Marxism and The Oppression of Women Lise Vogel
Marxism and The Oppression of Women Lise Vogel
Marxism and The Oppression of Women Lise Vogel
Lise Vogel
New Introduction by
Susan Ferguson and David McNally
Haymarket Books
Chicago, IL
First published in the USA in 1983 by Rutgers University Press.
New Appendix and Introduction by Susan Ferguson and David McNally
published in 2013 by Brill Academic Publishers, The Netherlands. © 2013
Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands
ISBN: 978-1-60846-340-4
Trade distribution:
In the US, Consortium Book Sales, www.cbsd.com
In Canada, Publishers Group Canada, www.pgcbooks.ca
In the UK, Turnaround Publisher Services, www.turnaround-psl.com
In Australia, Palgrave Macmillan, www.palgravemacmillan.com.au
In all other countries, Publishers Group Worldwide, www.pgw.com
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
"
MIX
Preface ............................................................................................................................. ix
Acknowledgements ..................................................................................................... xiii
Note on Previously Published Material :'................................................................ xv
Capital, Labour-Power, and Gender-Relations: Introduction to the
This project began more than ten years ago. Like that of many other women in the
late 1g6os, my commitment to the emerging women's liberation movement
coincided with my discovery of Marxist' theory. At first, it seemed to many of us
that Marxist theory could simply be extended in order to address our con-cerns as
women's liberationists. Very soon, we recognised that this solution was far too
mechanical, and left much to be explained. The Marxist theory we encountered,
and the socialist legacy of work on women's oppression, required thorough
transformation. With this realisation, some turned away entirely from Marxism.
Others persisted in the attempt to use Marxist theory, aiming now to develop a
'socialist-feminist' synthesis that would transcend the inadequacies of the socialist
tradition. While sympathetic to this approach, I continued to pursue the original
goal of extending Marxist theory, and quickly came up against the necessity of
examining just what Marxist theory is. Additionally, a careful read-ing of the major
nineteenth-century texts pertaining to the so-called woman-question made it clear
that the theoretical tradition is highly contradictory. In the past several years, I have
sought to confront these and related problems. This book is the result. Not
surprisingly, its order of presentation parallels the development of my own thinking
on these issues. That is, the text begins with an evaluation of socialist-feminist
theory, moves on to a critical reading of the nineteenth-century writings, and closes
with a theoretical treatment of women's oppression that situates it in the context of
the overall reproduction of society. In the course of working on the book, m}-
respect for socialist-feminist efforts to address the question of women's oppression
has deepened. Nevertheless, I remain convinced that the revival of Marxist theory,
not the construction of some socialist-feminist synthesis, offers the best chance to
provide theoretical guidance in the coming battles for the liberation of women.
When I first started work on the problem of women's oppression, a text by Marx
caught my attention. He is commenting on the relationship between reli-gious
ideology and social reality, and uses the Christian holy family as his exam-ple:
'Once the earthly family is discovered to be the secret of the holy family, the
x • Preface
Several articles came to my attention too late to be incorporated in the text. They
are relevant to the arguments I make concerning the limited scope of the con-cept
of patriarchy, and the problems inherent in paralleling sex, race, and class as
comparable sources of oppression. Recent work in social history emphasises that
the concept of patriarchy does not suffice to explain the complex linkages among
women's oppression, family-experience, and social reproduction. Two
1. Marx 1968, p. 29. Vogel1979. This text was, in fact, an 1888 revision by Engels of
Marx's 1845 notes. For discussion, as well as a more accurate translation of the 1888
ver-sion, see note 5 of Chapter 4·
2. Mitchell1971, pp. 93-4.
3· Robinson 1975·
Preface • XI
I cannot list, here, all the friends and co-workers who have provided encourage-
ment and helpful criticism during the years in which I worked on this project. For
their warm support, I am deeply grateful. As the manuscript took shape in an early
version, I benefited from the critical judgment of many. In particular, I am indebted
to Lee Austin, Egon Bittner, Ron Blackwell, Ralph Miliband, Molly Nolan, and
Charlotte Weissberg for intelligent readings and detailed commentar-ies on this
version. I want also to thank jeanne Butterfield, Marlene Fried, Sheila Morfield,
Susan Okin, Tim Patterson, Rayna Rapp, Carol Robb, and the members of several
study-groups. As I prepared the manuscript for publication, several people read,
and in some cases re-read, sizeable portions of it: Jill Benderly, Ira Gerstein,
Nancy Holmstrom, Beth Lyons, and Susan Reverby. For their thought-ful
comments and suggestions, particularly on the theoretical arguments and political
ramifications, as well as their generous willingness to come through on short
notice, I would like to express a special gratitude. Appreciation also to the staff at
Rutgers University Press, and especially to my editor Marlie Wasserman, for her
firm support of this project, and to my copy-editor Barbara Westergaard, for her
high standards and good sense.
Thanks, finally, to the women throughout the world whose participation in
movements for liberation gives this theoretical project meaning. Without them, it
would not exist.
Note on Previously Published Material
Previously published material has been adapted and/ or incorporated in this work.
The author wishes to thank the publishers for permission to use the
following: "
Excerpts from Lenin, Vladimir Ilych 1966, The Emancipation of Women, New York:
International Publishers.
Excerpts from Engels, Frederick 1968 [1848], The Condition of the Working Class in
England, translated and edited by W. 0. Henderson and W. H. Chaloner.
Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Excerpts from Engels, Frederick 1972 [1884], The Origin of the Family, Private
Property and the State, New York: International Publishers.
Robinson, Lillian 1975, 'The Question' from Robinson on the Woman Question,
Buffalo: Earth's Daughters.
Portions of Vogel, Lise 1981, 'Marxism and Feminism: Unhappy Marriage, Trial
Separation or Something Else?' in Women and Revolution: A Discussion of the
Unhappy Ma"iage ofMarxism and Feminism, edited by Lydia Sargent, Boston:
South End Press.
Portions ofVogel, Lise 1981, 'Marxism and Socialist-Feminist Theory: A Decade of
Debate', in Current Perspectives in Social Theory, 2: 209-31.
Vogel, Lise 2000, 'Domestic Labour Revisited', Science & Society, 64, 2: 151-170.
Capital, Labour-Power, and Gender-Relations:
Introduction to the Historical Materialism Edition of
Marxism and the Oppression ofWomen
Susan Ferguson and David McNally
Every book has its curious life-history. While some soar to great heights of suc-
cess on a wave of public acclaim, others quickly plunge into obscurity. Then there
are those that live a largely underground existence, kept alive through the efforts of
small bands of dedicated followers who spread the word in defiance of a larger
silence. The latter is the story of Lise Vogel's Marxism and the Oppression of
Women: Toward a Unitary Theory. First published in 1983, Vogel's work appeared at
a moment of acute disarray for the socialist-feminist movement that had shaped the
book's very terms of reference. Reeling under the hammer-blows delivered by
neoliberalism in the political sphere and postmodem theory in the intellectual
realm, and deeply disoriented by the retreat of working-class, social-ist, and
women's movements, socialist feminism clung to a desperate existence on the very
margins of intellectual and political life. A decade earlier, a book like Vogel's would
have become a lightning-rod for energetic discussion and debate. By the mid-
1g8os, it barely registered on the cultural radar.
But the sheer originality of Vogel's text helped nourish its below-the-radar
survival, ensuring that it would not entirely disappear. Despite its unpropitious
moment, individual Marxist and socialist-feminist scholars and activists (the cur-
rent authors among them) spread the w,<;td, pointing readers towards arguably the
most sophisticated Marxist intervention in the theoretical debates thrown up by
socialist feminism. And today, amidst a resurgence of anti-capitalist struggle and a
small renaissance for Marxist and radical thought, its republication seems both
timely and compelling. There is, after all, a growing hunger for theoretical work
that integrates accounts of diverse forms of oppression into an overarching anti-
capitalist analysis. To that end, key lines of argument laid down in Marx-ism and
the Oppression of Women offer indispensable resources for the rigorous development
of historical-materialist theorisations of capitalism and women's oppression.
XVIII • Capital, Labour-Power, and Gender-Relations
First and foremost, Marxism and the Oppression ofWomen is distinguished by the
fact that Marx's Capital (Volume I) forms its theoretical point of departure. To be
sure, many socialist feminists had deployed Maixist texts for analytical purposes.
Typically, however, works such as The German Ideology or Engels's Origins of the
Family, Private Property and the State constituted the main points of reference. From
such texts, analysts derived general commitments to a focus on the social
production and reproduction of material life. But rarely did writ-ers engage with
the locus of Marx's mature account of the capitalist mode of production, to be
found in his life's work, Capital. Yet, as Vogel recognised, any serious Marxist
account of women's oppression in capitalist society is obliged to reckon with the
central theoretical categories of that towering work. Put simply, Marx's critical
procedure in Capital disclosed a series of interrelated concepts - the commodity,
value, money, capital, labour-power, surplus-value, and so on - that were designed
to illuminate the deep structural processes through which the capitalist mode of
production reproduces itself. So, while materialist com-mitments in general are
laudable, the specific historical-materialist theorisations unfolded across Capital
move us to a markedly higher level of conceptual clarity. By raising the problem of
women's oppression within the categorical framework of Capital, and by doing so
in more than an ad hoc fashion, Vogel opened a new direction for socialist-feminist
research. And while her text is by no means entirely successful in this regard, its
accomplishments are nonetheless consider-able. To see this, we need to undertake a
brief excursion through the field of socialist-feminist theorising in the decade and a
half prior to the appearance of
Marxism and the Oppression of Women.
One crucial way in which Marxism differentiates itself from 'bourgeois' theo-ries
of society is in its commitment to materialism, or, to be more precise, its
commitment to theory grounded in the embodied human practices through which
socio-material life is produced and reproduced. To be a Marxist is to delve into the
realm of the concrete, historically-constructed relationships of
Introduction • XIX
people and things, and to hold up the patterns, rules, and contradictions dis-
covered in that realm as critical explanations of the social. And it was a confi-
dence in this approach that inspired the rich, groundbreaking Marxist-feminist
literature of the 1g6os and 1970s, a body of work that developed in conversation
with the increasingly radical ideas of the left wing of the contemporary women's
movement.! Emerging at the end of the 1g6os, the domestic-labour debate crys-
tallised the quest to locate the socio-material foundations of women's oppres-sion
in the terms and concepts of Marxian political economy.
That debate - the problems it set out to explore, the paths down which it took
readers, and the eventual collapse of its analytic framework - sets the scene for
Marxism and the Oppression of Women. While Vogel rehearses those contours in
Chapters Two and Nine in some deta'il, it is worth taking a moment, here, to
summarise the aims and trajectory of that debate.
Previous feminisms had identified the household as a site of women's oppres-
sion, and some had loosely related the domestic sphere to the realm of produc-tion.
But it was not until1g6g, with the publication of Margaret Benston's article 'The
Political Economy of Women's Liberation', that the work women performed within
the household became a subject of critical enquiry. Benston's originality lay in
proposing an understanding of that work as productive labour - a process or set of
activities upon which the reproduction of (capitalist) society as a whole depends. 2
Quite simply: without domestic labour, workers cannot reproduce themselves; and
without workers, capital cannot be reproduced.
It is difficult to overstate the significance of this single move. Benston's for-
mulation introduced an analytic framework in which to situate experiences that
feminists of an earlier generation such as Simone de Beauvoir and Betty Friedan
could only describe. Intuiting the power of that framework, social-ist feminists set
out, over the following decade, to theorise domestic labour as an integral part of
the capitalist mode of production. In and through the pages of Radical America,
New Left Review, the Review of Radical Political Eco-nomics, Cambridge journal of
Economics,•. Bulletin of the Conference of Socialist
Economists, and other journals,3 they pr6bed Marxist concepts of use-value and
exchange-value, labour-power, and class for what these might reveal about the
While her own proposal on how such a unitary theory of women's oppression
might be achieved - through a division-of-labour analysis - disappoints,? the notion
that the very categories of Marxism could be re-envisioned through a feminist lens,
and an analysis of gender-relations integrated into an over-arching 'theory of the
relations of production', opened up a significantly new line of enquiry.
Socialist feminism, too, bent under the winds of this political and intellectual
shift. Michele Barrett's analysis of patriarchy as ideology - a powerful set of pre-
capitalist ideas able to withstand the very real equalising impulse that charac-
terises capitalism -was crucial in this regard.8 Barrett's Althusserian Marxism
g. See Ferguson 1999, for a review of other work that explored and developed the
social-reproduction-feminist paradigm in the early 1g8os.
10. Vogel1983, p. 138.
Introduction • XXIII
debate and dual-systems theory. In so doing, it lays out the parameters of a the-ory
of women's oppression under capitalism that aspires to be both materialist and
historical.
n. Vogel suggests (Vogel1g8g, p. 62) that Marx's omissions in this area flow from his
tendency to naturalise an historically-specific division of labour. This is clearly part of the
story. In addition, as we shall see, Marx's views may have been skewed by his belief that the
working-class family was in a state of irreversible disintegration.
12. Marx 1976, p. 270.
XXIV • Capital, Labour-Power, and Gender-Relations
by selling their labouring capacities for a wage, can the systematic process of
capital-accumulation be launched. Capital, in other words, 'can spring into life,
only when the owner of the means of production and s-ubsistence meets in the
market with the free labourer selling his labour-power. And this one historical
condition comprises a world's history'P
Having identified labour-power as the hinge upon which the entire sys-tem
turns, Marx declares that We must now examine more closely this pecu-liar
commodity, labour-power. Like all others it has a value. How is that value
determined?'14 This question- as to how the value oflabour-power is determined-
has excited significant controversy in Marxist scholarship, and it has also pre-
occupied many socialist-feminist theorists. But if we follow Marx too quickly here,
we run the risk of failing to ask an equally powerful - and, for present pur-poses,
more crucial - question: how is that special commodity itself produced and
reproduced? Marx senses that there is an issue, here, but he does not get to the
heart of it. Vogel's critical insight involves interrupting Marx's argument at just this
point, by asking: what are the conditions ofpossibility of this 'special commodity',
labour-power, the very pivot of the capitalist economy? What is the nature of the
social processes through which labour-power is itself produced? Vogel's answer is
decisive. 'Labor power ... is not produced capitalistically'. Rather, it is produced
and reproduced in a 'kin-based site', the 'working class family'.l 5 Focusing on the
working-class family is not itself an original move. Vogel's innovation has to do
with the social role she ascribes to the working-class family (itself organised on the
basis of age- and gender-difference) and the ways in which she analyses this. To
begin by identifying the working-class family as the social site for the
production/reproduction of the special commodity, labour-power, Vogel shifts from
an overriding preoccupation with the internal structure and dynamics of this
family-form to its structural relation to the reproduction of capital. Of course, other
feminist theorists had focused on the relationship of the working-class family to
capital via the reproduction of labour-power. But the majority of these critics
erroneously concluded that because domestic work produces the labour-power that
creates value and surplus-value for capital it too must be a form of value-creating
labour.l6 Vogel clearly grasps what is wrong
with this argument: labour in the household is not commodified; it produces use-
values, not commodities whose sale realises surplus-value for the capitalist.
Others, too, had noted as much, but unlike these domestic-labour theorists,
Vogel's appreciation of this reality does not lead her to argue that the socio-material
basis of women's oppression can be found in the gender-relations within the
household. While the family is fundamental to women's oppression in capitalist
society, the pivot of this oppression is not women's domestic labour for men or
children, however oppressive or alienating this might be. Rather, it pivots on the
social significance of domestic labour for capital - the fact that the production and
reproduction of labour-power is an essential condition under-girding the dynamic
of the capitalist system, making it possible for capitalism to reproduce itself. And
while this does noi: strictly have to be carried out within households - state or
private-run orphanages, for instance, take on the respon-sibility of reproducing
labour-power, too - the fact that it is overwhelmingly a private, domestic affair
undertaken according to the bio-physical fact that pro-creation and nursing require
female-sexed bodies, explains why the pressures on the household to conform to
unequal gender-norms exist in the first place. That is, women are oppressed in
capitalist society not because their labour in the home produces value for capital,
nor because of a transhistorical patriar-chal impulse pitting men against women
(although such attitudes have of course persisted across time and place). The socio-
material roots of women's oppres-sion under capitalism have to do instead with the
structural relationship of the household to the reproduction of capital: capital and
the state need to be able to regulate their biological capacity to produce the next
generation of labourers so that labour-power is available for exploitationP
18. Other social institutions, particularly schools, also play important roles, here. But
private households remain the linchpin of labour-power's bio-social production and
Introduction • XXVII
assumes this, the seller of labour-power must perpetuate himself, 'in the way
that every living individual perpetuates himself, by procreation'. The labour-
power withdrawn from the market by wear and tear and death, must be con-
tinually replaced by, at the very least, an equal amount of fresh labour-power.
Hence the. sum of the means of subsistence necessary for the production of
labour-power must include the means necessary for the labourer's substitutes,
i.e. his children, in order that this race of peculiar commodity-owners may
perpetuate its appearance in the market.19
In a footnote to the passage above, Marx further observes, 'capital, for the purposes of
its self-valorization, has usurped the family labour necessary for consumption'. 22
These passages are noteworthy for the ways in which Marx registers the real-ity of
domestic work, describing it as 'independent labour at home' and 'family labour
necessary for consumption'. He is here at the threshold of identifying the problem of
how the (non-capitalist) production and reproduction of the special commodity at the
heart of capitalism is to be secured. Were he to have con-fronted that question directly,
he would have been forced to reckon with the contradictions it throws up for his own
claim that industrialisation, machinery, and the growth of female and child-labour were
undermining the working-class family. For that claim would then sit uneasily with the
recognition that some social institution, like the kin-based working-class family, is
essential to the reproduction of a wage-labouring class. In another passage, we witness
Marx's partial recognition of the gendered dimensions of this question:
Since certain family functions, such as nursing and suckling children, cannot
be entirely suppressed, the mothers confiscated by capital, must try
substitutes of some sort. Domestic wrk, such as sewing and mending, must
be replaced by the purchase of ready-made articles. Hence, the diminished
expenditure of labour in the house is accompanied by an increased
expenditure of money outside. The cost of production of the working class
family therefore increases, and balances its greater income. In addition to
this, economy and judgment in the consumption and preparation of the
means of subsistence becomes impossible.23
Here, Marx effectively raises the question of biological difference - not preg-nancy and
birthing, about which he is silent, but 'nursing and suckling'. In so doing, he tacitly
acknowledges that the work of producing the next generation has a distinctly gendered
character rooted in biological difference. This, of course, opens onto the question as to
why women experience unique forms of oppres-sion in capitalist societies. And at just
this point, Vogel makes a critical contri-bution, arguing that the social organisation of
biological difference constitutes a
This vision of a new and 'higher' form of relations between women and men, and
adults and children is inspiring. But it is based on a faulty premise: that capitalist
development inevitably spells the disintegration of the working-class family. In
fact, Marx failed to register the overall significance of concerted leg-islative
moves, particularly throughout the Victorian period in Britain, to reas-sert gender-
differences and to reinforce the working-class family. Parliamentary commissions
figured prominently, here, particularly the Report of the Children's Employment
Commission (in two parts) and the Coalmines Regulation Act (both of 1842 ).
Reports such as these spurred legislative processes designed to limit child-labour
and hours of work, and to restrict female employment. Combined with legislation
creating mandatory public schooling of children, the state had clearly undertaken
to counter infant- and child-mortality rates, 'educate' children in the skills and
docility appropriate to industrial capitalism, and reassert gen-dered divisions of
labour that reinforced the identification of women with the domestic sphere. (It is
interesting, in this regard, that female work in the mines was restricted, while
frequently more onerous domestic service went untouched.) Moral panics
accompanied all these processes, including a telling alarm about trousered women
working underground with picks and shovels, which coincided with legislation
banning women and girls from below-ground work in the mines. Across the
Victorian period, then, the state sought to reconstitute the working-class family by
way of new restraints on female and child-labour, a reinforced gender-order, the
state's responsibility for public education of children, along-side health- and
sanitation-reform - much of it promoted by way of fear about the dirty, uncivilised
working-class hordes, at home and in the colonies, and fear of transgressive
working-class women in particular.29
Of course, working-class people also campaigned to defend their household-life
and kin-networks. In so doing, they unwittingly accelerated reforms that were in
the long-term interests of capital - restrictions on child-labour, pres-sures for a
male 'family-wage', and limits on female employment- and which also buttressed
the dominant gender-order.30 As a result, female participation-rates in paid
employment stabilised at around 25 percent across the nineteenth-
especially with respect to the active role men play in instituting and maintaining
gender-oppression. As a result, she argues, Vogel passes over key socialist-feminist
questions about why men 'almost universal1y' exercise power over women within
the family-system.33
Intriguingly, Brenner attributes this failure to the 'high level of abstraction and
generality' ofVogel's analysis. 'Anadequate "unitary'' theory', she insists, 'would
have to specify at least how class structure sets the limits within which subor-
dinate classes organize families and households and how these terms are set in
such a way as to encourage "male-dominated" family systems'. Such a proj-ect, she
continues, involves looking beyond the 'material basis' of society to the ideological
and political structures that comprise the gender-hierarchy. Lacking such an
account, Vogel offers only a 'preliminary stage' of social-reproduction theory. 34
Brenner's comments, here, are instructive for the degree to which they articulate
the very problem Vogel has set out to solve: the establishment of a theoretically
indispensable first-level analysis of capital-, gender-, and social reproduction that
will make a unitary theory - as opposed to a dualist or purely descriptive account-
possible. Brenner is indeed correct that Vogel does not try to theorise the exercise
of male power within the household per se, or to provide an historical account of
its development. Instead, her interest is in analysing what it is about the
fundamental relations of capitalism that seems to require a family-system based
upon a male-dominated gender-order. As she puts it, 'it is the responsibility for the
domestic labor necessary to capitalist social reproduc-tion - and not the sex
division of labor or the family per se - that materially underpins the perpetuation of
women's. oppression and inequality in capitalist society'. 35 Unlike so much
feminist thought, especially after the linguistic turn in social theory, she seeks to
decipher the socio-material foundations for a house-hold-system based on female
oppression. To this end, she explores the way in which specifically-capitalist
dynamics establish definite limits on the possible range of institutions and practices
of social reproduction. In identifying capital's contradictory need to exploit and
renew labour-power - and considering this in light of the necessarily differentiated
relationship of men and women (or male-sexed and female-sexed bodies) to the
procreative and nursing aspects of those practices - Vogel identifies the socio-
material dynamic of the capitalist system
33· Brenner 1984, p. 6gg. Brenner rightly criticises Vogel for her overly narrow review of
the socialist tradition on 'the woman-question', noting that she fails to engage with the work
of either the anarchist Emma Goldman or the Bolshevik Alexandra Kollontai.
34· Ibid.
35· Vogel1983, p. 170.
Introduction • XXXIII
out of capital's funds. 38 This is why Marx refers to wages.as variable capital. There
is much more unwaged work - labour that does not have to be paid for by capital -
that is necessary to the reproduction of a capitalist society. And capital is certainly
greatly aided by the fact that children are birthed, nursed, nourished, loved, and
educated in kin-based units, just as adults are physically, psychically, and socially
reproduced there. But individual capitals here benefit from social practices that do
not form any of their necessary costs. 39 There is thus no rate of surplus-value,
here, both because these practices are not commodified (they produce use-values
but not values), and because there is no direct cost-structure for capital involved.
Vogel's later correction of this point is an important clarification that readers
should bear in mind when reading her text. More than this, it is a reminder of the
critical-scientific spirit that informs Marxism and the Oppression ofWomen, and that
makes it a work capable of renewal, extension, and development.
38. Of course, as we have seen, these wages must be adequate to help sustain the
production of the next generation of labourers. But the necessary cost for capital is the
direct payment of the labourers who engage in the immediate process of production.
39· Of course, some of these costs might be claimed by the state by way of taxes on
profits. We abstract from that issue here as they do not affect the argument about the rate of
surplus-value.
40. For a sample of Marxist treatments of these developments, see Jameson 1972;
Palmer 1990; Hennessy 1993; and McNally 2001.
Introduction • XXXV
Inevitably, perhaps, as the harsh realities of gender, race, and class persisted, and
as imperial militarism intensified, notably during the First Gulf War, dis-course
theory's rarefied abstractionism and its utter remoteness from politi!::al
intervention produced a counter-reaction. Theorists committed to materialist modes
of critique along with emancipatory politics soon launched theoretical responses to
the disabling constraints of 'post theory'. The early 1ggos witnessed key moments
in this counter-movement, largely initiated under the banners of black feminism
and materialist feminism.41
Black feminism in particular drove the agenda that gave rise to the framework
known as 'intersectionality', which quickly became a major point ofreference in a
wide range of theoretical debates. This approach had deep roots in the experi-ence
of socialist-feminist organisations of Mrican-American women, notably the
Combahee River Collective formed in Boston in 197 4, in which the scholar-
activist Barbara Smith played a central role. Undertaking campaigns around
reproduc-tive rights, prison-abolition, rape, lesbian rights, forced sterilisation, and
more, the Combahee River Collective and similar black-feminist initiatives had
little time for the reduction of politics to discourse. Bodies, particularly the
racialised and gendered bodies of black working-class women, figured centrally to
their theory and practice.42 As it emerged from black feminism, the
intersectionality-perspective thus maintained an abiding materialist orientation,
however much it stretched and modified earlier materialisms.43
Patricia Hill Collins, perhaps the most prolific and celebrated feminist of this
tradition, insightfully developed W.E.B. Du Bois's contention that social hierar-
chies of race, class, and nation co-determined the political-economic realities of
black people in America, thereby drawing attention to the 'matrix of domination'
encompassing race, class, and gender. 44 This approach tackled a key problem that
had plagued both the dual-systems and identity-politics perspectives: to elu-cidate
the interrelations among distinct dimensions of social experience and the
institutions and practices that shape them. However much these earlier perspec-
tives acknowledged a connection between, say, sexism and racism, or class and
heterosexism, they paid little attention ·t~ the operation of the totality within
41. See, for instance, Collins 1992 and 1993; Smith 1993; Hennessy 1993; Landy and
Maclean 1993.
42. It is important to acknowledge the influence on such work of two pioneering texts:
Selma James's Sex, Race, and Class Oames 1975), and Angela Davis's Women Race and Class
(Davis 1981).
43· There were, ofcourse, black-feministpositions that spun offsome ofthisworkinmore
postmodernist ways. The work of bell hooks is often indicative of this, although hooks has
regularly returned to unfashionably non-postmodern concerns with social class. See, for
instance, hooks 2000.
44. See Collins 1993, 1998; Collins and Anderson 1992.
XXXVI • Capital, Labour-Power, and Gender-Relations
47· Hennessy 1993; Landry and Maclean 1993; Hennessy and Ingraham 1997.
Introduction • XXXVII
48. Examples of the reversion to dual systems and descriptivism are discussed in Fer-
guson 1999.
49· Bannelji 1995, p. 8o. As we have noted, Vogel's later embrace, via Althusser, of a
rarefied notion of 'Theory' uncontaminated by the empirical, commits a similar error (see
Vogel2ooo).
so. See Katz 2om; Camfield 2002; and Bakker and Gill 2003. As we have intimated
above, this work would be strengthened in and through the dialectical approach to expe-
rience developed by Bannelji.
51. Such a perspective need not involve a simple humanist voluntarism. If humans are
themselves understood as part of nature, as embodied beings capable of making history,
XXXVIII • Capital, Labour-Power, and Gender-Relations
then the notion of world production remains enmeshed in the natural and the biological,
while also reworking it. On this point, see McNally 2001.
52. Ferguson zoo8; Luxton 2006, pp. 38-40; Bakker and Silvey 2008, p. 6.
53· Marx 1973b, p. 101.
54· See Roediger 1991, 1994, zoo8; and Ignatiev 1995. For the foundational text, here,
see Dubois 1998. In our view, work such as this can and should complement impor-tant
Marxist scholarship on racism and social control of the sort developed by Allen 1994, 1997·
Introduction • XXXIX
class in the United States, including its gendered dimensions, and the way in
which that experience has involved the political-cultural production of enduring
'freedom dreams'.55 Recognising that experiences of gender, race, and class are
always already mutually inflected, or co-constituted, Kelley has also attended
closely to the development of 'a new multiracial urban working class' in Amer-ica,
analysing the interconnection of diverse aspects of social experience in capitalist
society.56
Equally promising is the emergence of a vibrant Marxist scholarship on sexu-
ality and queerness, particularly studies that have examined the class-tensions
involved in the formation of queer identities shot through by socio-cultural pro-
cesses of commodification. Linking sexual-identity formation to larger social pro-
cesses of capital-accumulation in raciaH~ed and gendered spaces, these studies
are interrogating the dialectics of class, sexuality, race, and gender in subtle and
provocative ways. 57 In so doing, they are making indispensable contributions to
the development of a robust historical materialism of late capitalism in which
sexuality and sexual oppression are positioned as essential features of any viable
unitary theory of capitalist society.
None of these theoretical developments, however, can productively engage one
another outside a dialectical social theory. And while many theorists have been
working in this area, few have been more effective at laying the ground-work for
an 'anti-racist feminist marxism' than Himani Bannerji. Starting with the notion of
experience, as does E.P. Thompson in his discussion of the making of a working-
8
class,~ Bannerji develops a dialectical and multi-dimensional anal-ysis centred on
the concept of mediation. The advantage of this concept lies in its insistence that
our 'immediate' experience of the world is always socially and historically
mediated. 59 As a result, each 'moment' of social experience is always already
refracted through, or mediated by, other moments. Rather than trying to grasp
distinct social relations that arrive at an intersection, this approach pro-poses a
'relational and an integrative analysis' designed to theoretically construct
'a meditational and formational view of1 social practice'.60 Bannerji suggests that
such a methodological approach is ·~imultaneously deconstructive - disas-
sembling the totality to locate distinct moments of the whole - and dialecti-cally
reconstructive: 'At its best it is a relational and integrative analysis which
needs a deconstructive method to display the process of mediation. It cim both take
apart and put back together (in a non-aggregative fashion) an event or an
experience within a wider context by using a materialist theory of consciousness,
culture and politics'.61
By proposing that no category of social experience is not already inflected,
refracted, and constituted in and through others, this perspective understands the
social whole as always a (frequently antagonistic) unity of differences. In so doing,
it can attend to both the differentiated mediations of social life and their complex
unity, the very task Marx described when he advocated grasping the concrete as
'the concentration of many determinations', and, therefore, the 'unity of the diverse'.
To be sure, such a project can only ever be an unfinished one. Yet, a central task
of historical materialism is to develop a conceptual map of the real in all its
complex and contradictory processes of becoming. And this is impossible without
a theory of the ongoing production and reproduction of the social total-ity. It was
Marx's great innovation to have grasped the ways in which the pro-duction and
reproduction of labour-power - and the histories of dispossession and expropriation
it implies - is the great secret to understanding the totalising processes of capital.
By putting that secret at the centre of the analysis in Marx-ism and the Oppression
ofWomen, and linking it to specifically female reproduc-tive activities in working-
class households, Lise Vogel critically extended Marx's project and made an
indispensable contribution to understanding the gendered forms of capitalist social
reproduction. That there is much more work to be done in that regard should not
prevent us from appropriating and developing this work's most powerful insights.
Chapter One
Introduction
1. Red Apple Collective 1978, p. 39· While socialism and Marxism are of course not
synonymous, I use the terms socialist feminism and Marxist feminism interchangeably,
following ordinary practice within the contemporary women's movement in the United
States. Socialist feminism is not, moreover, the exclusive province of women: the New
American Movement called itself a socialist-feminist organisation.
2 • Chapter One
This book constitutes an argument for the power of Marxism to analyse the
issues that face women today in their struggle for liberation. It strongly rejects,
however, the assumption made by many socialists that the classical-Marxist tra-
dition bequeaths a more or less complete analysis of the problem of women's
oppression. In this sense, it could be called a socialist-feminist work, although it
shares neither the current scepticism among socialist feminists as to the useful-ness
of Marxist theory, nor their high hopes for radical-feminist perspectives. Instead,
the text argues that the socialist tradition is deeply flawed, that it has never
adequately addressed the question of women, but that Marxism can nev-ertheless
be used to develop a theoretical framework in which to situate the problems of
women's oppression and women's liberation.
The force and character of the feminist upsurge of the 1960s and 1970s, and of its
socialist-feminist component, owe much to the particular circumstances of the post
war period. Serious transformations in capitalist domination followed the end of
World-War II as the structure of power began to undergo profound changes, both
within each nation and internationally. Women, regardless of their class, soon faced
significantly altered tasks, expectations, and contradictions.
During World-War II, an emergency mobilisation had thrust women into an
unprecedented variety of new roles, many of them traditionally the preserve of
men. With the War's end and the return of the soldiers, the situation changed
Introduction • 3
dramatically. Men flooded into the labour-force, pushing women back down the
job-ladder or out altogether.
In reality, women's participation in the labour-force never returned to its pre-war
level. Within a few years, moreover, statistics revealed a new phenomenon.
Whereas, before the War, the typical woman-worker had been young, unmar-ried,
and only temporarily in the labour-force, by 1950 large numbers of older married
women, often with school-age children, had entered the labour-force on a semi-
permanent basis. The trend was to continue unabated, in flagrant contra-diction to
the ideal of the nuclear family.
The social impact of these shifts in the character of female labour-force partic-
ipation was blunted by the intensification Of the ideology emphasising women's
place in the home. Beginning in the late 1940s, a new emphasis on domesticity
projected images of the happy home-maker devoting herself solely to the con-
sumption of goods and services and to the socialisation of children in isolated
nuclear-family households. Women, especially wives, were working in increasing
numbers but were supposed to believe that their real identity lay in their family-
roles. In more intimate fashion, the myth of the nuclear family fostered inter-
personal relations characterised by hierarchy, oppression, and isolation, thereby
contributing at the psychic level to the post war reconstruction of stability.
Tensions between the norm of the nuclear family and the reality of women's
lives were especially sharp in the United States. In the late 1950s, they reached the
breaking point, as more and more women chafed at the bonds of what Betty
Friedan was soon to name the feminine mystique. The early 196os witnessed the
beginnings of a critique, which took a variety of political, ideological, and
organisational forms. Many of these converged in the formation of the National
Organization for Women (NOW) by a group of militant middle-class feminists.
Founded in 1966, NOW announced its purpose to be 'to take action to bring
women into full participation in the mainstream of American society now, exer-
cising all the privileges and responsibilities thereof in truly equal partnership with
men'.2
2. Important landmarks in the early sixties include the following: In 1961, President
Kennedy established the President's Commission on the Status of Women, whose final
report appeared in 1963. Friedan's The Feminine Mystique was published in 1963, heralded by
magazine-articles and media interviews. As the book quickly became a bestseller, a series of
more scholarly reconsiderations of woman's place - led off in 1964 by a special issue of
Daedalus, the magazine of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences - sig-nalled a new
tum in liberal ideology. Meanwhile, legislation and executive orders had begun to create a
governmental policy structure in support of women's equality: the 1963 Equal Pay Act, Title
VII of the 1964 Civil Rights Act, and executive orders in 1962 and 1965 prohibiting
discrimination in federal employment. For NOWs statement of purpose, see Hole and
Levine 1971, p. 85.
4 • Chapter One
demanded equality within the framework of capitalist society, yet pressed the
notion of equal rights to the threshold of a vision of liberation. .
Not until the mid-1g6os did large numbers of people step across that thresh-old.
In the United States, the rise of black-liberation movements, highly sensitive to
international developments, converged with the intensification of the war in
Vietnam. Periodic urban insurrections, an aggressive anti-war movement, and
resistance to the war within the military itself shook the country. Meanwhile, a
massive resurgence of Left activity swept Europe in the wake of the May 1968
events in France. And everywhere, the Chinese Cultural Revolution inspired a new
generation of social activists, who rejected all attempts to resolve discontent within
the confines of bourgeois society. Drastic social transformation seemed on the
immediate agenda. In this atmosphere, a 'women's liberation movement' emerged
in the United States, its founding members seasoned as (white) activists in the
Civil Rights, community-organising, and anti-war movements. Seemingly
independent of all earlier feminist efforts, including the liberal feminism of the
early 1g6os, the new movement initially adopted the form of small groups com-
mitted to consciousness-raising, local organising, and, at times, direct action.
