Materialism PDF
Materialism PDF
Materialism PDF
Materialism
S e b a s t i a n Tr u s k o l a s k i
Terminology (1974) and his magnum opus It is noteworthy, too, that many of the
Negative Dialectics (1973). Other notable most pointedly Marxian aspects of the early
examples include Bloch, who explores the Frankfurt School’s materialism were taken
issue in his book Das Materialismus- up in the 1960s/1970s by students of Adorno
Problem, seine Geschichte und Substanz and Horkheimer in Germany, and Herbert
[The Problem of Materialism, its History and Marcuse and Leo Löwenthal in the United
Substance] (1972), Benjamin, who debates States. Significant examples include works
the matter in the notes comprising his unfin- by Alfred Schmidt (1971, 1973, 1974, 1975,
ished Arcades Projects (1999), and Marcuse, 1977, 1981), Hans-Jürgen Krahl (1974), Hans-
who examines the subject in his essay ‘New Georg Backhaus (1997), Helmut Reichelt
Sources on the Foundation of Historical (2001), Alexander Kluge and Oskar Negt
Materialism’ (2005). What holds these texts (2014), as well as Angela Davis (1998). Their
together is that, in one way or another, they positions markedly contrast with those of
all interrogate the professed materialist dis- prominent figures from the so-called ‘second-
position of Marxian social criticism, which, generation’ of the Frankfurt School, includ-
they suggest, had hardened into a dogmatic ing Jürgen Habermas and Axel Honneth,
worldview by the 1930s – at least in its offi- whose work has tended to foreground ques-
cial iterations. Following figureheads of tions of normativity over explicitly Marxist-
‘Western Marxism’ (Elbe, 2013), such as materialist forms of social criticism.
Georg Lukács and Karl Korsch, the authors Without presuming to account for the full
from the Institute for Social Research thus breadth of the Frankfurt School’s materialism –
re-inscribe the diverse concerns collected there are, of course, considerable differences
under the heading of materialism into the his- between its individual players – the follow-
tory of philosophy, especially that of German ing pages will attempt to highlight some of
Idealism – a tradition which, in their estima- its salient features, such as the prominent
tion, had been prematurely left for dead. In emphasis on the suffering body, on material-
this regard, Horkheimer, Adorno et al. ist epistemology, and on the negative image
explore questions of experience and affectiv- of utopia that the examination of these themes
ity, cognition and morality, as well as the is supposed to throw into relief. To this end
relation between nature and culture in the age the chapter is organised into three parts:
of ‘positivism’ – a byword for the philo- (1) An overview of the history of materialism,
sophically un-reflected empiricism of much and an indication of the Frankfurt School’s
scientific thought, including its Marxist vari- place therein; (2) An account of Adorno’s
ants. By re-engaging with the problems of ‘imageless materialism’ as a paradigmatic
materialism in this expanded sense, and by instance of the Frankfurt School’s position;
drawing on a range of disciplinary special- (3) An attempt to highlight the cotemporary
isms – from sociology to philosophy and resonance of the Frankfurt School’s ideas in
economics – the authors from the orbit of the contrast with a recent form of philosophical
Institute for Social Research thus sought to materialism known as Speculative Realism.
recast the parameters of this concept with and All the while the overarching conceit is the
beyond Marx. In this regard they position following: the Frankfurt School’s re-formula-
themselves against a tendency, prevalent tion of materialism – the malleability of man’s
amongst Soviet Marxists such as Lenin, who historical, material situation – intends to safe-
tended to neglect the wide-ranging philo- guard Critical Theory from the perceived pit-
sophical implications of Marx’s early writ- falls of both Soviet-style Marxism and liberal
ings, thus re-converting the emphasis on the scientism by creating an interdisciplinary
material transformation of society into a toolkit with which to change the world that
metaphysical doctrine. philosophy has hitherto only interpreted.
