Eco Umberto The Open Work
Eco Umberto The Open Work
Eco Umberto The Open Work
Umberto Eco
With an Introduction
by David Robey
Notes 251
Index 277
Introduction
by David Robey
This book collects for the first time in English Eco's major "pre-
semiotic" writings on modern literature and art—writings, that
is, which predate the publication in 1968 of his first semiotic
or semiological book (the terms "semiotics" and "semiology" can
be used interchangeably), La struttura assente (The absent structure).
Most of them are taken from one or more of the many editions of
1. Il problema estetico in San Tommaso (Turin, 1956); now revised by the author
and recently translated into English as The Aesthetics of Thomas Aquinas (Cam-
bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1988). Much of this introduction ap-
peared in my chapter on Umberto Eco in M. Caesar and P. Hainsworth, eds.,
Writers and Society in Contemporary Italy (Leamington Spa, England: Berg Publishers,
1984), pp. 63-87. Readers are referred to this volume for further information on
the literary context of Eco's writing, and especially to the chapter by C. Wagstaff,
"The Neo-Avantgarde." I am grateful to the publishers for permission to reprint
parts of my chapter here. Some of the material was also previously published in
the Times Higher Education Supplement.
viii INTRODUCTION
Opera aperta (The open work), published in 1962, the first of Eco's
books on a modern topic and the work with which he made his
name in Italy. Two chapters of the present volume were originally
written after Eco's conversion to semiotics. The first, "The Death of
the Gruppo 63," is included here because it deals with an artistic
movement with which Eco became closely associated immediately
after the publication of Opera aperta. The other, "Series and Struc-
ture," is of particular interest because it deals with the relationship
between the poetics of the "open work" and the structuralist theory
which was the starting point of Eco's semiotics.
Since Opera aperta first appeared, Eco's thinking has developed in a
great many ways. But, as we shall see, there is a substantial and
striking continuity between his early and his later writings. More
important in the present connection, there is a great deal in Opera
aperta and in Eco's writings of the same period that has not been
superseded in his subsequent development, and that remains of
considerable relevance and interest. Opera aperta in particular is still a
significant work, both on account of the enduring historical use-
fulness of its concept of "openness," and because of the striking way in
which it anticipates two of the major themes of contemporary
literary theory from the mid-sixties onward: the insistence on the
element of multiplicity, plurality, or polysemy in art, and the em-
phasis on the role of the reader, on literary interpretation and re-
sponse as an interactive process between reader and text. The ques-
tions the book raises, and the answers it gives, are very much part
of the continuing contemporary debate on literature, art, and cul-
ture in general.
Opera aperta is a polemical book, in marked conflict with the
Crocean aesthetics that dominated the Italian academic world in
the early sixties. There are a great many references to Croce in the
chapters that follow, testifying to the strength of his philosophical
Crocinfluence on thinkers of Eco's generation; indeed, the
hegemony e exercised over Italian intellectual life throughout the
Fascist period and for the first two postwar decades is probably
without parallel in modem European history. The problematic
concept of pure intuition/expression, which constitutes the
foundation of Crocean aesthetics, is something we need not
consider here, bur some of the consequences it entails are worth
recalling if we want
INTRODUCTION
possible orders; if Mallarm÷ had ever finished his Litre, for in-
stance, the reader would have been left, at least up to a point, to
arrange its pages for him- or herself in a variety of different se-
quences. Works of this kind are for the most part of recent origin,
evidently, and even today are very much the exception rather than
the rule. Eco's point, however, is that the intention behind them is
fundamentally similar to the intention behind a great deal of mod-
ern art since the Symbolist movement at the end of the nineteenth
century.
Traditional or "classical" art. Eco argues, was in an essential
sense unambiguous. It could give rise to various responses, but its
nature was such as to channel these responses in a particular direc-
tion; for readers, viewers, and listeners there was in general only
one way of understanding what a text was about, what a painting
or sculpture stood for, what the tune was of a piece of music. Much
modem art, on the other hand, is deliberately and systematically
ambiguous. A text like Finnegans Wake, for Eco the exemplary
modern open work, cannot be said to be about a particular subject;
a great variety of potential meanings coexist in it, and none can be
said to be the main or dominant one. The text presents the reader
with a "field' of possibilities and leaves it in large part to him or her
to decide what approach to take. The same can be said, Eco argues,
of many other modem texts that are less radically avant-garde than
the Wake—for instance, Symbolist poems, Brecht's plays, Kafka's
novels.
This is where the analogy with works like Mallarrne's Livre ob-
tains: just as Mallarme's reader would have arranged the pages of
the book in a number of different sequences, so the reader of the
Wake perceives a number of different patterns of meaning in Joyce's
language. In the Lure it is the material form that is open, whereas
in the Wake it is the semantic content; but in each case, according to
Eco, the reader is in substantially the same position, because in each
case he or she moves freely amid a multiplicity of different interpre-
tations. The same analogy obtains, he argues, between abstract vi-
sual art and mobiles; and between the aleatory music of Stockhau-
sen, Berio, or Pousseur and the serial music of a composer like
Webem (see particularly Chapter to). All these characteristically
modern forms of art are said by Eco to mark a radical shift in the
relationship between artist and public, by requiring of the public a
INTRODUCTION
special union of sound and sense; but the explanation seems to cre-
ate more problems than it resolves. We shall return to this answer,
and to these questions, in connection with his later work.
Such difficulties are not, of course, serious grounds for objecting
to the thesis of Opera aperta. As Eco emphasized in the preface to
the second edition,' the book is more concerned with the aims of
certain kinds of art than with their success or failure, with questions
of poetics (poetica: a work's artistic purpose) rather than aesthetics.
This claim is anticipated in the essay "Two Hypotheses about the
Death of Art," written in 1962 and now Chapter 8 below. Here Eco
argues that questions of poetics are central to the discussion of all
modern works of art, although their treatment needs to be comple-
mented by acts of aesthetic judgment (in connection with which he
once again invokes Pareyson's theory of formativity). This insis-
tence on the importance of poetics is a major part of Eco's, and
many of his contemporaries', polemic against the then dominant
"aesthetic criticism" inspired by Croce, for whom the act of aes-
thetic judgment was the essential task of the critic, and questions of
poetics of second-order interest.
In this essay, as in Opera aperta, Eco argues that the modern open
3. Opera aperta, znd ed. (Milan: Bompiani, 1972), p. 8.
XiV INTRODUCTION
What, then, do we gain from art forms that reflect what can only
seem a negative aspect of the world in which we live? Eco's essay
answers this question through a discussion of the concept of alien-
ation, in which he outlines a position that has remained character-
istic of all his activity as an intellectual. In one sense alienation is
both necessary and desirable, in that we can say that we are alien-
ated to something other than ourselves, and therefore lose full pos-
session of ourselves, whenever we become involved in it. Losing
possession of ourselves is not something to be lamented; it is
simply part of the back-and-forth movement between self and the
world that is the condition of a truly human existence. What we
must do is accept our involvement in things other than ourselves,
and at the same time assert our selfhood in the face of the world by
actively seeking to understand it and transform it. Art, Eco argues,
can contribute significantly to this process of understanding and
transforming the world, because its function is essentially cogni-
tive. "Art knows the world through its own formative structures,"
he proposes (Chapter 6), referring to the aesthetics of Pareyson
once again. Art represents the world—or more exactly our experi-
ence of the world—through the way it organizes its constituents
(the modo di formare) rather than through what the constituents
t h emsel v esrepresen . This representation is a type of knowledge
t
by virtue of the element of organic form: "Where a form is realized
there is a conscious operation on an amorphous material that has
been brought under human control" (Chapter 6). Thus, the mod-
em open work is a form of knowledge of the world in which we
I N T ROD UC T I ON XV
But between Opera apena and Eco's first major semiotic text
there came another book which pursued a line of interest that has
since constituted an important part of Eco's activities: the study of
mass culture and the mass media. Chapter 9 below ("The Structure
of Bad Taste") is an excerpt from it. Published in 1964, the book
had as its title Apocalittici e integrati (Apocalyptic and integrated (in-
tellectuals)), the two terms standing for two opposite attitudes to
the mass media and their effect on contemporary culture: the apoc-
alyptic view that culture has been irredeemably debased by the
mass media, and that the only proper way to treat these is to disre-
gard them; and the wholly positive view of those who are so well
integrated in the modern world that they see the nature and effect
of the mass media as necessary and even desirable. Eco's own view
lies between these two extremes. The mass media, he argues, are
such an important feature of modern society as to require the seri-
ous attention of intellectuals, and, far from being a necessarily neg-
ative influence, they are to be welcomed for providing universal
access to cultural experiences previously restricted to an elite. They
are not to be accepted as they are, however; the intellectual's task is
to analyze their nature and effect and to seek actively to transform
them, by criticizing their deleterious features and pointing the way
to the improvement of their cultural content.
littici e integrati of such things as comic strips, pop songs, and tele-
vision programs, a discussion which is supplemented by two es-
says, published the following year, on Eugene Sue's Mysteres de
Paris and on the James Bond novels of Ian Fleming. 6 The main pur-
pose of these essays and of the discussion of specific mass media in
the book is to lay bare the ideological implications of different
forms of popular entertainment, particularly, in the case of the
comic strips and the novels, the relationship between ideology and
narrative structures. From the analysis a distinct set of common
themes emerges. The kind of entertainment that Eco criticizes, as
did Vittorini, is that which is consolatory, in the sense of reaffirm-
ing the public's sense of the essential rightness and permanence of
the world in which they live. The great fault of the mass media, for
Eco, is to convey a standardized, oversimplified, static, and com-
placent vision that masks the real complexity of things and implic-
itly denies the possibility of change.
6. Now in II superuomo di massa (Milan: Bompiani, 1978), pp. 27-67 and 145-
184; and translated into English in The Role of the Reader: Explorations in the Semiotics of
Texts (Bloomington, Ind.: Indiana University Press, 1979).
EESTI
AKADEEMILINE
XV111 INTRODUCTION
character of the historical circumstances in which we live, because it
allows for the possibility of change and serves as a stimulus
in lulus
i to
reflection and criticism, because it generates a sense of ndepen-
dence and choice instead of conformism and passivity.
This should help make clear what kind of political commitment
Eco expresses in his writings. The emphasis on change, the hostility
to conformism and conservatism must mark him as a man of the
left. Yet however he personally may vote, there is no recognizably
party-political element in his books. This is partly because his
intellectual task, as he conceives it, is cultural rather than narrowly
political, but more because his values are broadly democratic rather
than specifically socialist or communist. In particular, as a writer,
he has always kept his distance from the Italian Communist Party.
Opera aperta, with its insistence on the special function of the mod-
em open work, was in conflict with the view of art at that time
favored by the Party. In Apocalittici e integrati the emphasis on criti-
cism, debate, and the complexity of things also seems implicitly
opposed to the Party line, at least at that period. Eco particularly
favors the television discussion program "Tribuna Politica" as a
form of "education for democracy" that helped viewers become
aware of the "relative" character of politicians' opinions (Apocalittici e
integrati, p. 351); and in his analysis of the Bond novels (The Role of
the Reader, p. 162) he argues that the "democratic" man is the one
who "recognizes nuances and distinctions and who admits contra-
dictions." Finally, the themes of disorder and incomprehensibility in
Opera aperta, and the arguments about the limitations of system- atic
worldviews in his later semiotic works again tend to set him apart
from mainstream Marxist ideas. Marxism has been an important
influence on Eco's thinking, but this relativism and individualism
are major qualifications of his left-wing position.
Eco s shift of interest to semiotics began as he was supervising
the translation of Opera aperta into French. He was introduced to
the structuralism of Jakobson and Levi-Strauss,' and as a result re-
vised sections of the book along structuralist lines (Chapters 2 and 3
below), as has already been mentioned. This contact with struc-
turalist thought was the main source of Eco's semiotics or semiol-
ogy, and in particular of his first major semiotic work, La struttura
7. Opera aperta, 3rd ed. (Milan: Bompiani, 1976), pp.
INTRODUCTION XIX
To turn now to semiotics, what sort of subject is it, and what can a
theory of it do? Semiotics or semiology is the science of signs, and
Eco's theory has been mainly concerned with what he calls general
semiotics, the general theory of signs. All forms of social, cultural,
and intellectual life can be viewed as sign systems: as forms of com-
munication, and therefore as verbal or nonverbal languages. The
task of general semiotics, for Eco, is to develop a single, compre-
hensive conceptual framework within which all these sign systems
may be studied, not because they are all fundamentally identical but
because a systematic and coherent approach has intrinsic merits,
and because such an approach facilitates cross-fertilization between
the different fields that it covers. Thus, A Theory of Semiotics is not
principally concerned with the specific features of these different
INTRODUCTION XXI
Since Eco has told us that his interest in semiotics arose out of his
work on art in Opera aperta," and since this interest is also closely
connected to his work on mass communications in Apocalittici e
integrati, what changes did his new theoretical framework bring to
the ideas of the earlier books? Although his new interests broad-
ened Eco's horizons considerably. it is notable that the subjects of
art and mass communications occupy almost half the pages of La
stnatura assente, and could still be said to be a central, if less promi-
nent, object of attention in A Theory of Semiotics as well. To begin
with the theory of art, it is perhaps surprising how many of the
aesthetic principles of Opera aperta remain in the later works. In A
Theory of Semiotics, as in Opera aperta, Eco maintains that art pro-
duces an essential effect of ambiguity through the contravention of
conventions of expression, but that such contraventions are prop-
erly artistic only if they are part of a specifically aesthetic form.
What the later work does, first, is express these ideas in more wide-
ranging theoretical terms; like all other forms of cultural activity,
the production and consumption of art is seen as governed by
codes, and it is the violation of these codes that is said to be the
source of the effect of ambiguity. This new formulation opens the
way to a different conception of the function of art; whereas in Op-
era aperta the function was said to be essentially cognitive, in the
later books it is explained according to the structuralist principle
that the effect of the violation of codes in a work of art is to focus
attention first on the structure of the work itself, then on the codes
which the work employs, and finally on the relationship between
the codes and reality, thus generating in the reader or viewer a ren-
ovated perception of him- or herself and the world.
that is, a code is violated not just at one level of a work, but at all of
its levels, and between these different violations there is a funda-
mental similarity of structure. This structural pattern constitutes
what he calls the "aesthetic idiolect": just as the term "idiolect" is
employed in linguistics to mean the language habits peculiar to an
individual, so here it stands for the overall pattern of deviation, the
"general deviational matrix" (p. 271) peculiar to and characteristic
of each work of art.
The trouble is, of course, that it is very difficult to see how such a
pattern might be realized in practice. It is true that there are nu-
merous cases in literature in which the sound seems to be an echo
to the sense (though not as many cases as sometimes is supposed),
and stylistic analyses such as Leo Spitzer's have shown parallels be-
tween the meaning of texts and other levels of expression, for in-
stance syntax. But to suggest, as Eco does, that there is a multiple
set of correspondences in all works of art, beginning from their
physical substance—to which Eco attaches special importance: in
art, matter is "rendered semiotically interesting" (p. 266)—and
proceeding down to the various aspects of their content, seems to
require a good deal of clarification and empirical verification, nei-
ther of which has been adequately provided in any of Eco's works.
As I have said, the sense of the social and political role of art
becomes much weaker in Eco's work after 1968. It is thus not in the
sphere of aesthetics but in the study of mass communications that
the social relevance of his semiotics is most apparent. For Eco,
semiotic theories of meaning serve to expose the ideological (in the
sense of false) nature of forms of persuasion, when these suppress
parts of the meaning of signs and privilege others in order to fur-
ther the purposes of specific interest groups, a process Eco terms
"code switching." This process is one to which he attaches particu-
lar weight, and his discussion of it is one of the culminating points
of A Theory of Semiotics. The "heuristic and practical power" of a
semiotic theory lies in its ability to show how acts of communica-
tion can "respect or betray" the real complexity of the various sign
14. Ibid. This book is not the same as The Role of the Reader, which is a transla-
tion into English of a variety of earlier essays; it does however 'extend and develop
the first chapter of the English book.
INTRODUCTION XXVII
t to The Name of the Rose (San Diego, Calif.: Harcourt Brace Jo-
XXX INTRODUCTION
care and highly organized classification of its books, all can be seen
as a nostalgic material correlative of the ordered system of medieval
scholastic thought, which Eco initially adhered to and then
abandoned earl y in his career. The connections between the novel
and Eco's subsequent, more modem interests are less obvious
but, to my mind, equally striking. I say "to my mind" especially
because, even if the novel is not an open work, Eco nonetheless
insists, in his Postscript, that it is capable of a number of
interpretations, none of which should be regarded as definitive.
At the very start of Eco's Postscript the connection is made clear
between the novel's title and the principle of unlimited semiosis,
although the point is not spelled out. The reference to the rose in
the Latin hexameter with which the narrative ends ("The former
rose survives in its name; bare names are what we have") seems to
assert for Eco the unbridgeable gap between the world of signs and
the world of things. On the other hand, there is also, clearly, a
contrast between the picture of instability, disorder, and incompre-
hensibility offered by Eco's view of semiotics in particular and
knowledge in general, and the stable, ordered world of the monas-
tery in which the story is set. Eco himself points out in the Postscript
that the labyrinth of the monastery library is not the same as the
rhizome-like labyrinth or net of the encyclopedia. Far from permit-
ting an infinite variety of possible connections, it is a labyrinth
through which there is only one path—a material image, we may
take it, of the intellectual world of the books it contains and the
monastic community it serves. We can read the burning down of
the library at the end of the novel as anticipating, metaphorically,
the final destruction of this world, already seriously threatened, as
Eco's characters repeatedly observe, by the new culture of the cities
and their secular universities.
4. In Pierre Boulez's Third Sonata for Piano, the first section (An-
tiphonie, Formant t) is made up of ten different pieces on ten corre-
sponding sheets of music paper. These can be arranged in different
sequences like a stack of filing cards, though not all possible per-
mutations are permissible. The second part (Formant 2, Thrope) is
made up of four parts with an internal circularity, so that the per-
former can commence with any one of them, linking it successively
to the others until he comes round full circle. No major interpreta-
tive variants are permitted inside the various sections, but one of
them, Parenthese, opens with a prescribed time beat, which is fol-
lowed by extensive pauses in which the beat is left to the player's
discretion. A further prescriptive note is evinced by the composer's
instructions on the manner of linking one piece to the next (for
example, sans retenir, enchainer sans interruption, and so on).
Pousseur has observed that the poetics of the "open" work tends to
encourage "acts of conscious freedom" on the part of the performer
and place him at the focal point of a network of limitless interrela-
tions, among which he chooses to set up his own form without
being influenced by an external necessity which definitively pre-
scribes the organization of the work in hand. = At this point one
could object (with reference to the wider meaning of "openness"
already introduced in this essay) that any work of art, even if it is
not passed on to the addressee in an unfinished state, demands a
free, inventive response, if only because it cannot really be appre-
ciated unless the performer somehow reinvents it in psychological
collaboration with the author himself. Yet this remark represents
the theoretical perception of contemporary aesthetics, achieved
only after painstaking consideration of the function of artistic per-
formance; certainly an artist of a few centuries ago was far from
being aware of these issues. Instead nowadays it is primarily the
THE POETICS OF THE OPEN W ORK
vidual in his every action, prescribing the ends for him and offering
him the means to attain them.
It is not that the four solutions of the allegorical passage are
quantitatively more limited than the many possible solutions of
a contemporary "open" work. As I shall try to show, it is a
different vision of the world which lies under these different
aesthetic experiences.
If we limit ourselves to a number of cursory historical glimpses,
we can find one striking aspect of "openness" in the "open form"
of Baroque. Here it is precisely the static and unquestionable
definitiveness of the classical Renaissance form which is denied:
the canons of space extended round a central axis, closed in by
symmetrical lines and shut angles which cajole the eye toward
the center in such a way as to suggest an idea of "essential"
eternity rather than movement. Baroque form is dynamic; it tends
to an indeterminacy of effect (in its play of solid and void, light
and darkness, with its curvature, its broken surfaces, its widely
diversified angles of inclination); it conveys the idea of space
being progressively dilated. Its search for kinetic excitement and
illusory effect leads to a situation where the plastic mass in the
Baroque work of art never allows a privileged, definitive, frontal
view; rather, it induces the spectator to shift his position
continuously in order to see the work in constantly new aspects,
as if it were in a state of perpetual transformation. Now if
Baroque spirituality is to be seen as the first clear manifestation of
modern culture and sensitivity, it is because here, for the first
time, man opts out of the canon of authorized responses and
finds that he is faced (both in art and in science) by a world in a
fluid state which requires corresponding creativity on his part. The
poetic treatises concerning "maraviglia," "wit," "agudezas," and
so on really strain to go further than their apparently Byzantine
appearance: they seek to establish the new man's inventive role. He
is no longer to see the work of art as an object which draws on
given links with experience and which demands to be enjoyed;
now he sees it as a potential mystery to be solved, a role to fulfill, a
stimulus to quicken his imagination. Nonetheless, even these
conclusions have been codified by modern criticism and
organized into aesthetic canons. In fact, it would be rash to
interpret Baroque poetics as a conscious theory of the "open work."
In every century, the way that artistic forms are structured reflects
the way in which science or contemporary culture views reality.
The closed, single conception in a work by a medieval artist re-
flected the conception of the cosmos as a hierarchy of fixed, pre-
ordained orders. The work as a pedagogical vehicle, as a monocen-
tric and necessary apparatus (incorporating a rigid internal pattern
of meter and rhymes) simply reflects the syllogistic system, a logic
of necessity, a deductive consciousness by means of which reality
could be made manifest step by step without unforeseen interrup-
tions, moving forward in a single direction, proceeding from first
principles of science which were seen as one and the same with the
first principles of reality. The openness and dynamism of the Ba-
roque mark, in fact, the advent of a new scientific awareness: the
tactile is replaced by the visual (meaning that the subjective element
comes to prevail) and attention is shifted from the essence to the
appearance of architectural and pictorial products. It reflects the ris-
ing interest in a psychology of impression and sensation—in short,
THE POETICS OF THE. OPEN WORK
14
an empiricism which converts the Aristotelian concept of real sub-
stance into a series of subjective perceptions by the viewer. On the
other hand, by giving up the essential focus of the composition and
the prescribed point of view for its viewer, aesthetic innovations
were in fact mirroring the Copernican vision of the universe. This
definitively eliminated the notion of geocentricity and its allied
metaphysical constructs. In the modern scientific universe, as in
architecture and in Baroque pictorial production, the various com-
ponent parts are all endowed with equal value and dignity. and the
whole construct expands toward a totality which is close to the
infinite. It refuses to be hemmed in by any ideal normative concep-
tion of the world. It shares in a general urge toward discovery and
constantly renewed contact with reality.
