Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

ACSA Intl 1998 68 PDF

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 4

323

1998 A C S A I N T E R N A T I O N A L C O N F E R E N C E

Space Architecture:
A Reinterpretation sf Its

MICHAEL K. JENSON
University of Colorado at Boulder

One of the most influential theoretical positions defining the predominant conception of architecture in the twentieth century has
been the conception that architecture is the art of creating and
defining space. However, though prevalent, the formulation of this
theory has contained no centralized singular manifestation. Consequently, this multiplicity of views on the subject has produced a
multitude of contradictory statements concerning the meaning and
value of the concept of architecture as space.'
The beginnings of the theory of space as a central idea within
architectural discourseemerged in the late nineteenthcentury concurrent with the appearance of the Art Nouveau movement. It was in this
movement that the tendencies to merge the notions of construction
and ornament into a unified aesthetic sensibility emerged, as well as
the development of a new type of spatial awareness that was more
highly abstracted than its predecessors. As a result, thecentral role that
the notion of space played within the foundational theories of this
early form of modernism was indicative of its later theoretical
emergence as the intrinsic attribute of modem ar~hitecture.~
This emergence of the idea of space as of the essential aspect of
architecture also coincided with the prevalent aesthetic theories of
the nineteenth century as defined by Hegel's system of aesthetic
understanding. Two prevalent ideas within this system stated that
true art attained the fullest expression of pure idea and that the
hierarchical order of the fine arts was to be circumscribed in relation
to the ability of the methodology of expression of the specific art
form to manifest the metaphysical properties of spirit. Consequently, as Cornelis Van de Ven asserts in his article on the role of
space, "The identification of space with architecture in the early
1890's promoted architecture, unquestionably, as the ars magna,
because space is, by definition the most immaterial of all means of
artistic expression."'
Despite its prevalence throughout much of the present century, this
theoretical stance has not been without its critics. A more recent
example of this criticism can be found in a text by the philosopher
Roger Scruton. In his book, The Aesthetics oj'Architect~re.~
Scruton
sets out to discover the essential qualities of the aesthetic understanding involved in the architectural endeavor. Scruton asserts that the
modemconception of spaceembodied by the statement of one modern
architect as; "the most difficult aspect of architecture, but it is its
essence and the ultimate destination to which architecture addresses
itself ' 5 iessentialist
~
by natureand cannot possibly describeall that we
appreciate inarchitecture. In fact, he contends that theconcept of space
as a central factor in our understanding of architecture is suspect,
because most theorists advocating this premise utilize architecture to
illustrate the meaning behind spatial experience. Due to this fact,
Scruton dismisses this reasoning as vacuous, circular, and fundamentally a functionalist argument masquerading as an aesthetic one.6
In attempting to search for the essential nature of this art and

before validity of Scruton's criticism can be assessed, there are


several questions that must be addressed. Only after the issues that
these questions raise are explored will it be possible to illustrate the
true role that the notion of space plays in this endeavor. In the first
instance; what is one describing fundamentally, when one is speaking of "space"? The second is two fold; what is the essential aspect
or intent that separates architecture from the other arts and why is it
necessary for humans to attempt its creation? Finally; how does
humankind's interaction with this attribute affect the human condition in both the physical and imaginative sense? It is the assertion of
this paper that after exploring the issues endemic to these questions,
Scruton's conception of space will emerge as being rather limited
because of its reliance on the scientific depiction of absolute space.
Once a more encompassing view of the nature of space is investigated, it will be possible to uncover its true relation to the architectural endeavor.