MATERIALISM 663
(It exceeds the limitations of the present actualised form of reason, and an associated
chapter to outline a fifth important forebear of state of freedom, which, they claimed, fol-
the Frankfurt School’s position, namely: the lowed from Hegel’s thinking, but exceeded in
messianic materialism of the Jena Romantics its radicality his stated intentions. Although
[Frank, 2004].) Feuerbach is best remembered for the criti-
First, then, Moleschott, Vogt and Büchner cisms levelled at him by Marx (2000) and
are notable principally because their posi- Engels, his central work – The Essence of
tions demonstrate the extent to which Christianity (1957) – is an important fore-
German-speaking philosophers had aban- runner of dialectical/historical materialism,
doned the precepts of Idealism by the mid not least because it emphasises the impor-
nineteeth century (Gregory, 1977). Over the tance of human sensuality. As Feuerbach
course of the 1850s, Vogt, for instance, pub- writes, ‘I negate God. For me this means that
lished a series of popular texts that echoed I negate the negation of the human. I put the
the fierce atheism of the French materialists sensual, real, and, consequently, necessarily
by rejecting the biblical view of creation on political and social position of the human
biological grounds, arguing that the world, in place of its illusory, fantastic, heavenly
and our experience of it, is to be explained position’ (Feuerbach, 1990: 189). On this
in purely physiological terms; a view that, in basis, Schmidt has done much to rehabilitate
turn, led him to identify psychological pro- Feuerbach’s philosophy by pointing out the
cesses with physical ones (e.g. thinking with importance of his atheistic humanism for the
brain activity). Vogt’s ideas were vigorously development of subsequent materialisms. As
contested by an array of Christian thinkers, he argues:
most prominently Rudolf Wagner, culminat-
If, in its most advanced form, Marx’s theory dis-
ing in a public disagreement at Göttingen in
cusses societal reality on two levels (which are
1854 – the so-called Materialismus-Streit related precisely by dint of their mediation); if it
(Bayertz et al., 2012). Without touching on insists that, despite their objectivity, economic
the finer points of these debates – in essence categories, such as the commodity, value, money,
they amount to a series of broadly ideological and capital are ‘subjective’, i.e. that they are con-
crete existential determinations of embodied
declarations of the superiority of materialism
human beings, then this insight points back to
over spiritualism and vice versa – the public Feuerbachian impulses. (Schmidt, 1973: 19)
interest in such issues, spurred on by major
advancements in the life sciences, created a Third, then, Marx and Engels are crucial for
fertile climate for the proliferation of other carrying out a practical re-orientation of
materialist philosophies. Feuerbach’s anthropological materialism, by
Second, Ludwig Feuerbach – a contem- foregrounding the agency inherent in human
porary of the physiological materialists, who sensibility, which is central for the wider
corresponded for a time with Moleschott and project of re-shaping the material world.
