Toward A Theory of Aesthetic Learning Experiences: P. Bruce Uhrmacher
Toward A Theory of Aesthetic Learning Experiences: P. Bruce Uhrmacher
Toward A Theory of Aesthetic Learning Experiences: P. Bruce Uhrmacher
P. BRUCE UHRMACHER
University of Denver
Denver, Colorado, USA
ABSTRACT
The purpose of this article is to reveal ways to provide the opportunity for students
to have aesthetically engaged learning experiences. Using John Deweys ideas from
Art as Experience as a framework, the author uses aesthetic theory to show how such
ends can be reached. In addition, he suggests six themes that teachers can draw
upon to help students attain engaged learning experiences. The themes, which are
elaborated upon fully in this article, include connections, active engagement,
sensory experience, perceptivity, risk taking, and imagination. In addition to pro-
viding engaged learning, the upshot of providing aesthetic learning experiences is
likely to include student satisfaction, an increase in perceptual knowledge, episodic
memory retention, meaning making, and creativity and innovation.
INTRODUCTION
students are doing school: They realize that they are caught in a system
where achievement depends more on doinggoing through the correct
motionsthan on learning and engaging with the curriculum (p. 4). This
point has been echoed in various ways over the years (Goodlad, 1984;
Powell, Farrar, & Cohen, 1985). Elliot Eisner (2005) suggests that inasmuch
as educators want to provide occasions for excitement, satisfaction, and
meaning, they ought to focus on degrees of engagement students display
in the classroom rather than test scores. Jennifer Fredricks, Phyllis Blu-
menfeld, and Alison Paris (2004) in their review of the literature on
engagement point out that despite various definitions (behavioral, emo-
tional, and cognitive) and measures, which in their view needs further
examination and synthesis, engagement is associated with positive
academic outcomes, including achievement and persistence in schools
(p. 87).
What, then, can we do to get all students engaged in classrooms? The
purpose of this article is to present a set of ideas derived from the arts to
assist educators in providing all students with enriched or aesthetically
engaging learning experiences regardless of the ultimate aims desired.
Whether aiming toward ideals set out in a core knowledge school or a
progressive school, teachers are in a position to help students turn their
ordinary learning experiences into aesthetic ones. The upshot of this trans-
formation is deep (Wong, 2007) or aesthetic engagement.
RELATED RESEARCH
David Wong (2007) has ten suggestions, which include ideas on provoking
imagination, creating a sense of an unfolding of events in which anticipa-
tion is fostered so that students feel like detectives, and encouraging stu-
dents to attend to or even dwell on their feelings in a situation. Wong also
offers what he calls provocative ideas, one of which is exploring faith in
education. By faith he does not mean a belief in a higher power, but a firm
belief in something for which there is no formal proof. Faith of this kind is
critical for deep engagement with new ideas (p. 214).
Girod, Rau, and Schepige (2003) offer five guidelines for science edu-
cators. These include crafting content (so that content becomes some-
thing that is relished [p. 579] rather than simply portrayed; crafting
dispositions [asking students to be imaginative]; artistic expansion of per-
ception [ re-seeing is an attempt to focus our perception on the nuance
and detail of the world [pp. 579580]); teacher modeling appreciation
and value for the transformative power of science ideas; and scaffolding
efficacy and identity beliefs, which means that teachers must capitalize on
students identity and efficacy beliefs as they unfold in experiencing a wide
range of emotions and dispositions: Aesthetic understanding forces us to
see and think about the world in very unusual ways and initial attempts in
this regard must be received in a nurturing way (p. 580).
I summarize Wongs and Girod, Rau, and Schepiges ideas, in particular,
to show the reader the kinds of ideas about aesthetic learning experiences
that are already circulating. Moreover, I believe they and others offer
important correctives about teaching and learning which are important in
any era, but especially in these times of high-stakes testing and the usage of
narrow types of accountability measures. While it is possible that these
practices may improve test scores, more importantly they are likely to
actually engage students in subject matter.
The ideas I put forth in this article are an attempt to contribute to
this small but growing literature on developing Deweys aesthetic
theory for educational implications. Because there is some overlap of my
work and that in the literature (e.g., imagination and perceptivity
[re-seeing], in particular), I hope my research serves to support and
encourage these ideas. Moreover, I add four other key themes, which I
hope will prove useful to both teachers in classrooms and educational
researchers.
