Walzer's Theory of Morality in International Relations
Walzer's Theory of Morality in International Relations
Walzer's Theory of Morality in International Relations
Gerald Doppelt
Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 8, No. 1. (Autumn, 1978), pp. 3-26.
Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0048-3915%28197823%298%3A1%3C3%3AWTOMII%3E2.0.CO%3B2-T
Philosophy and Public Affairs is currently published by Princeton University Press.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained
prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in
the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/journals/pup.html.
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic
journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers,
and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take
advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
http://www.jstor.org
Mon Jan 7 16:57:38 2008
GERALD DOPPELT
In his new book Just and Unjust Wars, one of Michael Walzer's central concerns is to advance a theory of international aggressi0n.l His
theory would guide us in determining precisely when one state practices aggression against another and on what grounds aggression is immoral. It would also help to define the nature of the right possessed by
the victims or observers of aggression to resist militarily and punish
the aggressors. For Walzer, aggression involves the forceful violation
by one state of the territorial integrity or political sovereignty of an
independent state. As such, it defines the most serious moral problem
which arises in international relations; it is "the only crime that states
can commit against other states: everything else is, as it were, a misdemeanor" (JUW, p, 51).
Walzer's theory of aggression is articulated by means of what he
calls the "legalist paradigm" which postulates a moral order among
independent states on an analogy with the more familiar case of the
civil order among independent citizens within any one state. From
the standpoint of this paradigm, states have rights and duties; they
can suffer or commit crimes such as murder or armed robbery in
their relations to one another in much the same way as do persons
(or citizens) within a particular society. Indeed, on Walzer's "domesI. Michael Walzer, Just and Unjust Wars (New York: Basic Books, 1977).
Hereafter referred to as JUW.
tic analogy," states are like persons in that the proper moral order between both sorts of "individuals" derives from their deepest underlying claims to independence and autonomy. Just as every state in principle regulates the relations among its citizens to secure each some
privileged sphere of autonomy (for example, Lockean rights), states
ought to regulate their relations in order to secure for each state a
similar freedom from external force or intervention. Such autonomy
is conventionally signified in terms of a nation's right to political sovereignty, territorial integrity, and self-determination. Drawing on this
paradigm, Walzer elaborates his theory of aggression as a system of
axioms, which can be paraphrased as follows. There exists an international society of independent states, each of which has rights of
territorial integrity and political sovereignty. Any use or imminent
threat of military force by one state against the rights of another constitutes criminal aggression and justifies forceful resistance and eventual punishment meted out either by the victim or by other states
within international society or both. Finally, the use of military force
by one state in relation to another can be justified only as a response
to aggression, and not for any other end (with a few exceptions to
be noted later), JUW,pp. 61-62.
The initial power of Walzer's legalist paradigm is the great simplicity and elegance of the absolute moral prohibitions it justifies to
starkly limit the occasions for the legitimate use of military force in
international relations. But this paradigm generates a series of problems which, as Walzer himself realizes, must be solved if it is to work.
The problems grow out of the paradigm's basic analogy between persons and states. When the classical liberal theorists (for example,
Locke) argued that all human beings have certain rights of life and
liberty, it is fairly clear who has these rights, what entitles them to
these rights, and the conditions under which they might be legitimately denied. But rights of states to territorial integrity and political
sovereignty are much more difficult and controversial to determine.
First, who is correctly viewed as the bearer of the rights of political
sovereignty? Is it the people of the nation-state as a whole? Or is it
the particular government which claims to rule them with legitimacy?
Obviously, aggression directed at a tyrannical government, and at
those few who may upon some occasion be paid or intimidated to look
after its defense, need not necessarily amount to aggression against
the people or nation itself. Second, if a state does have the right of
political sovereignty, in virtue of what features does it have this right?
For example, as Locke would have it, only a government which protects
the natural rights of its citizens and enjoys their consent gains the
rights of political sovereignty. Third, when does a state or government
which has this right forfeit it? Following Walzer's legalist paradigm,
just as an individual within a society forfeits his rights (or at least
some of them) when he violates the rights of another, a state which
commits aggression against the rights of another state loses its political sovereignty, at least in some degree; it can be punished against its
will. So far so good. But let us carry the analogy one step further. An
individual may also forfeit his rights if he violates the rights of the
government itself, as when he refuses to fight its legal war or obey its
constitutional laws. Walzer's analogy would thus suggest that a state
may not only forfeit its rights when it violates the rights of other
states, but also when it violates the rights of its own citizens; in that
case, the use of military force or intervention against a government
might be justified even though it has only practiced aggression on its
own citizens and not upon any other state. The point is, in justifying
the use of (or resistance to) force in international relations, what is
the status of the rights of states relative to that of individuals? We
begin with the assumption that Walzer may want to avoid a theory
of international morality which places the rights of states or governments above those of individuals. These problems show that Walzer's
theory of aggression must be able to say when a state-a government
or a people-has these rights of political sovereignty (and territorial
integrity), on what basis it has them, and when they are forfeited.
ultimately from the rights of individuals, and from them they take
their force" (JUW, p. 5 3 ) . As a result, aggression is immediately an
attack upon the state, but its criminality stems from the fact that it
is an attack upon the basic human rights of its individual citizens.