Unlike the more sober feminism of such organisations as NOW, women's lib-
eration succeeded in tapping and mobilising the dissatisfaction engendered by the
many contradictions in all aspects of women's lives. 'Sisterhood is power-ful'
argued the women's liberation movement, as it rapidly spread throughout the
United States, Canada, Europe, and beyond. No sphere of experience could escape
attention, moreover, for these feminists recognised that 'the personal is political',
and put their theories into practice. In a period of social upheaval, the women's
liberation movement catapulted the idea offemale liberation into pub-lic
consciousness and laid the groundwork for a mass women's movement.
From the start, activists in the women's liberation movement differed among
themselves on the role of women's issues in the process of social change, and
developed distinct strategic orientations. Some saw the fight against women's
oppression as part of a larger struggle for ~ocialism. For these women, the task
became how to resist a traditional soci£list tendency to subordinate feminist issues
in the course of the struggle for socialism. Others insisted that the issue of women's
domination by men was fundamental to any process of social trans-formation, had
a sharply autonomous character, and required a qualitatively distinct struggle.
Here, the problem concerned the demarcation of this position from that held by the
most militant liberal feminists. As both discussion and practice deepened, a
cleavage developed within the women's liberation move-ment. Radical feminists
increasingly emphasised the primacy of sex-antagonisms in social development,
the critical role of sexuality and sexual preference, and the irredeemable
weaknesses of socialist work on women. In opposition, another
6 • Chapter One
tendency within the women's liberation movement began to argue that the
strengths of radical feminism could in fact be melded with socialist analysis into a
new strategy. By the early 1970s, this latter tendericy - soon dubbed Marx-ist
feminism or socialist feminism - had consolidated into ah important force within
the women's movement, as well as on the Left.3
Socialist feminists share a general strategic and organisational perspective. They
argue that the participation of women, conscious of their own oppression as a
group, is critical to the success of any revolutionary struggle. They assert that the
key oppressions of sex, class, and race are interrelated and that the struggles
against them must be co-ordinated - although the precise character of that co-
ordination remains unspecified. In any case, socialist feminists agree on the
necessity of an independent movement of women from all sectors of soci-ety
throughout the revolutionary process: working women; housewives; single women;
lesbians; black, brown, and white women; blue-collar and white-collar women, and
so on. For socialist feminists, only such an autonomous women's movement can
guarantee socialist commitment to women's liberation, partic-ularly in the
ideological and interpersonal areas, and in the domestic sphere. Autonomy, they
maintain, is a political as well as a tactical principle. Finally, socialist-feminist
theorists argue that the movement shares with much of the New Left 'a totalistic
view of the socialist transformation, an emphasis on subjective factors in the
revolutionary process, and a rejection of mechanical stage-ism'.4 For most activists,
however, the essence and strength of the socialist-feminist movement lie not in its
view of socialism but in its tenacious insistence on, and particular interpretation of,
the feminist insights that sisterhood is powerful and the personal political.
Theory did not play a large role in the development of the women's liberation
movement in its first stages. Indeed, the very ability to exist and grow without firm
theoretical or organisational bearings test;ified to the movement's strength as a real
social force. By the early 1970s, however, the movement began to re-evaluate its
practice, and to examine more closely the theoretical framework implicitly guiding
its activity. In turning to theoretical work, participants in the women's liberation
movement addressed practical issues arising out of their political experience.
Nowhere was this new commitment to theory stronger than· among socialist
feminists. Their interest in theory responded, in large part, to a
3· For differing accounts of the history of second wave feminism, see: Deckard 1978;
Dixon 1970, and 1972; Easton 1978; Epstein 1980; Sara Evans 1975, and 1979; Freeman
1972 and 1973; Anonymous 197s; Red Apple Collective 1988. For the development of
feminist consciousness and movements for women's liberation in the Third World, see:
Chinchilla 1977, and 1979; Omvedt198o, and 1978; Urdang 1979.
4· Anonymous 1975, p. 87.
Introduction • 7
First, all women, not just working-class women, are oppressed in capitalist
society. Women occupy a subordinate place, moreover, in all class-societies, and
some would argue that women are subordinated in every society, including
socialist society. What is the root of women's oppression? How can its cross-class
and transhistorical character be understood theoretically?
Second, divisions of labour according to sex exist in every known society:
women and men do different types of work. 5 In particular, women tend to be
responsible for work in the area of child-rearing, as well as other types of labour in
the household; they may also be involved in production. Generally speaking, sex-
divisions of labour represent stubborn barriers to. women's full participa-tion in
every society. What is the relationship of these sex-divisions oflabour to women's
oppression? Given women's child-bearing capacity, how is it possible for women
to be truly equal? Should not the very notion of equality be discarded or
transcended in order for women to be liberated?
Third, women's oppression bears strong analogies to the oppression of racial
and national groups, as well as to the explo),tation of subordinate classes. Are sex,
race, and class parallel oppressions of art ~ssentially similar kind? Does female
oppression have its own theoretically specific character? What is the relation-ship
of the fight against women's oppression to the struggle for national libera-tion and
for socialism?
5· I use the plural - sex-divisions of labour - because in most societies there are, in
fact, distinct divisions of labour according to sex in different areas of work and for dif-
ferent classes, age-groups, and so forth. While the singular term - the sex division of
labour - can be taken to include these variations, it tends also to merge them into an
abstract unity. For a similar conceptualisation, if not terminology, see Middleton 1979.
See also Beneria 1979·
8 • Chapter One
For Mitchell, the way out of this impasse is to differentiate woman's condition
into four separate structures: production, reproduction, socialisation, and sexu-
ality. Each structure develops separately and requires its own analysis; together,
they form the 'complex unity' of woman's position. Under production, Mitchell
includes various activities external to what we might intuitively call the domestic
or family sphere, for example, participation in wage-labour in capitalist society.
Conversely, the remaining three categories, oppressively united in the institu-tion
known as the family, encompass woman's existence outside of production, as wife
and mother. In an effort to reach general strategic conclusions, Mitchell then
surveys the current state of each of the four structures. Production, repro-duction,
and socialisation show little dynamism, she says, and indeed have not for years.
The structure of sexuality, by contrast, ·is currently undergoing severe strain, and
represents the strategic weak link - that is, the structure most vulner-able to
immediate attack.
While one structure may be the weak link, Mitchell argues that socialist strat-
egy will have to confront all four structures of woman's position in the long run.
Furthermore, 'economic demands are still primary' in the last instance. In this
context, Mitchell makes a number of sensitive strategic observations. The left must
reject both reformism and voluntarism on the issue of woman's oppres-sion, for
they always lead to inadequate strategic programmes. The reformist
Even with its problems, easier to recognise at a distance of more than fifteen
years, Mitchell's 1966 article played an extremely positive role within the devel-
oping socialist-feminist movement. Its differentiation of the content of women's
lives into constituent categories helped women's liberationists to articulate their
6. Mitchel11966, p. 34·
7· Ibid.
8. Murdock argued that the universal nuclear family incorporates the 'four functions
fundamental to human social life - the sexual, the economic, the reproductive, and the
educational [i.e. that pertaining to socialization]'. (Murdock 1949, p. 10.) For critiques of
Mitchell's functionalism, see also: Landes 1977-8; Middleton 1974. On the family in
functionalist theory, see: Beechey 1978; Morgan 197s; Vogel1978.
A Decade of Debate • 17
experience and begin to act on it. Its perceptive overview of the classical-Marxist
literature on women provided a base from which to confront both mechanical
versions of Marxism and the growing influence of radical feminism. Its insis-
tence, within a Marxist framework, on the critical importance of social phe-
nomena not easily characterised as economic, anticipated the socialist-feminist
critique of economic-determinism. And the political intelligence of its specific
strategic comments set a standard that remains a model. 'Ifsocialism is to regain its
status as the revolutionary politics', Mitchell concluded, 'it has to make good its
practical sins of commission against women and its huge sin of omission - the
absence of an adequate place for them in its theory'. 9 In the theoretical arena,
Mitchell's central contribution was to legitimate a perspective that recognises the
ultimate primacy of economic pheno1nena, yet allows for the fact that other
aspects of woman's situation not only have importance, but may play key roles at
certain junctures.
g. Mitchell1971, p. 86.
10. Margaret Benston's article circulated under the title What Defines Women?' and was
published as 'The Political Economy of Women's Liberation'. Peggy Morton's original essay,
'A Woman's Work Is Never Done, or: The Production, Maintenance and Reproduc-tion of
Labor Power', was abridged in Le:viathan in May 1970 and then revised for publica-tion as
'A Woman's Work Is Never Done'. See Benston 1g6g, and Morton 1971.
18 • Chapter Two
Peggy Morton's article, published in 1970, one year after Benston's, extended the
analysis of the family-household as a materially rooted social unit in capital-ist
society. For Morton, Benston's discussion of how unpaid household-labour forms
the material basis of women's oppression leaves open a number of ques-tions: Do
women form a class? Should women be organised only through their work in the
household? How and why has the nature of the family as an eco-nomic institution
in capitalist society changed? Morton sees the family 'as a unit whose function is
the maintenance and reproduction of labour power, meaning that 'the task of the
family is to maintain the present work force and provide the next generation of
workers, fitted with the skill~ and values necessary for them to be productive
members of the work force'P Using this approach, Morton is able to tie her analysis
of the family to the workings of the capitalist mode of production, and to focus on
the contradictions experienced by working-class women within the family, in the
labour-force, and between the two roles. In particular, she shows that as members
of the reserve-army of labour, women are central, not peripheral, to the economy,
for they make possible the functioning of those manufacturing-, service-, and state-
sectors in which low wages are a priority. While the strategic outlook in the several
versions of Morton's paper bears only a loose relationship to its analysis, and
fluctuates from workers' con-
13. For early critiques of Benston, see: Morton 1971; Rowntree 1969; and Salper 1972. 14·
Mariarosa Dalla Costa's article Women and the Subversion of the Community' was
published in Italian in 1972, and appeared simultaneously in English in Radical America.
A corrected translation is found in Dalla Costa 1973.
zo • Chapter Two
to whichever class she belongs'.15 At the same time, Dalla Costa concentrates her
attention on the working-class housewife, whom she sees as indispensable to
capitalist production.
As housewives, working-class women find themselves excluded from capital-ist
production, isolated in routines of domestic labour that have the technologi-cal
character of pre-capitalist labour-processes. Dalla Costa disputes the notion that
these housewives are mere suppliers of use-values in the home. Polemicis-ing
against both traditional-Left views and the literature of the women's move-ment,
she argues that housework only appears to be a personal service outside the arena
of capitalist production. In reality, it produces not just use-values for direct
consumption in the family, but the essential commodity labour-power - the
capacity of a worker to work. Indeed, she claims, housewives are exploited
'productive workers' in the strict Marxist sense, for they produce surplus-value.
Appropriation of this surplus-value is accomplished by the capitalist's payment of a
wage to the working-class husband, who thereby becomes the instrument of
woman's exploitation. The survival of the working class depends on the working-
class family, 'but at the woman's expense against the class itself. The woman is the
slave of a wage slave, and her slavery ensures the slavery of her man ... And that is
why the struggle of the woman of the working class against the family is crucial'. 16
than a sham reform. Women have worked enough, and they must 'refuse the myth
of liberation through work'P
The polemical energy and political range of Dalla Costa's article had a substan-
tial impact on the women's movement on both sides of the Adantic. Unlike Ben-
stan, Morton, and other North American activists, Dalla Costa seemed to have a
sophisticated grasp of Marxist theory and socialist politics. Her arguments and
strategic proposals struck a responsive chord in a movement already committed to
viewing women's oppression mainly in terms of their family situation. Few noticed
that Dalla Costa, like Morton, talked only of the working class, and never specified
the relationship between the oppression of working-dass housewives and that of
all women. What was most important was that Dalla Costa, even more than
Benston and Morton, seemed ro have situated the question of women's oppression
within an analysis of the role of their unpaid domestic labour in the reproduction
of capitalist social relations. Moreover, since her article functioned as the
theoretical foundation for a small but aggressive movement to demand wages for
housework, which flourished briefly in the early 1970s, it acquired an overtly
political role denied to most women's liberation theoretical efforts. 18
After all, to label women's work unproductive seemed uncharitable, if not down-
right sexist. Furthermore, the argument that unpaid labour in the household is
productive suggested that women perform a certain amount of surplus-labour,
which is expropriated from them by men for the benefit of capital. In this sense,
women could be said to be exploited, sex-contradictions acquire a clear material
basis, and housewives occupy the same strategic position in the class-struggle as
factory-workers. For those wishing to reconcile commitments to both Marxism
and feminism, this implication acted as a powerful magnet. Few participants in the
women's movement or on the Left had the theoretical and political ability to grasp,
much less propose, a convincing alternative.
Once the domestic-labour debate was underway, the problem of the relation-ship
between wages and domestic labotir emerged as an issue. For Marx, the wage
represents the value of the commodity labour-power, a value that corre-sponds at
any given historical moment to a socially-established normal level of subsistence.
Participants in the domestic-labour debate pointed to difficulties created by Marx's
formulation, and asked a number of questions about the role of domestic labour
and household-structure in the establishment of the normal wage-level. For
example, it was not clear in Marx's work whether the normal wage covers
individuals or the entire household supported by a worker. In addi-tion, the
functioning of the wage as a type of articulation between domestic labour and the
capitalist mode of production required investigation. Those who viewed domestic
labour as value-producing proposed that the wage is the vehicle by which the value
produced by women, and embodied in male wage-workers' labour-power, is
transferred to the capitalist employer. Many also believed that women's unpaid
domestic labour enables the capitalist class to pay less than the value of labour-
power, that is, less than the normal level of subsistence. Some suggested that a
non-working wife cheapens the value of male labour-power. Those who
maintained that domestic labour produces use-value but not value attempted to
identify the role of domestic labour in the reproduction of labour-
power. Most participants in the debate also explored the possibility that cer-tain
tendencies immanent in capitalist d'~~elopment affect the performance of
domestic labour and, therefore, wage-levels.
Several years after the domestic-labour debate began, certain questions could be
said to be settled. As it turned out, it was relatively easy to demonstrate the-
oretically that domestic labour in capitalist societies does not take the social form
20
of value-producing labour. Benston's original insight that domestic labour
20. See Smith 1978, as well as Holmstrom 1981, and Molyneux 1979. For a recent revival
of interest in the issues raised by the domestic-labour debate, see the essays collected in Fox
(ed.) 1980.
24 • Chapter Two
produces use-values for direct consumption had been essentially correct. In the
scientific sense, then, domestic labour cannot be either productive or unpro-
ductive, and women are not exploited as domestic labourers. At the same time,
domestic labour is indispensable for the reproduction of capitalist social rela-tions.
Just what domestic labour is, rather than what it is not, remained a prob-lem only
superficially addressed by participants in the domestic-labour debate. Some
suggested it constitutes a separate mode of production which is outside the
capitalist mode of production but subordinate to it. Others implied domestic labour
is simply a special form of work within the capitalist mode of production. Most
left the question unanswered. The problem of specifying the character of domestic
labour, and issues concerning the wage and women's wage-work, now represent
the central concerns of most theorists working with Marxist economic categories.
As for politics and strategy, few today would use their analyses of the material
foundation for women's oppression to draw easy conclusions about the role of
women in revolutionary struggle.
Benston, Morton, Dalla Costa, and the participants in the domestic-labour debate
set an important agenda for the study of women's position as housewives and the
role of domestic labour in the reproduction of social relations. Their work
proceeded, however, within severe limits which were not clearly identi-fied. In the
first place, they focused mainly on the capitalist mode of production. Second, they
concentrated almost exclusively on domestic labour and women's oppression in the
working class. Third, they generally restricted their analysis to the economic level.
Fourth, they tended to identify domestic labour with house-work and child-care,
leaving the status of child-bearing undefined. Some of these limitations might have
been defended as necessary steps in the development of a theoretical argument, but
they rarely were. Although the discussion of domestic labour had been launched in
response to the need for a materialist theory of women's oppression, its promise
remained unfulfilled.
In any case, by the mid-1g7os, socialist-feminist theorists were turning their
attention to other questions. For example, the domestic-labour debate shed little
light on the problem of whether housework is analytically the same in differ-ent
classes within capitalist society, and even less on the theoretical status of domestic
labour in non-capitalist societies. Socialist feminists also turned their attention to
the child-bearing and child-rearing components of domestic labour, and
investigated the problem of why domestic labour generally falls to women. Since
women's oppression is not specific to capitalist societies, furthermore, many
wondered how to reconcile its particular contemporary character with the fact that
women have been subordinated for thousands of years. Similarly, they asked
whether women are liberated in socialist countries, and if not, what obstacles hold
them back. Finally, the relationship between the material pro-
A Decade of Debate • 25
cesses of domestic labour and the range of phenomena that make up women's
oppression, especially those of an ideological and psychological nature, became a
key issue. In general, these questions spoke more directly than the issues of the
domestic-labour debate to the experience and political tasks of activists in the
women's movement, and they quickly became the focus of socialist-feminist
theorising.
While Juliet Mitchell had advised that 'we should ask the feminist questions, but
try to come up with some Marxist answers', many socialist feminists began to
disagree. They argued that the quest for Marxist answers to their questions led
down a blind alley, where the feminist struggle became submerged in the socialist
struggle against capitalism. Mabctst theory, they believed, was incapa-ble of
incorporating the phenomenon of sex-differences. To move forward, then, socialist
feminism had to take on the task of constructing an alternative frame-work using
other theoretical categories. As Heidi Hartmann put it, 'if we think Marxism alone
inadequate, and radical feminism itself insufficient, then we need to develop new
categories'. 21
Socialist feminists turned first to the radical feminism of the late sixties for a
conceptual orientation that could address the depth and pervasiveness ofwomen's
oppression in all societies. Radical feminists typically considered male suprem-acy
and the struggle between the sexes to be universal, constituting indeed, the
essential dynamic underlying all social development. At the same time, some
radical-feminist writings seemed to be extensions or deepenings of the insights
offered by Marx and Engels. Shulamith Firestone's Dialectic ofSex,22 for instance,
claimed to go beyond the merely economic level addressed by Marx and Engels, in
order to uncover the more fundamental problem of sex-oppression. 'The class
analysis is a beautiful piece of work', Firestone wrote, 'but limited'. In propos-ing a
dialectic of sex, she hoped 'to take the class analysis one step further to its roots in
the biological division of the sexes. We have not thrown out the insights of the
socialists; on the contrary, radicalJeminism can enlarge their analysis, granting it
an even deeper basis in objective conditions and thereby explaining many of its
insolubles'. Similarly, Kate Millett's Sexual Politics23 acknowledged Engels as a
major theorist, but her presentation of Engels's work transformed it almost beyond
recognition into a subordinate contribution to what she called the sexual
revolution. The limitation of Marxist theory, she maintained, was that it 'failed to
supply a sufficient ideological base for a sexual revolution, and was
for discussing social phenomena that seem to escape Marxist categories. Some
suggested that a theory of patriarchy could explain why certain individuals, men as
well as women, are in particular subordinate or dominant places within the social
structure of a given society. Others believed that issues of interpersonal dominance
and subordination could best be addressed by a theory of patriarchy. Socialist-
feminist theorists were not in agreement, moreover, on the meaning of the concept
of patriarchy. For some, it represented a primarily ideological force or system.
Many argued that it has a major material foundation in the ability of men to control
women's labour, access to resources, and sexuality. 'Patriarchal authority', wrote
Sheila Rowbotham, for example, 'is based on male control over the woman's
productive capacity, and over her person'. Different approaches emerged also to
the problems of the origin of divisions of labour by sex, and of the relationship
between patriarchy and the workings of a particular mode of production. 26
26. Hartmann and Bridges 1975, p. 14; Rowbotham 1973, p. 117. On dissolving the
hyphen: Petchesky 1978. Early and influential socialist-feminist discussions of patriarchy
include: Hartmann and Bridges 197s; Kelly-Gadol1975-6; Rubin 1975.
27. Bridenthal 1976, p. 5· Mitchell used the concept of a mode of reproduction as early
as 1966. Mitchell1966, p. 21. For other examples, see: Gardiner 1976; Harrison 1973;
z8 • Chapter Two
A second theme in recent critiques is the problem of dualism. Again and again,
theorists using the concepts of patriarchy and reproduction analyse women's
oppression in terms of two separate structures; for example, capital-ism and
patriarchy, the mode of production and the mode of reproduction, the class-system
and the gender-system. These 'dual-systems theories', as Iris Young terms them,
imply that 'women's. oppression arises from two distinct and rela-tively
autonomous systems'. Because they fail to relate the systems in a coherent, non-
mechanical way, dual-systems theories present a mysterious co-existence of
disjunct explanations of social development. The duality generally recapit-ulates
the opposition between feminism and Marxism that socialist-feminist theory had
attempted to transcend. Veronica Beechey argues, for instance, that 'the separation
of reproduction or patriarchy from other aspects of the mode of production has
tended to leave the Marxist analysis of production untouched and uncriticised by
feminist thinking'. Similarly, Young suggests that 'dual sys-tems theory has not
succeeded in confronting and revising traditional Marxist theory enough, because it
allows Marxism to retain in basically unchanged form its theory of economic and
social relations, to which it merely grafts on a theory of gender relations'. 30
Larguia 197s; O'Laughlin 1975, pp. 365-6. In the context of the study of imperialism, a notion
of the mode of reproduction is implicit in: Caulfield 1981; Deere 1976; Saffioti 1977. The
anthropologist Claude Meillassoux has put forth the concept of families as perpetual sources
of cheap labour-power, notably in Meillassoux 1977. Important reviews of Meillassoux,
which discuss the concept of reproduction, include: Mackintosh 1977; O'Laughlin 197s; Rapp
1977.
28. Beechey 1980; Burris 1982; McDonough and Harrison 1978; Young 1981, and 1980.
See also Barrett 1980, pp. 10-38, 126-8, and 131-8.
29. Edholm Harris and Young 1977.
30. Young 1980, pp. 170, 173-4; Beechey 1979, p. 78.
A Decade of Debate • zg
In short, despite the vitality of deba"ie, socialist-feminist theorists have not yet
been able to achieve their goal of developing a unified dialectical-materialist
perspective on women's liberation.
~hapter Three
Socialist Feminism and the Woman-Question
1. Engels 1972.
Socialist Feminism and the Woman-Question • 33
dominant factor shaping every woman's consciousness, whether or not she par-
. ticipates in wage-labour. An important strategic orientation accompanies this view.
Socialist feminists maintain, against some opinions on the Left, that women can be
successfully organised, and they emphasise the need for organisations that include
women from all sectors of society. In support of their position, they point to the
long history of militant activity by women in the labour-movement, in
communities, and in social revolution. They observe, moreover, that mobilisa-tion
demands a special sensitivity to women's experience as women, and they assert the
legitimacy and importance of organisations comprised of women only. It is precisely
the specific character of women's situation that requires their separate organisation.
Here, socialist feminists frequently find themselves in opposition to much of the
tradition ol socialist theory and practice. Socialist-feminist theory takes on the essential
task of developing a framework that can guide the process of organising women from
different classes and sectors into an autonomous women's movement.
The citation of these sentences, in article after article, accomplishes several pur-
poses. It affirms the socialist-feminist commitment to the Marxist tradition. It
suggests that Marx and Engels had more to say about the question of women than
the later socialist movement was ab(~' to hear. It seems to situate the prob-
lem of women's oppression in the context of a theory of general social repro-
duction. It emphasises the material essence of the social processes for which
women hold major responsibility. And it implies that the production of human
beings constitutes a process that has not only an autonomous character, but a
theoretical weight equal to that of the production of the means of existence. In
short, Engels's remarks appear to offer authoritative Marxist backing for the
socialist-feminist movement's focus on the family, sex-divisions of labour, and
unpaid domestic work, as well as for its theoretical dualism and its strategic
commitment to the autonomous organisation of women. Yet the passage actu. • ally
reflects Engels at his theoretical weakest. Socialist-feminist insights into the role of
women in social reproduction need a more solid basis.
Despite the strengths, richness, and real contributions of socialist-feminist
theoretical work, its development has been constrained by its practitioners'
insufficient grasp of Marxist theory. With their roots in a practical commitment to
women's liberation and to the development of a broad-based autonomous women's
movement, participants in the socialist-feminist movement have only recently
begun to explore their relationship to trends and controversies within the Left. At
the theoretical level, the exploration has taken the form of several waves of
publications seeking, on the one hand, to delineate the substance of socialist
feminism more clearly, and on the other, to situate women's oppres-sion more
precisely within, rather than alongside, a Marxist theory of social reproduction. 3
These efforts are important, although they continue to suffer from an inadequate
theoretical orientation. Socialist-feminist theory has not yet overcome its tendency
to analyse women's oppression in dualistic terms as a phenomenon that is
independent of class, race, and mode of production. Nor has socialist-feminist
theory moved far enough away from its overemphasis on women's position within
the family, and within ideological and psychological relations. The links, that is,
between women's oppression, social production, and overall societal reproduction
have yet to be established on a materialist basis. Most important, socialist-feminist
theory has not been able to develop the theo-retical underpinning for its strategic
commitment to uniting women across such differences as class, race, age, and
sexual orientation.
3· See, for example, the following collections: Eisenstein (ed.) 1978; Kuhn and Wolpe ( eds.)
1978; Sargent (ed.) 1981. Important recent articles include: Barrett and Mcintosh 1980; Beechey
1979, and 1977; Beneria 1979; Blumenfeld and Mann 198o; Bujra 1978; Chin-chilla 1980;
Edholm, Harris and Young 1977; Holmstrom 1981; Humphries 1977; Kelly 1979; Mcintosh
1979; Mackintosh 1979; Molyneux 1979; O'Laughlin 197s; Quick 1977, and 1980; Young 1981,
and 1980.
I Socialist Feminism and the Woman-Question • 35
'renerally, it has been used by socialists to refer to the issue of women's subordi-
\ ·ption in all historical societies. At times this subordination is specified in terms
. flfwomen's differential role in the family, or in production. Most socialist con-
Jiderations of the so-called woman-question focus on women's oppression and
inequality in capitalist society, and the fight for equal rights. The term may also
include, finally, personal relations between the sexes and among family-mem-
bers, and sometimes extends to personal and non-work relations of all sorts. In
short, the woman-question is not a precise analytical category, but a tangled knot
of disparate strands. Three major strands have dominated theoretical work on the
so-called woman-question: the family, women's work, and women's equality.
Socialist theory has been unable, however, to weave these strands into a coher-ent
perspective on the problem ofwome"n•s liberation.4
Socialist feminists have subjected the socialist tradition of work on the woman-
question to critical examination, seeking the kernels of serious theoretical and
practical import stored within it. From this point of view, a major contribution of
the socialist-feminist movement has been its insistence that those who use tradi-
tional categories of Marxist theory must make their case adequately. The ques-tions
that socialist feminists raise - concerning the roots of women's oppression, the
persistence of sex-divisions oflabour in all areas of social life, the meaning of
women's liberation, and the organisation of the struggle against sexism and for
socialism - require answers that go beyond what socialist theory has so far been
able to provide. All indications suggest, furthermore, that the socialist theoretical
legacy is not only unfinished but seriously flawed. An important task, then, is a
rigorous re-examination of the texts of the socialist movement, starting with the
work of Marx and Engels.
Modem students of the socialist movement often suggest that Marx and Engels
produced virtually nothing of real usefulness about the oppression and libera-tion
of women. Even less, it is implied, did they put their convictions concerning
women's emancipation into practice. Yet these claims, whether openly stated or
merely insinuated, are generally not fjJ;Jilly based in research. Indeed, they are
often more the expressions of particular theoretical and political perspec-tives than
they are serious considerations of the actual work of either Marx or Engels. Such
statements reveal, therefore, the range and character of the widely held assumption
that a theory of women's liberation cannot be based on Marxist categories.
4· Vogel1979·
36 • Chapter Three
Marx and Engels 'relegated the family to the backwaters of the superstructure',s
More circumspectly, Richard Evans, a meticulous and sympathetic historian 0 the
feminist and socialist movements, comments that 'Marx and his collabora-tor
Engels had litde to say about the emancipation of women ... For them it was a
marginal question; Marx himself barely alluded to it except to repeat, in a slighdy
modified form, Fourier's critique of marriage in an early unpublished manuscript
and in the Communist Manifesto. There is also a brief passage on women in Capital,
much quoted because it is all there is'.6 The carelessness of these statements, made
by otherwise scrupulous scholars, is surprising. Masked by the current interest in a
feminist re-interpretation of Marxism, it suggests a i certain prejudice against
Marxism itself.
On a different tack, the observation that Marx and Engels were imprisoned
within the limited and sexist horizons of their period provides a somewhat more
secure basis for pessimism concerning their commitment to the liberation of
women. Marx was, after all, not only a man but a Victorian husband and father
with traditionally patriarchal attitudes in his own family-life. Engels, while more
unconventional in his personal relationships, could hardly escape the sex-typed
presumptions of nineteenth-century society. Both men participated in the largely
all-male socialist and working-class movements of their time. These facts have led
many, particularly activists in the women's movement, to conclude that Marx and
Engels could never have transcended their male-chauvinist blinders to say or do
anything useful on the woman-question. Marlene Dixon, for example, an
influential militant in the women's movement and on the Left for more than ten
years, has argued that the circumstance that Marx and Engels were men living in a
particular historical context irrevocably blocked their ability to implement good
intentions with respect to the woman-question. Moreover, she contends,
nineteenth- and early-twentieth-century Marxists never adequately challenged their
own bourgeois and sexist ideas concerning women, much less those of the (male)
proletariat. As a result, the sexist bias i!J. Marxism, originating with Marx himself,
actually reinforced the oppression of socialist women and contributed to the
growth of distortions of theory and strategy within the socialist movement. 7
Although Dixon herself might not go so far, the logical implication of this line
5· Poster 1978, pp. 42-3. Poster also declares that with the exception of Juliet Mitchell,
'feminists have in general not shed much light on family theory' (pp. xvii-xviii).
6. Evans 1977, p. 156. Meyer claims that The German Ideology was 'virtually the last
pronouncement either Engels or Marx made about male-female relationships for four
decades, except for the brief statements made in the Principles of Communism and the
Communist Manifesto, both written in 1847, and the occasional references to the plight of
female workers in Capitaf. Indeed, 'the relative neglect of the "woman question" was built
into Marxist theory' (Meyer 1977. pp. 8g-go, gg). Even Eisenstein suggests that 'Marx never
questioned the hierarchical sexual ordering of society' Eisenstein 1978, p. g.
7· Dixon 1977, pp. 35-41.
l reasoning is that socialists who today seek to develop theory, strategy, and gramme for women's liberation waste their time when they study Marx and
!Sngels. .
·•. Despite its obvious limitations, many socialist feminists have searched the
fiOrk of Marx and Engels for insights into the problem of women's subordina-tion.
They expect, not unreasonably, that the founders of the modern socialist tradition
were able at least to suggest some general orientation. These efforts often end,
nonetheless, in frustration and disappointment. Reluctantly, those who had hoped
for more concrete theoretical and practical guidance conclude that Marx and
Engels could only do so much. Charnie Guettel expresses the views of many in her
pamphlet Marxism and Feminism. 'Just as Marx and Engels had no theoretical work
on racism, a phenomenon that has become a central brake on progress in the
working class movement in the stage of imperialism, 80 did they lack a developed
critique of sexism under capitalism. Their class analysis of society still provides us
with the best tools for analysing both forms of oppression, although concerning
women it is very underdeveloped'. 8
The indisputable failure of Marx and Engels to develop adequate tools and a
comprehensive theory on women represents only part of the problem. The
frustration many socialist feminists experience derives also from the fact that
Marx and Engels did not say what these modern critics of the so-called woman-
question want to hear. Or, to put it another way, today's questioners often ask, and
try to answer, a different set of woman-questions.
Marx and Engels approached the issue of women's subordination and libera-tion
from the point of view of an evolving socialist movement. They sought to situate
the question within a theory of the essential mechanisms of social devel-opment as
a whole, and therefore paid special attention to social relations of production. By
contrast, contemporary socialist-feminist theorists and activists usually approach it
from within the framework of the women's movement. They seek a theoretical
perspective that will encompass both an understanding of how female persons
come to be oppressed wo~en and a comprehensive analysis of the elements required
for women's total liberation. Despite its commitment to socialism, socialist
feminism's different starting point often leads to a theoretical emphasis divergent
from that of Marx and Engels.
While Marx and Engels focused on the oppression of women within given social
relations of production, contemporary socialist-feminist theorists fre-quently try to
disengage the issue of women's oppression from the study of the family and social
reproduction. Juliet Mitchell complains, for example, that 'what is striking in
[Marx's] later comments on the family is that the problem of
8. Guettel1974, p. 15.
38 • Chapter Three
1
women becomes submerged in the analysis of the family -::- women, as such, are ,
not even mentioned!' At the same time, she finds the analysis of Marx and Engels
too narrow, and too dependent on what she sees as simplistic economic expla-
nation. 'The position of women, then, in the work of Marx and Engels remains
dissociated from, or subsidiary to, a discussion of the family, which is in its turn
subordinated as merely a precondition of private property'. 9 These statements,
originally formulated in 1966, reflect two widely held assumptions within the
socialist-feminist movement: first, that women and the family constitute the sole
possible objects of analysis, and that the category of woman, rather than the
family, represents the appropriate object for women's liberationists; and second,
that an adequate Marxist approach to the problem of women's oppression can-not
be developed, even conditionally, at the level of relations of production.
Not surprisingly, it proves impossible to speak of women's oppression without
some discussion of the family, and many socialist feminists focus on questions of
gender-development and on relations between the sexes in the family, or, more
generally, in society. These are often conceptualised in terms of inter-personal
dynamics, ideology, and power-relations, while productive relations and issues of
class tend to recede into the background. Then, when the works of Marx and
Engels are studied for their contribution, they are found to be wanting. Contem-
porary theorists offer various explanations for the gaps, and move on quickly to
alternative versions of a Marxist theory of the family and women's subordina-tion.
Yet what they have actually done is to substitute their own concerns and categories
- a primary focqs on psychology, on ideology, and on relations of hierarchy and
authority - for those of Marx and Engels.
In sum, because they are asking different questions, however important, those
socialist-feminist theorists and activists who today chide Marx and Engels for
their failings often cannot hear what they actually said. And yet a substantial
amount of the material is there, waiting to be developed. As a matter of fact, Marx
and Engels had a great deal more to sar_ of relevance to resolving the so-called
woman-question than either socialists or women's liberationists have noticed.
More precisely, Marx and Engels had a great deal to say, even if it was,
nonetheless, nowhere near enough.
Before proceeding, it is important to consider the kinds of things a compre-
hensive approach to the problem of women's oppression ought to include. First, it
must start from a firm commitment to the liberation of women and to the real
social equality of all human beings. Second, it must make a concrete analysis of
the current situation for women, as well as study how it arose. Third, it must
present a theory of the position of women in society. That is, in addition to a
1. Marx 1975a, p. 172; Marx and Engels 1975b, pp. 295-6, 297.
2. Marx and Engels 1975b, p. 196, Marx claims he is quoting Fourier, yet in fact he very
freely renders a passage in which Fourier makes a quite different point, arguing that 'the
extension of the privileges of women is the fundamental cause of all social progress'. In
other words, for Fourier the condition of women is the cause, not the index, of social
progress. Beecher and Bienvenu ( eds.) 1971, pp. 195-6. Alfred Meyer also notes the dis-
tinction between Fourier's statements and Marx's paraphrase in Meyer 1977, p. 86, n. 2. See
also Okin 1979, p. 8.
