The Limitations of Markets: Background Essay: Neva Goodwin
The Limitations of Markets: Background Essay: Neva Goodwin
The Limitations of Markets: Background Essay: Neva Goodwin
Tufts University
Medford MA 02155, USA
http://ase.tufts.edu/gdae
There are a number of ways in which economic theory affects both the study and
the practice of business. Economic theories may be offered to explain how businesses
operate; students and teachers of business generally ignore some of the less realistic
portions of these explanations, while making use of the more practical aspects.
Economic theories are also used as justification for government policies that regulate or
otherwise affect business.
There is an especially relevant part of economic theory that describes how
socially optimal results can come about through perfect markets that allocate resources
according to societys most preferred uses. This theory is important because it is the
theoretic underpinning for policies and prescriptions that have significantly shaped the
modern world. Recommendations to reduce trade restrictions to privatize utilities,
prisons, or water distribution to reduce regulations on businesses and generally to get
the government out of the way of the free operation of markets all are supported by
the theory of perfect markets.
Business leaders and voting citizens as well as policy makers are influenced in
their decision-making by the idea that a perfectly free market can produce a social
optimum (a best of all possible worlds). Because this idea is so influential, it is
important to understand the conditions that must be met for the theory to work. The
theoretic prediction of the optimality of market outcomes presupposes a number of
requirements, which can be grouped into three broad categories: (1) the assumption of
perfectly functioning markets; (2) market-oriented patterns of motivation and behavior,
on the part of both individuals and firms; and (3) the universal existence and scope of
markets.
This essay will begin with an emphasis on (1). We will then touch briefly on the
second and third requirements, and end with (4) a comment on the important issues that
are buried in the concept of the most preferred uses for resources (referred to, above, in
the statement that socially optimal results can come about through perfect markets that
allocate resources according to societys most preferred uses).
Public goods
Some goods cannot, or would not, be well-provided by private individuals or
organizations acting alone. A public good is one where the use of it by one person does
not diminish the ability of another person to benefit from it (technically called
nondiminishable or nonrival), and where it would be difficult to keep any individuals
from enjoying its benefit (nonexcludable).
For example, if a local police force helps make a neighborhood safe, all the
residents benefit. Public roads (at least those that have no tolls) are also public goods, as
is national defense. Publicly-provided education and quality childcare are public goods
because everyone benefits from living with a more skilled and socially well-adjusted
population. A system of laws and courts provides the basic legal infrastructure on which
all business contracting depends. Environmental protection that makes for cleaner air
benefits everyone.
In a community where public services have failed to keep abreast of
private consumption.... in an atmosphere of private opulence and
public squalor, the private goods have full sway. Schools do not
compete with television and the movies
A community decision to have a new school means that the individual
surrenders the necessary amount, willy-nilly, in his taxes. But if he is
left with that income, he is a free man. He can decide between a better
car or a television set. The difficulty is that this argument leaves the
community with no way of preferring the school.
(John Kenneth Galbraith, The Affluent Society (Mariner Books, 1998,
40th Anniversary Edition.) The first quotation is from p. 191; the second
from p. 198.)
government, but the collective action could also be on the level of a family or an industry
group. Disagreements around this subject are generally not about what kind of
institutional response is required when something has been identified as a public good.
Rather, disagreements tend to revolve around whether something is a public good; and, if
it is, how much of it the society is willing, collectively, to provide.
Externalities
Markets are sensitive only to benefits or costs that can be translated into
willingness to pay on the part of buyers, or into costs incurred by sellers. An economic
choice or action by one economic actor that affects the welfare of others who are not
involved in that choice or action is called an externality. In defining externalities we
focus on effects that impinge on third parties through non-market channels. More
specifically:
*
When a market transaction affects the welfare of third parties who are not involved
in the transaction, the market behavior of the economic actors will not reflect all the
preferences of, or all the costs to, everyone affected. This is because the costs or benefits
affecting the particular actors differ from the costs or benefits to society as a whole. For
example:
*
If the cost of polluting is not borne by the polluters, they will not feel an economic
motivation to reduce their creation and discharge of wastes.
If employers do not benefit in full from the cost of providing training to their
employees, they are likely to provide less of that training than is socially desirable.
If the price of water or of petroleum is set below the true cost to society of using
these resources, this will produce an incentive to use too much of them.
