Introduction To Tractatus - Friedrick Hustler
Introduction To Tractatus - Friedrick Hustler
Introduction To Tractatus - Friedrick Hustler
Cover Art:
The editors gratefully acknowledge permission by NASA, ESA, and STScI
to use the photo Galactic Center taken by the Hubble Telescope.
Editors’ Note . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6
Author’s Preface . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11
Chapter 2 Communication . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 37
References . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 113
Table of Contents 5
... to read this book: If you are a person whose profession is not
philosophy, and if you are interested in the fundamental question
“What can be expressed by language?” then this book is a good
way to start an investigation of that question.
It is written by a physicist who for many years was baffled by the
fact that language is frequently abused. He then decided to focus
on the above question. He started out by studying the works of
Wittgenstein, who had dedicated most of his life trying to answer
this question.
Don’t be deterred from reading this book by the fact that Witt-
genstein later refuted the Tractatus. Actually, he desired to publish
the Tractatus together with the Philosophical Investigations, so that
the reader could see how the two works are related.
Editors’ Note 9
Acknowledgement
I. T. and K. T.
Summer 2015
Author’s Preface
Friedrich Hülster
Louveciennes, France, July 1969
Chapter 1
The World
“An aging man ceases to understand the world.” In this phrase from
Jean Amery’s book On Aging, the world is primarily a process in
which the individual is involved.
In contrast, the world of the Tractatus is the same for all think-
ing beings, the one about which their thoughts, if rightly formed,
must coincide. This presupposes that thoughts are communicable.
Consequently, the world only includes what can be the object of
communicable thoughts.
ideas? In short, what about everything that since the time of Plato
has been included in the category of ideal objects?
As for ideal objects, it will become clear in the course of our inquiry
where they belong. But a look ahead is useful: Ideal objects in the
sense of things that we find in the world, do not exist; they do not
form part of what we can state about the world, but are part of the
process of making statements.
So how do we accomplish the description of a thing? The things
we encounter in the world are mostly not simple, but composed
of other things that are their constituent parts. Even these latter
parts are in most cases made up of other things. For example, a tree
is composed of a trunk, large and small branches, and leaves; the
leaves are made up of nerves and leaf tissue; the leaf tissue is made
of cells, which in turn consist of nucleus, plasm, and membrane; and
so on.
When we describe a complex thing, in our mind we take it apart into
pieces. By so doing, we discover new things which are its constituent
parts; we then stop considering the complex thing and focus on the
constituents. We also discover relations connecting these new things.
These relations are facts. For example, branches end in leaves, plasm
surrounds the nucleus of the cell.
The further we continue the process of description, the more we split
up constituent parts into their sub-constituent parts. At the same
time, we state the facts linking the larger units to the smaller ones.
At the end, we have obtained a chain of facts. The original thing and
its components have gradually faded out of our statements, leaving
finally the last sub-sub-constituents when we are unable to carry out
1.3 Elementary Things and Elementary Facts 20
When the analysis stops, we only have names for the final compo-
nents, and no further information about them.
Naturally, one would like to see a practical example where the ana-
lytical description of a thing is continued down to elementary things
and elementary facts. However, Wittgenstein gives no such example
and—according to notes in his diary—concluded that he could not
do so.
1.3 Elementary Things and Elementary Facts 21
Physics also shows us how things that once passed for being ele-
mentary may dissolve under further analysis into things yet more
elementary and related to one another by new facts.
Since then, the complex theory of atomic nuclei, with their neutrons,
mesons, etc. and the intricate facts about how these are packed
together and how much energy they hold, has become tragically
famous through the development of nuclear weapons. Despite such
detailed insight, we still cannot predict where further analysis will
lead us. But some physicists hope that someday we shall come up
against particles which are absolutely and finally elementary.
1.4 Properties
The case is the same with any mental experience, such as grief at
someone’s death. Indeed, with a bit of training in self-observation,
I can divide the complex whole of the experience into pieces: enu-
merating memories of the dead person, my love for her, thoughts
of my future loneliness, and so on. But I cannot communicate the
grief which colors all these elements.
1.5 Logical Form of Things 29
But there are other facts that on the contrary seem to have an
internal, necessary connection with one another.
A particular example are facts about events that follow one an-
other in temporal succession and concern two or more objects. An
instance is the collision of two billiard balls and the subsequent
recoil.
