Bastards Auto Saved)
Bastards Auto Saved)
Bastards Auto Saved)
drturner@mindspring.com
©2010
system is all about. In each case that goes before a judge, each side will cite those cases that
support its version of the case, and the judge's job is to decide which side's cases most closely
Activists expand on this practice in their public advocacy, asserting that their claim to
injustice is analogous to that of other, previously successful movements. In doing so, they
perform the practice that Jack Balkin and Reva Siegel have identified, that of applying old
principles to old practices in new ways, thereby usually changing both the principles and the
practices.1 Lesbian, gay, bisexual, and transgender (LGBT) civil rights activists plainly pursue
these strategies as part of their movement. They apply old constitutional principles of privacy
and equal protection of the laws to assertedly old (although not as old as their advocates often
practice that the United States Supreme Court invalidated using the old principle of equal
protection of the laws. The African American civil rights movement is always an inviting target
for social movement comparisons, given its enormous success in statutes and case law, and its
One area of constitutional law that lesbian/gay rights activists have mostly failed to
explore in seeking analogies to buttress their legal claims is cases involving non-marital
children.3 The parallels between cases of discrimination against non-marital children and cases
of discrimination against lesbians and gay men are striking, and very encouraging from the
LGBT rights perspective. The United States Supreme Court developed over the course of some
twenty years a highly consistent doctrinal position according to which discrimination against
non-marital children for the sole purpose of expressing the community’s moral condemnation
violates the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth Amendment for essentially the same
reasons that discrimination based on sexual orientation does so. It places legal burdens on
individuals without regard to individual responsibility or culpability, punishing them for their
status, not for their conduct. Such discrimination against non-marital children is constitutionally
permissible only where the state can show some administrative necessity, usually in the
disposition of decedents’ estates. No such administrative necessity exists with respect to lesbians
Thus, these cases provide solid doctrinal ammunition against Antonin Scalia’s claim that
legislation discriminating against lesbians and gay men for the sole purpose of expressing the
community’s moral standards is constitutionally acceptable. One reason to examine these cases
is that, on the basis of the public debates over lesbian/gay civil rights claims, everyone – Justices
Scalia implicitly took this position – that the majority’s moral preferences simpliciter are
valid justification for legislation -- in his dissent in Romer v. Evans, the 1996 case in which the
United States Supreme Court invalidated a state constitutional amendment that repealed all
existing local lesbian/gay rights ordinances and prohibited any entity of state government from
using lesbian, gay, or bisexual as the basis for any sort of civil rights protection.4 Dissenting,
Scalia found in the amendment only “a modest attempt by seemingly tolerant Coloradans to
preserve traditional sexual mores against the efforts of a politically powerful minority to revise
Dissenting in Lawrence v. Texas, the 2003 case in which the Supreme Court overruled
Bowers v. Hardwick, which had found state sodomy laws constitutionally acceptable, and struck
down the sodomy law of Texas, and by implication all other state sodomy laws, Scalia made
explicit his belief that the majority's moral preferences are a constitutionally sufficient basis for
Countless judicial decisions and legislative enactments have relied on the ancient
proposition that a governing majority's belief that certain sexual behavior is "immoral and
4
Romer v. Evans 517 U.S. 620 (1996).
5
Id.
unacceptable" constitutes a rational basis for regulation.... State laws against bigamy,
bestiality, and obscenity are likewise sustainable only in light of Bowers' validation of
The cases involving non-marital children belie this claim, as well as Scalia's other doctrinal
The cases involving non-marital children consistently and squarely hold that the bare
justification for legislation. Justice Kennedy made this point in his majority opinion via a
quotation from Justice Stevens' dissent in Bowers: “…the fact that the governing majority in a
State has traditionally viewed a particular practice as immoral is not a sufficient reason for
upholding a law prohibiting the practice; neither history nor tradition could save a law
prohibiting miscegenation from constitutional attack.”7 Here Stevens practices casuistry in both
the narrow legal and the broad social movement sense, analogizing from a famous case striking
down explicitly racist legislation to legislation that was homophobic in effect, if not on its face.
Similarly, Justice O'Connor, in her concurrence, agreeing with the holding of Lawrence
but basing her conclusion on the equal protection clause of the fourteenth amendment, rather
than the right to privacy under substantive due process, as the majority held, stated flatly that
This case raises a different issue than Bowers: whether, under the Equal Protection
Clause, moral disapproval is a legitimate state interest to justify by itself a statute that
bans homosexual sodomy, but not heterosexual sodomy. It is not. Moral disapproval of
this group, like a bare desire to harm the group, is an interest that is insufficient to satisfy
6
Lawrence, 539 U.S. 558 (Scalia dissenting).
7
Ibid., quoting Bowers, 478 U.S. at 216 (Stevens dissenting).
rational basis review under the Equal Protection Clause.... Indeed, we have never held
that moral disapproval, without any other asserted state interest, is a sufficient rationale
under the Equal Protection Clause to justify a law that discriminates among groups of
persons.8
O'Connor made no mention of the cases involving non-marital children, finding ample precedent
In his Lawrence dissent, Scalia objected not only to the substance of its holding, but also
to the majority's procedure in arriving at that holding. He accuses the majority and the
concurrence of “apply[ing] an unheard-of form of rational-basis review that will have far-
reaching implications beyond this case.” Although the majority's opinion in fact applies
something one might call “rational basis plus,” it does not explicitly address the issue.
O'Connor, however, cites various cases for the proposition that “When a law exhibits such a
desire to harm a politically unpopular group, we have applied a more searching form of rational
basis review to strike down such laws under the Equal Protection Clause.” Again, O'Connor did
not cite any of the cases involving non-marital children here, but she might well have. Like the
majority opinion in Lawrence, the non-marital children cases do not much discuss the standard
of review involved, but they do tend to apply something that looks like “rational basis plus.”