Some of the most important externalities have to do with the economic activity of
resource maintenance1: Relying on markets alone to coordinate economic activities
allows many activities to happen that damage or deplete the natural environment, because
the damage often does not carry a price tag, and because people in future generations,
who will be most affected, are not direct parties to the decision-making.
Solutions: The standard economic response to this topic is Internalize the
externalities! For example, find ways to charge businesses the full cost for the pollutants
they emit, or raise the price of coal, gasoline, etc. to represent the full cost of the
increased risks to the economy from global climate change, as well as the health and
environmental damages from burning fossil fuel. One economist has made the rather
1 Contextual economics (as formulated, for example, in the introductory textbook, Microeconomics in
ContextHoughton Mifflin, 2005) identified four basic economic activities. These include production,
distribution, consumption, and resource maintenance.
extreme suggestion of tying retirement benefits to the earnings of each persons children.2
There are many cases where intelligent and imaginative means can be found to
internalize externalities, but the difficulties are also many, including the following:
*
The actors who impose negative externalities on society often do so with impunity
because they possess political and economic power. For example, some automobile
manufacturers and some firms in the petroleum industry are worried about results that
might show that their products are posing a serious danger to society. While other firms
in these industries have addressed the dangers of global climate change in constructive
and creative ways, the less progressive firms have funded scientists to dispute the
findings of the far more numerous and well-reputed scientists who put out the reports of
the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC), and have used the results to
support massive lobbying of governments to prevent action being taken to tighten
automobile emissions standards3.
Defining the precise cost or benefit in question is difficult, can be costly, and,
again, is complicated by interests. Who is in a position to perform such calculations?
Whose figures can be trusted? While cost-benefit analysis is often touted as the solution
to these problems, it is often marred by data inconsistency, by difficulties in quantifying
values that may be unquantifiable (such as the value of a life), and by the motivations of
those collecting and evaluating the data. As has been noted by Frank Ackerman and
2 The justification for this idea, put forth by Shirley Burggraf (The Feminine Economy and the Economic
Man: Reviving the Role of Family in the Post-Industrial Age), is that it is costly to raise children; those who
have none have more opportunities to save for their own retirement, and parents who have given up such
savings opportunities should be rewarded by the state. One questionable assumption (among several) in this
proposal is that better parenting produces children with higher earnings.
3 The website www.exxonsecrets.org provides a comprehensive list of organizations that Exxon-Mobil has
funded since 1998, indicating how Exxon-Mobil funds climate change skeptics. The site lists 125
organizations. Greenpeace also reports on Exxon-Mobils attempts to prevent climate change action. See
A Decade of Dirty Tricks (2002) at http://www.stopesso.com/pdf/Dirty_Tricks.pdf and Exxons
Weapons of Mass Deception (2002) at
http://a520.g.akamai.net/7/520/1534/release1.0/www.greenpeace.org/multimedia/download/1/50571/0/exx
on_long.pdf, which provides some details of the links between Exxon-Mobil and organizations attacking
the climate change consensus.
In recent decades General Motors has led the effort to fight against increased emissions standards;
GMs political successes have probably contributed to its loss of economic competitiveness against foreign
competitors, such as Honda, which are, instead, preparing for a world in which more externalities, such as
the environmental impact of carbon emissions, will be internalized. A Dec. 8, 2004 article in the NY Times
mentions that GM (along with seven other automakers) filed suit against the state of California over the
states law to regulate greenhouse gas emissions (see
http://www.nytimes.com/2004/12/08/business/08auto.html?ex=1260248400&en=7e162bf9a583e2a5&ei=5
088&partner=rssnyt). The Union for Concerned Scientists recently criticized an ad campaign by the Auto
Alliance, an automaker lobbying group that includes GM, Ford, BMW, Toyota, and others. See
http://www.ucsusa.org/clean_vehicles/avp/automaker-v-the-people-alliance-ad-fact-sheet.html. For a
March 22, 2005 NY Times article on the ad campaign, see
http://www.nytimes.com/2005/03/22/business/media/22adco.html?ex=1269147600&en=70d951945fa991f
e&ei=5090&partner=rssuserland. This article notes that Honda is not a member of the Auto Alliance and
recognizes that CO2 emissions remain a significant contributor to global warming trends. Honda also got
the highest ranking by the UCS in their evaluation of emissions by different automakers (GM ranked the
lowest), see http://www.climateark.org/articles/reader.asp?linkid=37091.
