Create Your Own Constitutional Theory
Create Your Own Constitutional Theory
Create Your Own Constitutional Theory
5-1-1999
Recommended Citation
Dorf, Michael C., "Create Your Own Constitutional Theory" (1999). Cornell Law Faculty Publications. Paper 98.
http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/facpub/98
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. It has been
accepted for inclusion in Cornell Law Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. For
more information, please contact jmp8@cornell.edu.
Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org)
at Tue Nov 25 21:00:53 2008
Other terms apply to this subscription. See the complete license at heinonline.org.
Create Your Own
Constitutional Theory
Michael C. Dorft
INTRODUCTION
dubious about Fallon's basic undertaking. The title suggests that the choice
of a constitutional theory precedes the formulation of answers in particular
cases:-one chooses a constitutional theory and then applies it to constitu-
tional cases. Yet in practice, matters typically proceed in the opposite di-
rection.
Before I had views about constitutional theory, I had views about con-
stitutional law. I thought that judicial review was a fair inference from the
Constitution's text, structure, and history, even though I thought John
Marshall's argument in Marbury v. Madison2 question-begging; I thought
the post-New Deal but pre-United States v. Lopez3 construction of the
Commerce Clause too generous, given Article I's evident strategy of lim-
iting national authority by enumerating specific powers; I thought the
Court should ground its unenumerated-rights jurisprudence in the Ninth
Amendment and the Privileges or Immunities Clause (and thus overrule the
Slaughter-House Cases4), rather than continue to rely on the Due Process
Clauses; and so on. I lacked a theory of constitutional interpretation, not
because I believed I did not need one, nor because I did not realize that my
views about concrete constitutional doctrines were interpretive.' I lacked a
theory of interpretation because, at least in the beginning, I did not know
enough about the practice of constitutional law to be able to evaluate theo-
retical claims about that practice.
I very much doubt that my experience was unusual. By the time any-
one has occasion to think about constitutional theory, she will likely have
views about a fairly wide range of constitutional issues. At that point,
choosing a constitutional theory is a matter of finding one that fits these
views. "Fit" will have both descriptive and normative elements, if only be-
cause one's views about concrete issues themselves combine descriptive
and normative elements.
To say that one fits constitutional theory to one's views about con-
crete constitutional issues is not to say that constitutional theory then plays
no role in what one thinks about subsequent cases. Once one settles on a
constitutional theory that comes close to fitting her views on concrete is-
sues, a judge or academic may find that the theory leads her to change her
views on some of these issues, which in turn may lead to adjustments to
the theory, and so forth, until a "reflective equilibrium"6 is reached.
However, it will be the rare judge or academic that self-consciously
goes through this process of trying on different theories. Even among those
who do, in most instances the theory upon which she settles will rarely lead
to substantially different results from those she favored before she engaged
in the search for a theory. These are empirical assertions, I recognize, and I
have conducted nothing like a comprehensive study of the ways in which
judges and academics form doctrinal and theoretical views; nonetheless, I
venture that they will ring true for anyone who has observed the practice of
constitutional law.
Notwithstanding the awkward metaphor of "choice,"in some places in
his article, Fallon could be read to agree with the account I have just given.
For example, he writes that he aims "to provide a framework within which
readers can determine how various constitutional theories should be
assessed in light of their own views about the rule of law, political
democracy, and the individual rights necessary for substantive justice."7
Because no two participants in the debates about constitutional law and
constitutional theory will have identical views about these matters, there
will be as many constitutional theories as there are people who care to
think about constitutional theory. Of course, if the adoption of a constitu-
tional theory proceeds in the way I have just described, "choosing" is an
inapt description. One does not choose a constitutional theory like a suit
off the rack; one tailors constitutional theory to one's own views, including
one's views as they are modified by the initial selection of a theory.
But I do not merely wish to take issue with the title of Fallon's article.
Instead, my basic disagreement is with the size of the categories that Fallon
employs in his analysis of constitutional theory.' "Almost without
exception," he states, constitutional "theorists claim that their preferred
approaches optimally realize sometimes competing values associated with
(i) upholding the rule of law, (ii) promoting political democracy, and (iii)
advancing substantive justice by respecting a morally defensible set of
individual rights.' Fallon treats these values as the criteria by which to
evaluate or choose a constitutional theory. In this Reply, I argue that these
values are simply too encompassing to provide a useful window into the
constitutional theory debate. I contend that both the differences that divide
and the common ground that unites various constitutional theorists can be
found in the concrete practices of constitutional interpretation.
