Representative Democracy and Democratic Citizens: Philosophical and Empirical Understandings
Representative Democracy and Democratic Citizens: Philosophical and Empirical Understandings
Representative Democracy and Democratic Citizens: Philosophical and Empirical Understandings
Delivered at
[231]
232 The Tanner Lectures on Human Values
Šrm sense of their own identity, with their own goods in their
hands, caught up in their everyday troubles. . . .”3 Walzer cer-
tainly seems to invoke a real public with a real set of opinions.
What about those philosophers who seek to develop general,
perhaps universal, principles of political morality on the basis of
logic and thought experiments, rather than information about the
real world of citizens? John Rawls, in The Theory of Justice,4 starts
in an imagined world of rational people in a contrived state of ig-
norance as to who they are. Even here, one has the sense that one
will have sometime to face the issue of what people will actually
do and actually think. Rawls assumes a citizenry capable of reason,
of cooperation, and of conceptions of the good; reasoning, cooper-
ative, and moral citizens. These attributes are discussed at a most
abstract level, but they are attributes that are (or at least could be)
real. Rawls moves closer to the public in Political Liberalism, where
he asks how one can have a stable society when there exist multiple
conceptions of morality that are not compatible with each other.
In this book, the public is a more palpable entity. He states in the
opening of the book, “We start then, by looking at the public cul-
ture itself as the shared fund of implicitly recognized basic ideas
and principles.”5
A public philosophy is, thus, not a philosopher’s philosophy. It
seems to be something out there; something that needs to be dis-
covered and taken into account. But it is hard to deŠne and hard
to Šnd. “A public philosophy is an elusive thing, for it is con-
stantly before our eyes. It forms the often unrešective background
to our political discourse and disputes.”6 In saying this, Sandel
echoes comments by James Bryce a century ago about public opin-
ion in America. Bryce noted that nowhere is public opinion more
3 Ibid., p. 5.
4 John Rawls, The Theory of Justice (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,
1971).
5 John Rawls, Political Liberalism (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993).
6 Sandel, Democracy’s Discontent, p. 4.
[Verba] Representative Democracy 233
explanation: What causes the values that people hold? What are
the consequences of those values? They pitch their arguments
against alternative methods or alternative descriptions or alterna-
tive explanations.
I hasten to add that we ought not to take the distinction too far.
Few normative philosophers ignore facts, and some pay a lot of at-
tention. Few empirical researchers deny the normative founda-
tions or implications of their work. Facts and values are not as
sealed off from one another as some once tried to make them. But
normative philosophers and empirical social scientists seem ani-
mated by different concerns and largely go about their businesses
differently.
But for both, the issue of the public philosophy or public opin-
ion is a problem. How then does one ascertain what the public
thinks and how the public thinks? Does it even make sense to ask
about such matters? Normative philosophers Šnd public opinion
elusive. No systematic social scientist who has worked on the sub-
ject would disagree.
There are several reasons for this elusiveness. Citizen values are
not immediately apparent. Philosophers tell us about their nor-
mative systems. That is their business. Citizens have no such obli-
gation. They do not spend time ruminating about their normative
systems, nor do they write treatises explicating and justifying
them. If one is interested in such values, one has to go out and Šnd
them.
There is a further problem in the empirical study of citizen
values and preferences: the fact that they must be studied on two
levels, that of the individual and that of the aggregate. The conse-
quence of citizen values for political outcomes depends not on in-
dividual values and preferences but on the aggregate of values and
preferences manifested in various ways—as votes, as public opin-
ion, as communications to political elites, and so on. This second
level of values—the values of aggregates—adds additional difŠ-
culty to the observation of citizen attitudes. Measuring the values
[Verba] Representative Democracy 235
A Consideration of Method
describing what each believes and how they got there. But it is not
easy, probably impossible, to sum up a multitude of such biogra-
phies to understand a large population. To add up values across in-
dividuals requires that we reduce those values to comparable and
countable items and, in so doing, we lose some of the substance of
that which we count.
