A Positive Account of Property Rights - David Friedman PDF
A Positive Account of Property Rights - David Friedman PDF
A Positive Account of Property Rights - David Friedman PDF
BY DAVID FRIEDMAN
Judith Jarvis Thomson, The Realm of Rights (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1990).
2
Or the equivalent in civil rather than criminal terms.
1994 Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation. Printed in the USA.
DAVID FRIEDMAN
accounts seem irrelevant, given the attitude of Argentina toward the British claim. Yet the willingness of Britain to accept costs far out of proportion to the value of the prize being fought over is difficult to explain
except on the theory that the British felt they were defending their property, which raises the question of what that concept means in such a
context.
A further difficulty with moral accounts of rights, in particular of property rights, is the degree to which the property rights that people actually respect seem to depend on facts that are morally irrelevant. This
difficulty presents itself in libertarian accounts of property as the problem
of initial acquisition. It is far from clear even in principle how unowned
resources such as land can become private property. Even if one accepts
an account, such as that of Locke, of how initial acquisition might justly
have occurred, that account provides little justification for the existing
pattern of property rights, given the high probability that any piece of
property has been unjustly seized at least once since it was first cleared.
Yet billions of people, now and in the past, base much of their behavior
on respect for property claims that seem either morally arbitrary or clearly
unjust.
A further difficulty with legal accounts of rights is that they are to some
degree circular. We observe that police will act in certain ways and that
their actions (and related actions by judges, juries, etc.) imply that certain
people have certain rights. But the behavior of police is itself in part a consequence of rightssuch as the right of the state to collect taxes and pay
them to the police as wages, and the property right that the police then
have over the money they receive.
For all of these reasons, I believe it is worth attempting a positive
account of rightsan account which is both amoral and alegal. In Section I of this essay, I present such an account-one in which rights, in
particular property rights, are a consequence of strategic behavior and
may exist with no moral or legal support.3 The account is presented both
3
1 would like to thank James Buchanan for bringing Schelling points to my attention and
Gordon Tullock for provoking me into exploring them further. See especially Winston Bush,
"Individual Welfare in Anarchy," in Explorations in the Tiieory of Anarchy, ed. Gordon Tullock (Blacksburg: University Publications, 1973).
5
This point is made by Gordon Tullock in "Corruption and Anarchy," in Tullock, ed.,
Further Explorations.
DAVID FRIEDMAN
because each finds it in his own interest to do so. What is it that we have
and the Hobbesian jungle does not have that makes it in the interest of
people to behave in a law-abiding and peaceful manner? To say that the
answer is "police, courts, government" only throws the question back a
step; if civil order is enforced by men with guns, what controls them?
There are two sorts of answers to these questions. One is that the difference is a moral one. People somehow accept an obligation, agree not
to behave according to simple self-interest, feel themselves bound by that
agreement, and alter their actions accordingly.
There are difficulties with this sort of explanation. First, there is the
empirical observation that people do not feel themselves bound to obey
laws; many, perhaps most, people feel free to violate those laws (speed
limits, drinking laws, customs regulations) which they disagree with and
believe they can get away with breaking. Second, to the extent that people do feel a moral obligation to obey social rules, it is hard to derive that
feeling from any variant of social-contract theory. The traditional variants
encounter the difficulty eloquently described by Lysander Spooner:6
since we ourselves did not sign the contract, we are not bound by it.
The difficulties with deriving moral obligation from the sort of pairwise
social contract suggested by Winston Bush7 are equally great. Even if we
consider that each of us is, at every instant, in an implicit contract with
each of his neighbors to respect some agreed-upon set of rights, still that
contract, in Bush's model, is based on the threat of coercion. It has no
more moral legitimacy, according to conventional moral ideas, than the
obligation to pay off a protection racket.
It may be possible to explain the difference between a Hobbesian state
of nature and civil society as a moral difference, but I prefer the alternative explanation-that the essential difference is not in the motivation of
the players but in the strategic situation they face. This raises the question of how making an agreementin a society with no mechanisms for
enforcing agreementscan change anything, the strategic situation
included.
A. The tool: Schelling points8
2,5,9,25,69,73,82,96,100,126,150
Two people are separately confronted with the list of numbers shown
above and offered a reward if they independently choose the same num6
Lysander Spooner, No Treason: No. VI, Tlie Constitution of No Authority (1870; reprint,
Larkspur, CO: Pine Tree Press, 1966).