The perspective on constitutionalism that I advance here is pragmatist
in the sense that philosophers use that term-namely, the view that one
understands institutions and practices by participating in them according to
their own (corrigible) rules, rather than by pondering them from the
10. The leading pragmatist texts are JOHN DEWEY, LOGIC: THE THEORY OF INQUIRY (1938);
WILLIAM JAMES, PRAGMATISM (1907); and Charles S. Pierce, How to Make OurIdeas Clear,reprinted
in PRAGMATISM: A READER 26 (Louis Menand ed., 1997). Two leading neo-pragmatist texts are
RICHARD J. BERNSTEIN, BEYOND OBJECTIVISM AND RELATIVISM: SCIENCE, HERMENEUTICS, AND
PRAxIs (1983), and RICHARD RORTY, CONSEQUENCES OF PRAGMATISM (1982). Although not ordinarily
considered a pragmatist, Wittgenstein, especially in his later work, expressed similar views about the
primacy of practice. See LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN, PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS 198-201 (G. E.
M. Anscombe trans., 3d ed. 1958).
11. Fallon, supra note 1, at 564. Ronald Dworkin uses the term "pragmatism" in roughly the
same way that Fallon does. See DWORKIN, supra note 5, at 160 ("Pragmatism... says that judges
should follow whichever method of deciding cases will produce what they believe to be the best
community for the future.").
12. In denying a necessary connection between instrumentalism and contextualism, I do not deny
that the proponents of American philosophical pragmatism-as-contextualism also endorsed
instrumentalism. See, e.g., William James, What PragmatismMeans, in PRAGMATISM (1907), reprinted
in PRAGMATISM: A READER, supra note 10, at 93, 98 ("[T]he pragmatic method means.., looking
away from first things, principles, 'categories,' supposed necessities; and of looking towards last
things,fruits, consequences,facts.").
13. See Fallon, supra note 1, at 559 (arguing that the interests in workable government and
economic efficiency should be subsumed within the rubrics of fit, political democracy, and individual
rights).
14. See id. at 551 ("[N]or do I advance a constitutional theory of my own.").
1999] CREATE YOUR OWN CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY
I
META-THEORY AND THEORY
19. See ROBERT H. BORx, THE TEMPTING OF AMERICA: THE POLITICAL SEDUCTION OF THE
LAW 318 (1990) (describing originalism as "essential if courts are to govern according to the rule of
law"); ANTONIN SCALIA, A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION 25 (Amy Gutman ed., 1997) ("Long live
formalism. It is what makes a government a government of laws and not of men.").
20. See BRUCE AcKERmA A, 1 WE THE PEOPLE: FOUNDATIONS 6 (1991) (describing "dualist
democracy," in which the Constitution derives its legitimacy from adoption by the People); ELY, supra
note 18, at 73-75, 101-04 (describing the Constitution's role as facilitating democracy).
21. See RONALD DWORKIN, FREEDOM'S LAW: THE MORAL READING OF THE AMERICAN
CONSTITUTION 7-8 (1996) ("[G]ovemment must treat all those subject to its dominion as having equal
moral and political status."); RICHARDS,SUpra note 18, at 149 (arguing that particular rights derive
from substantive principles of freedom of conscience that "speak to contemporary democratic concerns
about moral independence in a mass society directly and vitally"); Lawrence G. Sager, Justice in Plain
Clothes: Reflections on the Thinness of ConstitutionalLaw, 88 Nw. U. L. REV. 410, 416 (1993)
(offering a "justice-seeking" account of constitutional interpretation).
22. See PHILIP BOBBITT, CONSTITUTIONAL INTERPRETATION 131-54 (1991) (contending that any
effort to identify an algorithm for deciding disputes among constitutional arguments leads to an infinite
regress); Michael C. Doff, Integrating Normative and Descriptive ConstitutionalTheory: The Case of
OriginalMeaning, 85 GEo. LJ. 1765, 1794 (1997) (agreeing with Bobbitt that there can be no all-
purpose algorithm, but disagreeing with other elements of his approach). Ronald Dworkin arguably
belongs in this pluralist or eclectic camp rather than in the rights-foundationalist camp because
Dworkin has emphasized the responsibility that judges have to fit their vision of political justice within
the existing legal framework. See generallyDwoRaN, supranote 5, at 225-75 (describing the role of
"integrity" in law).