Early Views • 45
symbolic representation in the realm of ideas. It is also a reality, and one that Marx
contrasts, in scathing prose, to the hypocrisy of contemporary bourgeois notions
about women. Indeed, he specifies that under current conditions 'the general
position of woman in modern society is inhuman'.3
The nature of the tension between social reality and its ideological representa-
tion became a central concern for Marx less than a year later, as he developed a
severely critical stance with respect to Feuerbachian materialism itself. In a set
of'notes hurriedly scribbled down for later elaboration, absolutely not intended for
publication', Marx sketched his new perspective. According to Engels, who
published these 1845 notes in 1888 as Theses on Feuerbach, 'they are invaluable as
the first document in which is deposited the brilliant germ of the new world
outlook'.4 Here, it is of interest that Marx uses the family and its contradictory
internal relations to illustrate one of the theses:
That the secular basis lifts off from itself and establishes itself as an indepen-dent
realm in the clouds can only be explained by the inner strife and intrinsic
contradictoriness of this secular basis. The latter must, therefore, itself be both
understood in its contradiction and revolutionized in practice. Thus, for
instance, once the earthly family is discovered to be the secret of the holy family,
the former must then itself be destroyed in theory and in practice. 5
Almost accidentally, then, this thesis reveals Marx's initial programmatic orien-
tation toward the family: it must 'be both understood in its contradiction and
revolutionized in practice ... [It must] be destroyed in theory and in practice'. 6
Engels's first examination of woman's position in society appears in his book The
Condition ofthe Working Class in England, written in late 1844 and early 1845, and
published in May 1845. In contrast to the highly abstract approach taken dur-ing
this period by Marx, Engels's orientation is largely descriptive and historical. He
focuses on the actual experience of working-class women, members of the small
but growing industrial and agricultural proletariat. He insists that it is not
1
the invention of machines but capitalism' itself, with its drive for accumulation
and profit, that makes the cheap labour of women and children attractive to
employers. Methodically surveying the development and present state of vari-ous
spheres of production, he documents the details ofi:he lives ofworking-class
women - as workers and as wives, mothers, and daughters. At the same time, his
remarks offer a general overview of the situation of working-class women, as well
as some insights of an essentially theoretical character.
To Engels, the most obvious effects of factory-work on women are physical and
moral. Long hours and ghastly working and living conditions render women-
workers vulnerable to severe bone deformations and diseases. Women-workers
have a high rate of miscarriages. Child-birth is exceptionally difficult. Fear of loss
of wages or dismissal forces pregnant workers to stay at their jobs to the last
moment. 'Itis quite common for women to be working in the evening and for the
child to be delivered the following morning, and it is by no means uncommon for
babies to be born in the factory itself among the machinery'. For the same reasons,
few are able to stay home after the birth of a child for more than a week or two. 'Itis
often only two or three days after confinement that a woman returns to the factory,
and of course, she cannot take the baby with her. When there is a break in the
factory routine she has to rush home to feed the infant and get her own meal'. As
might be expected, the babies are weak; perhaps so percent of working-class
children never reach their fifth birthday. In general, children in the factory districts
tend to be 'pale and scrofulous', 'weak and stunted'. Menstrua-tion often begins late,
or not at all.7
Such conditions are, according to Engels, literally demoralising. In nineteenth-
century fashion, he castigates the moral evils of factory-work, where 'members of
both sexes of all ages work together in a single room'. While we may smile at his
relatively archaic standards of morality, Engels nevertheless points to real
problems: seduction of girls by employers under threat of dismissal, unwanted
pregnancy, drunkenness and alcoholism, suicide, general lack of education, and a
high level of crime and interpersonal brutality. !v'loreover, widespread prostitu-
tion accompanied the 'appalling degree of demoralisation' characteristic of the
working class Engels describes. 8
The enormous surge of prostitution in the nineteenth century drew the atten-tion
of moral reformers and Utopian socialists of every stripe, who repeatedly pointed
to it as a shocking cultural symbol of modem social degradation. Marx himself
follows this tradition when, in a footnote in the Economic and Philo-
7· Engels 1968, pp. 182, 161, 184, 226. This translation has been the subject of much
criticism; see, for example, Marcus 1974, pp. xi-xiii, 28-9. In the interest of readability, I
follow Marcus in citing it nonetheless. For the authorised translation by Florence Kelley
Wischnewetzky, see Engels 1975b, 4, pp. 295-596.
8. Engels 1968, pp. 166, 134. More generally, see pp. 124-9, 166-8.
Early Views • 47
From all this, Engels draws the stark conclusion that 'family life for the worker is
almost impossible under the existing social system'. Again and again he looks at
prevailing conditions and finds 'the dissolution of family ties', and 'the uni-versal
decadence of family life among the workers'. Again and again he notes
that 'these faults are due entirely to existing social conditions'. More specifically,
Engels points to the employment of marrl~d women in factory-work. 'Ifa mar-
ried woman works in a factory family life is inevitably destroyed and in the pres-
ent state of society, which is based upon family life, its dissolution has the most
demoralising consequences both for parents and children'. The problem is not just
the work itself. Long hours and terrible living, as well as working, conditions, take
a heavy toll in 'endless domestic troubles and family quarrels'. Moreover, 'if a
woman works for twelve or thirteen hours a day in a factory and her husband
·is employed either in the same establishment or in some other works, what is the
fate of the children?' So far as Engels could see in England in 1844, capitalism,
unless blocked by the united action of the working class, promised a succes-sion of
generations faced with the same conditions: 'Pregnant women working until the
hour of their confinement, lack of skill as housewives, the neglect of household
duties, the neglect of the children, indifference to - even hostility towards- family
life, and general social demoralisation',l2
Women sometimes became the main earner in working-class households, and
this epitomised, to Engels, the apparent tendency toward family-dissolution.
Confused as well as struck by this trend, he experienced it as a 'complete reversal
of normal social relationships', and therefore a betrayal of the 'normal structure of
the family'. In shocked tones, he observes that 'very often the fact that a married
woman is working does not lead to the complete disruption of the home but to a
reversal of the normal division of labor within the family. The wife is the
breadwinner while her husband stays at home to look after the children and do the
cleaning and cooking ... Family relationships are reversed, although other social
conditions remain unchanged'. Such a situation 'deprives the husband of his
manhood and the wife of all womanly qualities ... It is a state of affairs shameful
and degrading to the human attributes of the sexes'. In the same vein, Engels lists
among child-labour's 'evil consequences' the possibility that 'the children become
emancipated and regard their parents' house merely as lodgings, and quite often, if
they feel like it, they leave home and take lodg-ings elsewhere' .13
Engels's comments on the dissolution of the family, which emphasise the sup-
posedly natural character of divisions oflabour and authority according to sex or
age, and misconstrue the effects of their reversal, reflect conventional nineteenth-
century assumptions. Engels fails, at this point, to recognise the possibility of a
contemporary form of family-life other than that established by the bourgeoisie,
and therefore declares the working-class family_ to be in a state of disintegra-tion.
He senses the contradictory character of his remarks, however, and seeks to root
them in historical development. If the present state of the working-class family
seems to be unnatural, it must result from 'some radical error in the original
relationship between men and women. If the rule of the wife over her husband - a
natural consequence of the factory system - is unnatural, then the former rule of the
husband over the wife must also have been unnatural'. Indeed, these observations
permit Engels a glimpse not only into the past but into the future as well. 'Such a
state of affairs shows clearly that there is no rational or sensible principle at the
root of our ideas concerning family income and prop-
erty· If the family as it exists in our present-day society comes to an end then its
disappearance will prove that the real bond holding the family together was not
affection but merely self-interest engendered by the false concept of family
14
prope rty' ·
In The Condition ofthe Working Class in England, Engels also makes three gen-uine
theoretical contributions to an understanding of the situation of women, each, as
he later observed, in embryonic form.1 5 First, he implicitly recognises that neither
individuals nor the family exist as ahistorical abstractions. Focusing throughout
the book on working-class people and the working-class family, he often contrasts
their experience with bourgeois expectations and relationships. Furthermore, he
links, however vaguely and inconsistently, the nature of rela-tions between the
sexes in the family to social forms of property holding. In short, Engels suggests
that women's oppression and the family must be concep-tualised in terms of
specific modes of production and specific classes.
Second, Engels considers the determination and structure of the wage - the
means by which individual and family ensure their own reproduction. He argues
that two types of competition affect the level of the wage. Exceptionally, in peri-
ods of full employment or even job-surplus, employers must compete among
themselves for labour, and wages of course rise. More normally, competition
among workers for available jobs tends to force wages down. Nevertheless, there
are limits in the play of these forces of labour-supply and demand. Differ-ent
categories of workers require different living standards and therefore com-mand
different wages, under even the severest competition. Wages must be 'high enough
to maintain the living standards of the worker at a level appropriate to the job'.
Moreover, wages must be high enough for workers to replace them-selves,
although again within definite limits. In the case of factory-labour, for example, it
is 'in the interests of the middle classes that factory wages should be high enough
to enable the workers to bring up their children, who will in due course be fit for
regular industrial employment. On the other hand, the worker's wages must be low
enough to force him to ~.~nd his children to the factory rather than encourage them
to improve their lot hy training for something better than mere factory labor'.16
The nurnber of earners in a household affects the level of the wage. When an
entire family is working the wages of the individual can be cut down'. In this way,
the greedy bourgeoisie has 'craftily succeeded in depressing men's wages'
14. Engels 1968, pp. 164-5. Engels also briefly discusses the dissolution of the family
under the impact of the factory-system in his Outlines of a Critique ofPolitical Economy
(1843-44); see Engels 1975c, pp. 423-4.
15. Engels 1968, pp. 363-4.
16. Engels 1968, p. go.
so • Chapter Four
17. Engels 1968, pp. go-2. In 1885, Engels observed that 'the thesis that the "natu-
ral", i.e. normal, price of labour-power coincides with the minimum wage, i.e., with the
equivalent in value of the means of subsistence absolutely indispensable for the
life and procreation of the worker, was first put forward' in his Outlines of a Critique of
Political Economy (1843-4) and in Condition. Still, he adds, the 'thesis is nevertheless
incorrect ... In Capital Marx has put the above thesis right'. Marx 1975d, p. 125. For the
Outlines, see Engels 1975c.
Early Views • 51
he expressed the view that more people existed than could be fed from avail-able
resources. The real reason for the existence of the superfluous population is the
competition of the workers among themselves'. Engels thereby links the
phenomenon of surplus-population to the same processes that regulate wages and
the length of the working day. The difference is simply that they take place •on a
much larger scale [and] in the country as a whole'.18
By 1845, Marx and Engels had arrived, on different paths, at a provisional under-
standing of what was to become known as the materialist theory of history, or
historical materialism. Between November 1845 and August 1846, they produced a
long manuscript entitled The German Ideology. As Marx later recalled, they
'decided to set forth together our conception as opposed to the ideological one of
German philosophy, in fact to settle accounts with our former philosophi-cal
conscience'. The intention was carried out in the form of a critique of post-
Hegelian philosophy. Although never published in full, the manuscript 'achieved
our main purpose - self-clarification'.19 The German Ideology marks a turning point
in the development of Marx and Engels's work. It also contains their first
comprehensive formulation of a theory and history of the family.
In The German Ideology, Marx and Engels take the opportunity to explore sev-
eral aspects of the relationships among family, ideology, and social reproduction.
They call attention to the contradiction between ideological conceptions of the
family and the actual historical experience of families in different classes. In the
bourgeoisie, the family acts as a property-transmitting unit whose existence 'is
made necessary by its connection with the mode of production'. The bourgeoisie
develops an idealised concept of the family which it nevertheless betrays in its
every action. In the bourgeois family, 'boredom and money are the binding link,
[yet] its dirty existence has its counterpart in the holy concept of it in official
phraseology and universal hypocrisy'. Marx and Engels claim that, in contrast, the
family is 'actually abolished' in the proletariat, where 'the concept of the fam-ily
does not exist at all, but here and there, family affection based on extremely
_,ol,
real relations is certainly to be found'. In sum, Marx and Engels draw the explicit
theoretical lesson that 'one cannot speak at all of the family "as such"'.20
,ession of the family'.23 For the first time in their work, Marx and Engels here
.touch on the utopian-socialist theme of the abolition of the family.
:Marx and Engels now had the firm beginnings of both a theory and a history of
the issues involved in the problem of women's subordination. Marx summed up
the general theoretical insight in a letter to the Russian liberal Pavel Vasilyevich
Annenkov. 'Assume particular stages of development in production, commerce and
consumption and you will have a corresponding social constitution, a cor-
responding organisation of the family, of orders or of classes, in a word, a cor-
responding civil society'.24 From a theoretical point of view, in other words, all
social relations can ultimately be rooted in the relations of production dominant in
a given society. As for empirical mat~rial concerning the history of women and the
family, it was still quite scarce, but Marx and Engels had already been able to
piece together a fair sketch of the historical development.
21.
With the 'new world outlook' consolidated in the writings of1845-46, Marx and Engels found themselves confronting new tasks. A wave of re-awakened demo-cratic aspirations and intensified political activity was sweeping across Europe, triggered by the economic crisis of 1847 and culminating in the revolutions of 1848-so. Practical organisational work, first with the Communist Correspon-dence Committee and then with the Communist League, became paramount. When the newly formed Communist League required a theoretical
and practical platform, Marx and Engels were asked to draft it. Two preparatory versions, both by Engels, survive. An initial Draft ofa Communist Confession ofFaith, written in the question-and-answer format commonly used at the time by workers' organi-sations, was discussed at the First Congress of the Communist League in London in June 1847. In late October, Engels produced an improved version, the Prin-ciples of Communism, also in the form of a revolutionary catechism. By Novem-ber 1847 it was clear that the question and answer format conflicted with the
historical approach, and Engels suggested to Marx that they drop the catechism form. The result, The Manifesto of the Communist Party, was written between December 1847 and January 1848, on the instructions of the Second Congress of
25
the Communist League. In its pages, as well as in the drafts, Marx and Engels
recast their views on the issue of women's subordination into a more program-
matic, and frequently quite striking, form.
Having grasped the mechanisms underlying historical development, Marx and
Engels were able to link past, present, and future phenomena with a new, if still
rather unsubtle, clarity. Thus Engels observes in the Confession ofFaith that 'the
family relationship has been modified in the course of history by the prope
relationship and by periods of development, and ... consequently the ending 0
private property will also have a most important influ~nce on it'. More dramaij. cally,
the Manifesto delineates the relationship between family and property in. capitalist
society. The bourgeois family is based 'on capital, on private gain. In its completely
developed form this family exists only among the bourgeoisie. But this state of
1
things finds its complement in the practical absence of the fam. ily among the
proletarians, and in public prostitution'. Since the working class lacks property, the
proletarian's 'relation to his wife and children has no longer anything in common
with bourgeois family relations'. At the ideological level, the Manifesto claims, with
a dramatic flourish, that 'the bourgeoisie has torn away from the family its
sentimental veil, and has reduced the family relation to a mere money relation'. 26
Communists argued that such relations within families, as well as prostitu-tion,
are natural products of bourgeois society. In addition, they had to respond to the
bourgeois accusation that they intended to collectivise women, that is, turn them
into prostitutes. In the Principles of Communism, Engels is terse and analytic:
26. Engels 1975d, pp. 102-3; Marx and Engels 1975d, pp. 501, 494, 487.
27. Engels 1975e, p. 354·
28. Rowbotham 1972, p. 65.
Early Views • 55
For the rest, nothing is more ridiculous than the virtuous indignation of our
bourgeois at the community of women which, they pretend, is to be openly and
officially established by the Communists. The Communists have no need to
introduce community of women; it has existed almost from time imme-morial.29
Manifesto also situates the future of marriage and of relations between the
with respect to the prevailing mode of production. 'The abolition of the
.,, 11,, ...,.~··- system of production must bring with it the abolition of the community of
women springing from that system, i.e., of prostitution both public and pri-
; vate'. More specifically, 'the bourgeois family will vanish as a matter of course
when its complement [public prostituti~n and the disintegrating working-class
30
family] vanishes, and both will vanish with the vanishing of capital'. In con-
trast to these fairly cryptic remarks, Engels's draft versions are in places more
explicit. The Confession of Faith, for example, argues that communist society would
be able, if necessary, to 'interfere in the personal relationship between men and
women or with the family in general to the extent that the maintenance
31
of the existing institution would disturb the new social order'. In Principles of
Communism, Engels revises this position:
Question 21: What influence will the communist order of society have upon the
family?
Answer: It will make the relation between the sexes a purely private relation
which concerns only the persons involved, and in which society has no call to
interfere. It is able to do this because it abolishes private property and edu-cates
children communally, thus destroying the twin foundation of hitherto existing
marriage - the dependence through private property of the wife upon the husband
and of the children upon the parents.32
bourgeois and the proletarian family better represented.. their position. In this way,
to the bourgeoisie's charge that communists seek the destruction of 'the family "as
such"', they quite properly replied that communists fight for the aboli-' tion of
classes as embodied in the specific institutions - here; the bourgeois and the
working-class family - of class-society.
Marx and Engels also refer very briefly, in the Manifesto, to the problem of the
structure of the wage with respect to the household. In an analytic mode, they
observe that 'the less the skill and exertion of strength implied in manual labour, in
other words, the more modern industry becomes developed, the more is the labour
of men superseded by that of women. Differences of age and sex have no longer
any distinctive social validity for the working class. All are instru-ments of labour,
more or less expensive to use, according to their age and sex'. This foundation
laid, they proclaim dramatically that 'all family ties among the proletarians are torn
asunder, and their children transformed into simple articles of commerce and
instruments oflabour'.33
Marx addressed the theoretical questions surrounding the wage more directly in
a set of lectures delivered at the time of the writing of the Manifesto, and pub-lished
sixteen months later as Wage Labour and Capital. He observes that with the
development of capitalism, competition increases and wages fall. Further-more, the
introduction of machinery has the effect of 'replacing skilled workers by unskilled,
men by women, adults by children', thereby generally depreciating the value
oflabour-power and changing the structure of the household's income. When, for
example, the factory employs three children and a woman in place of a man
discharged because of the machine, 'now four times as many workers' lives are
used up in order to gain a livelihood for one worker's family'. At the same time,
Marx confronts the difficult question of the determination of wage-levels. Wages,
or the 'wage minimum', are the price of'the cost of existence and reproduction of
the worker'. Marx cautions, however, that the concept of a wage-minimum pertains
to the working class as a whole. 'This wage minimum, like the determination of the
price of commodities by ·the cost of production in general, does not hold good for
the single individual but for the species. Individual work-ers, millions of workers, do
not get enough to be able to exist and reproduce themselves; but the wages ofthe
whole working class level down, within their fluc-tuations, to this minimum'. While
still holding to the notion of a hypothetical minimum-wage, Marx recognises its
essentially aggregate and social character. 34
' . In their early writings, Marx and Engels evidence a commitment to the impor-lsnce of the
problem of the oppression of women. They dissect, to the extent the ~ailable empirical material
allowed, the hard facts of women's subordination in past and present society. Against this ugly picture,
they counterpose a serious, if somewhat simplistic vision of women's liberation in the future, and of the
aboli-tion of the family as it exists in class-society. Although their strategic approach hardly matches
the scope of this vision, its programmatic weakness reflects the level of development of the working-
class movement at the time. In their theo-retical views, Marx and Engels begin to distinguish their
position on the question of women from the imprecision and utopianism of earlier socialist opinions.
In the next decades, both Marx and Engels sought to elaborate the theoretical, as
well as the programmatic, aspects of their perspective. Insofar as they contin-ued
their emphasis on the division oflabour according to sex, on the oppression of
proletarian women at work, and on the supposed dissolution of the working-class
family, they set the terms within which the so-called woman-question was to be
discussed and acted upon by socialists for the next hundred years. At the same
time, they deepened their understanding of women's oppression as a struc-tural
element of the overall reproduction of the working class and of general social
reproduction. In this sense, they began to move toward a broader theoreti-cal and
practical approach to achieving the goal of women's liberation.
~hapter Five
Marx: the Mature Years
linkage between the reproduction of the working class an<f the workings of the
capitalist mode of production.
As for family and household, Marx only mentions th€m in the Gmndrisse when
considering pre-capitalist forms of production. Speaking of various pre-industrial
or non-European societies, he consistently represents the family-household by its
individual, presumed male, head. Thus, for example, the aim of work in such
societies is 'sustenance of the individual proprietor and of his family, as well as of
the total community'. Moreover, Marx assumes the universality of a natural sex-
division of labour when he puts production of certain goods in brackets as a
'domestic side occupation of wives and daughters (spinning and weaving)'. Marx's
surprisingly uncritical stance in these remarks in part owes its existence to the
weakness of his sources.9 It is more deeply rooted, as we shall see in the next
section, in the relatively broad and unexplored conceptual boundaries accorded the
sphere of 'the natural' in nineteenth-century thought.
The Gmndrisse was the first in a series of manuscripts culminating in the publica-
tion of Capital. Only Volume I of Capital, which first appeared in 1867, was edited
by Marx himself. After Marx's death, Engels used the various drafts produced by
Marx in the 186os to edit versions of Volumes II and III for publication. Volume
IV, known today as Theories of Surplus Value, was assembled and published by
Karl Kautsky. Considerable portions of the manuscripts Marx drafted between
1857 and 1870 remain unpublished.10 ·
Scattered through the pages of Capital, Marx's comments on women's situ-ation,
on the family, on divisions of labour according to sex and age, and on the
reproduction of the working class have never been sufficiently appreciated by
students of the so-called woman-question. A systematic review of the three
volumes discloses a great deal of important material.
Marx considers the actual situation of working-class women, as well as chil-
dren, in the context of his description of capitalist development, focusing on the
impact of the introduction of machinery.' Machinery notably lessens the
importance of physical strength in the labour-process. Under capitalist condi-tions,
machinery therefore enables the employer to hire women and children, paying
lower wages than male workers ordinarily command. The employment of women
and children has specific physical, moral, and intellectual consequences, which
Marx describes in a manner reminiscent of Engels's account, twenty years
g. Marx 1973b, pp. 472, 475; see also pp. 473, 484, 495· On the sources, see the intro-
duction by Eric Hobsbawm in Marx 1965, pp. 20-7.
10. For a clear summary of the publishing history of the manuscripts, see the Vintage
Books edition of Capital, Marx 1977, pp. 26-8. See also Marx 1973b, pp. n-12.
Marx: the Mature Years • 63
;arlier, in The Condition of the Working Class in England. 11 He emphasises how tlbe
introduction of machinery also has a severe impact on branches of produc-tion not
yet mechanised. Here, employers shift to 'cheap labor', that is, to a work-force
composed of women, children, and the unskilled. The·exploitation of these
workers is merciless, for 'the technical foundation of the factory system, namely,
the substitution of machines for muscular power, and the light character of the
labor, is almost entirely absent in Manufacture, and at the same time women and
over-young children are subjected, in a most unconscionable way, to the influence
of poisonous or injurious substances'. In such sweatshops, mines, and huts, even
more than in the mechanised factories, the capitalist mode of produc-tion 'shows
its antagonistic and murderous side' .12
The evolution of capitalism has the general effect of continually altering the
composition of the labour-force with respect to sex and age, as well as size. The
introduction of machinery, for example, throws many people out of work, but may
draw in others, among them women and children. In numerous branches of
production, women and children replace men as the principal element in the work-
force. Moreover, the extraordinary productivity of capitalist mechanised industry
permits the number of domestic servants, go percent of them women, to increase
greatly. Despite constant capitalist expansion, which to some extent offsets the
impact of mechanisation on employment, crises periodically cripple production,
force wages down, and cause mass unemployment. 'The workpeople are thus
continually both repelled and attracted, hustled from pillar to post, while, at the
same time, constant changes take place in the sex, age, and skill of the levies' .13
Next to the rich picture of social conditions under capitalism, the descriptive
material in Capital on non-capitalist past societies is quite sparse. Nothing spe-
cifically relevant to the experience of women per se appears, and Marx concen-
trates instead on the family. Alluding to the variety of family forms in history, he
observes that no single form is 'absolute and final'. Moreover, 'taken together
[they] form a series in historical develog¥Ient'. 14 He is most interested in the self-
supporting peasant-family, for it represents the family-form just preceding that of
capitalist society. The peasant-family is an elementary unit of production,
n. Marx 1971a, pp. 372-g. (Unless stated otherwise, all citations to Capital refer to the
Progress Publishers edition.)
12. Marx1971a, pp. 434-5. Marx then proceeds to a series ofexamples, pp. 435-42; see
also pp. 455-6, 612-66. Other evidence appears in the discussions of unregulated branches
of industry, the shift-system, and the struggle for a normal working day; pp. 233-8, 246-51,
264-81.
13. Marx 1971a, p. 428; see also pp. 384, 421-46, 457, and Marx 1977, p. 1061. On
domes-tic servants, see Marx 1971a, pp. 420-1.
14. Marx 1971a, p. 460.
64 • Chapter Five
an 'individual direct producer', which unites 'agricultural activity and the rura}
home industries connected with it' in an 'indispensable combination'. Charac-
terising the peasant-household as 'an isolated laborer with his family', Marx is
minimally concerned with the division of labour inside it. Rather, he focuses on
the peasant-family as a producing unit that may itself dispose of some surplus-
labour, because it is here, in the distribution of this 'combined agricultural and
industrial family labour', that he locates the mechanism for social reproduction in
the feudal system.15
Marx explicitly discusses divisions of labour by sex or age in several places in
CapitaL The peasant family 'possesses a spontaneously developed system of divi-
sion of labour. The distribution of the work within the family, and the regulation of
the labor-time of the several members, depend as well upon differences of age and
sex as upon natural conditions varying with the seasons'. Machinery sweeps away
the importance of skill: 'In the place of the artificially produced distinctions
between specialized workers, step the natural differences of age and sex'. When
early industrial capitalists tried to extend working hours beyond any possible
endurance, 'all bounds of morals and nature, age and sex, day and night, were
broken down'.16 These natural distinctions have their historical root in biology. At
the beginning of time, 'there springs up naturally a division of labor, caused by
differences of sex and age, a division that is consequently based on a purely
physiological foundation' P
Marx's view of the natural character of divisions of labour by sex and age leads
him to the corollary that servile relations naturally constitute the internal
organisation of all families in class-society. Along with most of his contempo-
raries, including Engels, he assumes that a single male adult, the husband and
father of subordinate family-members, ordinarily and naturally heads the family-
household in all societies. Hence, he observes, 'in private property of every type
the slavery of the members of the family at least is always implicit since they are
made use of and exploited by the head of the f~mily'.I8 As early as The German
Ideology, Marx and Engels had used the notion of 'latent slavery' to represent
internal relations in the family. Like the division of labour itself, 'the slavery latent
in the family only develops gradually with the increase of population, the growth
of wants, and with the extension of external intercourse, both of war and of barter'.
Indeed, it is clear that 'latent slavery in the family, though still very crude, is the
first form of property'.19 In his mature work, Marx returns to the
15. Marx 1971b, pp. 790-91, 796, 807, 79s; see also p. 877, and Marx 1971a, p. 82.
16. Marx 1971a, pp. 82, 396, 264; see also pp. 384, 595·
17. Marx 1971a, p. 332.
18. Marx 1977, p. 1083.
19. Marx and Engels 1975a, p. 46.
Marx: the Mature Years • 65
20. Marx 1974, p. 88; Marx 1971a, p. 373; see also p. 285.
21. Marx and Engels 1975d, p. 501.
22. For reviews of this literature, see Rapp 1978-9 and Atkinson 1982-3. See also the
works cited in notes 12 and 22 of Chapter 10.
66 • Chapter Five
The existence of divisions oflabour according to age and sex has definite polit-
ical ramifications, to which Marx briefly alludes in Capital. In the early period of
capitalist development, 'the habits and the resistance of the male laborers' suc-
cessfully block the entry of women and children into the wage-labour force. The
introduction of machinery, however, 'at last breaks down the resistance which the
male operatives in the manufacturing period continued to oppose to the despotism
23
of capital'. Thereafter, capital tends to equalise all work, while 'the technical
subordination of the workman to the uniform motion of the instru-ments oflabor,
and the peculiar composition of the body of workpeople, consist-ing as it does of
individuals of both sexes and of all ages, gives rise to a barrack discipline'. 24 This
process of economic and social equalisation meets a barrier, however, in the
dependent and subordinate status of women, and especially of children, who are
also highly vulnerable to the assaults of large-scale industrial capitalism. Marx
argues the necessity of protective legislation, and sketches its history. The
development of capitalism overturned 'the economic foundation on which was
based the traditional family, and the family labor corresponding to it', and thus
tended to dissolve traditional family-relationships. 'The rights of the children had
25
to be proclaimed'. A long struggle ensued to force the state to for-mulate,
officially recognise, and promulgate regulations protecting children and women.
The passage of such protective legislation - limiting hours, forbidding night-work,
providing meal-periods, and so forth - represented the outcome 'of a protracted
civil war, more or less dissembled, between the capitalist class and the working
class•.26
Marx does more, in Capital, than comment descriptively on the situation of women,
the family, and sex-divisions of labour in past and present society. He makes a
major contribution toward the development of the theory required to illuminate
such historical developments. To the extent that the object of the so-called woman-
question actually lies in the sphere of the reproduction of labour-power and the
working class, Marx's economic Writings constitute an essential starting point.
From this perspective, the Marx of Capital had more to say of relevance to the issue
of women's liberation than either he or his socialist fol-lowers ever realised. Three
concepts are key: individual consumption, the value of labour-power, and the
industrial reserve-army.
Individual consumption is a concept that Marx develops in opposition to
productive consumption. While both productive and individual consumption
23. Marx 1971a, p. 346, 379; see also pp. 380, 384.
24. Marx 1971a, p. 399·
25. Marx 1971a, p. 459; see also p. 285.
26. Marx 1971a, p. 283; see also p. 268.
Marx: the Mature Years • 67
pertain to labour-processes in which human beings use up, that is, consume,
·products, the distinction is critical. Productive consumption refers, broadly
speaking, to the bringing together of means of production - raw materials, tools or
machines, auxiliary substances - and producers in a specific labour-process whose
outcome is new products, either means of production or means of sub-sistence. By
contrast, individual consumption refers to the processes by which producers
consume means of subsistence - food, housing, clothing, and the ]ike - with the
result that they maintain themselves. 'The product, therefore, of individual
consumption, is the consumer himself; the result of productive con-sumption is a
product distinct from the consumer' ,27
In the most general sense, individual and productive consumption are pro-cesses
that must take place in some form in any society, if it is to reproduce itself from
day to day and year to year. Marx is, of course, especially interested in the
workings of the capitalist mode of production, and focuses on the particular forms
taken by individual and productive consumption under its dominance. Here, the
process of individual consumption is mediated by the wage paid to the worker by
the capitalist for the use of his or her capacity to work, and the distinction between
productive and individual consumption takes a specific dual form.
Marx defines labour-power as 'the aggregate of those mental and physical capa-
bilities existing in a human being, which he exercises whenever he produces a use-
value of any description'. In the capitalist mode of production, labour-power takes
the form of a commodity, that is, a thing that has both use-value and value. It is
labour-power's use-value that so endears it to the capitalist, for unlike any other
commodity, it 'possesses the peculiar property of being a source of value'. When
put to use - consumed - in the capitalist labour-process, labour-power creates more
value than was originally invested. Surplus-value originates, then, in the productive
31
consumption of this unique and wonderful commodity. But before labour-power
can be consumed in the production- process, the capitalist must acquire it in the
market by exchanging for it an equivalent value.
According to Marx, the value of the commodity labour-power is determined in
the same way as the value of any other commodity. That is, the value of labour-
power represents the socially necessary labour ~equired for the production of
labour-power. For a given individual, then, 'the production of labor power con-sists
in his reproduction of himself or his maintenance. For his maintenance he requires
a given quantity of the means of subsistence. Therefore the labor-time requisite for
the production of labor-power reduces itself to that necessary for the production of
those means of subsistence; in other words, the value of labor-power is the value of
the means of subsistence necessary for the maintenance
the laborer'. Nonetheless, there is something quite special about the value of
bour-power, for 'the number and extent of [man's] so-called necessary wants,
t.
IS also the modes of satisfying them, are themselves the product of historical
·development'. Into the determination of the value oflabour-'power enters, there-
fore, a 'historical and moral elemenf.32
Marx developed this point at greater length in a series of lectures entitled
'Wages, Price, and Profit', delivered two years before the publication of Capital.
Here, Marx distinguishes two components of the value oflabour-power, 'the one
merely physical, the other historical or social'. The physical element determines
the ultimate lower limit, although Marx observes that this limit is extremely
elastic. Thus, 'a quick succession of unhealthy and short-lived generations will
keep the labor market as well supplied 'as a series of vigorous and long-lived
generations'. The value of labour-power 'is in every country determined by a
traditional standard oflife. It is not mere physical life, but it is the satisfaction of
certain wants springing from the social conditions in which people are placed and
reared up'. Marx retains, in this discussion, the concept of a more or less natural
physical subsistence-level, but emphasises the wide latitude for expan-sion and
contraction in the 'historical or social' component. In Capital, even this small
concession to the notion of a natural physical minimum has all but disap-peared,
and the 'historical and moral element' plays the principal role. Never-theless, Marx
insists that the value of labour-power can be established, for 'in a given country, at
a given period, the average quantity of the means of sub-sistence necessary for the
laborer is practically known'.33
As with every commodity, the price oflabour-power does not ordinarily coin-
cide with its value, but rather fluctuates around it. At times, the price will rise
above the value of labour-power, with a consequent easing of 'the length and
weight of the golden chain' of capitalist exploitation. More ominously, the price of
labour-power may fall substantially below its value, to the point that sectors of
34
existing labour-power are not renewed in the next generation.
The existence of fluctuations in the pric;e of labour-power, and their impact on
the lives of working people, had already been discussed several times by Marx and
Engels. With Capital, Marx roots these fluctuations in a theory of the value of
labour-power, and thereby goes beyond the surface phenomena of supply, demand,
and capitalist avarice. Thus, for example, he offers a clear, if all too brief, analysis
of the structure of the value of labour-power with respect to the household,
focusing, as in earlier texts, on the effects of the increasing entry of
32. Marx 1971a, pp. 167, 168; see also pp. 486, 524.
33· Marx 1973c, pp. 72-3; Marx 1971a, p. 168. See also Marx 1977, pp. 1067-9.
34· Marx 1971a, p. 579; see also pp. 580-1, and Marx 1977, pp. 1032, .1068. For the fluc-
tuation of a commodity's price around its value, see Marx 1971a, pp. 98-106.
70 • Chapter Five
women and children into the wage-labour force. Marx assumes a situation in which
the value of labour-power is such that the wage of a single adult male worker
suffices to support an entire family-household. -While this assumption is
questionable from a historical perspective, it provides a theoretical base-line
against which to examine variations in the value of labour-power. An innova-tion
such as the introduction of machinery, 'by throwing every member of [the
worker's] family on to the labor market, spreads the value of the man's labor power
over his whole family. It thus depreciates his labor power'. The value of the
individual worker's labour-power falls because it now takes the wage-work of
several household-members to obtain the original quantity of means of sub-
sistence. Marx amplifies this observation in several ways. Most important, the
entry of additional household-members into wage-labour means, other things being
equal, an intensification of the rate of exploitation. Further, the fact that several
family-members work where only one did before may require the pur-chase of
more means of subsistence, and thus raise somewhat the total value of the
household's labour-power. For example, 'domestic work, such as sewing and
mending, must be replaced by the purchase of ready-made articles. Hence the
diminished expenditure of labor in the house is accompanied by an increased
expenditure of money. The cost of keeping the family increases, and balances the
greater income'.35
It is perfectly possible for the value of the labour-power expended by an entire
household to rise substantially, accompanied by a real shift upward in its 'stan-dard
of life', while at the same time the value of the labour-power of the indi-viduals
comprising the household falls and the rate of exploitation increases. In general,
'the capitalist may pay higher wages and still lower the value of labor [power], if the
rise of wages does not correspond to the greater amount oflabor extracted, and the
quicker decay of the laboring power thus caused'. Marx gives a strikingly familiar
example of how bourgeois ideology interprets this phenom-enon: 'Your middle
class statisticians will tell you ... that the average wages of factory families in
Lancashire have risen. They forget that instead of the labor of the man, the head of
the family, his wife and perhaps three or four children are now thrown under the
Juggernaut wheels of capital, and that the rise of the aggregate wages does not
correspond to the aggregate surplus labor extracted from the family'.36
t the absolute mass of the proletariat and the productiveness of its labour, the
greater is the industrial reserve army ... This is the absolute generalla:w ofcapital-ist
accumulation'.37 More clearly than in the Grundrisse, Marx ties the existence, , size,
and form of a surplus-population to the processes of capital-accumulation.