7
Bush, "Individual Welfare in Anarchy."
8
Thomas C. Schelling, Vie Strategy of Conflict (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1960),
ch. 3. While I am using Schelling's concept, my analysis of it, in particular my grounds for
applying it to games with communication, is somewhat different from his.
ber. If the two are mathematicians, it isiikely that they will both choose
2the only even prime. Nonmathematicians are likely to choose 100
a number which seems, to the mathematicians, no more unique than the
other two exact squares. Illiterates might agree on 69, because of its peculiar symmetryas would, for a different reason, those whose interest in
numbers is more prurient than mathematical.
There are three things worth noting about this simple problem in coordination without communication. The first is that each pair of players is
looking for a number that is in some way unique. To a mathematician, all
three squares are special numbers, as are the three primes. But if they try
to coordinate on a square or a prime, they have only one chance in three
of successand besides, one may be trying primes and the other squares.
The number 2 is unique. If the set of numbers did not contain 2 but did
contain only one prime (or only one square, or one perfect number) they
would choose that.
The second thing to note is that there is no single right answer; the
number chosen by one player, and hence the number that ought to be
chosen by the other, depends on the categories that the person choosing
uses to classify the alternatives. The right strategy is to find some classification in terms of which there is a unique number, then choose that
numbera strategy whose implementation depends on the particular
classifications that pair of players uses. Thus, the right answer depends
on subjective characteristics of the players.
The third point, which follows from this, is that it is possible to succeed
in the game because of, not in spite of, the bounded rationality of the
players. To a mind of sufficient scope every number is unique.9 It is only
because the players are limited to a small number of the possible classification schemes for numbers, and because the two players may be limited to the same schemes, that a correct choice may exist. In this respect
the theory of this game is radically different from conventional game
theory, which assumes players with unlimited ability to examine alternatives and thus abstracts away from all subjective characteristics of the
players except those embodied in their utility functions.10
Consider now two players playing the game called bilateral monopoly.
They have a dollar to divide between them, provided they can agree on
9
There is a semi-serious theorem according to which all integers are interesting. The
proof is by induction. If some positive integers are uninteresting, then there must be a
smallest positive uninteresting integer. But this unique characteristic makes that number
interesting. So there can be no smallest uninteresting positive integer, so there can be no
uninteresting positive integers. Similarly, mutatis mutandis, for negative integers.
10
In practice, game theory sometimes smuggles subjective characteristics back into the
argument in the process of choosing a particular strategy set. A famous example of this problem is the analysis of oligopoly. The assumption that the firm's strategy is defined as a choice
of quantity and the assumption that it is defined as a choice of price lead to very different
conclusions. See David Friedman, Price Titeory: An Intermediate Text (Cincinnati: Southwestern Publishing Co., 1990), ch. 11.
DAVID FRIEDMAN
1 have discussed this point, and the game of bilateral monopoly, at greater length in
David Friedman, "Bilateral Monopoly: A Solution," Fels Discussion Paper No. 52, University of Pennsylvania, March 1974 (unpublished, available from the author).
tives of the game, and thus changing the Schelling points which depend
on those categories.
In the case just discussed, for example, one player (presumably the
richer) might remind the other of their shared belief in the importance of
utility in order to make sure the equi-utility Schelling point would be chosen. If, in the first game I described, the players were allowed to talk
before seeing the numbers, a conversation on the interesting properties
of primes or the special uniqueness of the lowest of a series of numbers
might well alter the Schelling point, and thus the result of the game. One
can interpret a good deal of bargaining behavior in this lightas an
attempt by one party to make the other see the situation in a particular
way, so as to generate a Schelling point favorable to the first party.
A slightly different way in which one may conceptualize the process of
agreement on a Schelling point is in terms of bargaining costs in a context of continuous bargaining.12 Consider a situation in which the number of possible outcomes is very large. Suppose the process of bargaining
is itself costly, either because it consumes time or because each player
bears costs (such as staying out on strike) in trying to validate his threats.
As long as the players are faced with a choice among a large number of
comparable alternatives, each proposal by one player is likely to call forth
a competing proposal from another, slanted a little more toward his own
interest.
But suppose there is one outcome that is seen as unique. A player who
proposes that outcome may be perceived as offering, not a choice between that outcome, another slightly different, another different still, . . .
but a choice between that outcome and continued bargaining. A player
who says that he insists on the unique outcome and will not settle for
anything less may be believable, where a similar statement about a different outcome would not be. He can convincingly argue that he will
stand by his proposed outcome because, once he gives it up, he has no
idea where he will end up or how high the costs of getting there will be.
