antithetical middle sphere between being and the Notion, makes for two types of judgment, because judgment, in its own turn, is the locus of separation. (Syllogism, as the locus of
unity and identity, is not thus torn asunder by the negativity of essence):
Being
Essence1 (reflection)
Essence2 (necessity)
Notion
96
positive judgment in the domain of the qualitative judgment. But let me follow LN 30, in a
short survey.
(a) Qualitative judgment.
We have a (logical) quale, i.e. a d-being which is identical with its quality, and press it into
predicative form, using it two times over, as subject and as its own predicate:
1. The positive judgment: the individual is a particular, the rose is red.
Now, Hegel always treats the copula as expressing identity, as if being were identity. This
gives him the supposed justification for saying: But the rose is not identical to (its) redness;
therefore we need to pass on to the negative judgment. Isnt that sheer sophistry? No, not
here, given our starting point: the logical quale which was used twice, as S and as P. The
judgment tears it asunder in two, thus belying the identity that it expresses at the same time in
the qualitative is.
Note: Hegel tries to deduce the specific sense (or senses) of the copula, and all he has to start
from is the identity of the logical quale which was torn asunder in the qualitative judgment.
2. The negative judgment (justified by the form of judgment, given the identity of the
logical quale that serves as S ans as P): the individual is not a particular, the rose is
not read (but of some other colour).
3. (aa) The identical judgment, the individual is the individual and (bb) the infinite
judgment, the individual is not [P from a foreign sphere], the lion is not a table.
After the logical quale/something, which thus does not ground a true judgment, we have to
consider an existent/thing:
(b) Judgment of reflection
Here the predicates arent immediate (sensible) qualities anymore, but more like dispositions:
e.g. useful, dangerous; weight, acidity ( 174).
1. Singular judgment: The subject, the individual as individual, is a universal.
2. Particular judgment: The subject is partly this (and partly that).
3. Universal judgment: Some are the universal (i.e. all).
Now, the universality is posited as well on the side of the subject, which makes for the:
(c) judgment of necessity
Again the subject matter of the judgment has changed (no formalism!): We have now arrived
in the region of substance. So in the
1. categorical judgment, the genus or the species get predicated of the individual.
2. Hypothetical judgment: both sides have the form of self-subsistent actuality, whose
identity is only an inner one. (So, we have here a self-alienation of the Notion)
3. Disjunctive judgment: Universality as genus and as the circle of its self-excluding
particularisation.
(d) Judgment of the Notion
The content now, finally, is the Notion.
1. Assertoric judgment: S is an individual, and P is the reflection of the subjects particular Dasein onto its universal: S is good/bad/true/beautiful etc.
2. Problematic judgment: Assertoric judgments are mere affirmations under the principle of bivalence: true or false, and thus invite their counter-affirmation. Thus an assertoric judgment is degraded to a problematic judgment.
97
3. Apodictic judgment: Here, the reason or justification is built into the judgment:
This house, qua being so and so, is good. The mediating ground or reason is here
present in the judgment: All things are [i.e. each thing is] a genus (its determination
and end) in an individual actuality of a particular constitution (Enc. 179).
180:
In this manner subject and predicate are each the whole judgment. [] What has been
really made explicit [posited] is the oneness [unity] of subject and predicate, as the notion itself, filling up the empty is of the copula. While its constituent elements [its
moments] are at the same time distinguished as subject and predicate, the notion is put
[posited] as their unity, as the connexion [relation] which serves to intermediate them:
in short, as the Syllogism.
-- -- --
98
28-Apr 2009
In the logical development of the judgment, the copula has achieved the value of the notion
(concept, term) in the apodictic judgment (The house, being so and so constituted, is
good). --- It first had the value of d-being (in the qualitative judgment or judgment of dbeing), then of reflection, then of necessity.
Thus, the apodictic judgment gives way to the syllogism, first the qualitative syllogism.