In its own way. the "openness" that we meet in the decadent
strain of Symbolism reflects a cultural striving to unfold new vis-
tas. For example. one of Mallarme's projects for a multidimen-
sional. deconstructible book envisaged the breaking down of the
initial unit into sections which could be reformulated and which
could express new perspectives by being deconstructed into corre-
spondingly smaller units which were also mobile and reducible.
This project obviously suggests the universe as it is conceived by
modern, non-Euclidean geometries.
Hence, it is not overambitious to detect in the poetics of the
"open" work—and even less so in the "work in movement"—
more or less specific overtones of trends in contemporary scientific
thought. For example. it is a critical commonplace to refer to the
spatiotemporal continuum in order to account for the structure of
the universe in Joyce's works. Pousseur has offered a tentative defi-
nition of his musical work which involves the term "field of possi-
imbues." In fact, this shows that he is prepared to borrow two ex-
tremely revealing technical terms from contemporary culture. The
notion of "field" is provided by physics and implies a revised vision
of the classic relationship posited between cause and effect as a
rigid,
one-directional system: now a complex interplay of motive
i
forces is envisaged, a configuration of possible events, a complete
p
dynamism of structure.
cal canon which reflects aThe notion tendency
widespread of "possibility" is a hiloso
contemporary oraryh-
i
science; the discarding of a static, syllogistic view oforder, and a
THE POETICS OF THE OPEN WORK 15
How can anything ever present itself truly to us since its synthe-
sis is never completed? How could I gain the experience of the
world, as I would of an individual actuating his own existence,
since none of the views or perceptions I have of it can exhaust it
and the horizons remain forever open? ... The belief in
things and in the world can only express the assumption of a
complete synthesis. Its completion, however, is made impos-
sible by the very nature of the perspectives to be connected,
since each of them sends back to other perspectives through its
own horizons . . . The contradiction which we feel exists be-
tween the world's reality and its incompleteness is identical to
the one that exists between the ubiquity of consciousness and
its commitment to a field of presence. This ambiguousness
does not represent an imperfection in the nature of existence or
in that of consciousness; it is its very definition . . . Conscious-
ness, which is commonly taken as an extremely enlightened
region, is, on the contrary, the very region of indetermina-
tion. i2
* * *
THE POETICS OF THE OPEN WORK 19
all performances are definitive in the sense that each one is for
the performer, tantamount to the work itself; equally, all per-
formances are bound to be provisional in the sense that each
performer knows that he must always try to deepen his own
interpretation of the work. Insofar as they are definitive, these
THE POETICS OF THE OPEN WORK
22
equals the sum of the squares of the lengths of the other two sides"
is also universal, being a principle that retains the same validity at
every point on the globe, but it refers to just one specific, well-
defined property of reality. On the other hand, when I recite a line
of poetry or an entire poem, the words I utter cannot be immedi-
ately translated into a fixed denotatum that exhausts their meaning,
for they imply a series of meanings that expand at every new look,
to the point that they seem to offer me a concentrated image of the
entire universe. This is how we should understand Croce's often
quite ambiguous theory concerning the totality of artistic expres-
sion.
According to Croce, an artistic representation is a reflection of
the cosmos: "Each part of it throbs with the life of the whole, and
the whole is in the life of each part. A true artistic representation is
at the same time itself and the universe, the universe as individual
form, and the individual form as universe. Every accent of the poet,
as well as every creature of his imagination, encloses the entire des-
tiny of mankind, with all its hopes, its illusions, its pains, its joys,
its grandeur, and its misery, the entire drama of reality, incessantly
becoming and growing out of itself, in suffering and pleasure."'
Croce's words effectively translate the vague emotion many of us
have felt at the reading of a poem, but they don't explain it. In other
words, Croce does not accompany his observation with a theoreti-
cal framework that would account for it. Similarly, when he states
that "to give an artistic form to an emotive content is to imprint it
with totality, to lend it cosmic inspiration," 2 he is again insisting on
the need for a rigorous foundation (on which to base the equation
artistic form = totality), but without providing us with the philo-
sophical tools necessary to establish the connection he proposes. To
say that artistic form stems from the lyrical intuition of feeling does
not amount to much more than asserting that every emotive intui-
tion becomes lyrical when it takes the form of art, thereby assum-
ing the character of totality—all aesthetic reflection thus dwindles
to suggestive verbalism, or to charming tautologies involving phe-
nomena that are, however, never explained.
notes, the Symbolists have turned into the main object of their art: -
About ever y explicit and focal object there is a recession into the
implicit which is not intellectually grasped. In reflection we call it
dim and vague. - But Dewey is perfectly aware of the fact that the
"dim- and the "vague" of a primary experience—which always
recede the categorical rigidity imposed on us by reflection—are
prec
aspects of its global nature. "At twilight, dusk is a delightful quality
of the whole world. It is its appropriate manifestation. It becomes a
specialized and obnoxious trait only when it prevents distinct per-
ception of some particular thing we desire to discern." If reflection
forces us to choose and focus on just a few elements of a given
situation, "the undefined pervasive quality of an experience is that
which binds together all the defined elements, the objects of which
we are focally aware, making them a whole. - Reflection does not
generate but, rather, is generated by this original pervasiveness
within which it exercises its selectivity. According to Dewey, the
very essence of art lies precisely in its capacity to evoke and empha-
size "this quality of being a whole and of belonging to the larger, all-
inclusive, whole which is the universe in which we live"'—
hence the religious emotion inspired in us by aesthetic contempla-
tion. This sense of totality is as strongly registered in Dewey as it is
in Croce, even though in a different philosophical context, and con-
stitutes one of the most interesting features of an aesthetics which,
given its naturalist foundations, could at first sight seem rigidly
positivistic. In fact, Dewey's naturalism and his positivism share
the same romantic origins, which might well explain why all his
analyses, no matter how scientific, always culminate in a moment
of intense emotion before the mystery of the cosmos (it is no coin-
cidence that his organicism, though marked by Darwin, stems
more or less consciously from Coleridge and Hegel).'
better vet, the world that results from this active participation."'
Thus, [lie experience of totality (the experience of the aesthetic mo-
ment as an openness of knowledge) could very well lend itself to a
psychological explanation, the absence of which makes Croce's ac-
counts, and in part Dewey's, somewhat suspect.
From a psychological standpoint, this question involves the very
conditions of knowledge. and not just the aesthetic experience—
unless, of course. we see it as the liminal condition of all knowl-
edge, its primary and essential phase, which is quite plausible but
not exactly pertinent at this stage of our investigation. For the time
being, our investigation will be limited to the process of transaction
between a perceiving subject and an aesthetic stimulus. To make
things even clearer, we are going to focus our analysis on the sub-
ject's reaction to language. Language is not an organization of nat-
ural stimuli, like a beam of photons; it is an organization of stimuli
realized by man, and, as such, an artifact, like any other art form.
No need, therefore, to identify art with language in order to pursue
an analogy that would allow us to apply to one what we have said
about the other. As the linguists have clearly understood," lan-
guage is not one means of communication among others, but rather
"the basis of all communication,"or, even better, "language really is
the foundation of culture. In relation to language, other systems of
symbols are concomitant or derivative."
Thousand and One Nights. In this case, the term "Basra" would
cease to be a stimulus directly connected to a specific reality,
a precise signified, and would become the center of an
associative network of memories and emotions, all exuding
the same exotic blend of mystery, languor, and magic: Ali
Baba, hashish, flying carpets, odalisques, sultry aromas and
spices, the wisdom of caliphs, the sounds of oriental
instruments, wily Levantine merchants, Baghdad. The less
precise the receiver's culture and the more fervent his imagination,
the more undefined and fluid his reaction will be, and the more
frayed and smudged its contours. Let's not forget the effect
that the sign displaying the words "Agendath Netaim" has on
Leopold Bloom (Ulysses, chapter 4); the "stream of
consciousness" it provokes constitutes a precious psychological
document. The divagations of a mind prodded by a vague
stimulus can cause the suggestiveness of one word (such as
"Basra") to permeate the rest of the text: the subject of the
sentence ceases to be an insignificant traveler and becomes an
individual charged with mystery and intrigue, and the verb
"comes," no longer a mere indication of movement from one
place to another, begins to evoke images of a fabulous journey, a
journey along the paths of fairy tales, the archetypal Journey. In short,
the message (the sentence) opens up to a series of connotations that
go far beyond its most immediate denotations.
it. In other words, the variety of meanings that can be drawn out
of a sentence from Finnegans Mk( does not depend on the same
kind of aesthetic achievement as the line from Racine we have ex-
amined above. Joyce was aiming at something else, something dif-
ferent, which demanded the aesthetic organization of a complex of
signifiers that were already, in themselves, open and ambiguous.
On the other hand, the ambiguity of the signs cannot be separated
from their aesthetic organization: rather, the two are mutually sup-
portive and motivating.
To give a more concrete example of all this, let us compare two
passages, one from the Divine Comedy and the other from Finnegans
Wake. In the first passage, Dante wants to explain the nature of the
Trinity, the highest and most difficult concept in his entire poem.
Already univocally clarified by theological speculation, this con-
cept is no longer open to interpretation, since it can have only one
meaning, the orthodox one. The poet, therefore, uses only words
with very precise referents:
Information Theory
Information theory tries to calculate the quantity of information
contained in a particular message. If, for instance, on August 4 the
weather forecaster says, "Tomorrow, no snow," the amount of in-
formation I get is very limited; my own experience would have
easily allowed me to reach that conclusion. On the other hand, if
on August 4 the forecaster says, "Tomorrow, snow," then the
amount of information I get is considerable, given the improbabil-
ity of the event. The quantity of information contained in a
particular message is also generally conditioned by the confidence I
have in my sources. If I ask a real estate broker whether the
apartment he has just shown me is damp or not and he tells me
that it is riot, he gives me very little information, and I remain as
uncertain as I was before I asked him the question. On the other
hand, if he tells me that the apartment is damp, against my own
expectation and his own interest, then he gives me a great deal of
information and I feel I have learned something relevant about a
subject that matters to me.
In the case of the coin, if I am told that the coin will show heads.
the expression will read:
1/
1/2
log2 = 1.
Yet this also means that the very order which allows a message to
be understood is also what makes it absolutely predictable—that is,
extremely banal. The more ordered and comprehensible a mes-
sage, the more predictable it is. The messages written on Christmas
cards or birthday cards, determined by a very limited system of
probability. are generally quite clear but seldom tell us anything we
don't already know.
On reflection, one sees that this is precisely the case with every-
day speech. whose very power of communication and information
seems to be directly proportional to the grammatical and syntactic
rules it constantly eludes—the very same rules deemed necessary
to the transmission of meaning. It often happens that in a language
(here taken to mean a system of probability), certain elements of
disorder may in fact increase the level of information conveyed by
a message.
But if the lover were Petrarch, he would do away with all the
conventional rules of construction, shun all logical transitions, dis-
dain all but the most daring metaphors, and, refusing to tell us that
he is describing a memory but using the past tense to suggest it, he
would say: "Chiare, fresche e dolci acque—dove le belle membra-
pose colei the Bola a me par donna" ("Clear, fresh and sweet waters
where she who alone to me seems woman rested her lovely
limbs")." In fewer than twenty words, he would also succeed in
telling us that he still loves the woman he remembers, and would
manage to convey the intensity of his love through a rhythm whose
liveliness imbues the memory with the immediacy of a cry or a
vision. Nowhere else have we thus savored the sweetness and vio-
lence of love and the languor of memory. This communication al-
lows us to accumulate a large capital of information about both
Petrarch's love and the essence of love in general. Yet from the point
of view of meaning, the two texts are absolutely identical. It is the
second one's originality of organization—that is, its deliberate dis-
organization, its improbability in relation to a precise system of probabil-
ity—which makes it so much more informative.
At this point, of course, one could easily object that it is not just
OPENNESS, INFORMATION, COM MU NI CAT I ON 55
II
Poetic Discourse and Information
The example of Petrarch should have helped us understand that the
originality of an aesthetic discourse involves to some extent a rup-
ture with (or a departure from) the linguistic system of probability,
which serves to convey established meanings, in order to increase
the signifying potential of the message. This sort of information,
characteristic of every aesthetic message, coincides with the basic
openness of all works of art, as discussed in the previous chapter.
Let us now turn to contemporary art and the ways in which it
deliberately and systematically tries to increase its range of mean-
ings.
According to the laws of redundancy, the probability that the
article "the" will be followed by a noun or an adjective is extremely
high. Similarly, after the phrase "in the event" the probability that
"that" will be the next word is fairly high, whereas the probability
that "elephant" will be the next word is very low. At least, this is
true for the type of English we commonly use. Weaver gives nu-
merous examples of this kind and concludes by saying that, in
everyday language, a sentence such as "Constantinople fishing
OPENNESS, INFORMATION, COMMUNICATION 59
What all this means is that the contemporary poet constructs his
or her poetic message with devices and according to procedures
unlike those used by the medieval poet. Once again, the results are
62 OPENNESS, INFORMATION, COMMUNICATION
Musical Discourse
Let us now transpose all that has just been said onto a musical level: a
classical sonata represents a system of probability that makes the
succession and superposition of themes easily predictable. The
tonal system institutes other rules of probability, whereby the plea-
sure and the attention of the listener are stimulated by his expecta-
tion of the inevitable resolutions of certain tonal progressions. In
both cases, the composer can repeatedly break away from the es-
tablished scheme of probability and introduce a potentially infinite
number of variations into even the most elementary scale. The
twelve-tone system is just another system of probability. Not so the
more contemporary serial compositions, in which the musician
chooses a constellation of sounds that can lend themselves to a va-
riety of possible connections. Thus, he breaks away from the banal
order of tonal probability and institutes a degree of disorder that,
compared to the initial order, is quite high. By so doing, however,
he also introduces new forms of organization which, being more
open than the traditional one and therefore more charged with in-
formation, permit the development of new types of discourse and,
as a result, new meanings. Here again, we are confronting a poetics
which, aiming at a greater availability of information, makes of this
availability its very method of construction. This, of course, has
absolutely no effect on the aesthetic result: a thousand awkward
constellations of sounds that have broken away from the tonal sys-
tem may well provide less information and satisfaction than Eine
kleine Nachtmusik. Nevertheless, it is important to remember that
the main objective of this new music is the creation of new discur-
sive structures that will remain open to all sorts of possible conclu-
sions.
S A T O R
A R E P 0
T E N E T
O P E R A
R O T A S
Postscript
All these points need further clarification. It would indeed be pos-
sible to show that the mathematical concept of information cannot
be applied to the poetic message, or to any other message, because
information (qua entropy and coexistence of all possibilities) is a
characteristic of the source of messages: the moment this initial equi-
probability is filtered, there is selection and therefore order, and
therefore meaning.
This objection is perfectly correct if we consider information
theory only as a complex of mathematical rules used to measure the
transmission of bits from a source to a receiver. But the moment
the transmission concerns information among human beings, in-
formation theory becomes a theory of communication, and we need
to establish whether concepts borrowed from a technique used to
quantify information (that is, a technique concerned with the phys-
ical exchange of signals considered independently from the mean-
ings they convey) can be applied to human communication.
A source of information is always a locus of high entropy and
absolute availability. The transmission of a message implies the se-
lection of some information and its organization into a signifying
complex. At this point, if the receiver of the information is a ma-
chine (programmed to translate the signals it receives into messages
that can be rigorously referred back to a particular code, according
to which every signal signifies one and only one thing), either the
message has a univocal meaning or it is automatically identified
with noise.
Things are, of course, quite different in a transmission of mes-
sages between people, where every given signal, far from referring
univocally to a precise code, is charged with connotations that
make it resound like an echo chamber. In this case, a simple refer-
ential code according to which every given signifier corresponds to
a particular signified is no longer sufficient. Far from it, for, as we
have already seen, the author of a message with aesthetic aspirations
will intentionally structure it in as ambiguous a fashion as possible
precisely in order to violate that system of laws and determinations
which makes up the code. We then confront a message that delib-
erately violates or, at least, questions the very system, the very or-
der—order as system of probability—to which it refers. In other
OPENNESS, INFORMATION, COMMUNICATION 67
III
Infinmation and Psychological Transaction
I hope that this discussion has demonstrated how a mathematical
study of information can provide the tools necessary for elucidating
and analyzing aesthetic structures, and how it reflects a penchant
for the "probable" and the "possible" that mathematics shares with
the arts.
On the other hand, information theory evaluates quantity and
not quality. The quantity of information concerns only the statisti-
cal probability of events, whereas its value can be measured only in
terms of the interest we bring to it.26 The quality of information is
related to its value. To determine the value an unforeseeable situa-
tion may have for us (unforeseeable but verifiable, whether it be a
weather forecast or a poem by Petrarch or Eluard), and the nature
of its singularity, we must consider both the structural fact in itself and the
attention we have brought it. At this point, questions of information
become questions of communication, and our attention must shift from
the message itself, qua objective system of possible information, to
the relationship between message and receiver—a relationship in
which the receiver's interpretation constitutes the effective value of
the information.
The statistical analysis of the informative possibilities of a signal
is, in fact, a syntactic analysis, in which the semantic and pragmatic
dimensions play only a secondary role, the former to define in what
cases and under which circumstances a given message may provide
more information than another, and the latter to suggest what kind
of behavior this information might entail.
But although the transmission of signs conceived according to a
rigorous code, based on conventional values, can be explained
without having to depend on the interpretive intervention of the
receiver, the transmission of a sequence of signals with little redun-
dancy and a high ratio of improbability demands that we take into
consideration both the attitudes and the mental structures by which
the receiver, of his own free will, selects a message and endows it
with a probability that is certainly already there but only as one
probability among many.
This, in turn, means that it may be necessary to add a psycholog-
ical point of view to the structural analysis of certain communica
OPENNESS, INF ORMAT ION, COMMUNICAT ION 71
then it is obvious, as Meyer points out, that the laws of form pre-
side over musical discourse only on condition that they be con-
stantly violated during its development. The solutions the listener
expects are not the most obvious but rather the least common, a
transgression of the rules that will enhance his appreciation of and
the pleasure in the final return to legality. According to Gestalt
theory, the "right" form is the one that natural data assume by ne-
cessity the moment they organize in unitary complexes. Does mu-
sical form also manifest the same tendency toward an original sta-
bility?
At this point, Meyer tempers his Gestaltism and admits that the
notion of optimal organization, in music, can refer only to a cultural
datum. This means that music is not a universal language, and that
our tendency to prefer certain solutions to others is the result of our
apprenticeship within the context of a musical culture that has been
historically defined. Sounds that a particular musical culture con-
siders unexpected may well be, in a different culture, so legitimate
as to be banal. The perception of a totality is neither immediate nor
passive: it is an act of organization that has to be learned within a
sociocultural context. The laws of perception are not natural and
innate; rather, they are the reflection of cultural patterns, or, as a
transactional psychologist would say, they are acquired forms, a sys-
tem of preferences and habits, convictions and emotions, fostered
in us by the natural, social, and historical context we inhabit.38
Art, in all its forms, has also evolved in a similar fashion, within a
"tradition" that may seem immutable but which, in fact, has
never ceased to introduce new forms and new dogmas through
innumerable revolutions. Every real artist constantly violates
the laws of the system within which he works, in order to create
new formal possibilities and stimulate aesthetic desire: when
Brahms's works were first performed, the expectations aroused by one
of his symphonies in a listener accustomed to Beethoven were
certainly very different, both in quality and range, from the
expectations aroused by a Beethoven piece in a listener
accustomed to Haydn. And yet, theorists of contemporary music (and
with them, those of contemporary art in general) reproach classical
tradition for the fact that all its formal innovations, and the kind
of expectations they entailed, would no sooner be introduced
than they would become new systems of assumptions aiming at the
completion and final
So OPENNESS, INFORMATION, COMMUNICATION
This brief typological survey ranges all the way from the patho-
logical to the everyday, and allows for a large number of perceptive
possibilities which it entirely justifies. There is no need to stress the
value that these psychological hypotheses can have for a discussion
of art. All one needs to add is that, given such premises, psycholo-
gists will have to explain how and to what extent an apprenticeship
based on unusual perceptual exercises and intellectual operations
might modify the usual schemes of reaction. (Which is to say: Will
the use of information theory prevent the violations of codes and
systems of expectation from turning into the key elements of a new
code, of a new system of expectations?) Aesthetics, art history, and
the phenomenology of taste have confronted, if not quite solved,
this problem for centuries, at a macroscopic level. How often have
new creative modes changed the meaning of form, people's aes-
OPENNESS, INFORMATION, COMMUNICAT ION 83
This is not the case with Gabo's work. Seen from below, his
sculptures make one imagine a variety of possible and mutually
exclusive perspectives; and though each perspective is satisfactory
in itself, it inevitably frustrates the viewer who would like to appre-
hend a totality.'
Calder goes still further: his forms move before our eyes. Each
of his works is a "work in movement" whose movement combines
with that of the viewer. Theoretically, work and viewer should
never be able to confront each other twice in precisely the same
way. Here there is no suggestion of movement: the movement is
real, and the work of art is a field of open possibilities. The myriad
reflections of Munari's ',mini and the "moving works" of the young
avant-garde are more extreme examples of the same phenomenon.'