In order for a Schelling point to provide a peaceful resolution to a conflict of interest, both parties must conceptualize the alternatives in similar wayssimilar enough so that they can agree about which possible
outcomes are unique, and thus attractive as potential Schelling points. So
one interesting implication of the argument is that violent conflict is especially likely to occur on the boundary between cultures, where people
with very different ways of viewing the world interact.
B. Up from Hobbes
Two people are living in a Hobbesian state of nature. Each can injure
or steal from the other, at some cost, and each can spend resources on his
12
This approach is discussed in Friedman, "Many, Few, One" (supra note 3).
DAVID FRIEDMAN
through on it and because you have less reason to resist it. Before, the
attempt to get a bushel of apples from you would have been an attempt
to move you away from the Schelling point established by the initial contract. Now it is an attempt to restore the Schelling point established by
our subsequent agreement.
A more conventional explanation of this is that the reason it is in your
interest to deliver the apples once you have agreed to do so is that you
wish to establish a reputation for keeping promises, and that the reason
it is in my interest to punish you if you do not deliver the apples is
because I wish to establish a reputation for enforcing contracts made with
me. While this may be true, there are two reasons why it cannot be a
complete explanation. First, it depends on a particular perception of consistent behaviorin pure logic, there is no more reason to think of
"always enforce" as more consistent than "back down the first, third,
fifth, . . . time and fight the second, fourth, sixth, . . . time." Each
describes a single possible strategy. The important difference between
them is that the former is a Schelling point and the latter is nota fact not
about the strategies but about the way we classify them.
A second and related problem with the conventional account is that I
might equally well wish to establish a reputation as a consistent extortionist. We need some way of explaining why I cut down the shade tree first,
instead of simply committing myself to demand your apples. If the former pattern creates a Schelling point of contract fulfillment and the latter does not, that provides a possible explanation.
I believe I have now resolved the apparent paradox of contracting out
of the Hobbesian jungle. The process of contracting changes the situation
because it establishes new Schelling points, which in turn affect the strategic situation and its outcome. The same analysis can be used from the
other side to explain what constitutes civil society. The laws and customs
of civil society are an elaborate network of Schelling points. If my neighbor annoys me by growing ugly flowers, I do nothing. If he dumps his
garbage on my lawn, I retaliatepossibly in kind. If he threatens to dump
garbage on my lawn, or play a trumpet fanfare at 3 A.M. every morning,
unless I pay him a modest tribute, I refuseeven if I am convinced that
the available legal defenses would cost more than the tribute he is
demanding.
If a policeman arrests meeven for a crime I did not commitI go
along peacefully. If he tries to rob my house, I fight, even if the cost of
doing so is more than the direct cost of letting him rob me. Each of us
knows what behavior by everyone else is within the rules and what
behavior implies unlimited demands, the violation of the Schelling point,
and the ultimate return to the Hobbesian jungle. The latter behavior is
prevented by the threat of conflict even if (as in the British defense of the
Falklands) the direct costs of surrender are much lower than the direct
costs of conflict.
One question this raises is how we succeed in committing ourselves not
10
DAVID FRIEDMAN
to back down in such situations. One answer has been suggested already.
It is in my long-run interest not to back down because if I do I can expect
further demands: "[I]f once you have paid him the danegeld/You never
get rid of the Dane." 13
This explanation is not entirely adequate. In some situations, the
aggressor may be able to commit himself to keeping your surrender secret
and limiting his own demands. In others, the short-run costs of resistance
may be larger than the long-run costs of surrender.
People (and nations) do sometimes surrender to such demands. If they
do so less often than a simple calculation of costs and benefits might predict, the explanation may be found in a class of arguments made by Robert Frank and others.14
The central insight of such arguments is that even if surrender is sometimes in my private interest, being the sort of person who will surrender
when it is in his interest to do so may not be, since if it is known that I
will not back down, there is no point in making the initial demand.15 My
first best option is to pretend to be tough, in the hope that the demand
will not be made, while reserving the option of surrendering if my bluff
is called. If, however, humans are imperfectly able to lie to each other
about what sort of people they areas seems to be the casethen the
best available option may be to really be tough, despite the risk that I will
occasionally find myself forced to fight when I would be better off surrendering.