Our starting point for the exploration of the theory of space in


architecture will commence with an examination of two statements
made by Scruton in theopening paragraphs of thesection investigating its role in the creation of architecture. In the first, the assertion is
made that such a theory marginalizes much of thearchitect's activity
into the useless practice of creating a decorative container devoid of
both utility and meaning. A second assertion follows the lead of the
first, in its insinuation that one can experience all the spatial qualities
of an edifice such as St. Peter's in Rome by standing in an open field.
The only difference lies not in the change in the spatial configuration, but merely in the absence of the material envelope designed by
Bramante and Mi~helangelo.~Though
he immediately plays down
the significance of what each statement implies on the grounds of its
literal nature, they nevertheless underlie his criticism of the notion
of space as an intrinsic component to the essential nature of architecture.
These statements indicate aconception of space transposed by the
philosopher onto the ideas of prominent spatial theorists such as
Gidieon and Zevi, in a potentially inappropriate manner. Scruton
interprets their concepts as portraying the totality of our aesthetic
appreciation and value that we place on architecture rests exclusively on our experience of the remaining void (space) between the
constructed materiality of an edifice. In Architecture as Space; Zevi
clearly states that this is not the intention:
To maintain that internal space is the essence of architecture
does not mean that the value of an architectural work rests
entirely (my italics) on its spatial values.....Whileit is incontestable that beautiful decoration will never create beautiful space,
it is also true that a satisfactory space, if it is not complemented

324

by an adequate treatment of walls which enclose it is not


sufficient to create an aesthetic e n v i r ~ n m e n t . ~
So, whereas Zevi is attempting to describe space as inherently
multi-dimensional with a layering of aspects describing and defining
it, Scruton bases his assumption of its character on the scientific
notion of absolute space. This follows the Cartesian notion of space
as extension. By this, space is identical with that which constitutes
its spatiality, i.e., "length, breadth, and thickness."' It is that which
can be divided, shaped, and displaced in any way, yet still retains its
inherent nature through all such mutations.1 By this, space is
considered the remaining void between the material nature of the
physical world. This view is related to the negative perspective on
space expounded by theorists such as Riegl and Wolfflin, who spoke
of the "horrible vacuum' that surrounds our existence on earth. This
theory of the intrinsic spatial apprehension of humanity arose soon
after the "architecture as space" theory became prominent.'' It sees
the attribute of space in a similar fashion to both Descartes generally,
and Scruton more specifically, where the idea of space is based on
a reverse physicality that can only be measured in the negative. It is
considered the unoccupied emptiness between the surfaces of the
corporeal mass of the world's materiality.
This conception of space seems rather limited due to its oversight
in regards to an imperative characteristic of humankind's imaginative interaction with it, i.e. the space of habitation. This interpretation of the spatial characteristics of objective world addresses the
totality of its space inclusive of the subject's imagination, value
systems, and memories. It melds these characteristics to the more
concrete materiality of our world which is comprised of such
attributes as light, dark, material surface extension, and values of
scale. All that our senses perceive in the present as well as memories
of past encounters are incorporated to bring about a full experience
of space as phenomenon. This notion of the space of habitation is
described by Bachelard as; "Space that has been seized upon by the
imagination cannot remain indifferent space subject to the measures
andestimatesofthesurveyor. It has been livedin, not in its positivity,
but with all the partiality of the imagination.""
So, when the argument is presented for space as an essential
component of architecture, to be successful, it must allow for both
the idea of a geometricized spatiality as wcll as an imaginative one.
It also calls for a balance between the influence of mass and space on
our perception of architecture. Thus, the basis for this interpretation
demands that the various aspects of building such as materials,
decoration, and light are all intrinsic elements to the architectural
realm. Volumes, structures, and walls then, are the constitutive
elements serving as boundaries or interludes in the continuity of the
infinite space of the world. Such constructs and spatial relationships
function on several levels. The first is concerned with the notion of
abstract geometricized space, the second involves our perception
within the material present by our senses, while the third and final
one involves the spaces interpreted by the imagination which fuses
past, present, and future possibilities into a singular spatial experience.
T o consider, as Scruton does, that by the utilization of the
expression "space," one is describing a "void" between several
solids is a superficial view of a complex issue. The corporeal mass
of the envelope and the "vacancy of matter" found between must be
thought of in terms of its being a unified ensemble as inherently
interdependent components. The aesthetic spatiality of a building
must bejudged in relation to both of these attributes simultaneously.
These elements coalesce into an inhabitable environment that interacts with the faculty of the imagination. This subtle mixture of
elements composes more than a geometrically measurable void, it
constitutes a temporal, material, and spatial context where humanity
can dwell. It is a necessary element for that existence, both in terms
of a physical and spiritual survival. T o interpret the theory of "space
as architecture" as describing this essential attribute in reference

CONSTRUCTING NEW WORLDS

solelv to its ~eometricallvmeasured aspects is to miss Bachelard's


profound point that6'lnhabited space transcends geometrical space."13
The former interpretation dismisses the importance of the imagination, that attribute which speaks most to our aesthetic judgment.