As capital grows, it demands progressively more labour. Workers must work
harder and for longer hours, and more workers must be hired. 'Accumulation of
capital is, therefore, increase of the proletariat'. This tendency to swell the num-ber
of wage-workers absolutely is opposed by a second, and far more powerful,
mechanism also inherent in capital-accumulation. The drive for surplus-value
forces capitalists constantly to augment productivity, chiefly through the intro-
duction of machinery. An ever-growing quantity of means of production requires
less and less human labour to be set in motion in the production-process. As a
result, demand for labour falls relatively, and a surplus-population of wage-
workers emerges. This relative surplus-population constitutes 'a condition of
existence of the capitalist mode of production. It forms a disposable industrial
reserve army ... Independently of the limits of the actual increase of popula-tion, it
creates, for the changing needs of the self-expansion of capital, a mass of human
material always ready for exploitation'.38
The industrial reserve-army fluctuates in size according to the cruel whims of
the capitalist accumulation-cycle. At all times, moreover, relative surplus-
population takes several distinct forms. The floating reserve is made up of work-
ers who move in and out of employment according to the needs of the constantly
changing capitalist labour-process. The latent reserve consists of those thrust out of
work by the extension of capitalism into non-capitalist sectors. The stagnant
reserve is formed by chronically under-employed workers, who are condemned to
terrible poverty and always willing to work for the lowest wages in the worst
conditions. Below these three categories of reserves, paupers make up the bot-tom
layer of the surplus-population. 'Pauperism', Marx observes, 'is the hospital of the
active labor army and the dead weight of the industrial reserve army'.39
While he is never entirely clear in his for~ulations, Marx seems to regard the
industrial reserve-army as included in, rath~r than co-extensive with, the relative
surplus-population.
At once the product of capital-accumulation and the lever for its further
extension, the industrial reserve-army embodies a 'law of population' specific to
capitalism. In this sense, Marx puts the reproduction of the working class at the
heart of the capital-accumulation process. 'The reproduction of a mass of labor
power, which must incessantly re-incorporate itself with capital for that capital's
self-expansion; which cannot get free from capital, and whose enslavement to
capital is only concealed by the variety of individual capitalists to whom it sells
itself; this reproduction of labor power forms, in fact, an essential of the repro-
duction of capital itself'.40
In Volume III of Capital, Marx returns to the concepts of relative surplus-
population and the industrial reserve-army, this time looking at them in the con-
text of total social reproduction. At this level, the capitalist accumulation-process
itself gives rise to the tendency of the average rate of profit to fall. Among the
factors potentially counter-acting this tendency, Marx names the relative sur-plus-
population. Members of the industrial reserve-army form a pool of available cheap
labour. Some capitalists hire them at extremely low wages, and forgo the advances
in productivity that lead eventually to a falling average rate of profit. In these
branches of production, the rate and mass of surplus-value are unusu-ally high,
producing a counter-balance to those branches in which the rates have fallen. It
may even be that the industrial reserve-army 'more or less paralyzes' the tendency
of the average rate of profit to fall. Once again, the reproduction of the working
class stands at the centre of the process of capitalist production, now considered as
a whole.41
Marx's discussion of individual consumption, the value of labour-power, and the
industrial reserve-army is tantalisingly incomplete. In particular, the treat-ment of
three issues remains vague and requires clarification. First, it is never obvious
whether the concept of the value of labour-power covers the mainte-nance and
replacement of the individual worker alone or includes that of other persons as
well, for example, family-members supported by a worker's wage. Second, Marx
scarcely mentions the unpaid domestic labour performed as part of the tasks that
result in the reproduction of the worker, and accords it no clear theoretical status.
Third, the critical question of the relationship between the concept of the industrial
reserve-army, which appears in the context of dis-cussions of capital-
accumulation, and the more limited concept of individual consumption is never
really addressed.42 Despfte these ambiguities, and the
40. Marx 1971a, pp. 575-6. On laws of population, see pp. 591-2.
41. Marx 1971b, pp. 236-7. See also the section entitled 'Excess Capital and Excess
Population', pp. 250-9.
42· Marx would perhaps have taken on the task of resolving these contradictions and
gaps in the future, never developed, 'special study of wage labor'. Marx 1971a, p. 508.
Whether or not he would have addressed the question of women's oppression directly in the
study is, of course, another issue. Roman Rosdolsky's argument that Marx entirely
abandoned the plan for the separate book on wage-labour is unconvincing. Rosdolsky 1g77,
pp. 57-62. Molyneux suggests that the reproduction of labour-power constitutes a condition
of existence for capitalism, but cannot itself be placed theoretically within the concept of the
capitalist mode of production; hence, she claims, it was proper for Marx to exclude it from
the discussion in Capital: Molyneux 1979, p. 20. For the author's view, see Chapters 10 and
n.
Marx: the Mature Years • 73
In these years, Marx seized, once again, the opportunity to engage in practi-cal
political work. After a period of relative inactivity, the working classes of Europe
recovered from the defeats of 1848-so, and began a process of reorgani-sation
which took its most advanced form in the International Working Men's Association.
Founded in 1864 on the initiative of working-class militants, the International
represented an uneasy coalition of English trade-union leaders, whose chief
political aim was suffrage, a,J?.d French utopian socialists, bent on establishing
producers' cooperatives and 'opposed to both strikes and political action. It fell
largely to Marx and Engels to attempt the shaping of this amalgam into an adequate
force for socialism. For a decade, until the International col-lapsed in the wake of
the Paris Commune, they committed themselves to the delicate task.
'The woman has thus become an active agent in our social production', Marx
observed. It followed that women must be incorporated as active participants in
political work. 'Anybody who knows anything of history', he wrote to his friend
Dr. Ludwig Kugelmann, 'knows that major social transformations are impossible
without ferment among women'.48 In 1871, Marx initiated and the International
adopted a new rule recommending the establishment of female branches, with-out
excluding the possibility of branches composed of both sexes. 49 Effective
implementation of the recommendation depended, above all, on its being taken
seriously by men at every level of leadership. In view of the history of the nine-
teenth-century working-class movement, prospects for such a general commit-ment
were quite poor, and in any case, the International was nearing the end of its
organisational existence. Nonetheless, Marx's recommendation left an impor-tant
legacy by establishing, at least in principle, the legitimacy of autonomous women's
organisations within the mass movement.
After the collapse of the First International, Marx and Engels served as theo-
retical and tactical advisers to the emerging working-class parties that were later to
form the Second International. Thus, delegates from the new French Workers'
Party consulted them on the Party's programme for the 188o elections. Discussed
and drawn up in London, the programme included an introduction by Marx in
which, as he later put it, 'the communist goal is defined in a few words'. The
opening sentence of the introduction specifically asserts that 'the emancipa-tion of
the producing class involves all human beings without distinction of sex or race'. 50
These two issues- which, in the form of the so-called woman- and national
questions, were to constitute central problems for revolutionaries in the coming
decades - had already become a pressing concern in socialist theory and practice.
At the threshold of the epoch of imperialist domination and world revolution, but
at the close of his own life, Marx was still very much in step.
48. Anonymous 1964, pp. 2, 232. Marx to Dr. Kugelmann, 12 December, 1868, Marx
1934, p. 83 (translation slightly modified to accord with the German original; Marx und
Engels 1gs6a, pp. 582-3)· '
49· Anonymous 1964, pp. 442, 460. Like Marx, Engels supported, at least in principle,
equal participation by women in political life; see Engels to Ida Pauli, 14 February 1877,
cited in Meyer 1977, p. 93·
so. For the programme, see Guesde 1959, p. 117. The translation in Marx 1974, p. 376,
made, unaccountably, from a German version, misleadingly gives 'mankind' for 'etres
humaines'. Marx's later comment is in a letter to F. A. Sorge, 5 November 188o, Marx and
Engels 1965, p. 332. See also Engels to E. Bernstein, 25 October 1881: Marx and Engels
1965, p. 344·
76 • Chapter Five
Naturally enough, that outlook included some comments on women, the family,
and the reproduction of the working class, which generally recapitulate his own
and Marx's earlier analyses and positions. In a survey of pre-Marxist socialist
thinkers, for instance, Engels approves Fourier's critique of the relations between
the sexes and of women's position in capitalist society, and asserts, following
Marx's free paraphrase of Fourier in The Holy Family, that the utopian socialist was
the first to regard woman's position as an index of general social devel-opment.l
Engels also reviews a number of themes discussed in previous works: the
determination of the value of labour-power, the effects of machinery on the
working-class family, the emergence of an industrial reserve-army, the character
ofbourgeois marriage as a legal form of prostitution, and the progressive dissolu-
tion of traditional family-bonds, including 'patriarchal subordination', with the
advance of capitalism.2 Looking at the family in earlier societies, Engels speaks of
'the natural division of labor within the family', and with some qualification,
subsumes all members of a household under its male head. 3 Finally, Engels insists
that family-forms are rooted in social relations, and thus that the family can change
if society is transformed. In this context, he draws a critical pro-grammatic
corollary from Marx's statement in Capital that capitalism creates the foundation
for such changes. What is necessary is not only 'the free association of men', but
'the transformation of private domestic work into a public industry'. This is the first
formulation within the classical-Marxist tradition of a position later to become a
central tenet of socialist strategy. 4
Engels's other major book from this period is the famous The Origin ofthe Family,
Private Property, and the State, written between March and May of 1884, pub-lished
that October, and instantaneously accorded the place of a socialist classic.
The circumstances of Engels's startlingly rapid production of the Origin remain
somewhat mysterious. The book is based, as its subtitle ('In the Light of the
Researches of Lewis H. Morgan') indicates, on Morgan's Ancient Society, which had
appeared in 1877 and immediately engaged Marx's interest. Writing to the German
socialist Kautsky on 16 February 1884, Engels described the late Marx's enthusiasm
for Morgan's book, adding 'if I had the time I would work up the material, with
Marx's notes, ... but I cannot even think of it'. Yet by late March he was already at
work on the Origin and by the end of April close to
1. Engels 1947, p. 308. For Marx's paraphrase of Fourier, see note 2 of Chapter 4·
2. Engels 1947, pp. 243-5, 304, 310, 325-8.
3· Engels 1947, pp. n8, 214, 215, 319, 322.
4· Engels 1947, p. 377· The question of changes in the organisation of domestic labour
had, of course, long been a concern among utopian thinkers; see, for example, Hayden
1981.
Engels: a Defective Formulation • 79
finishing. 5 The full explanation of the reasons for Engels's change in plan, which is
especially striking in view of the fact that he was already immersed in the edit-ing
of Marx's unfinished volumes of Capital, must await further research. It seems }
ikely that the context was political. In 1879, the German socialist leader August Be
bel had published Woman in the Past, Present and Future, which appeared in a
revised version late in 1883. Tremendously popular from the start, Be bel's Woman
bore the influence of utopian socialism throughout; in addition, it reflected
emerging tendencies toward reformism within the socialist movement. Engels's
decision to write the Origin surely reflected a recognition of the weaknesses in
Bebel's work. The socialist movement's commitment to the liberation of women
urgently required an adequate theoretical foundation. Understood as an implicit
polemic within the movement, the Origin represented Engels's attempt to provide
one. 6
The socialist tradition has treated the Origin as the definitive Marxist pro-
nouncement on the family and therefore on the so-called woman question. Fur-ther,
the tradition holds that the book accurately reflects the views of Marx as well as
Engels. Neither assertion fairly measures the work's status. In the first place, the
subject covered in the Origin, as its title indicates, is the development not only of
the family but of private property and the state. The observation is important, for it
suggests the book's limited goals with respect to the issue of women's
subordination. Rather than provide a comprehensive analysis of women, the family,
and the reproduction of the working class, the Origin seeks simply to situate certain
aspects of the question securely in a historical and theo-retical context. In the
second place, the Origin bears the scars of its hasty genesis throughout. Far from
the work of either Marx or Engels at his best, it constitutes, in Engels's words, a
'meagre substitute for what my departed friend no longer had the time to do'.7
In drafting the Origin, Engels relied not just on Morgan's Ancient Society, but on
a series of notebooks in which Marx had entered passages from various authors'
writings concerning primitive so~Jety. These 'Ethnological Notebooks', composed in
188o-1, include a lengthy abstract of Morgan's book. It is not at all clear what Marx
intended to do with the material he was collecting, and Engels altered the
framework established in the 'Notebooks' to some extent. To grasp the structure and
meaning of Engels's book, it is, therefore, necessary
5· Engels to Kautsky, 16 February and 26 April 1884, Marx and Engels 1965, pp. 368,
372. See also Krader ( ed.) 1972, pp. 388-90.
6. For the publication history and a critique ofAugust Be bel's Woman and Socialism, see
Chapter 7·
7· Engels 1972, p. 71. Important critical evaluations of the Origin include: Brown 1978;
Brown 1979; Delmar 1976; Draper 1972; Hindess and Hirst 1975, pp. 28-9, 58-9; Krader
1972; Lane 1976; Leacock 1963; Sacks 1975; Santamaria 1975; Stem 1948.
So • Chapter Six
Morgan devotes nearly two-thirds of Ancient Society to Part Two, 'Growth of the
Idea of Government'. Here, he presents a theory of the evolution of social
organisation from early kin-based forms to fully developed political governance.
The social organisation of the most primitive peoples is based simply on broadly
defined 'classes' of persons permitted to marry one another. As the circle of pos-
sible marriage partners narrows, the 'gens', or clan, develops. A clan consists of
persons related through one parental line only. In a 'gentile' society - that is, one
organised on the basis of clans - an individual belongs to the clan of either mother
or father, not to both. Marriage must ordinarily be to someone outside one's own
clan. Where property exists, it is retained within the clan upon the death of a
member. The fundamental social unit is therefore the clan, either matrilineal or
patrilineal. The couple bond cannot have the central structural role it later acquires,
for it links persons whose major allegiances are to distinct clans. Morgan shows
that the gentile, or clan, system provides the foundation for
8. Morgan 1877. Of many subsequent reprint-editions, the most useful is Leacock 1963
(Krader 1972).
Engels: a Defective Formulation • 81
quite complex types of social organisation. Clans may be grouped in larger units,
called phratries, and these in tum may join to form tribes. In the clan-system's
rnost developed form, which Morgan believed he had observed among the
Iroquois Indians, several tribes constitute a confederacy,· or nation, able to include
thousands of members over a vast geographical area, yet lacking formal political
institutions and still based on personal ties.
In the latest stages of barbarism, technological advances in productivity ren-der
society so complex that clan organisation must give way. The city develops,
bringing heightened requirements at the level of governance not solvable by the
dan-system. Property, while not a new phenomenon, attains a dominant role.
'Henceforth the creation and protection of property became the primary objects of
the govemment'.9 In place of the clan-system step the institutions of political
organisation, for government can no longer rest on personal relations. Morgan
sketches the early evolution of the state, which organizes people, now distrib-uted
in property-classes, on a territorial basis. Taking Rome as his example, he cites
three principal changes that mark the shift from gentile to political society. First, a
system of classes based on property replaces the clan-organisation. Sec-ond,
instead of government by means of a democratic tribal council, an assembly
dominated by the propertied classes holds, and soon extends, political power.
Third, territorial areas, rather than kin-based clans, phratries, or tribes, become the
units of government.
Even before the emergence of developed political organisation, a critical change
occurred within the clan-system. At a certain point, matrilineal clan-organisation
succumbed to the principle of patrilineality, under the impetus of the development
of property. According to Morgan, descent through the female-line was the original
form of clan-organisation, because of its biological certainty. However, as soon as
property in cattle and land emerged, two facts, entirely self-evident in Morgan's
view, meant that 'descent in the female-line was certain of overthrow, and the
substitution of the male-line equally assured'. 10 First, men naturally became the
owners of the propeJ;ty; second, they developed a natural wish to transmit it to
their own children.'Hence, in the middle-stages of barba-rism, the accumulation of
property has the consequence that the patrilineal clan becomes the basic unit of the
gentile social system.
Part Three, entitled 'Growth of the Idea of the Family', makes up roughly one-
quarter of Ancient Society. Emphasising that the form of the family is highly vari-
able, Morgan traces its evolution through five stages. Progressive restriction of
permissible marriage partners constitutes the basis of the development. In the first
type of family, the, 'consanguine', sisters and female cousins are married, as
a group, to their brothers and male cousins. The next family type, the 'punaluan',
modifies the first by prohibiting marriage between own brothers and sisters.
These two forms of group-marriage, which suggest an even earlier stage of
promiscuous intercourse, represent conjectural forms, reconstructed by Morgan on
the basis of his understanding of kin-terminology, and broadly corresponding to
the stages of savagery and early barbarism.
The third form, the 'syndyasmian' or 'pairing' family, is founded on marriage
between single-pairs, who live within communal households and whose bond may
be dissolved at the will of either partner. The pairing family constitutes the family-
type associated with clan-based societies. Lineage-ties remain primary to each
partner, for the clan is the basic social unit and takes final responsibility for its
members. Morgan notes the measure of collective security provided to individuals
by this system, as well as its relative egalitarianism when compared with
subsequent family forms.
The last two family-types reflect the influence of the development of property.
The 'patriarchal' family organises a group of persons - slave, servant, and free -
under a male head who exercises supreme authority. The 'monogamian' family is
based on the marriage of a single couple which, with its children, composes an
independent household. Morgan conceptualises both family-types as insti-tutions
whose primary purpose is to hold property and transmit it exclusively to their
offspring. To ensure the children's paternity, strict fidelity is required of women.
Paternal power is more or less absolute, and only death can break the marriage-
bond. The patriarchal and monogamian families therefore stand in total opposition
to clan-organisation. They are forms more appropriate for political society, and
they appear in the last stages of barbarism and continue into the period of
civilisation.
Morgan argues that the patriarchal and monogamian families represent a social
advance, for they permit a heightened individuality of persons. At the same time,
he recognises that in practice, such individuality was available to men only.
Women, as well as children, were generally subordinated to the pater-nal power of
the family-head. By contrast, the pairing family of clan-society had provided
women with a certain level of relative equality and power, particu-larly before the
transition to patrilineal descent. So long as children remained in their mother's
clan, the pairing family was embedded in the matrilineal clan household, and
Morgan thought it likely that the woman, rather than the man, functioned as the
family's centre. With the shift to descent in the male line, the pairing family
became part of the patrilineal clan household, and the woman was more isolated
from her gentile kin. This change 'operated powerfully to lower her position and
arrest her progress in the social scale', but the woman was still a member of her
own clan and thus retained a substantial measure of
Engels: a Defective Formulation • 83
independent social standing.11 The advent of paternal power in the patriarchal and
monogamian families opens the way to a much more profound degradation of
woman's position. Here, the cruel subordination of women and children belies
Morgan's optimistic notions of evolutionary development. He presents the mate-
rial honestly, however, heartened by a faith that monogamy is, in principle at least,
the highest and most egalitarian form of the family. Nevertheless, the empirical
evidence stands in contradiction to Morgan's own commitment to a progressivist
theory of evolution.l2 It fell to Engels, in the Origin, to suggest a more adequate
theoretical framework.
Ancient Society closes with Part Four, entitled 'Growth of the Idea of Property', in
which Morgan summarises his understanding of social development. He dis-
tinguishes three stages in the developmeht of property, generally corresponding to
the three major evolutionary periods. Among the most primitive peoples, those at
the level of savagery, property scarcely exists. Lands are held in com-mon, as is
housing, and Morgan speculates that the germ of property lies in a developing right
to inherit personal articles. Property in land, houses, and live-stock emerges in the
stage ofbarbarism. The rules of inheritance at first conform to clan-organisation:
property reverts to the clan of the deceased, not to his or her spouse. Eventually,
individual ownership through the monogamian family prevails, with property
inherited by the deceased owner's children. The period of civilisation has arrived.
In conclusion, Morgan offers the observation that in his own time, property has
become an 'unmanageable power'. Society is on a collision course, and its
disintegration is the logical consequence 'of a career of which property is the end
and aim; because such a career contains the elements of self-destruction'.
Nevertheless, Morgan holds out hope for society's reconstruction on 'the next
higher plane', where it will appear as 'a revival, in a higher form, of the liberty,
equality and fraternity' of ancient clan society.l3
Ancient Society is a monumental work. In it, Morgan solved the puzzle of dan-
organisation, described the sequence ,?f social institutions in evolutionary terms,
and attempted to analyse the basis 'for their development. Published in 1877, the
book became the foundation for all subsequent research on the his-tory of early
human societies, despite its many factual and interpretive errors. These short-
comings, as well as Morgan's substantial contributions, have been
14· The starting point for any evaluation of Morgan's Ancient Society must be Lea-
cock's introduction to Ancient Society - Leacock 1963.
15. Morgan 1877, pp. vii, 3, 8.
16. Morgan 1877, pp. 511-12, 263, vii; see also pp. 5-6.
Engels: a Defective Formulation • 85
To the extent that Engels incorporated the material in Ancient Society into his
Origin, he adopted the organisation of Marx's excerpts in the 'Ethnological
Notebooks' - making, however, several important structural changes. He did not
devote a separate chapter to the subject of property. He greatly enlarged the
relative importance of the chapter on the family, giving it almost as much space as
he assigned to the chapters on the state. And he shifted the focus to the transition
between barbarism and civilisation, in accordance with his and Marx's interest in
the emergence of the state. In this way, Engels converted Morgan's four 'lines of
human progress' into three sections, which make up the bulk of the Origin.
17. Krader 1972, pp. n and 365, n. 21. See also the review of Krader in Santamaria
1975·
18. Engels 1972, p. 93·
86 • Chapter Six
•HnJteis regards the shift to the patrilineal clan-system as pivotal in its impact
society and on women's position. It marks the establishment of a set of social
-~t14Jns conducive to the further evolution not only of private property but of
.....r.,~~- class-society. More dramaticallt, 'the overthrow of mother right was
world historic defeat of the female sex. The man took command in the home the
woman was degraded and reduced to servitude; she became the slave of his lust
and a mere instrument for the production of children'.22 The patriarchal
family, with its incorporation of slaves and servants under the supreme authority
of the male head, now emerges as a form intermediate between the pairing fam-ily
and monogamy. Engels offers specific historical examples of this transition-stage,
emphasising the relationship between land-tenure and social structure, as well as
the brutality of the patriarch toward women in the household.
In discussing the monogamous family, Engels again follows Morgan while
simultaneously incorporating a clearer analysis of property-relations and focusing
on the question of woman's position. The monogamous family appears toward the
end of the second stage in the development of the arts of subsistence - that is, at
the threshold of civilisation - and represents a perfected form for the transmission
of private property from father to children. Engels emphasises the origin of the
monogamous family in economic conditions and its function as a property-holding
institution. 'It was the first form of the family to be based not on natural but on
economic conditions - on the victory of private property over primitive, natural
communal property'.23 Although Engels never states it unam-
•1
biguously, the implication is that the fori:n of the monogamous, as well as the
patriarchal, family constitutes a product of the rise of class-society.
Engels has no illusions about the position of women in the monogamous fam-
ily. Monogamy is a standard enforced on the woman only, and exists solely to
guarantee the paternity of the offspring, not for any reasons oflove or affection.
Men remain free to live by a different standard. At the same time, the phenom-
enon of the neglected wife begets its own consequences. Thus, side by side with
the husband over the wife in the modem family, the necessity of creating rea}
social equality between them and the way to do it, will only be seen in the clear
light of day when both possess legally complete equality ·of rights.'28
Although generally consistent with Marx's sketch of the reproduction of labour-
power, Engels's consideration of women's oppression is flawed or incom-plete in
several critical respects. In the first place, he assumes that it is natural for 'family
duties' to be the exclusive province of women, and that therefore they always will
be. Furthermore, he does not clearly link the development of a spe-cial sphere
associated with the reproduction oflabour power to the emergence of class-, or,
perhaps, capitalist society. For pre-capitalist class-societies, he fails to specify the
nature of women's subordination in different classes. Finally, Engels's emphasis on
the strategic importance of democratic rights leaves open the ques-tion of the
relationship between socialist revolution, women's liberation, and the struggle for
equal rights. The result is ambiguous, potentially suggesting that the socialist
programme for women's liberation consists of two discrete objectives: equal rights
with men in the still-capitalist short term; and full liberation on the basis of a
higher form of the family in the far distant revolutionary millennium.
Engels closes the chapter on the family with a long look to the future. 29 These
pages trace, yet again, the development of monogamy on the basis of private
property, and attempt a sketch of family-experience in a society in which the means
of production have been converted into social property. True monogamy, that is,
monogamy for the man as well as the woman, will now be possible, along with
wide development of that highest of intimate emotions, individual sex-love.
Exactly what relations between the sexes will look like cannot be predicted, for it is
up to a new generation of women and men born and raised in socialist society.
'When these people are in the world, they will care precious little what anybody
today thinks they ought to do; they will make their own practice and their
corresponding public opinion about the practice of each individual - and that will
be the end of it'. Engels's focus on the emotional and sexual content of inter-
personal relations within the family-household reflected a common view that they
represent the essence of the so-called woman-question.30
Only at one point in this section does he dwell on the implications of the future
abolition of the family's economic functions, observing that with the means of
production held in common, 'the single family ceases to be the eco-nomic unit of
society. Private housekeeping is transformed into a social industry'.
28. Ibid.
29. Engels 1972, pp. 138-46.
30. Engels 1972, p. 145. The subjects oflove and sexuality are covered at even
greater length by Bebel in Bebel1971.
Engels: a Defective Formulation • 91
Moreover, 'the care and education of the children becomes a public affair'. 31 These
brief hints offer the barest programmatic guidance, and do not differ, in substance,
from nineteenth-century communitarian proposals. In short, Engels's chapter on
the family in the Origin remains an unintegrated mix of Morgan's dry materialism
and a radical view of sexual liberation - seasoned with genuine insights into the
nature of property- and social-relations, and liberally sprinkled with Engels's
warmth and wit.
In Chapters 3-8 of the Origin, corresponding to the section on government in
Morgan's Ancient Society, Engels examines the nature of clan-society and traces the
rise of the state. As in Chapter 2 on the family, he follows Morgan's general line of
argument, while at the same time focusing it and integrating the material on
property. In Engels's words, the chaflges 'in form' between the institutions of the
gentile constitution and those of the state 'have been outlined by Mor-gan, but their
economic content and cause must largely be added by myself'. 32 The resulting
discussion suffers from defects similar to those already observed in Engels's
account of the family. Moreover, it becomes more obvious in these chapters that
Engels identifies private property and the market-exchange of commodities as the
pivotal social developments in history. Nowhere, however, does he clearly discuss
these phenomena in terms of the social relations that constitute the mode of
production in which they originate.
In these chapters, a critique of property takes the place of a critique of class-
relations. Property, not exploitation - the appropriation of the surplus-labour of the
producing class by another class - becomes the implicit object of class struggle.
From the point of view of Marx's theory of social reproduction, how-ever, both
private property and commodity-exchange only represent specific manifestations
of particular types of class-society. In such societies, a given set of relations of
exploitation always dominates, constituting the basis for specific social relations
and forms of private property, the market, the state, and so forth. The difference
between this formulation and that in the Origin is crucial, and not simply a matter
of style or manner of exposition. It reveals that the argu-
•1
ments put forth by Engels in the Origin' generally remain within the theoreti-cal
framework of a utopian critique of property. Marx's comments about his favorite
utopian-socialist target, Proudhon, would apply equally to Engels: he should have
analysed 'property relations as a whole, not in their Legal expres-sion as relations
ofvolition but in their real form, that is, as relations ofproduc-tion. [Instead,] he has
entangled the whole of these economic relations in the general juristic conception
of "property'". Furthermore, Engels has confused the
circumstance that the products of labour are exchanged in a society, with the
presence of capitalist, or at least class-, relations ofproduction.~3
In the Origin's closing Chapter g, 'Barbarism and Civilization', Engels exam-ines
the 'general economic conditions' behind the developments presented in previous
chapters. 'Here', he observes, 'we shall need Marx's Capital as much as Morgan's
book'.34 Unfortunately, it is already far too late, for the analytical weaknesses
encountered throughout the Origin permeate this highly repetitive chapter.
Engels restates his account of social evolution in the period of the decline of
clan-society and the emergence of civilisation, this time pointing out a series of
major milestones. In the middle-stages of barbarism, the separation of pastoral
tribes from the mass of other peoples marks the 'first great social division of labor'.
These tribes tame animals and develop agriculture; as a result they soon find
themselves with products that make regular exchange possible. Inevitably and
automatically, the increasing exchange leads to higher productivity, more wealth,
and a society in which the harnessing of surplus-labour becomes fea-sible. Hence,
slavery appears. 'From the first great social division of labor arose the first great
cleavage of society into two classes: masters and slaves, exploit-ers and exploited'.
Engels reminds the reader that the change in the division of labour also has
consequences for relations between the sexes in the family. Because the pre-
existing division of labour had supposedly assigned the task of procuring
subsistence to men, men become the holders of the new wealth, and women find
themselves subordinated and confined to private domestic labour. A 'second great
division of labor' occurs at the close of the period of barbarism, when handicraft
separates from agriculture. On this basis, a new cleavage of soci-ety into classes
develops, the opposition between rich and poor. Inequalities of property among
individual male heads of families now lead to the break up of the communal
household, and the pairing marriage dissolves into the monoga-mous single family,
even more oppressive to women. Finally, a third division of labour emerges in the
period of civilisation: a class of merchants arises, parasites whose nefarious
activities lead to periodic trade-crises. In the meantime, the rise of class-cleavages
has necessitated replacement of the gentile constitution with a third force, powerful
but apparently above the class-struggle - namely, the state. 35
In sum, the concluding chapter of the Origin argues that civilisation results from
the continual evolution of the division oflabour, which in turn gives rise to
33· Marx to J.D. Schweitzer, 24january 186s; Marx and Engels 1965, p. 153. Marx 1971a, pp.
115-16, 165-7·
34· Engels 1972, p. 217.
35· Engels 1972, pp. 218-25.
Engels: a Defective Formulation • 93
As in the chapter on the family, Engels here assumes that domestic labour is purely
women's work, does not locate his statement with respect to a specific class-
society, and blurs the relationship between women's eventual liberation in
communist society and immediate strategic goals.
Engels formulates the relationship between social transformation and women's
equality more specifically in a letter written in 1885: 'It is my conviction that real
equality of women and men can come true only when the exploitation of either
36. Engels 1972, pp. 223, 224, 235; see also pp. 119, 161.
37· Engels 1972, p. 221.
94 • Chapter Six
by capital has been abolished and private housework has been transformed into a
public industry'. In the meantime, protective legislation is necessary. 'That the
working woman needs special protection against capitalist exploitation because of
her special physiological functions seems obvious to me ... I admit I am more
interested in the health of the future generations than in the absolute formal
equality of the sexes during the last years of the capitalist mode of production'. 38
Once again, Engels wrestles with the problem of distinguishing juridical equality
from real social equality.
Engels made one argument in the Origin that the socialist movement later refused
to endorse, but which has recently been taken up by theorists of the contemporary
women's liberation movement. In a frequently cited passage from the 1884 preface
to the Origin, Engels spoke of two types of production proceed-ing in parallel: on
the one hand, the production of the means of subsistence, and on the other, the
production of human beings. The dualistic formulation strikingly recalls the never
published German Ideology of 1846, in which Marx and Engels had suggested a
similar characterisation of the dual essence of social reproduction: 'The production
of life, both of one's own in labor and of fresh life in procreation, ... appears as a
twofold relation: on the one hand as a natural, on the other as a social relation'. 39
The dependence of the Origin on the forty-year-old German Ideology is not lim-
ited to this dramatic linguistic parallel. Engels drew quite heavily on the forgot-ten
manuscript of his and Marx's youth, which he had just rediscovered among Marx's
papers.40 Thus, both texts make a relatively sharp distinction between natural and
social phenomena, emphasising the purely biological or animal-like character of
procreation. Furthermore, The German Ideology assigns, as does the Origin, a
central motivating role in social development to the continual evolu-tion of the
division of labour. According to The German Ideology, society devel-ops in stages,
beginning from the simplest forms, in which the only division of labour is natural,
and rooted in the sexual act. With-the growth of the division of labour, social
relations distinguish themselves from natural ones, and the 'family relation'
becomes subordinate. Both The German Ideology and the Origin refer to the
development, at this point in history, of a relationship of latent slavery within the
family, representing 'the first form of property'.41 Finally, both texts
38. Engels to Gertrude Guillaume-Schak, 5 July 1885, Marx and Engels 1965, p. 386.
39· Engels 1972, pp. 71-2; text of passage cited in Chapter 3 of Marx and Engels 1975b,
p. 43·
40. Marx und Engels 1956b, pp. 33-4; see also pp. 39, 41, and 54, and Engels 1972, p.
129. For The German Ideology, see Chapter 4· On the textual similarity, see also Geiger
1968, pp. 30-2.
41. Marx and Engels 1975a, pp. 33, 46; Engels 1972, pp. 121, 134, 137.
Engels: a Defective Formulation • 95
put forth an equivocal image of the family as a germ or nucleus within which
larger social contradictions originate or are reflected, and which itself constitutes
the fundamental building block of society.42
Engels's extensive reliance on The German Ideology has the effect of importing
into the Origin many of the theoretical weaknesses of the earlier manuscript. In
1846, when Marx and Engels composed The German Ideology, they had been on the
threshold of two lifetimes of profound contributions to the socialist move-ment.
The manuscript bears, nonetheless, the marks of its very early place in their
development. Thus when Engels, in the preface to the Origin, echoes the
dichotomy suggested in The German Ideology by positing two separate sys-tems of
production of material life, he simply takes a very primitive distinction between
natural and social phenomena to its logical conclusion. His return to this
dichotomy, long after he, and even more so Marx, had generally transcended it in
subsequent work, epitomises the theoretical ambiguity found throughout the
Origin. Socialists at the tum of the century found the preface's assertion concerning
the duality of social reproduction 'very remarkable', indeed, 'almost
incomprehensible'. Soviet commentators eventually settled on the view that Engels
was mistaken, and that the statement can only refer to the very earliest period of
human history, when people were supposedly so much a part of nature that social
43
relations of production could not be said to exist. What disturbed these theorists
was the implication that the family represents an autonomous, if not wholly
independent, centre of social development. And it is precisely this implication that
has caught the imagination of contemporary socialist feminists, often tempting
them into a quite cavalier reading of the Origin.
Engels's purpose in writing the Origin was 'to present the results of Morgan's
researches in the light of the conclusions of [Marx's] materialist examination of
history, and thus to make clear their full significance'. 44 Engels's treatment of the
material falls short, however, of this goal, for he only partially transforms
Morgan's crude materialism. The Origin is J.llarred throughout by Engels's fail-,'
ure to base the discussion on an adequate exposition of Marx's theory of social
development. Instead, Engels relies, quite erratically, on several theoretical
frameworks in addition to his understanding of Marx's work: the technologi-cal
determinism implicit in Morgan's Ancient Society, his main source of data; The
German Ideology's early version of historical materialism; and a generally
42. Marx and Engels 1975b, p. 46; Engels 1972, pp. 121-2, 129, 131, 137.
43· On the tum-of-the-century socialists, see Geiger 1968, pp. 31-2; similar opinions have
been expressed more recently in Hindess and Hirst 1975, pp. 58-9. On the Soviet view, see
Sterri 1948, p. 48, n. 10. For other critiques of the dualism implicit in the Origin, see Brown
1979 and O'Laughlin 1975, pp. 5-7.
44· Engels 1972, p. 71.
g6 • Chapter Six
utopian critique of property and view of the socialist future. While the Origin
manages, in places, to rise above this eclecticism, its theoretical weaknesses and
omissions were to have serious consequences. The Origin constituted a defec-tive
text whose ambiguous theoretical and political formulations nevertheless became
an integral part of the socialist legacy.
Part Three
The Socialist Movement
thapter Seven
fhe Second International
war broke out in 1914, these paths diverged. With a few important exceptions
'
the International splintered along the lines of opposing armies. For the
socialist movement, the problem ofwomen'soppression was, in prin-ciple, an
inseparable part of what was called the 'social question'~ Socialist parties took up the
so-called woman-question in party-newspapers, and also produced a modest
amount of theoretical and agitationalliterature. With some reluctance, they
incorporated women's political rights in their programmes, sought to build mass
women's movements, and encouraged trade-unions to organise women workers.