The problem is a general one—not only for the social scientist
but for actual political choice and action situations across a large
population. James C. Scott has written most interestingly about
the attempt by governments to control societies by making them
“legible”—that is, by standardizing things (people, towns, trans-
actions) so that they can be counted or regulated. People and ob-
jects need to be put in categories (laws of course depend on
categories), observational techniques need to be standardized, ac-
counting schemes need to be devised. All of this smooths out the
edges of a reality that is much more complex and contextually var-
ied. Scott focuses on the pathologies this can create but realizes
that some such systematization is needed in any complex society.
The problem Scott identiŠes in relation to the action of states is
a well-known problem in the social sciences. He calls his book See-
ing Like a State.9 If it were a book on social science methodology, it
might be called Seeing Like a Social Scientist. Social scientists (or at
least some of us) consider the task of social science to be one of
making society legible, to Šnd order out of the chaotic business of
everyday life. We, like bureaucrats, tax collectors, and planners—
among other unpleasant people—like to have people neatly cate-
gorized. But, just as Scott worries about the pathologies associated
with this as states use such information to impose a rigid order
to society that is destructive of ordinary practices, so one might
worry that systematic social science bleaches out reality in its at-
tempt to systematize.
In democratic politics, the best example of the simpliŠcation
9 James C. Scott, Seeing Like a State: How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human Condi-
tion Have Failed (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1998).
240 The Tanner Lectures on Human Values
Democratic Citizens
Democratic Dilemmas
about the public from surveys. The substantive issue I shall con-
sider relates to a major democratic dilemma associated with citi-
zen participation in a democracy. It is interesting how commonly
the words “democracy” and “dilemma” seem to go together.
When not acting as a social scientist, I am the director of the Har-
vard University Library, and I sometimes look at our electronic
catalogue just to see what one can learn from the catalogue re-
cords. I found over sixty records that contain the words “democ-
racy” and “dilemma.” Apparently authors like to put the terms
together. Democracy seems to pose a dilemma in relation to,
among other things, religion, bureaucracy, secrecy, science, social-
ism, nationalism, funding of the arts, school desegregation, au-
thority, national defense, in a number of titles Germany, and—for
whatever it means—the future. This is not surprising. Democracy
as a system spawns dilemmas and contradictions. The very term
“democratic government” is contradictory. “Democracy” refers to
the people, to control from below, to procedures for giving citizens
a voice over decisions. “Government” refers to policies, to author-
itative decisions, to control from above, to the means for making
effective policies. This is the dilemma I wish to explore from the
perspective of the role of the public in democratic governance: can
one have a democracy that gives the citizenry substantial and
equal voice over public affairs and at the same time produces effec-
tive and just policies?
Let me spell this out. Citizen voice and participation are at the
center of the democratic half of democratic government. Through
participation citizens express their preferences to governing ofŠ-
cials and induce them to respond to those preferences. They send
information about themselves (who they are, what they want,
what they need) and apply pressure on ofŠcials for some response.
Citizens do this in many ways: by voting, working in political
campaigns, writing letters, taking part in community actions,
protests, and on and on. The sum of these activities represents the
way in which democratic voice is expressed.
[Verba] Representative Democracy 243
needs? And why an equal voice? For some the answer lies in the
belief that all people are equal before God. A more secular set of
reasons expressed by such democratic thinkers as Robert Dahl and
John Rawls is that people are reasoning beings, capable of under-
standing the world; and that they are moral beings, capable of
conceptions of the good. What does this mean for the ordinary cit-
izen, and why is it the principle on which equal citizen voice is
grounded? For one thing, it means that citizens should be good (or
at least adequate) moral reasoners. Their preferences and values,
whatever their substance, should have some coherence and be
somewhat stable. If preferences and values change from moment
to moment, or if they are incoherent and self-contradictory, it is
hard to know how they can be given meaningful expression. Also,
citizens should be good (or at least adequate) social scientists.
They should have enough information to know how to pursue
their goals through politics. They should be capable of making
causal inferences about how their activity might lead to desired
outcomes (for instance, to be able to Šgure out, in the light of their
preferred policy outcomes, whom to vote for or how one policy
rather than another will affect their welfare). If they cannot reason
about the political world, what do their expressed preferences
mean?