To understand the notion of the creation of space as the potential


attribute that separates architecture from other mediums traditionally associated with the fine arts, it is important to analyze the
reasons whv the definition and demarcation of space is such an
imperative indertaking by humankind. Within thi;context several
pertinent questions emerge immediately. What force drives the
human race to construct material containers that manipulate or
"carve out" spatial environments from the absolute space contained
within the world? What is the force that drives thecreation ofedifices
enclosing space that range from the modest nature of singular
dwellings to the soaring sacred space found in cathedrals, mosques,
and palaces comprising the built environment? A potential answer
can seemingly be found in the aspect of necessity inherent to human
existence within the world.
In the creative process of the conception of architecture, necessity
contains a two-fold influence. The first, emerges as the need for the
creation of habitable space serving as protection from the hostile
forces of nature, while the second involves the human spirit's need
for artistic expression embodied in its attempts to manifest the
concept of beauty. The former has been deemed in certain intellectual circles as "the inventor of the arts." In a passage by Charles
Batteuxin his text, LesBeaux-Arts Reduita un Meme Principe,I4this
attribute of need is described as the most ingenious and best learned
in the true life lessons of all the masters of mankind.
Primitive humankind, having found himself cold, hungry, and
exposed to the dangers of the climate, searched for a place of refuge
under the branches of a nearby tree. After discovering the utility of
these branches, he soon learned that by the bringing together or the
joining of several trees in the formation of a primitive roof was more
effective in protecting himself, his family, and his provisions. As
time passed, these first observations and experiments were multiplied by others, which in turn werecompiled withmore sophisticated
notions of taste and industry that added ornament and ideas conceming solidity in the formation of a body of fundamental principles.
Thesecanons came to be seen as comprising the essential parameters
of architectural theory and the art-of building. Therefore, at its
essence, this art form was declared as the action of "making dwellings firm, convenient, and decent."I5 In other words, Batteux is
describing the primary action undertaken in the endeavor of building
conceptualized as the making of hospitable and formidable spaces
for man to dwell within.
This description outlines an account of a view of the formation of
this art claiming to have its origins in the mythical image of the
"primitive hut." This image served as the paradigm for a theory of
architecture that held thenecessity of shelter as the first and foremost
driving principle behind the manifestation of all built structures.
This intellectual lineage spawned a movement in the eighteenth
century that advocated the return to the ideas of the great ancient
authors on the subject such as Seneca, Lucretius, and most notably
Vitruvius, in the development of a doctrine that refused the ideas of
civilized progress in search of an essential nature of architecture
grounded within the structural and spatial beginnings of the archetypes of dwellings and m o n ~ m e n t s . ~saw
~ I t a return to a theoretical
foundation embedded in the mythical notions of the purity of spirit
and the innocence of the "primitive savage." This archetype stood as
the symbol of the innate goodness of humankind before his exposure
to the cormpting influences of civilization. This movement proposed a theory grounded in humankind's intrinsically natural mores,
one centering on an architectural morality that connected the necessities of function and symbolism.

