A Faithful Compass: Rethinking The Term Restorative Justice To Find Clarity
A Faithful Compass: Rethinking The Term Restorative Justice To Find Clarity
A Faithful Compass: Rethinking The Term Restorative Justice To Find Clarity
In the field of restorative justice (RJ) there is regular debate regarding the terms
restorative and justice. In spite of efforts to come to a common vision, this
ongoing discussion illustrates how theoretical and practical disagreements have
resulted in RJ being characterized as ambiguous and inconsistent within the
judicial context and beyond. Arising out of research conducted in an educational
context, this paper identifies the impact of this ambiguity on educators. More
importantly, however, it examines the term justice and discovers that an overem-
phasis on justice as fairness and individual rights has pulled the field off-course.
What is needed is a broader understanding of justice, one in which justice is
identified as honoring the inherent worth of all and enacted through relation-
ship. If understood as such, the terms restorative and justice when paired serve
as a much-needed compass needle that guides proponents of RJ in the field to
their desired destinations.
Keywords: restorative justice; restorative practice; restorative justice theory;
transformative justice; education; narrative inquiry
In the field of restorative justice (RJ) there is regular debate over the terms
restorative and justice (Gavrielides, 2008; Johnstone & Van Ness, 2007; Sullivan &
Tifft, 2005). The term restorative frequently leads to questions about what exactly
is being restored. The word justice is problematic as fields engaged with the princi-
ples of RJ such as counseling, education, and the environment tend to replace the
word with terms such as restorative practice, restorative approaches, restorative
schools, etc. in an effort to avoid any potential connotations the term evokes relat-
ing to crime and the judicial system. This ongoing discussion regarding theoretical
and practical perspectives has resulted in RJ being characterized as ambiguous and
inconsistent within the judicial context and beyond (Gavrielides, 2008; Johnstone &
Van Ness, 2007; Sullivan & Tifft, 2005) in spite of efforts to come to a common
vision. These tensions, however, have not impeded the growth of RJ initiatives as
*Email: dvaandering@mun.ca
two administrators were observed over a six-week period as they went about their
daily work. By taking the position of participant-observer and using reflexivity, I
was able to critically examine my own perspectives as well as those of the partici-
pants (Cohen, Manion, & Morrison, 2000; Harding, 1991; Pillow, 2003). Because
of this role, the initial purpose of the study, which was to examine what RJ looked
like, sounded like, and felt like on the ground, expanded to include an analysis of
theoretical frameworks as I began to question my own understanding of RJ. Change
in the researcher is not uncommon in qualitative studies that employ participant-
observation (Denzin, 1978; Patton, 2002; Merriam, 1998). By acknowledging the
change additional insights can emerge which in this case formed the foundation for
this essay, which calls for rethinking the term restorative justice. This coincides
with Toews and Zehr’s (2003) call for ‘finding ways of knowing and doing research
that reflect the values we espouse in restorative justice’ in order to avoid perpetuat-
ing harmful hierarchical power structures (p. 257). In that spirit I included myself
as a participant-observer engaging with the participants in a communal dialogic
manner in the hope that, like in a RJ conference/circle, a fuller story or perspective
of RJ might emerge. Theoretical insights arose as I listened to the different voices
and thus in the context of this article are presented as my personal experience.
address this, I found some clarity by turning to the work of those who were instru-
mental in re-introducing RJ principles and practices in Western society prior to it
entering educational institutions.
Howard Zehr (2005), an early pioneer in the field promoted RJ as a paradigm
shift, a different way of understanding justice, one that acknowledged the needs of
the victim as the purpose of the judicial system and required that the offender be
held accountable for the harm done. This paradigm shift moved the focus from the
inanimate laws and rules being broken, to the harm caused and suffered not just by
those directly involved but also by stakeholders affected indirectly. Zehr’s work,
grounded in a Judeo-Christian, Mennonite perspective, resonated with my own phi-
losophy and provided a framework for comprehending the practical application of
Wachtel and O’Connell.
