9 - Chapter 1. The Components of Quality in Health Care PDF
9 - Chapter 1. The Components of Quality in Health Care PDF
9 - Chapter 1. The Components of Quality in Health Care PDF
Efficacy
Efficacy is the ability of the science and technology of health care to
bring about improvements in health when used under the most favorable
circumstances. Some further considerations should be noted.
First, it is not always possible to specify what "the most favorable
circumstances" I have postulated are. Therefore, it is possible to substitute
"under specified circumstances" for the vaguer concept of "most favorable."
Second, it follows from what I have just said that efficacy is the
standard against which any improvement in health achieved in actual
practice is to be compared. As suggested in Figure 1.1, efficacy is not
itself subject to monitoring when the quality of practice is being assessed.
Rather, it is given to us, a priori, as a product of research, experience,
and professional consensus.
Third, as I show in Figure 1.1, the science and technology of health
care set the standard not only for efficacy but for the other attributes of
quality as well. This means that actual performance in all its aspects is
compared to what our science and technology, at its best, is expected to
achieve. This formulation has a consequence also alluded to in Figure
1.1. It requires that "science and technology" be defined broadly to in-
elude not only biological factors but the behavioral sciences as well. It is
true that these sciences may not be, as yet, sufficiently developed to offer
us clear guidelines and precise standards. It is hoped, however, that they
will be able to do so as they mature. And finally, we should remember
that not all standards of performance derive from what we are accustomed
to call "science and technology." Some standards are set by social and
individual preferences, and some others by ethical and moral considerations.
Effectiveness
Effectivenessss isis the degree to which improvements in health now attainable are, in fact, attained. This implies, as I have already said, a compar-
ison between actual performance and the performance that the science
and technology of health care, ideally or under specified conditions, could
be expected to achieve. This formulation is presented graphically in Figure 1.2.
To simplify my presentation, I assume in Figure 1.2 that we have in
mind a mostly self-limiting disease; for example, a moderately severe upper respiratory infection, not threatening to life. On the ordinate axis I
have a measure of health status; for example, the ability to perform the
activities of daily living. On the abscissa is plotted the passage of time.
As the figure shows, the person in question (or the average of a group
of persons) begins with a specified level of health close to "wellness."
When illness strikes, as shown by the solid line in the figure, health
deteriorates for a while and then, because the disease has been assumed
to be self-limiting, begins to improve, finally attaining a level similar to
that present at the beginning.
With this formulation, the area A in Figure 1.2 represents the effect
of treatment. Areas A and B combined represent the effect of the best
treatment. Effectiveness can now be represented by the fraction (A) -j- (A
+ B), which is the ratio of the health improvement achieved in actual
practice to the health improvement that could have been achieved had
the best treatment been given. Effectiveness is, therefore a relative concept, which can be defined as follows:
Efficiency
"Efficiency" is the ability to lower the cost of care without diminishing
attainable improvements in health. Expressed as an equation:
Improvements in health expected
from the care to be assessed
Efficiency =
1 he cost ot that care
This means that efficiency is increased if, for a given cost, health improvement is increased or if the same degree of health improvement is
attained at a lower cost. It follows that the mere reduction in cost does
not denote efficiency unless health benefits are either unaffected or are
improved.
10
11
Optimality
Optimality is the balancing of improvements in health against the cost of
such improvements. This definition implies that there is a "best" or "optimum" relationship between costs and benefits of health care, a point
below which more benefits could be obtained at costs that are low relative
to benefits, and above which additional benefits are obtained at costs too
large relative to corresponding benefits.
Figure 1.3 will help illustrate this somewhat abstract concept. To
generate the figure it is necessary to engage in a "mental experiment": an
experiment rather difficult to duplicate in actual practice, but nonetheless
one from which emerges a fundamental principle very relevant to medical
practice and social policy.
To begin with, we assume that we have an ideal physician, one who
has perfect knowledge of both health-care improvements and cost. This
Figure 1.3. Hypothetical relations between health benefits and costs of progressively more elaborate care, when care is clinically most efficient.
12
13
Gains
Losses
Reduced cost of
caring for pneumonia
Increased quality of
life as a result of
prevention of
pneumonia
Reduced quality of
life as a result of
complications of
vaccination
Cost of treatment
of illnesses other
than pneumonia
as a result of
extended life
Increased life
expectancy as a
result of avoiding
death from pneumonia
Discounted at 5% annually
Vaccination Age
2-4
5-24
25-44
45-64
65 plus
Reduced quality of
life as a result of
extended life
0.05
0.07
0.15
0.43
1.59
$77,200
35,300
22,900
5,700
1,000
From Willems et al., "Cost effectiveness of vaccination against pneumococcal pneumonia," New England
}. ofMed. 303: 553-559, September 4, 1980.