Vogt (Feuerbach, 1993) – is significant for Although Marx acknowledges the impor-
introducing an anthropological dimension tance of Feuerbach for the development of
into the newly fangled German debates about these ideas, one of the best-known docu-
the primacy of matter. Along with Bruno ments of his consequential efforts to recast
Bauer, Max Stirner and others, Feuerbach the concept of materialism is a set of critical
had been associated with the left-leaning notes known as the ‘Theses On Feuerbach’
Young Hegelians, who – in the period before (2000): ‘Feuerbach’, we are told, ‘wants
1848 – foregrounded aspects of Hegel’s phi- sensible objects – really distinguished from
losophy that had seemed to them to call for a thought-objects: but he does not conceive
ruthless criticism of the present (chiefly reli- human activity itself as objective activity …
gion, but also the state) in the name of a fully Hence he does not grasp the significance of
MATERIALISM 665
In a clear echo of Engels’ later works, sense materialism that was forcefully contested by
data is said to mirror the world as it really is, the members of the Frankfurt School, espe-
independently of (and external to) conscious- cially following the publication of Marx’s
ness. Consequently, Lenin argues that ‘sensa- Grundrisse in 1939. This juncture invites
tion, perception, idea, and the mind of man a preliminary observation. To the extent
generally’ are to be regarded ‘as an image of that one can speak of materialism in terms
objective reality’ (Lenin, 1961: 267). This of a unified concept, it seems to fall under
framework is supposed to guarantee the sim- what Adorno and Horkheimer describe as
ple primacy of matter over ideas since ‘con- a ‘dialectic of enlightenment’ (Adorno and
sciousness is only an image of the external Horkheimer, 2002: 26): on the one hand, the
world, and it is obvious that an image can- philosophically problematic insistence on
not exist without the thing imaged, and that the simple primacy of matter can serve as an
the latter exists independently of that which emancipatory blow against the entrenched,
images it’ (Lenin, 1961: 69). The proof that and apparently divinely ordained social struc-
these images are bearers of objective truth is tures of, say, the ancien régime; however, on
supposed to be provided by scientific experi- the other hand, a suggestion such as Lenin’s,
mentation, the analogue of which is seen as that human consciousness merely reflects
political praxis. However, here Lenin runs mind-independent matter, risks reproducing
into difficulties since his suggestion that ‘it these structures under a different name – as
is absolutely unpardonable to confuse … any incontestable facts of a seemingly inevitable
particular theory of the structure of matter’ historical process, which tends (in Adorno
with the ‘epistemological category’ of matter and Horkheimer’s estimation) to culminate
itself, suggests that the primacy of matter is in barbarism rather than socialism. In other
somehow immune to scientific contestation words, a materialist programme like that of
(Lenin, 1969: 129). Accordingly, his effort the Frankfurt School – to ‘reject the illusion
to escape the trappings of Idealism (the mas- that … the power of thought is sufficient to
tery of reality in thought) runs the danger of grasp the totality of the real’ (Adorno, 1977:
reproducing, rather than refuting, the posi- 120) – cannot be put into practice if matter is
tion he rallies against. Indeed, the problem transformed into a philosophical ideal.
that Adorno, Schmidt and others point to in
this regard can be summed up as follows: if
no ‘particular theory’ can pose a challenge to
the unshakeable reality of matter as an ‘epis- ADORNO’S ‘IMAGELESS’
temological category’, then matter itself – MATERIALISM
along with the revolutionary politics that it
is supposed to guarantee – is dogmatically Having briefly outlined some major markers
elevated to a metaphysical invariant. from the history of materialism – from
It goes beyond the limitations of the pre- d’Holbach to Lenin – it remains to consider
sent chapter to explore in detail how Lenin’s the Frankfurt School’s particular contribution
reflections bear on his explicitly political to the development of this theme. Instead of
thought, and, furthermore, on his consequen- surveying its members’ individual positions,
tial revolutionary activities. The mediations the following section will focus on one para-
are complex. Suffice to note that Lenin’s digmatic example, which speaks to many of
views became fundamental for formulat- their common concerns, namely: Adorno’s
ing the theoretical self-understanding of the notion of an ‘imageless’ materialism. As will
Soviet Union as the quasi-inevitable product become apparent, Adorno outlines a philo-
of history’s untrammelled, ‘dialectical’ pro- sophically self-reflexive challenge to the
gress. It is this official iteration of a Marxist scientistic tendencies of Marxist materialism
668 THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF FRANKFURT SCHOOL CRITICAL THEORY
This reflection theory, then, played a significant is, at the very least, theoretically deficient.