In the case of a temporal connection of this kind, we speak of a
causal connection or a cause-and-effect relation between two facts.
We also speak of the rule of natural laws by which one event is
followed by a foreseeable—indeed, absolutely determined—event,
and not just by some arbitrary event.
In daily life, we get along very well by assuming the truth of such
causal connections or natural laws. For example, if a pot is put on a
fire, can’t we predict with certainty that it will get hot? Yet physics
objects: Although the passage of heat from a hotter to a colder
body is a valid rule for cooking in a kitchen, it is not a strict law
of nature. What appears to us as heat, is in physics a disorderly
movement of atoms. In a hot body, this movement is on average
faster than in a cold one. Indeed, when the two bodies touch, the
faster moving atoms on average pass some of their energy of motion
to the slower ones. But the opposite must also occur in small areas
of a body, and indeed is observed to do so.
In fact, the events of the macroscopic world are not determined
by strict laws, but rather by extremely reliable rules. For example,
according to the rules of gravity, a stone released from some height
will always fall down to the ground. But quantum physics declares
that there is a probability, though very small, that at some point
1.6 Essential Unconnectedness of Facts 32
in time, a stone may rise in the air instead of fall, contrary to the
rule of gravity. This exceptional event is predicted to occur once in
tens of billions of years.
If perfect strictness existed in natural laws at all, it would be con-
fined to the world of atoms. Even supposing that we found it there,
could we mean by it anything other than regularity? Are we en-
titled to speak of necessity in connection with consecutive facts?
That the idea of necessity has for so long been applied unhesitat-
ingly but wrongly to the events of the macroscopic world should be
a warning that we must be very careful.
The word “necessary” has a clear meaning in the case of logical
necessity, as found for instance in the logical conclusions we draw
in a mathematical proof. In that case, we can know—in the genuine
sense of the word—that something is true if something else is true.
Our knowledge of logical necessity is of an a priori nature, not
depending upon real experiences. We possess no such knowledge of
natural laws.
In Wittgenstein’s view, facts are only externally connected by their
simultaneous occurrence in a configuration of things, and not by
any inner necessity. Although the consecutiveness of two events may
invariably have been observed, we still do not know—in the strict
meaning of the word—that this will also be the case in the future.
Wittgenstein’s opinion produces less of a shock today than it must
have caused in 1921, when his Tractatus first appeared. For in the
meantime, physics has further undermined our old ideas of the iron
laws of nature. The discovery of the bending phenomena observable
in corpuscular radiation has in fact led us to view the sequence of
1.6 Essential Unconnectedness of Facts 33
Each item can be the case or not the case while everything else
remains the case. (Tractatus 1.21)
Anyone who finds all this difficult to accept should call to mind
once more that we are focusing on the world common to all thinking
beings. In everyday life, we too easily delude ourselves about how
much is exactly the same for us and our fellow citizens. Wittgenstein
demolishes these delusions.
Yet the world has substance, in the sense that there is something
beyond mere phantoms that get combined higgledy-piggledy as if
in a dream.
That something does not itself belong to the world. It consists pre-
cisely of what is not our common possession as humans, and not of
what we can pass on to one another by communication. It consists
of elementary things. Wittgenstein sometimes calls them objects,
or depending on context, things; see Appendix B. We cannot com-
municate them, but nevertheless they are the items that provide
consistency for our communications.
The isolated symbols in our third group are not like this. They just
say what has already been explained to us, and no more. To un-
derstand them, we first must have learned their whole message. For
example, we learned as children that, when a building is burning,
a shout of “Fire!” is a cry for help and not a request for a match
to light a cigarette. Consequently, the signs in the third group are
rarely used to make statements, but rather as signals or instructions
to behave or act in a certain way.
We can therefore confine our inquiry into means of communication
to the two first two groups, which rely on a composition process
that involves many symbols.
It must be emphasized—and this is of decisive importance for un-
derstanding the Tractatus—that in the case of speech we are only
interested in speech propositions that are intended to actually con-
vey information. Typically, this is not the case with lyric poems,
songs, requests, prayers, or curses.
In daily life, picture has a slightly less precise sense than represen-
tation and often is used in a metaphorical sense. Wittgenstein uses
both words in the same sense. But what is the exact meaning in his
picture theory?
(1) Its elements, called the picture elements, must represent things
in the reality which is being pictured.