1998 ACSA INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE

This conceptual tendency found an ardent disciple in the historian


and philosophe, Marc-Antoine Laugier17who pressed the formulation of an aesthetic logic from the mythical imagery of the narrative
of origins through the elimination of all material and social references from his manifesto. This process of elimination involving
what Laugier considered the superfluous baggage of the architectural endeavor was assumed to have left only the natural instinct or
"simple nature" of humankind to invent the most efficient and
authentic meansfor the satisfaction of Human need. The figure of the
"little rustic hut," as it was described by the author, depicted three
archetypal elements of architectural intervention relating to this act
of efficiency.
According to Anthony Vidler, these elements were: "those parts
of the building essential to the composition of the orders, those
introduced subsequently according to need, and those added simply
by caprice."18 Laugier considered that the authentic essence of
architecture could be found only within the first category and
equated materially to three basic components: the columns, the
entablature, and the roof. He went on further to claim that: "If each
of these three parts is found to be placed in the situation and in the
form suitable to it, there will be nothing to add for the work to be
perfect."'" It was felt that the quest for the embodiment of beauty as
well as the fulfillment of the need for shelter could be accomplished
in architecture within theelegant simplicity symbolized in the vision
of the "primitive hut."
Though claiming the opposite, this austere interpretation of the
metaphoric nature of origins contains merit in its acknowledgment
of the importance of necessity. However, its inherent singlemindedness ignores a paramount question pertaining to the creation
of architecture: What truly accounts for the emergence of the
aesthetic qualities or "art" of architecture if only pure material
necessity is addres~ed?~"A
possible answer emerges within Abbe
Batteux's claim of the impossibility of reducing architecture to a
singularorigin. Hecontended that it was and wouldalways bean"art
of necessity," but due to its intrinsic aspirations to reach a higher
plane of meaning it was an inherently mixed art form.21
Consequently, architecture was to be seen as being at once useful
and beautiful. It contained all the practical and societal requirements
of solidity,commodity,and pleasure, which are allelements grounded
within our perception of the guild related arts or crafts, but differs
from them because it cannot be judged solely on the merits of its
utilitarian nature. Nor could it be likened exclusively to what is
generally categorized as the fine arts because it must achieve more
than merely pleasing certain senses such as sight and sound. It forms
a distinct third category, one which resides between these two
categories of expression; the fine arts and the crafts of necessity. On
one level, this endeavor is an art of convenience and comfort which
is raised above this aspect of invention driven by need, through its
development according to the attribute of taste which inevitably
rests on the imitation of nature. Consequently, it seems that the
essential nature of architecture either as space or any other element,
pertains to more than the mere fulfillment of the human need for
shelteror inhabitable space. It entails another element in the equation
of necessity that drives men to push for a higher ideal in the creation
of the spatial constructs of architecture.
In his seminal text on aesthetics, the philosopher G.W.F. Hegel
describes an intrinsic need of the spirit that seems to relate directly
to this secondary notion of necessity. This aspect drives humans to
create works of art such as architecture that go beyond the mere
fulfillment of material need and desire. It seeks to fulfill a universal
"need of the spirit" through attempts at the material manifestation of
theelusiveconcept of beauty. Hegel describes this spiritual quest as;
'The universal need for art, that is to say, is man's rational need to
lift the inner and outer world into his spiritual consciousness as an
object in which he recognizes again his own ~elf."*~The
universal
need described in this quote finds its origin in the inherent quality of
the being of humankind as a reflective consciousness. Such a

325

consciousness or self-realization can occur in two distinct ways that


are intricately connected.
The first method is theoretical in nature, while the second is
embodied throughpractical action. In the former, there is an inherent drive to discover the intrinsic qualities that define such a
consciousness. This entails attempts to translate the emotional state
of humankind into a self-conscious image that defines its essential
attributes and what it is related to within the objective world. In the
latter, the needs of this consciousness are fulfilled through practical
activity, which satisfy impulses to alter external things in ways that
impress upon them the seal of humankind's inner Being. Such
activity shapes this external material into forms that becomes manifest objects of an external realization of this consciousness. Such
activity is endemic to all human labor, but practical activity in
regards to the artistic endeavor pushes beyond the normalcy of this
in the everyday sense and in doing so raises two expectations. Again,
to quote Hegel;
The work of art, present to sense, should give lodgment to an
inner-content, while on the other hand, it should so present this
content as to make us realize that this content itself, as well as
its outward shape is not merely something real in the actual and
immediately present world, but is a product of the imagination
and its artistic activity."
So, in terms of Hegel's argument, the essential quality of a work
of art consists in the symbolic content of the sensuous material
manipulated in reference to the interpretation of an event by the
imagination. A form created in this fashion attempts to duplicate the
parameters of the objective world in a certain way so as to improve
ones' conscious understanding of it.
In terms of our argument involving the creation of space as the
essential element that separates architecture from the other arts,
several of the ideas put forth in both Laugier's and Hegel's texts
could be combined and utilized to provide a description of this
attribute that counters Scruton's claim against its central position
within this endeavor. With such a combination, architecture could
then be described as the distinctly human endeavor of creating
inhabitable spatial environments in which to dwell. To be rightfully
classified as such, it must satisfy humankind's needs in the material
sense, through the provision of shelter, and in the spiritual sense,
through the material manifestation of spaces semantically charged
that challenge the rational powers of those residing within its
enclosures.
In Ruskin's description concerning the virtues of architecture in
The Stones of Venice, a similiar point involving the duality of its
intended ends is made quite eloquently; "It is not, therefore, that the
signs of his affections, which man leaves upon his work, are indeed
more ennobling than the signs of his intelligence, but it is the balance
of both whose expression we need...."24 Therefore, it serves to
protect the inhabitants of its spaces from both enemies and harsh
climatic conditions through the aptitude and strength of its enclosures, while simultaneousl y providing an outlet for the fundamental
striving for the creation and admiration of beauty that the artistic
enterprise fulfills. Architecture then. has the potential to be considered the creation of a spatially structured environment that enriches
our experience of the world and is a necessary element which
humans strive to create.