As a participant-observer in the research, this perspective was deepened with
work that draws more significantly on indigenous cultural responses to brokenness
in community. Pranis, Stuart, and Wedge (2003) as well as Ross (1996) have done
much to highlight and recognize that key RJ principles originate from ancient and
current indigenous traditions that honor the significance of the interconnected nature
of community. Within this interwoven cultural milieu, circle processes are employed
to find ways for all members of the community to learn from each other’s wisdom
in addressing conflict and harm done in the community. This indigenous approach
served to illuminate how harm done has roots in how the community is structured
and interacts. As such it highlighted how RJ is a way of being, a philosophy, and
not simply a response to harm done.
Integrating many of the perspectives put forward to date, more recently
Llewelyn (2009) has presented a comprehensive relational theory to explain why
the judicial system would do well to engage more fully with RJ. Her insights
point to RJ as a ‘restoration of balanced social relations and reparation of harms
and is rooted in values of equality, mutual respect and concern’ (NSRJ-CURA,
2007).
Interspersed throughout these theoretical proposals and discussions on RJ is the
dilemma put forward by justice advocate Morris (1998) that questions the use of
the term restorative. Stating clearly that restorative allows for a reinforcement of
the belief that crime begins with an individual and that it encourages a restoration
to unjust social structures, she calls for transformative justice. Transformative jus-
tice sees crime and harm as an opportunity for transformative healing for the whole
community. She interprets RJ as focusing on an incident of harm whereas transfor-
mative justice takes a broader view recognizing that harm did not begin with the
act but arose out of a community context and cause. Her insights are echoed in the
practice of those seeking to reinforce the view that harm done must result in the
transformation of social structures, not the restoration of structures and relationships
that were the sites for producing the harm in the first place (Lockhardt & Zammit,
2005; Moore, 2004).
All of these perspectives combined reinforce the potential RJ holds for school
communities that are looking for improved interaction with students, but also create
confusion for how to decipher the field and find a way forward for its effective inte-
gration into education. The fault lines Gavrielides (2008) lays out to clarify the
debates in the field provide a structure. Though he chooses the judicial system to
illustrate his observations as it was from here that the current engagement with RJ
arose, he indicates that the fault lines are alive and well in other jurisdictions, such
312 D. Vaandering
as education as I discovered. He lays out six existing debates, five of which address
RJ beyond the judicial context:
Vinegrad (2002) propose dropping the term justice in an effort to focus on relation-
ships. However in doing so, they and others with similar intentions, fall into what
Bianchi (1994) considers to be a fundamental mistake.
They refrain from a discussion and explanation of the concept of justice. This failure
leads to regrettable errors in thinking. Their lack of philosophical reflection on the
concept of justice usually makes the results they achieve practically nil or even the
very contrary of what they intended. (pp. 1–2)
Bianchi’s prediction for ineffective and/or contrary results became evident in this
research challenging me to take seriously the need to explore the concept of justice.
It is important to acknowledge that this argument is not the first of its kind. Bianchi
and Zehr (2005) have made substantial contributions to examining the concept of
justice. However, rarely are these contributions referenced in the RJ literature and
rarely do they effectively guide implementation and practice. It is my intention to
bring it to the foreground again by reflecting on the concept of justice using Bian-
chi and Zehr’s insights and adding the insights of Freire (2005), Buber (1958), and
Wolterstorff (2006, 2008). In this way, I aim to illustrate how a clearer, intentional
understanding of the terms restorative and justice can help to clarify the ambiguity
and inconsistency that exists across the field.
2. Finding North
The theoretical argument for maintaining the term justice is presented in two parts.
First, I illustrate how eliminating the term results in further confusion about what is
being restored and encourages practice for the sake of practice. Second, I demon-
strate how a careful examination of the concept of justice leads to a broader under-
standing that has the potential for providing clarity that will aid in the development
of purposeful, effective, sustainable practice.
Restorative practices is the study of building social capital and achieving social disci-
pline through participatory learning and decision-making. The most critical function of
restorative practices is restoring and building relationships. (IIRP, n.d.)