"Informal" art, in the broader sense I have given it, belongs here,
next to these formal experiments. It is not work in movement,
since the painting is there, before our eyes, physically defined once
and for all by the pictorial signs that constitute it; neither does it
require any movement on the part of the viewer—no more, that is,
than any other painting that demands that its viewer be constantly
aware of the various incidences of light on the roughness of its sur-
face and the contrasts of its colors. And yet, it is an "open work"—
in an even more mature and radical way than any of those men-
tioned above. Its signs combine like constellations whose structural
relationships are not determined univocally, from the start, and in
which the ambiguity of the sign does not (as is the case with the
Impressionists) lead back to reconfirming the distinction between
form and background. Here, the background itself becomes the
subject of the painting, or, rather, the subject of the painting is a
background in continual metamorphosis. Here, the viewer can (in-
deed, must) choose his own points of view, his own connections,
his own directions, and can detect, behind each individual config-
uration, other possible forms that coexist -while excluding one an-
other in an ongoing relationship of mutual exclusion and implica-
tion. At this point we need to ask two questions concerning not
only the poetics of the "informal" but the poetics of the "open
work" in general:
communicability and what are the guarantees that they will not
suddenly lapse into either silence or chaos? In other words, can we
define the tension between the mass of information intentionally
offered to the reader and the assurance of a minimal amount of
comprehensibility, and is there a possible agreement between the
intention of the author and the viewer's response?
Neither of these questions concerns the aesthetic value of the
works under examination. The first presumes that, in order to
express an implicit vision of the world and its relationship with
an entire aspect of contemporary culture, a work of art must at
least partly satisfy the requisites of that particular
communicative discourse commonly known as "aesthetics." The
second concerns the elementary conditions of communication
necessary for the recognition of a potentially richer and deeper
meaning, characterized by the organic fusion of various elements,
and characteristic of aesthetic value. As for the aesthetic
possibilities of informal art, I shall discuss them in the third part of
this chapter.
lows one to describe certain microphysical events with all due caution—
caution that should also be used when dealing with the same
notion at a philosophical level. On the other hand, rather than
questioning Mathieu's right to use a scientific concept as a stimulus
to the imagination, we should try to figure out how much of the
original stimulus is left in the structuring of pictorial signs, and
whether there is any continuity between the vision of things im-
plicit in the scientific notion and the one expressed by the new
forms. As I have pointed out elsewhere, Baroque poetics evolved
from the new vision of the cosmos introduced by the Copernican
revolution and already figuratively suggested by Kepler's discovery
of the elliptical shape of planetary orbits—a discovery that called
into question the privileged position of the circle as the classical
symbol of cosmic perfection. Just as Baroque structure reflects the
conception—no longer geocentric and, therefore, no longer an-
thropocentric—of a nonfinite universe, so it is possible, as Mathieu
tries to show in his article, to find a parallel between the
non-Euclidean geometries of today and the rejection of
classical geometric forms by art movements such as Fauvism
and Cubism; between the emergence of imaginary or
transfinite numbers in mathematics and the advent of abstract
painting; between Hilbert's attempts to axiomatize geometry and
the appearance of Neoplasticism and Constructivism:
Dubuffet deals with primordial realities and the mana, the mag-
ical currents that connect human beings to the objects that sur-
round them. But his art is much more complex than any prim-
itive art. I have already alluded to his multiple ambiguities and
zones of signification. Many of these are produced by complex
THE OPEN W ORK IN THE VISUAL ARTS 91
Fautrier paints a box as if the concept of box did not exist; more
than an object, it is a debate between dream and matter, a ten-
tative groping in the direction of the box, in that zone of uncer-
tainty where the possible elbows the real . . . The artist has the
marked impression that things could be quite different.'
Fautrier's matter . . . is a matter that never gets simpler; rather,
it becomes ever more complicated as it captures and assimilates
all sorts of possible meanings, incorporating aspects or mo-
ments of reality, and saturating itself with live experience.'
The attributes that best suit Dubuffet's representation are quite
different: they express in-finity, in-distinction, in-discretion (all
these terms should be taken in their etymological sense). The
optics of matter in fact demands that we witness the shattering
of all notional outlines, the disintegration and disappearance of
familiar aspects, in both things and people. And if some trace,
some presence of formal definition, persists, this optics de-
mands that we question it, that we inflate it by multiplying it
and confusing it in a tumult of projections and dislocations.9
Suppose we take a white sheet of paper and spill some ink on it.
The result will be a random image with absolutely no order. Let's
now fold the paper in two so that the ink blot will spread evenly on
both sides of the sheet. When we unfold the paper we will find
98 THE OPEN WORK IN THE VISUAL ARTS
Let's now transform both the ink blot and the pieces of the mo-
saic into the gravel which, crushed and pressed by a steamroller,
becomes pavement. Whoever looks at the surface of a road can de-
tect in it the presence of innumerable elements disposed in a nearly
random fashion. There is no recognizable order in their disposi-
tion. Their configuration is extremely open and, as such, contains a
maximum amount of information. We are free to connect the dots
with as many lines as we please without feeling compelled to follow
any particular direction. This situation is very similar to that of
white noise: an excess of equiprobability does not increase the po-
tential for information but completely denies it. Or rather, this po-
tential remains at a mathematical level and does not exist at the level
of communication. The eye no longer receives any direction.
Thus, in the dialectics between work and openness, the very per-
sistence of the work is itself a guarantee of both communication
and aesthetic pleasure. Not only are the two values intimately con-
nected, but each implies the other—which is certainly not the case
with a conventional message such as a road sign, where the act of
communication exists without any aesthetic effect and exhausts it-
self in the apprehension of the referent, without ever inducing us to
return to the sign to enjoy the effectiveness of its message in the
way it is formally expressed. "Openness." on the other hand, is the
guarantee of a particularly rich kind of pleasure that our civilization
pursues as one of its most precious values, since every aspect of our
culture invites us to conceive, feel, and thus see the world as possi-
bility.
V
Television has long been the object of so many debates and so many
theoretical reflections that some people have begun to speak of a
"televisual aesthetics."
In the context of Italian philosophical terminology, "aesthetics"
refers to the investigation of art in general, to the human act that
generates it, and to the overall characteristics of its objects. We can-
not speak of an "aesthetics of painting" or of an "aesthetics of cin-
ema," unless we refer to certain problems that, though they may be
particularly obvious in painting or in cinema, are nevertheless com-
mon to all the arts, and, as such, likely to reveal certain human
attitudes that could become the object of theoretical reflection and
contribute to a philosophical anthropology. In order to apply the
term "aesthetics" to the technical discourses, stylistic analyses, and
critical judgments of a particular art, we would have to give it a
different, more concrete meaning, as has already been done in other
countries. On the other hand, if we want to remain faithful to
traditional Italian terminology (if only for clarity's sake) it may
be preferable to speak of poetics or of a technical-stylistic
analysis—thus acknowledging the importance of such a practice as well
as its theoretical perspicuity, often far superior to that of most
philosophical "aesthetics."
In this essay, I would first of all like to examine what television, and
the structures it generates, can contribute to the field of aesthetic
reflection—whether it can reconfirm certain stances or, as a phe-
nomenon that does not fit into any of the existing categories,
broaden certain theoretical definitions.
Second, I would like to see whether there is any rapport between
106 CHANCE AND PLOT
As soon as the event begins, the director receives the three im-
ages filmed by the three cameras on three separate screens. Prior to
108 CHANCE AND PLOT
favor those that seem to fit that perspective over those that don't. In
other words, we need to group them in a specific form. In yet other
words, we need to unify them into experiences.
I am using the term "experience" here because it allows us to
refer back to Dewey's definition, which seems to be particularly
relevant to the present argument: "We have an experience when the
material experienced runs its course to fulfillment. Then and then
only is it integrated within and demarcated in the general stream of
experience from other experiences . . . In an experience, flow is
from something to something."3 According to this definition, only
those actions that have been brought to their preestablished conclu-
sion, such as a job well done or a completed game, can be consid-
ered experiences.
The artistic aspects of the televisual phenomenon, with all that they
entail, would be fairly easy to recognize if it weren't for the condi-
tions of improvisation, characteristic of live TV, that somewhat
complicate the issue. Dewey, speaking of the experience of logical
thought (though his example can actually be applied to all sorts of
experiences), notes that "in fact in an experience of thinking, prem-
ises emerge only as a conclusion becomes manifest." 8 In other
words, the predicative activity is not a mere syllogistical deduction,
but rather a relentless effort to achieve a conclusion that—alone-
will justify its initial motivation.' Thus, both the "before" and the
"after" of an experience become apparent only after a prolonged
processing of all the data in our possession—data which, of course,
already include some purely chronological "befores" and "afters,"
CHANCE AND PLOT 113
but not the essential ones, the ones that will still be there once the
process of predication is over.
A TV director faces the difficult task of having to identify the
logical phases of an experience at the very moment when these are
still merely chronological. He can isolate a logical thread out of an
ensemble of events but, unlike even the most "realist" of artists,
who can avail himself of both an a priori and an a posteriori stance
vis-a-vis his text, he can neither plan nor revise. In other words, he
must stick to his "plot" while it is still unfolding among many
other plots. By having the cameras follow a particular point of
view, the TV director must essentially invent an event that is still
happening, and invent it so that it is the same as the one that is
taking place. In other words, he must both guess and predict the
time and space of the next phase of his plot. As a result, his artistic
activity is fairly limited and yet, from the viewpoint of production,
very new, for it must be based on a particular sympathy with the
event, an intuition and hypersensitivity (more commonly known
as flair) that would allow him to grow with the event, to happen with
the event. Or, at least, to distinguish the event immediately and
highlight it before it has passed. '°
Whereas theater and the novel have long been progressing in this
direction (I am thinking of works such as those by lonesco, Beck-
ett, and Adamov, and The Connection, by Gelber), cinema, another
art based on plot, has been shying away from it. Its reluctance to
follow this trend was probably determined by various factors, pri-
marily its social role. While other arts were experimenting with
"open" structures, cinema felt obliged to keep in touch with the
broader public and provide it with the traditional dramas our
culture legitimately demands. At this point I would like to add,
parenthetically, that it would be wrong to believe that a poetics of
the open work is the only possible contemporary poetics; I do
not mean even to imply this. For, in fact, the open work is only
one expression, probably the most interesting, of a culture
whose innumerable demands can be satisfied in many different
ways—for instance, by using traditional structures in a more
modern fashion. A movie as fundamentally Aristotelian as
Stagecoach is a perfectly valid example of contemporary narrative.
And yet there have been a few movies that have definitely broken
away from the traditional structures of plot to depict a series
of events totally devoid of conventional dramatic connections—
stories in which nothing happens, or, rather, where things happen
not by narrative necessity but, at least in appearance, by chance. I am
I 16 CHANCE AND PLOT
L'Avventura often lapses into the long, blank spells of live TV; as
do the night revels in La None, or the heroine's interminable walk
amid boys setting off fireworks.
All this seems to suggest that, indeed, live TV may well deserve
to be included—both as a source and as a contemporary phenome-
non—in any study concerning the openness of narrative structures
and the possibility of reproducing life in all its multiplicity, in its
casual unfolding beside and beyond any preestablished plot.
Lion (in itself already a filtered life) that would force them to find
their way amid all sorts of intellectual and moral dilemmas. In other
words, openness presumes the lasting and accurate organization of
afield of stimuli.
Of course, it is quite possible that a live broadcast may be able to
seize, out of a variety of facts, the very ones that lend themselves to
an open organization. But at this point two essential factors come
into play: the nature of the medium and its social purpose—in other
words, its syntax and its audience. It is precisely because of the
chance nature of its material that, in order to keep some control,
live TV resorts to the most traditional and dependable forms of
organization, the most Aristotelian ones, determined by the laws
of causality and necessity which, in the end, are none other than the
laws of verisimilitude.
But aside from these restrictions, which mostly have to do with the
functional relationship between television as a news medium and a
public that demands a particular product, there is also, as I have
already suggested, another kind of restriction, a syntactic one, de-
termined by the very nature of the production process and the sys-
tem of psychological reflexes of the director.
Life, by virtue of the element of chance, is already dispersed
enough to disorient the director who tries to interpret it narratively.
He is constantly in danger of losing the thread and of becoming a
mere photographer of the unrelated and the uniform—not of that
which is intentionally unrelated but of that which is factually acci-
dental, alien. In order to avoid this sort of dispersion, he must
constantly impose some organization on the available data. And
he must do it there and then, without preparation and in the
shortest possible time.
For all its contemporariness, the poetics of the open work is not
yet suited to every form of artistic communication. The structure
with a "plot" in the most Aristotelian sense of the term, is still the
most widespread, even at the highest levels (for, after all, aesthetic
value doesn't necessarily have anything to do with the novelty of a
technique—even though the latter is frequently the symptom of an
originality of both thought and method on which art often thrives).
As for live TV, as long as it responds to this deep need for a plot
that all people feel—a need that will always find satisfaction in
some form or other, whether old or new—it will have to be judged
according to the demands it satisfies and the structures it uses to
satisfy them.
First of all, let's look at the term's origins and correct usage. Its
meaning changes depending on whether it is followed by the prep-
osition "from" (as is generally the case in English) or the preposi-
tion "in" or "to." Philosophical tradition prefers the latter usage as
the more correct translation of the German word Entfremdung,
which implies renouncing oneself for the sake of something else,
abandoning oneself to some extraneous power, becoming "other"
in something outside oneself, therefore ceasing to be an agent in
order to be acted upon. "Alienation from," in the sense of "es-
trangement from" something, corresponds instead to the German
Verfremdung and means something quite different.
In its daily use, however, the term has acquired yet another
meaning which implies that the something that is acting upon us,
and on which we depend, is something totally extraneous to us, a
hostile power that has nothing to do with us, an evil will that has
subjugated us despite all our efforts and that someday we may be
124 FORM AS SOCIAL COMMITMENT
is no longer working for others but working for himself and his
own kin, and thus feels that what he makes is his own product and
that he is one with it.
But then, how could Hegel have so easily confused objectifica-
tion and alienation, as Marx says he did?
From the vantage point of a later historical and industrial reality,
we can now reconsider the whole question of alienation in a differ-
ent light. Hegel did not make any distinction between the two
forms of alienation because, in fact, the moment man objectifies
himself in the works he has created, and in the nature he has modi-
fied, he produces an inevitable tension. The two poles of such a
tension are, on the one hand, his domination of the object, and, on
the other, his total dissolution in the object, his total surrender to it.
This is a dialectic balance that is based on a constant struggle
between the negation of what is asserted and the assertion of what is
denied. Thus, alienation would seem to be an integral part of
every relationship one establishes with others and with things,
whether this be in love, in society. or within an industrial struc-
ture.' The question of alienation would then become (to put it in
Hegelian terms, at least metaphorically) "the question of a human self-
consciousness, which, unable to conceive of itself as a separate 'cogito,'
can find itself only in the world that it itself constructs, and in the
other Ts it recognizes, and, at times, misconstrues. But, this way of
finding oneself in the other, this objectification, is always more or
less a form of alienation, at once a loss of oneself and a recovery of
oneself."' Obviously, if the lesson of Hegel sounds much more
concrete today than it did to Marx it is because our culture has had
the advantage of rereading him through Marx.
The kind of alienation Marx speaks of is, on the one hand, the same
as that which is studied by political economy, namely that which
derives from the use that a society based on private property makes
of the objects produced by a worker. (Because he produces for
others, he makes himself ugly by producing beauty and
mechanizes himself by producing machines.) On the other hand,
it is the sort of alienation that is intrinsic to the very process of
production. This second kind of alienation is fostered by the worker,
who fails to see his work as an end in itself and instead considers
it as a means of survival in which he fails to recognize himself
(since neither the product nor the work belongs to him).
Since these two types of alienation are necessary for the survival
of a particular society, it is conceivable, following a Marxist line of
reasoning, that a radical modification of the system of relationships
on which that society is based would eliminate alienation.
On the other hand, even though a modification of society may
liberate man from this sort of subjection (and give him back the
object he produces as well as the productive work he has
accomplished both for himself and the collectivity), the constant
tension characteristic of his alienation "in" the object would remain
(this is where Hegel contributes to a greater understanding of
the problem), since the object the worker has produced is
constantly threatening to control him. This sort of alienation
could indeed be perceived as an existential structure or, if we prefer, as
the problem that confronts every subject who, having produced an
object, turns to it with the intent either to use it or, simply, to
consider it. My remarks here will concentrate on this
particular kind of alienation—the one that follows every act of
objectification—since I believe that this problem has its own
characteristics and that it is part of the relationship between man
and the world that surrounds him. Of course, a Marxist point of
view could easily maintain that this problem would be confronted
with greater freedom and awareness in a society that has
eliminated economic alienation. But even in this case, the problem
would retain most of its urgency.'
* * *
FORM AS SOCIAL COMMITMENT 13I
From the very beginning of time, the ability to extend one's cor-
poreality (and therefore to alter one's own natural dimensions) has
been the very condition of homo faber. To consider such a situation
as a degradation of human nature implies that nature and man are
not one and the same thing. It implies an inability to accept the idea
that nature exists in relation to man, is defined, extended, and
modified in and by man; just as man is one particular expression of
nature, an active, modifying expression who distinguishes him-
self from his environment precisely because of his capacity to act
upon it and to define it—a capacity that gives him the right to
say "I."
FORM AS SOCIAL COMMITMENT 133
The only difference between Cecilia and the inventor of the flint-
stone lies in the complexities of their respective actions, which,
otherwise, are structurally very similar. Cecilia is like the caveman
who, having seized his tool, starts using it frantically, to crack the
nuts he has gathered, to beat the earth on which he is kneeling, until
he loses himself so entirely in his savage actions that he forgets why
he seized the object in the first place (just as, at certain orgiastic
moments, a drummer ceases to play the drums and is himself
played by them).
There is an ante quern limit; that is, up to this limit, letting a car
possess us is a sign of sanity and the only way in which we can
really possess the car: to be unable to sense that there is such a limit,
and that it is possible to reach it, means that we don't understand
the object and therefore destroy it. This is what the "beautiful soul"
does, thereby losing itself in its own negations. There is also a post
quem limit, which is where morbidity begins. And there is a way of
understanding the object, the experience we have of it, and the use
we make of it, which in its sheer optimism risks making us forget
the presence of a limit, the constant danger of alienation.
At the opposite extreme of the beautiful soul's refusal, we find
Dewey's philosophy.
rience that is had, and the close which completes it is the institution
of a felt harmony."
It is easy to see how this particular notion of experience could
also define, albeit in an absolutely positive way, a typical instance of
alienation, such as the relationship between Cecilia and her car. The
tragic suspicion that a relationship with an object may fail precisely
because it succeeds too much is absent from Dewey's philosophy.
For Dewey, an experience can fail (that is, fail to be a full-fledged
experience) only when between the person and the object there is a
polarity that cannot be resolved by integration; when there is inte-
gration there is experience, and an experience can only be positive.
Dewey would see Cecilia's relationship with her car as good simply
because it is based on total integration, and is expressive of a har-
mony in which all the original polarities are combined.
Thus, we have identified two extreme attitudes toward the recur-
ring and ineluctable possibility of alienation present in all our rela-
tionships with things and others: the pessimistic attitude, which
destroys the object (or rejects it as evil) for fear of being implicated
in it, and the optimistic attitude, according to which integration
with the object is the only positive aspect of a relationship.
The availability to the world characteristic of the second attitude
is fundamental, because it allows us to commit ourselves to the
world and to act in it. But the fear that accompanies our every
dealing with the world, and the awareness that our adjustment
could turn out to be a failure, are also essential to the welfare of the
relationship.
With this last observation, the discussion has moved from the ex-
amination of a direct, real relationship with a situation, to that of
the forms through which one organizes one's analysis of the situa-
tion. How does alienation manifest itself at the level of art or of
pseudo-art forms?
Since I have decided here to use "alienation" in its broadest sense,
my argument on this subject will develop along two different, if
converging, lines.
First of all, one could speak of the sort of alienation that occurs
within a formal system, and which could be more aptly defined
as a dialectic between invention and manner, between freedom
and formal restrictions. Let's, for instance, consider the system of
rhyme.
maintained that this type of formal habit has its roots in a society
based on respect for an immutable order of things; in other words,
tonal music is merely another way of reiterating the basic attitude
of an entire educational system at both a social and a theoretical
level." Obviously, to postulate such a perfect reflective relationship
between a social structure and the structure of a musical language
may appear a hasty generalization; yet it is not by chance that, in
our day, tonal music has become the music of an occasional com-
munity of people, brought together by the ritual of going to concerts—
people who like to express their aesthetic sensibility at a particular
time of the day, wearing a particular kind of clothing, and who pay
the price of admission in order to undergo an experience of crisis
and resolution, so that when they leave the "temple" they will feel
fully purged by the cathartic effect of art.
So, the avant-garde musician rejects the tonal system not only
because it alienates him to a conventional system of musical laws,
but also because it alienates him to a social ethics and to a given
vision of the world. Of course, the moment he breaks away from
the accepted system of communication and renounces its advan-
tages, he will inevitably appear to be involved in an antihuman ac-
tivity, whereas in fact he has engaged in it in order to avoid mysti-
fying and deceiving his public. By rejecting a musical model, the avant-
garde musician actually rejects (more or less consciously) a social
model. But it would be wrong to assume that this double
rejection involves no affirmation.
The musical system that the avant-garde musician rejects com-
FORM AS SOCIAL COMMITMENT 141
judge the actual state of affairs. In other words, he would lead them
to trust in the orderly world expressed by their orderly language.
Though it is commonly believed that avant-garde artists are out
of touch with the human community in which they live, and that
traditional art remains in close contact with it. the opposite is true.
In fact, only avant-garde artists are capable of establishing a mean-
ingful relationship with the world in which they live.'
Antonioni does not tell us anything about our world and its
problems, about a social reality that would interest any movie di-
rector eager to express an artistic opinion of our contemporary in-
dustrial situation—or, at least, not in so many words. Instead, he
shows us two people, a man and a woman, who leave each other
for no reason, or out of emotional aridity. The woman subse-
FORM AS SOCIAL COMMITMENT 149
quently has an affair with another man, also for no reason and
without any emotional commitment. The emotional inertia of the
characters and their perfunctory actions are regularly punctuated
by the hard and ineluctable presence of objects, which seems to
dominate both human relationships and the situation in which
these occur. Predictably, the central setting of the movie is the
stock market, where fortunes are made and unmade according to
no visible logic, for no palpable reason, and with no definite aim.