23. Fallon, supranote 1,at 551.
1999] CREATE YOUR OWN CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY
Constitution's text allows a role for natural law, and that the Founders so intended); David N. Mayer,
The Natural Rights Basis of the Ninth Amendment: A Reply to ProfessorMcAffee, 16 S. ILL. U. L.J.
313, 313 (1992) (advocating a "'Natural Law' reading of the amendment"); Suzanna Sherry, The
Founders' Unwritten Constitution,54 U. CHI. L. REv. 1127, 1164-66 (1987) (arguing that the Ninth
Amendment reflected the Founders' belief in natural law). But see Thomas B. McAffee, The Original
Meaning of the Ninth Amendment, 90 COLUm. L. REv. 1215, 1218-23 (1990) (defending the
"traditional" interpretation of the Ninth Amendment as simply reaffirming that the federal government
has no powers beyond those enumerated).
29. U.S. CONST. preamble.
30. One might object to seeking interpretive aids in the Preamble on the ground that
constitutional theories (and meta-theories) are supposed to provide guidance forjudicialinterpretation,
whereas the Preamble appears to be addressed principally to political actors. Yet even if the Preamble
does not, by itself, create justiciable entitlements, it does not follow that the Preamble should play no
role in constitutional interpretation. After all, Fallon's own three preferred values also do not create
justiciable entitlements. The values that inform constitutional theory need not themselves create
constitutional rights or otherwise directly decide constitutional controversies. It is sufficient that they
provide guidance, and we might find such guidance in the Preamble. The Preamble sets forth values
that could be used in aid of interpretation of justiciable provisions. See, e.g., Charles L. Black, Jr.,
FurtherReflections on the ConstitutionalJustice of Livelihood, 86 COLuM. L. REV. 1103, 1105-08
(1988) (turning to the Preamble and the Declaration of Independence as sources of guidance).
31. See, e.g., RAwLS, supranote 6, at 75 ("[T]he higher expectations of those better situated are
just if and only if they work as part of a scheme which improves the expectations of the least
advantaged members of society.").
1999] CREATE YOUR OWN CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY
democracy, and individual rights are worthwhile values,35 and a few more
in which he contends that other values can be described in terms of these
three.36 In other words, on close inspection, his meta-theory turns out to be
primarily descriptive. Whether it succeeds therefore depends on how good
a job it does of capturing the agreement and divisions that exist among
constitutional theorists and practitioners. Let us turn to that question.
II
THE THIN CONSENSUS IN CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY
40. Note that Ely himself grudgingly endorses the Supreme Court's unwillingness to tolerate
major departures from the principle of one-person/one-vote on the ground that any other rule would be
difficult to administer. See Ely, supranote 18, at 121 ("[A]dministrability is [the] long suit [of the one-
person/one-vote principle], and the more troublesome question is what else it has to recommend it.").
41. See Antonin Scalia, Originalism: The Lesser Evil 57 U. Cmr. L. REv. 849, 862 (1989).
42. See David A. Strauss, What Is ConstitutionalTheory?, 87 CALIF. L. REv. 581, 584 (1999).
(describing "the legitimacy of Brown" as "absolutely rock solid"). There are some exceptions. See, e.g.,
RAOUL BERGER, GOVERNMENT BY JUDICIARY: THE TRANSFOnIATION OF THE FOURTEENTH
AmENDjtNT 132-54 (1997); Maltz, supranote 33, at 93. However, for the most part, originalists twist
their theory to accommodate Brown. See Michael C. Dorf,A NonoriginalistPerspectiveon the Lessons
of History, 19 HARV. J.L. & PUB. POL'Y 351, 357 (1996) (observing that most self-described
originalists attempt to explain away the substantial evidence that the Framers of the Fourteenth
Amendment did not intend to end segregation, in order to avoid the embarrassment of embracing an
interpretive methodology that produces the wrong result in a seminal case).
43. 198 U.S. 45 (1905).
44. Bruce Ackerman may be an exception. As part of his larger project of recapturing
constitutional politics for democratic movements, he argues that Lochner accurately reflected the
prevailing understanding of its era. See Bruce Ackerman, LiberatingAbstraction,59 U. CHI. L. REv.
317,339-41 (1992).
CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:593
45. Ackerman states the prevailing view when he acknowledges the authority of a hypothetical
repeal of the First Amendment, and its replacement with a provision stating: "Christianity is
established as the state religion of the American people, and the public worship of other gods is hereby
forbidden." ACKERMAN, supranote 20, at 14. As James Fleming notes, however, Ackerman arguably
elevates a raw fact of political power into a matter of constitutional principle. See James E. Fleming,
We the ExceptionalAmerican People, 11 CONST. COMMENT. 355, 361 (1994) (citing JOHN RAWLS,
POLITICAL LIBERAISM 233 (1993)); see also Jeff Rosen, Note, Was the Flag Burning Amendment
Unconstitutional?, 100 YALE L.J. 1073, 1073-74 (1991) (arguing that an amendment could be
unconstitutional because it violates natural law).
46. See Cass R. Sunstein, A New Deal for Speech, 17 HAsTINGS COMM. & ENT. L.J. 137, 138
(1994) (explaining that free speech doctrine rests on the pre-New Deal view that the Constitution
prohibits government regulation that disturbs existing distributions of rights).
47. See, e.g., San Antonio Indep. Sch. Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1 (1973) (rejecting an equal
protection challenge to Texas's system of funding public education).
1999] CREATE YOUR OWN CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY
II
VALUES OTHER THAN FALLON'S THREE CRITERIA
I have argued thus far that, stated at the level of abstraction at which
Fallon states them, his three constitutional values are largely indeterminate.
Suppose one were to disagree. Fallon would still face the difficulty of ac-
commodating other values. If Fallon allows that a limitless class of other
values also inform-and thus can be made to serve as the evaluative crite-
ria for-constitutional theory, he surely falls prey to the charge of indeter-
minacy, not to mention banality. For then Fallon's claim would reduce to
the trivial assertion that constitutional theorists all agree on the need for
constitutional adjudication to serve some combination of values.
On the other hand, for Fallon to exclude other values from his account
would render it incomplete, because constitutional adjudication, and there-
fore constitutional theory that seeks to be descriptively accurate, aims not
only for principled solutions, but also workable ones. Fallon acknowledges
that "it is an obvious concern whether a particular theory would permit a
'workable' government that can respond effectively to changing needs and
exigencies,"' but omits such concerns from his catalogue of principal con-
stitutional values because he believes they can be subsumed, however
awkwardly, within his three categories. 0
The crucial question for Fallon's meta-theory, therefore, is whether
constitutional theory does better by channeling-and thus potentially dis-
torting-all value arguments through the three values he identifies.
Fallon's approach may be right. It may be better for the practice of consti-
tutional law if some kinds of values and arguments are employed only indi-
rectly. I would suggest, however, that considerations of governmental
48. See, e.g., DeShaney v. vinnebago County Dep't of Soc. Servs., 489 U.S. 189 (1989) (finding
no constitutional violation in government agency's failure to remove a child from a severely abusive
home).
49. Fallon, supranote 1, at 559.
50. See id. at 559.
CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 87:593
51. See Richard A. Posner, Against ConstitutionalTheory, 73 N.Y.U. L. REv. 1, 11-12 (1998).
52. See, e.g., Adarand Constructors, Inc. v. Pena, 515 U.S. 200, 239 (1995) (Scalia, J., concurring
in part and concurring in the judgment) ("To pursue the concept of racial entitlement-even for the
most admirable and benign of purposes-is to reinforce and preserve for future mischief the way of
thinking that produced race slavery, race privilege and race hatred.").
53. See, e.g., Regents of the Univ. of Cal. v. Bakke, 438 U.S. 265, 407 (1978) (Blackmun, J.,
separate opinion) ("In order to get beyond racism, we must first take account of race.").
54. See, e.g., Garcia v. San Antonio Metro. Transit Auth., 469 U.S. 528, 550-51 (1985)
(Blackmun, J., joined by Brennan, white, Marshall, and Stevens, JJ.) ("It is no novelty to observe that
the composition of the Federal Government was designed in large part to protect the States from
overreaching by Congress.").
55. See, e.g., id. at 560-61 (Powell, J.,dissenting, joined by Burger, C.J., and Rehnquist and
O'Connor, JJ.) (lamenting that under the majority's view, "the role of the States in the federal system
may depend upon the grace of elected federal officials").
56. See, e.g., City of Lakewood v. Plain Dealer Publ'g Co., 486 U.S. 750, 757 (1988) ("[I]n the
area of free expression a licensing statute placing unbridled discretion in the hands of a government
official or agency constitutes a prior restraint and may result in censorship.").