However, what occurs when the term justice is dropped and replaced by various
other terms in hopes of emphasizing relationship and community, is continued and
perhaps deepened ambiguity. This is illustrated in discussions with administrators
and teachers in the study who after being trained, willingly embrace RJ because
they find it resonates with their approach to education. Yet, among those inter-
viewed (Vaandering, 2009), there was little consistency in terms of identifying and
articulating what is being restored. Emphasis was on RJ as a strategy for better
managing student behavior; few mention it in terms of it being philosophy; as one
participant stated clearly:
For it to be a philosophy you have to use it every single time without any other . . .
but a tool is something you use, you have a little bag of tricks and if the need arises
for restorative practice it’s a really good one to use. . . I don’t consider it a philosophy
because that would mean I use it all the time no matter what. (Vaandering, 2009, p.
245)
Why, in spite of significant training and eliminating the use of the term justice
does this inconsistency and ambiguity continue? I propose three reasons:
First, because schools have ‘traditionally adopted a quasi-judicial approach to
the management of student misconduct, modeled on existing western criminal jus-
tice systems’ (Thorsborne & Vinegrad, 2002, p. 9), school administrators are
attracted to the effectiveness RJ has had in the judicial context. Thus, many seeking
to address issues of violence, bullying, and harassment after initial attempts using
zero-tolerance policies had failed and alienated students, continue to associate RJ
with student behavior and management strategies. Like in the judicial context,
because past policies and codes of conduct are rooted in an entrenched adversarial
approach to addressing behavioral issues, RJ tends to be integrated into schools
alongside the previous adversarial code. When it appears the restorative approach
does not have the immediate desired outcome, the default position in the midst of a
hectic school day becomes the more adversarial procedures with which most people
Contemporary Justice Review 315
are familiar. Thus, dropping the term justice does not eliminate underlying connota-
tions; simply changing the term does not ensure that the underlying purpose for
implementing RJ is about relationships. A careful analysis of policy statements of
schools and districts committed to RJ indicate this clearly. Because schools histori-
cally have been hierarchical institutions, it is very difficult to change the retributive,
adversarial language that has led to the problems in the first place (Vaandering,
2009). This is an echo of what Eisler (2000) states when she describes a domina-
tion model of schooling that is based on submission and coercion, a model that was
and continues to be prevalent, and a model that we will ‘unwittingly reinforce’
unless we understand how they were created (pp. 9–13).
This traditional quasi-judicial, dominator model also puts educators in a difficult
position as the lack of clarity and various terms attached to restorative encourages
them to waffle back and forth between understanding RJ as a response to behavior
and a way of being. They feel a social expectation to be in control as a teacher,
thereby prompting them to return to the ‘judicial’ understanding of RJ. Yet inher-
ently they know it is a strong relational partnership model (Eisler, 2000) that will
provide an atmosphere where they can set clear expectations and provide adequate
support for nurturing academic and social well-being of students.
Second, deepened ambiguity results when the word restorative is paired with
terms such as ‘discipline’ or ‘school’ or ‘approach.’ Changing the term increases
the confusion in regard to what is being restored as it opens up whole new arrays
of possibilities. Is it a person, a relationship, a school, someone’s possessions or
dignity? Is it the school’s sense of control, or ability to produce informed citizens?
Without clearly defining what is being restored, educators are quick to make
assumptions about what it means and most often that tends to be something they
want it to mean so that it reflects their personal approach and philosophy. This is
the route of least resistance requiring little change on their part and leads to the fre-
quent response that RJ is ‘what we’ve always been doing anyway.’ Educators, tired
of being required to engage with new initiatives, look for permission to avoid what
RJ has to offer if they sense it will require change on their part (Vaandering, 2009).
Finally, dropping the term justice contributes to ambiguity and the creation of
fault-lines in the field because the focus shifts to more practical aspects of the word
when attached to a different term. For example, restorative discipline shifts attention
to how-to discipline more effectively; restorative schools shifts attention to how-to be
school; restorative approaches focuses on some aspect of how-to be students, educa-
tors or schools. With the more ambiguous, conflicted term justice out of the way, train-
ing is permitted to race or gloss over philosophical and theoretical foundations in
order to get to the how-to of education. This is what appeals to educators who are
looking for quick, effective solutions to the challenges they face in the classroom. One
trainer conscious of this desire for the practical and eager to convey the usefulness of
RJ, introduces his session stating, ‘This is a workshop about practice, not philosophy,
not theory, but practice.’ (Vaandering, 2009). As a result, schools engaged with RJ run
the risk of implementing RJ practice simply for the sake of effective practice not for
the sake of the building relationships and promoting healing.