Lisa Heinzerling,
In practice, most cost-benefit analyses could more accurately be described as
complete cost-incomplete benefit studies. Most or all of the costs are readily
determined market prices, but many important benefits cannot be meaningfully
quantified or priced, and are therefore implicitly given a value of zero. Thus [this
methodology] systematically disfavors protection of goods that, like health and
environmental protection, are priceless. (Priceless: on knowing the Price of
Everything and the Value of Nothing. New York: The New Press, 2004; p. 40)
*
Transaction costs
Transaction costs are the costs of arranging economic activities. In many standard
economic models as distinct from the thinking that goes on in actual firms transaction
costs are assumed to be zero. If a firm wants to hire a worker, for example, the academic
economist may assume that the only cost involved is the wage paid. In the real world,
however, the activity of getting to a hiring agreement may involve its own set of costs.
The firm may need to pay costs related to searching, such as placing an ad or paying for
the services of a recruiting company. The prospective worker may need to pay for
preparation of a resume and transportation to an interview. One or both sides might hire
lawyers to make sure that the contract terms reflect their interests. Because of the
existence of such costs, some economic interactions that might lead to greater efficiency,
and that would occur in a transaction-cost free, frictionless idealized world, may not
happen in the real world.
Solutions: The increased availability of information on the Internet is an example
of a technology breakthrough that can provide good solutions to a market failure; websavvy individuals and firms are increasingly able to shorten the time and decrease the
cost of finding a good fit between skills and job requirements. While this may increase
the digital divide between individuals who can, and those who cannot, use this
resource, one can imagine a future in which web-literacy is raised to the level of oldfashion reading literacy. Other ways of reducing transactions costs include programs to
provide legal and other assistance to less-well-resourced individuals and firms. Some
such programs are charitable, such as the Service Corps of Retired Executives
(http://www.score.org/). Others are run by governments, at various levels, and others are
initiated by businesses.
Market power
In the standard economic model all markets are assumed to be perfectly
competitive, such that no one buyer or seller has the power to influence the prices or
other market conditions they face. Since perfect competition is central to the conception
of perfect markets, it has been extensively analyzed. There are a number of conditions
that are required in order for perfect competition to exist, to wit:
Each market must involve trading in one homogeneous good, so that price, rather
than other considerations, is the overwhelming influence on consumer choice. That is,
any one unit of the good must be virtually identical to any other.
Each market must have no significant barriers to entry, including no brandname loyalties, and no need for high levels of advertising, as well as no technological
and financial barriers to entry.
All factors of production must be mobile. That is, labor, capital, and raw
materials must be able to be moved from one location to another, rather than being at
the mercy of a single local firm or industry.
There must be numerous, small buyers and sellers, all of whom are compelled
to be price takers since they cannot acquire significant market power.
Information about the market must be freely and equally available to all
actual and potential market participants. That is, everything one needs to know about
prices, quantities, and qualities of goods and services for sale must be public, or readily
accessible, knowledge.
10
are illegal, international markets for some organs), or for the probable future earnings of a
child who is learning to play the violin.
The free market model assumes that markets exist for, and are used to allocate,
everything that affects economic wellbeing. That is, it is assumed that society relies
completely on the market for all economically relevant resource allocation. This general
statement has a number of more specific implications. Total reliance on the market
implies that there are no free goods or services. Everything of value that a wife does for a
husband, a father for his children, or a friend for another friend, is paid for according to a
price that has been determined through the market.
Full scope for the market implies a definite, and limited, role for the government.
In negative terms, the government must avoid any distortion of prices, or any actions that
would undermine market mechanisms. There must be no subsidies, price supports, price
controls, or taxes or tariffs on particular goods. And the government must certainly avoid
direct, nonmarket distribution of particular commodities to individuals. At the same time,
the government must ensure that contracts and property rights are enforced, creating the
legal and political environment within which the market economy can function.
While this is not quite a call for total inaction, it implies a smaller role for
government than exists in virtually all nations today. It also suggests some logical
inconsistencies. For example, the government's role in creating the framework for the
market may need to include the creation of policies to address environmental and other
externalities. However, it is often impossible to implement such policies without having
some distorting effect on prices.
