McGinn's Ethics, Evil, and Fiction
McGinn's Ethics, Evil, and Fiction
McGinn's Ethics, Evil, and Fiction
648656
650
NOS
Before concluding, McGinn rounds off the book with two chapter-length
discussions of novels, Wildes Dorian Gray and Shelleys Frankenstein. As I
understand the function of these chapters in the book, the one on Dorian Gray
is intended to explore further the aesthetic theory of virtue. The chapter on Frankenstein, I think, is meant to send us back to the chapter on evil, particularly
to the discussion of the conditions of genesis from which the evil character
~the evil person! emerges. McGinn emphasizes that Shelleys book teaches that
the plight of Frankensteins monster could befall anyone. But what surprised
me about this chapter was that McGinn did not make more of the relevance of
his notion of existential envy here, since arguably that is the source of the Frankenstein monsters evil.
As well, as interpretations of the relevant texts, these chapters are somewhat
disappointing, since they add little that is new to a literary understanding of these
classics. This is a perhaps predictable outcome, insofar as McGinn shows little
familiarity with other scholarship on these books. Thus, it is a bit of a letdown
to encounter these explications as the proof of McGinns recommended reorientation of moral philosophy toward literary criticism.
McGinn concludes by returning to the theme that moral philosophy would
profit by taking literary fiction more seriously than it presently does. Moral discourse, as exemplified by the Bible, can be divided into two sorts: moral directives and parables. Moral philosophers, by focusing so intently on directives,
pay scant attention to parables, of which literary fiction is a prime example. But,
McGinn argues, narrative plays a crucial, formative role in moral experience,
geared as it is to scrutiny of particularsparticular persons and particular situations. Moreover, highly detailed stories are more likely to elicit more consensus than universalized moral principles and, thereby, to be highly revealing
about our moral concepts. If for no other reason, this should be a compelling
reason for moral philosophers to consult literature more often than they do. Thus
McGinn concludes where he began.
McGinn has the idea that the parable form activates moral knowledge that
we already possess and thereby becomes a pretext for rediscovering moral knowledge. This fits nicely with his notion that moral knowledge is a priori, though
he does not deal with longstanding worries that the moral insights derived
from fiction have been rhetorically rigged by their authors and that fictions
provide no confirmation, internal to the text, of the putative moral knowledge
they elicit from readers. Thus, though people like me who already subscribe to
McGinns viewpoint are happy to cheer his conclusions, I suspect the skeptic
will find the argument incomplete.
Since the most radical thought in this altogether radical book is McGinns
defense of the aesthetic theory of virtue, I will devote most of my commentary
to it. The theory maintains that virtue correlates with beauty of soul and vice
with ugliness. McGinn believes this thesis is literally true. Why?
First, the thesis makes sense out of a great deal of ordinary moral discourse
which is characteristically charged aesthetically. We speak of virtuous people,
652
NOS
for example, as pure and stainless, whereas evil people are foul, rotten, slimy, repulsive, toxic, and so on. The best explanation of these linguistic tendencies is that deep down we believe the aesthetic theory of virtueit
is what governs attributions like these. Furthermore, the aesthetic theory of virtue explains certain prominent regularities in our artistic practices. Why, in religious paintings for example, are saints depicted as beautiful? Again, because
deep down we believe the aesthetic theory of virtue, and the best way to express the conviction that beautiful souls are beautiful is to portray them as perceptibly beautifuleven if beauty of soul and perceptible beauty are different
and not necessarily convergent. Moreover, though presently out of fashion, the
aesthetic theory of virtue was an article of faith among moral theorists from
Plato to Shaftesbury, and, as well, is presupposed in literary works like Dorian
Gray, whose readers find little difficulty in assimilating it.
These considerations, however, only support the hypothesis that there is an
enduring mythology of the aesthetic theory of virtue. They corroborate the fact
that people have believed it in the past and that the remnants of that belief live
on in our language and its vocabulary, and in our art. That that mythology once
gripped peoples imagination in no way argues in behalf of the truth of the aesthetic theory of virtue. As McGinn is well aware, stronger arguments are required for that. And, of course, he obliges.