role in the history of Marxist materialism. To this As Adorno contends, Lenin’s trans-historical
day it lives on in the form of DIAMAT reflection
metaphysics of matter embeds human beings
theory, according to which theory is supposed to
be an image of reality, regardless of the fact that in a system of seamlessly determined nature
whilst the spiritual and intentional may be directed which belies ‘the possibility of freedom,
at particular states of affairs – it may mean them, whilst’, paradoxically, ‘speaking at the same
make judgements about them – it does not resem- time of spontaneous action, even revolution’
ble them … imagistically. (Adorno, 1974: 212)
(Schmidt, 1984: 18). Whether or not bad
politics necessarily stems from bad theory,
To be sure, Adorno’s identification of Lenin’s as Adorno implies, cannot be decided here.
dialectical materialism with Epicurean Suffice to note that his objections to Lenin
Atomism is uneasy. His suggestion that there are designed to underscore the historical
is an absolute correspondence between constructed-ness of capitalist modernity, as
Democritus’ belief that nothing happens by well as the imperative to critically interro-
chance and Lenin’s alleged historical deter- gate its apparent permanence.
minism, for instance, does not account for But what does Adorno’s criticism of Lenin
the role of Democritus’ doctrine of the say about his own conception of material-
atomic swerve – clinamen – which states that ism? If ‘Materialism Imageless’ negates
the movements of atoms, the indivisible the images of Leninist reflection theory by
building blocks of matter, are ultimately polemically invoking the theological ban on
random – a claim that is supposed to account images, then this strategy implies a different
for the existence of human beings’ free will mode of grasping (and acting upon) the mate-
in an otherwise mechanistic universe. rial world, which does not limit itself to mere
Nevertheless, Adorno argues, Lenin’s theory mirroring, and which does not inflict on it the
of reflection reproduces those meta-physical kind of violence that Adorno associates with
presuppositions that it seeks to recant by identity thinking. In other words, Adorno
assigning an extra-physical quality to osten- seeks to cast into relief a different way of con-
sibly disenchanted matter. By positing the struing the relation between mind and matter;
mysterious ability of mind-independent a relation which calls to mind the ‘Utopia
bodies to emit images whose truthfulness is of cognition’ cited above. Such a relation,
confirmed through sensory reflection, and by however, resists positive portrayal, not least
elevating this reality to the status of an unal- because the tools available for its construal
terable philosophical principle which ensures are insufficient for expressing it. The task of
the efficaciousness of revolutionary praxis, philosophy is thus to think thought beyond its
Adorno charges that Lenin’s concept of inbuilt limitations whilst using the restricted
materialism succumbs to the very ‘meta- terms at its disposal. Materialism, on this
physical subtleties and theological niceties’ reading, implies a complete overhaul of how
that it aims to overcome (Marx and Engels, human beings think the material world, and
1996: 81). In other words, Lenin is said to the possibility of its transformation, from the
fetishise matter by imbuing it with life-like inside out. Such a complete overhaul, how-
qualities, whilst simultaneously reifying ever, raises questions – not directly answered
human consciousness by turning it into a by Adorno – as to the kind of Marxism that is
passive object: a reflecting mirror. It follows conceivable on this basis. What seems clear
that if the official materialist doctrines of the is this: whereas Lenin (following Engels)
so-called ‘East’ aid the ‘uncritical reproduc- postulates socialism as a quasi-natural his-
tion of existing relationships in conscious- torical inevitability, Adorno (and the other
ness’, as Schmidt suggests, then the kind of members of the Frankfurt School) stress
Marxism that these doctrines serve to ground contingency, failure and the reversal of an
MATERIALISM 671
emancipatory tendency into its opposite; Physical’. As he writes, ‘all pain and all nega-
and whereas Lenin (again, following Engels) tivity, the motor of dialectical thought, is the
emphasises the mind’s propensity to reflect variously mediated, sometimes unrecognis-
the world, Adorno aims to negate the image able form of physical things’ (Adorno, 1973:
of the status quo. 202, translation altered). In a characteristic
Having thus established the sense in which gesture Adorno identifies the antithetical
Adorno’s confrontation with Leninist reflec- moment of dialectical thought – ‘negativity’ –
tion theory throws into relief a new form with ‘pain’. His ‘Utopia of cognition’ thus
of materialist epistemology whose utopian presents itself as ‘the mirror image’ of a neg-
implications cannot be positively pictured, ative affect, which inversely signals a state
it remains to explore the aforementioned of hedonic fulfilment (Adorno, 1974: 247).