Thus, democratic voice would seem to rest on some capacity of
citizens to be moral reasoners and social scientiŠc reasoners. It may
rest on another quality of ordinary citizens: their willingness to
transcend their own values and preferences. There are two compo-
nents of this willingness. One is a willingness to look beyond their
own narrow self-interest to consider the common good and the
other their willingness to commit to (or at least accept) principles
of fair democratic procedure that allow a multiplicity of view-
points or doctrines to be expressed. Some would argue that the
Šrst is not necessary: let self-interest rule and an invisible hand
will provide good social outcomes. This may work in the market-
place of commodities; I believe (though I cannot argue the case
[Verba] Representative Democracy 245
fully here) that it does not apply in the making of public policy
through the political process. The second is more unambiguously
tied to democracy. Rawls refers to this as a free-standing overlap-
ping consensus on a democratic process that involves tolerating al-
ternative doctrines. This, as he notes and as many democratic
theorists have noted before, is needed to maintain a stable democ-
racy given the inevitable plurality of competing doctrines sub-
scribed to by citizens in a democracy.
But what if citizens are not up to the task: if they are inade-
quate moral reasoners or social scientists—if they don’t know
what they want or how to get it? What if they can’t be relied upon
to go beyond their own preferred value system to allow others to
exist? Democratic voice becomes meaningless or undesirable. Or
what if citizens are unequally equipped for moral reasoning or so-
cial science analysis? Some are competent, others not. And what if
they are unequally committed to democratic procedures? Equal
democratic voice might be meaningless or undesirable. These con-
siderations have led many philosophers of democratic government
to express skepticism about the public, about too much democ-
racy, about populist democracy. The voice of the people, un-
checked, coming equally from those who might be expected to be
more democratically competent and supportive of democratic
principles and from others who are less so, might be dangerous for
democracy. And systematic social science studies have supported
that position. Yet without voice and without equal voice, what
happens to the equal consideration of the needs and preferences of
all?
This is the democratic dilemma of my lectures. Equal citizen
voice is needed for equal consideration of needs and preferences.
Equal citizen voice may be disruptive of effective government and
dangerous to democracy. I want to look more closely at what we
know about citizen voice and public opinion to see if this is the
case.
In this look at citizens, I am interested less in the substance of
246 The Tanner Lectures on Human Values
So let us look more closely at the data—with all due caution about
the weakness of systematic data but, I hope, with respect for what
it can tell us. I will proceed as follows. I want to begin with work
I have been doing for a number of years on political equality, more
speciŠcally equality in political participation. This is not exactly
the same thing as political voice but close to it if we think of par-
ticipation as the means by which citizens exercise their political
voice—by which they communicate their interests and prefer-
ences to governing elites and induce them to respond. It is empir-
ical research based on large-scale surveys of what citizens do, work
done collaboratively with Kay L. Schlozman and Henry E. Brady.
I want to summarize this research briešy and then connect it,
more than it has been connected, to normative issues of political
equality.
Our work begins with the basic principle of equality men-
tioned earlier: that in a democracy citizens ought to receive equal
[Verba] Representative Democracy 247
and database or television time, more than they want people who
can walk the streets or stuff envelopes.
This increases the stratiŠcation of political activity for the sim-
ple and obvious reason that money is a stratiŠed resource, time is
not. The rich have money; the poor don’t. All of us, rich and poor,
seem to have as much—or as little—time.
From the point of view of our evaluation of political inequality,
it makes a difference whether the inequality in political voice is
based on a disparity in motivation or a disparity in resources. If the
former is the reason—people prefer to stay home and watch televi-
sion rather than turning out to vote or going to a community
meeting; or they prefer a few more hours in the ofŠce rather than
getting involved in a political campaign—we would be less con-
cerned with the fact that their voice is not heard. If it is a matter of
“they can’t”—because of resource inadequacy—then there is a
more serious problem. Our research on citizen participation shows
that, though both motivation and resources play a role, the latter
seem to be a much greater inhibitor of activity than the former.
Such resource disparities are, however, hard to remove. One
can imagine limiting the use of money in politics. That is what
campaign Šnance legislation in the United States attempts. It is
ineffective because of the inventiveness of campaign managers.
Furthermore, the U.S. Supreme Court has severely restricted the
extent to which one can limit the use of money in politics, arguing
that it inhibits free speech. There are many who disagree with that
interpretation and who might argue that speech is freer when the
ability to speak is more equal. But the Supreme Court ruling
stands. In American English—I don’t know about British Eng-
lish—there is the saying that “Money talks.” It is truly appropri-
ate for American politics, for money talks loudly and receives
constitutional protection as a form of speech.