A VARIETY OF EXPERIENCES
This section examines Deweys (1938) ideas about experience and learning
experiences, as well as aesthetic experiences and aesthetic learning expe-
riences. Deweys ideas begin with a focus on the concepts of interaction,
continuity, and growth (see pp. 3536, 51).3 Simply, an experience is an
interaction between the person and the environment in which one takes up
something from past experiences and modifies in some way the quality of
those which come after (p. 35). By attending to the idea of an interaction
between the person and the environment Dewey avoids the dualism of
mind/body. The whole person comes in contact with and grasps qualities
in the world. By noticing the past, present, and future of an experience,
Dewey indicates how people construct and reconstruct what we come to
learn and know. When experiences foster growth, we may think of them as
educative experiences. When experiences stunt growth, we may refer to
these as miseducative because they produce conditions that hinder further
interest in learning. Therefore, everything, says Dewey, depends upon
the quality of experience which is had (p. 27).
Oftentimes a particular quality pervades an experience, and then upon
reflection we refer to our experience by that quality. We say it was intellec-
tual, kinesthetic, emotional, boring, and so on. There are some experi-
ences that we have on occasion which are particularly sensory and
enlivened. These same experiences when brought to fruition may be
called aesthetic experiences:
In order to understand the esthetic in its ultimate and approved forms, one must
begin with it in the raw; in the events and scenes that hold the attentive eye and ear
of man, arousing his interest and affording him enjoyment as he looks and listens:
the sights that hold the crowdthe fire-engine rushing by; the machines excavating
enormous holes in the earth; the human-fly climbing the steeple-side; the men
perched high in air on girders, throwing and catching red-hot bolts. The sources of
art in human experience will be learned by him who sees how the tense grace of the
ball-player infects the onlooking crowd . . . the zest of the spectator in poking the
wood burning on the hearth and in watching the darting flames and crumbling
coals. (Dewey, 1934, pp. 45)
620 P. BRUCE UHRMACHER
The term aesthetics is derived from the Greek aesthetikos and means
capable of sensory perception. The German philosopher Alexander
Baumgarten (1735/1954) circumvented aesthetics as a branch of philoso-
phy dealing with art. But Dewey reinvigorated the term by opening it up to
refer to certain kinds of experiences that may be had in any aspect of
lifewith watching a campfire as well as with looking at impressionist
paintings.
If indeed aesthetic experiences take place in all walks of life, then this
includes learning situations. Indeed, students may have sensory learning
experiences in which they feel heightened vitality (Dewey, 1934, p. 19). Is
there a way to increase the possibility for students to have such heightened
learning experiences instead of ordinary ones? A clue can be found in the
way Dewey discusses artists, art, and appreciators of art.
Dewey noted that it is unfortunate that there is not one word describing
the experience of artists creating a work of art and a spectator who appre-
ciates it. He pointed out that the experiences undertaken by artists in
creating works of art are parallel to the experiences undertaken by appre-
ciators of the works of art (p. 54). According to Dewey, They are not the
same in any literal sense, but there is work done on the part of the
percipient as there is on the part of the artist (p. 54) if the experience is
to be something more than scattered and unfulfilled. Says Dewey, The one
who is too lazy, idle, or indurated in convention to perform this work will
not see or hear (p. 54). Such work,4 whether had by the artist or the
appreciator, may be called characteristics (themes) of aesthetic experi-
ences. By drawing out the characteristics or themes, teachers are able to
enhance classroom activities in numerous ways. Ill return to this idea at the
end of this article after examining the six aesthetic themes that are part of
the work needed to be done by artist, appreciator, teacher, or learner to
have an aesthetic experience.
Connections
That art weds man and nature is a familiar fact. Art also renders men aware of their
union with one another in origin and destiny. (Dewey, 1934, p. 271)
The first aesthetic theme that we will explore is connections, which may be
derived from Deweys big picture on aesthetic ideas. That is, Dewey offers
us the most general abstraction he seems capable of mustering. He points
out that an aesthetic experience has the potential of beginning when an
individual interacts (p. 246) with the environment. When the interaction
provides for an integrated experience and when it runs its course to fulfill-
ment, one has what might be called an aesthetic experience. When the
connection is not made, an aesthetic experience cannot be had. Dewey says
it this way:
TOWARD A THEORY OF AESTHETIC LEARNING EXPERIENCES 621
When the linkage of the self with its world is broken, then also the various ways in
which the self interacts with the world cease to have a unitary connection with one
another. . . . Intrinsic connection of the self with the world through reciprocity of
undergoing and doing . . . is a . . . main consideration. (p. 247)
Active Engagement
The intelligent mechanic engaged in his job, interested in doing well and finding
satisfaction in his handiwork, caring for his materials and tools with genuine affec-
tion, is artistically engaged. (Dewey, 1934, p. 5)
Another type of work, as Dewey would put it, that must be undergone
to have an aesthetic experience may be called active engagement. The
artist, the appreciator of art, or the student in the classroom must be
engaged with some kind of object focus for almost any kind of worthwhile
experience much less an aesthetic experience to be had:
. . . mind forms the background upon which every new contact with surroundings is
projected; yet background is too passive a word, unless we remember that it is
active. . . . This active and eager background lies in wait and engages whatever
comes its way so as to absorb it into its own being. (p. 264)
Having focused on the mind, Dewey is quick to point out that it is not
mind alone that engages in the world. As we saw earlier, ones whole being
is affected. Stated in the negative sense, Dewey writes that a conception of
mind as something isolated from the body strengthens the conception
which isolates the esthetic from those modes of experience in which the
body is actively engaged with the things of nature and life (p. 264). Hence,
an aesthetic experience is an active one. According to Dewey, To steep
ourselves in a subject-matter we have first to plunge into it. When we are
only passive to a scene, it overwhelms us (p. 53).