The later cases explicitly hold that status as a non-marital child is not suspect at the level of
racial or ethnic identity, meaning that strict scrutiny, which the Court applies to legislation
relying on racial or ethnic categories, does not apply to statutes affecting non-marital children.
Even so, the Court held squarely and repeatedly that the expression of the majority's moral
8
Lawrence, 539 U.S. 558 (O'Connor concurring).
There is also a compelling strategic reason for lesbian/gay activists to foreground cases
involving non-marital children. Insofar as the unstated purpose, but certainly the obvious effect,
of statutes disfavoring non-marital children is plainly to allow men to escape responsibility for
their extra-marital sexual activity, this is very much and very directly a feminist issue. It thus
presents an opportunity, along with defense of abortion rights,9 for lesbian/gay activists to make
There is also the obvious, but rarely remarked, point that, in a regime where few states
recognize marriage rights for same-sex couples, the many children born to same-sex couples are,
by definition, non-marital. Beyond our desire to protect our children from any sort of stigma,
legal or otherwise, for being non-marital, there is the point that, both politically and legally,
lesbian/gay activists should do more to encourage the children of same-sex couples to speak out
against discrimination against their parents. Following Balkin and Siegal, lesbian/gay legal
activists should explore methods of using equal protection decisions on behalf of non-marital
children to secure rights for their parents – using an old principle in a novel way to challenge an
old practice. Prohibitions on same-sex marriage, after all, have the effect of visiting invidious
discrimination on the heads of their children, discrimination that is irrational and unjust for the
The remainder of this article consists of an examination of the cases in which the United
States Supreme Court reviewed statutes and policies disfavoring non-marital children in various
ways. This discussion emphasizes the ways in which the issue of non-marital children and the
community’s moral sensibility resembles cases involving lesbian/gay civil rights claims.
9
I take it that, apart from the doctrinal similarity of “privacy rights” that grounds the
Supreme Court's decisions striking down prohibitions on both abortion and sodomy, the
underlying rationale for the right to abortion and the right to sodomy are the same: both
involve claims to bodily autonomy at a profound and fundamental level, and resistance to
domination by heterosexual men, the need for which lesbians and gay men share with
women. Together, we are the majority, so why do we let them run the place?
Between 1968 and 1986, the Supreme Court heard fourteen cases involving statutes or
Court upheld the statutes in only four of these cases, striking down the statute or policy in all
others.11
The first of these cases, Levy v. Louisiana, involved Louisiana statutes that prevented five
non-marital children from filing a wrongful death action at the death of their mother, and from
continuing a cause of action that the mother had initiated before her death. The majority's
opinion set out a conceptual framework that would govern all subsequent cases, with
disagreement largely around the margins of the central definitions. In an indication of the
10
Reed v. Campbell, 476 U.S. 852 (1986) (Reversal of Texas appeals court's upholding of decision excluding non-
marital child from father's estate under statute that excluded all non-marital children from decedent parent's estate
unless parents subsequently married, despite Trimble v. Gordon, Supreme Court decision invalidating essentially
identical statute from another state on the argument that Trimble did not apply retroactively); Trimble v. Gordon,
430 U.S. 762, 767 n.11 (1977) (striking down on equal protection grounds an Illinois statute that categorically
prohibited non-marital children from taking in intestacy from their fathers even where the decedent had legally
acknowledged paternity); Jimenez v. Weinberger, 417 U.S. 628 (1974) (striking down on due process/equal
protection grounds a categorical prohibition on receipt of Social Security disability benefits by non-marital children
born after the parent’s disability); Gomez v. Perez, 409 U.S. 535 (1973) (striking down on equal protection grounds
Texas law holding that non-marital children have no claim to support from their fathers, unlike marital children);
New Jersey Welfare Rights Org. v. Cahill, 411 U.S. 619 (1973) (striking down on equal protection grounds
provision of New Jersey welfare statute that categorically denied benefits to non-marital children); Weber v. Aetna
Casualty & Surety Co, 406 U.S. 164 (1972) (striking down on equal protection grounds Louisiana statute allowing
unacknowledged, non-marital children to recover under workers’ compensation only to the extent that other
claimants did not exhaust the amount available for remedy); Griffin v. Richardson, 346 F. Supp. 1226 (Md.),
summarily aff’d, 409 U.S. 1069 (1972) (striking down on equal protection grounds portion of federal statute that
allows non-marital children to receive Social Security benefits on parent’s death only if other, favored, claimants do
not exhaust the available benefit); Davis v. Richardson, 342 F. Supp. 588 (Conn.), summarily aff’d, 409 U.S. 1069
(1972) (same as Griffin); Glona v. American Guarantee & Liability Ins. Co., 391 U.S. 73 (1968) (per curiam)
(striking down under equal protection Louisiana statute that prohibited mother from filing wrongful death suit at
death of her non-marital child); Levy v. Louisiana, 391 U.S. 68 (1968) (striking down state's statutory scheme that
precluded children from pursuing wrongful death action for their mother's death, or continuing a cause of action that
she had initiated during her lifetime).
11
Lalli v. Lalli, 439 U.S. 259 (1978) (plurality opinion)(upholding against equal protection challenge a New York
state statute requiring non-marital child to show judicial recognition of decedent’s paternity before allowing the
child to take in intestacy); Matthews v. Lucas, 427 U.S. 495 (1976) (upholding against due process/equal protection
challenge federal statute requiring showing claimant’s actual dependency on decedent in order for non-marital
children to receive survivors’ benefits under Social Security); Beaty v. Weinberger, 478 F.2d 300 (CA5 1973),
summarily aff’d, 418 U.S. 901 (1974) (upholding against equal protection challenge federal policy categorically
prohibiting non-marital children from receiving Social Security benefits via parent’s disability claim)”; Labine v.