The moral wrong of aggression "is to force men and women to risk
their lives for the sake of their rights" (JUW, p, 51). How then, does
Walzer identify these human rights which are at the foundation of
his theory of aggression? On first impression, they appear to be "individual rights to life and liberty" (JUW, p. 54). The result would
then be the familiar liberal view that a state derives its legitimacy and
political sovereignty from the fact that it protects the basic individual
rights to life and liberty of its citizens. Suppose one state uses military
force on another state which consistently and brutally violates these
basic rights of its citizens. In such a case, this action would not in itself
constitute aggression, for no right to political sovereignty could have
been violated, unless the victim is redefined as the people, the nation,
and not the government. Of course, the use of force might still be
morally wrong for various other reasons (its ends are unjustifiable or
it violates individual rights), but it would not constitute aggression,
for the victim would not be a legitimate state with the rights of political sovereignty.
While such a view has some plausibility, it is not Walzer's view. On
his view, a state may possess the right of political sovereignty independently of the form of its political institutions, whether or not it
protects individual rights to life and liberty as we have come to understand them within the liberal-democratic tradition. Walzer agrees
with Mill's view that "we are to treat states as self-determining communities . . . whether or not their internal political arrangements are
free, whether or not the citizens choose their government and openly
debate the policies carried out in their name" (JUW, p. 87). Furthermore, it is not simply undemocratic governments which possess the
rights of political sovereignty, but also illiberal or tyrannical governments which deny their citizens basic personal and civil liberties (for
example, trial by jury, equality before the law, freedom of movement),
J W , pp. 87-90. Indeed, for Walzer a government can forfeit its rights
of political sovereignty only when it engages in the "enslavement or
massacre" of its own citizens. Walzer's understanding of "massacre"
is always morally wrong. As Walzer puts it, ". . . domestic tyrants are
safe, for it is not our purpose in international society . . . to establish
liberal or democratic communities, but only independent ones"
(JUW, p. 94). There is a paradoxical element in Walzer's theory
which sets the stage for the critique to be developed here. We may recall that the crime of international aggression "is to force men and
women to risk their lives for the sake of their rights." The paradox
arises because on this definition, it seems that a domestic government
can also commit "aggression" against its own citizens: through its
tyranny, it may also force them "to risk their lives for the sake of their
rights." In this case, consider the moral status of ( a ) some case of
foreign military intervention against ( b ) a tyrannical state. How can
( a ) force the citizens of ( b ) "to risk their lives for the sake of their
rights" if they are already denied their rights by ( b ) ? Furthermore, if
( b ) forcibly denies its people (or the majority of them) their rights,
why isn't it conceivable that ( a ) be morally justified as a means to
help the citizens of ( b ) gain a free state-one in which they would
not be forced "to risk their lives for the sake of their rights?" Walzer
himself glosses the paradox when he says, "Though states are founded
for the sake of life and liberty, they cannot be challenged in the name
of life and liberty by any other states" (JUW, p. 61 ) . Why not?
On the other hand, a foreign military intervention against a tyrannical government might be immoral for reasons having nothing to do
with its rights of political sovereignty; for example, the intervention
might aim to impose foreign rule, annex the territory of the people or
impose other hardships on them. Nonetheless, how could it count as
an aggression against a tyrannical government's rights of political
sovereignty, if these rights are supposed to derive from individuals'
rights, which are denied by the government itself? Ilralzer's theory
seems to give states rights of independent political sovereignty which
are either in no demonstrable relation to, or worse, at the expense of,
the indiviual rights ("life and liberty") on which the former were supposed to be based.
This paradox poses the two questions central to the remainder of our
discussion: ( I ) Why would Walzer have us treat unfree states as
WaLzer's T h e o r y o f Morality
possessing moral rights of political sovereignty? ( 2 ) In what conceivable sense do such rights "derive ultimately from the rights of
individuals?" Walzer's theory seems to operate on two levels: on the
first level, he implicitly identifies the state with the established government and seeks to account for the right of an (unfree) government to political sovereignty; on the second level, he identifies the
state with the people, nation, or political community-not its de facto
government-and seeks to account for the right of an (unfree) people
to "self-determination." Let us offer a "rational reconstruction" of Walzer's underlying theory.