Eliminating the term justice does not ensure or contribute to the hoped for
development of a relational, partnership school culture, as doing so will not address
the structure and policies governing the institution. For change to occur, the power
relationships underlying past ineffective practices must be challenged (Eisler, 2000;
Morrison, 2005) and harm must be recognized not as an individual behavioral
316 D. Vaandering
incident but rather as a breach in relationship among people and/or the system of
which they are a part (Jones, 2004; Lindstrom, 2007; Morrison, 2005). To accom-
plish this, I argue that engaging with a broader understanding of the concept of
justice is necessary.
Paulo Freire (2005) primarily grapples with what it means to be human in his
seminal work Pedagogy of the Oppressed in an effort to comprehend how to stop
the harm done to peasants in an oppressive regime. Poignantly, he points out that
people have come to accept that they are ‘beings for others’ reduced to the level of
object by an oppressive, powerful minority. He refutes this perspective that humans
are adaptable, manageable beings and calls for transformed social structures that
allow people to become ‘beings for themselves,’ with an ontological vocation of
becoming more fully human (pp. 73–75). Freire simplifies this by distinguishing
between people living ‘to be’ and living ‘to be like’ (p. 48). People living to be like
are forever seeking approval and direction limiting their potential to discover their
uniqueness. They become imprisoned or are convinced that to be imprisoned in the
control of another is acceptable and inescapable. People living to be grow to recog-
nize themselves as human and thus begin the journey of discovering more fully
what it means to be human. They discover that freedom is the point at which they
stretch to take on their capacity to be human. With this common vocation recog-
nized and in place, incidents of harm and oppression are reduced as people allow
the other to be more fully human as well. Freire commits his life to challenging
people to recognize when they have been reduced to the level of an object or have
become someone who dehumanizes others, treating them as objects and thereby
ultimately turning themselves into an object. For Freire to be human means to be
engaged in ‘being’ a subject that initiates living, not an object that exists to be
acted upon or to act on other objects.
This understanding of what it means to be human is echoed in Buber’s (1958)
influential writing I-Thou where he identifies that ‘all real living is meeting’ (p. 25).
Though Buber does not focus on the results of objectification, he clearly identifies
that being human occurs when people engage in relationships where they honor
each other as human. He explains this in terms of the well-known I-Thou relation-
ships:
The primary word I-Thou can be spoken only with the whole being. Concentration
and fusion into the whole being can never take place through my agency, nor can it
ever take place without me. I become through my relation to the Thou; and as I
become the I, I say Thou. (pp. 24–25, emphasis in original)
If I face a human being as my Thou, and say the primary word I-Thou to him, he is
not a thing among things, and does not consist of things... (p. 16, emphasis in origi-
nal)
state. relationships.
Figure 1. Two different views of justice (Zehr, 2002). Reprinted from The Little Book of
Restorative Justice. Ó by Good Books (www.GoodBooks.com). Used by permission. All
rights reserved.
Contemporary Justice Review 319
humans not to objects. Freire (2005) makes this clear when he explains that when
people are viewed as objects the cycle of dehumanization sets in as it is then possi-
ble to justify doing anything to them because objects exist to be acted upon and
can be broken, but cannot be harmed.
Seen in this way, harm is injury inflicted on or against a person in any capacity
they hold as a human being – physical, emotional, social. It is here that justice
moves beyond the boundaries it has been given by the judicial system.