In the premises of the qualitative syllogism one can (non-trivially) predicate
U of P or U of I or P of I (always the more general of the less general).
Two of these predications have to be picked as premises; and then we have to look what term
occurs in both premises: this is the middle term, to be left out in the conclusion. This procedure gives us the three Aristotelian figures of the (qualitative) syllogism:
1st figure:
U of P,
P of I,
therefore U of I
(P as middle term)
2nd figure:
U of I,
P of I,
therefore U of P
(I as middle term)
3rd figure:
U of P,
U of I,
therefore P of I
(U as middle term)
The usual combinatorial form yields a fourth figure, with the middle term, M, as predicate in
the major and as subject in the minor premise. But then M must be P (the particular) again,
like in the first figure, for only P can occur, both, as predicate (of I) and as subject (for U). So,
Hegel says that the forth figure is an empty formalism.
Here is the regular table of the four figures (G as middle term, F as minor, H as major),
with Hegelian subscripts as reminders:
1st figure
2nd figure
3rd figure
4th figure
Gp Hu
Gi Hu
Hp Gu
H G
Fi Gp
Gi Fp
Fi Gu
G F
Fi Hu
Fp Hu
Fi Hp
F H
One sees that subject and predicate are simply reversed in both premises of the fourth figure,
as compared with the first. The middle term, G, is functioning, both, as subject and as predicate, in both figures, while in the 3rd figure it is functioning only as predicate (and must therefore be U) and in the 2nd figure only as subject (and must therefore be I).
So Hegel skips the 4th figure in LN 30 altogether as a superfluous and even absurd addition
of the Moderns (Enc. 187, Aristotle had only three figures), while in LN 16 he had taken
the chance of putting the tautological, mathematical syllogism in its place (U U U).
In the qualitative syllogism, first, an individual is coupled (concluded) with a universal by
means of a (particular) quality. But an individual has many qualities and each quality can in
turn be subsumed under many different universals. So in the first figure one can prove different and then (as difference is followed by opposition in the logic of reflection) even opposite
claims of a given individual.
99
This contradiction of the syllogism expresses itself as an infinite progress (or, in fact, an
infinite regress): the premises are as such unproven, therefore only judgments, not syllogisms.
So they too must be proven (mediated) by more premises, and so on up.
This deficit (expresses and) sublates itself in the further development of the syllogism. The
immediate syllogism (of the 1st figure) gives way to the 2nd figure and this in turn to the 3rd.
In the conclusion of the 1st figure, the individual is declared to be universal and thus (being
both, I und U, at the same time) may now serve as middle term. The same happens to the particular in the 2nd figure.
So, taken together, the qualitative syllogism goes full circle in its three figures and all its
terms get fully mediated by each other: I and U by P, P and U by I, I and P by U. The progress (or regress) is thus bent back into a circle:
The major of the 1st figure is the conclusion of the 2nd and the minor of the 1st the conclusion
of the 3rd figure, and so on for the premises of the other figures as well. (But, of course, this
circle has still something vicious about it: a mutual presupposing of the figures. So the story
of the syllogism must go on.)
-- -- -In the syllogism of reflection, the middle is not an abstract particular determinacy of the subject any longer but is as well all individual concrete subjects who have this particular determinacy among others (Enc. 190). This gives us the syllogism of allness (so to speak the 1st
figure of the syllogism of reflection, because here again P is the middle term):
Major:
Minor:
Conclusion:
All P are U
I is P
So, I is U
But the major here presupposes the conclusion and has to be justified, which leads to the syllogism of induction, where I is the middle term (as in the 2nd figure of the qualitative syllogism), but the individual now as the potentially infinite totality of all individuals, which thus
cannot be inspected empirically in their entirety. (Hegel displays its form at SoL 690.)
Because the totality of the individuals cannot be inspected as something present and given, the
syllogism of induction presupposes the syllogism of analogy, where U functions as mediating
middle (SoL 692):
The earth (an individual, but ) is inhabited,
The moon is an earth ( in the value of a universal),
Therefore the moon is inhabited.