("What happens to all these billions?" the young woman asks a
young broker, who readily admits he does not know. His aggressive
manner gives the impression of a strong will in action, but in fact
he is a pawn, acted upon by the very situation he is trying to
control: he is the perfect example of alienation.) No
psychological parameter can explain this situation. It is what it is
precisely because nowadays it is impossible to believe in unitary
parameters; each individual is fragmented and manipulated by a
number of external forces. Of course, an artist cannot express
all this as a judgment because a judgment would require, along
with an ethical parameter, the syntax and the grammar of a
rational system, the grammar of the traditional movie, in
which events follow one another causally. The best solution for a
movie director is to show the moral and psychological indeterminacy
of the situation in the indeterminacy of the sequences: scenes
follow one another for no apparent reason; the camera lingers
on objects with an intensity that has no motive and no aim.
Antonioni lets his forms express the alienation he wants to
communicate to his public. By choosing to express it in the
very structure of his discourse, he manages to control it while
letting it act upon his viewers. This movie about a useless and
unlikely love affair between useless and unlikely characters tells us
more about contemporary man and his world than a panoramic
melodrama involving workers in overalls and countless
social confrontations, structured according to the logical, rational
demands of a nineteenth-century plot—whose very denouement
would imply the resolution of all contradictions into a universal
order.'3 In fact, the only order man can impose upon his situation
is the order of a structural organization whose very disorder
leads to the apprehension of the situation.
no longer relate to them, though they might yet find a new way of
doing so in the future. The fluidity of characterization in In the
Labyrinth—where objects also appear as fluid—is, in fact, only an
expression of a new vision of time and reversibility, such as has
emerged from the hypotheses of modern science. (As I have men-
tioned elsewhere, the temporal structure of In the Labyrinth had
already been sketched by Hans Reichenbachr Although, at the
level of macroscopic relationships, the only applicable notion of
time remains that of classical physics as it is reflected in the struc-
tures of traditional narrative—and, more specifically, in the irrever-
sible and univocal relationship between cause and effect—the artist
can decide to make an experiment that has absolutely no scientific
validity but is characteristic of the way in which an entire culture
reacts to new stimuli; he can thus structure his narrative according
to a nonclassical notion of time. At this point, such a notion of time
is no longer a scientific model used to describe remote microphysi-
cal events; rather, it becomes a sort of game that we play from in-
side and that gives shape to our entire existence.
Installed in a language that has already done so much speaking: this is the
problem. The artist realizes that language, having already done too
much speaking, has become alienated to the situation it was meant
to express. He realizes that, if he accepts this language, he will also
alienate himself to the situation. So he tries to dislocate this lan-
guage from within, in order to be able to escape from the situation
and judge it from without. Since language can be dislocated only
according to a dialectic that is already part of its inner evolution,
the language that will result from such a dislocation will still, some-
how, reflect the historical situation that was itself produced by the
crisis of the one that had preceded it. I violate language because I
refuse to express, through it, a false integrity that is no longer ours,
but, by doing so, I can't but express and accept the very dissociation
that has arisen out of the crisis of integrity and that I meant to
dominate with my discourse. There is no alternative to this dialec-
tic. As already mentioned, all the artist can hope to do is cast some
light on alienation by objectifying it in a form that reproduces it.
In any case, the artistic process that tries to give form to disorder,
amorphousness, and dissociation is nothing but the effort of a rea-
son that wants to lend a discursive clarity to things. When its dis-
course is unclear, it is because things themselves, and our relation-
ship to them, are still very unclear —indeed, so unclear that it
would be ridiculous to pretend to define them from the uncontam-
inated podium of rhetoric. It would be only another way of escap-
ing reality and leaving it exactly as it is. And wouldn't this be the
ultimate and most successful figure of alienation?
VII
Formativity
According to Pareyson, all human life is the invention and produc-
tion of forms. Everything mankind does, whether on an intellec-
tual, moral, or artistic level, results in forms—full-fledged, or-
ganic, autonomous creations, endowed with a comprehensibility of
their own. This includes theoretical constructs as well as civic insti-
tutions, daily achievements as well as technical endeavors, paintings
as well as poems.
nism: a total form in which all the so-called "padding" has a "struc-
tural" value (and here I am using the term "structure" as a synonym
for "form," for an artistic entity), since it shares in the perfection
and legitimacy of the form that it supports.
What finally unifies all these theoretical formulations is the fun-
damental premise according to which a form, once it has reached
completion and autonomy, can be seen as perfect only if it is dynam-
ically considered. Aesthetic contemplation is this active considera-
tion that retraces the process which gave life to form. The work is
thus defined as the narration of the effort that went into its making:
"form is the very process in its conclusive and inclusive aspect; it is
not separable from the process of which it is the perfection, the
conclusion, and the totality." Form is at once the "current mem-
ory" and the "permanent recollection" of the productive activity
that gave it life.
This polarity between the concrete personality of the artist and that
of the interpreter allows Pareyson to situate the potential for per-
manence of a work of art in the very infinity of the interpretations
it opens itself to. By giving life to a form, the artist makes it acces-
sible to an infinite number of possible interpretations—possible be-
cause "the work lives only in the interpretations that are given of
it," and infinite not only because of the characteristic fecundity of
the form itself, but because this fecundity will inevitably be con-
fronted with an infinity of interpreting personalities, each with its
own way of seeing, thinking, and being. Interpretation is an exer-
cise in "congeniality," based on the fundamental unity of human
166 LUIGI PAREYSON'S AESTHETICS
was understood that I was not going to be concerned with the suc-
cess or failure of a work, since my approach was not that of a liter-
ary, figurative, or musical critic but that of a cultural historian. I
was going to be concerned only with the works, both as projects
and products of particular formal approaches capable of clarifying
certain aspects of contemporary culture. Criticism had nothing to
do with it. Obviously, those who condemned this kind of study for
avoiding the risk of an axiological distinction between valid and
nonvalid works were essentially expecting the historian of poetics
to do the job of the critic. It was a little as if, during a historical
investigation of the effects of the Sarajevo assassination (how did
the event influence other important historical movements such as
the Allies' intervention in the war, and the Russian Revolution?),
someone had suddenly wondered whether the murderer's act was
moral or not. Though perfectly valid in a different context, such an
ethical consideration would be totally useless to a historical analysis
of causes and effects. And yet, on second thought, that sort of ob-
jection is never entirely irrelevant. After all, it is fairly natural that
a historian working on a particular period should center his study
on the events he deems most relevant. Similarly, the cultural histor-
ian who attempts a description of the artistic movements of his
times is inevitably led to discuss those art phenomena which,
though they may mostly interest him for their implicit or explicit
poetics, have also met with his approval as finished works of art;
otherwise he would not have noticed them or would not have been
able to conceal the irritation, disgust, or boredom they might have
provoked in him.
What the stories could tell was secondary and no longer interest-
ing. Unfortunately, the constructive idea was hardly more intrigu-
ing, since it was merely a far-fetched variation on an exploit that
had already been realized, and with much more vigor, by contem-
porary narrative. As a result, Saporta's was only an extreme case,
and remarkable only for that reason.
TWO HYPOTHESES ABOUT THE DEATH OF ART 171
But one does not need a Saporta to reach this kind of conclusion.
As we all know, some interpretations of Finnegans Wake risk being
more interesting, informative, and entertaining than the work it-
self. Similarly, the summary of a movie, or a description of the
criteria according to which it has been realized, is often more per-
suasive than the movie itself. Indeed, it often happens that a work
falls quite short of the expectations that its poetic intentions have
aroused in us. The banal question of the neophyte confronting a
work of abstract art ("What does it mean?"), a question that would
seem to have nothing to do with aesthetics, criticism, or the history
of poetics, is much more illuminating than it seems. The hapless
viewer asks what the author of the painting wanted to do, because
if he does not know this he won't be able to enjoy the painting. If
someone explains it to him, then he may begin to appreciate the
work. The work or its rationalization? In any case, his critical ap-
proach clearly shows us (as if it were necessary) that in modern art
the question of poetics has become more important than the crea-
tion of the work itself, that the way in which a work is constructed
has become more important than the constructed work, and that
form can be appreciated only as the outcome of a formal approach.2
In this essay, Formaggio shows how the elements that have pre-
occupied us in the preceding pages—that is, the emergence of a
poetry of poetry and of the critical awareness of this phenome-
non—were already present in Schiller, Novalis, and Hegel, not to
mention HOlderlin. The careful analysis that he devotes to these
authors and to the evolution of the notion of the "death of art"
shows that it would be much too simplistic to believe in "a histori-
cal end of art," and that it would be much more reasonable to
understand the formula in the Hegelian sense of "the end of a cer-
tain form of art," part of a historical development in which the
advent of a new idea of "art" must appear as the negation of what
the same term meant for the preceding culture.
the idealistic nineteenth century was very much aware of this pro-
cess. Rather than interpreting it as a symptom of impending death,
however, De Sanctis chose to see it as the beginning of a new devel-
opment born out of dialectic negation. "What's the point of com-
plaining about the state of art and wishing this or that? Science has
infiltrated poetry and is here to stay, because this fact corresponds
to the current condition of the human mind. We have never been
able to look at something beautiful without immediately wonder-
ing whether it is also reasonable—and here we are already in the
midst of criticism and science! Not only do we want to enjoy, but
we also want to be conscious of our enjoyment; not only do we
want to feel, but we also want to understand. Today, honest poetry
is as impossible as honest faith. Just as we are unable to speak of
religion without being irked by doubts ('But is it really true?'), so
are we unable to feel without philosophizing about our feelings, or
to see without trying to understand our vision. All those who re-
sent Goethe, Schiller, Byron, and Leopardi for constructing, as
they see it, a "metaphysics in verse," remind me of those priests
who rail and rant against philosophy and bemoan the loss of faith.
Unfortunately faith is gone, and poetry is dead. Or rather, since
both faith and poetry are immortal, what is dead is one of their
particular ways of being. Today, faith springs out of conviction, and
poetry out of meditation. They are not dead; they are only dif-
ferent."'
cure, the work of art expresses a particular notion of time and space,
how will this notion differ from the one elaborated by other disci-
plines?
The defender of contemporary art could reply that when a work
of art expresses certain ideas about the world, or man, or the rela-
tionship between the two in the way in which it is constructed, it
always does so in a "total" sense, as if the work, or the structural
model the work realizes, were a compendium of reality (as seen,
for instance, in Finnegans Wake), whereas both science and philoso-
phy (at least nonmetaphysical philosophy) seem to proceed in
terms of partial definitions, allowing us only a temporary knowl-
edge of separate aspects of reality—since they cannot afford to give
us a comprehensive synthesis, or they would become works of
imagination and move into the realm of art. For the sake of synthe-
sis, such an answer could be translated into the following one: art
offers us an organic knowledge of things—in other words, it ac-
quaints us with things by gathering them into one form. The struc-
tural model envisioned by poetics and revealed by the critical dis-
course is just a configuration, a Gestalt, that can be seized only in
its totality. It must not be verified in its isolated elements, but rather
accepted as the proposal of an intuitive vision, valid at the level of
the imagination, even if rationally analyzable in its various aspects.
This sort of answer would lead us back into an autonomous zone
reserved exclusively for artistic discourse. And we would realize
that if it is true that in contemporary art the formed object tends to
disappear behind the formal model it is supposed to express, it is
also true that this model assumes all the prerogatives that once be-
longed to the formed object, and, as a result, it can be not only
"understood" but also "enjoyed" for its organic qualities and,
therefore, appreciated in an exquisitely aesthetic sense.
Bad taste shares the same lot that Croce saw as characteristic of art:
everybody knows what it is and how to detect and predicate it, but
nobody knows how to define it. For this, it is often necessary to
turn to the experts. the connoisseurs, people "with taste," on the
basis of whose behavior we can then define good or bad taste, in
relation to particular cultural settings.
At times we recognize bad taste instinctively, in the irritation we
feel when confronted by an obvious lack of proportion, or by
something that seems out of place—a tactless remark (what we
commonly know as a gaffe) or unjustified pomposity: "It was dy-
namic hatred and loathing, coming strong and black out of the
unconsciousness. She heard his words in her unconscious self, con-
sciously she was as if deafened, she paid no heed to them"; "Her
subtle, feminine, demoniacal soul knew it well" (both examples
courtesy of D. H. Lawrence's Women in Love). In all these cases,
bad taste manifests itself as a lack of measure, a "measure" that is
itself very difficult to define, since it varies from place to place and
from age to age.
A Stylistics of Kitsch
The sea whispers in the distance, and in the enchanted silence
the wind gently ruffles the stiffened leaves. An opaque silken
gown, embroidered with gold and ivory, flowed along her
limbs, revealing a smooth sinuous neck swathed in fiery
tresses. No light yet burned in Brunhilde's solitary chamber;
slender palms rose out of precious Chinese vases like dark, fan-
tastic shadows, in the midst of which flashed, white, the mar-
moreal bodies of ancient, ghostly statues. Barely visible, on the
walls, lurked the subdued glimmer of gold-framed paintings.
Brunhilde, her hands softly gliding over the keyboard of the
piano at which she was seated, was lost in sweet reflection.
Thus, music flowed in somber search, like veils of smoke rising
out of incandescent ashes, frayed by the wind, swirling and
soaring in fantastic tatters, away from the inessential flame.
Slowly and majestically the melody rose, bursting into power-
ful accents, folding back onto itself with the pleading, enchant-
ing, ineffably sweet voices of children and angelic choirs, whis-
pering above nocturnal forests and solitary vales, ample,
ardent, fraught with ancient steles, playing through forlorn
rural cemeteries. Clear meadows are thus disclosed, the
slender-bodied games of spring, while autumn lurks behind an
evil old hag seated under a shower of leaves. It will soon be
winter; large bright angels, as tall as heaven above the snow,
will bow
182 THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE
over the listening shepherds and will sing about the wondrous
child of Bethlehem.
A heavenly enchantment, full of the secrets of the holy
Christmas, is thus woven around the wintry vale sunk in peace-
ful slumber, like the faraway song of a harp, estranged by the
noise of day, like the secret of sadness singing of the divine
origin. Outside, the nocturnal wind caresses the golden house
with tender hands, and stars wander through the wintry night.
every step one has a sense of the transience, the ephemerality of the
effect, always on the point of dissolving in its own echo but never
allowed to do so.
Killy cites the example of great poets who have occasionally felt
the need to rely on lyrical evocation, even if (as in the case of
Goethe) this meant grafting verse onto prose in order to suddenly
reveal an essential trait of the story which the narrative, articulated
according to a certain logic, was unable to express. But with
Kitsch, a change of tone has no cognitive function; it merely rein-
forces the sentimental stimulus, so that, in the end, this sort of
episodic insertion becomes the norm.
Given the way in which it articulates itself, like any other artistic
communication whose project is not that of involving the reader in
an act of discovery but that of forcing him to register a particular
effect (in the belief that therein lies aesthetic pleasure), Kitsch would
seem to be some sort of artistic hoax, or, as Hermann Broch puts
it, "the element of evil in the value system of art." 3
As an easily digestible substitute for art, Kitsch is the ideal food
for a lazy audience that wants to have access to beauty and enjoy it
without having to make too much of an effort. According to Killy,
Kitsch is largely a petty bourgeois phenomenon, the cultural pre-
tense of a public that believes it can enjoy an original representation
of the world whereas in fact it can only appreciate a secondary imi-
tation of the primary power of the images.
Killy seems to be part of that critical tradition which has spread
from Germany to a number of Anglo-Saxon countries and which,
having defined Kitsch as a petty bourgeois phenomenon, has iden-
tified it with the most glaring expressions of mass culture—of an
average, consumer culture.
well as to the destiny of art in society. Arguments such as these are works of art. In other words, Killy's passage is Kitsch not only
often based on a rather ahistorical notion of art, for in fact it would because it aims at producing sentimental effects but also because it
be enough to consider the function fulfilled by art in other histori- is constantly trying to convince its readers that if they enjoy these
cal contexts to realize that the fact that a work is capable of produc- effects, then they will share a privileged aesthetic experience.
ing an immediate effect has never been a reason to exclude such a To become a piece of Kitsch, a passage needs more than the lin-
work from the realm of art. If one is to believe Aristotle, in Greece guistic factors intrinsic to the message: it also needs the author's
art had the function of producing a psychological effect; such was, intent to sell it to his audience, and the audience's intent to appre-
at least, the function of both music and tragedy. Whether in that ciate it. Broch is right when he says that Kitsch does not concern
particular context there was actually another meaning given to the art so much as a certain kind of behavior, or a certain kind of per-
concept of aesthetic pleasure. involving the appreciation of the son, a "Kitsch-man" who needs such a form of falsehood so that he
form through which the effect is realized, is another question. Suf- can recognize himself in it. If we agree with this, then Kitsch will
fice it to say that in certain societies art is so deeply integrated with appear as a negative force, a constant mystification, an eternal es-
daily life that its primary function is precisely that of provoking cape from the responsibilities involved in the experience of art. As
particular reactions (ludic, religious, erotic) as effectively as pos- the theologian R. Egenter used to say, the Father of Lies would use
sible. Kitsch to alienate the masses from all notion of salvation, because
he would recognize it as much more powerful, in its mystifying
The production of an effect becomes Kitsch in a cultural context
and consoling power, even than scandals, since these have a ten-
in which art is seen not as technical ability (as was the case in ancient
dency to awaken the moral defenses of the virtuous at the very
Greece and in the Middle Ages) but rather as something produced
moment in which they are most effectively attacking them.'
for art's sake. According to this definition, any process that, using
"artistic" means, aims at achieving a heteronomous end would fall
under the more generic rubric of an "artisticity" that can assume a
variety of forms but that should not be confused with art. No mat- Kitsch and Mass Culture
ter how much art I might pour into the creation of a cookie, it will
never be anything more than a mere effect of artisticity, since in The definition of Kitsch as a communication aiming at the produc-
tion of an immediate effect has certainly helped to identify it with
order to be art (in the noblest sense of the term) it would have to be
mass culture, and to set it in dialectic opposition to the "high" cul-
appreciated for its style rather than desired for its taste.'
ture proposed by the avant-garde.
But what allows us to say that an object whose artisticity seems
The culture industry appeals to a generic mass of consumers (for
to have a heteronomous end is by definition in bad taste?
the most part quite unaware of the complexities of specialized cul-
A dress designed so as to enhance the charms of its wearer is not, tural life) by selling them ready-made effects, which it prescribes
by definition, a product of bad taste (though it would be if it drew along with directions for their use and a list of the reactions they
the attention of the viewer only to the more obvious attributes of should provoke. This technique is very similar to the one used in
the wearer, thus reducing her personality to a mere prop for one the sixteenth century to hawk popular prints. Even then, emotional
particular physical trait). But if the production of an effect is not in appeal was the best way to awaken the public's need for a certain
itself enough to constitute an instance of Kitsch, then something product. From the titles of sixteenth-century popular prints to to-
else must be needed. This something else emerges out of Killy's day's slogans, via nineteenth-century romances and popular novels,
analysis the moment we realize that the passage he has brought to the procedure has not changed a great deal. As a result, while petty
our attention wants to be considered as art. And we realize it be- bourgeois and mass culture (both fully industrialized) are more in-
cause of the way it ostentatiously employs modes of expression that terested in the presumed effects of a work of art rather than in the
have previously appeared in works traditionally considered as work itself, artists have moved to the opposite extreme: what they
THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE 185
care about is neither the work nor its effects but the process that
leads to both.
According to Clement Greenberg's felicitous formula, "Avant-
garde imitates the processes of art; Kitsch imitates its effects," Pi-
casso paints the cause of a possible effect, whereas Repin (an oleo-
graphic painter particularly favored by Soviet cultural policy under
Stalin) paints the effect of a possible cause. Whereas the avant-garde
stresses the importance of the processes that lead to the work and
turns them into the very object of its discourse, Kitsch focuses on
the reactions that the work should provoke in its audience and sees
these as its very raison d'etre.6 This definition is very much related to
that new stance of contemporary criticism according to which,
from Romanticism to our own day, poetry has increasingly as-
sumed the traits of a metapoetry (a discourse on poetry and its po-
tential). As a result, today's poetics are much more important than
the works themselves, since, after all, the works are nothing more
than discourses on their own poetics, or, better yet, are their own
poetics.'
But the question of the dialectics between Kitsch and the avant-
garde is not solved by eschewing all aesthetic evaluation in favor of
more serious concerns such as the ones considered above. Quite the
contrary, for not only does the avant-garde emerge as a reaction to
the diffusion of Kitsch, but Kitsch keeps renewing itself and thriv-
ing on the very discoveries of the avant-garde. While the latter, re-
fusing to serve as an experimental laboratory for an ever-growing
188 THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE 189
cultural industry, is constantly concocting new forms, the former, dure to pitch a particular drink or a new car model, or when Tin
relentlessly stimulated by the new ideas of the avant-garde, keeps Pan Alley transforms Beethoven's "Fur Elise" into a dance tune, the
processing, adapting, and diffusing these according to its commer- use of the cultural product is meant for a consumption that has
cial standards, in the process changing them from procedural forms nothing to do with, and does not pretend to have anything to do
which try to direct the audience's attention to the causes of their with, an aesthetic experience. On the other hand, it is possible that
being, into effect-producing formulas. while enjoying such a product the consumer may catch on to a
particular phrase, a stylistic element that has kept some of the orig-
From this particular standpoint, the anthropological situation of inal's nobility. Even though he may not know where the phrase
mass culture would seem to hinge on a perpetual dialectic between comes from, he might enjoy its formal arrangement, its function,
innovative ideas and acceptable adjustments, in which the former and in the process take delight in an aesthetic experience which,
are constantly betrayed by the latter, since the greater part of the however, does not claim to replace other, "higher" experiences.
public is convinced that it is enjoying the first, whereas it is actually These examples open up a different set of issues (the legitimacy of
enjoying the second. advertising, the pedagogical and social functions of dance) that have
little or nothing to do with the problematics of Kitsch. We are deal-
ing with mass products that aim at the production of effects with-
Midcult out pretending to be art.
but it decently covers them with a cultural figleaf." To understand they are not individuals so much as universal values and that there-
what MacDonald means by "Midcult," it is worth following him fore, through them, the reader will undergo a philosophical expe-
in his cruel but keen analysis of Hemingway's The Old Man and rience, a profound revelation of reality. "'Undefeated' is fifty-seven
the Sea.'° pages long, as against Old Man's one hundred and forty; not only
does much more happen in it but also one feels that more has hap-
It is indeed possible to follow the dialectics between Kitsch and
pened than is expressed, so to speak, while Old Man gives the op-
the avant-garde just by examining Hemingway's opus: at the begin-
posite impression. " Not only does The Old Man proceed unsteadily
ning, his writing is very clearly a means of discovering reality, but
along the edge of a false universality, but it also frequently relies on
by and by, and despite a seemingly unaltered appearance, it bends
what MacDonald calls "constant editorializing" (in other words, it
to the demands of an audience that wants to have access to such an
advertises itself). At a certain point in the book, Hemingway has
exciting writer. MacDonald quotes the beginning of one of Hem-
the old man say: "I'm a strange old man," to which MacDonald
ingway's first short stories, "The Undefeated," a bullfighting story
ruthlessly retorts, "Prove it, old man, don't say it!" It is not difficult
he wrote in the 192os when "he was knocking them out of the
to see why this tale appeals to the average reader: it still has the
park": "Manuel Garcia climbed the stairs to Don Miguel Retana's
exterior trappings of the early Hemingway (raw, distant), but here
office. He set down his suitcase and knocked on the door. There
they are diluted and reiterated till they are fully digested. The hy-
was no answer. Manuel, standing in the hallway, felt there was
persensitivity of Manuel Garcia, who is by now used to bad luck,
someone in the room. He felt it through the door." Vintage Hem-
is suggested, represented in his feeling, through the closed door,
ingway. Only a few words—the situation is rendered through the
the hostile presence of the elusive impresario. The bad luck of the
attitudes of its characters. The theme is that of an old-timer getting
old man is instead explained to the reader, whose sympathy is
one last chance. The beginning of The Old Man and the Sea also
nudged by the author's waving in front of his eyes, until they well
introduces us to an old-timer getting one last chance:
with tears, that tattered sail that looks like "the flag of permanent
defeat" (close kin to the enchanted silence and the subdued glimmer
He was an old man who fished alone in a skiff in the Gulf that hover over Brunhilde's chamber in the first quoted passage).
