Examship
Examship
Examship
I have spent many hours with students caught in this unwelcome bitterness. These hours lend
an urgency to my theme. I have found that students have been able to come to terms with the
ethical problem, to the extent that it is real, only after a refined study of the true nature of bull
and its relation to knowledge. I shall submit grounds for my suspicion that we can be found
guilty of sharing the students' confusion of moral and epistemological issues.
I:
I present as my premise, then, an amoral fabliau. Its hero-villain is the Abominable Mr.
Metzger '47. Since I celebrate his virtuosity, I regret giving him a pseudonym, but the peculiar
style of his bravado requires me to honor also his modesty. Bull in pure form is rare; there is
usually some contamination by data. The community has reason to be grateful to Mr. Metzger for
having created an instance of laboratory purity, free from any adulteration by matter.
The more credit is due him, I think, because his act was free from premeditation, deliberation,
or hope of personal gain.
Mr. Metzger stood one rainy November day in the lobby of Memorial Hall. A junior,
concentrating in Mathematics, he was fond of diverting himself by taking part in the drama, a
penchant which may have had some influence on the events of the next hour. He was waiting to
take part in a rehearsal in Sanders Theater, but, as sometimes happens, no other players appeared.
Perhaps the rehearsal had been cancelled without his knowledge? He decided to wait another five
minutes.
Students, meanwhile, were filing into the Great Hall opposite, and taking seats at the testing
tables. Spying a friend crossing I the lobby toward the Great Hall's door, Metzger greeted him
and extended appropriate condolences. He inquired, too, what course his friend was being tested
in.
Oh, Soc. Sci. something-or-other.
What's it all about? asked Metzger, and this, as Homer remarked of Patroclus, was the
beginning of evil for him.
It's about Modern Perspectives on Man and Society and All That, said his friend. Pretty
interesting, really.
Always wanted to take a course like that, said Metzger. Any good reading?
Yeah, great. There's this book - his friend did not have time to finish.
Take your seats please said a stern voice beside them. The idle conversation had somehow
taken the two friends to one of the tables in the Great Hall. Both students automatically obeyed;
the proctor put blue-books before them; another proctor presented them with copies of the
printed hour-test.
Mr. Metzger remembered afterwards a brief misgiving that was suddenly overwhelmed by a
surge of curiosity and puckish glee. He wrote George Smith on the blue book, opened it, and
addressed the first question.
I must pause to exonerate the Management. The Faculty has a rule that no student may attend
an examination in a course in which he is not enrolled. To the wisdom of this rule the outcome of
this deplorable story stands witness. The Registrar, charged with the enforcement of the rule, has
developed an organization with procedures which are certainly the finest to be devised. In
November, however, class rosters are still shaky, and on this particular day another student,
named Smith, was absent. As for the culprit, we can reduce his guilt no further than to suppose
that he was ignorant of the rule, or, in the face of the momentous challenge before him, forgetful.
We need not be distracted by Metzger's performance on the objective or spot questions on
the test. His D on these sections can be explained by those versed in the theory of probability.
Our interest focuses on the quality of his essay. It appears that when Metzger's friend picked up
his own blue book a few days later, he found himself in company with a large proportion of his
section in having received on the essay a C+. When he quietly picked up George Smith's
bluebook to return it to Metzger, he observed that the grade for the essay was A-. In the margin
was a note in the section man's hand. It read; Excellent work. Could you have pinned these
observations down a bit more closely? Compare. in . . . pp . . . 11
Such news could hardly be kept quiet. There was a leak, and the whole scandal broke on the
front page of Tuesday's Crimson. With the press Metzger was modest, as becomes a hero. He
said that there had been nothing to it at all, really. The essay question had offered a choice of two
books, Margaret Mead's And Keep Your Powder Dry or Geoffrey Gorer's The American
People. Metzger reported that having read neither of them, he had chosen the second because
the title gave me some notion as to what the book might be about. On the test, two critical
comments were offered on each book, one favorable, one unfavorable. The students were asked
to discuss. Metzger conceded that he had played safe in throwing his lot with the more
laudatory of the two comments, but I did not forget to be balanced.
I do not have Mr. Metzger's essay before me except in vivid memory. As I recall, he took his
first cue from the name Geoffrey, and committed his strategy to the premise that Gorer was born
into an Anglo Saxon culture, probably English, but certainly English speaking Having heard
that Margaret Mead was a social anthropologist, he inferred that Gorer was the same. He then
entered upon his essay, centering his inquiry upon what he supposed might be the problems
inherent in an anthropologist's observation of a culture which was his own, or nearly his own.