First of all, the right of an established government (free or unfree)
to political sovereignty derives from its claim to protect from external
encroachment what Walzer calls "the common life" or "independent
community" which a people has shaped over a long period of time
(jUW, p. 5 4 ) . In his view, the rights of a state thus rest on the consent of its members though "this is consent of a special sort." It is not
hypothetical (as it is for Rawls) but rather refers to an actual social
process of individual participation in building or sustaining a common life. Consent "is a metaphor for a process of association and mutuality" in which individuals collectively make a common life through
"shared experience and cooperative activity of many kinds." This
process further creates an "independent community" with a right to
exist free from foreign interference. Walzer thinks of this "independent community" formed by people as "their shared life and
liberty." Hence, he thinks of their right to the preservation of this
independent community (right to self-determination) as a "collective
form" of their individual rights of life and liberty (JUW, p. 54). From
his standpoint, through the exercise of their individual rights to life
and liberty, individuals jointly create a collective life to which they
then have a sort of "collective" right-a right to preserve or alter it independently of external intervention.
Finally, as long as a de facto government "stands guard over [this]
community of [its] citizens at least to some degree" it enjoys the rights
of political sovereignty and "we assume the justice of [its] defensive
wars" (JUW, p. 54). But suppose a civil war or revolution or "struggle
for national liberation" breaks out and the established government
loses its power or right to provide this protective function. This
struggle in which they play the major roles, make the major decisions,
and control the new institutions as they emerge from the old. Clearly,
such political capacities cannot develop if the struggle for popular institutions is waged by a foreign power and not the populace itself. But
granting this axiom of politics, Walzer's dichotomy of "foreign intervention" or "internal struggle" does not follow. For it is surely empirically possible in some cases for a people to wage a popular internal
struggle against tyrannical institutions in which they in fact need,
request, and obtain the active military assistance of another people
without forfeiting their own integrity, leadership, and evolving political capacities. Furthermore, why should the right of a people to
self-determination be understood so that it is always morally wrong,
independently of the particular historical circumstances, for them to
seek and for other states to provide active military assistance in
the struggle which they nonetheless initiate, direct, and inspire? In
the modern world as we know it, some popular struggles may be
doomed to failure if those who wage them cannot in principle avail
themselves of such assistance; the reason is that their internal foesoften military governments allied with privileged, powerful minorities-enjoy a substantial monopoly on the means of force and repression, often provided by foreign governments and groups interested in
maintaining their own political influence, economic domination, or
privilege in the nation in question.
Of course, Walzer's argument while inadequate in general, does
provide a good reason for the immorality of intervention in some
cases. If such intervention in fact "denies to a people those political
capacities," it will need to govern itself [and this is known], then it
is self-defeating and immoral ( J U W , p. 89). Furthermore, foreign
intervention may be immoral in such cases for many other reasons:
it may unleash intervention by other states with a terrible toll for human life, world peace, and the prospects of civilization. Or, in some
civil wars, struggles of national liberation, and revolutions, it is simply
impossible to determine who, if anyone, represents popular social
forces with genuinely democratic or liberal intentions. And, of course,
states typically intervene in such struggles, not to advance the forces
of democracy or liberal government, but to assist the side that will
favor their own political, military, or economic interests. In such cases,
W a l z e r ' s T h e o r y o f Morality
fend it from foreign attack? Walzer might respond that our view
opens the moral floodgates to foreign military intervention against
unfree states while denying us the moral grounds for condemning it
as "aggression." But this is not true because in such cases there are
typically several moral grounds for condemning such acts as aggression and asserting an obligation or right of a people to defend itself.
These are wholly independent of its government's alleged rights of
political sovereignty. The grounds may be that the aggressor seeks to
impose foreign rule on a people or to violate its rights of territorial
integrity.
Now Walzer may respond that these moral reasons are not logically
independent of a government's rights of sovereignty. For the only way
the people or nation can defend its rights of self-determination and
territorial integrity is by defending its de facto government's rights of
sovereignty. In some cases the two are in fact connected, but still
logically distinct as moral grounds for self-defense. For example, a
people may be forced to defend its government not because it recognizes its rights, but as the lesser of two evils. The greater evil may be
the yoke of foreign rule, classified by the people as the greater evil because it would abolish their right of self-determination even more
harshly and permanently than it is already violated by the lesser evil
of their own tyrannical government. From their standpoint, the foreign intervention counts as aggression and their self-defense is justified by their right of self-determination, not by their government's
sovereignty (even though in defending the former, they must in fact
secure the latter). In such a case, ( I ) the defense of the de facto
government's "rights" and ( 2 ) the defense of the rights of the people
to national independence are logically distinct though factually overlapping; furthermore, on my account of the matter, ( 2 ) rather than
( I ) is entirely sufficient on its own to justify the self-defense and the
condemnation of the intervention as "aggression." Indeed, even though
those citizens who wage the defensive war do so under the auspices of
the government (for example, in its army), they might in perfect
clarity and consistency justify their behavior in the way my account
suggests.