We now have two types of work that must be had to secure an aesthetic
experience. Placing these two together, we may say that an individual needs
to be actively engaged7 and connected to an object (or idea) of focus. The
next category is also essential for an aesthetic experience.
Sensory Experience
Perceptivity
Risk Taking
There is always a gap between the here and now of direct interaction and the past
interactions whose funded result constitutes the meanings with which we grasp and
understand what is now occurring. Because of this gap, all conscious perception
involves a risk; it is a venture into the unknown, for as it assimilates the present to
the past it also brings about some reconstruction of the past. (Dewey, 1934, p. 272)
Creating art is an uncertain affair, but how, one might ask, is appreciating
art risky? Where is the risk in having a private aesthetic experience? The
answer to these questions lies in the risk of opening up of oneself to
something newa new experience in understanding someone elses expe-
rience. Greene (1978) has referred to such experiences as wide-awakeness.
Whether one reads Alice Walker, Thomas Pynchon, or Robert Frost, or one
scrutinizes a painting by Willem de Kooning, Georgia OKeefe, or Pablo
Picasso, one remains open to new possibilities and new ways of seeing. The
willingness to be open is the place in which risk is involved.
Imagination
Whether we believe the ideas are really from a muse or from our pent-up
subconscious meanings, we may refer to such experiences as intuitive
imaginations.
Finally, we may also think of an interactive type of imagination, which is
the workhorse of experience. Coleridge calls it secondary, an echo of the
former, co-existing with the conscious will (Coleridge, 1817/1983, p. 304).
An artist engages with material and there is a dialogue that takes place.
When a writer, for instance, writes one sentence, the infinite world of
possibilities closes down. Now the narrative has a voice in what can be
saidwhat seems likely and probable. As the writer interacts with the
material she uses her imagination. She tries things out. She takes risks.
Sometimes the ideas work and sometimes they do not. In this sense imagi-
nation is interactive.
While the artist exhibits imagination, what about the appreciator of a
work of art? We dont often think of the appreciator as imaginative, but
Dewey notes that when an appreciator really has an artful experience, he or
she reconstructs the ideas and emotions that the artist placed in the work
of art in the first place. According to Dewey (1934),
For to perceive, a beholder must create his own experience. And his creation
must include relations comparable to those which the original producer under-
went. . . . The artist selected, simplified, clarified, abridged and condensed
according to his interest. The beholder must go through these operations
according to his point of view and interest. (p. 54)
AN EXAMPLE
Claire asks her students, Whats a constellation? There are numerous responses
from the students. One says, a shape, and another, a picture. Claire writes on the
board: A group of stars that makes a picture thats been named. Raise your hand,
she says, if you know the big dipper. A lot of hands go up. Its like a soup ladle,
she adds.
The students and teacher talk about numerous constellationsOrion, Pegasus,
Queen Victoria. Huh? says Claire. I havent heard of that one. Claire informs
students that constellations are tied to gods and goddesses, Greek myths, and
astrological signs: Orion, for example, is about a handsome and famous hunter
who fell in love with a goddess.
In their space booksindividual journalsClaire has students write the word
constellation and its definition. Next to the definition, they draw a picture of the big
dipper. But Claire adds, If you already did something different that is fine.
After a few minutes Claire says, Im going to talk while some of you finish writing.
Were going to make our own constellations. I made mine last night. Take out a
black piece of paper. Take a small handful of rock salt. Im going to toss it on the
black paper and then Im going to look and see if something comes to me. Dont
have an idea in advance.