14
15
16
different ages. In the young, health gains are relatively small and costs
high. In the aged, costs are lower and gains higher. Such a comparison
can help in deciding to which age groups it would be socially appropriate
to offer vaccination based on how much society is willing to pay for a
given gain in a year of quality-adjusted life. The comparison does not,
however, fix the optimal point below which gains exceed losses and above
which losses exceed gains. To do that, it would be necessary to set a
monetary value for each year of life gained at each age. So that benefits
(or "gains") expressed in dollars can be compared to losses, also expressed
in dollars. I am not prepared to describe the methods by which economists have proceeded to convert years of life into their equivalent in dollars. I must, however, warn the reader that these methods invariably rest
on assumptions that have serious ethical implications.
Now that the reader has a better understanding of the concept of
optimality, it is time to move on to some further implications of the model
shown in Figure 1.3. One consequence of this model is the presence of
two standards of quality: "maximally effective care" and "optimally effective care." Which of these two standards is the one to be used in defining
and "assuring" the quality of care? As I shall show a little further on, when
I discuss the attribute of "social legitimacy," the answer depends on
whether individual or social interests are to be safeguarded.
Still other implications of the model presented graphically in Figure
1.3 have a bearing on important aspects of the relationship between cost
and quality. First, as I have already shown, if optimality is chosen as the
standard of quality, any expenditures beyond those required to achieve
the optimum can be regarded as wasteful. In other words, beyond the
optimum, quality can be considered to be lower rather than higher.
Second, if maximally effective care is taken as the standard of quality,
expenditures below that point are justified. Only expenditures beyond that
point are considered wasteful. And if they result in harm, care is not only
wasteful but also of lower quality.
It will be recalled that in order to generate the curves in Figure 1.3
it was assumed that the care given was that by an "ideal physician" who
consistently avoided all useless care. In actual practice, in any community,
most physicians depart from the ideal, sometimes to a remarkable degree.
17
18
Acceptability
Acceptability is defined as conformity to the wishes, desires, and expectations of patients and responsible members of their families. I shall develop this definition in five parts:
1. Accessibility
2. The patient-practitioner relationship.
3. The amenities of care
4. Patient preferences regarding the effects, risks, and cost of care
5. What patients consider to be fair and equitable
I shall briefly comment on each of these.
Accessibility
By accessibility I mean the ease with which persons can obtain care. This
depends on spatial factors such as distance from the sources of care and
on the availability and cost of transportation; on organizational factors
such as the days and hours when sources of care are open to receive
patients; on economic factors such as income and the possession of health
insurance; on social and cultural factors such as the ethnic or religious
preferences of those who seek care or the biases of those who provide it.6
We could debate whether or not accessibility is properly an aspect,
attribute, or component of quality or, on the contrary, whether it is only
an attribute of care separate from quality. Irrespective of such debate, it
is true that people continue to be vitally concerned about their ability to
get care when they want it and with how easily and conveniently it can
be obtained. And, as we shall see soon, accessibility is also a critical
component in the social acceptability of care.
The Patient-Practitioner Relationship
It is not easy to list all the properties that stand for goodness in the
patient-practitioner relationship. As a beginning, mainly to stimulate the
19
reader's thinking, I offer the attributes listed in Table 1.3. I shall not go
over these in detail. To put it briefly: personal concern, empathy, respectfulness, avoidance of condescension, willingness to take time, effort to
explain, attention to the patient's preferences, honesty, truthfulness, and
plain good manners are essential ingredients in good care.
To begin with, these attributes are desirable in their own right. They
embody cherished values of the health care professions, and include desirable characteristics of every interaction in a civilized society. Moreover,
when such attributes are present, patients are not only pleased, but also
reassured. They regard their presence as evidence (which they understand) that technical care (which they do not understand so well) will
also be good. For these reasons, when patients have a choice, and when
competition among providers of care is allowed, the attractiveness of the
patient-practitioner relationship becomes a key to success among competing organizations. To emphasize this point, some have taken to using
the terms client or customer, rather than patient, to designate those who
Table 1.3. Some Attributes of a Good Patient-Practitioner Relationship
Congruence between therapist and client expectations.