Needless to say, when McGinn speaks of the beauty of the soul, he is not
speaking of perceptible beauty. It is inner beauty, beauty that supervenes on virtue. He argues that evidence for the aesthetic theory of virtue includes that we
would not say someone were good, unless they possessed some inward beauty
~inward beauty is a necessary condition for being virtuous!. But, if I understand the thesis, it seems strained. Beauty of soul, if there is such a thing, would,
I presume, be striking, as perceptible beauty is. It could be subtle, but once
detected, it would be arresting. But most people are probably on the whole
virtuousgoodyet they are not striking with respect to inner beauty. Inner
beauty, if you are disposed to talk this way, might be the property of saints. But
there are many ordinary virtuous people who do not radiate inner beauty. Thus,
if the intuition that no person can be good and have no beauty of soul is supposed to support the aesthetic theory of virtue, I am not convinced that it is up
to the task.
McGinn also maintains that the possession of inner beauty is sufficient for
attributing inner beauty to persons. Perhaps this is connected to his view that
there are not any terms that describe the soul aesthetically that are morally neutral. But that seems wrong. Does McGinn count elegance as an aesthetic property? If he does, can we not imagine an evil genius whose mind is so elegant in
its operation, even given the ugliness of the projects to which he puts it, that its
brilliance and elegance are not over-shadowedmaybe even to the point where
we might concede that, on balance, his soul ~his mind! is ~inwardly! arrestingly beautiful. But then beauty of soul is not sufficient for attributions of the
possession of virtue.
654
NOS
But McGinn is ready for guys like me, and he has two arguments against us.
The first, following Thomas Reid, is that no physical thing ~no perceptible thing!
is intrinsically beautiful, but is beautiful rather because it expresses a mental
act which is the original source of the beauty. Thus, beautiful things, like paintings, inherit their perceptible beauty from imperceptible mental acts. Consequently, there should be no problem in calling souls ~minds! beautiful. Secondly,
it is not true that beauty talk is only reserved for perceptible things. Mathematical proofs and chess solutions are frequently called beautiful, and these need
not be perceptible.
The first argument seems to have little to recommend it, since Reids expressivism must be misguided; beautiful things in nature, like the starry sky at
night, do not inherit their beauty from any mental acts. Moreover, the second
argument appears to me to be inconclusive. Mathematicians do call proofs beautiful, but there is a real question here about whether they are speaking metaphorically. McGinn is aware of this possible line of objection, but he seems to
me to dismiss it with an argument that is way too hasty.
He points out that with respect to many aesthetically evaluable items, perhaps like pieces of music, aesthetic predicates, say sadness, are applied as
literal descriptors of perceptible configurations, such as, for example, sound
configurations. Though such aesthetic descriptions may be metaphorical, they
need not be. They may be literal. And this is true. But it does not seem to dispel the anxiety that the mathematicians use of the term beautiful is not a metaphorical use of the literal aesthetic concepts of beauty that we antecedently
apply to artworks. McGinn, I feel, still owes us a much more developed account of why we cannot consign the application of aesthetic terms, like beauty,
to imperceptibilia, like theorems and souls, to the realm of metaphor, namely
metaphors derived from literal aesthetic attributions to artworks.
In addition to defending the aesthetic theory of virtue, McGinn elaborates
some consequences that he thinks it suggests. One is a kind of aesthetic environmentalism. Beautiful environments, notably beautiful cultural environments,
stimulate the cultivation of the beautiful soul ~beautiful personhood!, whereas
aesthetic pollution has a tendency to lead to moral pollution... ~pp. 120121!
The mechanism here is mimicry; humans have a tendency to imitate. Surrounded
by beauty, including beautiful music, beautiful architecture, and so on, one has
an inclination to imitate it, to internalize it so that one might become a more
beautiful soul ~p. 120!.
I find this conjecture pretty imponderable. Since beauty of the soul is distinct from the beauty of objects, why should beauty in the latter sense, even if
it is imitated ~however one imitates beautiful architecture!, be conducive to
beauty in the former sense? The two sorts of beauty are so utterly different.
Likewise, in his discussion of evil, McGinn suggests that the violence of popular culture, including not only films and rock music, but sports, may afford a
dangerous precondition for the gestation of evil souls. For evil takes pleasure
from pain, and popular media depictions of violence associate pleasure with it.
656
NOS