If meting out justice and rendering judgment become relevant when injustice has
occurred or is said to have occurred, then there has to be another kind of justice and
injustice than that of meting out justice and rendering judgment. There has to be a jus-
tice which has been violated or said to have been violated. There has to be a kind of
justice which has broken down or is said to have broken down. Call that kind of jus-
tice, ‘primary justice’. Only when primary justice has broken down or is said to have
broken down do rendering judgement and meting out justice enter the picture. (p. 25)
need rather than merit, when it is understood as an act of liberation and of love
which seeks to make right relationships, its concern is not with measuring if all
individuals have equal basic liberties and rights, but rather with how to make things
better for the poor and oppressed (pp. 136–157). Specifically, Zehr (2005) indicates
that questions of crime and harm done to others cannot be separated from questions
of poverty and power (p.153).
This discussion must also acknowledge Rawls’s (2001) seminal work Justice as
Fairness. This work has had a significant impact on Western society today as his
theory encourages a two-pronged understanding of justice – distributive and retribu-
tive. In an effort to access the notion of justice, Rawls idealizes that in a perfect
democratic society ‘justice as fairness’ would be the most appropriate system for
social cooperation. Here, each person would have two basic rights: (a) the same
indefeasible claim to a fully adequate scheme of equal basic liberties (i.e., the dis-
tributive principle); and (b) social and economic inequality, only when it exists if
one is attached to an office open to all or if the inequality is seen to be to the great-
est benefit to the least advantaged (i.e., the difference principle). Though these two
prongs may well seem to align with Wolterstorff’s (2008) perceptions of justice and
include a deep respect and honor for people (Rawls is often seen as being the origi-
nator of social justice [Pogge, 2007]), Rawls’s principles essentially provide the
basis for justice as deserts wherein what people are entitled to depends on what
they do or do not do (p. 72). Though Rawls’s intention may be a society where all
are honored equally, his emphasis on fairness encourages people to examine how
they are like others which then according to what Freire and Buber indicate, leads
to objectification. Zehr (2005) identifies this as an overemphasis of individual rights
that measures if all individuals have equal basic liberties and rights and precludes
our responsibility to honor each other as worthy human beings.
Justice as shalom, justice as tsedeka, primary justice, social justice, justice as
inherent rights all speak of justice where humans are respected as subjects that are
nurtured and set free through respectful relationship. Justice honors the worth of the
other, where honor is a praxis that encapsulates both the active relationship and
respect for the other. This understanding of justice is what I propose has been
usurped by an overemphasis on justice as fairness and individual rights that the
judicial system is intent on implementing. It is the difference between doing justice
and due justice. Thus what is needed in the field of restorative justice is a concerted
effort to remind all people that
justice is a call to recognize that all humans are worthy and to be honored
simply because they are human;
injustice occurs when people are objectified;
and the term restorative becomes meaningful as it specifically refers to restor-
ing people to a state of being honored as human.
Understood in this manner, it is crucial that the terms restorative and justice be
maintained and paired to provide the much needed reference point that has been
lacking. The field has been functioning in many instances like a compass without a
needle. Justice understood in its primary sense serves as the consistent reference
point, always reminding us what it is to be human. The term restorative justice
serves as the compass needle that allows us all to keep our bearings as RJ moves
into different fields and directions.
Contemporary Justice Review 321
conferencing, peer mediation, and problem solving circles for the purpose of man-
aging difficulties and disruption arising with some students with the goal of repair-
ing relationships. The peak of the triangle represents full restorative justice
conference approaches taken with 1–5% of the population that require intensive
attention for the rebuilding of relationships.
Looking through the lens of justice as honoring the worth of the other, this
whole school model of restorative justice also has no foundation to draw upon.
Though there is consistency evident throughout each of the levels in regard to an
emphasis on relationship, there is nothing in place that will prevent the approaches
from encouraging participants to remain or slip further into objectification of each
other. This is evident in the fact that each of the three levels of the triangle exists
primarily to target inappropriate, disruptive behavior. It could be argued that the pri-
mary level is proactive and thus focused not on behavior but relationship. However,
in describing this primary level, Morrison (2007) indicates, ‘the aim is to develop
and affirm students’ social and emotional competencies and skills, particularly in
the area of conflict resolution, so that students are able to resolve differences in
respectful and caring ways’ (p. 107, emphasis added). Looking back at the discus-
sion of what it means to be human, this theoretical approach teeters as a result of
placing significant emphasis on relationship while forgetting about the reason for
striving for positive relationship.