Vincent, 401 U.S. 532 (1971) (upholding against equal protection and due process challenges a Louisiana statute
excluding non-marital children from taking in intestacy unless the father legally acknowledge paternity).
general opprobrium non-marital children suffered under at the time, the Court began by stating
what one would hope was obvious: “We start from the premise that illegitimate children are not
'nonpersons.' They are humans, live, and have their being. They are clearly 'persons' within the
meaning of the Equal Protection Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment.”12 It then offered a short,
pedestrian review of Court doctrine regarding review of state legislation under the equal
protection clause, explaining that, while states have broad leeway to classify their citizens, still
In evaluating the rationality of state statutory classifications, “we have been extremely
sensitive when it comes to basic civil rights and have not hesitated to strike down an invidious
classification even though it had history and tradition on its side.”14 The opinion contains no
explicit discussion of standard of review. This statement, however, does indicate that the Court
is applying O'Connor's “more searching form of rational basis review,” and for the same reasons
that O'Connor invoked it: that the law in question seemed to have as its primary or sole purpose
to express animosity toward the group in question. In the end, the Court concluded that the
children's status as non-marital was, or should be, irrelevant to their legal claims.
In particular, the Court noted that, because the present case involved tort actions, for
wrongful death and, apparently, the mother's separate cause of action, by denying her children
the opportunity to initiate a wrongful death action or continue the mother's separate action, the
Louisiana statutes had the undesirable effect of allowing tortfeasors to escape liability for no
12
Levy, 391 U.S. at (footnotes omitted). See infra, discussion of Trimble v. Gordon for
common law doctrine that non-marital children were filius nullius, or “son of nobody” from
the Latin.
13
Id.
14
Id. (citations omitted)
The same year, in Glona v. American Guaranty & Liability Ins. Co., the Court also struck
down a Louisiana statute that had the inverse effect, of prohibiting a mother from filing a
wrongful death action for the death of her non-marital child. The court offered an overview of
course.”15 Louisiana's statutes made no distinction between marital and non-marital children for
purposes of defining incest, and the mother could inherit from a non-marital but recognized child
on the child's death, just as she could take under the state's workers' compensation law were she
in fact dependent on the child who died as the result of a workplace accident.16 Louisiana's
defense of its “curious course” gets to the core of the issue with respect both to non-marital
children and lesbians and gay men: “Yet it is argued that since the legislature is dealing with
'sin,' it can deal with it selectively and is not compelled to adopt comprehensive or even
consistent measures.”
This argument has a sort of intuitive plausibility to anyone who grew up in the
overwhelmingly Christian culture of the United States, yet one hesitates to attempt any rational
explanation of it, insofar as the point seems to be that, because the classification of actions as
“sin” is itself inherently not a product of rational calculation, then any subsidiary classifications
may also escape any inquiry as to their rationality. Insofar as all legislation at base deals in
essentially moral claims and classifications, this argument seems to allow a blanket escape hatch
by which all statutes could elude examination of their rationality. Statutes prohibiting same-sex
sexual activity, and otherwise imposing disabilities on lesbians and gay men, have their origin in
15
Glona v. American Guarantee & Liability Ins. Co., 391 U.S. 73 (1968).
16
Id.
similar Christian notions of “sin,” and degree of religiosity is a strong indicator of likely hostility
toward the rights claims of lesbians and gay men.17 Such statutes also lack all rational basis.
The Court goes on to note that the statute can scarcely be defended as an effective means
for deterring the getting of non-marital children. “It would, indeed, be farfetched to assume that
women have illegitimate children so that they can be compensated in damages for their death.”18
It then makes a point similar to that of Levy: “A law which creates an open season on
illegitimates in the area of automobile accidents gives a windfall to tortfeasors. But it hardly has
a causal connection with the 'sin,' which is, we are told, the historic reason for the creation of the
disability.”19 Such statutes thus have the dual flaws of allowing the irresponsible to escape the
The next case, Labine v. Vincent, presented facts that would become common in
subsequent cases involving non-marital children. It is the first of the cases in which the Court
upheld the statute and represents thereby a departure from the larger legal trend. The case again
originated in Louisiana, this time challenging on equal protection grounds a statutory scheme
that prohibited non-marital children from taking from their fathers' estates in intestacy even
17
BERNICE E. LOTT & DIANE MALUSO, THE SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY OF INTERPERSONAL DISCRIMINATION (1995), 84-85.
As an aside, this seems to me to be ample reason to eschew the whole notion of “sin” in any
public law. Them as wants to subject themselves to a religious regime that talks about sin
should be free to do so, but it is not a concept that can ever meet the standards of public
rationality that Americans rightly expect from their laws.
18
Id.
19
Id.