Drawing in part from memories of table-talk on cultural relativity* and in part from creative
logic, he rang changes on the relation of observer to observed, and assessed the kind and degree
of objectivity which might accrue to an observer through training as an anthropologist. He
concluded that the book in question did in fact contribute a considerable range of 'objective', and
even 'fresh', insights into the nature of our culture. At the same time, he warned, these
observations must be understood within the context of their generation by a person only partly
freed from his embeddedness in the culture he is observing, and limited in his capacity to
transcend those particular tendencies and biases which he has himself developed as a personality
in his interaction with this culture since his birth. In this sense the book portrays as much the
character of Geoffrey Gorer as it analyzes that of the American people. It is my regrettable duty
to report that at this moment of triumph Mr. Metzger was carried away by the temptations of
parody and added, We are thus much the richer.
In any case, this was the essay for which Metzger received his honor grade and his public
acclaim. He was now, of course, in serious trouble with the authorities.
I shall leave him for the moment to the mercy of the Administrative Board of Harvard College
and turn the reader's attention to the section man who ascribed the grade. He was in much worse
trouble. All the consternation in his immediate area of the Faculty and all the glee in other areas
fell upon his unprotected head. I shall now undertake his defense.
I do so not simply because I was acquainted with him and feel a respect for his intelligence; I
believe in the justice of his grade! Well, perhaps Justice is the wrong word in a situation so
manifestly absurd. This is more a case in equity. That is, the grade is equitable if we accept
other aspects of the situation which are equally absurd. My proposition is this: if we accept as
valid those C grades which were accorded students who, like Metzger's friend, demonstrated a
thorough familiarity with the details of the book without relating their critique to the
methodological problems of social anthropology, then George Smith deserved not only the
same, but better.
The reader may protest that the Cs given to students who showed evidence only of diligence
were indeed not valid and that both these students and George Smith should have received E's.
To give the diligent E is of course not in accord with custom. I shall take up this matter later. For
now, were I to allow the protest, I could only restate my thesis: that George Smith's E would, in
a college of liberal artist be properly a better E.
At this point I need a short-hand. It is a curious fact that there is no academic slang for the
presentation of evidence of diligence alone. Parroting won't do; it is possible to par-rot bull. I
must beg the reader's pardon, and, for reasons almost too obvious to bear, suggest cow.
Stated as nouns, the concepts look simple enough:
cow (pure): data, however relevant, without relevancies.
bull (pure): relevancies, however relevant, without data.
The reader can see all too clearly where this simplicity would lead. I can assure him that I
would not have imposed on him this way were I aiming to say that knowledge in this university
is definable as some neuter compromise between cow and bull, some infertile hermaphrodite.
This is precisely what many diligent students seem to believe: that what they must learn to do is
to find the right mean between amounts of detail and amounts of generalities. Of course
this is not the point at all. The problem is not quantitative, nor does its solution lie on a
continuum between the particular and the general. Cow and bull are not poles of a single
dimension. A clear notion of what they really are is essential to my inquiry, and for heuristic
liberal education should teach students how to think, not only in their own fields but in fields
outside their, own - that is, to understand how the other fellow orders knowledge, then bulling,
even in its purest form, expresses an important part of what a pluralist university holds dear,
surely a more important part than the collecting of facts that are facts which schoolboys learn
to do. Here then, good bull appears not as ignorance at all but as an aspect of knowledge. It is
both relevant and true. In a university setting good bull is therefore of more value than facts,
which, without a frame of reference, are not even true at all.
Perhaps this value accounts for the final anomaly: as instructors, we are inclined to reward bull
highly, where we do not detect its intent, to the consternation of the bullster's acquaintances. And
often we do not examine the matter too closely. After a long evening of reading blue books full
of cow, the sudden meeting with a student who at least understands the problems of one's field
provides a lift like a drought of refreshing wine, and a strong disposition toward trust.
This was, then, the sense of confidence that came to our unfortunate section man as he read
George Smiths sympathetic considerations.
II:
In my own years of watching over students shoulders as they work, I have come to believe
that this feeling of trust has a firmer basis than the confidence generated by evidence of diligence
alone. I believe that the theory of a liberal education holds. Students who have dared to
understand mans real relation to his knowledge have shown themselves to be in a strong
position to learn content rapidly and meaningfully, and to retain it. I have learned to be less
concerned about the education of a student who has come to understand the nature of mans
knowledge, even though he has not yet committed himself to hard work, than I am about the
education of the student who, after one or two terms at Harvard is working desperately hard and
still believes that collected facts constitute knowledge. The latter, when I try to explain to him,
too often understands me to be saying that he doesnt put in enough generalities. Surely he has
put in enough facts.