What my argument contributes to Blood and Morrison’s (2007) model is a foun-
dation out of which each of the three they suggest can grow. The goal of this level
however is different than that of changing or managing student behavior. Its empha-
sis would be identified as our common human vocation of ‘becoming more fully
human’ (Freire, 2005) through relationship. This foundation provides a definite pur-
pose for the encounters we have with each other in schools and reinforces the call-
ing of schools to be institutions of learning rather than institutions that exist to
control behavior.
Looking back now to the fault-lines that Gavrielides (2008) suggests, defining
justice as honoring the worth of the other through relationship provides a means
for assessing the purpose of each of the differences. Here the practical contribu-
tion of having a common reference point becomes evident. For example, in regard
to fault line #1 the question can be asked, does RJ as a new paradigm honor the
worth of the other and support a common vocation of becoming more fully
human through relationship? If yes, than it can be accepted as a RJ principle.
Does RJ as a pragmatic parallel approach honor the worth of the other? Again if
yes, then it continues as it is. But if it becomes evident in a school either
approach does not honor students, then students are at risk of being turned into
objects, and continuing in this manner will undermine the potential of RJ as co-
optation will occur. This is a very serious concern as RJ will then be used to
harm and manipulate the people involved under the guise of being committed to
repairing harm.
Each of Gavrielides fault-lines could be assessed in a similar manner to gauge
and inform the various principles that are being adhered to in the field. Fault-line
#2: Does the RJ process employed provide people with a greater sense of their
humanity? Does the outcome of the RJ practice acknowledge that all involved are
human? Fault-line #3: Does the mediation allow for participants to participate in
such a way that the humanity of all stakeholders is enhanced? Does the RJ confer-
ence that includes all stakeholders provide a process that guides participation that
Contemporary Justice Review 323
practices, the curriculum and pedagogy, sent messages that honored or measured
school participants. Educators, myself included, became painfully aware that how
we spoke to our students was often from a place of dominance where we were
commanding students rather than dialoguing with them; it became evident that the
math problem solving questions encouraged selfish measuring and judging with
their attempts at motivating students to buy and sell, enlarge their property and
count their possessions; assessment and evaluation strategies became glaring exam-
ples of objectifying students where after spending weeks encouraging and support-
ing them in their efforts to learn, a test or report card mark proclaimed loudly that
they did or did not measure up. Again wherever we turned we realized that choos-
ing to honor people was counter-cultural and that the educational institution was in
most cases not designed to honor the people it served. Implementing RJ required
commitment, and that commitment as teachers and administrators express, is
exhausting (Vaandering, 2009).
In spite of the effort required to honor people as worthy, along with exhaustion,
comes a perspective on living that resonates with who we are as human beings. It
is this perspective that Zehr (2005) speaks of as a paradigm shift, and that Freire
(2005) identifies as a cultural revolution. That revolution takes place in and through
the lives of individuals and communities who live the reality that RJ is a way of
being, a life style, a worldview, a philosophy. If we can honor people regardless of
what they do or say, regardless of whether they have committed a crime, broken a
school rule, or hurt another human being, we consider what we can do that would
allow them to be more fully human, to be free. If we honor people it opens the
door to recognizing them as part of a broader community that has an impact on oth-
ers. We recognize more fully what we would feel like if we were in their shoes.
Honoring people sends us seeking ways to maintain and build connections; measur-
ing people allows us to think of people as disposable objects and we have no prob-
lem cutting our connections with them.
Though there have been many attempts at defining RJ that have accumulated to
a point where there seems to be a tradition that says RJ resists a complete definition
(Wheeldon, 2009), I believe the following contribution may be significant. I submit
it in the hope that perhaps it will contribute a sense of stability and consistency in
the field while at the same time be flexible enough to allow the various jurisdictions
freedom to develop effective processes and outcomes.
RJ acknowledges justice as honoring the inherent worth of all and is enacted through
relationship. As such it affects all social structures. When something occurs that
undermines the well-being of some, RJ provides a space for dialogue so that the
humanity of all involved and affected can be restored and each person can once again
become a fully contributing member of the community of which they are a part.