But of course, taking the middle term in two different values comes close to a quaternio terminorum. So the syllogism of analogy cannot be the end of the story either.
-- -- -The qualitative syllogism as such (and in its first figure) has the particular as middle term,
which then gets replaced by the individual and the universal in the other figures. So the qualitative syllogism is dominated by the 1st figure.
The syllogism of reflection as such (and in its middle version) has the individual as middle
term, though here as well the other two terms attain to the middle position. So the syllogism
of reflection is dominated by induction (its second figure).
The third syllogism is the syllogism of necessity, which, as such (and at its happy end), has
the universal as its middle, again in such a way that the other terms (I and P) will attain to the
100
middle position as well. (Cf. Enc. 191.) So the syllogism of necessity is dominated by its
third figure.
Categorical syllogism:
Hypothetical syllogism:
Disjunctive syllogism:
In the disjunctive syllogism one and the same universal is (the case) in these different determinations, which are therefore now negated:
This realization of the notion, a realization in which the universal is this one totality
withdrawn back into itself (of which the different members are no less the whole, and)
which has determined itself as immediate unity by sublating the mediation: this realization of the notion is the object. (Enc. 193)
This transition corresponds to the sound kernel of the (in its syllogistic form deficient) ontological argument for the existence of the perfect being.)
-- -- Thus, the absolute is the object now (Enc 194), which then splits asunder into many objects
each of which is the totality: the absolute contradiction of the complete self-subsistence of
the manifold [objects] and their equally complete non-self-subsistence.
The object is then considered over the developmental stages of mechanism (macro-physics),
chemism (micro-physics and chemistry) and teleology (biology as objective teleology and
end-means-relations as subjective teleology).
The realized end then leads to the last stage of the logic: the idea, which is
(a) life,
(b) cognition (in general), and then more precisely
(i) cognition proper (()analysis; ()synthesis: (1)definition, (2) division, (3) theorem)
(ii) volition (practical cognition),
(c) the speculative or absolute idea: the method of the logic in which its whole course is
sublated.
-- -- --
101
Vgl. Nietzsche, Werke III, ed. Schlechta, S. 476; Adorno, Negative Dialektik, Schriften 6, Ffm 1973, S. 21.
Vgl. zu diesem weitgespannten Thema Mike Stange, Antinomie und Freiheit. Zum Projekt einer Begrndung
der Logik im Anschlu an Fichtes Grundlage der gesamten Wissenschaftslehre, Diss. Tbingen 2007.
iii
For this part of the paper I have drawn upon my article Hegel und Heidegger, to appear in YYY(ed.), ZZZ.
ii
Freiburg: Alber.
iv
Hegel 1970: 76. (Cf. the translation by A.V. Miller, Hegel 1977: 52-53.)
vi
vii
viii
Hegel 1970 and Hegel 1977: chapter IV. B. Freedom of self-consciousness: Stoicism, Scepticism, and the
Unhappy Consciousness.
ix
xi
xii
xiii
xiv
xv
Priest 2002:103-104.
References:
Castaeda, H.-N. (1966), He: A Study in the Logic of Self-Conciousness, Ratio, 8: 130-157.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1971), Wissenschaft der Logik, ed. G. Lasson. Erster Teil.Hamburg: Meiner.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1970), Phnomenologie des Geistes. Werke 3. Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp.
Hegel, G. W. F. (1977), Phenomenology of Spirit, translated by A.V. Miller. Oxford: University Press.
Perry, J. (1977), Frege on Demonstratives, Philosophical Review, 86: 474-497.
Priest, G. (2002), Beyond the Limits of Thought, Oxford University Press.
Sellars, W. (1963), Science, Perception and Reality, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Strawson, P. F. (1959), Individuals. An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics. London: Methuen.