The final question that must be addressed to fully lay bare the
implications surrounding the notion of space as the essential attribute in the creation of architecture pertains to how humankind
inhabits and interacts with it as a structured spatial environment. It
is here that the nature of the reciprocal relationship of humankind
and spaceemerges. This relationshipentails humankind defining the
spatial structure of an architectural edifice, which in turn, conies to

CONSTRUCTING NEW WORLDS

326

obtain a profound influence on thedefinition of his activity and even


his nature. It is this interaction that separates the architectural
endeavor from the other arts. Though other arts such as painting or
sculpture can have a profound emotional effect and carry with them
an incredibly charged semantic content, they lack the capacity to
create or demarcate a place. For architecture essentially seeks to
create spaces in which one can dwell, and it is the aspect of dwelling
within such spaces that orders as well as bestows its sense of purpose
and meaning. And it is this ability to dwell within the artifacts of this
enterprise that gives architecture its unique character in relation to
the other arts.
When one inhabits architectural space, the experiential qualities
of this encounter d o not consist solely of geometrically based
relationships of substances or volumes, but of the occupation of such
spaces by the faculty of the imagination. When this faculty inhabits
the spatial boundaries of a place, it utilizes past experiences, dreams,
future possibilities, and even latent fears in the constitution of the
essential parameters that give meaning to its space. Such a faculty
sin~ultaneouslyreacts and constructs the experience of the space it
encounters. Thus, habitation of architectural space is not exclusively
a passive venture, but a rationally active one as well.
Considered in this sense, the spatial qualities of a house are not
experienced merely in terms of its being an inert box with six static
sides. Humans intrinsically attach to such spaces values such as
"protective" or "sacred," which carry both real and imagined connotations. With spatial perceptions of this sort, the spectator loses the
detached analytical gaze of the cartographer attempting to scientifically measure space, and engages it in the same emotional and
intellectual state that one interacts with art. However, unlike the
other artifacts of art, the encounter with the space of architecture is
within the context of the everyday, in fact, it comprises this very
context. This is how, unlike other art forms, architecture is simultaneously ordered by and orders humankind's habitation olits spaces.
Architectural space is experienced or "lived in," both in the material
sense of an organism existing within the boundaries of a place and
in the more spiritual sense as described by Bachelard in the earlier
statement quoted above as being experienced; "with all the partiality
of the i m a g i n a t i ~ n . " ~ ~
When wedwell within the space of architccture this way, connections are observed between its boundaries and many of the essential
notions pertaining to our manner of perceiving, thinking, and feeling. Likewise, a spatial order can also be indicative of temporal
passage, for it can have contained within its confines, remnants of
significant past events that allow it to become a symbolic focal point
representative of past histories, present events, and future possibilities simultaneously. Through its survival of the effects of dramatic
past events, an edifice becomes the material manifestation of a
historical mythology that lends added significance to the lives of
both the individual and its culture within its spatial boundaries. It
provides both the artifact and the metaphoric backdrop to the human
imagination's experience of past and present events. The ordering of
space endemic to the creation of our sense of place serves as the
perpetual reminder of the world's temporal sequence. In doing this,
it gives humankind a foundational knowledge in regards to what has
been accomplished before, and in providing this link to the past,
indicates potential avenues for the future.
This reciprocal relationship between the demarcation of place
spatially and the definition of human nature occurs in a sinlultaneity
of scales ranging from the individual domicile to that of an entire
city. Architecturedivides continuous or absolute space according to
the scale necessary for the activities of repose, labor, worship, or
recreation. In the constitution of such orders, a spatial reinforcing of
the societal hierarchy perseveres and is handed down from generation to generation. No design, construction or experience of a
building can be void of the cultural imagery and technological
advancement of the society that created it. Architecture must con-