In any case, even if there were limitations on money, it would
be difŠcult to go beyond limiting money to limit other resources.
Few of us would think it appropriate to limit the use of one’s
250 The Tanner Lectures on Human Values
That is our story in a nutshell. But let me come back to the open-
ing normative principle and make it a question: should all voices
be equal? Let’s look at that from two perspectives: the substance of
what is communicated to the government in terms of citizen pol-
icy preferences and citizen need (when citizens use their political
voice, what do they communicate?) and in terms of the quality of
[Verba] Representative Democracy 251
you where you want to go. The information acquired through the
use of a heuristic may not be valid. It may be irrelevant to the issue
at hand, wrong, or biased. Citizens who take information from
others often select those near at hand or those who share their
views. This is the road to biased information. There is, however,
evidence from an interesting study by Robert Huckfeldt that,
though individuals do use the criterion of shared views in choos-
ing information sources, they can tell who is informed and who is
not and they choose information also on that basis. They are fairly
good at choosing those who are in the know. They get by with the
help of their friends—and can choose friends who are informed.
This is not to convert ordinary citizens into social scientists.
They do place some quality control on information sources, but
they also look for that which is comfortable with what they al-
ready believe. (Social scientists sometimes do also.) Perhaps the
ordinary citizen differs from the systematic social scientist most in
the area where I suggest there might be some weakness in the in-
formation seeking by normative philosophers—in the area of sam-
pling and representativeness. Systematic social science depends on
representativeness (that’s why we like random samples and sur-
veys). The ordinary citizen samples information, not randomly
and perhaps not in terms of typicality, but in terms of the congeni-
ality of the information to what is already there, or the vividness of
an example, or the recency of acquisition of the information—
none of which criteria would satisfy the canons of proper research
design. The ordinary citizen always has an Aunt Edna—a person
well known to students of survey research. When someone is con-
fronted with statistics about health habits and longevity, espe-
cially when the statistics make the person uncomfortable, we hear
about Aunt Edna, who drank a quart of scotch and smoked two
packs every day but lived to be ninety-Šve. Ordinary citizens use
concrete examples—a particular news story, a particular personal
event—and analogize from that. Studies suggest that sample bias
[Verba] Representative Democracy 259
little in their minds, but that they have too much. John Zaller has
given the clearest expression of this position in relation to survey
responses. The reason responses seem to have a weak, almost ran-
dom character is that people have many values or principles in
their heads. Zaller calls them considerations—a broad and useful
term because it encompasses what we would call values or princi-
ples but also other considerations such as narrow self-interest, so-
cial pressures, and the like. When faced with a question about
public policy in a survey, people do not answer at random in order
to show that they have an answer (as many theories of the survey
response believe). They do answer “off the top of their heads”—
that is, without much rešection—but do so by sampling from the
set of considerations the question evokes. They see what kind of an
issue it is, they look at the considerations it relates to, they often
sample from the considerations they hold in their heads, and on
that basis they come to an answer.
This description of the process accords well with several facts
about the choice situation in relation to some issue of public pol-
icy. One is that almost all social issues involve a tradeoff among
values. Thus, an issue position can be affected by multiple consid-
erations. Most people have many such considerations in their
minds. Some of these are inconsistent with each other, but that in-
consistency is not apparent since citizens do not routinely critique
their values for logical coherence. Furthermore, when faced with
an issue where multiple and conšicting values may apply, individ-
uals can choose to frame the issue as involving one set of consider-
ations rather than another. In this way, they handle the inconsis-
tency without reconciling the various sides.