Finally, if the market economy is to make an optimal choice between present and
future consumption, there must be markets existing today for future investments and
future consumption of particular goods. Here the theoretical requirements become
somewhat esoteric, calling for a complete set of futures markets in which commodities
are traded across time periods. For example, in addition to ordinary markets for
refrigerators and cars, there must be markets in which consumers can buy options to
purchase refrigerators and cars five years from now, at prices that are specified today.
The same must be true for all other goods and all time periods. In reality, futures markets
are well established only for bulk agricultural and industrial commodities and for some
types of financial investments; for other goods and services, futures trading is the rare
exception, not the rule.
There is much fungibility between paid and unpaid economic activity. An
individual can receive comfort at a time of stress or bereavement from a friend or from a
paid counselor. People who are sick or disabled can be cared for by family or by paid
nursing staff. The elderly can live at home, with paid or unpaid help, or in special
facilities. Such facilities may be entirely marketized, or may include a component of
charity, such as volunteer work. If, as we assume, the ultimate goal of any economic
system is human well-being, in the present and the future, then it is important to continue
the debate over which approach, or combination of approaches, ultimately works out best
11
for all concerned (recognizing that there may be some irresolvable conflicts; what is best
for A may simply not be the same as what is best for B). But standard economic analysis
only looks at that part of the world that operates through markets. This is one reason that
its optimality predictions and prescriptions may not address the realities of the world we
live in.
4)
There is another, deeper reason why standard economic prescriptions may not, in
fact, lead to a social optimum.
We began with the statement that economic theory describes how socially optimal
results can come about by freeing up markets to allocate resources according to societys
most preferred uses. In concluding this essay we address the issue of how we can define
and identify societys most preferred uses.
Value in economic terms is synonymous with price. The social preferences that
are visible to standard economic analysis are what economic actors in a society are able
and willing to pay for. Demand is ultimately dependent on consumer demand; that is,
firms may demand parts and other inputs from suppliers, and raw materials from primary
industries, but they only do so on the expectation that the final products will be bought by
consumers. The only consumer demands for goods and services that are visible to the
standard economic model are those that are backed up by a consumers ability to pay.
This has several implications.
The model does not take into account non-marketed production, such as the care
given to children, the sick and the elderly by family and friends. There is nothing in
standard models that assures that these sorts of production will be supplied in adequate
quantities and quality.
There are important categories of people especially, but not only young children
whose preferences are either not taken into account by the market (because they are not
in a position to make market decisions), or whose uninformed preferences are heavily
manipulated by market forces.
There is nothing in the model that assures that resources are distributed in such a
way that people can meet their basic human needs. If a few rich people have a lot of
money to spend on mac-mansions while many poor people lack the money to pay for
basic health care, free markets will motivate producers to respond to the demand for macmansions, but not to the need for basic health care.
The standard model claims a kind of justice, in that people are paid in some
relation to the value of what they produce. This claim is open to a number of arguments.
Production is normally a cooperative affair, so that it is hard to determine precisely what
portion of the output is due to the efforts of which worker or supervisor, or CEO. The
12
13
REFERENCES
Note: The Featured Collection on Market Failure, within which this essay is embedded,
offers a wide range of references and cases on the topics discussed here. The following
references are merely intended to supplement these.
Everything for Sale: The Virtues and Limits of Markets by Robert Kuttner (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press; 1999). The BOOK points out several industries (including
health care, education, and telecommunications) where unregulated markets fail to
produce optimal results.
A related ARTICLE by Kuttner was published in The American Prospect. It is available
at http://www.prospect.org/print/V8/31/kuttner-r.html.
The Limits of Market Organization, Richard Nelson, ed. (New York, Russell Sage
Foundation; 2005). The BOOK includes chapters by 12 different authors, divided into
sections on the following areas where markets alone cannot adequately organize an
economy: infrastructure, natural monopoly and equitable access; human services; science
and technology; and protecting the public and the state.
What Money Cant Buy: The Moral Limits of Markets, by Michael Sandel;
LECTURES from 1998 that discuss problems with commodification; this may be found
at www.tannerlectures.utah.edu/lectures/sandel00.pdf.
1995 TESTIMONY before the International Congress of Advertising and Free Market on
market failures in advertising may be found at
http://www.ftc.gov/speeches/azcuenaga/lima.htm.
14