Stream and he had gone eighty-four days now without taking a On the other hand, no average reader would respond to the persua-
fish. In the first forty days a boy had been with him. But after sive power of that sail if its metaphor did not bring back to his mind
forty days without a fish the boy's parents had told him that the the memory of other similar metaphors, from other poetic con-
old man was now definitely and finally salao, which is the texts, that have by now become part of the literary canon. Once the
worst form of unlucky, and the boy had gone at their orders in mnemonic short circuit is provoked, and the impression of poetic-
another boat which caught three good fish the first week. It ity registered and felt, the game is over. The reader is aware of
made the boy sad to see the old man come in each day with his having consumed some art and of having recognized Truth in the
skiff empty and he always went down to help him carry either face of Beauty. At this point, Hemingway is an author that can be
the coiled lines or the gaff and harpoon and the sail that was appreciated by everybody, and as such worthy of being awarded
furled around the mast. The sail was patched with flour sacks the Nobel Prize (which, as MacDonald reminds us, had already
and, furled, it looked like the flag of permanent defeat. been awarded to Pearl Buck).
they are not individuals so much as universal values and that there-
fore, through them, the reader will undergo a philosophical expe-
rience, a profound revelation of reality. "'Undefeated' is fifty-seven
pages long, as against Old Man's one hundred and forty; not only
does much more happen in it but also one feels that more has hap-
pened than is expressed, so to speak, while Old Man gives the op-
posite impression. " Not only does The Old Man proceed unsteadily
along the edge of a false universality, but it also frequently relies on
what MacDonald calls "constant editorializing" (in other words, it
advertises itself). At a certain point in the book, Hemingway has
the old man say: "I'm a strange old man," to which MacDonald
ruthlessly retorts, "Prove it, old man, don't say it!" It is not difficult
to see why this tale appeals to the average reader: it still has the
exterior trappings of the early Hemingway (raw, distant), but here
they are diluted and reiterated till they are fully digested. The hy-
persensitivity of Manuel Garcia, who is by now used to bad luck,
is suggested, represented in his feeling, through the closed door,
the hostile presence of the elusive impresario. The bad luck of the
old man is instead explained to the reader, whose sympathy is
nudged by the author's waving in front of his eyes, until they well
with tears, that tattered sail that looks like "the flag of permanent
defeat" (close kin to the enchanted silence and the subdued glimmer
that hover over Brunhilde's chamber in the first quoted passage).
On the other hand, no average reader would respond to the persua-
sive power of that sail if its metaphor did not bring back to his mind
the memory of other similar metaphors, from other poetic con-
texts, that have by now become part of the literary canon. Once the
mnemonic short circuit is provoked, and the impression of poetic-
ity registered and felt, the game is over. The reader is aware of
having consumed some art and of having recognized Truth in the
face of Beauty. At this point, Hemingway is an author that can be
appreciated by everybody, and as such worthy of being awarded
the Nobel Prize (which, as MacDonald reminds us, had already
been awarded to Pearl Buck).
To let snobbery infiltrate an aesthetic sociology of the consump- ered as two corollary aspects of the same situation. When Adorno
tion of forms is quite dangerous. Formal procedures sooner or later speaks of the reduction of the musical product to a fetish' s —and
become worn out, but who can decide what are the best criteria for when he points out that this fate befalls not only the popular song
judging consumption? The difference between critical sensibility but also the artistic product of nobler origins the moment it is pop-
and snobbery is minimal: a critique of mass culture can be the ularized—he is trying to tell us that it is not so much a question of
ultimate and most refined product of mass culture, whereas the knowing whether, listening to a particular composition, the con-
"aristocrat," who merely does what others don't yet do, in fact sumer appreciates a message because of the effects it produces in
depends entirely on what they do to know what not to do. him, as whether, in fact, he appreciates it because he mistakes its
Abandoned to individual moods, particular palates, and value obsolete form for that of the original aesthetic experience. Accord-
judgments. the critique of taste becomes a sterile game. likely to ing to Adorno, this distinction does not make any difference, since
produce a few pleasant emotions but unable to tell us much about in both cases the average man's relationship to the commercialized
the cultural phenomena of an entire society. Good and bad taste artistic product expresses itself in the blind and thoughtless adora-
thus become flimsy categories that may be of absolutely no use in tion of the fetish. Unable and unwilling to apprehend either good
defining the complex functionality of a message within a given or bad music analytically, he accepts it as it is, as something that it
group or society. Mass society is so rich in determinations and is good to consume because the law of the market has decreed it to
possibilities, that it acquires an immensely elaborate network of be so, thus relieving him of any need to express his own judgment.
mediations and reactions between a culture of discovery, a culture
of mere consumption, and a culture of popularization and This radically negative criticism, which we have already seen to
mediation, none of which can be easily reduced to a simple definition be unproductive, turns mass consumers into a generic fetish and
of Beauty or Kitsch. the object of consumption into another, unexplainable fetish, while
totally ignoring the great variety of attitudes present at the level of
All these supercilious condemnations of mass taste, in the name mass consumption.
of an ideal community of readers involved solely in discovering the
secret beauties of the cryptic messages produced by high art, ne-
glect the average consumer (present in just about all of us) who at Consumption and Recovery of Artistic Messages
the end of the day may resort to a book or a movie in the hope that
it may evoke a few basic reactions (laughter, fear, pleasure, sorrow, Any work of art can be viewed as a message to be decoded by an
anger) and, through these, reestablish some balance in his or her addressee. But unlike most messages, instead of aiming at trans-
physical and intellectual life. A well-balanced cultural context does
mitting a univocal meaning, the work of art succeeds precisely in-
not require the eradication of this sort of message; it only needs to sofar as it appears ambiguous and open-ended. The notion of the
keep them under control, dose them, and see to it that they are not open work can be satisfactorily reformulated according to Jakob-
sold and consumed as art.
son's definition of the "poetic" function of language." Poetic lan-
guage deliberately uses terms in a way that will radically alter their
referential function (by establishing, among them, syntactic rela-
The Structure of the Public Message tionships that violate the usual laws of the code). It eliminates the
The production of effects and the popularization of consumed forms: the possibility for a univocal decoding; it gives the addressee the feeling
definition of Kitsch or of Midcult seems to oscillate between these that the current code has been violated to such an extent that it can
two fundamental poles. The first refers to a formal characteristic of no longer help. The addressee thus finds himself in the situation of
the message; the second, to its historical "destiny," to its sociologi- a cryptographer forced to decode a message whose code is un-
cal dimension. known, and who therefore has to learn the code of the message
from the message itself." At this point, the addressee will find him-
The two poles can, of course, be brought together and consid
THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE 195
self so personally involved with the message that his attention will possibilities, at least to the extent to which every work of art can
gradually move from the signifieds, to which the message was modify the cultural habits of a community and render even the
supposed to refer, to the structure itself of the signifiers, and by most "aberrant" expression acceptable. The poetic message thus
so doing will comply with the demands of the poetic message, ceases to surprise its addressee, who, given his familiarity with it,
whose very ambiguity rests on the fact that it proposes itself as can now decode it merely by applying to it its most recent interpre-
the main object of attention: "This emphasis of the message on its tation, or a formula that sums it up. Its potential for information
own self is called the poetic function..." When we speak of art as has been drained; its stylemes have been exhausted.19
an autonomous process, as form for form's sake, we are stressing a This fact should be enough to explain the phenomenon com-
particular aspect of the artistic message which communication monly known among sociologists as "the consumption of forms"
theory and structural linguistics would define as follows: "The set and to clarify the process by which a form becomes a "fetish"—
(Einstellung) toward the MESSAGE as such, focus on the message for its that is, ceases to be appreciated for what it is or can be and instead
own sake, is the POETIC function of language." lb comes to be coveted for what it represents, for the prestige it is
To this extent, ambiguity is not an accessory to the message: it is supposed to convey. To love the Mona Lisa because it represents
its fundamental feature. This is what forces the addressee to ap- Mystery, or Ambiguity, or Ineffable Grace, or the Eternal Femi-
proach the message in a different fashion, not to use it as a mere nine, or because it is a more or less "sophisticated" topic of conver-
vehicle (totally irrelevant once he has grasped the content it is car- sation ("Was it really a woman?" "Just think: one more brush stroke
rying) but rather to see it as a constant source of continually shifting and that smile would have been different!") means to accept a par-
meanings—a source whose typical structure, begging relentlessly ticular message not for itself but because of a previous decoding
to be decoded, is organized so as to coordinate all the addressee's which, having now stiffened into a formula, sticks to the message
possible decodings and force him to repeatedly question the like a tag. In this case, we are no longer considering Leonardo's
validity of their interpretations by referring them back to the painting as a message whose structure is in itself worthy of appre-
structure of the message." ciation, but as a conventional signifier whose signified is a formula
diffused by advertising.
What matters to us here is to prove that the addressees of a poetic
message find themselves in a situation of interpretive tension pre-
cisely because the ambiguity of the message, by expressing itself as We could then say that the term Kitsch can be applied to any object
a violation of the code, comes to them as a surprise. From the very that (a) appears already consumed; (b) reaches the masses, or the
start, the decoding of this sort of message appears as an adventure average customer, because it is already consumed; and (c) will
into an unusual, unpredictable organization of signs that no code quickly be reconsumed, because the use to which it has already
could have foreseen. Committed to the discovery of the new code been put by a large number of consumers has hastened its erosion.
(new because never used before, and yet connected to the common Phenomena such as the Mona Lisa embroidered on a pillow would
code, which it at once upholds and violates) and bereft of the sup- only encourage this interpretation.
port of any exterior code, the addressees have to rely on their sen-
sibility and their intelligence to construct their own hypothetical However, it is impossible to speak of the consumption of poetic
code. Their understanding of the work is a result of this interac- messages the way one would speak of the consumption of ordinary
tion." messages. A message such as "Do Not Lean Out the Window,"
commonly affixed below the windows of most European trains,
But once it is understood, introduced into a circuit of constantly has been repeated and decoded so many times that by now it has
enriched perception, the work starts to lose its interest for the ad- lost all effect. To recover some effect, the message needs to be re-
dressees, who have gradually grown used to it. The way of forming freshed, reiterated in a novel fashion—for instance, it could be ac-
that was once a violation of the code has become one of its new companied by a list of the fines incurred by its transgressors, or
THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE 197
We could then say that the term Kitsch can be applied to any object
that (a) appears already consumed; (b) reaches the masses, or the
average customer, because it is already consumed; and (c) will
quickly be reconsumed, because the use to which it has already
been put by a large number of consumers has hastened its erosion.
Phenomena such as the Mona Lisa embroidered on a pillow would
only encourage this interpretation.
sensationalized by means of an unexpected new formula, such as: often constitutes the ideal criticism. Which only proves that the
"Two months ago, Mr. Jones lost his right eye to a protruding consumption of a form is not always total and irreversible. Even
branch as he leaned out of this window." the structure that is appreciated for only one of its levels will, given
This is not what happens with the poetic message. Its ambiguity the deep kinship that connects all the stylemes to one another, re-
is a constant challenge to the absent-minded decipherer, a constant main intact in the background, like a lurking presence, the una-
invitation to cryptanalysis. No matter how popularized, con- chieved promise of a potentially fuller appreciation.
sumed, and fetishized, a poetic message will still find someone who On the other hand, if an inexact or incomplete reading impover-
will approach it with, as it were, a virginal mind, even if this means ishes the message, without however entirely obliterating it, the op-
that he or she may interpret it according to a IIC11 code that has little or
. posite can also occur: a message containing little information, read
nothing to do with the one initially intended by the author. in the light of an arbitrary code, can often appear much richer than
it was meant to be. When the Wounded Bison of Altamira is inter-
This sort of "misinterpretation" is an inevitable corollary of the
preted according to contemporary aesthetic standards, it will auto-
"fortunes" of a work of art through the centuries. The Romantic
matically acquire a wealth of intentions that for the most part are
interpretation of the marmoreal "whiteness" of Greece is a perfect
contributed by the addressee. Most archaeological finds are generally
example of a message that has been decoded according to an alien
interpreted with the help of references that were totally foreign to
code.
their authors: the missing arms and the natural erosions of time
Certainly, the reproduction of a famous classical painting bought become the signifiers of an allusive incompleteness fraught with
as a fetish, a status symbol, a cultural alibi, can work for its Kitsch meanings that have been acquired through centuries of culture but
consumer just as the Mona Lisa does on a pillow. On the other were quite unknown to the Greek artisan. And yet, as a system of
hand, it is quite possible that, in the course of his inept perusal, this elements, the object may have also implied this system of signifiers
consumer will bump into an aspect of the work—one of the infinite and of possible signifieds. Similarly, to the eyes of an intellectual in
aspects of its structural complexity—that will unexpectedly offer search of local lore, certain forms of popular entertainment can ap-
him a tenuous glimpse of a much richer sort of communication, pear charged with a Fescennine obscenity of which the comedian is
thereby rescuing the work from the basest form of consumption. quite unaware; and yet, in his desire to satisfy the presumed taste of
his audience, he might have well included in his show a series of
Giorgione's Tempesta, appreciated only for its most immediately references to archetypal behaviors that still function, and are devel-
referential aspects (without any of its iconographic connotations— oped and grasped, instinctively.
for instance, the shepherd seen as a handsome youth and not as
Mercury), Bruegel's Hay Wagon taken merely as the imitation of a
hay wagon, Manzoni's The Betrothed read only in order to know What happens to a message that is interpreted by means of an
what is going to happen to Renzo and Lucia, the Wounded Bison in overcharged code is very similar to what happens to the objet trouve
the caves of Altamira enjoyed merely as a lively sketch of a moving that the artist pulls out of context and frames as a work of art: in
animal with absolutely no reference to its magic function: all these this case, the artist selects certain aspects of the object as the pos-
are examples of a partial decoding, yet are nevertheless capable of sible signifiers of signifieds that have been elaborated by his cultural
bringing the viewer closer to the work by revealing to him, albeit tradition. By arbitrarily superimposing a code on a message that
in a rudimentary fashion, a few aspects that were part of the au- has none (a natural object, for instance) or has a different one (some
thor's intention. Throughout the centuries, the life of artworks has industrial product), the artist in fact reinvents, reformulates, that
been plagued by such misunderstandings, such misreadings, such message. The question here is whether he is arbitrarily imbuing the
crass misconceptions, indeed to the point that they almost seem to object with references culled from an extraneous tradition (that of
be the norm; whereas the exemplary decoding (exemplary not be- contemporary art, for instance, by virtue of which a stone may
cause unique, but because rich, complex, and all-encompassing) resemble a Henry Moore sculpture, and a mechanical assemblage a
THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE 199
often constitutes the ideal criticism. Which only proves that the
consumption of a form is not always total and irreversible. Even
the structure that is appreciated for only one of its levels will, given
the deep kinship that connects all the stylemes to one another, re-
main intact in the background, like a lurking presence, the una-
chieved promise of a potentially fuller appreciation.
On the other hand, if an inexact or incomplete reading impover-
ishes the message, without however entirely obliterating it, the op-
posite can also occur: a message containing little information, read
in the light of an arbitrary code, can often appear much richer than
it was meant to be. When the Wounded Bison of Altamira is inter-
preted according to contemporary aesthetic standards, it will auto-
matically acquire a wealth of intentions that for the most part are
contributed by the addressee. Most archaeological finds are generally
interpreted with the help of references that were totally foreign to
their authors: the missing arms and the natural erosions of time
become the signifiers of an allusive incompleteness fraught with
meanings that have been acquired through centuries of culture but
were quite unknown to the Greek artisan. And yet, as a system of
elements, the object may have also implied this system of signifiers
and of possible signifieds. Similarly, to the eyes of an intellectual in
search of local lore, certain forms of popular entertainment can ap-
pear charged with a Fescennine obscenity of which the comedian is
quite unaware; and yet, in his desire to satisfy the presumed taste of
his audience, he might have well included in his show a series of
references to archetypal behaviors that still function, and are devel-
oped and grasped, instinctively.
work by Jacques Lipchitz) or whether, in fact, it is contemporary work, just as it is always possible to reconnect a severed limb to a
art which, in its ways of forming, has included references to natural mutilated statue.
or industrial modes of being by integrating elements from other The successful work of art becomes a model and invites imita-
codes into its own...'" tion. This can occur in two different ways. In the first case, the
work of art offers itself as the concrete example of a particular way
The addressee's reception can thus alter the informative power of of forming which may inspire other artists to elaborate their own
the message. Because of its complex structure, the poetic message personal stylistic procedures. In the second case, the work of art
retains the power to elicit a variety of decodings. The life of mes- provides a whole generation of exploiters with the stylemes neces-
sages caught in the whirlwind of mass production and mass sary to evoke the characteristics of a particular context even after
consumption, including the life of the poetic message whenever it they have been extracted from it (if nothing else, as mere mne-
is sold as a commodity, is much more varied and unpredictable monic aids, so that when a consumer recognizes a given styleme he
than we might think in our moments of greatest discouragement. will instinctively remember its origin and attribute its former suc-
Even the most indiscriminate and naive superimposition of cess to the new context).
codes and decodings inevitably involves an exchange between Art is often much too complex for the average consumer, who
message and addressee that cannot be reduced to a simple has only so much time to devote to it. At best, he will be able to
scheme—an exchange that will remain forever open to appreciate only its most obvious features, or to interpret it accord-
investigation, exploitation, and renewal. It is here that tastes are ing to some formula, the pale ghost of a previous interpretation. So
determined and works are rediscovered, despite the thoughtless why not help him out by providing him with fragmentary stylemes
brutality of a daily consumerism that seems to reduce every message that have proved particularly effective? If Poe's "tintinnabulation of
to sheer noise and to thrive on absent-minded reception. the bells" has had a strong impact on the collective mind, then why
not employ it to advertise a detergent? No matter how successful it
is, the ad will never be considered as an aesthetic experience.
Kitsch as "Pars Pro Toto" or "Boldinism" Stravinsky's work is full of classical citations, which, openly ac-
A work of art is a system of relationships among several elements knowledged as such, become crucial elements of his compositions,
(the material elements that make up the object, the system of refer- to be reckoned with in any interpretation. This is also the case with
ences that underlies the work, the system of psychological reactions collages and "polymaterial" collage paintings, in which the various
that the work provokes and coordinates) occurring at different lev- items that are attached to the canvas are meant to refer back to their
els (the level of visual or sonic rhythms, the level of plot, the level origins.
of ideological content, and so on).21
But one of the most salient characteristics of Kitsch is its inability
The unifying characteristic of this structure, its aesthetic quality, to fully assimilate a citation into a new context. The borrowed sty-
is that it always appears organized according to a recognizable pro- leme sticks out of its new context (which is too shaky to support it,
cedure, "the way of forming" that constitutes the style of a work too diverse to integrate with it) like a sore thumb, and yet it is never
and that reflects the author's personality as well as his or her histor- acknowledged as an intentional citation. Quite the contrary, it is
ical and cultural context. 22 Once it is recognized as an organic palmed off as the real thing, an original invention. This is why I
work, the artistic structure allows for the identification of stylistic would like to define Kitsch in structural terms, as a styleme that has
elements that we shall here call stylemes. Given the unitary character been abstracted from its original context and inserted into a context
of the structure, each styleme possesses characteristics that connect whose general structure does not possess the same characters of
it to the other stylemes and to the fundamental structure—so much homogeneity and necessity as the original's, while the result is pro-
so, that a styleme is enough to suggest the structure of the entire posed as a freshly created work capable of stimulating new experi-
ences.
THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE 201
We find a typical example of this sort of procedure in the work which was not so easy to do with Renoir's impalpable women, or
of a painter justly famous with the average public of his time: with Seurat's asexual silhouettes. The average consumer consumes
Giovanni Boldini. his own lie.
Boldini was a well-known portraitist, a ladies' painter, the crea- But he consumes it as an ethical falsehood, a social falsehood, a
tor of portraits that have earned their owners prestige and pleasure. psychological falsehood, since in fact it is a structural falsehood.