None of this argument depends on moral sanctions. I may (indeed do)
believe that the tax collector is morally equivalent to the robber. I accept
one and fight the other because of my beliefs about other people's behaviorwhat they will or will not fight forand because there are beliefs
about my behavior which I wish others to hold. We are bound together
by a set of mutually reinforcing strategic expectations.
II. Two ROUTES FROM HOBBES TO HERE
11
Robert Ellickson, Order without Law (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1991).
See my review of Ellickson: David Friedman, "Less Law than Meets the Eye," Michigan Law Review, vol. 90, no. 6 (May 1992), pp. 1444-52.
17
12
DAVID FRIEDMAN
1 apologize to mathematicians and my fellow economists for using "local" and "global"
in senses that may seem inconsistent with their usual usage in classifying maxima; I will be
happy to consider suggestions for alternative terminology. To make my usage of the terms
seem less idiosyncratic, think of a change in norms involving only two people as a small
change and one involving many as a large change, and think of an "improvement" as a
change to a situation that is Pareto superior for those who are changing. Then a locally
efficient set of norms, like a local optimum, is one that cannot be improved by a small
change.
For a more mathematically elaborate approach to defining small and large changes and
using them to analyze the evolution of rules in a population, see Friedman, "Bilateral
Monopoly" (supra note 11).
19
A slightly different way of putting this argument is in terms of what Richard Dawkins
has described as the evolution of "memes": ideas evolving in an environment consisting of
the minds of humans. See Richard Dawkins, Vie Selfish Gene (New York: Oxford University Press, 1976), pp. 203-15. One reason a meme-such as the belief that "one ought to be
honest toward honest people"will spread is that those holding it are observed to be more
successful as a result. But in order for the process to get past the early stage, when the meme
13
In thinking about issues of rights, I find myself playing two quite different roles. As a human being and (like all human beings) an amateur
philosopher, I have moral intuitions; from that standpoint, the question
I ask is "Why ought one not to steal?" and the answer is "Because it is
wicked." As an economist, I ask and answer different questions. One is
"What are the consequences of people being free to steal?" Much of the
economic analysis of law is devoted to answering questions of that sort.
Another is "Why do people (often) not steal?"
This essay is an attempt to answer that final sort of question. I have
tried to answer the economist's question about rights rather than the philosopher's, not because economics is more important than moral philosophy, but because I am more confident in my ability to use economics to
produce answers. 21 1 have been encouraged in this policy by a curious
and convenient coincidence: in most cases, the rules I conclude to be efficient are also the rules I believe to be just.
It is not a double but a triple coincidence. The rules I believe to be efficient and just are also, to a significant degree, the rules enforced by the
laws and norms of the society I live in.22 In this essay, I have sketched
some ideas about the nature of those rules and how they have evolved.
is still rare in the population, it must be useful to hold the meme even when most other people do not. This works for memes representing norms such as honesty, but it does not work
for a meme for conservation of whales. It is accordingly puzzling that memes in favor of conservation have spread so rapidly in the current U.S. populationto the point where belief
in conservation has become very nearly the secular equivalent of a state religion.
20
To put the argument in something closer to conventional-game-theory terms, I am
combining a familiar concept of dominance in multiplayer games with the idea of transaction costs. Outcome A dominates outcome B if there is some set of people who together can
produce A and w h o all prefer A to B. A small number of people can produce a change
such as the adoption of a norm among themselvesthat only involves changing their own
behavior. A large group, because of transaction costs, cannot.
21
This point is discussed in David Friedman, Vie Machinery of Freedom, 2d ed. (La Salle,
IL: Open Court. 1989), chs. 41-43.
22
The correspondence is not perfect; it would be in some ways closer if I were writing
this essay a century ago. A particular form of the correspondencethe claim that the common law tends to be economically efficienthas been a central element of the work of Judge
Richard Posner, one of the leading scholars in the law-and-economics tradition. See Richard Posner, Economic Analysis of Law, 4th ed. (Boston: Little Brown, 1992).
14
DAVID FRIEDMAN
This raises the question of why, if my account is correct, the rules produced in this way resemble those that I deduce to be efficient and intuit
to be just.
In trying to answer that question, I find it useful to start by considering a class of property which underlies all other property and exists even
in a Hobbesian state of nature.
I can control the motions of my body by a simple act of will. You can
control its motions by imposing overwhelming force, by making believable threats to which I will yield, or in various other ways. Controlling it
may be possible for both of us, but it is much cheaper and easier for me.