The work of Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman is most
prominent in this area. In a long series of experimental studies,
they and others have shown that the same choice situation leads to
a different decision depending on the way the choice is framed—
that is, on the context in which the choice is placed. Take the same
[Verba] Representative Democracy 261
situation, change the symbolic description, and you change the re-
sponse.16 Often this is done by analogy: is intervention in Kosovo
like intervening to save the Jews under Hitler or intervening in
Vietnam? One of my favorite examples is an experimental prison-
ers’ dilemma study in which the likelihood of cooperative behav-
ior in exactly the same game was affected by whether the game was
named Community or Wall Street. Call it Community and players
are more likely to cooperate; call it Wall Street and they are more
selŠsh.17
The point here is that citizens have many standards in their
heads rather than one. Consider the self-regarding economic-type
calculations assumed in most economic modeling of human be-
havior. Such a standard may be applied in many situations, but
perhaps not in all. Experimental literature shows that the more
the experimental situation “approximates a competitive . . . mar-
ket” with anonymous buyers and sellers, the less other-regarding
behavior will be observed. As Samuel Bowles puts it, “ . . . market
like situations induce self-regarding behavior, not by making peo-
ple intrinsically selŠsh, but by invoking the self-regarding behav-
iors in their preference repertories.”18 What behavior individuals
choose depends on the context in which they are choosing.
The research on framing sheds light on what it means when
citizens appear to have changeable and uncertain views. Changes
in position from one question to another may be the result of sub-
tle changes in the frame that the question provides or change in
the context in which it has been evoked. Or it may be due to a
16 Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman, “The Framing of Decisions and the Psy-
chology of Choice,” in Roben Hogarth, ed., Question Framing and Response Consistency (San
Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 1982).
17 Lee Ross and Andrew Ward, “The Power of Situational Effects in the Prisoners’
Dilemma Game” (unpublished manuscript, 1993), cited in Cass Sunstein, “Social
Norms and Social Roles,” Columbia Law Review 96 (May 1996): 913n33.
18 Samuel Bowles, “Endogenous Preferences: The Cultural Consequences of Mar-
kets and Other Economic Institutions,” Journal of Economic Literature 36 (March, 1998):
75–111; quotation on p. 89.
262 The Tanner Lectures on Human Values
change in the media that have primed people for one frame rather
than another. This changeability is not necessarily a manifestation
of the weak views of people but may be due to a change of the con-
text in which they see the issue.
This fact does not, however, necessarily create conŠdence in
the thoughtfulness and reasonableness of citizen views. Tversky
and Kahneman Šnd evidence for the existence of an availability
heuristic—that is, issues are framed by the set of considerations
that are nearest to the top of the individual’s mind.19 This may
be the most recent consideration to which they have been exposed.
(As an aside, one ought to note that this is not a monopoly of rank
and Šle citizens; each of us can certainly think of high political
leaders whose views depend on whom they spoke to most
recently.)
This is a major way in which media coverage affects how citi-
zens think about issues. Newspapers and TV have their major im-
pact by “priming” people to consider one consideration rather
than another more salient in relation to an issue—by giving it a
particular frame. They cue citizens to place an issue in one or an-
other category. If change of the symbol changes the position, or if
the media or elites can frame issues in one way or another and elicit
response from citizens, this suggests perhaps that citizens do not
act autonomously; that they are manipulated by symbol spin doc-
tors in the media and in public ofŠce.
Certainly there is evidence for such manipulation—and a large
number of people spend a good deal of time and money trying to
do just that. But one can put a somewhat more optimistic inter-
pretation on citizen sensitivity to the nature and origins of the
message and to context. Individuals may change their views de-
pending on the context within which an issue or decision arises.
But this is not mere reaction to irrelevant symbols. Context mat-
19 Amos Tversky and Daniel Kaneman, “Availability: A Heuristic for Judging Fre-
quency and Probability,” Cognitive Psychology 5 (1973): 207–32.
[Verba] Representative Democracy 263
ters in terms of what values are applied. The games Wall Street
and Community differ. One ought to trust and cooperate in a com-
munity; on Wall Street less trust and more defection seems appro-
priate. We would not have much respect for the person who acted
like a Wall Street investor in all personal relationships. And the
investor who behaved like a communitarian on Wall Street would
likely soon go broke.
Furthermore, research shows that framing is not a manipula-
tion of passive individuals by sly framers. What frame an indi-
vidual accepts depends, at least in good part, on the values or
considerations the individual already has stored. There is a run-
ning interaction between that which is stored from earlier expe-
riences and the new input. There is evidence that individuals do
not accept just any frame. Frames are accepted if they are com-
patible with previously available considerations. And individuals
make judgments as to the credibility of a framer. Thus, the pro-
cess of framing is not merely a matter of passive citizens and
active elite manipulators. It may go too far to consider it a dem-
ocratic dialogue in which citizens interact with the media and
other elite communications, as well as with friends and others, to
consider and reconsider their positions on public matters in the
light of new arguments and changing contexts. But it may rep-
resent a quite reasonable decision process carried out by some-
what autonomous individuals. Certainly, there is evidence for
autonomous position-taking on the part of the mass public. Con-
sider the Bill Clinton/Monica Lewinsky affair. The public clearly
responded autonomously—that is, without cues from political or
media elites. When the story Šrst broke, all the pundits signaled
that Clinton was through since the public would not approve.