57. See Michael C. Dorf, The Supreme Court, 1997 Term-Foreword: The Limits of Socratic
Deliberation, 112 HARV. L. REv. 4, 37-38 (1998) (discussing the Supreme Court's limited use of
empirical data in addressing instrumental concerns).
1999] CREATE YOUR OWN CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY
IV
ALGORITHMS AND PHILOSOPHICAL PRAGMATISM
Throughout this Reply I have been at pains to distinguish between
pragmatism-as-contextualism-which I deem an appropriate approach to
constitutional interpretation-and pragmatism-as-instrumentalism-which
appears to be Fallon's least favorite constitutional theory. In this Part, I
explore the respective roles of these two conceptions of pragmatism in
Fallon's account of constitutional theory. To do so, I consider a theory of
constitutional adjudication that Fallon offered a decade ago.
In A Constructivist Coherence Theory of Constitutional
Interpretation,5" Fallon argued that constitutional adjudication recognizes
as legitimate five kinds of arguments, based on: (1) the text's plain mean-
ing; (2) the intent of the Framers; (3) constitutional theory; (4) precedent;
and (5) claims of justice or social policy s9 Fallon claimed further that
within the practice of constitutional law, these five forms of argument
overlap and inter-penetrate. Accordingly, justices, lawyers, and scholars
understand their task in any given case as using each of the various forms
of argument to support a unique result.' Thus, although in principle
"[c]onstitutional law has a commensurability problem,"6 in practice "it is
the rare judicial opinion, the anomalous brief, the unusual scholarly
analysis that describes the relevant kinds of arguments as pointing in dif-
ferent directions."'62
Because such clashes are merely rare rather than nonexistent, Fallon
believed himself obligated to offer a prescription for those cases in which
the forms of argument could not be made to align. Fallon's proposed solu-
tion was a hierarchy of constitutional arguments, ranking them in the order
set forth above.' I believe this was a mistake, not because I would prefer
some other hierarchy of constitutional arguments, but because our
64. For example, there are sound policy reasons for conducting bench trials in patent cases; yet
on the basis of the Seventh Amendment's text, the Supreme Court states unequivocally that patent
"infringement cases today must be tried to a jury, as their predecessors were more than two centuries
ago." Markman v. Westview Instruments, Inc., 517 U.S. 370, 377 (1996).
65. See, e.g., Planned Parenthood v. Casey, 505 U.S. 833, 846 (1992) ("Although a literal
reading of the [Due Process] Clause might suggest that it governs only the procedures by which a State
may deprive persons of liberty, for at least 105 years ... the Clause has been understood to contain a
substantive component as well, one 'barring certain government actions regardless of the fairness of the
procedures used to implement them."' (citing Mugler v. Kansas, 123 U.S. 623, 660-61 (1887), and
quoting Daniels v. Williams, 474 U.S. 327, 331 (1986))).
66. See infra text accompanying notes 67-72.
67. Fallon, supra note 58, at 1278.
68. See id. at 1279 ("The fourteenth amendment's guarantee of equal protection of the laws
certainly will support, even if it does not require, an interpretation that forbids racially segregated
public schools.").
69. See id.
70. See id. at 1280-82.
71. 347 U.S. 497 (1954).
1999] CREATE YOUR OWN CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY
76. Daniel Farber expressly links what I am calling legal pragmatism (instrumentalism) with
philosophical pragmatism (contextualism) by emphasizing anti-foundationalism in constitutional
adjudication. See Daniel A. Farber, Legal Pragmatismand the Constitution, 72 MINN. L. REv. 1331,
1332 (1988) ("Legal pragmatism-which essentially means solving legal problems using every tool
that comes to hand, including precedent, tradition, legal text, and social policy-renounces the entire
project of providing a theoretical foundation for constitutional law.").
77. Fallon, supranote 1, at 574.
78. I recently explored the role of pragmatism in institutional design and legal interpretation. See
Michael C. Dorf & Charles F. Sabel, A Constitution of Democratic Experimentalism, 98 COLUM. L.
REv. 267, 284-86 (1998) (institutional design); Dorf, supra note 57, at 80-83 (constitutional and
statutory interpretation).
1999] CREATE YOUR OWN CONSTITUTIONAL THEORY
CONCLUSION