20
I should note here that, with most states not yet recognizing marriage rights for same-sex
couples, virtually all of the many children born to such couples are non-marital. I certainly
wish to visit no comdemnation, legal or moral, on such children. Apart from the children of
same-sex couples, visiting any disability on non-marital children seems like an obviously bad
idea. Children are children and we as a society have the responsibility to care for them,
regardless of how they got here. Again, I can see nothing in such statutes except the desire
of heterosexual men to escape responsibility for their extra-marital sexual activity, not a
goal that I, or our society as a whole, can or should endorse or abet.
where the father had formally acknowledged the child. The Court distinguished Levy by noting,
in part, that Levy involved tort claims, rather than inheritance, and asserted that
the Court held that the State could not totally exclude from the class of potential plaintiffs
illegitimate children who were unquestionably injured by the tort that took their mother's
life. Levy did not say and cannot fairly be read to say that a State can never treat an
The Court then went on to compare the relationship of non-marital to marital children with that
of a wife and a concubine and asserted that the state surely could protect the interests of legally
One obvious flaw in this analogy is that, in the concubine/wife comparison, there is
always an individual, the wife, whose interests the law can legitimately protect by disfavoring
the other party. With non-marital children, whether the father does or does not have marital
children will vary by case. Also, all children, unlike all concubines, require various forms of
support from adults in order to grow themselves into productive adults. Depriving any child of
such support is plainly not in the best interests of the larger society, regardless of the social harm
one my posit as stemming from non-marital sexual relations. The Court then concluded the issue
in Labine by resort to the sort of tautology beloved of judicial conservatives: “One set of
relationships is socially sanctioned, legally recognized, and gives rise to various rights and
duties. The other set of relationships is illicit and beyond the recognition of the law.”23
Concubines and non-marital children lack rights because, well, because the state says so. Case
closed.
21
Id.
22
Id.
23
Id.
The Court ends its opinion by further explaining the difference it sees between this case
and Levy. In Levy, the Court asserts, the state had created an “insurmountable barrier” to
recovery by non-marital children. In Labine, by contrast, the father could have left a will
identifying the child as a beneficiary, or he could have legitimated the child by marrying her
mother, or by stating his intent to legitimate her in the formal, notarized acknowledgement of
paternity that he executed (no, such notarized acknowledgement of paternity was not sufficient
Predictably, Justice Brennan dissented, joined by Justices Douglas, White, and Marshall.
He asserted that the Court acknowledged that the Louisiana statute discriminates against the non-
marital child in a manner that violates the equal protection clause, but allowed this
discrimination by simply excluding the child from the protection of the clause. He then turned
the favorite charge of judicial conservatives against judicial liberals back on the conservatives in
the majority: “Based upon such a premise, today's decision cannot even pretend to be a
principled decision. This is surprising from Justices who have heretofore so vigorously decried
decisionmaking rested upon personal predilections, to borrow the Court's words, of 'life-tenured
judges of this Court'”25 The majority opinion, on Brennan's view, is an unprincipled reflection of
He concludes, damningly:
The conclusion the Court appears to draw from its itemization of other discriminations
among a deceased's relatives is that Louisiana needs no justification at all for any of the
distinctions it draws. That reasoning flies in the face not only of the Equal Protection and
24
Id.
25
Id. (Brennan dissenting).
Due Process Clauses of the Fourteenth Amendment, but also of the very notion of a rule
of law.26
Brennan earlier noted that the state's authority to regulate family relationships was not at issue
and not contested in this case. Here he accuses the majority of careening off to the opposite
extreme: in its zeal to protect the state's power to regulate,27 it effectively removes all restraints
on that power, which is of course completely antithetical to the genius of American government.
Brennan criticized the majority's “the law is what the state says the law is, case closed
reasoning” thus:
It is, to say the least, bewildering that a Court that for decades has wrestled with the
nuances of the concept of 'state action' in order to ascertain the reach of the Fourteenth
Amendment, in this case holds that the state action here, because it is state action, is
He goes on to note that the majority's basis for distinguishing Levy is mistaken: there, the child
could have pursued a wrongful death action had the parent formally acknowledged the child; no
Brennan concludes with an observation that he would make again in a subsequent dissent,
26
Id.
27
Conservatives love to complain that any attempt to eliminate sodomy laws is a wholesale
attack on the power of government to govern. See Bowers, “This is essentially not a question of
personal "preferences" but rather of the legislative authority of the State” (Burger concurring);
Lawrence, “The impossibility of distinguishing homosexuality from other traditional 'morals'
offenses is precisely why Bowers rejected the rational-basis challenge. 'The law,' it said, 'is
constantly based on notions of morality, and if all laws representing essentially moral choices are
to be invalidated under the Due Process Clause, the courts will be very busy indeed'” (Scalia
dissenting, quoting Bowers). This is a bizarre claim.
28
id. (Brennan dissenting).
29
Id. (Brennan dissenting).
In my judgment, only a moral prejudice, prevalent in 1825 when the Louisiana statutes
illegitimate children. Since I can find no rational basis to justify the distinction Louisiana
The implication is clear: in Brennan's view, at least, “moral prejudice” simpliciter is not a
constitutionally sufficient ground for legislation. Here he clearly poses the dichotomy: moral
prejudice on one hand, rational basis for legislation on the other, and never the twain shall meet.
The next two cases dealing with non-marital children the Court decided at the same time
in 1972, summarily affirming district court opinions striking down provisions of the Social
Security Act that allowed non-marital children to claim death benefits on a parent's earnings
record only insofar as other, more favored, beneficiaries did not exhaust the available benefit.31
Thus, by 1972, the Court had firmly established the principle that statutes and policies, state or
The next case to produce an opinion from the Court, also in 1972, was Weber v. Aetna
Casualty & Surety Co.32 Weber would subsequently become a lodestar case for disputes
involving the rights of non-marital children.33 Weber involved the claims of two non-marital
children to benefits under the workers' compensation statutes of Louisiana, which held that non-
marital children could receive such benefits only insofar as other beneficiaries in more favored
classes did not exhaust the available amount. In this respect, it presented essentially the same
30
Id. (Brennan dissenting).