Despite weaknesses, the socialist movement offered the most sustained and
thoroughgoing support then available to the struggle for sex-equality and women's
liberation. At the same time, examination of some examples of party-literature on
the woman-question suggests that for the most part, the Second International failed
to clarify, much less extend, the incomplete legacy of theo-retical work left by Marx
and Engels. Moreover, by codifying and in some mea-sure sanctifying this legacy,
the socialist movement actually hampered its ability
to move beyond inherited ambiguities.
Among party and trade-union militants able to find time to read socialist books,
Woman and Socialism, by the German Social-Democratic leader August Bebel,
ranked first in popularity. Originally published in 1879, by 1895 it had gone through
25 editions, and by 1910, so, not to mention numerous foreign transla-tions. For
years, Woman and Socialism was the book most borrowed from work-ers' libraries
in Germany, and it continued to serve as a major socialist primer into the first
decades of the twentieth century.
What was it that so persistently drew workers and socialists to a book nearly
five hundred pages long? In the first place, Woman, as the German movement
dubbed the book, was virtually the only work in the Marxist literature of the period
that spoke to people's desire for a detailed and specific picture of the socialist
future. Scanning the oppressive past an~ dissecting the capitalist pres-ent, the book
also devoted whole sections to sketching the general outlines of what life in the
socialist society to come might be like. 'It is quite safe to say', observed a library-
journal in 1910, 'that it was from this book that the proletarian masses derived their
socialism'. And years later, a party-activist reminisced that 'for us young socialists
Be bel's book was not just a programme, it was a gospel'. Until the Bolshevik
Revolution opened up the possibility of a real-life example, Woman offered the
most developed vision of what socialists were fighting for. 1
But the book was not just about socialism, it was also about women- Woman in
the Past, Present and Future, as the title of the second edition announced. For
Baader went on to join the party and take an active role in its politicallife. 2 For
certain militants within the German Social-Democratic Party, the publica-
tion of Woman and Socialism had a further meaning. Clara Zetkin, for instance,
observed in 1896 that Be bel's book, irrespective of any defects, 'must be judged
by the time at which it appeared. And it was then more than a book, it was an
event, a deed', for it provided party-members with a demonstration of the rela-
tionship between the subordination of women and the development of society.
Zetkin interpreted the publication of Bebel's work as a symbol of the Party's
practical commitment to developing women as socialist activists. 'For the first
time', she noted, 'from this book issued the watchword: We can conquer the future
only if we win the women as co-fighters'.3
As Woman progressed through edition after edition, Be bel continually revised
and enlarged its text. The first edition, totalling only 180 pages and not sub-divided
into chapters, appeared just after the German government attempted to crack down
on the growing socialist movement by banning the SPD and institut-ing severe
censorship. Despite the book's il,\egal status, it sold out in a matter of months. Not
until1883 was Bebel to locate another publisher willing to produce the book, as
well as find time to expand and revise it. In an unsuccessful attempt to get around
the anti-socialist laws, he re-titled the 220-page second edition Woman in the Past,
Present and Future, a change corresponding to the new chapter-structure. Although
the authorities nevertheless banned the book, it was once again an immediate
success and quickly sold out, as did six subsequent edi-tions in the following years.
In 18go, the anti-socialist laws were lifted, and Be bel prepared a substantially
reworked ninth edition, which appeared early in 1891.
Re-christened Woman and Socialism, and expanded to 384 pages, the ninth edition
also incorporated, for the first time, parts of Engels's analysis from the Origin. It
was this version of Woman, repeatedly reprinted, and in 1895 further i
extended to 472 pages for its 25th edition, that became the socialist classic. ·
The German-speaking socialist movement thus had the distinction of produc-
ing two major works on the question of women's oppression within a span of
only a few years: the first, Hebel's Woman and Socialism, by a major leader of
the powerful German socialist party, the second, Engels's Origin, published in
1884, by Marx's collaborator, now a tremendously respected but somewhat iso-
lated figure, living in political exile. Given the convergence of subject matter
and politics in the two books, one would expect the voluminous correspon-
dence between the authors to include a substantial exchange of views on the
issues. Instead, a strange silence reigns, punctured by a few casual comments. On
18 January 1884, Engels thanks Hebel for sending him a copy of the second edi-
tion of Woman. 'I have read it with great interest', he notes, 'it contains much
valuable material. Especially lucid and fine is what you say about the develop-
ment of industry in Germany'. On 6 June, he mentions the forthcoming publi-
cation of the Origin, and promises to send Hebel a copy. On 1-2 May 1891, he
notes his desire to prepare a new edition of the Origin, which he did that June.
Hebel's letters to Engels mention his own book only in the context of problems
arising with the English translation, and do not refer to the Origin at all. Engels's
letters to other correspondents document the Origin's conception, writing, and
preparation for publication during the first five months of 1884, but say nothing
about his opinion of Hebel's work. The impression remains of a silent polemic
between differing views. Despite his special relationship to the socialist move-
ment, Engels probably judged it tactically unwise to do more than publish the
Origin, and hope it would be recognised as the more accurate approach to the
issue of women's oppression.4
Hebel divides Woman and Socialism into three major sections, Woman in the
Past', Woman in the Present', and Woman in the-Future'. Most of the constant
textual revision in successive printings consists of changes of a factual nature,
made to deepen and update the arguments. Only the publication of Engels's Origin
required Hebel to make substantial modifications, which he largely con-fined to
the first section. In the early version of Woman in the Past', he had pre-sented an
abundance of ethnographic evidence in rather disorganised fashion, under the
assumption that 'although the forms of [woman's] oppression have varied, the
oppression has always remained the same'.
4· The correspondence between Be bel and Engels appears in Blumenberg ( ed.) 1965,
nos. 58, 59, 62, 8o, 157, 28o, 2g8. Engels's letters to other correspondents are listed in
Krader 1972, pp. 388-go. See also the discussion of Engels's Origin in Chapter 6.
The Second International • 103
, Engels's work made him realise the inaccuracy of this statement, and, as he ,ter
put it, enabled him to place the historical material on a correct foundation. Jebel
entirely recast the section in order to argue that relations between the ~es, like all
social relations, 'have materially changed in the previous course ef human
development ... in even step with the existing systems of production, ~n the one
hand, and of the distribution of the products oflabor, on the other'. :With the aid of
the Origin, he was now able to present the ethnographic material in the context of a
more systematic sketch of the history of the development of the family, private
property, the state, and capitalism. These changes hardly affected, however, Be
bel's analysis in the rest of the book.5
The section Woman in the Present' makes up the bulk of Woman and Social-ism.
It includes two long chapters on the 'current crisis of capitalism and on the nature
of socialist society ('The State and Society' and 'The Socialization of Soci-ety').
These chapters, as well as the four sections that close the book - Woman in the
Future', 'Internationality', 'Population and Over-Population', and 'Conclu-sion' -
barely touch on the situation of women. In other words, despite its title and chapter
headings, over a third of Woman and Socialism focuses on the larger 'social
question'. No wonder so many socialists read the book more as a sort of
inspirational general text than as a specific study on the question of women.
The strengths of Woman and Socialism lie precisely in its powerful indictment of
capitalist society, and the contrasting image it presents of a socialist future. As
detail follows detail and compelling anecdotes multiply, Bebel assembles a mass
ofinformation on virtually every aspect of women's subordination and the social
question in general. In capitalist society, marriage and sexuality have acquired a
distorted, unnatural character. 'The marriage founded upon bourgeois property
relations, is more or less a marriage by compulsion, which leads numerous ills in
its train'. Sexual repression results in mental illness and suicide. Sex without love
is also damaging, for 'man is no animal. Mere physical satisfaction does not suf-
fice'. Where 'the blending of the sexes is a purely mechanical act: such a marriage is
5· For the history of the early editions of Woman and Socialism, see Bebel's 'Vorrede
zur neunten Auflage', dated 24 December 1890, in Bebel 1891. The follow-ing
discussion cites the easily available English translations of the second and 33rd editions
to stand for, respectively, the early version and the classic text of Woman and Socialism.
The second edition is Bebel 1976, the 33rd is Bebel 1971, cited hereaf-ter as Woman.
Citations in this paragraph are from Bebel 1976, p. 18, and Bebel 1971, p. 10. For a
useful evaluation of Be bel's work, see Evans 1977, pp. 156-9.
6. Bebel1971, pp. 85, 86, 146.
104 • Chapter Seven
What is natural, he says, is the sexual instinct itself. Indeed, 'of all the natural
impulses human beings are instinct with, along with that of eating and drinking,
the sexual impulse is the strongest'. Despite a fairly simplistic view of instinct,
Bebel's lengthy attack on the notion of eternally fixed sex-divisions of labour
stands out as an important political contribution to the socialist movement. For
once a socialist leader confronted the ideological character of claims about the
social consequences of physiological sex-differences. 9
With all its strengths, Woman and Socialism nevertheless suffers from a seri-
ously impoverished theoretical apparatus, as well as various political defects. Be
bel's theoretical perspective actually consists of an eclectic mix of two major
trends within the socialist tradition, trends against which Marx himself had often
struggled. On the one hand, Woman and Socialism reflects a utopian-socialist
oudook reminiscent of Fourier and other early nineteenth-century socialists,
particularly in its view of individual development within a communitarian con-
text. And on the other, the book exhibits a mechanical and incipiently reform-ist
interpretation of Marxism, thus heralding the severe reformism that overran most
parties in the Second International by the turn of the century. Lacking an adequate
theoretical foundation, Be bel's discussion of women's oppression and liberation
follows an erratic and sometimes contradictory course. From the start, he
conceptualises the issues in terms of the free development of the female indi-
vidual. 'The so-called "Woman Question" ... concerns the position that woman
should occupy in our social organism; how she may unfold her powers and facul-
ties in all directions, to the end that she become a complete and useful member of
human society, enjoying equal rights with all'. In the present, capitalist society
stamps every facet of women's experience with oppression and inequality. 'The
mass of the female sex suffers in two respects: On the one side woman suffers
from economic and social dependence upon man. True enough, this dependence
may be alleviated by formally placing her upon an equality before the law, and in
point of rights; but the dependence is not removed. On the other side, woman
suffers from the economic dependence ~~at woman in general, the working-woman
in particular, finds herself in, along with the workingman'. Equality and liberation
are thus always social as well as individual issues, and Bebel hastens to add that
the 'solution of the Woman Question coincides completely with the solution ofthe
Social Question' - incidentally putting the final resolution of the question into the
far future.l0 Meanwhile, the working class, and not the bourgeois feminist
movement, constitutes women's natural strategic ally in the struggle. Moreover,
participation in the revolutionary movement enables 'more favorable relations
between husband and wife [to] spring up in the rank of the
working class in the measure that both realize they are tugging at the sarrie rope,
and there is but one means towards satisfactory conditions for themselves and
their family - the radical reformation of society that shall make human beings of
them all'.11
Insofar as Bebel considers the social source for the pervasive oppression of
women, he relies on the concept of dependence. In general, he asserts, 'all social
dependence and oppression [have their] roots in the economic dependence of the
oppressed upon the oppressor'. Thus, woman's oppression is founded on her
dependence upon men. 'Economically and socially unfree' in capitalist society, for
instance, woman 'is bound to see in marriage her means of support; accord-ingly,
she depends upon man and becomes a piece of property to him.' If oppres-sion has
its basis in personal dependence, then liberation in the socialist future must involve
the individual's independence. 'The woman of future society is socially and
economically independent; she is no longer subject to even a vestige of dominion
and exploitation; she is free, the peer of man, mistress of her lot'.I2 Apart from
carrying the bewildering theoretical implication that chattel-slavery systematically
characterises capitalism since every wife must be 'a piece of prop-erty', statements
such as these show that Bebel has lost touch with the essence of Marx's orientation.
For Marx, class-struggle within a specific mode of produc-tion constitutes the basis
of social development, and individual oppression has its root, therefore, in a
particular set of exploitative social relations that operate at the level of classes. Be
bel, caught up in the reformist tendencies of his time, replaces Marx's concept of
class-exploitation with the vague and far less con-frontational notion of
dependence, particularly the dependence of the individual on others. Social well-
being is measured, then, by the location of the individual on a scale ranging from
dependence to independence, not by the nature of the social relations of production
in a given society. Similarly, socialism is pictured largely in terms of the
redistribution of goods and services already available in capitalist society to
independent individuals, rather than in terms of the whole-sale reorganisation of
production and social relations. Despite Bebel's commit-ment to socialism, his
emphasis on the full development of the individual in future society recalls nothing
so much as liberalism, the political philosophy of the nineteenth-century
bourgeoisie.
It is the focus on individual dependence, viewed largely in isolation from the
mechanisms governing social development as a whole, that undermines Bebel's
strategic perspective. In Woman and Socialism, women's oppression is treated as an
important but theoretically muddled problem, and it is hardly surprising that Be bel
comes up with a variety of implicitly contradictory strategic approaches.
In the first place, he often insists that the complete resolution of the problem
. must be postponed to the revolutionary future, when it can be fully addressed in
the context of solving the social question. Nevertheless, practical work on the issue
remains critical in the present. At the same time, it somehow becomes subsumed in
the working-class movement's struggle against capitalism. Finally, Bebel often
pictures the solution to the so-called woman-question in terms of achieving equal
rights to participate in society without distinction of sex. This approach fails to
differentiate socialist aims from the liberal-feminist goal of sex-equality in
capitalist society. In short, Bebel could not, despite his best socialist intentions,
sufficiently specify the relationship between the liberation of women in the
communist future and the struggle for equality in the capitalist present. He
conceptualised the so-called woman-question as an issue pertaining to woman's
situation as an individual, on the one hand, and to social conditions in general, on
the other, but he was unable to construct a reliable bridge between the two levels of
analysis.
The popularity of Woman and Socialism reflected the consolidation within the
Second International of a definite position on the question of women, Engels's
low-key and rather ambiguous opposition in the Origin notwithstanding. Insofar as
the socialist movement took up the problems of women's oppression, it spon-
taneously embraced Bebel's analysis.
In England, for example, Eleanor Marx- Marx's youngest daughter and an active
participant in the British labour- and socialist movements - wrote with her hus-
band, Edward Aveling, a pamphlet entitled The Woman Question.13 First pub-lished
in 1886, and reprinted in 1887, the popular pamphlet took the form of a speculative
review of the recently published English edition of Be bel's Woman. Its 16 pages
represented 'an attempt to explain the position of Socialists in respect to the woman
question'.
Like Bebel's Woman, The Woman Question focuses on issues oflove, sexuality,
and human feeling, while at the same tiJPe challenging the supposedly natu-ral
character of woman's place in social relations. As for the source of women's
oppression in capitalist society, the authors repeatedly insist that 'the basis of the
whole matter is economic', but they hardly offer any exposition of what they mean.
The implication is, however, that they follow Bebel in pointing to wom-an's
economic dependence on men as the essential problem. In a future socialist society,
by contrast, 'there will be equality for all, without distinction of sex', and women
will therefore be independent. Equality, in the sense of equal rights, con-stitutes a
major theme throughout The Woman Question. Unlike the feminists,
13. Aveling and Aveling 1972. For the pamphlet's publication-history, see Kapp 1976, pp.
82-5.
108 • Chapter Seven
the pamphlet claims, socialists press beyond the concept of equal rights as a
'sentimental or professional' issue, for they recognise the economic basis of the
woman-question and the impossibility of resolving it within capitalist society.
The Woman Question strikes a new note when it openly argues that the posi-tion
of women with respect to men parallels that of men with respect to capital-ists.
Women are the creatures of an organised tyranny of men, as the workers are the
creatures of an organised tyranny of idlers'. Women 'have been expropriated as to
their rights as human beings, just as the labourers were expropriated as to their
rights as producers'. In short, both groups have been denied their freedom. With
such formulations, the authors conceptualise oppression primarily in terms of lack
of political rights and the presence of hierarchical relations of author-ity. Moreover,
the idea that women's situation parallels that of workers suggests a strategy of
parallel social struggles for freedom. 'Both the oppressed classes, women and the
immediate producers, must understand that their emancipation will come from
themselves. [The] one has nothing to hope from man as a whole, and the other has
nothing to hope from the middle class as a whole'. Despite the pamphlet's socialist
stance, its images of parallel denials of rights and parallel movements for liberation
come quite close to liberal views of purely political freedoms in bourgeois society.
This explicit emphasis on the parallels between sex- and class-oppression takes
a logical step beyond Engels's Origin and Bebel's Woman. In the Origin, the
parallelism had remained latent in the series of dualities Engels had used to frame
his arguments: family and society, domestic labour and public production,
production of human beings and production of the means of existence, equal rights
between the sexes and legal equality of the classes. In Woman and Social-ism, Bebel
often counterposed the woman-question and the social question, ambiguously
according them equal weight as either separate or, paradoxically, identical
questions. Moreover, in arguing that 'women should expect as little help from the
men as working men do from the capitalist class', he implicitly postulated a
strategy of parallel social movements.14 The notion of a theoreti-cal and strategic
parallel between the sex- and class-struggles obviously had a certain currency
within the Second International. While The Woman Question represented one of the
first clear formulations of the position, socialist theorists and activists had
evidently already adopted its substance, and it quickly became a staple of the
socialist heritage.
Bebel's Woman and Socialism and the Avelings' The Woman Question may be taken
as indicative of the dominant views within the Second International. To
reformism within the socialist movement could only acquire rudimentary shape,
most visibly within the German Social-Democratic Party.
The SPD had always been at the forefront of the socialist movement on the
issue of woman's oppression, even though its theory and practice left much to be
desired. It produced the major political text on the question, Hebel's Woman and
Socialism. Within the Second International, it consistently took the stron-gest and
most advanced positions for women's suffrage and against all types of
discriminatory legislation. The portion of its membership that was female was the
largest of any socialist party, reaching sixteen percent just before World-War I. It
supported, on paper at least, women's active involvement in party-affairs, and took
some steps toward developing special internal mechanisms to facilitate their
participation. By the closing years of the nineteenth century, the German Social-
Democratic Party could boast of a large, well-organised, and extremely militant
socialist women's movement.
Many of these achievements bore witness to the dedicated work of German
socialist women themselves. Moreover, on all major issues, women party-members
generally took political positions well to the left of the Party as a whole. As the
struggle around reformism intensified, the socialist women's movement became a
stronghold of left-wing revolutionary orthodoxy! While the issue of women's
subordination never became a clear area of disagreement, members of the left wing
put forth theoretical and practical perspectives that suggested opposition to
dominant SPD positions on women.
The speeches and writings of Clara Zetkin, leader of the SPD's socialist women's
movement and an early opponent of the reformism engulfing the Party, offer some
of the clearest statements of this implicitly left-wing approach to the prob-lem of
women's oppression. In 18g6, for instance, Zetkin delivered an address on the issue
at the annual party congress, which was subsequently distributed as a pamphlet. 2
The 18g6 talk was an official policy-statement of the German social-ist movement.
At the same time, its text suggest~d a theoretical position that implicitly countered
the movement's drift toward reformism.
Zetkin opens the 18g6 speech with a brief sketch of the origins of women's
social subjugation. Morgan and other writers have shown that the develop-ment of
private property engenders a contradiction within the family between
1. For discussions of the achievements and limitations of the SPD's work on women,
see: Evans 1980; Evans 1977, pp. 159-65; Honeycutt 1979-80, Nolan 1977; Quataert 1979.
2. Zetkin 1957b English translation, with slight cuts, in Draper and Lipow 1976,
pp. 192-201. According to Karen Honeycutt, some changes and deletions have been
made in the 1957 publication of the 1896 speech, Honeycutt 1975, chapter 5, nn.
106, 129. While only a single text can be analysed here, the full range ofZetkin's
theoretical and practical contributions should not be underestimated. For the period
up to 1914, see Honeycutt 1975·
Toward Revolution • 113
3· Zetkin 1957b, p. gs; Draper and Lipow 1976, p·. 192. Honeycutt notes that both
Be bel and Liebknecht wanted Zetkin to eliminate references to the class-rule of men
over women in the 1896 speech, but Zetkin argued successfully that the concept could
be found in Engels's Origin; Draper and Lipow excise the sentence without comment or
ellipsis. Honeycutt 1975, p. 193. Earlier, Zetkin had clung even more closely to Bebel's
work. For example, in a speech delivered in 188g to the founding conference of the
Sec-ond International, she stressed women's economic dependence and maintained that
'in the same way that the worker is enslaved by capital, so is the woman by the man;
and she will remain enslaved so long as she is not economically independent': Zetkin
1957a, p. 4; Honeycutt 1975, p. go.
114 • Chapter Eight
earlier had to fight against all privileged classes. In this sense, the struggle of
ruling-class women for control over their own wealth after marriage constitutes
'the last stage in the emancipation of private property', and Zetkin views it as
entirely consistent with bourgeois claims to liberate the individual.
The woman-question presents itself in a quite different social form among
women of the small and middle bourgeoisie and the bourgeois intelligentsia. These
are the intermediate strata, which undergo intensifying strain with the expansion of
capitalist relations of production throughout society. As a class, the small and
middle-bourgeoisie is increasingly driven to ruin, its small-scale enterprises unable
to compete with capitalist industry. At the same time, capital requires an intelligent
and skilled labour-force, and encourages 'overproduction in proletarian brain-
workers', with the result that the bourgeois intelligentsia gradually loses its
formerly secure material position and social standing. Men of the small and middle
bourgeoisie and of the intelligentsia often postpone marriage, or even put it off
altogether. The basis of family-life in these strata becomes ever more precarious,
with a growing pool of unmarried women, and Zetkin argues that 'the women and
daughters of these circles are thrust out into society to establish a life for
themselves, not only one that provides bread but also one that can satisfy the spirit'.
Among these women of the small and middle bourgeoisie and the bourgeois
intelligentsia, a specific woman-question appears in the form of a demand for
women's economic equality with men of their own class in the field of
employment. Women fight for equal access to the educa-tion that will enable them
to enter the liberal professions, and for the right to carry on those professions.
These demands amount to nothing less than a call for capitalism to fulfil its pledge
to promote free competition in every arena, this time between women and men.
And, according to Zetkin, it is the fear of this competition within the liberal
professions that lies behind the petty obstinacies of male resistance. The
competitive battle soon drives the women of these strata to organise a women's
movement and demand political rights, in order to over-come the barriers to their
full economic and sociai participation.
In speaking of the bourgeois women's movement, Zetkin refers mainly to the
organised activity of women from the small and middle bourgeoisie, and from the
intelligentsia. Like women of the ruling class, these women focus on their lack of
equality with men of their own class, although as earners rather than as property-
owners. In both cases, there is a gap between the promise of equal-ity offered by
bourgeois society and its actual absence in daily life. While the economic aspect
represents the heart of the matter, Zetkin observes that the bourgeois women's
movement encompasses far more than purely economic motives. 'It also has a very
much deeper intellectual and moral side. The bour-geois woman not only demands
to earn her own bread, but she also wants to
Toward Revolution • ns
}ive a full life intellectually and develop her own individuality'. Moreover, at all
levels, 'the strivings of the bourgeois women's-rightsers are entirely justified'. 4
Among the women of the proletariat, the woman-question assumes yet another
form. Working-class women have no need to fight for entry into capitalist eco-
nomic life; they are there already. 'For the proletarian woman, it is capital's need
for exploitation, its unceasing search for the cheapest labor power, that has cre-ated
the woman question'. Moreover, Zetkin claims, the working-class woman already
enjoys both equality and economic independence, although she pays for them
dearly, because of her dual obligations as worker both in the factory and in the
family-household. 'Neither as a person nor as a woman or wife does she have the
possibility ofliving a full life as an individual. For her work as wife and mother she
gets only the crumbs that are dropped from the table by capitalist production'.
Since capitalism has relieved her of the need to struggle for equality with the men
of her own class, the working-class woman has other demands. In the immediate
future, 'it is a question of erecting new barriers against the exploi-tation of the
proletarian woman; it is a question of restoring and ensuring her rights as wife and
mother'. Furthermore, 'the end-goal of her struggle is not free competition with
men but bringing about the political rule of the proletariat'. Alongside the men of
her own class, not in competition with them, she fights to achieve this goal. Her
principal obstacle is, then, capitalism itself. At the same time, adds Zetkin, the
working-class woman supports the demands of the bour-geois women's movement,
'but she regards the realization of these demands only as a means to an end, so that
she can get into the battle along with the working-men and equally armed'.
Obviously, a great deal of what Zetkin has to say about the three forms of the
woman-question departs from the realities of capitalist society. To some extent,
these inaccuracies owe their existence to her failure to distinguish, within the 1896
speech, theoretical argument from empirical description, a confusion shared by
most socialist writers of her day. Beyond this problem, however, Zetkin's contri-
bution remains limited by certain theoreticij.l weaknesses. That is, the distortions
in Zetkin's consideration of the woman-question appear to be largely empirical, but
they have theoretical roots as well as serious political ramifications.
In the first place, along with virtually all her contemporaries, not to men-tion
Marx and Engels, Zetkin glosses over the issue of domestic labour within the
family-household. She severely underestimates the contradictions that arise from
the sex-division of this labour in all three classes. In this way, she loses an
important opportunity to strengthen her argument for the existence of
Finally, Zetkin errs in arguing that specific woman-questions arise only within
those classes thrust forward by the capitalist mode of production. In a period in
which peasants still made up the majority of the European oppressed masses, she,
along with many other socialists, idealised the peasantry as representing a 'natural
economy', however 'shrunken and tattered' under the impact of emer-gent
capitalism. In general, the parties of the Second International tended to ignore the
difficult theoretical and strategic problems presented by the exis-tence of this
massive peasantry alongside a growing industrial proletariat, and Zetkin, despite
her political acuity, all too easily fell into line. Peasantwomen, she claimed, 'found
a meaningful content of life in productive work ... their lack of social rights did not
impinge on their consciousness', and therefore, 'we find no woman question arising
in the ranks of the peasantry'. Here, the reality of
Toward Revolution • 117
systematically, consistently, and on a large scale, she argues, the network of field-
organisers would draw many working-class women into the socialist movement.
In sum, Zetkin's 18g6 speech made an important theoretical and political con-
tribution to the socialist movement's understanding ofthe problem of women's
subordination. Significantly, the speech rarely mentions love, sexuality, interper-
sonal relations, or human feelings, subjects that represented the core of the so-
called woman-question for most nineteenth-century socialists. Instead, Zetkin
5· For these recommendations, see Zetkin 1957b, p. wg; the details are omitted in the
translation by Draper and Lipow 1976.
Toward Revolution • 119
focuses on the theoretical issues and practical tasks that confront the social-ist
movement. Only her comments on the working-class household sometimes depart
from this businesslike and unromantic stance, even idealising working women as
nurturant wives and mothers of the fighting --' male - proletariat. Similarly, her
sketch of the socialist future recalls Be bel's work in its depiction of the family as
an isolated entity as well as its emphasis on woman's indepen-dence. 'When the
family disappears as an economic unit and its place is taken by the family as a
moral unit, women will develop their individuality as comrades advancing on a par
with men with equal rights, an equal role in production and equal aspirations, while
at the same time they are able to fulfil their functions as wife and mother to the
highest degree'. From a theoretical standpoint, such remarks retreat from the
position put forth in the body of the speech. Politi-cally, they suggest an almost
ritual concession to the ambiguity of the socialist tradition, probably necessary to
guarantee the speech's acceptance by party-delegates.
The eruption ofWorld-War I in 1914 forced the tension within the socialist move-
ment between reformism and a more revolutionary outlook to breaking point. Most
parties in the Second International supported the war, taking whichever side their
national bourgeoisie happened to stand on. Working-class interna-tionalism
seemed to vanish into thin air, as a narrow patriotism swept through socialist
ranks. Meanwhile, individual left-wing socialists recognised they had lost the
battle against reformism, and began to re-group. They opposed the war, either
assuming an essentially pacifist stance or, more militantly, viewing it as an
opportunity for revolutionary action. As hostilities dragged on, popular discon-tent
replaced the initial patriotic euphoria, and important sectors of the popu-lation
turned to those who sought to end the war. In consequence, the pacifist and
revolutionary minorities in every socialist party grew stronger. Their anti-war
perspective seemed vindicated when the Bolshevik Party came to power in Russia
in 1917.
The Bolshevik Revolution transformed not only Russia but the international
socialist movement. For the first time, revolutionaries had fought for and won the
opportunity to begin the transition to a communist society, and the effort
commanded the attention of socialists everywhere. The seizure of state-power was
only the first step, and weighty problems confronted the new society. Exter-nally,
the forces of capitalism tried, in every possible way, including military
intervention, to undermine the revolution's success. And internally, the task of
building a socialist society quickly proved tremendously difficult. Every question
that had formerly concerned the international socialist movement now became a
matter of the utmost urgency, to be resolved in concrete detail, in both theory and
practice. Among these tasks loomed the problem of women's subordina-tion, made
all the more pressing because of several peculiarities of the Russian Revolution.
First, the majority of Russia's population consisted of peasants, half of whom lived
the particularly hard life of peasant-women - often working in the fields as well as
the household, and brutally oppressed by feudal traditions of male supremacy.
Second, women wage-earners constituted a relatively new and fast-growing group,
especially in the very small Russian industrial sector, where
6. Zetkin 1929, pp. 373, 375, 376. I would like to thank Charlotte Todes Stem of New
York City for bringing this article to my attention.
Toward Revolution • 121
their numbers rose to include forty percent of the industrial workforce during the
war. Last, radical movements in Russia had traditionally attracted a large number
of women-activists, who often played leading roles, and the Bolshevik party was
no exception. Objectively, and from the start, the question of women represented a
critical issue for the future of socialism in Russia.
The history of women's situation in the Soviet Union has yet to be fully
analysed. Most accounts sketch a gloomy picture in which numerous obstacles
conspire to block full liberation for women: insufficient material resources, erro-
neous or opportunist political priorities, wholesale ideological backwardness, a low
level of theoretical attention. Although correct in its general outlines, the picture
remains blurred. In particular, despite a great deal of research, it fails to situate the
history of the question of women within an adequate understanding of the
development of the Russian Revolution, and of the international socialist and
communist movements.7 Moreover, the problem of the nature and source of the
theoretical framework underpinning Soviet work on the issue of women's
subordination has barely been addressed.
The rudiments of that theoretical framework were established by V. I. Lenin, the
leader of the Bolshevik Party and a prolific writer on questions of socialist theory
and practice. Lenin's comments on women make up only a tiny portion of his
work, and it is not clear to what extent they were taken up within the Bolshevik
Party or implemented in practice. Nonetheless, they are important for their insight
into the theoretical heart of the problem of women's oppression.
Like Zetkin, Lenin took a left-wing position in the struggle against reform-ism.
In the Russian context, however, this struggle acquired its own form, quite distinct
from the public battle fought within the massive and powerful German party.
Under the Tsars, Marxism remained an illegal movement in a backward country.
Neither a strong trade-union movement nor a socialist party affiliated with the
Second International could be built. The major theoretical task for Rus-sian
socialists at the end of the nineteenth century was to assimilate Marxist theory in
order to put it into practice in !feir own country, where conditions differed sharply
from the industrialising nations of Western Europe and North America. Opposition
to revisionism among Russian socialists therefore initially took the particular shape
of an effort to grasp and defend Marxism itself.
Two tendencies within Russian radicalism stood in the way of the develop-ing
Marxist movement. First, the Russian populists, or Narodniks, argued that the
peasantry constituted the backbone of the revolutionary process, that Russia would
be able to bypass the stage of industrial capitalism, and that the peasant-commune
provided the germ of a future communist society. Second, a group
7· Important recent studies on women in Russia include: Bobroff 1974; Clements 1982-3.
Glickman 1977; Hayden 1976; Heitlinger 1979; Lapidus 1977; Massell1972; Stites 1978.
122 • Chapter Eight
known as the 'legal Marxists', so named because they wrote in. a form capable of
passing Russian censorship, embraced Marxism largely because it recognised the
historically progressive character 1 of capitalism. In oppos1tion to the Narodnik.s,
the legal Marxists welcomed capitalism as a necessary first stage on the way to
socialism; as might be expected, many of them later lost their interest in revolu-
tion and became staunch bourgeois liberals.
A central theme in Lenin's earliest writings was the defence of Marxism against
attacks from the Narodniks, on the one hand, and distortions by the legal Marx-ists,
on the other. At the same time, he began to elaborate a Marxist analysis of the
development of capitalism in Russia and of the prospects for a socialist revo-lution.
When Russian Marxists founded the Social-Democratic Workers' Party, after the
tum of the century, bourgeois liberalism became yet another target of his polemics.
Lenin's first comments touching on the problem of women's oppression appear
in his 1894 critique of the Narodnik writer Nikolay Mikhailovsky, who had
caricatured Marxist theory. The issue of women's situation arises because
Mikhailovsky mocks Engels's discussion of "'the production of man himself", i.e.
procreation', in the preface to the Origin, castigating it as a peculiar form of
'economic materialism'. He suggests instead that 'not only legal, but also eco-nomic
relations themselves constitute a "superstructure" on sexual and family relations'.
In reply, Lenin ridicules Mikhailovsky's argument that 'procreation is not an
economic factor', and asks sarcastically, 'Where have you read in the works of
Marx or Engels that they necessarily spoke of economic materialism? When they
described their world outlook they called it simply materialism. Their basic idea ...
was that social relations are divided into material and ideological ...
Mr. Mikhailovsky surely does not think that procreation relations are ideological?'
The way Lenin defends Engels's statements in the preface, however questionable
their theoretical status may be, is significant. He puts the major emphasis on the
point that Marxism is not economic determinism. And he insists on the material
core embedded in all social relations, even those involving women, the· family,
and sexuality.8 This perspective, which relies far more on Marx than on later
socialist theorists, became the foundation of Lenin's approach to the problem of
women's subordination.
Capitalism developed in Russia on the basis of a savagely patriarchal feudal
culture. In The Development of Capitalism in Russia, published in 18gg, Lenin
examined the impact of capitalist social relations on peasant-life. Because of its
highly socialised labour-processes, capitalism 'absolutely refuses to tolerate
survivals of patriarchalism and personal dependence' over the long run. Lenin
8. Lenin 1960-1970a, pp. 148-52. For an analysis of the preface to Engels's Origin, see
Chapter 6.
Toward Revolution • 123
argues that in this sense 'the drawing of women and juveniles into production is, at
bottom, progressive', despite the particularly oppressive conditions these sec-tors
often encounter under the rule of capital. In sum: 'By destroying the patriar-chal
isolation of these categories of the population who formerly never emerged from
the narrow circle of domestic, family relationships, by drawing them into direct
participation in social production, large-scale machine industry stimulates their
development and increases their independence, in other words, creates conditions
of life that are incomparably superior to the patriarchal immobility of pre-capitalist
relations'. Lenin points out that any attempts 'to ban the work of women and
juveniles in industry, or to maintain the patriarchal manner of life that ruled out
such work, would be reactionary and utopian'.9 With these remarks, Lenin has
simply used Marxist theory to develop an analysis of the significance in Russia of
women's and children's participation in social labour. Obvious though this approach
may seem, at the time it represented a rare return to the best of Marx and Engels.
In these early decades of the Russian socialist movement, Lenin also addressed
several specific problems having to do with the special oppression of women as
women. He condemned prostitution, locating it in social conditions and inciden-
tally taking swipes at liberal attempts to end it. He analysed the class-character of
the birth-control movement, contrasting the psychology of the petit-bourgeois
liberal to that of the class-conscious worker. At the same time he underscored the
need for socialists to support the abolition of all laws limiting availability of
abortion or contraception. 'Freedom for medical propaganda and the protection of
the elementary democratic rights of citizens, men and women, are one thing. The
social theory ofneomalthusianism is quite another'. Most important, Lenin
repeatedly denounced the peasantry's 'century-old traditions of patriarchal life', and
their particularly brutal implications for women.10
In subsequent years, Lenin began to pay special attention to the relationship
between sex-oppression and class-cleavages. While he had always supported
equality between women and men, in the traditional socialist manner, he now came
up against the more difficult probl~m of specifying the nature of that
equality. Initially, the problem appeared in the context of discussions on the so-
called national question. Among socialists, questions of the equality of nations and
the rights of national minorities became matters of heated debate in the
(and it is not complete without freedom of secession), the clearer will the
workers of the oppressed nations see that the cause of their oppression is
capitalism, not lack of rights, etc.I2
In this sense, the battle for democratic rights is a means for establishing and
maintaining the best framework within which to carry out the class-struggle.