No one primed the public to make distinctions between private
and public life. Indeed, the only fully reasonable participant in
that madness seems to have been the American public.
264 The Tanner Lectures on Human Values
must have an equal right to decide what is best for the country”
than accept the proposition that those of character and intelli-
gence ought to have more voice.21 They are not sure they know
what’s best, but they do not think anyone else has the right to de-
cide that for them. I Šnd that a somewhat contradictory but actu-
ally quite reasonable position.
The public wants change, but when it sees change going too
far, it backs off. Stimson likens the effect to that of a thermostat.
When things get too cool, it raises the temperature until it gets
too hot, and then it lowers it. Such moderation can look like in-
consistency, and to some extent it is. And it can be maddening, I
assume, to politicians who think they have won the support of the
public for a new direction to policy only to Šnd the public turning
against them as soon as they try to move in the new direction. But
the position seems not unreasonable. In this sense, the civic aggre-
gate may indeed be better than the civic individual.
Let us consider the other set of reasons why one might oppose
equal citizen voice: that citizens are morally incompetent and hold
values incompatible with an ongoing democratic polity. It is hard
to delineate what values are needed for democratic functioning.
Let me focus on two that seem basic and have the advantage of
having been studied empirically. These are having some consider-
ation for the public good and having tolerance for opposing and
unpopular views.
Let us begin with the issue of the consideration of the common
good. The ordinary citizen is commonly believed to be a narrow,
somewhat selŠsh, parochial person, concerned only with his or her
narrow world and seeing the broader society as a projection of his or
her inner needs. If that is the case, who will think of the common
good? I realize that this is an issue only for those who believe that
citizens can and ought to think beyond their narrow self-interest.
From a more economistic point of view, narrow self-interest is what
we would expect and, probably, what we would want. I cannot get
into that debate, so let me state that I think it good if people think
about the common good. In any case, let’s see if they do. And for
this I can return to my own research on citizen activism.
[Verba] Representative Democracy 271
the economists are not right either that they are rational calcula-
tors of narrow, individual self-interest. In sum, if by civic virtue
we mean “the disposition to further public over private good in
deliberation,”26 citizens appear to manifest it—indeed, they pro-
claim their commitment to it.
This is all consistent with another body of literature that shows
that citizens evaluate policies and candidates as public issues, not
in terms of the speciŠc effects on them. In research on attitudes to-
ward unemployment policy, Kay L. Schlozman and I found that
individuals (in deciding what policies to support or what candi-
dates to choose) were guided more by the national situation in
terms of unemployment than by their own experience.27 Similar
Šndings exist about attitudes toward racial matters, schooling,
American involvement in war, medical care, and other issues.
General commitments (self-identiŠcation as liberal or conserva-
tive, party afŠliation, general attitudes on matters of race, etc.) are
more likely than the impact of the issues on a person’s narrower
self-interest to predict the speciŠc policy preferences of an indi-
vidual or a voting decision.28
A comment on rational actor theory and the understanding of
ordinary citizens: Surely, if there is a candidate for a theory of citi-
zen involvement in public life that would universally explain citi-
zen behavior, it is rational actor theory. It is, in one form or another,
appearing as an explanation of behavior in many Šelds outside of
economics, from whence it came, and certainly in political science.
26 Quoted in Richard Dagger, Civic Virtues: Rights, Citizenship, and Republican Liber-
alism (New York: Oxford University Press, 1997), p. 14
27 Kay L. Schlozman and Sidney Verba, Injury to Insult (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1979).
28 See, for example, Richard R. Lau, Thad A. Brown, and David O. Sears, “Self-In-
terests and Civilians’ Attitudes towards the War in Vietnam,” Public Opinion Quarterly 42
(1978): 464–83; David O. Sears, C. P. Hensles, and L. K. Speer, “Whites’ Opposition to
Busing: Self-Interest or Symbolic Racism,” American Political Science Review 73 (1979):
369–84; and David O. Sears, Richard R. Lau, Tom R. Tyler, and Harris M. Allen, Jr.,
“Self-Interest vs. Symbolic Politics in Policy Attitudes and Presidential Voting,” Ameri-
can Political Science Review 74 (1980): 670–84.