31
Griffin v. Richardson, 346 F. Supp. 1226 (Md.); Davis v. Richardson, 342 F. Supp. 588 (Conn.), both
the Court cited Levy and Glona. In Weber, the deceased's household included four legitimate
children by the deceased's wife, who was then committed to a mental hospital, and two non-
marital children by the deceased's co-habitant, whom he could not marry, having a living spouse.
The award under workers' compensation to the four marital children exhausted the available
In sustaining the state's statutory scheme, the Louisiana courts held that the present facts
more resembled those of Labine, where the Supreme Court had upheld the state statute, than
Levy, where the Court had struck the statute down. Noting the similar historical origins and legal
reasoning behind wrongful death statutes and workers' compensation statutes, the Supreme Court
Given the similarities in the origins and purposes of these two statutes, and the similarity
precedent and the principle of stare decisis to hold that Levy did not control the facts of
The language that would prove to make Weber a lodestar for subsequent cases appears in
The status of illegitimacy has expressed through the ages society's condemnation of
irresponsible liaisons beyond the bonds of marriage. But visiting this condemnation on
the head of an infant is illogical and unjust. Moreover, imposing disabilities on the
illegitimate child is contrary to the basic concept of our system that legal burdens should
an unjust—way of deterring the parent. Courts are powerless to prevent the social
opprobrium suffered by these hapless children, but the Equal Protection Clause does
enable us to strike down discriminatory laws relating to status of birth where—as in this
otherwise.35
To state what may already be obvious, it is the argument of this article that the reasoning the
Court here articulates with respect to non-marital children applies, or should apply, with equal
force to lesbians and gay men, and to all legislation that imposes burdens on them.
Imposing burdens on lesbians and gay men “is contrary to the basic concept of our
system that legal burdens should bear some relationship to individual responsibility or
wrongdoing.” Even under the previous regime in which the Court found state statutes
prohibiting sodomy constitutional,36 the blanket discrimination visited on lesbians and gay men
rarely, if ever, depended on a successful prosecution for having violated such statute; more, most
of those statutes historically prohibited the conduct in question for all persons, making no
distinction among the gender or sex of the participants.37 The discrimination in most states
should, under the concept of equal protection of the laws, have aimed at all persons, regardless of
sexual orientation, who practiced sodomy, which many heterosexual couples do.38 As Justice
35
Id.
36Bowers v. Hardwick, 478 U.S. 1039, overruled by Lawrence v. Texas, 537 U.S. 1231.
37
This was true even in Bowers, although the Court chose to ignore that fact, characterizing
the issue as the right of “homosexuals” to engage in sodomy.
38
See Michael Rocke, Forbidden Friendships (1998) 215-16 (discussion of prosecutions for
heterosexual sodomy in late 15th and early 16th century Florence); Geraldine Bedell,
“'Unnatural,' Maybe, but Not Unknown: It Is Dangerous to Make Assumptions about What is
Normal Sex, Says Geraldine Bedell,” The Independent, July 5, 1992,
http://www.independent.co.uk/life-style/unnatural-maybe-but-not-unknown-it-is-dangerous-
to-make-assumptions-about-what-is-normal-sex-says-geraldine-bedell-1531306.html (last
visited, July 7, 2009) (article estimating that 20 to 43 percent of married women had tried
“sodomy,” referred to subsequently in the article as “anal intercourse,” although most
sodomy statutes have been understood to prohibit fellatio and cunnilingus as well. See
Kennedy noted in overruling Bowers v. Hardwick, the case upholding state sodomy statutes,
statutes aimed specifically at same-sex couples were a relatively recent permutation on the basic
crime.39
way of deterring” individuals from identifying as lesbian or gay. Neither sodomy statutes, nor
the various other disabilities that American law has variously visited on lesbians and gay men,
dissuaded all persons from adopting that identity. Indeed, those disabilities have had exactly the
opposite effect, causing large numbers of lesbians and gay men to assert their identities all the
Indeed, avowal of one's lesbian/gay identity has become a central tactic for lesbian/gay rights
activists on the logic that opinion polling data show that persons who know a lesbian or gay man
are more likely to support their rights claims than persons who do not. As I have argued
elsewhere, this vigorous participation in the political process is itself a separate reason why
courts should strike down all discriminations based on sexual orientation and gender identity
Finally, in effect anticipating its subsequent holdings in Romer v. Evans and Lawrence v.
Texas, the Court in Weber stated that “the classification is justified by no legitimate state interest,
compelling or otherwise.” Brennan's use of the term, “compelling” here seems to anticipate the
emergence of “compelling state interest” as the most common phrase the Court uses to indicate
the requirement the state must meet for any use of racial or ethnic classifications to pass
Lawrence, 517 U.S. at xxx for Texas sodomy statute defining “deviate sexual intercourse” as
"(A) any contact between any part of the genitals of one person and the mouth or anus of another person; or (B) the
penetration of the genitals or the anus of another person with an object."
39
Lawrence, 517 U.S. 1231.
40
William B. Turner, The National Masturbators' Task Force, SSRN abs. #1120588.
constitutional muster.41 The finding that a law must serve a compelling state interest, of course,
triggers the Court's strict scrutiny review, the most difficult form of review for a statute to
survive. This opinion, like Levy, thus seems to rest on rational basis plus review.
The Court's next review of a statutory scheme discriminating against non-marital children
came from Texas, where a state court found that the respondent was the biological father of the
child, and that the child needed the father's support, but held that, because the child was
“illegitimate,” it had no legal claim to support from the father.42 As noted above, all of the
statutes and policies at issue in these cases in varying ways have the effect, nowhere stated as the
express purpose, of allowing men to escape responsibility for their extra marital sexual activity.