I have come to see such quantitative statements as expressions of an entire, coherent
epistemology. In grammar school the student is taught that Columbus discovered America in
1492. The more such items he gets right on a given test, the more he is credited with
knowing. From years of this sort of thing it is not unnatural to develop the conviction that
knowledge consists of the accretion of hard facts by hard work.
The student learns that the more facts and procedures he can get right in a given course, the
better will be his grade. The more courses he takes, the more subjects he has had, the more
credits he accumulates, the more diplomas he will get, until, after graduate school, he will
emerge with his doctorate, a member of the community of scholars.
The foundation of this entire life is the proposition that a fact is a fact. The necessary correlate
of this proposition is that a fact is either right or wrong. This implies that the standard against
which the rightness or wrongness of a fact may be judged exists-someplace - perhaps graven
upon a tablet in a Platonic world outside and above this cave of tears. In grammar school it is
evident that the tablets which enshrine the spelling of a word or the answer to an arithmetic
problem are visible to my teacher who need only compare any offerings to it. In high school I
observe that my English teachers disagree. This can only mean that the tablets in such matters as
the goodness of a poem are distant and obscured by clouds. They surely exist. The pleasing of
befuddled English teachers degenerates into assessing their prejudices, a game in which I have no
protection against my competitors more glib of tongue. I respect only my science teachers,
authorities who really know. Later I learn from them that This is only what we think now. But
eventually, surely . . . . . Into this epistemology of education, apparently shared by teachers in
such terms as credits, semester hours and years of French the student may invest his ideals,
his drive, his competitiveness, his safety, his self-esteem, and even his love.
College raises other questions: by whose calendar is it proper to say that Columbus discovered
America in 1492? How, when and by whom was the year 1 established in this calendar? What of
other calendars? In view of the evidence for Leif Ericsons previous visit (and the American
Indians), what historical ethnocentrism is suggested by the use of the word discover in this
sentence? As for Leif Ericson, in accord with what assumptions do you order the evidence?
These questions and their answers are not more knowledge. They are devastation. I do not
need to elaborate upon the epistemology, or rather epistemologies, they imply. A fact has become
at last an observation or an operation performed in a frame of reference. A liberal education is
founded in an awareness of frame of reference even in the most immediate and empirical
examination of data. Its acquirement involves relinquishing hope of absolutes and of the
protection they afford against doubt and the glib-tongued competitor. It demands an ever
widening sophistication about systems of thought and observation. It leads, not away from, but
through the arts of gamesmanship to a new trust.
This trust is in the value and integrity of systems, their varied character, and the way their
apparently incompatible metaphors enlighten, from complementary facets, the particulars of
human experience. As one student said to me: I used to be cynical about intellectual games.
Now I want to know them thoroughly. You see I came to realize that it was only when I knew the
rules of the game cold that I could tell whether what I was saying was tripe.
We too often think of the bullster as cynical. He can be, and not always in a light-hearted way.
We have failed to observe that there can lie behind cow the potential of a deeper and more
dangerous despair. The moralism of sheer work and obedience can be an ethic that, unwilling to
face a despair of its ends, glorifies its means. The implicit refusal to consider the relativity oi
both ends and means leaves the operator in an unconsidered proprietary absolutism, History bears
witness that in the pinches this moral superiority has no recourse to negotiation, only to force.
A liberal education proposes that mans hope lies elsewhere: in the negotiability that can arise
from an understanding of the integrity of systems and of their origins in mans address to his
universe. The prerequisite is the courage to accept such a definition of knowledge. From then on,
of course, there is nothing incompatible between such an epistemology and hard work. Rather the
contrary.
I can now at last let bull and cow get together. The reader knows best how a productive
wedding is arranged in his own field. This is the nuptial he celebrates with a straight A on
examinations. The masculine context must embrace the feminine particular, though-:itself born
of Woman. Such a union is knowledge itself, and it alone can generate new contexts and new
data which can unite in their turn to form new knowledge.
In this happy setting we can congratulate in particular the Natural Sciences, long thought to be
barren ground to the bullster. I have indeed drawn my examples of bull from the Social Sciences,
and by analogy from the Humanities, Essay-writing in these fields has long been thought to
nurture the art of bull to its prime. I feel, however, that the Natural Sciences have no reason to
feel slighted. It is perhaps no accident that Metzger was a mathematician. As part of my
researches for this paper, furthermore, a student of considerable talent has recently honored me
with an impressive analysis of the art of amassing partial credits on examinations in advanced
physics. Though beyond me in some respects, his presentation confirmed my impression that
instructors of Physics frequently honor on examinations operations structurally similar to those
requisite in a good essay.