(2) The relations existing between the picture elements must repre-
sent relations between the real things in such a way that the latter
relations can be read off, so to speak.
The sketch would not be a picture at all—in the sense that we are
discussing—if the elements standing for roof and redness were not
arranged so as to indicate their connection—for instance, if the red
was put just somewhere at the edge of the picture, as can occur in
modern paintings.
The elements in the sketch of the house and those of the real house
have a visible resemblance. Due to this fact, the example is too
narrow to serve as a generally valid explanation of the picture idea.
Indeed, picture elements can be very different from the real elements
they represent. A piece of music can be depicted in a score, the
sounds being represented by the notation, or on a vinyl record using
wave impressions in the grooves as picture elements.
The picture elements must obey the following three conditions.
First, the picture must contain as many different kinds of elements
as there are different real elements that are to be distinguished.
Second, each picture element must always represent the same kind
of real element.
The third condition is a bit more complicated. Although the ele-
ments of the picture and their arrangement need not have any ob-
vious resemblance to reality, something in the picture and the real
object must in some sense be not merely similar, but absolutely
identical. Specifically, between the picture elements, the same num-
ber of kinds of relations must be possible, the same number be
necessary, and the same number be incompatible as between the
corresponding elements of reality. In other words, the relations be-
tween the elements in the reality and those between the elements
in the picture must exhibit the same mathematical multiplicity.
When the three conditions are satisfied, Wittgenstein says that pic-
ture and reality have identical structure.
The requirement of identical structure is met automatically when
the picture elements and the real elements are of the same nature—
for instance, when real colors are to be depicted by colors in the
picture, degrees of brightness by degrees of brightness, and spatial
elements by spatial elements.
2.3 Wittgenstein’s Idea of a Picture 44
it will not be called false but incomplete. For example, if our sketch
shows no chimney, an architect would consider the picture incom-
plete.
The word “also” implies that a picture can in addition have more
specialized qualities, such as being spatial or colored.
2.7 Thoughts and Speech Propositions 48
These pictures represent not only our thoughts, but also the speech
propositions by which our thoughts are transmitted to others. Witt-
genstein states this as follows:
A logical picture of facts is a thought. (Tractatus 3)
In a proposition, a thought finds an expression that can be perceived
by the senses. (Tractatus 3.1)
The word thought as used above requires more precise explanation.
As is customary among philosophers, Wittgenstein makes a distinc-
tion between thoughts and the mental events of thinking, in which
mental images of things and of words occur within us.
As an example, suppose I think “France is larger than Belgium.”
At the same time, I can imagine myself accommodating on a map
the whole area of Belgium well inside France. The thought is not
identical with this act of imagination, any more than the number 5
is identical with our imagination of five apples.
Thus, the thought is something abstracted from the images; it
emerges from them. Our ability to examine a thought, to consider
it, and to discuss it with other people—as if it were something
effectively present—arises from our ability to make perceptible im-
ages. The component parts of the images—for example, Belgium
and France on the map—then represent the component parts of the
thought.
We make up signs for the components of the thought, and for the
thought itself. In practice, we use for this purpose the words and
propositions of speech.
In principle, other kinds of elements could be used for this purpose.
As Wittgenstein remarks, signs used for the thought might be
2.7 Thoughts and Speech Propositions 50
represent real things; that is, they are names. Then “is on” denotes
a spatial relation, which in the logical form is also a thing. The
structure of the proposition consists of the fact that the two names
“book” and “writing pad” are separated by the name of the relation,
and “book” comes first and “writing pad” after the relation.
The meaning of “is on” is that the name coming before it denotes
the higher placed object, and the name coming after it the lower
placed one. Thus, the fact that the words are ordered in a certain
way allows us to express a fact in space.
The picture theory does not claim that all simple propositions—
in the casual form in which we meet them in daily speech—can
at once be identified as pictures of reality. It asserts rather that
the underlying thoughts can be expressed in propositions which are
pictures in the sense we have explained.
Indeed, the propositions occurring in everyday language often in-
clude elements that aren’t part of the actual information. Examples
are words expressing wishes, beliefs, or doubts of the speaker, like “I
hope” and “regrettably”; or words intended to draw the attention
of the listener to some important point, like the word “himself” in
the proposition “he saw it himself.”