There are other cases in which the recognition of a government's
Philosophy G Public A f f a i r s
Walzer's T h e o r y o f Morality
least, all reflective people (and nations) distinguish between the social
participation of a group or individual exclusively based on force, coercion, bare material survival, ignorance, or blind habit and another
kind which is "free" and approximates a meaningful sense of "consent." Needless to say, the central conflicts of social theory and life
concern the sense the concept "free" should have in this context, Walzer, however, does not enter this debate and thus his theory is vulnerable to the problems raised here.
Of course there is always the possibility that an oppressed group
may engage in some form of organized struggle (military or political)
to transform the society-a dramatic proof that they do not extend
their consent to it. Yet, given the substantial obstacles and risks such
revolutionary projects confront under repressive social conditions (in
which they mostly arise), their mere absence can hardly signal consent. But in some contexts, it seems that Walzer simply assumes the
existence of one unified political community and consent to it unless
there is either an internal "political or military struggle sustained over
time" to prove the existence of "a secessionist movement representing
a distinct community" or a civil war where "the insurgents establish
control over some substantial portion of the territory and population
of the state" (JUW, pp. 93, 96). Indeed, his conception of international morality allows foreign states to give "assistance to the established government . . . as long as it faces nothing more than internal
dissension, rebellion, and insurgency." This is strange in that one
would think the justification of such foreign assistance would at least
depend on a judgment of the moral character of the regime and the
legitimacy of the "insurgency." But in all such cases of mere "rebellion" Walzer is willing to allow foreign nations to assist the established
government, treating it as "the official representative of communal
autonomy" (JUW, p. 96). This view reflects the conservative dimension of 'CValzer's commitment to de facto governments as the cornerstone of international morality. Furthermore it suggests that his doctrine of consent is so weak that in the absence of a full-bloivn,
protracted civil war or secessionist movement, even the existence of
substantial "internal dissension, rebellion, and insurgency" does not
count for this doctrine as prima facie evidence of a sufficient lack of
consent to question the legitimacy of a state. And, to return to our
Walzer's T h e o r y of Morality
Walzer's T h e o r y of Morality
But the difference between the two standpoints is even more clearly
exposed in cases where they justify opposite behaviors on the part of
an oppressed group in a divided political community. From my standpoint, but not his, the black majority of South Africa would have n o
moral obligation to defend the political community from any foreign
intervention which did not threaten the political aspirations, interests,
or nationalist unity of the blacks themselves. Furthermore, because
South Africa is not a legitimate political community (on my view),
such a foreign attack or intervention would not be criminal aggression. Though, depending on the actual circumstances, it probably
would be wrong for other moral reasons (for example, its selfish ends
or the immoral consequences for individuals' lives and property). Finally, as we have seen, Walzer so prizes the independence of de facto
political communities that even where he admits revolution is justified, he holds that foreign intervention for the same ends as revolution
is always immoral. "It is not true, then, that intervention is justified
whenever revolution is," he states, "for revolutionary activity is an
exercise in self-determination, while foreign interference denies to a
people those political capacities that only such exercise can bring"
(JUW, p. 89). From our standpoint, this may be true in some cases,
but is decidedly false in others. In the case of South Africa, suppose it
is justified for the black majority to mount a revolutionary struggle to
transform the nature of their society. Then on my view, if they need,
request, and obtain the military participation of a neighboring state,
its intervention is not wrong; nothing w o r t h preserving has been violated (as long as it isn't a case where the foreign state "takes over"
the struggle and the indigenous black majority loses the chance to
develop its own political leaders and capacities for eventual self-rule).
We may now return to our point of origin : Walzer's claim to ground
the "collective" right of a state to self-determination in individual
rights to "life and liberty." By this point it should be clear that this
claim is for the most part incoherent. States which have the collective
right, for Walzer, may violate the individual rights of all or some
group of its citizens. Furthermore, how can the rights of a political
community constitute a "collective form" of individual rights when
the individuals whose activity is supposed to make this community
lack individual rights? Indeed this is another formulation of the
26