In other words, Boldini's art was in demand. The beautiful woman Boldini's paintings are a perfect example of a context that is unable
(be she noble or simply a member of the haute bourgeoisie) who to assimilate the borrowed stylemes. The formal disproportion be-
commissions her portrait is not interested in acquiring a work of tween the upper and lower parts of his paintings is indisputable.
art; what she wants is a flattering reminder of the indisputable fact His women are stylematic sirens, to be consumed from the waist
that she is a beautiful woman. To achieve this end, Boldini con- up and looked at from the waist down. There is absolutely no for-
structed his paintings by the book, with the specific intent of pro- mal reason why the painter should change his style as he moves
ducing the desired effect. The naked parts of his women are painted from the face to the feet. The only possible explanation here is that
according to all the canons of a refined naturalism: pleasantly clearly the face was painted to satisfy the demands of the client and
plump, suggestively creamy, teasingly flushed. Their lips are full the clothes to satisfy the ambitions of the painter, if it weren't for
and wet, their flesh eminently touchable; the look in their eyes can the fact that even the clothes are painted to satisfy the clients, if
be sweet, daring, malicious, or dreamy, but it is always straight- nothing else by reassuring them that only a respectable face could
forward, keen, and fixed on the viewer. These women do not evoke possibly emerge from such a commendable dress.
an abstract idea of beauty, nor do they turn it into a pretext for
formal digressions; they represent specific women, to such an ex- The term Kitsch does not apply only to the kind of art that aims
tent that the viewer will end up desiring them. Cleo de Merode's at producing an immediate effect; other forms of art, and other
nudity is meant to excite; Princess Bibesco's shoulders are offered respectable activities, have a similar aim. Nor does it simply desig-
to the desire of the viewer; Marthe Regnier's sex appeal invites di- nate a formal imbalance, since that is a characteristic of most ugly
rect contact. works. Nor does it refer only to the kind of work that has bor-
rowed stylemes which have previously appeared in a different con-
text, since this can happen without lapsing into bad taste. Kitsch
But the moment Boldini moves on to paint the clothes of these refers to the kind of work that tries to justify its provocative ends
women, the moment he moves from the cleavage to the corset, and by assuming the garb of an aesthetic experience, by palming itself
from this to the folds of the skirt, and from these to the background off as art.
itself, he abandons all pictorial gastronomy to venture into the At times Kitsch can occur, as it were, unawares, as an unwitting
realm of art: the contours are no longer as precise, the colors glance
and almost pardonable error. These cases are particularly interest-
off the canvas in luminous strokes, things are blobs of paint, objects ing because they display a very obvious mechanism.
melt in the light. The lower portion of Boldini's paintings is im-
pressionistic. Here he is clearly trying to be avant-garde, quoting Let's take the example of Edmondo de Amicis, a minor Italian
from contemporary painting. If the upper part of his paintings is author who has unconsciously succeeded in turning a Manzonian
sheer gastronomy, the lower part is art. Those desirable throats and styleme to laughable effect. The "borrowed" styleme concludes a
faces rise out of a pictorial corolla that is there only to be looked at. famous passage in Manzoni's story of the nun of Monza. The pages
The client need not feel ill at ease for having been displayed as a that precede it give a lengthy account of the terrible events that have
courtesan: the rest of her figure aims only to please the spirit, to led Gertrude to embrace the wrong vocation. Having succeeded in
provoke a purer kind of appreciation, to produce a higher form of taming her rebellious nature, she has now resigned herself to being
enjoyment. Both client and viewers are reassured: not only can they a nun. Or so the reader thinks, until suddenly Egidio makes his
experience art, but they can also respond to it with their senses, unexpected, and fatal, appearance on the scene: "One of his win-
THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE 203
The term Kitsch does not apply only to the kind of art that aims
at producing an immediate effect; other forms of art, and other
respectable activities, have a similar aim. Nor does it simply desig-
nate a formal imbalance, since that is a characteristic of most ugly
works. Nor does it refer only to the kind of work that has bor-
rowed stylemes which have previously appeared in a different con-
text, since this can happen without lapsing into bad taste. Kitsch
refers to the kind of work that tries to justify its provocative ends
by assuming the garb of an aesthetic experience, by palming itself
off as art.
dows overlooked a small courtyard which formed part of At this point, as may well be expected, the headmaster turns to
Gertrude's quarters. Noticing her once or twice as she passed young Franti and tells him "with earth-shaking vehemence, 'Franti,
through the courtyard, or strolled idly round it, he found the you are killing your mother!' Everybody turned to look at Franti.
difficulty and the wickedness of the enterprise an attraction And that rascal smiled." The styleme that concludes this passage is
rather than a deterrent and plucked up his courage to speak to her. The very similar to that used by Manzoni. "E quell'infame rispose":
poor wretch answered."23 Pages and pages of criticism have been here, too, we have an adjectival noun as the subject and a verb in
devoted to the lapidary efficacy of the last sentence: "La the past tense. But this is as far as the similarity goes. Given the
sventurata rispose." The sentence is extremely simple—three context in which it appears, this phrase has an altogether different
words, an article, an adjectival noun, and a verb —and yet, for all import. First of all, it occurs precisely at the moment the reader is
its concision, it manages to tell readers all they need to know expecting a coup de theatre, both to put an end to the scene and to
about Gertrude's response, the complexity of her character, and provide some relief to his overwrought emotions. Second, the ad-
the author's own moral and emotional response to it. The word
"sventurata" is at once a condemnation and an apology; in its role jectival noun that represents the subject is so loaded with condem-
as subject of the sentence, it defines both the character and her nation that it becomes almost comic when compared to the boy's
entire life, past, present, and future. The verb is anything but actual misdeeds. And third, the verb "smiled" is not nearly so allu-
dramatic: "rispose"—"answered." It informs us generally about sive and ambiguous as Manzoni's "rispose." Franti's smile, at this
her reaction without telling us anything about the tenor of her particular point, is the evidence of his cruelty. It says everything
answer or its intensity. But this is precisely the reason the sentence there is to say and as definitely as it could be said. This sentence,
is so powerful, so expressive in its suggestion of the abysses of unlike Manzoni's, does not lead anywhere. This is the way melo-
wickedness that that simple gesture implies and discloses—the drama ends, and shows how a successful styleme can be wasted and
gesture of a nun who, we now realize, was only waiting, albeit corrupted into Kitsch. The only mitigating circumstance in De
unconsciously, for a spark to explode into rebellion. Amicis's case is that he may have done it unintentionally.
When the intention is obvious, then we have a flagrant example
of Kitsch, the kind of Kitsch that is typical of Midcult. Kitsch is
The sentence occurs at the right moment, to conclude a lengthy Cubism applied to sacred art, as if a geometric Madonna were more
accumulation of details with a funereal note that strikes us as an appealing to modern taste than its Renaissance counterpart. Kitsch
epitaph. A marvelous example of stylistic economy. Was Edmondo is the winged figure that adorns the hood of a Rolls Royce, a Hel-
De Amicis aware of it while he was writing one of the most mem- lenistic touch meant to evoke the prestige of an object that should
orable pages of his book Cuore? Maybe not, but the analogy is there instead obey more honest aerodynamic and utilitarian criteria.
and deserves some attention. Franti, the bad boy who has been ex- Kitsch is the Volkswagen beetle that flaunts the hood of a Rolls
pelled from school. returns to his classroom accompanied by his Royce or the stripes of a swanky sports car. Kitsch is the transistor
mother. The headmaster does not send him away because he feels radio with an inordinately long antenna, quite useless to its recep-
sorry for the woman. She's disheveled, bedraggled, sopping wet. tion but necessary to its prestige. Kitsch is the sofa with a chintz
But obviously the author does not think these details are sufficient cover reproducing Van Gogh's Sunflowers, a tea set bearing the ef-
to produce the desired effect. So he has the poor woman launch figy of Botticelli's Venus, a bar with decor a la Kandinsky.
into a heart-rending speech, interspersed with loud sobs and excla-
mation points, in which she tells the headmaster her sad story—
violent husband and all. As if this were still not enough, fearing
that the reader may still fail to get the picture, the author then wal- The Malayan Leopard
lows in a short description of the woman's exit: she is pale and Between the poetic message that invites the reader to enjoy the
bowed, her tattered shawl drags on the floor, her head trembles, pleasure of discovery and the Kitsch object that imitates the discov-
she can be heard coughing all the way down the stairs.
THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE 205
cry of pleasure, there arc several other kinds of messages, from the To further clarify these distinctions, let's look at four examples
ones intended for mass consumption—with no artistic aims or pre- from literature. In the first, Marcel Proust describes a woman, Al-
sumptions—to artisanal messages which are meant to stimulate bertine, and the impression she makes on the narrator, Marcel, the
various kinds of experiences and aesthetic emotions and which, in first time he sees her. Proust is not trying to whet the appetite of his
order to attain their ends, borrow methods and stylemes from reader; rather, he is looking for a new way to broach an old situa-
avant-garde art and then insert them, though without vulgarizing tion. The subject is banal (the meeting between a man and a woman
them, into a mixed context aimed at producing various effects as and the man's response to it), but Proust wants to elaborate a new
well as at creating an interpretive experience. Because of this double approach to banal events.
function, such a message can often acquire a particular structure
and fulfill a useful task. Between this kind of message and a real
poetic message there is the same difference that Elio Vittorini finds To begin with, he refuses to stake everything on a description of
between "consumer goods" and "means of production." But often Albertine. Instead, he shows her to us little by little, not as an indi-
a message that aspires to a poetic function, though it may satisfy vidual but rather as part of an indivisible whole, a group of girls
the fundamental conditions of this type of communication, reveals whose features, smiles, and gestures keeps fusing into a continuous
a certain imbalance, some structural instability, whereas the mes- stream of images. To reinforce this sense of fluidity, he uses an im-
sage that aims solely at honestly pleasing its public, at being a mar- pressionistic style in which, even when he describes "un ovale
ketable commodity, often achieves a nearly perfect balance. This blanc" ("a pallid oval"), "des yeux noirs" ("black eyes"), "des yeux
indicates that, in the first case, despite the clarity of its intentions. verts" ("green eyes"), the somatic information loses all power of
the work is a failure, or at least only a partial success, whereas in sensual evocation to become one note in a chord (and, in fact, he
the second case we have such a successful commodity that the con- sees the group of girls as an ensemble "confus comme une musique
sumer can even appreciate the perfection of its structure; the on je n'aurais pas su isoler et reconnaitre au moment de leur passage
commodity has managed to revitalize old stylemes in an effective les phrases. distinguees mais oubliees aussitOt apres" ("confused as
manner. In this instance, we have a singular phenomenon of a piece of music in which I should not have been able to isolate and
recovery whereby a commodity becomes a real work of art identify at the moment of their passage the successive phrases, no
which can propose. for the first time in a stimulating fashion, sooner distinguished than forgotten"). It is difficult to cite passages
certain ways of forming that others had unsuccessfully tried from this description precisely because it stretches over a number
before. Thus, we have a dialectic between a kind of art that aims of pages and cannot be reduced to a nucleus of representations; it
at producing original experiences and another kind that aims at slowly brings us to recognize Albertine, but always with the feeling
the establishment of acquired procedures; in this dialectic it is that our attention, as well as that of the author, might have missed
often the latter that fulfills the fundamental conditions of a poetic its real aim. The reader fends his way through the images as one
message, whereas the former is only a courageous attempt at would through a jungle; he is not as struck by the "joues bouffies et
fulfillment. roses," ("plump and rosy cheeks") and the "teint bruni" ("dark
complexion") as he is surprised at his inability to distinguish even
one desirable face among the girls, who "mettaient entre leurs
Of course, each case deserves a thorough critical investigation. corps independants et separes, tandis qu'ils avancaient lentement,
Once again, aesthetic thought can define the optimal conditions for une liaison invisible, mais harmonieuse comme une mźme ombre
a communicative experience but cannot judge particular cases. chaude, une méme atmosphere. faisant d'eux un tout aussi homo-
All I wanted to do here, however, was stress the gradations gene en ses parties qu'il etait different de la foule au milieu de la-
which, within the same circuit of cultural consumption, allow us quelle se deroulait lentement leur cortege" ("established between
to distinguish between works of discovery, works of mediation, their independent and separate bodies, as slowly they advanced, a
commodities, and pseudo-artworks—in other words, between bond invisible but harmonious, like a single warm shadow, a single
avant-garde culture, Masscult, Midcult, and Kitsch.
THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE 207
atmosphere, making of them a whole as homogeneous in its parts hand would have sufficed to encircle it. Her complexion was as
as it was different from the crowd through which their procession rosy and fresh as that of a freshly bloomed flower. Her little
gradually wound"). head was admirable, her eyes were as blue as sea water, her
Of course, if we chose to analyze all the expressions one by one, forehead was incomparably pure and, below this, stood out the
we would find all the elements necessary to make up a fragment of sharp outline of two gently arched brows that almost touched.
Kitsch, but Proust's adjectives are never aimed at a precise object, A blond mane fell, in picturesque disorder, like a rain of
and even less at exciting a precise emotion; nor do they create a gold, over the white corset that covered her breasts.
vague aura of lyricism, because, though the reader is invited to At the sight of that woman, who looked so much like a
untangle the web of impressions that the passage offers him, he is child, the pirate was shaken by a shiver that went straight to the
also constantly expected to dominate these impressions, to be at bottom of his soul.
once receptive and critical, and never to abandon himself to the
personal feelings evoked by the context, since they must remain, No need to comment on this passage: all the mechanisms neces-
above all, the feeling of the context. At a particular moment, sary to produce an immediate effect arc there, both in the descrip-
Marcel is struck by the brown eyes of one of the girls, by the tion of Marianna and in the reaction of Sandokan. On the other
"rayon noir" ("dark ray") that strikes him and troubles him. But hand, this is sheer artisanship with no artistic pretensions; Emilio
the impression is immediately countered by a reflection: "Si Salgari never thought he was producing art.' All he wanted to do
nous pensions que les yeux d'une telle fille ne sont qu'une brillante was provide his public with a means of escape, with an attractive
rondelle de mica, nous ne serions pas avides de connaitre et d'unir a dream. His prose needn't be interpreted; it only has to be read. His
nous sa vie" ("If we thought that the eyes of a girl like that were merely work is an honest expression of Masscult, too honest to be consid-
two glittering sequins of mica, we should not be athirst to know her ered Kitsch. We shall let the pedagogues determine whether the
and to unite her life to ours"). Just a momentary halt, and then emotions it fosters are good or bad for our youth, or whether its
the discourse continues, no longer to refuse the emotion but style is appropriate for a respectable high school canon—which
rather to comment on it, to delve into it. Our reading is never generally seems to lean either toward the classics or toward sheer
allowed to follow a single thread. The passage refuses to hypnotize us. Kitsch.
Its suggestiveness is not meant to fascinate us but rather to spur
Let's now take the case of an author with both taste and culture
us into interpretive activity."
who, out of choice or vocation, decides to provide his public with a
product that is at once dignified but accessible, able to produce an effect
But if, instead of being described by Marcel, the meeting were and yet above the level of Masscult. His approach to the same situation
described by an honest artisan for a public eager to be charmed, (a meeting between a man and a woman) will be rather
troubled, soothed, and hypnotized, we would have something ambivalent: on the one hand, he will want to create a character (the
quite different. This is what happens to Sandokan, the Tiger of woman) capable of stirring the emotions and the fantasy of his
Malaya, when, in Emilio Salgari's The Tigers of Monpracem, he first readers; on the other, a sense of propriety will bid him control his
meets Marianna Guillonk, better known as the Pearl of Labuan: words by creating a certain amount of critical distance. This is
probably how he would describe the meeting between Sandokan
He had barely uttered these words than the Lord was back in and Marianna:
the room. He was not alone. Behind him, barely touching the
rug, advanced a splendid creature, at whose sight Sandokan The second lasted five minutes; then the door opened and in
was unable to repress an exclamation of surprise and admira- came Marianna. The first impression was of dazed surprise.
tion. The Guillonk family stood still, their breath taken away; San-
She was a girl of sixteen or seventeen, small but slender and dokan could even feel the veins pulsing in his temples. Under
elegant, with a superb build, and a waist so slim that a single
THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE 209
Let's now take the case of an author with both taste and culture
who, out of choice or vocation, decides to provide his public with a
product that is at once dignified but accessible, able to produce an effect
and yet above the level of Masscult. His approach to the same situation
(a meeting between a man and a woman) will be rather
ambivalent: on the one hand, he will want to create a character (the
woman) capable of stirring the emotions and the fantasy of his
readers; on the other, a sense of propriety will bid him control his
words by creating a certain amount of critical distance. This is
probably how he would describe the meeting between Sandokan
and Marianna:
The second lasted five minutes; then the door opened and in
came Marianna. The first impression was of dazed surprise.
The Guillonk family stood still, their breath taken away; San-
dokan could even feel the veins pulsing in his temples. Under
210 THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE 211
the first shock from hrr beauty, the men were incapable of able to tackle a series of sociopolitical issues, which, despite their
no-tieing or analyzing its defects, which were numerous; notoriety, had never reached such a wide readership in such a clear
there were to be many forever incapable of this critical form.
appraisal. The Leopard is an excellent commodity but not quite a product
She was tall and well made, on an ample scale. Her skin of Kitsch. No cross-contamination is ever quite so successful as
looked as if it had the flavor of fresh cream, which it resembled; Kitsch, and the thirst for prestige is much more obvious. The fol-
her childlike mouth, that of strawberries. Under a mass of ra- lowing passage is a perfect example of this last category, the basest.
ven hair, curling in gentle waves, her green eyes gleamed mo- Ray Bradbury, famous among the mid-intelligentsia for being
tionless as those of statues, and like them a little cruel. She was the only science-fiction author to have produced literary works
moving slowly, making her wide white skirt rotate around her, (which in a sense is true, since instead of writing honest sci-fi sto-
and emanating from her whole person was the invincible calm ries he is always trying to give them the appearance of art by using
of a woman sure of her beauty. an explicitly "lyrical" style), once wrote a novella for Playboy. As
everybody knows, Playboy is a magazine that has made its fortune
by publishing glossy photos of nude women in more or less entic-
This gastronomic description reveals greater stylistic economy and ing postures. Its emphasis is on the excellence of the product it
a better sense of rhythm, but despite the unquestionable concinnitas offers, not on its artistic value—an all too common alibi of porno-
of the passage, absent from the previous one, the communicative graphic publications. To this extent, Playboy is not a Kitsch prod-
procedure is very similar to that used by Salgari. However, the au- uct. Unfortunately, however, Playboy has cultural aspirations. Its
thorial interference in the middle of the passage employs the same aim is to be the New Yorker of libertines and good-timers, and to
styleme used by Proust in the description of Albertine's eyes. It this end it invites the collaboration of famous authors who, in the
likewise calls into question the effect the author has just suggested. name of tolerance and humor, seldom disdain the improbable com-
But Proust wouldn't have deigned to write anything so direct and bination with the rest of the magazine. Ironically, although Playboy
unequivocal, and Salgari would have never been able to moderate seeks this collaboration in order to raise its status and to allay the
his words so cleverly. Giuseppe Tomasi di Lampedusa fits perfectly uneasy conscience of some of its readers by providing them with a
between the two. The quoted excerpt is in fact a passage from The cultural alibi ("but it has very good articles"), this is precisely what
Leopard, in which I have replaced the names of Angelica, the Sali- turns it, as well as the hapless tale of the hapless contributor, into
nas, and Tancredi with names borrowed from Salgari's book. An- Kitsch. Of course, this is not exactly what happened to Ray Brad-
gelica's appearance at Donnafugata is structured like the perfect bury, since he was already Kitsch to begin with.
Midcult product, in which, however, the contamination between
Masscult stylemes and Hicult allusions does not degenerate into a
grotesque pastiche. This passage is not engaged in discovery, as Bradbury's novella likewise tells of a meeting between two
Proust's was, but is nevertheless a perfect example of dignified, people. Not between a man and a woman, however, since that sit-
well-balanced prose, perfectly suited to the edification of our uation is obviously much too banal for an author who's so keen on
youth. The borrowed styleme is used with discretion. The result is producing "art." So in his story In a Season of Calm Weather, Brad-
a commodity that will please without exciting, and that will pro- bury tells us of the meeting, and the ensuing passion, between a
voke a certain kind of critical participation without entirely polar- man and a work of art. Bradbury's hero is an American who de-
izing the attention of the reader onto the structure of the message. cides to spend his summer near Vallauris, on the French Riviera, in
Obviously, the passage is not the entire book, but it is an eloquent order to be close to his idol: Picasso. His devoted wife accompanies
sample of it. The success of this work is perfectly explained by him. Why Picasso? Because Picasso means art, modernity, and
these structural characteristics, and yet its success would not be prestige. Because Picasso is very widely known, and because his
enough to define it as either a product of Midcult or of Kitsch. This work, totally fetishized, no longer needs to be interpreted. Picasso
work is a commodity that also has the advantage of having been is the perfect choice.
THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE 211
One evening, toward sunset, our hero is dreamily strolling along more facile and decorative period of his oeuvre—which, of course,
a deserted shore, when, at some distance, he notices a small man only serves to make us (or those of us who hadn't yet done so)
busy drawing figures on the sand with a stick. Needless to say, it is realize that even Picasso may not have been totally impervious to
Picasso. But our hero does not realize it until, having walked closer, Kitsch. On the one hand, Bradbury interprets Picasso by means of
he can see the figures drawn on the sand. Spellbound, he watches the purest of codes (for the most part reduced to the cult of the
the little man draw He doesn't say a word, doesn't even dare arabesque and a series of facile connections between stereotyped
breathe lest the vision vanish. It does, eventually, when, having figures and trite emotions); on the other, he constructs his passage
finished his drawing, Picasso walks away. The lover wants to keep by clumsily stitching together a number of stylemes borrowed
the work, but the tide is rising. from the decadents (in it, one can hear faint echoes of Pater, Wilde,
Since a summary cannot possibly do justice to the style of the the earliest epiphanic Joyce—the bird girl!—and so on) simply in
story, this is what our hero sees as he watches the little old man order to accumulate effects. And yet, the main intention behind this
draw on the sand: message is self-reflexive: the reader is supposed to react to its style,
to be awed by an author "who can write so well."