More importantly, colloquial propositions contain adjectives, and
these are neither names of things, nor do they serve to assert rela-
tions between the names occurring in the proposition. They are, in
fact, names of properties.
2.9 Elementary Propositions 54
Just as the world common to all men consists of the totality of facts,
so must all possible communications about the world be capable of
being assembled out of the totality of valid elementary propositions.
This is true for communications concerning individual events and
relations—as in daily life and in history—and likewise for commu-
nications of general import arising from empirical science.
Suppose the answer were that propositions of daily speech can ex-
press nothing but facts. This would imply that our thoughts, insofar
as they are real thoughts capable of being communicated, can only
occur within the sphere of facts. Or as many of us would say with
regret, on a dull level of matter-of-factness.
Let us first consider the raw material available in speech for making
pictures.
The components of a proposition that contribute to its meaning
from a logical, not grammatical, viewpoint, are called symbols by
Wittgenstein. The perceptible portions of the symbols—for exam-
ple, nouns, adjectives and so on, but also whole portions of the
proposition—are called the signs of the symbols.
If we treat the symbols as identical with the signs, fatal errors will
arise, in particular because a single word can be the sign of different
symbols. For instance, the word “is” may occur as a simple link—
without any separate meaning of its own—or as the sign of equality,
or with the meaning “exists.”
The essence of a symbol is not its sign, but the way in which the
sign is used. When we say that in a proposition—considered as a
picture of reality—the words are the elements of the picture, then
by “words” we mean symbols and not signs used for them.
When we discussed the picture, we spoke of the necessity that the
elements of the picture and the possible relations between them
should exhibit the same degree of multiplicity as exists in elements
of the thing to be depicted and in the relations between those ele-
ments.
3.1 Peculiarities of Picture Components 64
One may say that a proposition gives a picture and asserts that it
is a correct one. The assertion of correctness is usually contained
in the proposition just by implication, but it can also be added
explicitly to the proposition—for example, in a phrase like “It is
true that ....”
Yet neither the picture given by the proposition, nor the assertion
that it is a true picture, makes us aware whether the proposition is
true. To know whether it is true or false, we must compare it with
reality. The proposition by itself cannot tell us this.
It may seem that daily life tautologies such as “Boys will be boys”
and “Time passes,” and contradictions like “That is true and also
not true” and “Sixty minutes are more than an hour” do have a
certain meaning or even profundity. But this is only so, because we
do not interpret them literally.
and only give a brief description of its role when propositions supply
pictures.
According to Wittgenstein, negation does not appear at all in the
picture that a proposition supplies.
Remember the dual function of a proposition. First, it gives a pic-
ture. Second, it asserts the truth of that picture. Negation itself
cannot appear in the picture; there is nothing in reality that corre-
sponds to it. It does not even turn the picture into a sort of negative
picture, comparable to a photographic negative. Take the propo-
sition “The letter is on the notepad.” The corresponding negative
picture would be something like “The notepad is on the letter.” But
the negated proposition says “The letter is not on the notepad.” In
this proposition, the picture elements, apart from the negation, are
the same as those occurring in the original phrase. But the second
function of the proposition has been changed by the negation: The
assertion of truth is reversed.
Affirmation and negation when applied to the contents of a propo-
sition are called logical constants analogously to the mathematical
idea of constants. Indeed, when a mathematical variable is multi-
plied by a nonzero constant, a new variable is obtained that pre-
serves all the essential characteristics of the original variable, such
as the position of extreme values. For a proposition, affirmation and
negation play a part analogous to that played in mathematics by
multiplication of a variable by 1 and by −1, respectively. Multipli-
cation by the constant 1 leaves the variable unaltered, while the
constant −1 leads to a reversal of the sign of values of the variable.
Affirmation and negation are also called logical operations, and their
symbols are called logical operators. In mathematics, an operator is
3.4 Compound Propositions by Logical Operations 75
the name for a symbol that, when placed before an expression, spec-
ifies that a certain operation is applied to that expression. The use
of the names “operation” and “operator” therefore implies that the
logician does not consider affirmation or negation as part of the pic-
ture furnished by a proposition. On the contrary, it is considered as
an instruction to perform a particular mental act upon the picture
as a whole.
Hence, the word “and” expresses assertion (1) in our table and
rejects assertions (2), (3), and (4). It claims that the compound
proposition is false if, in fact, the wind is from the east without
the sun shining (2), or the wind is not from the east and the sun
is shining (3), or the wind is not from the east and the sun is not
shining (4).