stantly modulate human activities endemic to our dwelling within an


environment conducive to the definition of both personal and cultural identities simultaneously. Therefore, a spatial construct on an
urban scale or a wall on an individual scale are not simply located by
whim or caprice. Their form and location relate directly to the
complex nature of humanity's spatial experience, which is at once
both p h y s ~ ~ aand
l spiritual. The spatial orders of architectural
constructs define and serve as a backdrop to every individual
perception of culture, emotional insight, and possible sense of
fulfillment.
Hence, the concept of space, as an intrinsic element to the
architectural endeavor can never be envisioned as merely being the
"void" contained between the material nature of its enclosing structures. Space, in this sense, must be thought of more in terms of an
environment or surroundings comprised of qualities such as light,
sound, and materiality that influence human -perception
and spark
the faculty of the imagination. It is the design and manipulation of
these aswcts in an intentional effort to transform our e x ~ e r i e n c eof
space that distinguishes architecture from the other arts. Though the
other arts can interact with or represent space, none can truly define
it in a real sense, and it is this definition that impacts our lives within
the context of the everyday both physically and spiritually. So, in the
creation of architecture unlike any of the other fine arts, space is
being defined and our experience of it is being enhanced. This act,
in essence, speaks of the authentic and fundamental nature of
architecture.

NOTES
Cornelis Vande Ven, "The Theory of Space in Architecture" in Conrpanion To Contemporary Architecturd Thought, eds. Ben Farmer and
Mentie Louw (New York: Routledge, 1993), p. 357.
? Van de Ven, p. 357
' Ibid.
Roger Scruton, The Aesthetics cflArchitect~rre(Princeton,NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1979).
Denys Lasdun in RIBAJ (September 1977):367. Scruton, op. cit., p. 43.
"cruton, p. 48.
' Scmton, p. 43.
Bruno Zevi, Space U S Architecture (New York: Horizon Press, 1957).p.
30.
This follows adescription of Descartes's theory of spacegiven by Martin
Heidegger in Being and Tinle, trans. by J . Macquarrie and E. Robinson
(Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1962),p. 123.
'O Heidegger. p. 125.
' I Van de Ven, p. 359.
I? Gaston Bachelard, The Poetics of Space (Boston: Beacon Press, 1994),
p. XXXVI.
" Bachelard, p. 47.
l4 Charles Baneux, Les Beaux-arts reduits a un merue principe, 2d ed.
(Paris: 1776), p. 24-26. Anthony Vidler, The Writing of The Walls
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, l987), p. 7.
l5 Vidler, p. 7.
l6 Vidler, p. 7-8.
" Marc-AntoineLaugier,An E.~sayo~~Architect~lre(Los
Angeles: Hennessey
& Ingals, Inc.).
l H Vidler, p. 19.
Iy First quoted in Vidler, p. 19, from the original text by Laugier, Essuisur
l'urchirecture. 2d ed. (Paris: 1755). p. 10.
?" Vidler, p. 20.
? ' Ibid.
" G.W.F. Hegel, Aesrhetics (Oxford: Claredon Press, 1975). p. 31; also
quoted in Paul Crowther's article, "Art, Architecture, and Self-conscious: An Exploration of Hegel's Aesthetic," Journal cflPhilosopphyand
The Visuul Arts (1990): 66.
?3 Hegel, p. 635; also Crowther, p. 66.
" John Ruskin, The Stones of Venice (London:J. M. Dent & CO.,1907),p.
38-39.
" Bachelard, p. XXXVII. See also, note 13 above.
I

You might also like