For there on the flat shore were pictures of Grecian lions and To the Midcult reader, the overall impression will be one of "in-
Mediterranean goats and maidens with flesh of sand like pow- tense lyrical tension." In other words, the story is not only emi-
dered gold and satyrs piping on hand-carved horns and children nently comestible but also quite beautiful; more than that, it suc-
dancing, strewing flowers along and along the beach with ceeds in conveying a sense of Beauty. The difference between this
lambs gamboling after and musicians skipping to their harps kind of beauty and that of the nudes that surround it, in Playboy, is
and lyres, and unicorns racing youths toward distant meadows, minimal but significant: whereas the nudes bluntly refer to a reality
woodlands, ruined temples and volcanos. Along the shore in that not only exists but may also have a telephone number, Brad-
a never-broken line, the hand, the wooden stylus of this man bury's story tries to cloak its true nature behind the worn veil of
bent down in fever and raining perspiration, scribbled, rib- "art." Its very hypocrisy is enough to characterize Bradbury's piece
boned, looped around over and up, across, in, out, stitched, as Kitsch.
whispered, stayed, then hurried on as if this traveling bacchanal
must flourish to its end before the sun was put out by the sea.
Twenty, thirty yards or more the nymphs and driads and sum-
mer founts sprung up in unraveled hieroglyph. And the sand, Conclusion
in the dying light, was the color of molten copper on which Thus, we have looked at all the possibilities and found a definition
was now slashed a message that any man in any time might read for Kitsch within the context of aesthetics.
and savor down the years. Everything whirled and poised in its
Yet let's assume that a reader, excited by Bradbury's novella,
own wind and gravity. Now wine was being crushed from
would make it his duty to discover Picasso and, confronted for the
under the grape-blooded feet of dancing vintners' daughters,
first time with one of the master's works, would experience some-
now steaming seas gave birth to coin-sheathed monsters while
thing so personal as to quite obliterate the initial literary stimulus,
flowered kites strewed scent on blowing clouds . . . now ..
something that would draw him into the world of the painting and
now . . . now . . compel him to understand the wa y in which it was formed.
The artist stopped. Wouldn't this be enough to make us wary of all the theoretical def-
initions concerning good and bad taste?
Here again, there's no need for comment. The reader is clearly The ways of God are infinite, as some would say, forgetting that
told what he must see and what he must appreciate—and how—in even illnesses can bring us close to God. But the duty of a doctor is
Picasso's work. Better yet, the passage gives him a quintessence, a to diagnose and cure them.
summary, a concentrate of Picasso's entire oeuvre, or rather, of the
THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE 213
Conclusion
Thus, we have looked at all the possibilities and found a definition
for Kitsch within the context of aesthetics.
Yet let's assume that a reader, excited by Bradbury's novella,
would make it his duty to discover Picasso and, confronted for the
first time with one of the master's works, would experience some-
thing so personal as to quite obliterate the initial literary stimulus,
something that would draw him into the world of the painting and
compel him to understand the wa y in which it was formed.
Wouldn't this be enough to make us wary of all the theoretical def-
initions concerning good and bad taste?
The ways of God are infinite, as some would say, forgetting that
even illnesses can bring us close to God. But the duty of a doctor is
to diagnose and cure them.
214 THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE 215
We should suspect, a priori, every investigation of mass media inspired by syncopation is anything more than a superficial flirta-
that tries to reach a definitive conclusion. Within the tion. But this is an altogether different question. If we are ready to
anthropological situation of mass culture anything can happen, accept a situation in which this sort of music is capable of eliciting a
things can be turned upside down in no time; reception can particular kind of physiological and emotional excitement, then
change the physiognomy of transmission, and vice versa. At we have to admit that Gershwin's music fulfills its task both taste-
times, Kitsch is on the side of the message. at times on the side of fully and appropriately.
the receiver's intention, and, more often than not, on that of the
sender who tries to palm his product off for something it is not. Similarly, the above quoted passage from The Leopard, very hon-
Kitsch is Addinsell's Warsaw Concerto, with its accumulation of est in its intention to entertain its public, may seem exceedingly
pathetic effects and imitative suggestions ("Hear that? Those are pretentious when it is proposed as a poetic message, as the original
planes dropping bombs"), and its heavy-handed use of Chopin; revelation of certain aspects of reality that had presumably re-
just as Kitsch is the appreciation of this particular musical mained unexplored until its appearance. But in this case, the re-
passage as described in Malaparte's La pelle (The skin). The sponsibility of having produced Kitsch is not so much the author's
notes of this fragment arc heard during a reunion of British as the reader's—or the critic's, if he is the one who has decoded the
soldiers attended by the author, who at first thinks they are part of message in such a way as to present the mouth with the taste of
a Chopin concerto. He is set straight by one of the officers who, strawberries, the eyes as green as those of statues, and the nocturnal
with great satisfaction, informs him that "Addinsel is our Chopin." hue of the hair as the stylemes of a message whose worth resides in
In this sense, all the music known as "rhythmic-symphonic," the originality of its vision.
because of the way in which it tries to amalgamate dance music Given the spread of mass culture, it would be impossible to say
with the daring of jazz and the dignity of classical symphonies, that this sequence of mediations and loans is a one-way street:
produces effects similar to those of Addinsel's piece. But when the Kitsch is not the only borrower. Today, it is often avant-garde cul-
composer has a certain knack, he may be able to create a product ture which, reacting against the density and the scope of mass cul-
with a structure so particular as to completely avoid all suspicion ture, borrows its own stylemes from Kitsch. This is what Pop Art
of Kitsch and become an acceptable new product, the pleasant does when it chooses the most vulgar and pretentious graphic sym-
popularization of a higher musical universe. Gershwin's Rhapsody bols of advertising and turns them into the objects of morbid and
in Blue is such a piece of music because of the originality of its ironic attention by blowing them up out of all proportion and
composition and the freshness with which it translates popular hanging them on the walls of a museum. This is the avant-garde's
American material into unexpectedly new forms. But the moment revenge on Kitsch, as well as a lesson for it, because in most cases
this composition is played in a traditional concert hall, by a conduc- the avant-garde artist shows the producer of Kitsch how to insert
tor in tails, for the kind of audience one commonly finds at a clas- an extraneous styleme into a new context without abandoning
sical concert, it inevitably becomes Kitsch because it tries to stimu- good taste. Objectivized by a painter, on a canvas, both the Coca-
late reactions that are not suited to either its intentions or its Cola trademark and a comic strip fragment acquire a meaning they
capacities. It is decoded according to an alien code. did not previously have.27
But even here, Kitsch does not waste any time taking its revenge
Gershwin's dance music, in contrast, will never be Kitsch for the on the avant-garde, by borrowing its procedures and its stylemes
very simple reason that it has always done, and still does, what it for its ads, where once again the only thing that matters is the pro-
set out to do, and does it to perfection. Gershwin never saw his duction of an effect and the display of a higher level of taste. And
Lady Be Good as anything but a means of escape, a stimulus to this is only one episode in a phenomenon that is typical of every
dance, and that is precisely why he wrote it and how he sold it. At modern industrial society, of the rapid succession of standards
which point one may legitimately wonder whether this kind of es- whereby even in the field of taste every novelty is always the source
cape is conducive to a balanced life, or whether the kind of love of a future bad habit.
THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE 215
But even here, Kitsch does not waste any time taking its revenge
on the avant-garde, by borrowing its procedures and its stylemes
for its ads, where once again the only thing that matters is the pro-
duction of an effect and the display of a higher level of taste. And
this is only one episode in a phenomenon that is typical of every
modern industrial society, of the rapid succession of standards
whereby even in the field of taste every novelty is always the source
of a future bad habit.
216 THE STRUCTURE OF BAD TASTE
general morphology. Here (within serial thought) there are no pear unstructured), whereas structuralist thought deals with struc-
preconstituted scales—that is, no general structures within tural (structurales) laws. As we shall see, they are two fairly distinct
which a particular thought could inscribe itself. A composer's areas of research, even though in the end the results of one must be
thought, operating in accordance with a particular t ranslated into the other's terms. But the superficial similarity of
methodology, creates the objects it needs and the form the two terms has somewhat confused matters, so that the structur-
necessary for their organization each time it has occasion to ing activities of the avant-garde have often been related to the inves-
express itself. Classical tonal thought is based on a world tigation of structures proper to structuralism. Several rash critics
defined by gravitation and attraction; serial thought, on a (that is, most cultivated readers and all uninformed ones) have even
world that is perpetually expanding.' gone so far as to consider structuralism as the critical or methodo-
logical aspect of the artistic activity of the avant-garde. This was
This hypothesis of an oriented production of open possibilities, often just naive sophistry: since structuralism is an avant-garde
of an incitement to experience choice, of a constant questioning of method, then it must be the method of the avant-garde. At other
any established grammar, is the basis of any theory of the "open times, however, it was the result of a hasty identification that led
work," in music as well as in every other artistic genre. The theory some to apply structuralist categories to avant-garde operations,
of the open work is none other than a poetics of serial thought. with highly questionable results.
Serial thought aims at the production of a structure that is at once The aim of this chapter is not to separate the area of structuralist
open and polyvalent, in music as well as in painting, in the novel as
interests from that of the avant-garde's artistic effort, but rather to
well as in poetry and theater. But the very notion of "open work,"
the moment it is translated (reasonably, if daringly, as "open struc- distinguish their respective responsibilities by showing how they
ture") entails a problem: Can the instruments provided by structur- involve two different levels of experience. Only after such a clarifi-
alism for the analysis of open structures coexist with the notions of cation will it be possible to envision a language common to both
polyvalence and seriality? In other words, can one conceive of a practices.
series in structural terms? Is there homogeneity between series and On the other hand, there were reasons for such a misunderstand-
structure? ing, which may be why, in his introduction to The Raw and the
Cooked, Levi-Strauss insists on reminding us that serial thought is a
contemporary cultural current that must be carefully distinguished
It is significant that, in his text, Levi-Strauss speaks of "pens&
from structuralism precisely because they have so many features in
structurale" and not of "pens& structurelle," even though French
common.
would have allowed him to use either term. Jean Pouillon, in one of
his essays, deals with this semantic nuance and, by so doing, helps
us understand how an open work may have nothing to do with the Let's examine, then, how series and structure differ from each
structuralist problematic, and yet refer to it on another level. other, how they oppose each other, whether their opposition is to-
tal or only partial, and whether they should see in each other a
In his essay, Pouillon relates the adjective structure( to the real con- demonstration of their respective limitations and an indication of
figuration of an object as revealed by analysis, and the adjective other possible directions.
structural to the laws that uniformly govern the various occurrences What are the most important concepts introduced by structural-
of structured objects. "A relation is structurelle when it plays a deter- ist methods, following the models proposed by linguistics and,
mining role within a given organization, and structurale when it can
more generally, by communication theory?
manifest itself in several different but equally determining ways
within numerous systems."' This should make the difference be- (i) The code-message relation. Communication occurs to the extent
tween structural and structure/ quite clear: serial thought produces open- to which a given message is decoded according to a preestablished
structured (structurelles) realities (even when these realities ap code shared by both the addresser and the addressee.
SERIES AND STRUCTURE 219
Let's examine, then, how series and structure differ from each
other, how they oppose each other, whether their opposition is to-
tal or only partial, and whether they should see in each other a
demonstration of their respective limitations and an indication of
other possible directions.
What are the most important concepts introduced by structural-
ist methods, following the models proposed by linguistics and,
more generally, by communication theory?
(i) The code-message relation. Communication occurs to the extent
to which a given message is decoded according to a preestablished
code shared by both the addresser and the addressee.
220 SERIES AND STRUCTURE SERIES AND STRUCTURE 221
forces, modifies, or contradicts this significance. It is the same scale. According to Schonberg's significant formula, these
thing in painting, where contrasts of form and color arc per- notes are to be defined solely by "the total system of relations of
ceived as distinctive features simultaneously dependent on two the sounds with one another." However, the lessons of structural
systems: first, a system of intellectual significances, the heritage linguistics should make it possible to overcome the false
of common experience and the result of the subdivision and opposition between Rameau's objectivism and the convention-
organization of sense experience into objects; second, a system alism of modern theorists. As a result of the selection made in
of plastic values which only becomes significant through mod- the sound continuum by each type of scale, hierarchical rela-
ulating the other and becoming incorporated with it. Two artic- tions arc established among the notes. These relations are not
ulated mechanisms mesh to form a third, which combines the dictated by nature, since the physical properties of any musical
properties of both. scale considerably exceed in number and complexity those se-
It can thus be understood why abstract painting and more lected by each system for the establishment of its distinctive
generally all schools of painters claiming to be nonfigurative features. It is nevertheless true that, like any phonological system,
lose the power to signify: they abandon the primary level of all modal or tonal (or even polytonal or atonal) systems depend
articulation and assert their intention of surviving on the sec- on physical and physiological properties, selecting some
ondary one alone. from among the infinite number no doubt available, and
exploiting the contrasts and combinations of which they are
Levi-Strauss further elaborates his argument (already sketched in capable in order to evolve a code that serves to distinguish dif-
his Entre:lens, as well as in another structuralist text about serial ferent meanings. Music, then, just as much as painting, sup-
music, Nicolas Ruwet's essay on Henri Pousseur),' by lingering on poses a natural organization of sense experience; but it does not
a few subtle distinctions. Even Chinese calligraphic painting seems necessarily accept this organization passively.
to rest on forms that are merely sensible units belonging to the
second level of articulation (plastic occurrences, just as phonemes At this point, Levi-Strauss begins to define the difference be-
are auditory occurrences devoid of all meaning). But in Chinese tween concrete music and serial music. The very existence of con-
calligraphic painting, these units, which seem to be secondary ar- crete music involves a paradox: if such music retained the repre-
ticulations, rest on a preexisting level of articulation, a system of sentative value of the noises it uses, it would have at its disposal a
signs endowed with precise meanings that are not completely oblit- primary articulation, but since it instead alters those noises in order
erated by plastic articulation. to turn them into pseudo-sounds, it automatically loses that pri-
mary level which would have provided a basis for a secondary artic-
The example of calligraphic painting is useful because it allows ulation.
the argument to shift back from nonrepresentational painting to
music; indeed, music, by virtue of its purely sonorous existence, Serial music, in contrast, elaborates sounds according to a so-
hearkens back to a primary level of articulation created by cul- phisticated grammar and syntax that situate it within the traditional
ture—that is, the system of musical sounds. bounds of classical music. Nevertheless, it also lapses into a number
of contradictions shared by abstract painting and concrete music.
This comparison forces Levi-Strauss to take a stance on another "The serial approach, by taking to its logical conclusion that
fundamental issue that will become the key to the rest of the whittling down of the individual particularities of tones which be-
argument: gins with the adoption of the tempered scale, seems to tolerate only
a very slight degree of organization of the tones." Or, to use Bou-
This is an essential point, because contemporary musical lez's words, serial thought creates the objects it needs and the form
thought, either formally or tacitly, rejects the hypothesis of the necessary for their organization each time it has occasion to express
existence of some natural foundation that would objectively itself. To put it somewhat differently, it abandons the relations that
justify the stipulated system of relations among the notes of the constitute the sounds of the tonal scale, relations that, as Levi-
SERIES AND STRUCTURE 223
endowed with meaning, and there are phonemes, and that's that—
no other solution is possible). Clearly, the argument could be
turned around as follows: verbal language is only one form of lan-
guage, since there are other forms (such as musical language) that
are based on other systems of articulation—systems that are freer
and capable of different kinds of organization. Pierre Schaeffer an-
swers this argument indirectly but with remarkable acumen in his
Traite des objets musicaux, when he remarks how, in the Klangfarben-
melodie, the optional variant of a previous system, timbre, can as-
sume the function of a phoneme—that is, the function of a distinc-
tive feature, of a significant opposition.'
The second argument of the passage goes as follows: the strict
and unmodifiable relation between the two levels of articulation
is based on a few constants of communication, a few a priori
forms of communication—what elsewhere Levi-Strauss terms
"L'Esprit," which, in the final analysis, is none other than the
Structure as Ur-code. At this point, the only possible answer
(which would swing the argument away from what threatens to
become structural metaphysics and back within the context of a
structuralist method) is this: if the idea of a Code determining all
Codes is valid, there is no obvious reason why this should be so
hastily identified with one of its historical messages—that is, the
system of attractions resting on the principle of tonality—or why
the historical existence of such a system should force one to recog-
nize within its parameters the parameters of all possible musical
communication.
But Levi-Strauss does not hesitate to make this leap: music and
mythology are both cultural forms that appeal to mental structures
shared by different listeners. And before we have time to agree with
this general principle, we are once again face to face with an
arbitrary extrapolation: these shared common structures are the
same ones that are challenged by serial thought—that is, the
structures of the tonal system (as well as of representational
painting). Once he has completed this last identification. Levi-
Strauss can draw his final deduction: the fact that structural
thought recognizes common mental structures means that it is
aware of the series of determinations that act upon the mind, and
hence that it is materialistic. Conversely. the fact that serial thought
wants to get rid of the tonal system (which represents common
mental structures) means chat it sets itself up as a conscious
product of the mind and an assertion of its liberty, and therefore that
it is idealistic. Conclusion:
Of Generative Structures
For a proper understanding of Levi-Strauss's arguments and of all
their emotional recesses, we must remember how linguistics and
ethnological structuralism on one side, and contemporary music
on the other, have come to view the question of the universality and
determinativeness of the laws of communication.
After centuries of naĜve belief in the natural foundations of the
SERIES AND STRUCTURE 227
For the time being, however, let's accept the premises of ontolog-
228 SERIES AND STRUCTURE
one of those who refused to look into Galileo's telescope for fear
that it would confuse their ideas, since the Ptolemaic theory of
planetary spheres was supposed to constitute the only natural basis
for interplanetary "communication." When it clings to views such
as these (and only then), Levi-Strauss's structuralism (and only Levi-
Strauss's) reveals one of its most dangerously conservative aspects.
A structuralist methodology that wants to uncover the atemporal
abscissae beneath the historical process must wait for particular
historical movements to verify whether the structures it has
already posited can also explain the present. And particularly so
when (and structuralism seems to have become collectively con-
scious of this tendency) those universal structures are not the result of
a total analysis of particular instances, but have been posited as a
theoretical model, an imaginary construction that will have to ex-
plain all the instances to come. It would be quite naĜve to refuse a
priori all right to life to new modes of communication just because
they structure themselves in ways that have not been predicted by
theory—a theory that, moreover, was elaborated long before these
modes had begun to take shape. Of course, these new modes may
well be noncommunicative; on the other hand, it would be wrong
not to consider, even if only as a hypothesis, that the theory may
not be comprehensive enough. In this case, serialism would call
into question every extremely rigid interpretation of the double
articulation of linguistic systems, or the belief that all systems of
communication are linguistic, or the assumption that all art must
communicate.
Yet one should not underrate the importance. within a serial per-
spective—a perspective that transforms a serial technique into a
vision of the world, and therefore into serial thought—of the
recognition of the social and historical foundations of codes, the
belief that a superstructural act might contribute to change these
codes and that every change in the codes of communication
entails the formation of new cultural contexts, the organization
and continuous restructuration of new codes, and the historical
evolution of modes of communication (depending on the dialectic
interrelations between a system of communication and its social
context). All we need is to remember the correlations posited by
Henri Pousseur between the universe of tonal music and an
aesthetic of repetition, closure, and cyclicality that involves and
reflects the conservative ideology and pedagogy characteristic of
a particular political and social structure.°
justify the ultimate parameters to which both old and new forms
refer.
The main problem with the structural method (the very term
"method" here should indicate that the problem has a solution) is
that, in order not to be confused with an antihistorical science, it
must constantly avoid any identification between the Structure it
seeks and any given series, taken as the privileged manifestation of
the universals of communication. Once this ambiguity is removed,
the serial method will appear as the other dialectic side of the
structural method, the side of becoming as opposed to that of
permanence. Series will no longer be a negation of structure;
rather, it will be the expression of a structure that questions itself
and sees itself as a historical phenomenon—and this not so much
in order to deny itself all possibility of research as in order to turn
the utopia of an ultimate reality into a regulatory principle for an
investigation in progress (which should always push beyond the
structure, toward its very basis, toward an ulterior code of which
the structure is just a message). In other words, series will be a
structure that, recognizing itself as the mere temporal manifestation of
an ulterior code, is constantly looking for it within itself, in a state
of continuous tension and permanent methodological doubt
which alone can produce meaning.
In fact, only one path was open to us: we had to call into question
the grand system by means of a critique of the superstructural di-
mension which directly concerned us and could easily be adminis-
tered by our group. Hence we decided to set up a debate about
language. We became convinced (and nobody has gone back on this
idea) that to renew forms of communication and destroy estab-
lished methods would be an effective and far-reaching platform for
criticizing—that is, overturning—everything that those cultural
forms expressed.
2 4 0 T HE DEAT H O F T HE G RUPPO 63
At all events, we had one clear idea: if one was moving toward a
point of total rupture at the level of literature, art, and philoso-
phy—at that level of "culture" which constitutes the global
communication by which a society continues to exist—it was
absolutely no use to "communicate" our plans by way of known
and tested media; on the contrary, we had to smash the very media of
communication. This was the "poetics" of the Gruppo 63—and the
single common aim at the heart of a group of writers who each had
their own private axe to grind anyway.
rocity, was an image calculated to strike terror into the hearts of all
but the bravest. I myself heard an established Italian novelist, for
example, express alarm at the idea of violating his solitude as a
writer faced by the blank page and coming down with us to Pa-
lermo to talk about uncompleted pages. However, if we allow some
of the theoreticians to express their views, we shall see that the
terrorist attitude gradually gave way to a more measured assess-
ment of the historical situation and generational opportunities that
faced the group.
Guglielmi: "At the present moment there is no reason for avant-
garde activity in the historical sense of the term. What we need at
present is a new critical conscience. Terrorism itself is reactionary.
We have the advantage of being in a state of absolute availability
(what Marcuse would have called repressive tolerance), so what
gates should we break through, since all gates are open to us?
"Contemporary culture is in the same situation as a city from
which the enemy have retreated after sowing every street with
mines. Of course, one is not going to march into the city like some
conquering hero and then get blown to bits like an idiot. It's a better
plan to send in reconnaissance patrols equipped with geiger count-
ers. Better take an experimental attitude.
"How can we approach the situation? For a writer there's only
one approach: language. For language is not detached in any way
from the historical reality of a situation. The anonymous stereo-
typed language typical of modern Italy, a language which hasn't
developed from an evolution of dialects, but in fact represents
the percolation downward of mass media communications, is one
which acutely reflects a social condition. It mirrors an alienation
which the writer can only fight against by working with signs and
language rather than things and contents."