The very qualities that make the Natural Sciences fields of delight for the eager gamesman
have been essential to their marvelous fertility.
III:
As priests of these mysteries, how can we make our rites more precisely expressive? The
student who merely cows robs himself, without knowing it, of his education and his soul. The
student who only bulls robs-himself, as he knows full well, of the joys of inductive discovery, that is, of engagement. The introduction of frames of reference in the new curricula of
Mathematics and Physics in the schools is a hopeful experiment. We do not know yet how much
of these potent revelations the very young can stand, but I suspect they may rejoice in them more
than we have supposed. I cant believe they have never wondered about Lief Ericson and that
word discovered, or even about 1492. They have simply been too wise to inquire.>
Increasingly in recent years better students in the better high schools and preparatory schools
are being allowed to inquire. In fact they appear to be receiving both encouragement and training
in their inquiry. I have the evidence before me.
ach year for the past five years all freshmen entering Harvard and Radcliffe have been asked in
freshman week to grade two essays answering an examination question in History. They are
then asked to give their reasons for their grades. One essay, filled with dates, is 99% cow. The
other, with hardly a date in it, is a good essay, easily mistaken for bull. The official grades of
these essays are, for the first (alas!) C+, because he has worked so hard, and for the second
(soundly, I think) B+. Each year a larger majority of freshmen evaluate these essays as would the
majority of the faculty, and for the facultys reasons, and each year a smaller minority give the
higher honor to the essay offering data alone. Most interesting, a larger number of students each
year, while not overrating the second essay, award the first the straight E appropriate to it in a
college of liberal arts.
For us who must grade such students in a university, these developments imply a new urgency,
did we not feel it already. Through our grades we describe for the students, in the showdown,
what we believe about the nature of knowledge. The subtleties of bull are not peripheral to our
academic concerns. That they penetrate to the center of our care is evident in our feelings when a
student whose good work we have awarded a high grade reveals to us that he does not feel he
deserves it. Whether he disqualifies himself because theres too much bull in it, or worse
because I really dont think Ive worked that hard, he presents a serious educational problem.
Many students feel this sleaziness; only a few reveal it to us.
We can hardly allow a mistaken sense of fraudulence to undermine our students
achievements. We must lead students beyond their concept of bull so that they may honor
relevancies that are really relevant. We can willingly acknowledge that, in lieu of the date 1492 a
consideration of calendars and of the word discovered, may well be offered with intent to
deceive. We must insist that this does not make such considerations intrinsically immoral, and
that, contrariwise, the date 1492 may be no substitute for them. most of all we must convey the
impression that we grade understanding qua understanding. To be convincing, I suppose we must
concede to ourselves in advance that a bright students understanding is understanding even if he
achieved it by osmosis rather than by hard work in our course.
These are delicate matters. As for cow, its complexities ire not what need concern us. Unlike
good bull, it does not represent partial knowledge at all. It belongs to a different theory of
knowledge entirely. In our theories of knowledge it represents total ignorance, or worse. yet, a
knowledge downright inimical to understanding. I even go so far as to propose that we award no
more Cs for cow. To do so is rarely, I feel, the act of mercy it seems. Mercy lies in clarity.
The reader may be afflicted by a lingering curiosity about the fate of Mr. Metzger. I hasten to
reassure him. The Administrative Board of Harvard College, whatever its satanic reputation, is a
benign body. Its members, to be sure, were on the spot. They delighted in Metzgers exploit, but
they were responsible to the Facultys rule. The hero stood in danger of probation. The debate
was painful. Suddenly one member, of a refined legalistic sensibility, observed that the rule
applied specifically to examinations and that the occasion had been simply an hour-test. Mr.
Metzger was merely admonished.
* An important part of Harvards education takes place during meals in the Houses. -- An
official Publication.
This essay was written at the request of the Committee on Educational Policy of the Faculty of
Arts and Sciences, Harvard University, as a contribution to a collection of papers on the subject
of examinations, March 1963. It can be found as one of the essays in the volume entitled
Examining in Harvard College: a collection of essays by members of the Harvard faculty,
Cambridge: Harvard University, 1963, and is held in the Widener, Gutman, and Sociology
libraries at Harvard, in addition to the Harvard University Archives.