Radical Orthodoxy & Christian Psychology, Milbank & Oliver
Radical Orthodoxy & Christian Psychology, Milbank & Oliver
Radical Orthodoxy & Christian Psychology, Milbank & Oliver
60
62
I would want them to be seen by a good neuropsychologist or neurologist, because they will be able
to tell what she can do, what she cannot do, what she
needs to practice and so forth.
JM: Of course. But Im fascinated by the genealogy
of all this, that there has always been a discourse that
has recognised the link between the soul and the body,
such as the discourse about the humours and so on,
which were clearly aware of that, and the relationship
between these discourses and theological ones about
the soul, I do not fully know or comprehend the
history of it, but certainly naturalistic psychology is
not completely new.
PH: Let us return to the notion that ideally
psychology does need to look outside itself, the
notion that there has to be some sort of meaningful
reference for feeling, for example. In the 1970s,
many psychologists realised that perhaps they
should get interested in the everyday world! It is
not sufficient simply to explain activities that go
on inside peoples heads without some explanation
or account of the environment in which people
are immersed. This leads to a whole tradition of
studies of everyday memory, of reasoning in everyday
contexts and so on. As Mace (1977) wrote of
perceptual psychologist J.J. Gibson, Ask not whats
inside your head, but what your heads inside of. We
can take that idea as an analogy and ask, is it really
that we need psychology and the social sciences to
embed themselves within the wider theological and
philosophical environment? It is not then simply the
natural environment that we are talking about, but a
set of meanings and concepts that those disciplines
can bring to bear make a conceptual environment
for psychology.
JM: It is very strange the way naturalism seems to
trade on a materialised Cartesian idea that somehow
soul is simply something inside you, as if we simply
think with our brains, whereas a lot of work has
been done on how we think with our bodies, with
our environment, and so strangely, the more we
materialise, or recover, the soul as something tangible
that is part of this entire set of interactions, the more
you understand that you cannot really reduce the
soul.
65
66
but it is actually a very thoughtful, perceptive lecture. from the implications of what he is saying, which
does require a re-enjoinment with the world, but it
SO: I have been recently reading some work by Hans is as if nobody wants to look at that or thinks it silly.
Jonas, who was a German Jewish phenomenologist,
Another simple way of putting this is that if
a pupil of Heidegger, but who in the end turned on there is no God, you seem to be stuck with saying
Heidegger, who wrote a lot about the phenomenology that either matter is primary, or reason is primary,
of life (Jonas, 2000). Jonas has a very simple, but ending up either with materialism or with idealism,
very striking essay, in which he comments on the but theology allows you somehow to have both these
invention or prioritisation of death, or necrophilia, realities, and there is a higher reality that transcends
so he is saying that for the ancient, pre-modern them, especially if you bring in some things from
tradition what was always primary was life, and the theological neo-Platonism which allows that there
cosmos was understood as a living organism. Motion is something in matter which reflects the One, that
is indicative of life, and saturated in motion, the mind does not capture. I think this needs to be more
universe is in some sense alive, and the notion of life worked into Christian theology, in order to justify
is analogically attributed to various aspects of the the sacramental.
natural. Even the inert is still in some way oriented
towards the generation of life. This dies away with SO: Its also worth mentioning that faith is not
modernity and what becomes primary is the inert, simply a propositional state, at least not as Aquinas
the object as opposed to the subject. He argues that or Augustine understand it; faith is actually a way of
the invention of the science of biology is essentially being. So, in this way, the best scientists are those
the prioritisation of death, because life is then treated who tend to be quite faithful, in the sense that they
as the aberration, as something that is weird and odd, have a certain way of being. Any research project, by
and requiring explanation. I wonder if psychology is necessity, is always going to begin with best guesses
running on the back of that, because consciousness is and intuition, and is never going to be able to
suddenly an aberration, it is that which is weird and delineate its outcome with any precision. Being able
has to be explained. It is something that goes on in to make best guesses, based on what has gone before,
one corner of the universe, as opposed to something or what we understand now, is actually quite a skill,
which is part and parcel of the way things are.
which comes partly by practice and through sheer
This is where, I think, psychology might have experience. So many of sciences best breakthroughs
a recovery of nerve and gain a clearer sense of its have been based on the best intuitions, which reason
own place within the hierarchy of scientia. If human then works on, and yet so many of those discoveries
intellectual life is in some sense the apex of material have surprised us. If it was simply a matter of
life itself (as Aquinas thought), and psychology is the extrapolating or unfolding what we already know,
particular study of that life, it is placed at the heart nothing would ever really come out of science, and
of our study. Yet this requires some sense that the yet it does. In any human intellectual enterprise, we
phenomenon of human intellectual life is not some are always working with that which we perceived
unbelievably weird fluke in an essentially lifeless through a glass darkly, that we then try to illuminate
universe, but is in fact the goal of that creation. The or elucidate the meaning and implications of, by
raises the problematic spectre of teleology, but it reason of different kinds and in different contexts.
is an issue which I think we need to confront very
urgently.