Giuliani: "The measure of poetry for us consisted in the degra-
dation of meanings and in the constantly shifting physiognomy of
the verbal world into which we were plunged.
"These were the years of restoration in which Lampedusa's The
Leopard seemed to have reinjected Italian culture with a taste for
grandiose reflection on history in the Romanesque manner. The
world was justified by way of language.
"Let's be quite clear about one thing: language as a means for the
representation of reality is by now a machine gone out of control,
242 THE DEATH OF THE GRUPPO 63
Point I: All messages call into question their code; every act
of words constitutes a discussion of the language to which it
gives life. In its extreme sense this means that every message
postulates its own code, that every work of art is the linguistic
foundation of itself. the discussion of its own poetic system. It
releases itself from the bonds which previously claimed to
define and circumscribe it: every work of art is thus the key for its
own reading.
Point 2: Polyvalence: the whole notion of plurality of meaning
overturns the Cartesian axes of the vertical and the horizontal,
paradigm and syntagm. Series is a clustered constellation offer-
ing a field of infinite possibilities and multiple choice.
Point 3 : What matters in serial thought is the identification of his-
torical codes and the production of new modalities of
communication by calling them into question. The effect of serial
thinking is the evolution of codes and the discovery of new
codes, not a progressive recoil toward the original foundational
code. Series is not an investigation of history aimed at
uncovering absolute axes of communication, but simply the
permanent transformation of the past, the production of a new
ancient history.
the relationship between sign and denotation, and its syntactical aspect the
organization of words within a given discourse.
16. See Jakobson, Selected Writings, p. 218. "The set (Einstellung)
toward the MESSAGE as such, focus on the message for its own sake, is the
Poetic function of language." (See also "Linguistics and Poetics," in Se.
leered Writings, vol. 3, p. =S.)
17. We can attenuate the rigor of Ogden and Richards's distinctions with
Charles Stevenson's conclusions, according to which "the growth of emo-
tive and descriptive [referential] dispositions in language does not repre-
sent two isolated processes." In a metaphoric expression, the cognitive
aspects of the total discourse affect its emotive aspects. As a result, the
descriptive and the emotive meaning of an expression are "distinguishable
aspects of a total situation, not 'parts' of it that can be studied in isolation."
Then, after examining a third type of meaning (neither descriptive nor
emotive but rather the result of a grammatical incoherence that produces a
sort of "philosophical perplexity"), which he terms "confused meaning"
(and here we cannot help thinking of Joyce's ambiguous, open words),
Stevenson concludes by saying that "there will be emotive meaning de-
pendent on descriptive meaning...but there will also be emotive mean-
ing dependent on confused meaning." See Charles Stevenson, Ethics and
Language (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1944), ch. 3, pp. 71, 76, 78.
The studies of the Russian Formalists have yielded analogous results. In
the twenties, ShIclovsky and Jakubinsky had classified poetry as an ex-
ample of the emotive function of language. Their point of view was eventu-
ally changed thanks to the increasing formalization of poetic expression.
In 1925. Tomashevsky had relegated the communicative function of lan-
guage to the background in order to stress the absolute autonomy of the
verbal structures and the laws of immanence that govern poetry. In the thirties.
the Prague Structuralists tried to distinguish a multidimensional structure of
poetry that included the semantic level. "While a 'pure' Formalist brashly
denied the existence of ideas and feelings in a work of poetry, or declared
dogmatically that `it is impossible to draw any conclusion from a work of
literature,' the Structuralist would emphasize the inevitable ambiguity of
the poetic statement, poised precariously between various semantic
planes." Victor Erlich, Russian Formalism (The Hague: Mouton, 1965),
p. 200.
18. According to Charles Morris, "a sign is iconic to the extent to which it
itself has the properties of its denotata" (Signs, Language, and Behavior,
p. 23). This seemingly vague definition is, in fact, quite restrictive: as
Morris goes on to explain, a portrait cannot really be iconic, "since the
painted canvas does not have the texture of the skin, or the capacities for
speech and motion, which the person portrayed has." In fact, Morris sub-
NOTES TO PAGES 36-40 255
same subject have appeared in various issues of the Cahiers d'etudts de radio-
telioisiots.
23. See Inccntri rnitsicali, vol. 3 (1959). the exchange between Nicolas
Ruwet and Henri Pousseur.
24. Moles, IntOrmation Theory and Esthetic Perception, pp. 78-79. "There is
no absolute structural difference between noise and signal. They arc of the
same nature. The only difference which can be logically established between
them is based exclusively on the concept of intent on the part of the
transmitter: A noise is a signal that the sender does not want to transmit."
"If the sonic material of white noise is formless, what is the minimum
'personality' it must have to assume an identity? What is the minimum of
spectral form it must have to attain individuality? This is the problem
of coloring white noises" (p. 82). This is also the problem that confronts the
composer of electronic music.
25. This essay was originally written in 1960 for the fourth issue of
lncontri musicali. The postscript was written six years later. Garroni's cri-
tique was entitled La crisi semantica delle arti (Rome: Officina Edizioni,
1964), of which ch. 3 dealt with Opera aperta.
26. Goldman, Information Theory. p. 69.
27. If information theory corresponds to a statistical study of physical
phenomena (seen as "messages"), this step will take us toward a communi-
cation theory that will deal specifically with human messages. The notion of
"message" can operate on both levels, though we should not forget
Jakobson's objection to much theoretical work in communication: "At-
tempts to construct a model of language without any relation either to the
speaker or to the hearer, and thus to hypostasize a code detached from
actual communication, threaten to make a scholastic fiction out of lan-
guage." Roman Jakobson, Selected Writings (The Hague: Mouton, 1981),
vol. 2, p. 576.
28. "Knowledge does not create the organization of its message; it imitates
it to the extent that it is true and effective. Reason does not dictate its laws to
the universe; rather, there is a natural harmony between reason and universe,
since both obey the same general laws of organization." P. Guillaume, La
psychologie de la forme (Paris: Flammarion, 1937), p. 204.
29. "Several facts show that the perceptual interpretations of primary
sensorial data are remarkably plastic, and that the same material, under
given circumstances, may elicit very different reactions." H. Pieron, in La
Perception, a symposium volume (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France,
1955), P. / I-
tural evolution, there had been only one instance of the avant-garde. But,
in fact, contemporary culture is a "culture of avant-gardes." How can we
explain such a situation? We can no longer make a clear distinction be-
tween a rejected tradition and an avant-garde that proposes a new order,
because every avant-garde is the negation of a previous avant-garde,
which, however, given its relative contemporaneity, cannot yet be consid-
ered as a tradition in relation to the avant-garde that is negating it. Hence,
the suspicion that a valid act of Ur-avant-garde may often be the stimulus
for an avant-garde manner, and that, today, "to be avant-garde" may well
be the only way of belonging to a tradition. This situation is often seen as
the neocapitalist conversion of artistic rebellion. In other words, the artist is
a rebel because the market wants him to be one. Therefore, his rebellion has
no real value, since it is only a convention. But on close inspection, it is
not difficult to realize that what we arc again confronting here, in this
"denunciation," is the natural dialectic between invention and manner
which has always existed in the history of art. Every time an artist invents a
new form that involves a profound change in the vision of the world, he is
immediately imitated by a legion of pseudo-artists who borrow the
form of his art without, however, understanding its implications. It is
precisely because of the inevitability of such a phenomenon, and of its
frequency in a civilization such as ours (where things arc used up so rap-
idly and change is so sudden that no novelty is ever new for long) that it is
particularly important that every avant-garde action be immediately ne-
gated by a newer invention and thus prevented from becoming manner.
The combination of these two dialectics produces a constant alternation
between apparent innovations, mere mannerist variations on a theme, and
real innovations, the negations of these variations. Thus, forms that have
been negated by a number of successive avant-gardes often retain a power
that the newer ones do not have.
On the other hand, we should also note that if avant-garde methods are
often the swiftest and most direct way of confronting and dismantling a
declining artistic situation, they are not the only way. Another exists
within the very order that is being negated: parody, the ironic imitation of
such an order (Stravinsky's alternative to Schonberg). In other words, a
worn out, alienating form of expression can be negated in one of two
ways: one can dismantle the modes of communication on which it is
based, or one can exorcise them via parody. Parody and irony can thus be
seen as viable, subtler alternatives to the more common, revolutionary
ardor of the avant-garde. There is also a very dangerous, but plausible,
third possibility: one can adopt the communicative forms of a particular
system in order to question and challenge that very system—critically use
mass media to raise the consciousness of that part of the audience which
NOTES TO PAGES 43-152 267
would only feel negatively provoked by the more destructive and less ac-
cesisoib. leAascatsnoefxtahme pavicanit-shgaalrldeci
te a situation
o familiar to any reader wh itu
.
while visiting a foreign city, has walked into a bar, both to kill time and
(with a generally vain, often unconscious hope) to alleviate loneliness. It is
difficult to imagine a more unbearable or a more depressing situation; yet
we all understand it, and accept it as quite "literary." Why? Because litera-
ture has told us that if we sit alone at a bar something will happen to us: a
voluptuous blonde may suddenly appear, as in a detective novel, or, as in
Hemingway, there may be a subtler but equally inevitable revelation of
nada in the course of the most banal dialogue. Thus, a squalid, meaningless
situation becomes perfectly acceptable thanks to the false glamor cast on it by
the application of narrative structures that demand a solution for every
premise, an acceptable conclusion and an end for every beginning—since
these structures do not allow for a beginning without an end, unlike some
other narratives and some movies (Antonioni's, for instance), which dare
show us incomplete situations, such as we often find in life, without the
consolation of a finale, the reassuring return to the tonic, to conclude
everything we start.
It. For the notion of modo di formare ("way of forming"), see Luigi
Pareyson's Estetica.
12. As Elio Vittorini has justly noted in a recent issue of Menabb, "today,
that narrative that concentrates in its language the full weight of its respon-
sibilities coward the world is much closer to assuming a historically active
meaning than any literature that approaches things via their presumed pre-
linguistic content, treating them as themes, issues, and so forth."
13. Thus, narrative technique becomes the real content of the movie and
its most important statement. If the story appears unclear to the viewer, it is
because it is also unclear to the author, the director—who, however,
prefers to respect this obscurity as real rather than to impose on it a false
order. In other words, he prefers to let the situation create his movie than to
create a situation through his movie. Another example of this sort of
movie is Godard's A bout de souffle (Breathless), whose development is
seemingly affected by the same psychic disorder that affects its hero. As a
literary example, we can cite Conjectures on Jacob, by Johnson, in which the
inner split of the narrator, expressive of the moral, political, and geo-
graphic division of Germany, is also reflected in its narrative technique.
1965), pp
14. Alain19R2o 20, 2i
bbe-Grillet, For a New Novel (New York: Grove Press,
15. See Umberto Eco, "Il tempo di `Sylvie,'" in Poesia e critics 2.
16. Robbe-Grillet, For a New Novel, p. 22.
268 NOTES TO PAGES 1 S4-172
'vintage' look," whereas the verb verkitschen means "to sell cheaply."
z. Walther Kill, Deutscher Kitsch (Gottingen: Vandenhock & Riprecht,
1962). Killy's essay introduces an anthology of characteristic fragments
drawn out of German literature. The authors he used for his pastiche are,
in order: Wester Jansen, Natal von Eschtruth, Reinhold Muschler, Agnes
Gunther, Rainer Maria Rilke, Nathanael Jiinger.
3. Hermann Broch. "Einige Bemerkungen zum Problem des Kitsches,"
in Dichten und Erkennen. (Zurich, 1955). Translated as "Notes on the
Problem of Kitsch," in Kitsch: The World of Bad Taste, ed. Gillo Dorfles
(New York: Universe Books, 1969).
4. Luigi Pareyson, in "I teorici dell' Ersatz." De Homine 5-6 (1963), a
short essay that reiterates the main theoretical issues already discussed in
his Estetica. In his polemic against the calm recognition of the "digestibil-
ity" of the artistic product, Pareyson makes a distinction between the ge-
neric "artisticity" that pervades all human work, and art as the "culmina-
tion and the climax" of this attitude, as "norm and model." education of
taste, proposal of new "ways of forming." intentional forming for form's
sake. According to him, the product of the cultural industry would be
nothing more than simple expressions of "artisticity," and, as such, subject to
both consumption and wear. Of course, among the processes of artisticity,
Pareyson does not include all those works of art which, on the basis of a
particular poetics, or of the general tendency of a historical period, inten-
tionally aim at the attainment of heteronomous ends (whether pedagogi-
cal, political. or utilitarian). In these cases, there is art only insofar as the
artist manages to embody his intentions in his formal project, and insofar
as the work, though aiming at something outside itself, also manifests
itself as a form for its own sake.
5. R. Egenter, Kitsch and Christenleben (Ettal, 195o), as quoted by Giesz.
6. Clement Greenberg, "The Avant-Garde and Kitsch," in Dorfles, ed.,
Kitsch: The World of Bad Taste.
7. See Chapter 8, "Two Hypotheses about the Death of Art."
8. In his "Salon de 1859," Baudelaire expresses great irritation at pho-
tography's ambition to replace art, and exhorts all photographers to con-
fine their activity to the utilitarian recording of images rather than try to
infiltrate the realm of the imagination. But is it art that begs industry not
to invade its turf, or is it industry that is pushing art out into other fields?
On Baudelaire's attitude toward this new situation, see Walter Benjamin.
"On Some Motifs in Baudelaire," in Illuminations (New York: Schocken,
1969).
9. See Gerhart D. Wiebe, "Culture d'elite et communications de
masse," in Communications 3. For the sake of a more rigorous method of
investigation, Wiebe proposes a distinction between the characteristics of
NOTES TO PAGES 190-196 271
art and those of mass communication, even though they arc often joined in
one product. Except that his notion of the functions of "mass media"
saenedimim.s Tfida. w uicrlyit.,.., Adorno, "I would almost go so far as to say that
the moreTV programs fulfill a regulating social and psychological func-
popular
tion—that is, they tend to preserve a balance in a context that can be much
more turbulent than we think . . . People would not spend so much time
watching these programs if they did not satisfy a need, if they did not
redress certain distortions, if they did not fulfill certain desires."
11. See Dwight MacDonald, Against the American Grain (New York:
Random House, 1952), pp. 40-43, and in general the chapter "Masscult
Jakobson, Roman, xviii, 69, 195 Leonardo da Vinci: Mona Lisa, 197
Jalcubinsky, Lev, 254n17 Leopardi, Conte Giacomo, 173 Levi-
Jazz, 109-1 to Strauss, Claude, xviii, xxi, 69, 235;
Jesus Christ, 243 critique of serialism, 217, 219, 221226,
Jone, Hildegard, 62 228-229; Ur-code in, 219-220,
Jones, Ernest, 67 225; Entretiens, 217, 222; The Raw and
Joyce, James, ix, XV, 10-11, 14, 148, 247; the Cooked, 217, 219, 221-226, 245
Finnegans Wake, x, xii, xv-xvi, 10-i1, Liberate, 78, 137
40, 41, 156, 169, 171, 175-176; Ulysses, Lillie, R. S., 72
xv-xvi, to, 31, 148 Lipchitz, Jacques, 200
Jung. Carl G.. 243 Lippold, Friedrich, 85
Literature. See Detective story; Novel;
Kafka, Franz, x, 9 Poetry
Kandinsky. 205 Live broadcast. See Television
Kelly, Grace. 108-109 Logic: many-valued, 15; bivalent, 15, 87;
Kepler, Johannes, 89 dialectic, 2.0
Killy, Walther, 182-184 Lorentz, Hendrik Antoon, 120
Kinetic theory of gases, 55-56 MacDonald, Dwight, 189-193
Kitsch: aesthetic pretensions of, xvii, Mandiargues, Andre Pieyre dc, lot
184-185, 187-188, 190-192, 202-205, 211- Magnasco, 85
213, 214; as production of effect, 181, Malaparte, Curzio: La pelle, 214
182-185, 194-195, 203; vs. avant-garde Mallarme, Stephane, 8, 14, 169; Livre,
ZIT, 036-188. 190, 192, 193, 203, 215-216;
Midcult as, 188-194; as easy Manzix-xon 12-13, 15
consumption, 197, 211-213; as imitation Alessandro, 198, 203-204; The
aesthetic pleasure, 203, 205-206, 211- Betrothed, 198
213, 214; etymology of, 269n1 Maoism, 236
Maraviglia, 7
1.2C2/1, Jacques, 69, 232, 235, 246 Marcusc, Herbert, 241, 242
Lampedusa, Giuseppi Tomasi di: The Marinetti, Filippo, 236
Leopard, 209-211, 241 Markoff chains, 77-78
Language: poetic use of, 32-39, 41- Marx, Karl, 156, 232, 243; object in, 124-
43. 58-62, 144-146, 154-156, 195-197. 125; alienation in, 124-123, 126, 127, 136;
206; referential function of, xxiii, 2930, production in, 125-126, m8, 129
31, 32, 35-36, 195, 2531513; of pun, 10, Marxism, xviii; and structuralism, xxiii,
175-176; emotive function of, 3032, 37, 232-235; dialectical logic in, 20
2531113, 254n17; sign ambiguity Mass communication, vi, xxiv, xxvi-
xxvii, 187, 27009
36-37, 41-43; as branch system, so;
musical, 50, 62-65, 75-80, 224-225, Mass consumption, 20o, 206
271n14; redundancy in, 50-52, 58, 93. Mass culture, vii, xvi, xvii-xviii, 185-
256n2; televisual, 121-122; as reflection of 21 0 0 9 , 2 4 , 2 o
87-93. 98-99; communicability of, 64- 151, 169-170, 171, 174-175, 176, 177,
65. 68-69. 86, 102-104; informal art, 178, 201; of informal art, 84, 86-93, 102-
86-93, 101-104; and serialism, 218; 104; of television, 0)5, 107-11o, 112-113,
in Gruppo 63, 244-245. See also Art, 117-120, 121-122; phenomenological,
contemporary; Avant-garde art; 151; and aesthetic criticism, 167-169;
development of, 179; of Gruppo 63, 240
Optsanpnerresas, xviii, xix, xxi, Poetry: use of language in, xii, 32-35,
OrxdIeiri7xxxxiixv-xxxi, 6-7, 50-58. 74-81, 36, 41-43, 58-62, 144-146, 154-156,
139-141. 157. See also Disorder; En- 195-197; openness in, 40-43, 142; in-
tropy; Information formation in, 53-55, 58-62; intentional
Original locus. 234-235 disorder in, 53-55, 58-62, 196-zoo; of
Painting, 101, 102-103, 142. See also Art; alienation, 144, 145-146; of poetry,
Art, Contemporary; Avant-garde art 169, 172; as reflection of culture, 173,
Pareyson, Luigi, IX, xxv-XXVI, 21-22, 174
2.69n6, 270/14; forrnativity in, xii, xiii, Poggioli, Renato: Teoria dell'arte d'avan-
158-i61. 165, 26906; organic form in, guardia, 240
xxv; style in, xxv. 164-165; artistic Pollock, Jackson, 1o3
matter in, 160-161; formative process Polyvalence, 68-69, 218, 220, 246. See
in, 051-163; theory of interpretation, also Ambiguity; Disorder
163-164, 165-166 Pop Art, 215
Parody, 26509 Porta, Antonio, 244
Pascal, Blaise, 89 Pouillon, Jean, 218-219
Paul, Saint, 5 Pound, Ezra, 242, 243
Peirce, C. S., xxii, xxxi Pousseur, Henri, x, 4, 14, 8o, 222, 230;
Perception, 71-74, 76, 79, 97-98, 150, Srambi, 1-2, 10-11, 12; Mobiles, 19
259035; probabilistic, 16-17, 72-74. 81- Power, 17, 238
8z; and information, 81-83 Performance, Proust, Marcel, IO, 207-208, 242
3, 4-5, 15, 21, 251111 Perspective, 5, 85 Psychology. See Transactional psychol-
PPehtizrscohp,h5y4 -15754,-5187,56o, 61
ogy
Ptolemy, 229
Phenomenology, 16, 151
Puns, 10, 175-176
Physics, 14, 15-16, 18; complementarity
Stylenies, 200-20 I , 210 Univocity, 40, 42, 66, 86, 87, 93, 94,
Sue, Eugene, 156 /14, 152. See also Ambiguity; Meaning
Surrealism, 59
Symbolism. x, 8, 9 - t o , 14, 26, Valery, Paul, 9, 161, 162
2601143 Van Gogh, Vincent: Sunflowers, 205
Verdi, Giuseppe: Aida, 2
Tachisme, 99-too Verlaine, Paul: Art poitique, 8
Tchaikovsky, Peter, 142-143 Vico, Giovanni, 41
Television. xvii, 187; interpretive choice in, Visio, 177
105, I07-110, 112-113, 117-120, 121- Vitality, 99-too, 101, 103
122; montage in, 107. 114; live, to6-110, Vitruvius, 5
112-113, 116, 121; improvisation in. Vittorino, Elio, xiii, xvii, 206
109, 112-113; as open work, 114-120, Von Neumann, John: Game Theory, 89
121-122 VS, xx
Tel Quel, 236
Theater, 142 Weaver, Warren, 57, 58, 63, 65
.4 Theory of Semiotics, xix-xx, xxiv, xxv- Webem, Anton, x, 12, 62-63, 84, 95-96,
xxvi 228
Thomas Aquinas, Saint. vii, xvi, 5 Wellek, Rene, 225n18
Time. 106, 152 Wertheimer, Max, 74-75
Tindall, W. Y., 9-10 Whitehead, A. N., to
Tintoretto, Jacopo, 85 Wiener, Norbert, 49-50. 52-53
Tomashcvsky, Boris, 254n17 Wilder, Thornton: Our Town, 192-193
Tonal system, 50, izo; abandonment of, Wilson, Edmund, iv
62-63, 95-96; conventionality of, 76- Wit, 7
78, 139-141, 227-228. See also Music Wittgenstein, Ludwig, xxxi
Totality, 25-26, 27, 28, 39 Wols, 84
Tragedy. 114-115 Works in movement, ix-x, 12-20, 22-23,
Transactional psychology, 36, 71-74. 76 84-86; and science, 13-19, 22-23
Transactional rapport. 71-74
Travels in Hyperreality, xxix Yevtushenko, Yevgeny, 129