These last three propositions already show us the kinds of com-
pound propositions by which assertions (2), (3), and (4) can be
expressed. Thus the compound proposition “The wind is not from
the east and the sun is not shining” expresses assertion (4). Linking
the two propositions by “neither ... nor ...” claims that the com-
pound proposition is true if it is the case that original propositions
(a) and (b) are false; and it claims that the compound proposition
is false in all three of the other cases.
Notice that each of the four compound propositions contains not
one but four assertions—that is, one assertion about the condition
under which it is true, and three assertions under which it is false.
The four kinds of compound propositions we have discussed so far
are not the only ones that can be formed by the use of assertions (1)–
(4). Indeed, instead of declaring a single one of these four assertions
to be true and the other three to be false, additional compound
propositions choose several of the four at once and assert the truth
of the compound proposition if any chosen one is true. We explore
these cases while discussing compound propositions formed with
“or.”
First, we note that “or” is used with two distinct meanings. There
is an inclusive “or,” which means one or the other, or both together;
3.4 Compound Propositions by Logical Operations 78
and an exclusive “or,” which means either one or the other, but not
both together.
Suppose my desk lamp fails to work. When I say “The bulb is
burned out, or the current has failed,” I mean the inclusive “or,”
since both cases are possible.
The use of the inclusive “or” makes the compound proposition as-
sert that one of assertions (1)–(3) of the table is true, and assertion
(4) is false.
On the other hand, when I say “I’m going to bed now, or I’m going
for a walk,” I have the exclusive “or” in mind, for I cannot do both
at once. This “or” asserts that the compound proposition is true if
one of the assertions (2) and (3) in our table is true, and (1) and
(4) are false.
The four truth possibilities that occur in a proposition with two
components enable us to form a total of 16 groups of conditions in
which the compound proposition is true; each of these groups, as
we have seen, is composed of four individual conditions called truth
conditions. Of course not all these 16 groups occur in everyday
speech. The most frequently used of them are as follows:
Disjunction (inclusive “or”)
Alternative (exclusive “or”)
Implication (“if ... then ...”)
Equivalence (“is the same as”)
Incompatibility (“is inconsistent with”)
Unfortunately, these designations have not been internationally stan-
dardized; for example, one finds disjunction and alternative con-
fused with each other.
3.4 Compound Propositions by Logical Operations 79
Yet even in these not purely logical ways of giving reasons, it seems
impossible that they could lead us out of the domain of the physical
or psychological facts expressed in the components.
Bertrand Russell held this view about the time when the Tractatus
was written. Russell’s view and, more importantly, Wittgenstein’s
claim that all propositions are pictures of facts, motivated him to
pay special attention to this kind of proposition.
This chapter draws conclusions from the results of the picture the-
ory—in particular, from the necessary conditions that a meaningful
proposition must obey, and, equally important, from the limits of
what a proposition can express.
In daily speech, in professional activities, in fiction, in political
speeches, and in sermons we encounter numerous misuses of speech
that lead to meaningless or nonsensical assertions. These misuses
are sometimes deliberate, whether in jest or from evil intent.
More important for present purposes are abuses of language that
occur unnoticed by the speaker or writer. They can even be found
in scientific practice.
As a general rule, little harm is done when meaningless or nonsensi-
cal propositions arise from careless formulation of correctly observed
circumstances.
The situation is worse if the relations claimed by a proposition are
not yet clearly known, and indeed cannot possibly be known. If such
propositions do not directly conflict with the grammatical rules of
daily speech, then they can hold their ground for a long time and
hinder the progress of knowledge.
4.2 Traditional Philosophy 90
(2) The idealist thesis: “What is real is not the outside world itself;
only the perceptions and imaginings that we have about it are real.”
The second pair comes from ethics and concerns the thesis of util-
itarianism and the formal ethics of Immanuel Kant.
(3) The utilitarian thesis: “The highest aim of moral behavior is the
greatest happiness of the greatest number of mankind.”
(4) Kant’s formal ethics: “Act so that the maxim accepted by your
will could always be valid as the principle of a general legislation.”
centuries was David Hume, with his rejection of all science not built
up upon sense experience; and perhaps the most profound was Im-
manuel Kant, who rejected all metaphysical speculation about God,
the soul, and the world.