This effect appears no where so glaringly, however, as in this case, where a judge could hold that
the respondent was in fact the child's father, and the child needed support, but state statutes
prevented the judge from ordering that support solely because the child was non-marital. The
Texas appeals court sustained this decision against constitutional challenge, and the Texas
Supreme Court refused to hear the appeal. The United States Supreme Court granted certiorari
The U.S. Court rehearsed Texas statutes holding fathers responsible for supporting their
children, noting that such responsibility survives the end of the father's marriage to the mother,
applies regardless of whether the father has custody of the children in question, and is
enforceable by resort to criminal sanctions if necessary. It then reviewed its holdings in Levy
41
See, e.g., Grutter v. Bollinger,539 U.S. 306 (2003) (majority finding that diversity in
educational institutions is a compelling state interest, such that law school's race-based
affirmative action policy is constituionally acceptable, while dissenters all assert that the
majority's scrutiny of the affirmative action policy is anything but strict); Adarand
Constructors, Inc. v. Pena, 515 U.S. 200, 227 (clear statement of the doctrine that racial
classifications will undergo strict scrutiny to detemine if they are narrowly tailored to
achieve a compelling state interest).
42
Gomez v. Perez, 409 U.S. 535.
43
Id.
and Weber, concluding with this sweeping declaration against paternal irresponsibility: “We
therefore hold that once a State posits a judicially enforceable right on behalf of children to
needed support from their natural fathers there is no constitutionally sufficient justification for
denying such an essential right to a child simply because its natural father has not married its
mother.”44 Need I point out that the scheme under which the father could escape his support
obligation just by not marrying the mother was a virtual invitation to men to abandon their non-
The Court followed Gomez in the same year, 1973, with New Jersey Welfare Rights
Organization v. Cahill. This decision produced a notably brief opinion in which the Court
succinctly stated the facts, which were that, through its definition of the family types that were
eligible for public assistance, the state worked discrimination against non-marital children
without stating such discrimination explicitly. It then quoted the final paragraph of Weber,
quoted above, and restated the holdings of Weber, Levy, and Gomez to hold the New Jersey
Next, in Jiminez v. Weinberger, the Court reviewed a provision of the Social Security Act
prohibiting non-marital children born after the parent's disability from receiving disability
insurance payments absent a showing either that the father resided with the claimant, or was
actually supporting the claimant at the time of the disability, in contrast to marital children and
subsequently legitimated non-marital children. Jiminez was the father of three children with his
partner, had publicly acknowledged being their father, and had become their sole caretaker at the
departure from the household of the children's mother. Because the first child was born before
Jiminez became eligible for disability payments, she qualified for coverage of her own. The
44
Id.
other two children, by contrast, having been born after Jiminez's qualification for disability
Each side pointed to a Supreme Court decision assertedly supporting its position. The
Secretary of Health, Education, and Welfare relied on Dandridge v. Williams,45 where the Court
upheld a state's public assistance program that made no distinction in benefits regardless of
family size against a constitutional challenge. Appellants pointed by contrast to Weber for the
suspect.46 The Court distinguished Dandridge, noting that its decision in that case turned
significantly on the fact of limited resources, making rational the state's decision to support some
families sufficiently, but others less sufficiently, rather than supporting all families insufficiently.
The Court found no such concern operating in the case of the Social Security system, noting the
Secretary's own insistence that the prohibition on afterborn non-marital children from receiving
benefits was designed solely to minimize fraud resulting from spurious, including collusive,
claims to paternity.47
The Court then noted that all marital children, and certain classes of afterborn non-marital
children, qualified for benefits with no showing of actual dependence on the disabled wage
earner, whereas afterborn non-marital children who could not be legitimated under state law
were categorically barred from receiving benefits regardless of their actual dependence on the
disabled wage earner. The discrimination, then, was not between all non-marital and all marital
children, but between two subclasses of non-marital children. This discrimination was both
overinclusive, in allowing benefits to some children who were not in fact dependent on the
disabled wage earner, and underinclusive in denying benefits to some children who were in fact
45
397 U.S. 471 (1970).
46
Id.
47
Id.
so dependent. The distinction rested solely on the concern to prevent spurious claims. The
Court noted, however, that “the potential for spurious claims is the same as to both,” rendering
protection component of the Fifth Amendment.48 It did not note, though it might well have, that
such concern was completely unjustified on the instant facts because the father had publicly
acknowledged the children as his. This is a rare instance in which, because the mother had left
the household, the deleterious effects of the statute fell on a man rather than a woman, in
In 1976, the Court upheld an essentially identical provision of the Social Security
program against similar constitutional attacks. Both Matthews v. Lucas49 and Norton v.
Matthews50 resembled Jiminez in placing a higher burden of proof of dependence on certain non-
marital children not, as in Jiminez, for receipt of benefits at the parent's disability, but at the
parent's death. Relying on Jiminez and Gomez, the district court reversed the Secretary's
administrative denial of benefits in Matthews and ordered him to pay benefits to the claimants.51
Norton presented the same substantive issue, but also somewhat complicated jurisdictional issues
resulting from its status as a class action suit that need not detain us here (in Norton, note that the
father was serving in the Army in Vietnam and had begun the process of acquiring dependents'
pay for his child, but did not complete the application before dying in combat).52
These cases are obviously outliers in terms of this article's discussion of the cases in that
both involve upholding, rather than striking down, discriminations based on the marital/non-
marital distinction. The majority in Matthews distinguished Jiminez by asserting that Congress
48
Id.
49
427 U.S. 495 (1976).
50
427 U.S. 524 (1976).
51
Matthews, 427 U.S. 495.