She shows her example on the overhead. One student says he sees a policeman.
Someone else sees a horse. Next, says Claire, glue down these pieces of salt. After
that she tells them to draw lines and come up with a story about their picture.
Its not going to be perfect. Thats what is fun about this. We have to use our
imaginations.
We know that kids learn in different ways, like multiple intelligences and different
learning styles, and things like that. I think this gets to that too.
I have a couple students who its really hard to engage and so I worry that they will
be a little bit bored with space by the end of it, but my hope is to kind of go the other
direction and that they dont want to stop the unit.
First, she had her students imagine eating regular ice cream and describe how it
tasted. Students came up with words such as is cold, creamy, soft, icy, sweet,
and that it comes in a lot of colors. Students generated about 15 words and there
was some discussion about a few of them. When one student, for example, wanted
to add bitter to describe unsweetened cocoa, Claire suggested that they keep to
the description of ice cream and not toppings.
Then she gave each of her students the space ice cream and had them describe
what they noticed before eating it. The students noted that it was sticky, hard,
dry, light weight, flakey, room temperature, and stickyeven to itself.
Then the students ate it and added descriptors such as:
Claire said to me that without the idea of perceptivity, she would have
given the students the space ice cream at the end of the lesson as a kind of
treat, without any sensory elaboration. Consequently the students might
not have thought much about their experiences. But the theme of percep-
tivity encouraged her to dig deeper into the activity of eating ice cream
manufactured for space travel and as a result push the experience itself so
that the students were both conscious of the activity and reflective about it.
TOWARD A THEORY OF AESTHETIC LEARNING EXPERIENCES 629
One point to learn from this episode is that by moving toward providing
students with an aesthetically oriented activity, students had a rich and
enlivened lesson. It may not be the case that any of the students actually had
an aesthetic experience in the way Dewey might characterize it, but by
shifting the activity toward an aesthetically oriented one, the potential
results have an opportunity to be realized. To make this point by analogy,
consider the fact that one may not have a wow experience by viewing the
Mona Lisa. Nevertheless, the experiences leading up to the observation,
the observation itself, and the ruminations following the observation may
all lead to something that is enjoyable, edifying, and memorable.
Dewey (1934) noted that the non-esthetic lies within two limits. At one
pole is the loose succession that does not begin at any particular place and
that ends . . . at no particular place. At the other pole is arrest, constriction,
proceeding from parts having only a mechanical connection with one
another (p. 40). That there are two poles indicates that aesthetic experi-
ences exist on a continuum. For our purposes what is important to learn
here is that when teachers aim toward providing students with aesthetic
learning experiences, they may reach their educational goals (as indicated
below) even though each student may not have what could be called a
wow experience. There are numerous rungs on the ladder of aesthetically
oriented learning experiences, but I argue that each rung has the potential
to provide an enlivened educational experience.
POTENTIAL OUTCOMES
What happens when we engage in an aesthetic education in the classroom?
First, Id like to point out that teachers employing these themes ought to
use them in conjunction with each other. While it is not yet clear just what
combination of these themes needs to work together to enhance classroom
activities, I do believe that using these themes together augments the
possibilities. It does seem that connections, active engagement, and sensory
experiences are three themes that must be present. In addition, teachers
may utilize the themes by incorporating them in their lesson plans or they
may draw upon them in the moment. In regard to the former, I suggest that
teachers specifically include these themes in their lesson planning. Teach-
ers may ask themselves, Where is the risk taking? Or, How can I ensure that
students take charge of their own learning rather than having ideas thrust
upon them? In regard to teaching on the fly, if the teacher notices that the
activity is not working, she might draw on several themes, as though pulling
levers of paint, to coat the educational activity. I would suggest that when
doing so, one is able to improve the activity. Finally, reflection by the
students is a key experience that ought to be included in aesthetically
oriented lessons. Claire had students reflect on their experiences of eating
ice cream.
630 P. BRUCE UHRMACHER
can the subject contribute to the child, but we often forget to inquire as to
what the child can contribute to the subject matter. Such meaning making
is enhanced through activities that involve connections, risk, and imagina-
tion. One must first find the subject matter interesting. The student must
find a connection with it. Second, the student needs to work the subject
mattertransform it, which involves both risk and imagination. The risk
may be low level, but it comes into play in the sense that one must take a
chance particularly when expressing the newly realized meaning. The
potential outcome of meaning making is finding greater relevance in the
material being taught.