As different proponents and fields engaging with RJ grow and encounter road-
blocks, keeping in mind the essence of what it means to be human and challenging
ourselves to reflect critically on our own actions, there is greater potential for RJ
guiding significant social structural change in a wide variety of contexts.
come, and foundational philosophy. If understood as such it narrows the gap created
by RJ practice continuing to march ahead of theory and suggests a concrete solution
that contributes to clearing up the ambiguity and inconsistency that currently pla-
gues the field and holds it back from being more widely and deeply effective.
As a final illustration of this and as a challenge for all proponents of RJ I reiter-
ate the insights of Dyck (2006) who states in Reaching toward a structurally
responsive training and practice of restorative justice:
It is puzzling to see how many proponents of restorative justice can limit their focus
to only the correctional aspects of restorative justice . . . and refuse to take into
account the ‘transformative,’ economic, and structural dimensions of justice, that is,
the social structural conditions that constrain the lives of us all and affect the extent to
which any one of us can live restorative lives. (p. 537)
complex journey and one that requires a faithful compass with a needle that keeps
us headed in a definite direction.
Acknowledgement
This research was supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of
Canada.
References
Amstutz, L., & Mullet, J. (2005). The little book of restorative discipline for schools. Inter-
course, PA: Good Books.
Bianchi, H. (1994). Justice as sanctuary. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Braithwaite, J. (1989). Crime, shame and reintegration. Cambridge: University Press.
Braithwaite, J. (2004). Emancipation and hope. The ANNALS of the American Academy of
Political and Social Science, 79–98.., (4), 7.
Buber, M. (1958). I and thou (R. Gregory Smith Trans.). Edinburg: T&T Clark.
Buber, M., & Agassi, J.B. (1999). Martin Buber on psychology and psychotherapy: Essays,
letters, and dialogue. Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Press.
Cohen, L., Manion, L., & Morrison, K. (2000). Research methods in education. London:
Routledge & Falmer.
Cronin-Lampe, K., & Cronin-Lampe, R. (2010). Developing a restorative school culture:
The blending of a personal and professional ‘pilgrimage’. Explorations: An E-Journal of
Narrative Practice. Retrieved from www.dulwichcentre.com.au/explorations-2010-1-kath-
and-ron-cronin-lampe.pdf
Denzin, N. (1978). The research act: A theoretical introduction to sociological methods
(2nd ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill.
Doornai, A. (2009). Restorative practices for safe and supportive schools. Canadian Teacher,
5(4), 7.
Dyck, D. (2006). Reaching toward a structurally responsive training and practice of restor-
ative justice. In D. Sullivan & L. Tifft (Eds.), Handbook of restorative justice: A global
perspective (pp. 527–45). London: Routledge.
Eisler, R.T. (2000). Tomorrow’s children: A blueprint for partnership education in the 21st
century. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Freire, P. (2005). Pedagogy of the oppressed (3rd ed.). New York: Continuum.
Gavrielides, T. (2008). Restorative justice – The perplexing concept: Conceptual fault-lines
and power battles within the restorative justice movement. Criminology & Criminal Jus-
tice, 8(2), 165–183.
Harding, S. (1991). Strong objectivity and socially situated knowledge. In Whose science?
Whose knowledge? (pp. 138–163). New York: Cornell University Press.
Harris, M.K. (2006). Transformative justice: The transformation of restorative justice. In D.
Sullivan & L. Tifft (Eds.), Handbook of restorative justice: A global perspective (p.
555–566). London: Routledge.
Harris, N. (2006). Reintegrative shaming, shame, and criminal justice. Journal of Social
Issues, 62(2), 327–346.
Hopkins, B. (2004). Just schools: A whole school approach to restorative justice. London:
Jessica Kingsley.
IIRP (n.d.). What is restorative practices? Retrieved January 2008 from http://www.iirp.org/
whatisrp.php
IIRP (2003). Roundtable discussions 2 (video). Bethlehem, PA: International Institute for
Restorative Practices.
Johnstone, G., & Van Ness, D.W. (2007). Handbook of restorative justice. Portland, OR:
Willan.