52
Norton, 427 U.S. 524.
had based its statutory scheme on “reasonable empirical judgments that are consistent with a
design to qualify entitlement to benefits upon a child's dependency at the time of the parent's
death.” Those “reasonable empirical judgments” in turn served the rational interest in
“administrative convenience,” allowing the administration “to avoid the burden and expense of
long as that lack of precise equivalence does not exceed the bounds of substantiality tolerated by
the applicable level of scrutiny.”53 This despite the same problems of overinclusiveness and
underinclusiveness as in Jiminez.
Matthews is the first of these cases to contain an explicit discussion of the appropriate
level of review. It does so because the district court had found that non-marital status is like race
and ethnicity in requiring strict scrutiny from the courts. The Supreme Court disagreed with the
district court's finding on this point.54 Again quoting Weber's explanation that the non-marital
classification is inherently unjust and irrational, still the majority in Matthews cited other cases
involving non-marital children to note that it had invalidated statutes discriminating against the
class without finding that the class was suspect at the level of race or ethnicity. It also noted that,
merely because a classification is unconstitutional as applied in some contexts does not entail the
conclusion that it is unconstitutional in all contexts. Finally, the Matthews majority noted that
the discrimination that non-marital children suffered has never been so pervasive and severe as
that visited on women or racial and ethnic minorities. The Court concluded that “We conclude
that the statutory classifications are permissible…because they are reasonably related to the
53
Matthews, 427 U.S. 495.
54
Id.
likelihood of dependency at death.”55 “Reasonably related” says essentially the same thing as
“rational basis.”
Justice Stevens, joined by Justices Brennan and Marshall, dissented in both Matthews
and Norton, predicating his dissent on the merits on the same argument in both cases.56 In
Matthews he stated flatly that he could see no relevant difference between that case and Jiminez,
thereby rejecting the majority's effort to distinguish the two. He then discussed the majority's
approving rehearsal from previous cases of the point that visiting disabilities on non-marital
infants is “illogical and unjust,” again quoting Weber. Given this finding, Stevens would hold
the discrimination “invalid unless it is justified by a weightier governmental interest than merely
'administrative convenience.'"57
Stevens then offers a brief but highly acute and perspicacious discussion of prejudice in
However irrational it may be to burden innocent children because their parents did not
Because of that tradition of disfavor the Court should be especially vigilant in examining
likely to be used without pausing to consider its justification than is a newly created
classification. Habit, rather than analysis, makes it seem acceptable and natural to
distinguish between male and female, alien and citizen, legitimate and illegitimate; for
too much of our history there was the same inertia in distinguishing between black and
white. But that sort of stereotyped reaction may have no rational relationship other than
55
56
Matthews, (Stevens dissenting); Norton (Stevens dissenting).
57
Matthews, (Stevens dissenting).
pure prejudicial discrimination to the stated purpose for which the classification is being
made.58
As with the Court's explanation for the irrationality of the non-marital distinction in Weber,
Stevens' discussion here of the problem with traditional forms of discrimination applies with
equal force to lesbians and gay men. Although demonstrably not as deeply rooted in our nation's
traditions as some Justices would have us believe,59 still many defend their desire to discriminate
against lesbians and gay men in terms of tradition, and such discrimination has plainly in fact
In 1977, the Supreme Court decided Trimble v. Gordon, striking down an Illinois statute
that allowed non-marital children to inherit from their fathers in intestacy only if the parents had
married.60 The Illinois Supreme Court upheld the law on the authority of Labine. The U.S.
Supreme Court noted that it had distinguished Labine in Weber, and relied heavily on the
language of Weber in striking the Illinois statute down. In defending the Illinois statute, the state
noted that the current statute, which allowed non-marital children to inherit only from their
mothers, was an improvement over the previous common-law regime, which declared non-
marital children filius nullius and allowed them to inherit from neither parent. It found that the
statute had two purposes, to encourage family relationships, and to provide for the orderly
The Court acknowledged the legitimacy of the state's concern for family relationships,
but noted that cases such as this required more than a “mere incantation of a proper state
58
Id.
59
Fred Fejes, Gay Rights and Moral Panic: The Origins of America's Debate on Homosexuality
(2008) (explaining changing popular understandings of lesbians and gay men in the United
States during the twentieth century) ; Martin Bauml Duberman, “'Writhing Bedfellows, 1826:
Two Young Men from South Carolina's Ruling Elite Share 'Extravagent Delight'” (article
describing intimate correspondence between two young men from prominent South Carolina
families that discusses their sexual relationship with each other) Lawrence opinion.
60
Trimble v. Gordon, 430 U.S. 762 (1977).
purpose.” It then rehearsed its well established finding that disfavoring non-marital children to
express the community’s disapproval of extra-marital sexual relations was “illogical and unjust,”
and not a constitutionally permissible objective. It quoted again the final paragraph from Weber,
concluding that “The parents have the ability to conform their conduct to societal norms, but
their illegitimate children can affect neither their parents' conduct nor their own status.”61 The
permissible one. Perhaps it would be better to say that the state may certainly enact statutes for
the purpose of establishing “legitimate” families, but only insofar as such statutes work no
discrimination against persons who choose not to enter into such families.
It gave more credence to the other stated purpose of the statute, ensuring the orderly and
just disposition of decedents' estates. Acknowledging that problems of proof were greater for
non-marital claimants against fathers' estates than against mothers', still the Court asserted that
Illinois had failed to consider the possible middle ground between wholesale denial of
inheritance rights to non-marital children and case-by-case examination. Indeed, in the instant
case, a circuit court in Illinois had found the deceased to be the child's father and ordered him to
pay support, an order he assertedly complied with, obviating any concern for proof of paternity.62
The Court reversed and remanded to the Supreme Court of Illinois for further proceedings.