274 The Tanner Lectures on Human Values
citizens may merely be giving lip service to support for the Bill of
Rights (a positive symbol), or may be inconsistent in their posi-
tions (an illustration of inadequate logic), or may be placing one
value (free speech) against another (the desire to protect democ-
racy or religion from attack). But whatever the interpretation,
there did not seem to be much comfort for those who would base
democratic stability on a free-standing commitment to a more
open society.
The work of John Sullivan and his associates modiŠed Stouf-
fer’s design and carried the research forward. He and his associates
argued that Stouffer’s examples of groups to which people might
deny free speech rights were mostly groups that would be anath-
ema to conservatives—socialists, Communists, atheists. If one ex-
pands, and lets the individual choose his or her enemy (that is,
respondents are asked to name groups they really dislike and then
asked whether they would accord them free speech opportunities),
then intolerance is found to be even more endemic. Similar re-
search in Britain comes to a similar conclusion. What Sullivan’s
research seems to show is that people report commitment to some
free-standing principles of free speech and tolerance and may in-
deed have such commitments—but when it comes right down to
it, their opposition to people espousing doctrines they dislike
swamps their commitment. Again this can be seen not as intoler-
ance, but rather as a greater concern about social stability. The
least-liked groups in the United States include the Ku Klux Klan
and the American Nazi Party; in Britain, the National Front and
Sinn Fein.
The studies did suggest several mechanisms by which this gen-
eral expression of principle coupled with speciŠc rejection of free
speech did not create instability or a loss of such freedoms. The
mechanisms include the fact that those citizens least committed to
freedom of speech for speciŠc groups were also the least educated
and the least active citizens. Their views may be more threatening
[Verba] Representative Democracy 279
to democratic freedoms, but they are not likely to act on them. The
argument was that intolerance among the mass public did not
harm democracy—except perhaps in times of mass political
arousal—because it was irrelevant. The apathy and ignorance of
the intolerant mass neutralized its potentially deleterious effects.
Elites—more active and more tolerant than the mass—saved de-
mocracy. Stouffer found community leaders to be much more sup-
portive of democratic free speech than was the average citizen. And
the impressive massive survey work of Miller, Timpson, and Less-
noff in Britain conŠrms this.32 Similarly, John L. Sullivan et al.
found legislators in the U.S.A., the U.K., and several other coun-
tries to be much more supportive of civil liberties for unpopular
groups.33
One more body of research is relevant to this topic. Paul Sni-
derman and his associates, using some sophisticated analytical
techniques, found what strikes me as good evidence for a free-
standing commitment to tolerance. People who are tolerant of one
group are tolerant of others regardless of the closeness of the group
to the individual’s own preferred position. Thus, tolerance is free
standing and does not depend (certainly not fully) on one’s views
of the substance of the doctrine one is tolerating or not. Put an-
other way, among citizens who are generally tolerant, they are
more supportive of the free speech of groups they oppose than in-
tolerant citizens are tolerant of the free speech of groups of which
they approve. A generally tolerant racial liberal is more tolerant of
free speech for a racial bigot than an intolerant racial bigot is for
other racial bigots.
Sniderman and his associates call such general tolerance across
groups and doctrines principled tolerance. But it is interesting
32 Miller, Timpson, and Lessnoff, Political Culture in Contemporary Britain.
33 John L. Sullivan et al., “Why Politicians Are More Tolerant: Selective Recruit-
ment and Socialization among Elites in Britain, Israel, New Zealand, and the United
States,” British Journal of Political Science 55 (November 1993): 51.