Lenin's work on democratic rights went well beyond earlier socialist analy-ses
of the nature of equality. At the theoretical level, it offered serious insights into the
mystery of the relationship among sex-, class-, and national oppression in capitalist
societies. And practically, it constituted an important element in the development
of revolutionary strategy with respect to national minorities, oppressed nations, and
women. Here, 1\oyin dangers haunted the socialist move-ment. On the one hand,
some denied the critical significance of these special oppressions, and refused to
take them up seriously in practice, and often in theory as well. On the other, many
developed reformist positions that scarcely differed, at the practical level, from
bourgeois nationalism or liberal feminism. Armed with an understanding of the
character of democratic rights, a socialist movement had a better chance to
confront national and women's oppression without slipping into either error.
providing practical support for the special work among women. In a conversa-tion
recorded by Zetkin, Lenin criticised the general passivity and· backwardness of
male comrades on this issue. 'They regard agitation ahd propaganda among women
and the task of rousing and revolutionizing them as of secondary impor-tance, as
the job of just the women Communists ... Unfortunately, we may still say of many
of our comrades, "scratch the Communist and a philistine appears'". Behind this
view lies contempt for women. 'In the final analysis, it is an under-estimation of
women and of their accomplishments'. As evidence of the serious-ness of the
problem, Lenin describes how party-men complacently watch their own wives take
on the burdens and worries of the household, never thinking to lend a hand. Lenin
concludes that special work must be done on these questions among men. 'Our
communist work among the masses of women, and our politi-cal work in general,
involves considerable educational work among the men. We must root out the old
slave-owner's point of view, both in the Party and among the masses'. According to
Zetkin's notes, Lenin went so far as to weight this task equally with that of forming
a staff and organisations to work among women.2o
Lenin's remarks about male chauvinism never acquired programmatic form, and
the campaign against male ideological backwardness remained at most a minor
theme in Bolshevik practice. Nonetheless, his observations on the prob-lem
represented an extremely rare acknowledgment of its seriousness. As for the
development of special work among women, numerous socialists, almost all of
them women, took it up as best they could.
On the issues of love and sexuality, Lenin, like Zetkin, said very little, and
nothing that was meant for official publication. In a correspondence with Inessa
Armand in 1915, he criticises her notion of free love for its lack of clarity. While
agreeing that love must be free from economic, social, and patriarchal restric-tions,
he cautions against a 'bourgeois interpretation' that wishes to free love from
interpersonal responsibility.21 Later, in the conversation recorded by Zetkin, Lenin
directs a lengthy tirade against those who give too much attention to 'sex and
marriage problems'. He criticises German socialist organisers who dwell on the
subject in discussions with women-workers. And he worries about attempts in the
Soviet Union to transform the nihilist tradition of sexual radicalism into a socialist
framework:
Many people call it 'revolutionary' and 'communist'. They sincerely believe
that this is so. I am an old man, and I do not like it. I may be a morose ascetic,
but quite often this so-called 'new sex life' of young people - and frequently
20. Lenin 1966, pp. 83, 114-15. It must be remembered that virtually no socialist in this
period seriously challenged the sex-division of domestic labour, not even Alexandra
Kollontai; see Heinen 1978.
21. Lenin 1966, pp. 36-41.
Toward Revolution • 129
of the adults too - seems to me purely bourgeois and simply an extension of the
good old bourgeois brothel. All this has nothing in common with free love as we
Communists understand it.
For Lenin and much of the socialist tradition, it was individual sex-love in social-
ist society that was destined to transcend the hypocritical two-sided sexual life of
capitalist societies, abolishing repressive marriages on the one hand, and
prostitution on the other. Individual sex-love was the socialist answer to 'the decay,
putrescence, and filth of bourgeois marriage with its difficult dissolution, its
licence for the husband and bondage for the wife, and its disgustingly false sex
morality'. Anything else smacked of promiscuity, and 'promiscuity in sex-ual
matters is bourgeois. It is a sign of d~generation'.22 Lenin's formulations, as
remembered by Zetkin and published after his death, functioned mainly as a
rationale for sexual conservatism among socialists.
In the long run, the experience of the Russian Revolution raised at least as many
questions about the relation of women's liberation to socialist transfor-mation as it
answered. Zetkin might have observed that here, too, history had posed a specific
woman-question, distinct from those thrust forward by capital-ist relations of
production: the question of women in the era of the transition to communism.
Given the generally undeveloped state of socialist work on the problem of wom-
en's oppression, Zetkin's and Lenin's theoretical contributions failed to make a
lasting impression. With some exceptions, twentieth-century socialists and
communists have adopted positions very similar to those dominant within the
Second International. Yet the legacy is both incomplete and ambiguous.
22. Lenin 1966, pp. 101, 105-7. On nihilist sexual radicalism, and on the issue of sexual-
ity in the Russian socialist movement, see Stites 1978, pp. 8g-gg, 258-6g, 346-g1.
23.
Part Four
From the Woman-Question to Women's Liberation
Chapter Nine
A Dual Legacy
1. This terminology revises that used in Vogel1979, which opposed the 'family argu-ment'
to the 'social production argument'. The term dual-systems perspective is adopted from
Young 1980. I am grateful to Nancy Holmstrom for a discussion that clarified both the
terminology and the analysis in this chapter. For an interesting parallel, see the dis-cussion
of two positions on the so-called national question in Blaut 1982.
A Dual Legacy • 135
behind women's oppression. In other words, according to the theory implicit in the
dual-systems perspective, two powerful motors drive the development of history:
the class-struggle and the sex-struggle.
While the dual-systems perspective begins with empirically given phenomena
whose correlations are interpreted by means of a chain of plausible inferences, the
social-reproduction perspective starts out from a theoretical position- namely, that
class-struggle over the conditions of production represents the central dynamic of
social development in societies characterised by exploitation. In these societ-ies,
surplus-labour is appropriated by a dominant class, and an essential con-dition for
production is the constant presence and renewal of a subordinated class of direct
producers committed to the labour-process. Ordinarily, generational replacement
provides most of the new workers needed to replenish this class, and women's
capacity to bear children therefore plays a critical role in class-society.
From the point of view of social reproduction, women's oppression in class-
societies is rooted in their differential position with respect to generational
replacement-processes. Families constitute the historically specific social form
through which generational replacement usually takes place. In class societies, 'one
cannot speak at all of the family "as such"', as Marx once put it, for families have
widely varying places within the social structure. 2 In propertied classes, families
usually act as the carrier and transmitter of property, although they may also have
other roles. Here, women's oppression flows from their role in the maintenance and
inheritance of property. In subordinate classes, families usually structure the site at
which direct producers are maintained and repro-duced; such families may also
participate directly in immediate production. Female oppression in these classes
derives from women's involvement in pro-cesses that renew direct producers, as
well as their involvement in production. While women's oppression in class-
societies is experienced at many levels, it rests, ultimately, on these material
foundations. The specific working out of this oppression is a subject for historical,
not theoretical, investigation.
Presented in crystallised form, the distixwtion between the dual systems- and the
social-reproduction perspectives is relatively clear. Of the two, the social-
reproduction perspective accords most closely with Marx's analysis of the work-
ings of the capitalist mode of production, particularly as elaborated in Capital. The
demarcation between the two perspectives has always been blurred, how-ever,
even while the presence of contradictory positions underlies much of the ambiguity
marking the theoretical work produced by the socialist movement. The dual-
systems perspective has generally prevailed over the social-reproduction
The Origin's characterisation of the single family as the 'economic unit of soci-
ety', with the additional implication that 'modern society is a mass composed of
these individual families as molecules', further illustrates its implicit dependence
on the dual-systems perspective. In such statements, Engels retains the separation
of family from social reproduction, but peculiarly assigns a dominant-constitutive
role to the former. The manner in which the family-unit functions within social
reproduction, other than, in the case of the ruling class, to hold property, is never
clearly defined. Along the same lines, Marx, as well as Engels, spoke sev-eral
times of the sex-division of labour in the family as a sort of representative
miniature of the social division of labour in society. 'The modern family contains
in germ not only slavery (servitus) but also serfdom, since from the beginning it is
related to agricultural services. It contains in miniature all the contradictions which
later extend throughout society and its state'. Engels also uses the image to
describe relations between the sexes. Within the family, [the husband] is the
bourgeois, and the wife represents the proletariat'. Since neither Marx nor Engels
ever specifies, in any precise manner, the nature of this 'representation' - that is, the
relationship between the family 'germ' and the social whole - these images function
as simplistic parallels. At best, they are dangerous metaphors; at worst, uncritical
borrowings from early bourgeois political philosophy. 3
3· On the family as the 'economic unit of society' see Engels 1972, pp. 138, 139, 223, 235,
236n. On the family as the 'cellular form of civilized society' see Engels 1972, pp. 121-2, 129,
131, 137; see also Marx and Engels 1975a, p. 46, and Marx 1973b, p. 484. For a similar analysis,
see Brown 1978, pp. 38-41.
A Dual Legacy • 137
Finally, the Origin's discussion of the family as the site of a struggle between the
sexes accords with the dual-systems perspective. While Engels underscores the
simultaneous emergence of sex- and class-conflict, he never achieves a clear
picture of their connection. The two developments remain historically paral-lel
phenomena, whose theoretical relationship is best characterised as one of
autonomy. For the propertied family, women's oppression has its source in the
husband's need to preserve and transmit his private property. Obviously, the
absence of private property should be accompanied by an absence of sex-conflict.
In fact, as Engels is forced to acknowledge, women occupy a subordinate place in
propertyless households. Engels offers no theoretical basis for this historic
oppression, although the preface's concept of systematic 'production of human
beings themselves' hints obliquely at a distinct mechanism.
The Origin does not entirely neglect the social-reproduction perspective. It is
implicit when Engels states that participation in public production offers the path to
emancipation for the proletarian woman, when he insists that domestic work must
be converted into a public industry, or when he argues that the single family must
cease to be the economic unit of society. These assertions function as important
insights which need, however, to be supported theoretically. Why does participation
in public production offer a precondition for social equality? What does it mean to
say the family's aspect as an economic unit must be abol-ished? In what sense is
the family an economic unit? How are these issues linked to the requirement that
domestic work be converted into a public industry? Unfortunately, Engels never
manages to provide the explicit theoretical under-pinning necessary to answer these
questions properly. Marx had presented the outlines of a theory of the reproduction
of labour-power and the working class that could, in principle at least, have
constituted the starting point. But such a serious extension of Marx's work
represented an undertaking for which Engels lacked time and, perhaps, motivation.
With the publication of the Origin, Engels's contradictory blend of the dual systems-
and social-reproduction perspectives became, in effect, the unstable theoretical fS?
undation for all subsequent socialist investigation of the so-called woman-question.
The unrecognised gap between the two perspectives wide.ned as the strug-gle
between Marxism and revisionism intensified in the Second International. Whereas
Engels had managed to combine both perspectives, however awk-wardly, in a
single text, subsequent analyses tended more clearly to emphasise one at the
expense of the other. In general, the dual-systems perspective domi-nated within
the reformist wing of the socialist movement, while a rough ver-sion of the social-
reproduction perspective underlay the occasional efforts by opponents of
reformism to address the question of women.
138 • Chapter Nine
Behind the mass of data in August Be bel's Woman and Socialism, for instance is a
'
conceptual framework thoroughly in accord with the dual-systems perspective. The
book's position within the terms of the dual-systems perspective is estab-lished, first
of all, by Be bel's assumption that the category 'woman' represents an appropriate
theoretical starting point. Despite ritual assertions that the 'solution of the Woman
Question coincides completely with the solution of the Social Question', Be bel
treats the phenomenon of women's oppression as analytically separable from social
development as a whole. He argues, furthermore, that women's individual
dependence on men is the source of their oppression in class-society, but fails to
situate that dependence within overall social reproduc-tion. In short, Be bel's
Woman and Socialism puts the ·sex-division of labour and the relationship of
dependence between women and men, taken as empirically obvious and ahistorical
givens (at least until the advent of socialist society), at the heart of the problem
ofwomen's oppression.
Next to the theoretical and political confusion that permeates Woman and
Socialism, Engels's analysis in the Origin has considerable force and clarity. Rather
than zig-zagging erratically between the so-called woman- and social questions, he
concentrates on the social phenomena that produce woman's position in a given
society, and on the conditions that might lead to changes in that posi-tion. He does
his best, that is, to delineate the relationships among the factors involved in
women's oppression - the family, sex-divisions of labour, property relations, class-
society, and the state - at times hinting also at the more com-prehensive concept of
the reproduction of labour-power implicit in the social-reproduction perspective.
Although Engels's discussion in the Origin sorely lacks the powerful theoretical
and political insight that Marx might have brought to the subject, it moves well
beyond Bebel's effort in Woman and Socialism.
The Avelings' pamphlet The Woman Question confirms, even more clearly than
Bebel's Woman and Socialism, the dominance of the dual-systems perspective
within the socialist movement. Like Bebel, the authors assert that the basis of
women's oppression is economic dependence, but they fail to explain how, thus
effectively severing the problem of women's subordination from its loca-tion
within social development. The pamphlet's conceptualisation of woman's position
mainly in terms of love, sexuality, marriage, divorce, and dependence on men,
reinforces this theoretical demarcation between women, the family, and the sex-
division oflabour, on the one hand, and social reproduction, on the other. Finally,
the pamphlet's explicit formulation of sex- and class-oppression as parallel
phenomena, engendering parallel struggles whose relationship is never discussed,
reveals most sharply its reliance on the dual-systems perspective.
At the theoretical level, the growing strength of reformism in the Second
International undoubtedly found a reflection in the consolidation of the dual-
systems perspective as the unspoken basis for any socialist efforts to address the
A Dual Legacy • 139
question of women. Against this position, the left wing of the socialist move-ment
presented an implicit, if all-too undeveloped, challenge, which accorded with the
general premises of the social-reproduction perspective. Thus, in their approach to
the issue of women's subordination, Zetkin and Lenin, both leaders in the struggle
against reformism, reject the universal categories of 'woman' or 'the family' as
theoretical starting points. Instead, each focuses on the specificity of women's
oppression in different classes in a given mode of production.
In her 18g6 speech to the Party Congress, for example, Zetkin insists that the
character of the so-called woman-question in capitalist societies is dependent on
class. She identifies three distinct woman-questions, all demanding resolu-tion, but
differentiated by the source of oppression, the nature of the demands for equality,
and the obstacles to achieVing the demands. Refusing to consider the woman-
question as a classless abstraction to be resolved in the future, she suggests a
comprehensive programme of organisational activity. At the practi-cal level,
Zetkin's opposition to reformism took the form of a commitment to developing
socialist work among women of all classes -work that would support reforms
without falling into reformism, and simultaneously keep the revolution- ary goal
firmly in view. In contrast to many of her contemporaries in the socialist
movement, she saw the fight for changes in the relations between women and men
as a task for the present, not for some indefinite socialist future.
With more theoretical precision than Zetkin, ifless originality and commitment,
Lenin places the issue of women's subordination in the context of the reproduc-tion
of labour-power in class-society. His repeated emphasis on the decisive role of
domestic labour reflects an understanding, heightened by the experience of the
Bolshevik Revolution, of the material foundation of women's oppression. His grasp
of the workings of capitalist social reproduction enables him to sketch the outlines
of a theoretically coherent relationship between sex- and class-oppres-sion, by
means of the concept of democratic rights. These positions constitute the
theoretical basis underlying Lenin's strategic clarity - never sufficiently
implemented by the Bolsheviks in practice - on the importance of special work
•I
among women, on the need for mass women's organisations bringing together
women of all classes, and on the problem of combating male ideological back-
wardness. Taken together, Zetkin's and Lenin's observations on women offer the
rudiments of a specific use of the social-reproduction perspective to analyse
women's oppression in capitalist society.
In the context of the modem women's movement in North America and West-em
Europe, specifically its socialist-feminist wing, the tension between the two
perspectives has taken a new form. Whereas the socialist movement of the late
nineteenth century sought mainly to differentiate its positions on the problem of
women's oppression from those of liberal feminism, contemporary socialist
feminism has developed as much in sympathetic response to the views of radical
140 • Chapter Nine
feminism as to the failures of both liberal feminism and the socialist tradition. It is
this advanced position, in part, that has enabled the socialist-feminist move-ment
to make its many significant contributions.
In certain ways, theoretical work produced from within the socialist-feminist
framework recreates the major characteristics of the dual-systems perspective. For
example, socialist-feminist theorists tend, no matter what their stated inten-tions, to
separate the question of divisions of labour and authority according to sex from
social reproduction.4 Furthermore, they remain generally unable to situate women's
oppression theoretically in terms of mode of production and class. And they offer a
one-sided emphasis on the family and issues of sexuality and personal dependence.
Last, socialist feminists have not provided theoretical underpinning for their
strategic emphasis on the integral role, in the struggle for socialism, of the
autonomous organisation of women from all sectors of society. In these ways,
socialist feminists often reproduce the weaknesses of the dual-systems perspective,
but their work also points the way toward a more adequate theoretical grasp of the
issue of women's oppression. In particular, they insist on the centrality of achieving
a materialist understanding of woman's situation within the family - as child-
bearer, child-rearer, and domestic labourer - as the key to the problem of the
persistence of women's oppression across differ-ent modes of production and
classes. It is here that socialist-feminist theorists have made especially important
contributions. Those who focus on the task in terms of Marx's theory of social
reproduction have renewed, furthermore, the elements of the social-reproduction
perspective, and have deepened it in ways never achieved either by Marx or by the
socialist tradition. In sum, the political seriousness of socialist-feminist
involvement in theoretical work, fuelled by the continuing militancy of women in
social movements around the world has both reproduced and transformed the
tension between the two perspectives. On the one hand, socialist feminism revives
the contradictory co-existence of the two theoretical perspectives, which originated
with Marx and Engels, only to disap-pear under the pressures of revisionism. On
the other, it moves well beyond limitations established in the earlier period.
4· More recently, for example, Young intelligently demolishes the dualism of much
of socialist-feminist theory, but then suggests an emphasis on 'gender division of labor
analvsis' that threatens to recreate the verv dualism she wishes to avoid. Youn!! 1081.
Chapter Ten
The Reproduction of Labour-Power
The discussion in this and the following chapter suggests a theoretical frame-
work that can situate the phenomenon of women's oppression in terms of social
reproduction. Given the weak tradition of theoretical work on the question of
women, some words of caution are in order. Theory is, of course, critical to the
development of specific analyses of women's situation. Explicitly or implicitly,
empirical phenomena must be organised in terms of a theoretical construct in order
to be grasped conceptually. At the same time, theory is, by its very nature, severely
limited. As a structure of concepts, a theoretical framework simply provides
guidance for the understanding of actual societies, past and present. However
indispensable this theoretical guidance may be, specific strategies, pro-grammes,
or tactics for change cannot be deduced directly from theory. Nor can the
phenomenon of variation in women's situation over time, and in different societies,
be addressed solely by means of theory. These are matters for concrete analysis and
historical investigation. By contrast, the argument in these chapters is largely
theoretical, and it is therefore necessarily abstract. No attempt is made to develop
detailed analyses of women's oppression in, for example, contempo-rary capitalist
society. Such studies, and the political conclusions and tasks they imply, will be
undertaken elsewhere.
The phenomenon of women's oppression is a highly individual and subjec-tive
experience, often dissected in elaborate descriptive terms, with emphasis on issues
of sexuality, inter-personal relations, and ideology. As Michele Barrett observes,
'the women's liberation movement has laid great stress on the expe-riential aspects
of oppression in marriage, in sexual relationships, and in the ideology of
femininity and male dominance. In the establishment of "sexual poli-tics" as a
central area of struggle it has succeeded in drawing back the veil on privatized
relationships. This politicization of personal life ... is a major achieve-ment of
feminist activity and one from which Marxism has learnt a great deal'.
The Reproduction of Labour-Power • 143
Barrett argues that such analyses are not enough, however, for they have 'tended to
ignore the ways in which private oppression is related to broader questions of
relations of production and the class structure'. In the following pages, the focus is
on this latter question, in particular, on the economic, or material, aspect of
women's situation. However restricted the approach may seem from the point of
view of the desire for a full-blown exposition of women's oppression, it is
necessary to establish these material foundations. Once laid, they will form the
indispensable basis for further work. In sum, the starting point in these chap-ters is
a theoretical perspective on social reproduction, but the ultimate goal is to confront
the twin problems of women's oppression and the conditions for women's
liberation.l
1. Barrett 1980, p. 79· I would like to thank Ira Gerstein for his many perceptive com-
ments on the theoretical arguments in this and the following chapter.
2. Marx 1971a, pp. 164, 43, so, 179·
3· Marx 1971a, p. 173.
144 • Chapter Ten
The bearers of labour-power are, however, mortal. Those who work suffer wear
and tear. Some are too young to participate in the labour-process, others too old.
Eventually, every individual dies. Some process that meets the ongoing personal
needs of the bearers oflabour-power as human individuals is therefore a condition
of social reproduction, as is some process that replaces workers who have died or
withdrawn from the active work force. These processes of main-tenance and
replacement are often imprecisely, if usefully, conflated under the term
reproduction of labour-power. 5
Despite the linguistic similarity of the terms production and reproduction, the
processes that make up the reproduction of labour-power and those that form part
of a society's production are not comparable from a theoretical point of view.
Reproduction of labour-power is a condition of production, for it reposits or
replaces the labour-power necessary for production. Reproduction of labour-power
is not, however, itself a form of production. That is, it does not necessarily involve
some determinate combination of raw materials and means of produc-tion in a
labour-process whose result is the product labour-power. While some have argued
that the reproduction oflabour-power is a production-process tak-ing place in
family-households, in fact such activities represent only one pos-sible mode of
renewing the bearers oflabour-power. Labour-camps or dormitory facilities can
also be used to maintain workers, and the work-force can be replen-
entirely new set. In the more likely case, an existing labour-force is replenished
both generationaJly and by new labourers. Children of workers grow up and enter
the labour-force. Women who had not previously been involved begin to par-
ticipate in production. Immigrants or slaves from outside a society's boundaries
enter its labour-force. To the brief extent that Marx considered these questions in
general terms, he spoke of laws of population. 'Every special historic mode of
production has its own special laws of population, historically valid within its
limits alone. An abstract law of population exists for plants and animals only, and
only in so far as man has not interfered with them'. 9 Moreover, not all pres-ent
labourers will work in a subsequent production-period. Some will become sick,
disabled, or too old. Others may be excluded, as when protective legislation is
enacted to prohibit child-labour or women's night-work. In sum, at the level of
total social reproduction, the concept of the reproduction of labour-power does not
in the least imply the reproduction of a bounded unit of population.10
The discussion so far has not required that the gender of direct producers be
specified. From a theoretical perspective, it does not yet matter whether they are
women or men, so long as they are somehow available to make up the labour-
force. What raises the question of gender is, of course, the phenomenon of gen-
erational replacement of bearers of labour-power - that is, the replacement of
existing workers by new workers from the next generation. If generational
replacement is to happen, biological reproduction must intervene. And here, it
must be admitted, human beings do not reproduce themselves by parthenogen-esis.
Women and men are different.
The critical theoretical import of the biological distinction between women and
men with respect to child-bearing appears, then, at the level of total social
reproduction. While reproduction of labour-power at the level of total social
reproduction does not necessarily entail generational replacement, it is at this
theoretical level that the issue must be located.
Before proceeding further, a popular analytical misconception should be
acknowledged. People ordinarily experience the processes of generational
replacement in individualised kin-based contexts, and attempts to develop a theory
of the reproduction of labour-power often focus on the family-unit or household as
a starting point. Such a procedure, however understandable, repre-sents a serious
confusion with respect to theoretical levels. As commonly under-stood, the family
is a kin-based social structure in which take place processes
n. For a sensible discussion of common-sense meanings of the term family, see Rapp
1978.
12. On the social construction of sex-differences, see: Barrett 1980, pp. 74-7; Beneria
1979; Brown 1978; Edholm, Harris and Young 1977; Molyneux 1977· For a fine critique of
this literature, see Sayers 1982. See also the works cited in note 22 of this chapter.
13. Marx 1971a, p. 173.
148 • Chapter Ten
labour may also be devoted to securing the reproduction of other members of the
exploited class. Where, for example, children, the elderly, or a wife do not
themselves enter into surplus-production as direct producers, a certain amount
oflabour-time must be expended for their maintenance. Marx was never explicit
about what is covered by the concepts of individual consumption and neces-sary
labour. As discussed above, the concept of individual consumption has been
restricted here to the direct producer's immediate maintenance. Necessary labour is
used, however, to cover all labour performed in the course of the main-tenance and
renewal of both direct producers and members of the subordinate class not
currently working as direct producers.
Necessary labour ordinarily includes several constituent processes. In the first
place, it provides a certain amount of means of subsistence for individual con-
sumption by direct producers. In a feudal society, for example, direct producers
may retain a portion of the total product. In a capitalist society, wages permit the
purchase of commodities in the market. In most cases, the raw means of sub-
sistence so acquired do not themselves ensure the maintenance of the labourer. A
certain amount of supplementary labour must be performed in order that the
necessaries can be consumed in appropriate form: firewood must be chopped,
meals cooked, garden-plots tended, clothes repaired, and so forth. In addition to
these labour-processes facilitating the individual consumption of direct pro-ducers,
two other sets of labour-processes can be identified. A portion of neces-sary labour
goes to provide means of subsistence to maintain members of the exploited classes
not currently working as direct producers - the elderly, the sick, a wife. And an
important series oflabour-processes associated with the gen-erational replacement
of labour-power may also take place - that is, the bearing and raising of the
children of the subordinate class. As discussed above, these various aspects of
necessary labour have a certain autonomy from a theoretical point of view.
Together they represent an indispensable condition for the repro-duction of labour-
power and therefore for overall social reproduction. It should be noted that the
concept of necessary labour pertains strictly to tasks associated with the
reproduction of labour-power in tbe exploited class. Individuals in the ruling class
also require daily maintenance and ordinarily replace themselves through
generational reproduction. Such activities do not qualify as necessary labour in
Marx's sense, however, for they do not concern the renewal of exploit-able labour-
power.
In a given class-society, the circumstances and outcome of the processes of
reproduction of labour-power are essentially indeterminate or contingent. To
maintain otherwise would be to fall into the functionalist argument that a system's
needs for labour-power must inevitably be fulfilled by the workings of that system.
The social relations through which necessary labour is carried
150 • Chapter Ten
17. O'Laughlin 1977, pp. 6-7; Rapp 1979, pp. 319, 321-2; Vogel1978. For discussions of
functionalism in socialist-feminist theory, see Barrett 1980, pp. 93-6, and Sayers 1982, p.
202.
18. Quick 1977. In addition to her consideration ofwomen's oppression in class-society,
Quick develops a contrast between class- and non-class- societies, arguing that 'it is only in
class society that the involvement of women in child-bearing results in the oppres-sion of
women' (p. 45). Along similar lines, she makes the radical suggestion that '"the family'' ... is
a term applicable only to class societies, in which production (and repro-duction) have a
meaning distinct from the organization of production in the interests of society as a whole
(i.e. communist societies, both primitive and advanced)' (p. 47).
The Reproduction of Labour-Power • 151
19. For discussions of the relationship between biology, sex-divisions of labour, and
women's oppression, see Barrett 1980, pp. 72-7, 195-9, and Sayers 1982. Mark Cousins
claims that the biological distinction of sex cannot be addressed by Marxism, for 'the
capitalist and the labourer are personifications [that are] abstract to and indifferent to
the problem of sexual difference'. Cousins 1978, p. 63. By contrast, Marx did not
disregard the role of biology in social reproduction. He insisted, for example, that the
mortality of direct producers necessitates their maintenance and replacement, thereby
making the problem of the reproduction of labour-power critical to the social
reproduction of class-society. In the case of capitalism, 'reproduction of labor-power
forms, in fact, an essential of the reproduction of capital itself'. Marx 1971a, pp. 575-6.
If the biological fact of mortality is central to Marxist analysis, why not the biological
fact of sexual dimorph-ism as well!
152 • Chapter Ten
While women have historically had greater responsibility for the ongoing tasks
of necessary labour in class-societies, it is not accurate to say that there is some
universal domestic sphere separate from the world of public production. In class-
societies based on agriculture - feudalism, for example - the labour-processes of
necessary labour are frequently integrated with those of surplus-production.20 It is
the development of capitalism, as Chapter n shows, that creates a sharp
demarcation between the arena in which surplus-labour is per-formed and a sphere
that can properly be called domestic. To the extent that analysts assert the
universality of some invariant domestic sphere, they are in fact projecting onto
non-capitalist class-societies a distinction that is the product of capitalist relations
of production.
The exact form by which men obtain more means of subsistence than needed for
their own individual consumption varies from society to society, but the
arrangement is ordinarily legitimated by their domination of women and rein-
forced by institutionalised structures of female oppression. The ruling class, in
order to stabilise the reproduction oflabour-power as well as to keep the amount of
necessary labour at acceptable levels, encourages male supremacy within the
exploited class. Quick outlines the dynamic:
Any attempt by women to appropriate to themselves more than is
required for their subsistence is an indirect demand for part of the surplus
appropriated by the ruling class. Thus male authority over women is
supported and even enforced by the ruling class. On the oth~r hand, any
attempt by men to evade their 'responsibilities' for the support of women
is also resisted, within the confines of a system which relies on male
supremacy. Men's control of means of subsistence greater than needed for
their own reproduction on a day-to-day level is 'granted' to them only in
order to enable them to contribute to the reproduction of their class. 21
Such strategies work on behalf of the dominant class, whatever the immediate
advantages of male supremacy to men.
It is the provision by men of means of subsistence to women during the child-
bearing period, and not the sex-division oflabour in itself, that forms the mate-rial
basis for women's subordination in class-society. The fact that women and men are
differentially involved in the reproduction oflabour-power during preg-nancy and
lactation, and often for much longer, does not necessarily constitute a source of
oppression. Divisions of labour exist in all societies. Even in the most egalitarian
hunting and gathering society, a variety of tasks is accomplished every day,
requiring a division of labour. Differences among people arising out of bio-logical
and social development also characterise every society. Some individuals may be
mentally retarded or physically handicapped. Some may be heterosexual, others
homosexual. Some may marry, some may not. And, of course, some may
,,
be men, and others women, with the capacity to bear children. The social sig-
nificance of divisions of labour and of individual differences is constructed in the
context of the actual society in which they are embedded. In class-societies,
women's child-bearing capacity creates contradictions from the point of view of the
dominant class's need to appropriate surplus-labour. The oppression of women in
the exploited class develops in the process of the class-struggle over the resolution
of these contradictions.
Women in the ruling class may also be subordinated to the men of their class.
Where such subordination exists it rests, ultimately, on their special role with
The argument to this point may be recapitulated as follows. Human beings have the
capacity to produce more use-values than they need for their own imme-diate
subsistence. In a class-society, this potential is organised to the benefit of a ruling
class, which appropriates the surplus-labour of a subordinate class according to
some determinate set of social relations. For this class-society to survive, an
exploitable labour-force must always be available to perform surplus-labour.
Workers, however, do not live forever; they suffer 'wear and tear and death, [and]
must be continually replaced by, at the very least, an equal amount of fresh labor-
power'. Where replacement is through generational reproduction, the fact that
human beings fall into two distinct biological groups, women and men, comes into
play. Women's somewhat diminished capacity to work during the child-bearing
period potentially creates a contradiction for the ruling class. Out of the class-
struggle over resolving this contradiction, a wide variety of forms of reproduction
oflabour-power has developed in the course ofhistory. In virtu-ally all cases, they
entail men's greater responsibility for provision of material means of subsistence,
women's greater responsibility for the ongoing tasks of necessary labour, and
institutionalised forms of male domination over women. While exceptions exist,
and may indeed offer important insights on the question of reproduction of labour-
power in class-society, the historical legacy remains
22. For discussion of the historical origins of women's oppression, see Alexander 1976;
Beneda 1979; Caulfield 1981; Ciancanelli 1980; Deere and Leon de Leal1981; Godelier 1981;
Middleton 1979; Young 1981.
The Reproduction of Labour-Power • 155
one that has been characterised, for better or worse, as patriarchal. In this sense,
Joan Kelly is right to point out that 'patriarchy ... is at home at home. The private
family is its proper domain' .23
In most class-societies, women of the exploited class participate to some extent
in surplus production as well as in necessary labour. 24 Their specific responsibili-
ties and subordination in the tasks of necessary labour may carry consequences for
the work they do in the area of surplus-production. For instance, individual
responsibility for child-care in capitalist society renders women exceptionally
vulnerable to the oppressive conditions of home-work. Conversely, involve-ment
in surplus-labour may affect the forms of women's necessary labour. On American
plantations, for example, most slave-women worked in the master's fields, while
the tasks of cooking and child-care were collectively carried out by older women
and very young children.25 At a particular juncture in the develop-ment of a given
class-society, the oppression of women in the exploited class is shaped not only by
women's relationship to the processes of maintenance and renewal oflabour-power,
but by the extent and character of their participation in surplus-labour.
siderations, all individuals in the exploited class might be mobilised into surplus-
production, causing severe dislocation in its institutions of family-life and male
dominance. Such was the case in industrialising England during the nineteenth
century, and, such, it can be argued, is again the case in the advanced capitalist
countries today.
These tendencies will not proceed unopposed. Migrant-workers may fight
against their isolation from kin. Native-born workers may oppose the use of for-
eign labour. Women may refuse to stay home to bear and raise children. Men may
resist the participation of women in the labour-force. Workers may support
legislation banning child-labour. Women and men may organise to defend the
existing forms of their institutions of family life. In short, the processes of the
reproduction oflabour-power in class-society ordinarily constitute an important
terrain of battle.
Chapter Eleven
Beyond Domestic Labour
the reproduction oflabour-power in capitalist society, and even less on the man-ner
in which it takes place.1
Capitalist reproduction demands that labour-power be available as a com-
modity for purchase in adequate quantity and quality and at an appropriate price.
However imperfectly, these needs shape the processes that maintain the existing
bearers of labour-power, while at the same time the labour-force as a whole is
continually reconstituted to accord with future needs. The manner in which the
sellers of labour-power live out their lives is, in principle, a matter of indifference
to the capitalist class. By contrast, it represents a central concern for the bearers of
labour-power. In this sense, the circumstances under which reproduction of labour-
power takes place, which include the determination of its price, are always an
outcome of class-struggle.
Several characteristics of the reproduction of labour-power and women's
oppression in capitalist society arise from the logic of capitalist accumulation itself.
Perhaps most consequential is the special form taken by necessary labour.
Necessary labour becomes divided into two components. One, which we can call
the social component of necessary labour, is indissolubly bound with surplus-
labour in the capitalist production-process. As Marx showed, the working day in
capitalist employment includes a certain amount of time during which the worker
produces value equivalent to the value of the commodities necessary for the
reproduction of his or her labour-power. This is, for Marx, the worker's necessary
labor, for which he or she is paid. For the rest of the working day, the worker
produces surplus-value for the capitalist, value for which he or she is not paid.
From the point of view of the worker, however, no distinction exists between
necessary and surplus labour-time, and the wage appears to cover both. In Marx's
words, 'the wage-form thus extinguishes every trace of the division of the working-
day into necessary labor and surplus labor, into paid and unpaid labor. All labor
appears as paid labor'.2
Marx did not identify a second component of necessary labour in capitalist
society, one that we can call the domestic component of necessary labour -
1. Marx 1971a, pp. 535-6; similar statements appear on pp. 533, 537, 538, and 542, as
well as in Marx 1973b, pp. 458, 676-7, 717n. Marx's famous comments that the labourer
'belongs to himself, and performs his necessary vital functions outside the process of
production', a performance 'the capitalist may safely leave ... to the laborer's instincts of self-
preservation and of propagation', implicitly recognise reproduction of labour-power as a
process that must remain external to capitalist commodity-production. His unfortunate
phrasing, quite rightly the object of feminist criticism, appears to exempt the process from
theoretical examination, however, and conceals the kernel of genuine theoretical insight.