In 1978, the Court decided Lalli v. Lalli, the last of the cases involving non-marital
children in which the Court upheld the statute, which in this case came from New York and
placed a higher burden of proof on non-marital children who would take in intestacy. In doing
so, it noted its finding in Matthews, reiterated in Trimble, that non-marital status was not suspect
at the level of race or ethnicity; the court's strictest scrutiny, then, was not applicable, although
61
Id.
62
Id.
the intermediate level of scrutiny involved – call it rational basis plus – was not “toothless,” as
Trimble demonstrated in striking the statute down. The Court distinguished the New York
statute in Lalli from the Illinois statute in Trimble by noting that the New York statute imposed
only an evidentiary burden on the non-marital child, not the requirement that the parents marry,
as in Illinois. The Court noted that, under the New York statute, the petitioner in Trimble would
have been eligible to inherit, having a court order finding the deceased to be her father. The New
York statute resembled the Illinois statute, however, in being a reform that relaxed its more
draconian predecessor, which allowed non-marital children to inherit only from their mothers.
The Court rehearsed the relative difficulties of proof that claims of paternity present that
are not present in claims of maternity, holding that the New York scheme, unlike the Illinois
scheme, was sufficiently narrowly tailored to the state's legitimate goal of ensuring the just and
reliable disposition of decedents' estates. Dissenting, Justice Brennan noted that the requirement
of a judicial finding of paternity would often disqualify heirs such as the petitioner in Lalli,
whose father had acknowledged and supported him during his lifetime, but had simply never
gone through with the formality of a judicial proceeding. He also dismissed the asserted concern
to avoid belated claims by unknown non-marital children, noting that the commonly used legal
devices of notification by publication and a short statute of limitations for claims would be ample
to avoid the problems of unknown non-marital children fouling the legal process with their
claims.
Finallly, in 1986, the Court decided Reed v. Campbell,63 which involved essentially the
same facts as Trimble v. Gordon. A Texas statute allowed a non-marital child to inherit from the
father's estate in intestacy only where the father had legitimated the child by marrying the
however, also recognized that there is a permissible basis for some 'distinctions made in
part on the basis of legitimacy'; specifically, we have upheld statutory provisions that
have an evident and substantial relation to the State’s interest in providing for the orderly
Note the point: moral disapproval simpliciter is not a sufficient ground for imposing legal
disabilities on a minority group. According to the Reed court, expression of moral disapproval is
The Court concluded that the state court’s decision was unconstitutional. The state court
in Reed excluded the plaintiff from recovery solely because her father died four months before
the Supreme Court’s opinion in Trimble v. Gordon, which squarely held that the practice of
preventing non-marital children from inheriting in intestacy unless their parents had
subsequently married was unconstitutional. In Reed, the state court held that the plaintiff was
ineligible to inherit under such a rule, and that it had no responsibility to apply the holding of
Trimble retroactively.65 The Supreme Court could see no rational basis for refusing to apply
Trimble retroactively.
Interestingly, as we have seen, the Court consistently refused to find that non-marital
protection analysis. They did their work on behalf of non-marital children using rational basis
It is true, of course, that the legal status of illegitimacy, however defined, is, like race or
64
Id. at 854-55.
65
One really cannot help but ask, are these judges stupid, mean, or both?
national origin, a characteristic determined by causes not within the control of the
and contribute to society. The Court recognized in Weber that visiting condemnation
upon the child in order to express society’s disapproval of the parents’ liaisons “is
illogical and unjust. Moreover, imposing disabilities on the illegitimate child is contrary
to the basic concept of our system that legal burdens should bear some relationship to
Once again, every substantive statement in this quotation applies with equal force to lesbian and
gay men.
causes not within the control of the [lesbian/gay] individual, and it bears no relation to the
individual’s ability to participate in and contribute to society,” facts that only the most
recalcitrant homophobe would contest. We have already discussed the other two points – that
legal burdens should bear some relationship to individual responsibility or wrongdoing, and that
penalizing lesbians and gay men for their lesbian/gay identity is both unjust and
counterproductive, bringing about exactly the opposite of the desired outcome. Again, the
existence of a vigorous and, in the main, successful, LGBT civil rights movement in spite of
various legal disabilities proves both the ability of LGBT persons to participate in and contribute
The one important difference between non-marital children and LGBT persons, as the
66
Mathews, 427 U.S. at 505, quoting Weber, 406 at 175.
quotation above from Reed v. Campbell indicates,67 is that the courts have found legitimate
reasons to allow the use of the marital/non-marital distinction, especially where the state can
show a legitimate concern for fraud. Non-marital children may in some instances operate under
increased burdens of proof.68 One of the claims of this article is that no legislative
classifications based on sexual orientation are rational. But the underlying point is that the courts
have been quite thoughtful in their willingness to evaluate the actual circumstances that the cases
of non-marital children present, and they have achieved a reasonable, consistent balance between
the rights of non-marital children and the legitimate administrative needs of government.
Not surprisingly, Scalia carefully avoids mention of these cases in both his Romer and his
Lawrence dissents. Again, they conclusively disprove his contention that statutes serving no
purpose other than to express the community's moral condemnation of particular conduct are
constitutionally permissible.69 Given that no other “rational” basis for discriminations against
lesbians and gay men exists, this point necessarily invalidates all such discriminations under the
equal protection clause of the fourteenth amendment to the United States Constitution.
67
Supra note 108.
68
See, e.g., Lalli, 439 U.S. 259; Matthews, 427 U.S. 495.
69
Lawrence, 539 U.S. at 586ff (Scalia dissenting).