Finally, aesthetic experiences provide for the possibility of creativity and
innovation, two qualities stressed as being usefulin fact arguably,
mandatoryin the work world (Pink, 2006).12 By creativity I mean that one
is able to bring forth something new for the person who is doing the
creative work. Creativity should be seen from a personally referenced cri-
terion. The creative work does not need to be seen as new for the world, but
new for the person undergoing the process. By innovation, I mean that one
brings something new into the world. To be creative, one needs to be
imaginative. Imagination, as we saw earlier, refers to the fact that one has
the internal abilities to mess about, channel, or manipulate ideas or quali-
ties. Creative people are imaginative, but imaginative people are not nec-
essarily creative. Some people have an active inner life but cannot bring it
out into the world. Therefore, while the theme of imagination alone may
not lead to creativity, the themes of imagination and risk taking combined
are more likely to encourage creativity.
CONCLUSION
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
NOTES
1. Borrowing ideas and strategies depends on understanding the context from
which an idea initiates and the motivating rationale behind it and knowing how
the idea will play out in its new context, which includes awareness of aesthetic
preferences (Uhrmacher, 1997).
4. A better metaphor might have been play, but in this article I stick with the
term work because I believe Dewey was pointing out that an aesthetic expe-
rience is not to be taken lightlyit involves effort. Play, of course, can be seen
as serious business, but this point must be saved for another time.
6. Csikszentmihalyi and Robinson use the term perceptual, but to avoid confusion
with the themes of perceptivity and sensory experience, I use sensorial.
7. One could argue that aesthetic learning experiences as I describe them lead to
engagement because of the theme of active engagement alone. But I believe
that active engagement requires the other themes to provide deep or aes-
thetic engagement.
634 P. BRUCE UHRMACHER
10. Dewey discusses negative aesthetic experiences briefly. But his frequent use of
terms such as joy and satisfying in relation with aesthetic experiences certainly
suggests that he is much more concerned with positive ones. Admittedly, I am
more concerned with joyful learning experiences.
11. Thanks to Marty Tombari for helping me understand current research in brain
theory and how it supports aesthetic education.
12. Sir Ken Robinson (2006) distinguishes creativity (the process of having original
ideas) from innovation (putting ideas into practice).
REFERENCES
Aguirre, I. (2004). Beyond the understanding of visual culture: A pragmatist
approach to aesthetic education. International Journal of Art & Design Education,
23(3), 256269.
Alexander, T. M. (1987). John Deweys theory of art, experience and nature: The horizons
of feeling. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Arnheim, R. (1989). Thoughts on art education [Mimeo]. Los Angeles: J. Paul Getty
Center for Education in the Arts.
Augustine, S., & Zoss, M. (2006). Aesthetic flow experience in the teaching of
preservice language arts teachers. English Education, 39(1), 7295.
Baumgarten, A. (1954). Reflections on poetry. (K. Aschenbrenner & W. B. Holther,
Trans.). Berkeley: University of California Press. (Original work published
1735)
Bernstein, R. J. (1966). John Dewey. Washington, DC: Washington Square Press.
Booyeun, L. (2004). Aesthetic discourses in early childhood settings: Dewey,
Steiner, and Vygotsky. Early Child Development and Care, 174(5), 473486.
Coleridge, S. T. (1983). Biographia literaria (J. Engell & W. J. Bate, Eds.). Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press. (Original work published 1817)
Connelly, F. M. (Ed.). (2008). The Sage handbook of curriculum and instruction. Los
Angeles: Sage.
Cuban, L. (1993). How teachers taught: Constancy and change in American classrooms
18901990. New York: Teachers College Press.
Csikszentmihalyi, M., & Robinson, R. (1990). The art of seeing: An interpretation of the
aesthetic encounter. Malibu, CA: John Paul Getty Trust.
Dewey, J. (1934). Art as experience. New York: Perigee Books.
Dewey, J. (1938). Experience and education. New York: Collier Books.
Duckworth, E. (2006). The having of wonderful ideas and other essays on teaching and
learning (3rd ed.). New York: Teachers College Press.
Eisner, E., & Powell, K. (2002). Art in science? Curriculum Inquiry, 32(2), 131159.
Eisner, E. W. (1985). Aesthetic modes of knowing. In E. W. Eisner (Ed.), Learning
and teaching the ways of knowing: 84th yearbook of the National Society for the Study of
Education, Part II (pp. 2336). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Eisner, E. W. (1994a). The educational imagination: On the design and evaluation of
school programs (3rd ed.). New York: Prentice Hall.
TOWARD A THEORY OF AESTHETIC LEARNING EXPERIENCES 635