References
Benedict XVI (2006). Faith, reason and the
JM: This is where it seems to me that we have a loss
university: memories and reflections. The
of hylomorphism, in which you had the sense that
Regensburg Address. Given at the Aula
everything is composed of form and matter, that
Magna of the University of Regensburg Tuesday,
the mind is the form of forms, that you had this
September 12th, 2006. Available via: http://
mediation. It was as if the forms of the things out
www.vatican.va/holy_father/benedict_xvi/
there were like embodied meanings.
speeches/2006/september/documents/hf_benxvi_spe_20060912_university-regensburg_
PH: I think it is not just the notion of consciousness
en.html , accessed June 4th, 2010.
which is problematic, it is meaning, it is teleology, as Bergson, H. (2009 ed.), La pense et le mouvant.
we were discussing earlier. It is as if the burden of
Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.
explanation or proof is set in the wrong direction. Blond, P., & Milbank, J. (2010). No equality in
Given the background assumptions of modernity, we
opportunity. The Guardian, January 27th,
have to swim against the tide to establish the validity
2010. Available via, http://www.guardian.
of ideas which from a different standpoint could be
co.uk/commentisfree/2010/jan/27/inequalitytaken for granted.
opportunity-egalitarian-tory-left, accessed July
12th, 2010.
JM: John McDowells (1994) book Mind and World Chesterton, G. K. (1908). Orthodoxy. London: The
edges towards the idea that meaning is not just
Bodley Head.
something inside us, but then curiously backs off Haldane, J. (2004). Faithful reason: Essays Catholic
Edification: The Transdisciplinary Journal of Christian Psychology
67
68
Edification: Articles
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
References
Agamben, G. (1998). Homo sacer: Sovereign power
and bare life [trans. D. Heller-Roazen]. Stanford,
CA: Stanford University Press.
Agamben, G. (2005). State of exception [trans. K.
Attell]. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Anderson, M. (2007). The massive redeployment
hypothesis and the functional topography of the
brain. Philosophical Psychology 20 (2), 143-174.
Baker, L. R. (2007). The metaphysics of everyday
life: An essay in practical realism. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Berry, W. (2001). Life is a miracle: An essay against
modern
superstition.
Washington,
DC:
Counterpoint.
Brulle, P. de (1996). Discours de ltat et des grandeur
de Jsus. In M. Dupuy (Ed.), Oeuvres compltes.
Vol. 7. Paris: ditions du Cerf.
Bunge, M. (2003). Emergence and convergence:
Qualitative novelty and the unity of knowledge.
Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 2003.
Chomsky, N. (1972). Language and mind. New York:
Harcourt, Brace Jovanovich.
Churchland, P. (1986). Some reductive strategies in
cognitive neurobiology. Mind 95 (379), 279309.
Cunningham, C. (2002). Genealogy of nihilism:
Philosophies of nothing and the difference of
theology. London and New York: Routledge.
Cunningham, C. (2010). Darwins pious idea: Why
ultra-Darwinists and creationists both got it wrong.
Grand Rapids, Illinois: Wm B. Eerdmans.
Fodor, J. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (1985). Prcis of the modularity of mind.
The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 8, 1-42.
Fodor, J. (1998). In critical condition: Polemical essays
on cognitive science and the philosophy of mind.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. (2005). The selfish gene pool: Mother
nature, Easter bunnies and other common
mistakes. The Times Literary Supplement, 29 July
2005, pp. 3-6.
Foucault, M. (2002). The order of things: An
archaeology of the human sciences. London:
Routledge.
Gardner, H. E. (1983). Frames of mind: The theory of
multiple intelligences. New York: Basic Books.
Ghiselin, M. (1997). Metaphysics and the origin of
species. New York: State University of New York
Press.
Gilbert, W. (1992). A vision of the grail. In D. J.
Kelves and L. Hood (Eds.), The code of codes:
Scientific and social issues in the human genome
project (pp. 83-97). Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Glotin, . (2007). La Bible de coeur du Jsus. Paris:
Presse de la Renaissance.
Healy, III, N. J. (2008). Henri de Lubac on nature
and grace: A note on some recent contributions
to the debate. Communio: International Catholic
78
with James K.A. Smith: Radical Orthodoxy, Stroud, B. (2004). The charm of naturalism. In M.
secularity, and the roots of a Christian
De Caro and D. Macarthur (Eds.), Naturalism in
Psychology. Edification: Journal of the Society for
Question (pp. 21-35). Cambridge, MA: Harvard
Christian Psychology, 1(1), 68-72.
University Press.
Spaemann,
R.
(1985).
Funktionale Tooby, J. & Cosmides, L. (1992). The psychological
religionsbegruendung und religion. In P.
foundations of culture. In J. H. Barkow, L.
Koslowski (Ed.), Die religioese Dimension
Cosmides, and J. Tooby (Eds.), The adapted
der Gesellschaft (pp.9-29). Tuebingen, Mohr
mind: Evolutionary psychology and the generation
Siebeck.
of culture (pp. 19-136). Oxford: Oxford
Spaemann R. (2002). Persons: The difference between
University Press.
someone and something [trans. Oliver Wilson, E. O. (1978). On human nature. Cambridge,
ODonovan]. Oxford: OUP.
MA: Harvard University Press.
79