somatic dimension of his thought. In Negative Adorno thus upends the Engelsian-Leninist
Dialectics Adorno argues that ‘the object’, topos of reflection. This is the sense in
whose primacy is dogmatically asserted by which, for Adorno, suffering is imbued with
Lenin, ‘is a terminological mask’ (Adorno, an ethical imperative. The ‘physical moment
1973: 192). It covers over an elusive excess tells our knowledge that suffering ought not
of matter that cannot be captured by thought. to be, that things should be different “Woe
Wittingly or not, ‘Once the object becomes speaks: Go”. Hence the convergence of the
an object of cognition’, Adorno suggests, specifically materialist with the critical, with
‘its physical side’ – its irreducibly material socially transformative praxis’ (Adorno,
moment – ‘is spiritualised’ (Adorno, 1973: 1973: 203, translation altered). Once again,
192). As he contends, leaving this spirituali- Adorno’s multifarious concerns converge:
sation unchallenged reduces sensation – ‘the materialism is assigned an ethical dimension,
crux of all epistemology’ – to a ‘fact of one which coincides with his view of critique
consciousness’ (Adorno, 1973: 193). In this as a form of socially transformative praxis.
sense, theories of reflection, such as Lenin’s, Schopenhauer, Marx, Nietzsche and Freud
run the danger of misconstruing the thing resound in these lines. As Adorno continues,
that is registered in sensation as being merely ‘the telos of such an organisation of society’
another link in the chain of cognitive func- as would allow for the satisfaction of want
tions. By contrast, Adorno argues, sensation ‘would be to negate the physical suffering
is not spent in consciousness. ‘Every sen- of even the least of its members’ (Adorno,
sation is a physical feeling also’ (Adorno, 1973: 203–4). The insistence on a negation
1973: 193). It is such ‘physical feeling’ that of ‘physical suffering’, in turn, recalls a for-
Adorno associates with a ‘resurrection of the mulation from another important document
flesh’ in ‘Materialism Imageless’. Curiously, of Adorno’s materialism, his ‘Theses on
Adorno explicitly denies the Christological Need’ (1942). ‘The question of the imme-
connotations of his formulation. Instead, he diate satisfaction of needs should not be
cites the ‘Wisdom of Solomon’ as his source posed under the aspects “social” and “natu-
(Adorno, 1974: 187). Whatever the prov- ral”, “primary” and “secondary”, “true” and
enance of Adorno’s imagery, ‘resurrection’ is “false”. Rather it falls into the same category
intimated negatively. Suffering becomes the as the question of the suffering of the vast
somatic index of the non-identity between majority of all the people on earth’ (Adorno,
humankind and the material stuff of nature. 2005: 43). In a ‘classless society’, he argues
This contrasts starkly with Lenin’s Engelsian in an atypically affirmative manner, the rela-
suggestion that matter is simply reflected tion between ‘need and satisfaction will be
by sensory experience. Adorno sugges- transformed’ (Adorno, 2005: 43, emphasis
tively illustrates this point in a passage added). Notwithstanding the question as to
from Negative Dialectics titled ‘Suffering what kind of anthropology informs Adorno’s
672 THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF FRANKFURT SCHOOL CRITICAL THEORY
slippery conceptions of need and satisfaction, in which he argues that ‘the perspective van-
this passage points forward to a central tenet ishing point of historic materialism would
of his unfinished final work, Aesthetic Theory be its self-sublimation, the spirit’s liberation
(2002). The alleviation of bodily suffering, from the primacy of material needs in their
the reconciliation of subject and object, the state of fulfilment’ (Adorno, 1973: 207).