Jones, T.S. (2004). Conflict resolution education: The field, the findings, and the future. Con-
flict Resolution Quarterly, 22(1–2), 233–267.
Lindstrom, S.R. (2007). Review of school violence intervention best practices. Context: The
Journal Recognizing Student Health Professionals Engaged in Their Communities, 1
(Fall).
Contemporary Justice Review 327
Llewellyn, J. (2009). Relating to justice. Paper presented at the national restorative justice
symposium, St. John’s, NL.
Lockhart, A., & Zammit, L. (2005). Restorative justice: Transforming society. Toronto:
Inclusion Press.
Maxwell, G., & Morris, A. (2004). What is the place of shame in restorative justice? In Crit-
ical issues in restorative justice (pp. 133–142). Monsey, NY: Criminal Justice Press.
Merriam, S.B. (1998). Qualitative research and case study applications in education. San
Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
Moore, D.B. (2004). Managing social conflict–the evolution of a practical theory. Journal of
Sociology & Social Welfare 31(1), 71(21).
Morris, R. (1998). Why transformative justice? Paper presented at the ICCPPC World Con-
gress, Mexico City.
Morrison, B. (2005). Building safe and healthy school communities: Restorative justice and
responsive regulation. International Institute for Restorative Practices 6th International
Conference.
Morrison, B. (2007). Restoring safe school communities. Sydney, Australia: Federation
Press.
Morrison, B., & Ahmed, E. (2006). Restorative justice and civil society: Emerging practice,
theory, and evidence. Journal of Social Issues, 62(2), 209–215.
Nathanson, D. (1996). Knowing feeling: Affect, script, and psychotherapy. New York: W.W.
Norton.
Noddings, N. (1999). Care, justice, and equity. In M.S. Katz, N. Noddings & K.A. Strike
(Eds.), Justice and caring: The search for common ground in education (pp. 7–20). New
York: Teachers College Press.
NSRJ-CURA (2007). Introduction. Retrieved from http://www.nsRJ-cura.ca
Patton, M.Q. (2002). Qualitative research & evaluation methods. Sage.
Peterson, D., & Rau, C. (n.d.). Restorative justice in the classroom: Lesson 2 class meetings.
Retrieved from http://www.sacs.ca
Pillow, W. (2003). Confession, catharsis, or cure? Rethinking the uses of reflexivity as meth-
odological power in qualitative research Qualitative Studies in Education, 16(2), 175–
196.
Pogge, T. (2007). John Rawls: His life and theory of justice. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Pranis, K. (2005). The little book of circle process: A new/old approach to peacemaking.
Intercourse, PA: Good Books.
Pranis, K., Stuart, B., & Wedge, M. (2003). Peacemaking circles: From crime to community.
St Paul, MN: Living Justice Press.
Rawls, J. (2001). Justice as fairness: A restatement. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of
Harvard University Press.
Ross, R. (1996). Returning to the teachings: Exploring aboriginal justice. Toronto: Penguin.
Sawatsky, J. (2009). The ethic of traditional communities and the spirit of healing justice.
studies from Hollow Water, the Iona Community, and Plum Village. London: Jessica
Kingsley.
Sherman, L., & Strang, H. (2007). Restorative justice: The evidence. London: The Smith
Institute.
Sullivan, D., & Tifft, L. (2005). Restorative justice: Healing the foundations of our everyday
lives. Monsey, NY: Willow Tree.
Thorsborne, M., & Vinegrad, D. (2002). Restorative practices in schools: Rethinking behav-
ior management. Queensland: Inyahead Press.
Toews, B., & Zehr, H. (2003). Ways of knowing for a restorative worldview. In E.G.M.
Weitekamp & H.-J. Kerner (Eds.), Restorative justice in context: International practice
and directions (pp. 257–271). Cullompton, UK: Willan.
Vaandering, D. (2008). Dissertation field notes.
Vaandering, D. (2009). Towards effective implementation and sustainability of restorative
justice in Ontario public schools: A critical case study. Unpublished dissertation, Univer-
sity of Western Ontario, London.
Wachtel, T. (1997). Real justice. Pipersville, PA: Piper’s Press.
328 D. Vaandering