280 The Tanner Lectures on Human Values
do have the right. I know they do. . . . That’s what freedom is all
about. Freedom of speech. Yeah. I’m all just doing a topsy turvy
here. I know they have the right and our government isn’t perfect
and they might, you know, bring out a lot of things that would
change for the better, but I would not want to go to the extreme of
turning all of a sudden communist. . . . ”
One further example illustrates how people are likely to come
out if they rešect on such matters. James Kuklinski carried out an
interesting experiment.36 He asked about free speech rights for
members of the Ku Klux Klan and tried to get answers that were
more or less rešective. Some respondents were told to answer with
whatever they Šrst thought; others to rešect on the consequences
of the position they espoused. He found a not insigniŠcant differ-
ence. Interestingly, it was not that the more rešective respondents
were more favorable to free speech opportunities for the KKK;
they were less so. More rešection did not raise the importance of
the free speech perspective in the balance of values, but apparently
led them to think of the social harm coming from speech whose
content they found hateful. Rešection did not lead to more toler-
ance, but to less. There is a point to be made here. I am not sure
whether these results would always hold up. But they contradict
the assumption we sometimes make that people, if they only re-
šected, would become enlightened and more committed to free
speech. They may indeed come to a different position on rešec-
tion—but maybe it will not be the one we imagine.
In sum, the reasoning found in these interviews is not elegant;
the individual has not thought much about it and is deciding on
the spot. But one cannot expect most people to have spent much
time mulling over such issues, and the considerations are reason-
able.
36James Kuklinski et al., “The Cognitive and Affective Bases of Political Tolerance
Judgments,” American Journal of Political Science 35 (1991): 1–27.
284 The Tanner Lectures on Human Values
people need a job and ask for a job. More educated respondents
need a job and discuss the problem of unemployment—
while also asking for a job. Neither I nor my colleagues who have
sent in research proposals to the National Science Foundation ever
argued that the research funding would allow us to do what we like
better to do (research) than what we might otherwise have to do
(teach) or that the funding would increase the prestige of our re-
search institute, etc. But it may be (just may be) that some of us
have such things in mind—as well as having a sincere commit-
ment to the substance of the research and its value to scholarship
and the understanding of society.
It is to the good that the educated are more active. That educa-
tion fosters activity means it fosters better democratic participa-
tion. But the educated do not differ from the rest of the citizenry
only in their greater competence and commitment to democracy.
They are also wealthier, more likely to be male, more likely to
come from the dominant race and ethnic groups. They are less
likely to support spending on programs to aid the poor. More im-
portant, perhaps, they are less likely to face the deprivations faced
by those with less education. On a large number of measures of
need (the need to put off medical treatment, the need for better
housing, etc.) they differ substantially from those who did not
attend college. In sum, educated activists are more civically com-
petent, which makes for a more enlightened input into the demo-
cratic policy process; they are wealthier and more advantaged,
which means they have policy preferences and needs different
from those of the population as a whole, and that makes for a more
biased input into the policy process. Insofar as the participation of
the educated is driven by the democratic values of tolerance or by
the civic beliefs they acquire in school, this creates a better citi-
zenry. Insofar as their activity is driven by the components of their
social class position (their income, the networks of connections
that come with various jobs), this creates the more biased polity.
[Verba] Representative Democracy 287
Conclusion
could not be otherwise. Rabbi Hillel wrote: “If I am not for my-
self, who will be for me? If I am only for myself, what am I?” The
average person agrees.
Is the ordinary citizen the free and equal person that Rawls as-
sumes, with a capacity for a conception of justice and of the good?
Again the answer may depend on exactly what such conceptions
entail. But if one looks at what we know about individual citi-
zens—and looks at both the representative but sketchy informa-
tion we get from surveys and the more rounded picture we get
from depth studies—the answer would seem to be pretty much
yes.
Does this mean that representative government with its ability
to reŠne the preferences of the people can or should be replaced by
more direct citizen control—through referendums, or polls, or
other direct democratic means? I hope no one takes that to be the
implication of my remarks. There is a long distance between the
subtle complexities of policy-making and the preferences of ordi-
nary citizens as revealed by surveys and others means. The public
itself, so it would seem, does not favor that much unŠltered citi-
zen voice. But I do suggest that the collectivity of citizens can add
useful input to the political process, input that will make the gov-
ernment more democratically responsive. I am not sure that the
input ought to be labeled wisdom, but it is not foolishness. Wis-
dom may, in any case, be in somewhat short supply throughout
the political process—among ordinary citizens, and among our
leaders as well. But that is another topic.