Wittgenstein’s criticism goes even further. It embraces the whole
of philosophy; a philosophical statement without exception is either
meaningless or nonsensical. This is so whether we can identify faults
of reasoning or not. The very questions philosophy asks are absurd.
Most of the propositions and questions to be found in philosophical
works are not false but nonsensical. Consequently, we cannot give
any answer to questions of this kind, but can only establish that they
are nonsensical. Most of the propositions and questions of philoso-
phers arise from our failure to understand the logic of our language.
(Tractatus 4.003)
Faced with the attempts of traditional philosophy to make state-
ments about values, consciousness, the meaning of the world, and
so on, we find ourselves in a situation comparable to that of a tech-
nician or examiner in a patent office to whom today, long after the
discovery of the principle of conservation of energy, an invention is
offered that claims to produce perpetual motion. The examiner is
entitled to reject any such patent application, without any obliga-
tion to refer in detail to the defective logic. And this despite the
fact that the description of the invention may be precisely worked
out, and that the inventor likely will charge the examiner with in-
tellectual arrogance.
The comparison is imperfect, since the statements in patent appli-
cations may have perfectly precise meaning, which makes it possible
4.3 Inadmissibility of Philosophical Propositions 95
But this kind of existence is certainly not meant in the two philo-
sophical theses concerning the outside world. The theses deny or
assert that the world outside us is a hallucination. A mentally ill
person might face the same predicament. He cannot tell whether
the world is a hallucination. But in principle that person could es-
tablish by himself that such a perception is deceptive by comparing
it with his other perceptions. Among such perceptions, there might
be words he hears from trustworthy friends. But the kind of reality
which is affirmed or denied by theses (1) and (2) cannot be tested
that way.
if they are true, and what is the case if they are false. This demand
about the truth criterion of the thesis must not be confused with the
question of what happens if the thesis is obeyed and what happens
if it is not obeyed. An ethical thesis claims to be valid even if no
one obeys it. Moreover, there is no way of knowing where to look
for a criterion of the truth or falsity of such a thesis.
Therefore, if an ethical thesis tries to express anything more than
a mere opinion about value, then it is a pseudostatement. This
is always true of propositions dealing with values. Facts, the only
possible objects of communication, contain no value, and among
propositions dealing with facts there is no hierarchy. For they all
necessarily stem from elementary propositions, which are all of equal
value.
If there are any values—and Wittgenstein certainly believes so—
they are not in the world of facts; that is, they do not exist in the
world at all.
The sense of the world must lie outside the world. In the world,
everything is as it is, and everything happens as it does happen; in
it no value exists—and if it did exist, it would have no value.
If there is any value that does have value, it must lie outside the
whole sphere of what happens and is the case. For all that happens
and is the case is accidental. (Tractatus 6.41)
Therefore, there cannot be propositions of ethics. Propositions can
express nothing that is higher. (Tractatus 6.42)
We can indeed follow a system of ethics in our lives; we can also
attract others to it by our example, or by helping them to bring out
neglected feelings and suppressed urges. We can also describe what
4.4 Inadmissible Questions 99
(Indeed, problems that are not part of natural science must be solved.)
(Tractatus 6.4312)
Every person must seek the solution in actively coming to terms
with life. Knowledge of the facts in the world will not help to find
the solution.
All the facts are solely part of the problem, and not part of its so-
lution. (Tractatus 6.4321)
The solution is life itself.
The solution of the problem of life is seen in the vanishing of the
problem.
(Isn’t this the reason why persons to whom the meaning of life be-
came clear after a long struggle with doubts, could not tell what that
meaning consisted of ?) (Tractatus 6.521)
The world of possible communications is limited by what we can
think. This limit has only one side, the one turned toward us. A
wish to formulate the question of what lies beyond this limit already
contains the impossible attempt to cross it.
This is not to say that there does not exist anything uncommuni-
cable, anything that cannot be put into words. We have already
found such things: They are the elementary things. For us, they are
certain a priori; they make themselves manifest. But neither their
nature nor their very existence can be expressed in propositions.
Logical necessities also manifest themselves, but in another way.
They do so in propositions formed with logical correctness; but
they themselves cannot be explained or proved in propositions.
4.4 Inadmissible Questions 101
What field of activity is left for philosophy after all that has been
said? The search for facts must be left to the individual sciences.