Marx 1971a, pp. 536-7. Molyneux argues that 'domestic labour, as privatised individual
labour not subject to the law of value, lies outside the theory of the capitalist mode of
production', but she does not deny the importance of developing a Marxist analysis of domestic
labour in capitalist society: Molyneux 1977, p. 20.
2. Marx 1971a, p. 505.
Beyond Domestic Labour • 159
3· The units for the performance of the domestic component of necessary labour can be
analysed in terms of what has been called the double 'separation' of the direct pro-ducer, who
neither 'owns' nor 'possesses' the means and conditions of capitalist produc-tion. The
payment of wages and the isolated domestic-labour site embody this double separation.
Wage-labourers cannot appropriate, or own, surplus-value. Neither can they activate, or
possess, the concrete labour-process. In this sense, the payment of wages cor-responds to the
worker's lack of ownership of any property, save his or her own labour-power. Spatial,
temporal, and institutional separation of the site of domestic labour from that of wage-labour
reflects the worker's inability to set the instruments of social labour
160 • Chapter Eleven
in motion. In sum, the bearers of labour-power are in a state of non-ownership and non-
possession of the means and conditions of production. From this point of view, the
units for the performance of domestic labour constitute a special subset of social units
in capitalist society. They are concrete forms taken by the relation between the working
class's non-ownership and non-possession of the means and conditions of production.
Note Poulantzas's characterisation of the enterprise as 'the concrete form of the relation
between an economic ownership and a possession that both belong to capital'.
Poulantzas 1975, p. 123. See also Althusser and Balibar 1970, and Bettelheim 1975. Because
these social units materialise a definite relationship to the means and conditions of
production - namely, non-ownership and non-possession on the part of the bearers oflabour-
power-they cannot be viewed as private enclaves developing in relative isolation from the
processes of capitalist production. The form, composition, and internal structure of the
special set of social units acting as sites for domestic labour are, in fact, directly affected by
the course of capitalist accumulation.
In a limited sense, the social units in which the domestic component of necessary
labour takes place are the counterparts of capitalist enterprises. From this point of view,
Bettelheim's discussion of the 'displacement of the limits' of the enterprise with the rise
of monopoly-capitalism suggests a similar conceptualisation of the development of
family-households in capitalist society. The removal of certain functions from the pri-
vate household, for example, and the development of collective consumption, represent
analogous displacements of limits. It must be emphasised that to speak of the units of
domestic labour as counterparts to those of capitalist production implies no simple
parallelism.
Beyond Domestic Labour • 161
social, family and work, women and men. Rooted in the economic workings of the
capitalist mode of production, and reinforced by a system of male suprem-acy, this
ideology of separate spheres has a force that is extremely difficult to transcend.
Where some categories of male workers command wages sufficient to maintain a
private household staffed by a non-working wife, the ideology takes a particularly
stubborn institutional form.
The drive for accumulation causes constant change in capitalist societies,
including changes in the quantity and character of the domestic component of
necessary labour. As Marx demonstrated, capitalist accumulation depends on the
growth of surplus-labour, appropriated in the form of absolute and relative surplus-
value.4 He discussed these two forms of augmented surplus-value in terms of a
particular society's established working day of ten hours in capital-ist production,
divided into five hours each of necessary and surplus-labour. If the hours of work
are extended to, say, twelve hours, the capitalists appropri-ate two hours' worth of
absolute surplus-value for each worker. If the amount of necessary labour falls to,
say, four hours, they appropriate an hour's worth of relative surplus-value for each
worker. While both processes contribute to capitalist accumulation, relative
surplus-value ordinarily plays a greater part, for the established working day of an
individual can only be extended so far. Marx analysed two major ways of
producing relative surplus-value that are available to the capitalists: introduction of
machinery, technological improvements, and the like, and reduction in the costs of
the means of subsistence. Together, he noted, they fuel capitalism's penetration into
all sectors of social life.
Capital's need to augment surplus-value implies a· contradiction between
domestic labour and wage-labour. As a component of necessary labour, domes-tic
labour potentially takes away from the commitment workers can make to
performing surplus-labour through participation in wage-work. Objectively, then, it
competes with capital's drive for accumulation. If one tends one's own garden plot,
chops one's own firewood, cooks one's own meals, and walks six miles to work, the
amount of time and en~rgy available for wage-labour is less than if one buys food in
a supermarket, lives in a centrally-heated apartment-building, eats in restaurants,
and takes public transportation to work. Similarly, if one supports another person,
for example a wife, in order that she take care of domestic labour, that person is
less available to participate in wage-labour, while at the same time one's own wage
must cover the costs of her means of consumption. To the extent that the domestic
labour of a capitalist society takes place within private households, the pressure of
capitalist accumulation results in a tendency to decrease the amount performed in
each household. That is, the
labour-camps. Such arrangements reduce domestic labour and cheapen the cost of
renewal, but, as recent events in South Africa show, they also represent a political
threat to the ruling class by facilitating organisation. An ultimate barrier to the
socialisation of domestic labour is constituted by biology. While domestic labour
might conceivably be reduced to a minimum through the socialisation of most of its
tasks, the basic physiological process of child-bearing will continue to be the
province of women. 7
The tendency for domestic labour to be reduced in capitalist society remains, of
course, no more than a general trend. Actual arrangements develop out of and
depend on the history of a particular society, and are affected by class-conflict
within it. It is in this context that such pl,Ienomena as the family-wage, female
labour-force participation, discrimination against women in the labour-market,
protective legislation, and child-labour laws must be analysed. Generally speak-ing,
the specific amounts and kinds of domestic labour performed in a particular society
are an outcome of the struggle between contending classes at several levels.
Domestic labour has, in fact, a highly contradictory role within capitalist social
reproduction. On the one hand, it forms an essential condition for capi-talism. If
capitalist production is to take place, it must have labour-power, and if labour-
power is to be available, domestic labour must be performed. On the other hand,
domestic labour stands in the way of capitalism's drive for profit, for it also limits
the availability of labour-power. From the point of view of capital, domestic labour
is simultaneously indispensable and an obstacle to accumula-tion. Over the long
term, the capitalist class seeks to stabilise the reproduction of labour-power at a low
cost and with a minimum of domestic labour. At the same time, the working class,
either as a united force or fragmented into competing sectors, strives to win the best
conditions possible for its own renewal, which may include a particular level and
type of domestic labour.
Domestic labour takes as its raw material a certain quantity and quality of com-
modities bought with the wages workers obtain by selling labour-power on the
market. How are wages determined?
In Marx's view, the value of labour-power is determined by the amount of
socially necessary labour incorporated in the means of subsistence needed to
maintain and replace the labourer. That is, the value of labour-power equals the
value of the commodities the worker requires. Marx cautions, however, that
7· In their desire for equality and liberation, feminists have sometimes tried to abol-ish
the role of biology. For example, Firestone calls for 'the freeing of women from the tyranny
of their biology by any means available', including artificial reproduction outside the womb.
Firestone 1970, p. 206. See Sayers 1982 for discussion of the contradictory and anti-
materialist character of such positions.
164 • Chapter Eleven
into the determination of this value enters a 'historical and moral element'. Two
other factors also affect the determination of the value of labour-power: first, the
costs of developing labour-power with the appropriate skills; and second, 'its
natural diversity, the difference between the labor power of men and women, of
children and adults', a fact that 'makes a great difference in the cost of maintain-ing
the family of the laborer, and in the value of the labor power of the adult male'.
Throughout most of his argument, Marx makes the simplifying assump-tion that
the effect of these various factors can be excluded.8
Recent work on the value of labour-power, particularly that developed in the
context of socialist feminism, has pointed to ambiguities in Marx's formulation. Of
special interest, here, is the discussion centred on the role of non-working women
and other dependents supported by the worker's wage. The question of the
contribution, if any, made by domestic labour to the determination of the value of
labour-power has given rise to a prolonged controversy known as the domestic-
labour debate (reviewed in Chapter 2 ). The most satisfactory answer to this
question was first proposed by Ira Gerstein and developed in a more rigor-ous
fashion by Paul Smith. Both argue that domestic labour, as concrete, useful labour,
simply transfers the value of the commodities purchased with the wage to the
labour-power borne by the worker. The norm of the family-wage - a wage paid to a
single male worker sufficient to cover the consumption of his entire family -
represents, for Gerstein, a specific instance of how the 'historical and moral
element' affects the determination of the value oflabour-power. 9 That is, wage
norms not only include a certain quantity and quality of commodities, they also
imply a certain quantity and quality of domestic labour.
The wage of a worker corresponds, then, to the total value of the commodities
required for his or her maintenance and replacement in particular, historically-
established, conditions. These conditions may or may not include such non-
working dependents as wives, children, aged parents, and so forth. Existence of the
family-wage for some male workers has prompted discussion concerning the
proper interpretation of the 'historical and moral element' in this case. Some claim
that the family-wage represents a higher standard of living and therefore a victory
for the working class in its battle with capital. The family-wage has been available,
however, only to certain sectors within the working class; most working-class
households in capitalist societies cannot manage on one income. Other
commentators therefore argue that the family-wage functions as a con-
8. Marx 1971a, pp. 168, 486. For a more detailed exposition of Marx's discussion of the
value and price of labour-power, and of wages, see Chapter 5·
g. Gerstein 1978; Smith 1978. Smith does not address the question of the destination of
the value contained in the means of subsistence consumed by non-working house-hold-
members, and says nothing about the family-wage. The implication is that persons not
engaged in wage-labour somehow fall outside the capitalist mode of production.
Beyond Domestic Labour • 165
cession made by capital to certain sectors of the working class in return for a
political stability based on male supremacy. In this view, the family-wage con-
stitutes not a victory but a privilege offered to a sub-group of male workers. This
controversy cannot be resolved in the abstract. The significance of the demand for,
and achievement of, the family-wage must be ascertained through concrete
analysis, not logical deduction. It should be clear, however, that the presence of
a non-working wife does not lower the value of male labour-power, and there-fore
is not of inevitable benefit to the capitalist class. Quite the contrary: to have a wife
not in the labour-force requires a male wage large enough to cover the
consumption of two adults. The capitalist class will evaluate such a wage-level
very carefully, weighing economic costs against political and ideological benefits
and pressures.10 ·
10. For the controversy over the interpretation of the family-wage, see Barrett and
Mcintosh 1980. For clear discussions of how a dependent wife not in the labour-force
raises (rather than lowers) the value oflabour-power, see Holmstrom 1981 or Molyneux
1979·
166 • Chapter Eleven
mix of established and new workers - the latter including children of established
workers, members of the industrial reserve-army, and immigrants.
At this level, the reproduction of labour-power becomes a question of the
reproduction of the working class as a whole. The term working class is some-
times interpreted as referring solely to wage-workers. In this usage, for instance,
only women-workers would be considered working-class women. Such categori-
sation abandons all those not in the labour-force - children, the elderly, and the
disabled, as well as non-working wives - to a theoretical limbo outside the class-
structure. Here, the working class will be viewed as consisting of a society's past,
present, and potential wage-labour force, together with all those whose
maintenance depends on the wage but who do not or cannot themselves enter
wage-labour. At any given moment, it comprises the active labour-force, the
industrial reserve-army, and that portion of the relative surplus-population not
incorporated in the industrial reserve-army. The history of capitalism demon strates
that this last category has, at times, included very few persons, aside from infants
and toddlers. Even those seriously handicapped from birth have some-times been
forced into the labour-market, and have, therefore, belonged, how-ever tenuously,
to the industrial reserve-army.
In order to place women theoretically in terms of the working class, some
analysts have assigned them as a group to the industrial reserve-army. Women,
they argue, form a reserve, which can easily be called upon during periods of
expansion and returned to the home when no longer needed. Women not only
participate in this cyclical movement, they represent an increasingly important
element of the contemporary floating, latent, and stagnant layers within the
industrial reserve-army. Most such discussions suggest, finally, that women's entry
into the ranks of the industrial reserve-army is rather recent, and leave unanswered
the question of their previous location within the working class. While this analysis
of women in terms of their position in the industrial reserve-army is suggestive, a
more adequate view would acknowledge that major sectors of the female
population have been present in the industrial reserve-army for decades, even if, in
Engels's words, 'it is only at times of exceptionally good trade that they realize [it]'.
Those working-class women not in the industrial reserve-army would form part of
the relative surplus-population.11
The question of women's position with respect to the industrial reserve-army is
not, in fact, a theoretical one, but a matter for concrete analysis. Which groups of
women in a given society move more actively between the industrial reserve-army
and wage-labour? How large are the numbers and how intense the par-
n. Engels 1972, p. g8. For a summary of the recent discussion about women and the
industrial reserve-army, see Simeral1978. See also: Anthias 1g8o; Barrett 1980, pp. 24-7,
158-62; Bruegel1979.
Beyond Domestic Labour • 167
ticipation in the various sectors? Which groups of women remain locked in the
relative surplus-population outside the industrial reserve-army, and why? What are
the political and ideological obstacles to certain women's entry into wage-labour?
What are the determinants of any movement that can be observed? In a particular
capitalist society, for example, unmarried daughters living in their father's
households may work until marriage. Elsewhere, daughters from rural areas may
migrate to industrial concentrations, where they become the major support of
families left behind. Women in immigrant, but not in native house-holds, or black,
but not white mothers of school-age children, may enter wage-labour. Wives may
normally hold jobs until children are born, or after children enter school, or after
they leave home. In periods of intensifying labour-exploi-tation, mothers of pre-
school children may engage in wage-labour. As Veronica Beechey points out, 'the
question of who constitutes the preferred sources of the industrial reserve army in
any given historical situation must be concretely investigated. It cannot be derived
from the logic of capitalism, but is determined by the class struggle - by the
strategies employed by individual capitals, by trade union practices, and by state
policies which are themselves a product of class struggle'. 12 Beechey argues that
married women in Britain have been an impor-tant sector of the industrial reserve-
army since World-War II. To which it must be added that the general trend in the
advanced capitalist countries is toward equalisation of participation rates among
different categories of women, in the direction of increased commitment of all
women to wage-labour. In the United States, for example, labour-force participation
rates among different groups of women have been converging. As many white as
black wives are in the work-force, more mothers of very young children are now
working, and so forth.
Equalisation of female labour-force participation is a particular manifesta-tion of
the structural tendency in capitalist society toward free availability of all labour-
power. Like the tendency toward the reduction of domestic labour, this tendency
embodies the forward drive of capitalist accumulation. Marx dis-cussed it explicitly
in the context of his ana~is of competition among individual capitals. Capital moves
from sectors of reiatively low profit-rate into sectors of high profit-rate, thereby
contributing to the equalisation of the rate of profit in different branches of
production and among different individual capitals. The more mobile capital and
labour-power can be, the more easily and quickly can competition work its effects
in establishing an average rate of profit. In prin-ciple, then, capitalist accumulation
demands perfect mobility of labour-power and hence, in Marx's words, 'the
abolition of all laws preventing the laborers from transferring from one sphere of
production to another and from one local
13. Marx 1971b, p. 196. Gaudemar has developed the concept of the tendency toward
perfect mobility oflabour-power. Not once, however, does he consider the barrier formed by
the existence of domestic labour and the family-household (Gaudemar 1976).
14. Marx 1973b, pp. 6og-1o.
Beyond Domestic Labour • 169
and circulation. (This is not to say that equality of persons, even in formal terms, is
an inevitable accompaniment of capitalist relations of production. As it turns out,
numerous obstacles get in the way of the development of this tendency. The extent
to which the tendency toward equality of persons becomes a reality in a specific
society depends on its historical development, and in particular on the strength of
popular social movements in the subordinate classes.)
As Marx showed, the idea of equality takes different forms in different soci-
eties, only attaining a firm foundation with the capitalist mode of production.
'Equality and freedom presuppose relations of production as yet unrealized in the
ancient world and in the Middle Ages'.15 Two aspects of equality in capitalist
society are of interest for the analysis of women's oppression: first, the manner in
which the phenomenon of equality of persons is embedded in the economic
workings of the capitalist mode of production itself; and second, the transforma-
tions of this phenomenon with the evolution of capitalism.
The particular form taken by equality in capitalist society derives, ultimately,
from the special character of commodities. A commodity is a product of labour that
possesses both value and use-value. In the opening pages of Volume I of Capital,
Marx analyses the nature of commodities with great care, showing that value arises
in a process of equalisation of human labour. The exchange of com-modities puts
the great variety of concrete useful labour that produces them on an equal footing.
Through the exchange of these commodities, 'the private useful labor of each
producer ranks on an equality with that of all others'. Commodi-ties can be
exchanged because they each embody a certain amount of the same thing: human
labour in the abstract, that is, value. 'The equality of all sorts of human labor is
expressed objectively by their products all being equally values'. The existence of
value requires that differences among various types of labour be disregarded. 'The
equalization of the most different kinds oflabor can be the result only of an
abstraction from their inequalities, or of reducing them to their common
denominator, viz. expenditure of human labor-power or human labor in the
abstract'. In sum, equalisation of differences in human labour is a funda-mental
characteristic of the capitalist mode of production, providing the basis for the
formation of value.I6 Expansion of capitalism brings with it, furthermore, an
increasing equalisation oflabour. Accumulation demands that human labour more
and more take the form of undifferentiated abstract labour.
The very labour-power that, when put to use, releases labour, is itself a com-
modity, albeit a somewhat peculiar one. Like all commodities, labour-power has
both value and use-value. Its value, as we have seen, consists of the sum of the
15. Marx 1973b, p. 245. See also Engels 1947, pp. 124-9.
16. Marx 1971a, pp. 78, 76-7, 78. See also Marx 1971a, Chapter 1, Sections 2 and 4; Marx
1970a, Chapter 1; Rubin 1972, chapters 10-14.
170 • Chapter Eleven
values of the commodities required for the maintenance and replacement of its
human bearer, taking into account the particular 'historical and moral' circum-
stances. Its use-value, from the point of view of the capitalist, is its ability in
production to contribute more value than it has itself, thereby yielding surplus-
value. As a commodity, labour-power is bought and sold on the market. The
worker enters the market bearing his or her commodity - labour-power - and
looking for a buyer. Similarly, the capitalist comes to the market, carrying his
commodity - money - and seeking to purchase labour-power. Each is an owner,
desiring to sell a mass of abstract human-labour congealed in a commodity. As
commodity owners, they are equal traders who meet in the market to contract an
exchange - the wage-bargain. Their transaction follows the laws of commod-ity
exchange. To buy the worker's labour-power, the capitalist must offer a wage that
is equivalent to its value. Marx devoted considerable effort to showing that this
exchange of equivalents 'on the basis of equal rights' of buyer and seller goes hand
in hand with the exploitation characteristic of capitalist productionP In the sphere
of circulation, paradoxically, the requirements of the capitalist mode of production
itself decree that equality must reign.
In order for capitalists to buy labour-power, its bearers must be able to sell it.
That is, the bearers oflabour-power have to enter the market as independent trad-
ers, seeking an exchange of equivalents. In Marx's ironic words, wage-labourers
must be 'free in the double sense'. First, they have to be the free owners of their
labour-power, able to dispose of it as they wish. They cannot, for example, be
enmeshed in feudal restrictions, personally dependent and incapable of autono-
mous action. Second, they must be free of any other way to put their labour-power
to use for their own account. Those who have other sources of subsistence will not
easily submit to the capitalist's demands. It is precisely this double free-dom that
forces workers onto the market to sell their labour-power.l8
Equality of persons is situated in the sphere of circulation, where labour-power
is bought and sold. 'To be sure', Marx observes, 'the matter looks quite different if
we consider capitalist production in the uninterrupted flow of its renewal, and if, in
place of the individual capitalist and the individual worker, we view in their
totality, the capitalist class and the working class confronting each other. But in so
doing we should be applying standards entirely foreign to [the wage bargain]'.l 9
Class-relations are rooted in the process of capitalist production, not in the sphere
of circulation where the individual wage-bargain
17. Marx 1971a, p. 165. See also Marx 1971a, pp. 156-7, 164-6, 172, 188, 547-50. On
the laws of the exchange of commodities, see Marx 1971a, pp. 88-g6, 106-15.
18. Marx 1971a, pp. 164-7. This 'double freedom' embodies the double separation dis-
cussed in note 3 of this chapter.
19. Marx 1971a, p. 550. See also the citations in note 16 of this chapter.
Beyond Domestic Labour • 171
are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are
Life, Liberty, and the Pursuit of Happiness'. Nonetheless, the United States
Constitution excluded slaves, women, and the propertyless from equal status as
citizens. Much of the history of the last century reflects struggles to achieve the
basic freedom to dispose of one's person and property denied to these groups.20
Two hundred years after the beginnings of industrial capitalism, gross civil and
political inequalities have largely disappeared. Bourgeois society's promise
20. For good discussions of the nature of equality in the United States in the eight-eenth
and nineteenth centuries, see: Dawley 1976, pp. 1-10, 6o-S, 207-11; DuBois 1978, pp. 40-7;
Du Bois 1971, Chapters 1-2.
172 • Chapter Eleven
Many groups of varying make-up and character are denied equal rights within
capitalist society. Some, like those comprised of persons of African or native-
American origin in the United States, have specific histories as oppressed peo-ples.
Their members' lack of equality derives from a history of oppression that
relentlessly passes from generation to generation, stamping each person's expe-
rience from cradle to grave. Other groups, like homosexuals, the disabled, or the
elderly, are made up of individuals with particular characteristics acquired more or
less accidentally, and not necessarily shared by kin. These characteris-tics, which
may or may not be permanent, form a basis for discrimination and denial of rights.
Women in capitalist societies are neither an oppressed people with a distinct
history nor a collection of individuals with certain characteristics. They are, rather,
the 51 percent of human beings who have the capacity to bear children, which if
done may replenish capital's supply of labour-power. Their lack of equality has, in
other words, a specific character that distinguishes it from the denial of democratic
rights to other groups. It is a specific character rooted in women's differential place
within capitalist social reproduction. Correspond-ingly, the obstacles to the
achievement of real social equality for women have their own character, separable
from those blocking equality for other groups.
The differential location of women and men with respect to social repro-duction
varies according to class. Working-class women have disproportionate
responsibility for the domestic component of necessary labour, that is, for the
ongoing tasks involved in the maintenan'ie and replacement of labour-power.
Correspondingly, working-class men have disproportionate responsibility for the
social component of necessary labour, that is, for provision of the means of sub-
sistence that take the form of commodities, a responsibility they can only hope to
fulfil by entering into wage-labour. In the capitalist class, women may have
disproportionate responsibility for the processes involved in the generational
replacement of individual class-members, while men may be disproportionately
involved in maintaining the processes of capitalist accumulation. (The analysis of
just which women in contemporary capitalist society fall into the category of
working class is not attempted here. It properly forms part of the much debated and
still confused Marxist investigation into the contemporary class-structure.
174 • Chapter Eleven
Insofar as this problem remains unresolved, the movement for women's libe~a tion
lacks necessary theoretical guidance.)
While only certain women perform domestic labour in capitalist society _
namely, working-class women, whose efforts maintain and renew exploitable
labour-power - all women suffer from a lack of equality under capitalism, at least
in principle. Women's lack of equality constitutes a specific feature of women's
oppression in capitalist as opposed to other class-societies. Discrimina-tory
conventions that survive from earlier class-societies are supplemented and
strengthened by newly developed mechanisms of bourgeois political discrimi-
nation. Both the legal system and an array of informal social practices support the
oppression and inequality of women. At the same time, capitalism promises
equality to all persons, and where it fails to deliver in the case of women, the lack
is strongly felt. Like other groups denied equal rights, women struggle to achieve
them. In the past, the feminist movement focused on the gross inequalities in civil
society, especially those embedded in legal codes. In the advanced capitalist
countries today, the battle for equality continues, and reaches into areas never
dreamed of by nineteenth-century feminists. Women fight for equal rights in the so-
called private sphere, formerly regarded as largely outside the scope of legal and
social redress. For example, they focus on equality in the household, freedom of
sexual choice, and the right to bear or not bear children. In the area of paid work,
women push the issue of equality beyond demands for equal pay and equal
opportunity, by calling as well for equal compensation for work of comparable
worth. In essence, recent demands for equality often pose the question of the
meaning of formal equality in a society based on real inequity. Advanced capitalist
countries have become, furthermore, the first class-societies in which differences
between women and men sometimes appear to outweigh differences between
classes. In these countries, the expansion of the middle lay-ers of the class-structure
and the development of a homogenised consum-rist life-style combine with the still
powerful demarcation between 'women's sphere' of domestic labour and 'men's
sphere' of wage-labour to provide a context in which lack of equality with respect
to men may seem to be the most conse-quential social factor in many women's
lives. It is all too easy to overlook the fundamental distinction between the working
class and other sectors of soci-ety. Socialist feminists insist that Jacqueline
Kennedy Onassis is not, in any real sense, a sister, but other distinctions tend to
fade.
The specific character of women's oppression in capitalist societies is estab-
lished, in short, by women's particular dual position with respect to domestic
labour and equal rights. At the same time, women's special status constitutes an
obstacle to certain trends inherent in capitalist accumulation. Thus, barriers to
female labour-force participation and isolation in a private household inhibit the
Beyond Domestic Labour • 175
22. Coulsen, Magas and Wainwright 1975, p. 65; Gardiner 1977, p. 159.
176 • Chapter Eleven
So long as capitalism survives, domestic labour will be required for its repro-
duction, disproportionately performed by women and most likely accompanied by
a system of male supremacy.
23. Rayna Rapp summarises the literature on these variations in Rapp 1978-g.
Beyond Domestic Labour • 179
24. Marx 1971b, p. 877. For the non-antagonistic relationship between surplus-produc-
tion and the reproduction of labour-power, see also Marx 1970b; Marx 1971a, pp. 82-3, 496,
and Marx 1971b, pp. 818-20, 847, 878. Although I follow Marx's usage, his retention of the
terms necessary and surplus-labour for analysis of non-exploitative systems may be more
confusing than helpful, as he himself suggests when he comments that 'a part of what is now
surplus labor, would then count as necessary labor; I mean the labor of forming a fund for
reserve and accumulation'. Marx 1971a, p. 496.
25. Caulfield 1981, p. 213. See also Leacock 1977.
180 • Chapter Eleven
minority. With respect to women, democracy for the majority in socialist soci-ety
entails, in the first place, equal rights. Here, it is immediately obVious that laws
alone are not sufficient. As an obstacle to effective equality for women, domestic
labour has a stubborn material presence that no legislation, by itself, can
overcome. A major index of socialist society is, then, the progressive reduc-tion of
the disproportionate burden placed on women by domestic labour. Two paths
towards this goal are available. First, domestic labour itself can be reduced through
the socialisation of its tasks. Second, the domestic labour that remains to be done
outside public production can be shared among women, men, and, in appropriate
proportion, children. Because domestic labour cannot be substan-tially reduced,
much less eliminated overnight socialist society must take both paths in order to
assure women real social equality.
Kin-based sites for the reproduction of labour-power - that is, families - have a
definite role in social reproduction during the socialist transition. In principle, they
differ on several important counts from working-class families in capitalist society.
To an increasing extent, all family-members take part in public production and
political life as equal individuals. At the same time, domestic labour within the
family-household is progressively reduced. What domestic labour remains is
shared on a more and more equitable basis.
Existing socialist societies have made important advances in the area of wom-
en's equal participation in public production and political life. On the whole they
have been unable, however, to confront the problems of domestic labour and
women's subordination in a systematic way. To some extent, efforts have been
made to socialise domestic labour, but the oppressive division of labour within the
family-household remains largely untouched. As a result, socialist feminists
sometimes argue that the drawing of women into public production in socialist
societies represents not liberation, but the imposition of a burdensome double shift.
Only since the 1970s has the question of sharing housework and child-care
responsibilities been considered in a few socialist countries. How ade-quate the
concrete steps taken in this area are is a question that requires serious
investigation.26
In the long run, the establishment of effective social equality between women
and men in socialist society meets an obstacle in the real differences between
z6. Cuba initiated discussion of sharing housework and child-care responsibilities around
1973, as did China, and the topic was considered in Albania as early as 1967. The Soviet
Union has not yet given official support to equalising domestic responsibilities. For
thoughtful studies on women in the socialist transition, see Croll1978; Croll1981-2;
Molyneux 1982; Stacey 1983, as well as the works on the Soviet Union cited in note 7 of
Chapter 8. In addition to documenting women's inequality in the household in socialist
countries, these studies survey the persistence of a sex-division of labour in the areas of
public production and political life that likewise disadvantages women. On Albania, see
Omvedt 1975, especially pp. zs-6.
Beyond Domestic Labour • 181
must wither away.29 The proper management of domestic labour ~:~.nd women's
work during the transition to communism is therefore a critical problem for
socialist society, for only on this basis can the economic, political, and ideo-
logical conditions for women's true liberation be established and maintained. In
the process, the family in its particular historical form as a kin-based social unit
for the reproduction of exploitable labour-power in class-society will also
wither away - and with it both patriarchal family-relations and the oppression
of women.
Marxism and feminism. Their enthusiasm for this work is hard today to recap-
ture.4 It turned out, moreover, to be relatively brief. By the end of the 1970s, inter-
est in domestic-labour theorising had dramatically declined. The shift away from
the so-called domestic-labour debate was especially pronounced in the United
States. In this paper I look again at the challenge of theorising the unwaged labour
of housework, child-bearing, and child-rearing. I argue that much of the early
domestic-labour literature followed an intellectual agenda that has not been well
understood, reviewing my own work in this light. I then consider the reception of
such endeavours by their audiences. Finally, I suggest that the early domestic-
labour theorists' unfinished project deserves further attention.
4· For descriptions of the excitement with which feminists confronted Marxist theory in
the 1g6os and 70s, see Echols 1g8g; Vogel1gg8; and the personal accounts in Duplessis and
Snitow (eds.) 1998.
5· For fine (and very short) overviews of the domestic-labour debate, see Himmelweit
1983a and 1983c. For a survey of the literature, see Vogel1g86. See also the essays in Sar-
gent (ed.) 1981, and in Hansen and Philipson 1990.
Domestic Labour Revisited • 185
6. Molyneux 1979.
7· See, for example, Brenner and Holmstrom 1983; Molyneux 1979; or, in its own way,
Nicholson 1986.
186 • Appendix
8. See, among others, Althusser 1971a; Hindess and Hirst 197s; Willer and Willer 1973;
as well as Marx 1973d.
g. Althusser 1971a, p. 77·
Domestic Labour Revisited • 187
the lens - these tasks of empirical investigation and political analysis constitute
intellectual work of a different and, I would argue, more challenging sort.
12. Paddy Quick (Quick 1977) argues that the core material basis for women's subor-
dination in class-societies is not the sexual division of labour or gender-difference per se,
but the need to maintain subordinate-class women during child-bearing.
10 • Appendix
13. Likewise, dominant-class women have a special but quite different role in the
rraintenance and replacement of their class.
14. The following three paragraphs radically compress Marx's discussions of aspects of
he reproduction oflabour-power. Marx discussed the material at great length and with mple
empirical illustration.
15. Marx 1971a, p. 167.
Domestic Labour Revisited • 191
course.) He defined 'necessary labor' as the portion of a day's labour that enables
the worker to purchase the means of subsistence. And he defined 'surplus labor' as
the remainder of the day's labour, which the capitalist appropriates. IS To put it
another way, the worker works part of the time for himself and the rest of the time
for the boss. The first, the worker's necessary labour, corresponds to his wages; the
second, his surplus-labour, constitutes surplus-value at the disposal of the boss.
16. Strictly speaking, a portion of the value created by tile worker's labour goes to
replace constant capital.
17. Elsewhere, Marx recognised tliat such labour was a condition for overall social
reproduction.
18. Marx 1971a, p. 536.
192 • Appendix
19. At this level of abstraction, I use the term working-class to indicate all those who are
propertyless in the sense of not owning the means of production. The majority of the
population in the United States today, as elsewhere, is in this sense working-class, making it
necessary in less abstract contexts to consider the stratification of households by occupation,
education, income, and so forth.
20. The question of whether or not domestic labour has value in the Marxist sense
triggered its own mini-debate within the women's liberationist literature. In my view, it does
not. For an exposition of why, see Smith 1978.
Domestic Labour Revisited • 193
nent, is sharply different from the social component yet similarly indispensable to
capitalist social reproduction. It lacks value, but nonetheless plays a key role in the
process of surplus-value appropriation. Locked together in the performance of
necessary labour, social labour and its newfound mate, domestic labour, form an
odd couple never before encountered in Marxist theory.21
Capitalists' interest in reducing necessary labour may extend to its domestic as
well as its social component. If some people devote much of their energies to
domestic labour - hauling water from the well, cooking on a hearth, wash-ing
clothes by boiling them, teaching children the basics of reading, writing, and
arithmetic, and so forth - then they are less available for work in produc-tion. By
contrast, when domestic labour is reduced, additional labour-power is potentially
released into the labour-market. Reduction of domestic labour has
· been an ongoing process in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. By the early
1goos, food-preparation was less time-consuming, laundry was in some ways less
onerous, and schools had taken over most of the task of teaching skills. More
recently, frozen food, microwaves, laundromats, and the increased availability of
day-care, nursery, kindergarten, and after-school programmes have decreased
22
domestic labour even further. Reduction of domestic labour through techno-
logical and non-technological means does not inevitably make households send
more of their members' labour-power onto the market. It does, however, create a
greater possibility that they might do so.
In short, capitalists as a class are caught between a number of conflicting
pressures, including: their long-term need for a labour-force, their short-term
demands for different categories of workers and consumers, their profit require-
ments, and their desire to maintain hegemony over a divided working class. In the
abstract of my theoretical construction, these contradictory pressures gener-ate
tendencies, of course, not preordained inevitabilities. Such tendencies do not
necessarily produce outcomes favourable to dominant classes, as functionalist
interpretations would have it. Rather, the processes of reproduction of labour-
power constitute an embattled terrain. In actual societies, capitalists adopt a vari-
ety of strategies, some of which involve manipulating domestic labour in ways
21. This discussion, which clarifies but does not alter my earlier argument (Vogel 1983),
now seems to me less persuasive. What is clear, however, is that whether domestic labour is
conceptualised as a component of necessary labour or not, the bottom line is that some way
to theorise it within Marxist political economy must be found.
22. Nona Glazer (Glazer1987) discusses 'work-transfer' as an important twentieth-cen-
tury counter-tendency to domestic-labour reduction. Work-transfer occurs when labour
formerly performed by clerks is transferred to self-service shoppers, thereby increasing
domestic labour. Martha Gimenez (Gimenez 1990) incorporates Glazer's work transfer into
her discussion of four distinct kinds of domestic labour. Significant though the vari-ous
mechanisms of work-transfer are, I would doubt that they contradict long-term ten-dencies
for households to decrease the total amount of domestic labour performed.
194 • Appendix
23. This analysis of domestic labour as a key component of the reproduction of labour-
power has an empirical counterpart in the way studies of the working class have changed
over the past three decades. Rather than focus just on workers and their unions, numerous
researchers look more broadly at working-class households and communi-ties as bearers,
maintainers, and replacers oflabour-power. See Sacks 1g8g; Glucksmann
1990.
24. I agree with Nancy Fraser (Fraser 1998) that most of what can loosely be termed
gender-relations is not in the economic sphere. My claim here is that there is none-theless
some piece that is economic, that it plays a role in the dynamics of capitalist accumulation,
and that its theorisation belongs to political economy. This important but limited economic
aspect of women's oppression in capitalism is surely one of the factors that marks its
specificity as opposed to, for example, racial or class-subordination.
25. Here, again, I radically compress a lengthier account in Marx.
Domestic Labour Revisited • 195
women perform domestic labour, as discussed above, but all women suffer from
lack of equality in capitalist societies.
Efforts to expand equality's scope make radical challenges on at least two fronts.
First, they tend to reduce divisions within and among subordinate lay-ers and
sectors, by moving all persons towards a more equal footing. Second, they can
reveal the fundamentally exploitative character of capitalism, for the further rights
are extended, the more capitalism's economic and social charac-ter is exposed. Far
from exercises in fruitless reformism or supposedly divisive identity-politics,
struggles for equality can contribute to building strategic alli-ances and even point
beyond capitalism.
To sum up the theoretical scenario ~ offered, in all its abstractness: In the
capitalist mode of production, the logic of accumulation and the articulation
between the spheres of production and circulation doubly mark women's posi-tion.