In this sense, we may describe my body as my natural property. The
same description applies to my gunbecause I know where I hid it and
you do not. Even land may be natural property to some extent if my
detailed knowledge of the terrain makes it easier for me to use or defend
it. Such property is natural inasmuch as my possession of it exists in the
state of nature and is independent of social convention. The fact that I can
control certain things more cheaply than you can is technology, not law
or morals.
Natural property is a useful starting point for explaining the similarities among what is, what should be, and what would be efficient, because
it is relevant to all three.
If the account I have offered is correct, our actual civil order is the result
of extended bargaining, based ultimately on natural property. It was my
control over my body that made the initial steps out of the state of nature
possible. So natural property is relevant to what isto the existing pattern of laws and norms.
In a world of no transaction costs, any initial allocation of property
rights is efficient.23 In a world with positive transaction costs, the basis
for choosing among alternative allocations is the cost of enforcing and
changing them. A set of rules in which I own my body and you own
yours is superior to one in which each owns the other's body, or each has
a half interest in each body, in part because it is so much easier to enforce.
So we have a Coasian argument for the relevance of natural property to
what is efficient.
This argument also provides a second connection between natural
property and what is. My earlier arguments suggest that the evolution of
rules tends to move in a direction that is at least locally efficient. If so, and
if rules that allocate natural property to its natural owner are efficient, we
would expect to observe such rules. Put differently, the argument for
local efficiency of evolved norms provides a reason for some similarity
between the rules we observe and the rules that are efficient.24
23
Ronald Coase, "The Problem of Sociai Cost," ]oumal of law and Economics, vol. 3 (I960),
pp. 1-44.
24
1 am not claiming here that slavery is never observed or that it is never efficient. One
can imagine circumstances in which the self-enforcing element of contracts would be too
weak to enforce the contract that would be superior to slavery. An example is the prisoner
15
16
DAVID FRIEDMAN
lated, is a set of rules that exist because it was in the interest of pairs of
individuals to abide by them, not because it was decided by someone that
they would promote the general good of society.27
IV. CONCLUSIONS
The central project of this essay has been to give an account of rights,
especially property rights, that is both amoral and alegalan account that
would explain the sort of behavior we associate with rights even in a
world lacking law, law enforcement, and feelings of moral obligation.28
I have tried first to explain how, with no legal system to enforce contracts,
it might still be possible to contract out of a Hobbesian state of nature,
and then to show how the same analysis can be used to understand in
what sense a civil order, such as our own society, is different from a
Hobbesian state of nature. Having offered answers to those questions, I
then tried to show how we might get from the state of nature to something like the present society, and tried to use the analysis to partially
explain the puzzling similarity between actual rules, just rules, and efficient rules.
If my analysis is correct, civil order is an elaborate Schelling point,
maintained by the same forces that maintain simpler Schelling points in
a state of nature. Property ownership29 is alterable by contract because
Schelling points are altered by the making of contracts. Legal rules are in
large part a superstructure erected upon an underlying structure of selfenforcing rights.
Law and Economics, Cornell haw School
27
Which is not to imply that legislated rules necessarily are designed for the good of
society, b u t only that they might be.
28
This is n o t the only w a y in which a positive account of rights might b e developed.
Sugden pursues a similar project in a framework where conventions develop as players of
a multiplayer game learn by experience a n d alter their behavior accordingly; see Sugden,
Economics of Rights, Co-operation, and Welfare (supra note 3). Another alternative would be a
sociobiological explanation, in which respect for property is an inherited behavior pattern
that evolved because it resulted in increased fitnesswhich is to say, reproductive success.
It is unclear to what extent these are really competing explanations, rather than different views of the same elephant. The sociobiological account may be seen as Sugden's
repeated game, repeated through many generations, or as my account in a world where
humans' ability to alter property rights by contract simply reflects the richer set of Schelling points available to them. My sketchy account of the development of norms and Sugden's more detailed account of the development of conventions are the same, save that he
emphasizes anonymous adaptation where I emphasize explicit contracts among small subgroups. His account of the underlying games takes the available strategy set as given, where
mine takes it as a subjective fact about the players that may, under some circumstances, be
alterable. The similarities among the explanations are close; it is unclear whether the differences are sufficiently great to lead to significant differences in their implications.
29
By "property o w n e r s h i p " I m e a n the ability to control things, not the legal right to d o so.