Adaptation and flexibility: the ability of the therapist to accept his or her approach not
only to the expectations of the client but also to the demands of the clinical situation.
Mutuality: gains for both therapist and client.
Stability: a stable relationship between client and therapist.
Maximum client autonomy, freedom of action, and movement
Maintenance of family and community communication and ties.
Maximum egalitarianism.
Active client participation through shared knowledge concerning the health situation,
shared decision making and participation in carrying out therapy.
Empathy and rapport without undue emotional involvement of the therapist.
A supportive relationship without undue dependency.
Confining therapist and client influence and action to the boundaries of their legitimate social functions.
Avoidance of client and therapist exploitation economically, socially, or sexually.
Maintenance of client and therapist dignity and individuality.
Privacy.
Confidentiality.
From Donabedian, A., "Models for Organizing the Delivery of Personal Health Services and Criteria for
Evaluating Them." Milbank Memorial Fund Quarterly 50: 103-153, October 1972, Part 2.
20
are likely to need care or actually to seek it. In this way, one recognizes
the health care system as a market rather than a social organism motivated
mainly by its internal commitments and values.
Whether those who seek care are called clients, customers, or patients, it is reasonable to expect a link between the goodness of care and
the goodness of the patient-practitioner relationship. This is because this
relationship is the vehicle by which technical care is implemented. A
good relationship motivates the practitioner to do well. It also motivates
the patient to cooperate, so that the effectiveness of care is enhanced. In
fact, in many cases, the proper management of the patient-practitioner
relationship is in itself the most important technique of care.
Finally, the patient-practitioner relationship is perhaps the most sensitive indicator of the persistence of differences adverse to the underprivileged in the organization and delivery of care. Such differences are the
last to disappear when the goal is to put all patients on an equal footing
with regard to the care offered to them.
21
22
cost) in a way that differs from the valuations of their practitioners. Moreover, patients differ greatly from one another in their valuations.
When these differences arise out of ignorance of the consequences
of the care contemplated or received, education is the remedy. When
they arise out of economic considerations, the social financing of care
can help reduce the differences. But even then, differences among patients persist. For example, some are anxious to avoid an immediate risk
(let us say, from a surgical operation) whereas others are willing to accept
that risk if the prospect of subsequent longevity is improved.7 Similarly,
some patients would prefer a shorter life of higher quality, whereas others
would prefer longer survival even if the quality of life is relatively low.8
The consequence of the preceding considerations is that practitioners
should take time to explain to patients (or their relatives when patients
are unable to fully understand the situation) the expected cost, risk, and
effects of alternative methods of care, and be guided by the informed
opinion of these parties.9
Legitimacy
Legitimacy is defined as conformity to social preferences, as expressed in
ethical principles, values, norms, laws, and regulations. Briefly, it can be
regarded as social acceptability, the property that corresponds to "acceptability to individuals." In a democratic society, where patients and potential patients can express their wishes through a representative political
process, individual and social concerns can be expected to correspond,
23
24
Equity
Equity is defined as conformity to a principle that determines what is just
and fair in the distribution of health care and of its benefits among the
members of a population. Although equity is an important determinant
of individual and social acceptability, I have thought it worthy of separate
mention as a component of quality.
Obviously, equity depends first, on access to care, and second, on
the effectiveness and acceptability of the care received. As a general rule,
the aim is to erase all differences in these regards between population
groups characterized by age, sex, income, social class, ethnic origin, place
of residence, and so on. But, once again, we must recognize that individual and social preferences can intrude to disrupt the balance of what
could be considered equitable. As I have already said, individuals have
decided views of what equitably should be theirs. But society may determine, in the pursuit of equity, that persons already privileged should have
less care than they want, so that others, heretofore deprived, should receive more.
Attention to what is effective, efficient, or optimal can also intrude
on determinations of social equity. For example, it may be concluded that
certain categories of persons should have more care because the results
in health improvement are significantly greater when compared to cost.
The relative emphasis on prevention as compared to treatment is another
example of this kind of reasoning.
One can ask, therefore, whether or not everyone should receive
equal care relative to "need," whether need is determined by what individuals want or what health professionals estimate. One can also ask
whether, rather than distributing care according to "need," it should be
distributed according to the expected benefits from care. These issues are
to be settled by social consensus in a free society.
25
26
27
improving it when necessary. The steps one might take in carrying out
this intention can be listed as follows:
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.