On the one hand, subordinate-class women and men are differentially located with
respect to important economic aspects of social reproduction. On the other, all
women are denied equal rights. In actual societies, the dynamics of women's
subordination respond to this dual positioning, among other factors.
reading each other's work, not to mention that of usefully critiquing it, encoun-
tered the obstacle of paradigm incompatibility.26
Through the 1970s, the Left was mostly hostile to the notion of developing a
feminist socialism, much less that of revising Marxist theory. In many camps,
feminism was considered inherently bourgeois as well as a threat to class-unity. US
Marxist theorists, mostly male, generally ignored the domestic-labour litera-ture.
In part, the problem here was again a paradigm-incompatibility, this time of
a different sort. From a traditional-Marxist perspective, the dynamics of capitalism
had ultimately to do with class-exploitation. Other issues - for example, gender-,
race-, or national oppression - might be important concerns for socialists, but they
lay outside what was understood to be the realm of Marxist theory.
The audiences for domestic-labour theorising dramatically contracted in the
1g8os. Playing a role in the downturn, certainly, were the increasingly conservative
political climate and the decline or destruction of many radical social movements.
Feminist intellectual work managed to flourish, but with far fewer links than earlier
to women's movement activism. Surviving on college- and university-campuses, it
encountered a range of disciplinary constraints and professional pressures. Younger
generations of feminist scholars had missed, moreover, the chance to participate in
a radical women's liberation movement rooted in the upheavals of the 1g6os. Not
surprisingly, confidence in the relevance of socialist thought to feminist theory
diminished.
The 1g8os and 'gos did not, to the surprise of some, witness the demise of
domestic-labour theorising. Rather, a certain level of interest has persisted. Where
there are relatively strong traditions of Marxist theory for one reason or another, as
in England and Canada, small communities of economists, sociologists, and
historians, male as well as female, continue to address questions descended from
those posed in the early domestic-labour literature.27
In these years in the United States, however, relatively fewer researchers have
been involved with the issues posed in the domestic-labour debate. Feminists who
continue to use the terminology often do so in a manner more metaphori-cal than
analytical. Domestic labour, for example, is still taken to mean some-
26. Thomas Kuhn (Kuhn 1962) describes the many ways theoretical paradigms
remain invisible while powerfully framing their users' thinking. With respect to the
theoretical framework under discussion, Althusser (Althusser 1993, pp. 185-6) also
comments on the phenomenon: 'From the outset we had insisted on drawing a structural
distinction between a combinatory (abstract) and a combination (concrete), which created
the major problem. But did anyone acknowledge it? No one took any notice of the
distinction ... No one was interested in [my approach to] theory. Only a few individuals
understood my reasons and objectives'.
27. For England, see the bibliography in Gardiner 1997, and the journal Capital &
Class. For Canada, see Hamilton and Barrett 1990, and the journal Studies in Political
Economy.
Domestic Labour Revisited • 197
thing whose site and workers are obvious (the private household, women) and
whose content is self-evident (usually, housework, or housework and child-care).
Reproduction, a term with meanings within several distinct intellectual tradi-tions
that were at first the subject of much discussion, has also acquired a generic
meaning.28 Along with a new phrase, 'reproductive labour', it now often covers a
wide range of activities contributing to the renewal of people, including emo-tional
and intellectual as well as manual labour, and waged as well as unwaged work.
Reviewing the literature, Evelyn Nakano Glenn29 observes that:
The term social reproduction has come to be more broadly conceived ... to
refer to the creation and recreation of people as cultural and social, as well as
physical, beings. Thus it involves mental, emotional, and manual labor. This
labor can be organized in myriad ways - in and out of the household, as paid
or unpaid work, creating exchange value or only use value .... [For example,
food production] can be done by a family member as unwaged work in the
household, by a servant as waged work in the household, or by a short-order
cook in a fast-food restaurant as waged work that generates profit.
US Marxist theorists in the 1g8os and gos have continued to be mostly male and
generally inattentive to several decades of socialist-feminist scholarship and
commentary. Many take feminism to be an instance of a so-called identity-politics
that can only balkanise the Left. They worry as well about the unity of Marxist
theory. At the same time, they seem not to be aware of the range of cur-rent debates
and discussions that address these very problems. A handful have begun, however,
to enter the dialogue. Some cover ground already well travelled in the domestic-
labour debate, even reinventing analyses first proposed by femi-nists ih the 1970s.
Others interpret the issues surrounding female oppression as matters oflanguage,
psychology, or sexuality. In so doing, they construct women's subordination as
wholly external to the processes of surplus-appropriation and capitalist social
reproduction and therefore not the subject of Marxist political economy.
Early domestic-labour theorists sought '~o put women's lives at the heart of the
workings of capitalism. They were among the first to intuit the coming cri-sis of
Marxism and to begin exploring the limitations of Marxist theory. Their challenge
to feminist theory and to the tradition of Marxist political economy remains, in my
view, an unfinished project.
28. For 1970s considerations of the meanings of the concept of reproduction, see
Edholm, Harris, and Young 1977; and Beechey 1979. See also Himmelweit 1983b.
29. Glenn 1992.
.g8 • Appendix
30. Gimenez (Gimenez 1990, p. 37) suggests that such households 'simply
reproduce people; and [the labor power of] people ... without marketable skills, [has]
no value under capitalist conditions'. For a different interpretation, see Sassen 1998.
31. See, for example, Vogel1995·
References
Alexander, Sally 1976, Women's Work in Atkinson, Dorothy, Alexander Dallin, and
Nineteenth-Century London: A Study Gail Warhofsky Lapidus (eds.) 1977.
of the Years 1820-1850', in Mitchell and Women in Russia, Stanford: Stanford
Oakley ( eds.) 1976. University Press.
Allen, Theodore 1994, The Invention of the Aveling, Edward, and Eleanor Aveling Marx
White Race: Volume One, Racial Oppres- 1972 [1886), The Woman Question,
sion and Social Control, London: Verso. reprinted (with subtitles added), Marx-
- 1997, The Invention of the White Race: ism Today, 16, 3: 8o-8.
Volume Two, The Origins ofRacial Bakker, Isabella and Stephen Gill ( eds.)
Oppression in Anglo-America, London: 2003, Power, Production and Social
Verso. Reproduction, Houndsmills, Basingstoke:
Altbach, Edith ( ed.) 1971, From Feminism Palgrave Macmillan.
to Liberation, Cambridge, MA Bakker, Isabella and Rachel Silvey 2008,
Schenkman Publishing. 'Introduction: Social Reproduction and
Althusser, Louis 1971, Lenin and Global Transformations - From the
Philosophy and Other Essays, New York: Everyday to the Global', in Beyond States
Monthly Review Press. and Markets: The Challenges of Social
- 1971a [1969), 'Preface to Capital Vol- Reproduction, New York: Routledge.
ume One', in Althusser 1971. Banneiji, Himani 1995, Thinking Through:
- 1993, The Future Lasts Forever, New Essays on Feminism, Marxism and Anti-
York: The New Press. Racism, Toronto: Women's Press.
Althusser, Louis, and Etienne Balibar 1970, Barker, Diana Leonard and Sheila Allen
Reading Capital, London: New Left (eds.) 1976, Dependence and Exploita-
Books. tion in Work and Ma"iage, New York:
Anonymous 1964, International Work- Longman.
ingmen's Association, General Council Baron, Ava 1982, Women and the Making
Minutes, Volume 4, Moscow: Progress of the American Working Class: A Study
Publishers. . , 1 of the Proletarianization of Printers',
- 1975, 'The National Conference on Review ofRadical Political Economics 14,
Socialist-Feminism', Socialist 3= 23-42.
Revolution, 26:85-116. Barrett, Michele 1980, Women's Oppression
Anthias, Floya 1980, Women and the Today: Problems in Marxist Feminist
Reserve Army of Labour: A Critique of Analysis, London: Verso.
Veronica Beechey', Capital and Class, 10: Barrett, Michele, and Mary Mcintosh 1980,
50-63. 'The "Family Wage": Some Problems for
Armstrong, Pat and Hugh Armstrong 1983, Socialists and Feminists', Capital and
'Beyond Sexless Class and Classless Sex: Class, n: 51-72.
Towards Feminist Marxism', Studies in Bebel, August 1891, Die Frau und der
Political Economy, 10: 7-43. Sozial-ismus, Stuttgart: Dietz Verlag.
Atkinson, Jane 1982-3, 'Anthropology', --1976 [1885), Woman in the Past, Pres-ent
Signs, 8: 236-58. and Future, New York: AMS Press.
200 • References
- 1971 [1904], Woman under Socialism, Brenner, Johanna 1984, 'll.eview: Marxist
translated by Daniel De Leon, Reprint, Theory and the Woman Question', Con-
New York: Schocken Books. temporary Sociology, 13,6: 698-700.
Beecher, Jonathan, and Richard Bienvenu - 2000, 'Intersections, Locations, and
(eds.) 1971, The Utopian Vision ofCharles Capitalist Class Relations: Intersection-
Fourier, Boston: Beacon Press. ality from a Marxist Perspective', in
Beechey, Veronica 1979, 'On Patriarchy', Brenner ( ed.) 2000.
Feminist Review, 3: 66-82. - (ed.) 2000, Women and the Politics of
- 1977, 'Some Notes on Female Wage Class, New York: Monthly Review Press.
Labour in Capitalist Production', Capital Brenner, Johanna and Maria Ramas 1984,
and Class, 3: 45-66. 'Rethinking Women's Oppression', New
- 1978, Women and Production: A Critical Left Review, I, 144: 40-7.
Analysis of Some Sociological Theories Brenner, Johanna and Nancy Holmstrom
of Women's Work', in Kuhn and Wolpe 1983, Women's Self-Organization: The-ory
(eds.) 1978. and Strategy', Monthly Review, 34:
Benerfa, Lourdes 1979, 'Reproduction, 34-46.
Production and the Sexual Division of Bridenthal, Renate 1976, 'The Dialectics
Labour', Cambridge journal of Econom- of Production and Reproduction in His-
ics, 3: 203-25. tory', Radical America, 10, 2: 3-11.
Benston, Margaret 1969, 'The Politi-cal Bridenthal, Renate and Claudia Koonz
Economy of Women's Liberation', (eds.) 1977, Becoming Visible: Women
Monthly Review 21, 4:13-27. in European History, Boston: Houghton
Berreman, Gerald (ed.) 1981, Social Inequal- Mifflin Co.
ity: Comparative and Brown, Beverly 1978, 'Natural and Social
Developmental Division of Labour: Engels and the
Approaches, New York; Academic Press. Domestic Labour Debate', mlf, 1: 25-47.
Bettelheim, Charles 1975, Economic Calcu- Brown, Liz 1979, 'The Family and Its Gene-
lation and Forms ofProperty, New York: alogies: A Discussion of Engels' Origin of
Monthly Review Press. the Family', m!J, 3: 5-34.
Bezanson, Kate and Meg Luxton (eds.) Bruegel, Irene 1979, Women as a Reserve
2006, Social Reproduction: Feminist Polit- Army of Labour: A Note on Recent
ical Economy Challenges Neo-Liberalism, British Experience', Feminist Review, 3:
Montreal: MeGill-Queen's Press. 12-23.
Blaut, James 1982, 'Nationalism as an Buhle, Paul, Marl Jo Buhle and Dan
Autonomous Force', Science and Society, Geor-gakas ( eds.) 1998, Encyclopedia of
46:1-23. the American Left, second edition, Oxford:
Blumenberg, Werner (ed.) 1965, August Oxford University Press.
Rebels Briifwechsel mit Friedrich Engels, Bujra, Janet, 'Female Solidarity and the
The Hague: Mouton. Sexual Division of Labour', in Caplan
Blumenfeld, Emily, and Susan Mann 1980, and Bujra (eds.) 1978.
'Domestic Labour and the Reproduction Burman, Sandra (ed.) 1979, Fit Work for
of Labour Power: Towards an Analysis Women, London: Croom Helm.
of Women, the Family, and Class', in Burris, Val 1982, 'The Dialectic of Wom-
Fox (ed.) 1980. en's Oppression: Notes on the Relation
Bobroff, Anne 1974, 'The Bolsheviks and between Capitalism and Patriarchy',
Berkeley journal of Sociology, 27: 51-74.
Working Women, 1905-1920', Soviet
Studies, 26: 540-67.
Camfield, David 2002, 'Beyond Adding on
Gender and Class: Revisiting Marxism
Bottomore, Tom (ed.) 1983, A Dictionary of and Feminism', Studies in Political Econ-
Marxist Thought, Cambridge, MA: Har-
vard University Press. omy, 68: 37-54.
Boxer, Marilyn and Jean Quataert (eds.) Caplan, Patricia and Janet Bujra (eds.)
1978, Socialist Women: European Social-ist 1978, Women United, Women Divided,
Feminism in the Nineteenth and Early London: Tavistock Publications.
Twentieth Centuries, New York: Elsevier.
References • 201
Carroll, Berenice (ed.) 1976, Liberating Croll, Elisabeth 1978, Feminism and Social-
Freeman,Jo 1973, 'The Origins of the Wom- Guesde, Jules 1959, Textes choisis 1867-
en's Liberation Movement', American 1882, Paris: Editions sociales.
journal of Sociology, 78: 792-8n. Guettel, Chamie 1974, Marxism and Femi-
- 1972, 'The Women's Liberation Move- nism, Toronto: Women's Press.
ment: Its Origins, Structures, and Ideas', Hamilton, Roberta and Michele Barrett
in Dreitzel ( ed.) 1972. (eds.) 1986, The Politics ofDiversity,
Gardiner, Jean 1976, 'The Political Economy Lon-don: Verso.
of Domestic Labour in Capitalist Soci- Hansen, Karen V. and llene J. Philipson
ety', in Barker and Allen ( eds.) 1976. (eds.) 1990, Women, Class and the Femi-
- 1977, Women in the Labour Process and nist Imagination: A Socialist-Feminist
Class Structure', in Hunt (ed.) 1977, Reader, Philadelphia, Pennsylvania:
155-63. Temple University Press.
- 1997, Gender, Care and Economics, Harrison, John 1973, 'The Political
London: Macmillan. Economy of Housework', Bulletin ofthe
Gaudemar, Jean-Paul de 1976, Mobilite du Conference ofSocialist Economists, 7·
travail et accumulation du capital, Paris: Hartmann, Heidi 1979, 'The Unhappy
Fran~ois Maspero. Marriage of Marxism and Feminism:
Geiger, H. Kent 1968, The Family in Soviet Towards a More Progressive Union',
Russia, Cambridge, MA: Harvard Uni- Capital and Class, 8: 1-33.
versity Press. - 1981, 'The Unhappy Marriage of Marxism
Gerstein, Ira 1973, 'Domestic Work and and Feminism: Towards a More
Capitalism', Radical America, 7, 4-5: Progressive Union', in Sargent (ed.) 1981.
101-28.
- 1976, 'Production, Circulation and Value', Hartmann, Heidi, and Amy Bridges 1975,
Economy and Society, 5: 243-91. 'The Unhappy Marriage of Marxism
Gerstel, Naomi and Harriet Engel Gross and Feminism', working draft.
(eds.) 1987, Families and Work, Philadel- Haug, Frigga 2005, 'Gender Relations',
phia, Pennsylvania: Temple University His-torical Materialism, 13, 2: 279-302.
Press. Hayden, Carol Eubanks 1976, 'The Zhenot-
Gimenez, Martha E. 1978, 'Structuralist del and the Bolshevik Party', Russian
Marxism on "The Woman Question"', History, 3: 150-73.
Science and Society, 42, 3: 301-23. Hayden, Dolores 1981, The Grand Domes-
- 1990, 'The Dialectics of Waged and tic Revolution: A History of Feminist
Unwaged Work: Waged Work, Domes-tic Designs for American Homes, Neigh-
Labor and Household Survival in the borhoods, and Cities, Cambridge, MA:
United States', in Collins, Jane L. and M.I.T. Press.
Gimenez, Martha E. (eds.) 1990. Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich 1977, The
Glazer, Nona Y. 1987, 'Servants to Capital: Phenomenology of Spirit, translated by A.
Unpaid Domestic Labor and Paid Work', V. Miller, Oxford: Oxford· University
in Gerstel and Gross (eds.) 1987. Press.
Glenn, Evelyn Nakano 1992, 'From Servi- .Heinen, Jacqueline 1978, 'Kollontai and
tude to Service Work: Historical Con- the History of Women's Oppression',
tinuities in the Racial Division of Paid New Lift Review, no: 43-63.
Reproductive Labor', Signs, 19:1-43. Heitlinger, Alena 1979, Women and State
Glickman, Rose 1977, 'The Russian Socialism: Sex Inequality in the Soviet
Factory Woman, 1880...:.1914', in Union and Czechoslovakia, London:
Atkinson, Dallin, and Lapidus 1977. Macmillan and Co.
Glucksmann, Miriam 1990, Women Hennessy, Rosemary 1993, Materialist Fem-
Assemble: Women Workers and the New inism and the Politics of Discourse, New
Industries in Inter-War Britain, London: York: Routledge.
Routledge. - 2000, Profit and Pleasure: Sexual
Godelier, Maurice 1981, 'The Origins of Identities in Late Capitalism, New York:
Male Domination', New Lift Review, 127: Routledge.
3-17.
:hrys Ingraham Kelly, Joan I979• 'The Doubled Vision of
~ Feminism: AFeminist Theory', Feminist Studies, s:
:e and Women's 2I6-27.
lge. Kelley, Robin D.G. I990, Hammer and Hoe:
'Revisiting the Alabama Communists and the Great
te: An Indian Depression, Chapel Hill: University of
raterialism, I9,3: North Carolina Press.
- I994, Race Rebels: Culture, Politics
Jmestic Labour'and the Black Working Class, New York:
Free Press.
' in Bottomore -- I997, Yo' Mama's Dis.funktionaL· Fight-ing
the Culture Wars in Urban America,
r Power' in Bot- Boston: Beacon Press.
- 2002, Freedom Dreams: The Black
Hirst I975, Pre-Radical Imagination, Boston: Beacon
uction, London:Press.
ul. Kelly-Gadol, Joan I975-6, 'The Social Rela-
ine I97I, Rebirth tion of the Sexes: Methodological Impli-
:k: Quadrangle cations of Women's History', Signs, I:
\Tomen's Work", 809-23.
Kinsman, Gary I987, The Regulation of
sm', Science and Desire: Sexuality in Canada, Montreal:
:lara Zetkin: A Black Rose Books.
Krader, Lawrence (ed.) I972, The Ethnologi-
~eminist in Wil- cal Notebooks of Karl Marx, Assen: Van
D. dissertation, Gorcum.
1d Feminism in Kuhn, Annette, and Annemarie Wolpe
( eds.) I978, Feminism and Material-
s, s: 30-4I. ism: Women and Modes of Production,
Ve Stand: Class Boston: Routledge and Kegan Paul,
ledge. I978.
.ss Struggle and Kuhn, Thomas I962, The Structure ofScien-
Working Class tific Revolutions, Chicago: University of
nal of Econom- Chicago Press.
and Class Struc- Landes, Joan I977-8, Women, Labor and
Family Life: A Theoretical Perspective',
and Wishart. Science and Society, 41: 386-409.
"-e Irish Became Landy, Donna and Gerald Maclean I993,
dge. Materialist Feminisms, Cambridge, MA:
~ace, and Class, Blackwell.
ess/Race Today Lane, Ann I976, Women in Society: A
Prison-House of Critique of Frederick Engels', in Carroll
(ed.) I976.
inceton Univer- Lapidus, Gail Warshofsky I977, 'Sexual
fly Mother was Equality in Soviet Policy: A Develop-
mental Perspective', in Atkinson, Dallin
Black Women, and Lapidus (eds.) I977·
Under Slavery', Larguia, Isabel I975, 'The Economic Basis
69. of the Status of Women', in Rohrlich-
Jr Marx: II: The Leavitt ( ed.) I975·
~ London: Law- Laslett, Barbara and Johanna Brenner I989,
'Gender and Social Reproduction: His-
md Capitalism torical Perspectives', Annual Review of
Jcial Reproduc- Sociology, IS: 38I-404.
38.
References • 205
1975, Collected Works, New York: - 1979, 'Beyond the Domestic Labour
International Publishers. Debate', New Left Review, 116: 3-27.
-1975a [1845], The German Ideology in --1982, 'Socialist Societies Old and New:
Marx and Engels 1975, Volume 5· Progress Towards Women's Emancipa-
-1975b [1844], The Holy Family in Marx tion', Monthly Review 34.3= s6-IOO~
and Engels 1975, Volume 4· Morgan, D. H.J. 1975, Social Theory and the
-1975c [1850 ], 'Review of G. Fr. Daumer, Family, London: Routledge and Kegan
Die Religion des neuen Weltalters. Paul.
Versuch einer combinatorisch- Morgan, Lewis 1877, Ancient Society, New
aphoristischen Grundlegung' in Marx York: Holt.
and Engels 1975, Volume 10. Morton, Peggy 1971, 'A Woman's Work Is
- 1975d [1848], The Manifesto of the Never Done', in Altbach (ed.) 1971, 211-227.
Communist Party in Marx and Engels Murdock, George 1949, Social Structure,
1975, Volume 6. New York: Macmillan Co.
assell, Gregory 1972, The Surrogate Prole- Nicholson, Linda 1986, Gender and History:
tariat: Moslem Women and Revolutionary The Limits of Social Theory in the Age of
Strategies in Soviet Central Asia 1919-1929, the Family, New York: Columbia Univer-
Princeton: Princeton University Press. ay, sity Press.
Martha 1982, 'The Historical Problem of Nolan, Molly 1977, 'Proletarischer Anti-
the Family Wage: The Ford Motor Feminismus: Dargestellt am Beispiel der
Company and the Five Dollar Day', SPD-Ortsgruppe Dusseldorf, 1890 bis
Feminist Studies, 8: 399-424. cClintock, 1914', Frauen und Wtssenschaft, Ber-lin:
Anne 1995, Imperial Leather: Race, Courage.
Gender and Sexuality in the Colo-nial Okin, Susan Moller 1979, Women in West-
Context, New York: Routledge. cNally, em Political Thought, Princeton: Princ-
David 2001, Bodies of Meaning: Studies eton University Press.
on Language, Labor and Lib-eration, O'Laughlin, Bridget 1975, 'Marxist
Albany, NY: State University of New York Approaches in Anthropology', Annual
Press. Review ofAnthropology, 4: 341-70. ·
:eillassoux, Claude 1975, Femmes, - 1977, 'Production and Reproduc-tion:
greniers et capitaux, Paris: Frant;ois Meillassoux's Femmes, greniers et
Maspero. :eyer, Alfred 1977, 'Marxism capitaux', Critique of Anthropology, 8: 3-
and the Women's Movement', in Atkinson, 32.
Dal-lin and Lapidus 1977. Oilman, Bertell and Edward Vemoff (eds.)
:iddleton, Christopher 1979, 'The Sexual 1986, The Left Academy, 3, New York:
Division of Labour in Feudal England', Praeger.
New Left Review, 113-14: 147-68. Omvedt, Gail 1975, 'On the Liberation of
- 1974, 'Sexual Inequality and Stratifi- Women in Albania', New York: Gamma
cation Theory', in Parkin (ed.) 1974. ! Publishing Co.
iliband, Ralph and John Saville (eds.) - 1978, Women and Rural Revolt in India',
1976, Socialist Register 1976 London: journal of Peasant Studies, s: 370-403.
Merlin Press. - 1980, We Will Smash This Prison! Indian
:illett, Kate 1970, Sexual Politics, New Women in Struggle, London: Zed Press.
York: Doubleday and Co. Palmer, Bryan 1990, Descent into Discourse,
litchell,Juliet 1966, Women: The Longest Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
Revolution', New Left Review, 40: 11-37. Parkin, Frank (ed.) 1974, The Social Analy-
-1971, Woman's Estate, Baltimore: Pen- sis ofClass Structure, London: Tavistock
guin Books. Publications.
:itchell, Juliet and Ann Oakley (eds.) Petchesky, Rosalind 1978, 'Dissolving the
1976, The Rights and Wrongs of Women, Hyphen: A Report on Marxist-Feminist
Har-mondsworth: Penguin Books. Groups 1-5', in Eisenstein (ed.) 1978.
:olyneux, Maxine 1977, 'Androcentrism in Poster, Mark 1978, Critical Theory of the
Marxist Anthropology', Critique of Family, New York: Seabury Press.
Anthropology, 9-10: 55-81.
References • 207
Poulantzas, Nicos 1975, Classes in Contem- Rowntree, Mickey, and John Rowntree 1969,
porary Capitalism, London: New Left 'Notes on the Political Economy of
Books. Women's Liberation', Monthly Review,
Quataert, Jean 1978, 'Unequal Partners in 21, 7: 26-32.
an Uneasy Alliance: Women and the Rubin, Gayle 1975, ·'The Traffic in Women:
Working Class in Imperial Germany', in Notes on the "Political Economy'' of Sex'
Boxer and Quataert (eds.) 1978. in Reiter ( ed.) 1975.
- 1979, Reluctant Feminists in Ger-man Rubin, Isaak Illich 1972, Essays on Marx's
Social Democracy, 1885-1917, Theory ofValue, Detroit: Black and Red.
Princeton: Princeton University Press. Sacks, Karen 1975, 'Engels Revisited:
Quick, Paddy 1977, 'The Class Nature of Women, the Organization of Produc-tion,
Women's Oppression', Review ofRadical and Private Property', in Reiter (ed.) 1975.
Political Economics, 9, 3: 42-53.
- 1980, 'Why Women Work for Wages', Sacks, Karen Brodkin 1989, 'Towards a Uni-
New Political Science 1, 4: 43-8. fied Theory of Class, Race, and Gender',
Rapp, Rayna 1977, 'Review of Claude Meil- American Ethnologist, 16: 534-50.
lassoux, Femmes, greniers et capitaux', Saffioti, Heleieth 1977, Women, Mode of
Dialectical Anthropology, 2: 317-23. Production, and Social Formations',
- 1978, 'Family and Class in Con-temporary Latin American Perspectives 4, 1-2:
America: Notes Toward an 27-37·
Understanding of Ideology', Science and Salper, Roberta 1972, 'The Development
Society, 42: 278-300. of the American Women's Liberation
- 1978-9, 'Anthropology', Signs, 4: Movement, 1967-1971', in Salper (ed.)
497-513. 1972.
Red Apple Collective 1978, 'Socialist-Femi- - 1972, Female Liberation: History and
nist Women's Unions: Past and Present', Current Politics, New York, Alfred A.
Socialist Review, 38: 37-57. Knopf.
Reiter, Rayna R. (ed.) 1975, Toward an Santamaria, U. 1975, 'Review Article: The
Anthropology of Women, New York: Ethnological Notebooks of Karl Marx,
Monthly Review Press. edited by L. Krader', Critique ofAnthro-
Robinson, Lillian 1975, Robinson on the Wo- pology, 4-5: 156-64.
man Question, Buffalo: Earth's Daugh- Sargent, Lydia ( ed.) 1981, Women and Revo-
ters. lution: A Discussion ofthe Unhappy Mar-
Roediger, David 1991, The Wages ofWhite- riage ofMarxism and Feminism, Boston:
ness: Race and the Making of the Ameri- South End Press.
can Working Class, London: Verso. - (ed.) 1982, Women & Revolution: A
- 1994, Toward the Abolition of White- Discussion of the Unhappy Marriage of
ness: Essays on Race, Politics and Work- Marxism and Feminism, Montreal: Black
ing Class History, London: Verso. Rose Books.
- 2008, How Race Survived US His-tory: Sassen,
1
Saskia 1998, Globalisation and its
From Settlement and Slavery to the · ' Discontents, New York: The New Press.
Obama Phenomenon, London: Verso. Sayers, Janet 1982, Biological Politics: Femi-
Rohrlich-Leavitt, Ruby (ed.) 1975, Women nist and Anti-Feminist Perspectives, Lon-
Cross-Culturally: Change and Challenge, don: Tavistock Publications.
The Hague: Mouton. Sears, Alan 2005, 'Queer Anti-Capitalism:
Rosdolsky, Roman 1977, The Making of What's Left of Lesbian and Gay Libera-
Marx's 'Capital', London: Pluto Press. tion?', Science and Society, 69,1: 92-112.
Rowbotham, Sheila 1972, Women, Resis- Seccombe, Wally 1974, 'The Housewife and
tance and Revolution: A History of Her Labour Under Capitalism', New Left
Women and Revolution in the Modem Review, 83: 3-24.
World, New York: Pantheon Books. Simeral, Margaret 1978, Women and the
- 1973, Woman's Consciousness, Man's Reserve Army of Labor', Insurgent Soci-
World, Baltimore: Penguin Books. ologist, 8, 2-3: 164-179.
• References
ith, Barbara (ed.) I983, Home Girls: A - I983, Marxism and the Oppression of
Uack Feminist Anthology, Bristol: Fall- Women: Toward a Unitary Theory, New
ng Wall Press. Brunswick, New jersey: Rutgers Univer-
- I993, Writings on Race, Gender and sity Press.
reedom: The Truth that Never Hurts, Jew - I986, 'Feminist Scholarship: · The Impact
jersey: Rutgers University Press. ith, of Marxism', in Oilman and Ver-noff
Dorothy I987, The Everyday World IS ( eds.) I986.
Problematic: A Feminist Sociology, - I995, 'Beyond Equality: Some Feminist
~oronto: University of Toronto Press. ith, Questions', Woman Questions: Essays
Paul I978, 'Domestic Labour and lfarx's for a Materialist Feminism, New York:
Theory of Value', in Kuhn and Volpe Routledge.
(eds.) I978, I98-2I9. - I998, 'Socialist Feminism' in Buhle,
~ey, judith I983, Patriarchy and Socialist Buhle and Georgakas ( eds.) I998.
/evolution in China, Berkeley: - 2000, 'Domestic Labour Revisited',
University tf California Press. Science & Society, 64, 2: I5I-70.
inberg, Hans-josef I976, Workers' Willer, David and judith Willer I973, Sys-
.ibraries in Germany before I9I4', His- tematic Empiricism: Critique of a Psue-
ory Workshop, I: I66-8o. doscience, Englewood Cliffs, New
rn, Bernhard I948, 'Engels on the Fam- jersey: Prentice Hall.
ly', Science and Society, I2: 42-64. Young, Iris 198I, 'Beyond tile Unhappy
es, Richard I978, The Women's Libera- Marriage: A Critique of tile Dual Sys-
ion Movement in Russia: Feminism, tems Theory', in Sargent (ed.) I98I.
Nihil-sm, and Bolshevism, 7860-1930, - I98o, 'Socialist Feminism and the Limits
Prince-on: Princeton University Press. of Dual Systems Theory', Social-ist
Impson, Edward Palmer I963, The Mak- Review, 50-I: I69-88.
rzg of the English Working Class, Har- Zetkin, Clara I929, 'Surrender of the Sec-
nondsworth: Penguin. ond International in tile Emancipation of
1rnton Dill, Bonnie I983, 'Race, Class, Women', The Communist Interna-tional,
tnd Gender: Prospects for an All- 6: 37I-82.
nclusive Sisterhood', Feminist Studies, ,, - 1957a, 'Fiir die Befreiung der Frau!', in
I3I-50. Ausgewii.hlte Reden und Schriften, I:
lang, Stephanie I979, Fighting Two 3-11.
Colo-lialisms: Women in Guinea-Bissau, - I957b, 'Nur mit der proletarischen Frau
New (ork: Monthly Review Press. wird der Sozialismus siegen!', in
:el, Lise I973. 'The Earthly Family', Ausgewiihlte Reden und Schriften, I: 95-
Radi-:alAmerica, 7, 4-5: 9-50. m, translated by Hal Draper and Anne
-I978, 'The Contested Domain: A Note m Lipow in Miliband and Saville ( eds.)
the Family in the Transition to Capi- I976.
alism', Marxist Perspectives I, I: 50-73.
-I979, 'Questions on the Woman Ques-
ion', Monthly Review 3I, 2: 39-59·
- I98o, Women, Work, and Family:
iome Theoretical Issues', paper
pre-:ented at the annual meetings of the
iociety for the Study of Social Problems,
~lew York City.
Index
ee also family
x, Eleanor (Aveling) 107-9, 138
x,Karl
n absolute and relative surplus-value
161, 191-92
Jthusser on
Grundrisse by 59-60, 62
on holy family ix-x
in International Working Men's
Association 73, 74
on labour-power xxiv, 68-70, 143, i57,
188
on oppression of women 57
personal history of 43
on proletarian family xxix-xxx
on Proudhon 91
radical feminists on 25
on reproduction oflabour-power 145-6
on sexual division of labour 136
on surplus-labour 148-9, 178
on value of labour-power 163-4
on wages 23
on women 35-9
on women in International Working
Men's Association 75
See also Capital
Marxism and Marxists 2, 8
on domestic labour 195
on feminism 197
radical feminists on 25-6
sexism in 36-7
socialist feminists on 26
Marxist feminism xxii, 1, 6
distinguished from socialist-
feminism
xixm, 183n2
See also socialist-
feminism materialist
feminism xxxvi McNally,
David xvi-xl mediation
xxxix-xl
men
biological differences between
women and 146,147
commodity component of
necessary labour by 160, 173
in division of labour by gender
152 early Engels on relationship
between
women and 48-9
early Marx on relationship
between women and 43-4
Lenin on 128
in middle bourgeoisie 114
power over women within family
exercised by xxxii
as property owners 81
Meyer, Alfred 36n6
middle bourgeoisie 113-15
Mikhailovsky, Nikolay 122
Millett, Kate 25, 26
mining industry xxx
Index • 213
production
Molyneux, Maxine xx, 158m
monogamy 87-8, go Benston on 17-18
Morgan, Lewis H. 78-87, 91, 95 Capital on 66-8
Morton, Peggy xx, 17-19, 24 in domestic-labour debate 22-4
Murdock, George 16 Engels on 94
Narodniks 121-2 housework as 21
Mitchell on 14-16
National Organization for Women (NOW) reproduction distinguished from 144
3, 4, 183n2 productive consumption 66-8, 145
necessary labour 149-50 proletariat
components of 158-g Engels on marriage among 88-g
domestic labour as component of family among xxix-xxx
xxxiii-xxxiv, 159-62, 177 woman-question among us
family as site for 152 women among n6
Marx on 178-g, 191, 192 See also working class
reductions in 193 'property
during socialist transition 179 Engels on 85, 91-2
bywomen 155 Morgan on origins of 81, 83, 84
neoliberalism xxi oppression of women and 154
New American Movement (NAM) 1n1 prostitution
The Origin ofthe Family, Private Property Lenin on 123
Marx and Engels on 46-7, 54-5
and the State (Engels) 88-g6 protective legislation 194
Bebel and 102-3, 108 Engels on 94
dual-systems perspective in 136-8 International Working Men's Association
Margin's theories in 78-So, 83, 85-8 on 74
socialist-feminism in 32-4 Proudhon, Pierre Joseph 91
social reproduction perspective in 137 punaluan family 82, 86
outer barriers 61 queer identities xxxix
patriarchy 155
Quick, Paddy 150, 150ni8, 153
Barrett on xxi-xxii race xxxviii-xxxix
Morgan on 82
socialist-feminism on 26-8 radical-feminism 2, 5, 25, 183
pauperism 71 reformism 14-15, 108-g, ng, 120
peasantry relative surplus-value 161, 191
Capital on family in 63-4 reproduction
Lenin on 126 biological 151ni9
Zetkin on n6-17 of labour-power 142-52, 154-5, 157-8,
population 1Ss, 1Ss-s9
Malthus on 50-1, 61 . ·~mature Marx on 60-2
Marx on laws of 146 socialist-feminism on 26-8
surplus 71, 72 varied meanings of 197
Poster, Mark 35-6 of working class, Capital on 67-8, 71-2
postmodernism xxii reserve-army of labour
poststructualism xxii Capital on 70-2
Poulantzas, Nicos 16on3 surplus population in 61
President's Commission on the Status of women in 166-7
Women 3n2 revisionism 108-g
Principles oJCommunism (Marx and Engels) Robinson, Lillian x
36n6,53-5 Rowbotham, Sheila 27
procreation 122 ruling class 148n15, 153-6, 176
• Index
;ia 121-3 Soviet Union 121, 125