Investigation of a priori truths concerns logic and mathematics.
Philosophy cannot even establish propositions.
Philosophy aims at the logical clarification of thoughts.
Philosophy is not a body of doctrine but an activity.
A philosophical work consists essentially of elucidations.
Philosophy does not result in “philosophical propositions,” but rather
in the clarification of propositions.
Without philosophy, thoughts are, as it were, cloudy and indistinct;
its task is to make them clear and to give them sharp boundaries.
(Tractatus 4.112)
The propositions to be clarified by philosophy are above all those
of the sciences. Philosophy investigates the formation of concepts
and thoughts that the sciences make use of, the criteria for judging
the truthfulness of statements and theories, and the usefulness of
hypotheses.
In this sense, the theory of knowledge is the philosophy of psychol-
ogy; it has to inquire what is the meaning of concepts such as “I,”
“the outer world,” and “the will”; and to decide whether relations
put forward about these concepts have any meaning.
5.2 Philosophical Method and the Tractatus 104
When we dealt with the picture theory, we already pointed out that
it is not demonstrable, but that Wittgenstein gives it as a guide for
seeing things correctly. That argument may be acceptable, despite
the danger of optical illusion. But the picture theory is to furnish a
criterion of whether or not a proposition has meaning. Yet for use
in any concrete case, we should have to know, for example, whether
the symbols of a proposition are in their logical form compatible
with one another. But with regard to that problem, there is no
knowledge in the genuine meaning of that word, namely, factual
knowledge.
It seems that all this does not meet Wittgenstein’s requirement that
a philosophical work should consist essentially of elucidations. Here,
the meaning of elucidation is somewhat narrower than the usual one:
Ideas that cannot be defined or only defined with difficulty—such as
the idea of “imagination”—or grammatical forms such as genitive
or dative, can be elucidated by forming propositions in which the
ideas or forms occur.
The propositions used for the purpose of elucidation do not give the
explanation but allow it to become visible. Thereupon, we should
forget these propositions and only retain what has shown itself in
them.
Of course, not all events can reverse their succession in time accord-
ing to the conditions of observation; for this to happen, the events
must be close to each other in time, and far apart in space.
Appendix A 111
Boole, George, 91
cosmogony, 90
curve, simple closed, 45
differentia specifica, 18
Dirac, Paul, 95
disjunction, 78, see also logical
genus proximum, 18
Gödel, Kurt, 92
Hartnack, Justus, 10
Subject Index 120
Hertz, Heinrich, 92
Hilbert, David, 92
Hume, David, 94
necessity, 32
negation, 74
operation, 74
operator, 74
tautology, 71
Mach, Ernst, 92
McGuinness, B. F., 6
meaningful, 73, see also proposition
meaningless, 71, 73, see also proposition
metaphysics, 91, see also philosophy
misuse of language, see language
Morgan, Augustus De, 91
Mounce, Howard O., 9
multiplicity, mathematical, 43
object
ideal, 19
Tractatus definition, 35, 112
observer of speed of light
in motion, 109
Subject Index 122
stationary, 109
operation, 74, see also logical
operator, 74, see also logical
property, 23
complex thing, 24
external, 29
formal, 29
internal, 29
two different meanings, 25
proposition
compound, 75
two contradictory pairs, 92
elementary, 53, 54
formed by logical operations, 75
inadmissibility of philosophical propositions, 93
intention, 85
meaningful, 73
meaningless, 71, 73
negation, 73
nonsensical, 73
ordinary, 54
sense, 67
senseless, 71
sign, 67
simple, 66
structure, 51
universal, 83
pseudo-
answer, 99
proposition, 73
statement, 97
Subject Index 124
question, inadmissible, 99
Sartre, Jean-Paul, 93
saying versus showing, 68
senseless, 71, see also proposition
showing versus saying, 68
sign
relationship with symbol, 63
of generality, 84
special theory of relativity, 110
speed of light, 109
Stegmüller, Wolfgang, 21
structure, picture and reality, 43
symbol, 63, see also proposition
syntax
language, 64
rules defining combinations of words, 64
relation, 17, 21
substance of the world, 34
Tractatus definition, 35, 112
two groups, 16
thought see also proposition
logical picture of facts, 49
process, 50
sense of proposition, 67
time relations in physics, 109
truth possibility, 76