overcoming of societal antagonisms – in That is to say, properly speaking, materialism
short, Utopia – can only be achieved in sem- would mean its own undoing, erasing even
blance, through the labours of autonomous the trace of itself in the satisfaction of need.
art, conceived of as the paradoxical product As such, it is not simply a counter-position to
of modernity par excellence. In the present Idealism but rather the outcome of its imma-
context this means that whilst the possibility nent critique – an immanent critique that aims
of societal transformation is mandated by an at an altogether different relationship between
individual experience of bodily suffering, the humankind and the material world, which goes
‘satisfaction of material needs’ hinges on the beyond the coercive strictures of the status
continued criticism of a philosophical tradi- quo. Adorno’s ‘imageless’ mode of materialist
tion, and a lived political reality, that has been cognition, then, points beyond the critique of
prematurely declared obsolete. ‘The power of ‘representational thinking’ to a ‘Utopia of cog-
determinate negation’, as Adorno puts it in nition’ whose quasi-messianic ‘promise’ moti-
Hegelian terms, ‘is the only permissible fig- vates the unlikely deployment of an ostensibly
ure’ of such fulfilment (Adorno, 1992: 18). biblical motif in the critical re-imagination of
It occurs in formally advanced works of art. a Marxian materialism that rejects the lure of
With this in mind, let us recall briefly the long positive portrayals of a reconciled future.
passage cited at the beginning of this section.
If Adorno argues that ‘spirit’ would ‘be rec-
onciled and would become that which it only
promises while the spell of material condi- SPECULATIVE REALISM
tions will not let it satisfy material needs’,
then the implication seems to be that ‘such Having thus outlined Adorno’s misgivings
spirit may only emerge undiminished when concerning Lenin’s mode of ‘representa-
the conditions of lack and privation, which it tional thinking’, it remains to explore the
repressed, will come to an end’ (Buchholz, contemporary resonance of his critique.
1991: 144). This ‘end’ can only be arrived at Accordingly, it is worth noting that central
critically – through the consummate negation precepts of Lenin’s Materialism and Empirio-
of false life. Accordingly, Adorno argues that Criticism have recently resurfaced in a vari-
‘one of the substantive misinterpretations of ant of philosophical materialism known as
materialism believes that, since it teaches the Speculative Realism. This is especially true
preponderance of matter, or, indeed, of mate- of Quentin Meillassoux’s book After Finitude
rial conditions, this preponderance itself is (2008a), which has been described as reading
what’s desired’ (Adorno, 1974: 198). Rather, ‘like a repetition of Lenin’s ill-famed
he suggests, ‘the telos … of Marxist mate- Materialism and Empirio-Criticism …
rialism is the abolition of materialism, i.e. rewritten for the twenty-first century’ (Žižek,
the introduction of a state in which the blind 2012: 625). Before proceeding to interrogate
coercion of people by material conditions this claim, however, it bears emphasising the
would be broken and in which the question sense in which Lenin’s presence at this junc-
of freedom would become truly meaningful’ ture is revealing: if it is true that After
(Adorno, 1974: 198). On Adorno’s reading, Finitude seeks to ‘complete and correct the
then, a truly Marxian concept of materialism programme of Marxist philosophy under-
is ultimately self-cancelling. This is the sense taken by Lenin’ (Brown, 2011: 163), as has
MATERIALISM 673
been suggested by some critics, then the analogue of the sun’s revolution around the
question arises as to whether the kind of earth), we must now consider the reverse:
social/political change conceivable on this that objects ‘conform to our cognition’, i.e.
basis is prey to Adorno’s critique of dialecti- that the earth revolves around the sun (Kant,
cal materialism. The point here will be to 1998: 110). Without presuming to recount the
argue that, if Meillassoux’s approach marks a intricacies of Kant’s argument, the compari-
resurgence of a quasi-Leninist metaphysics son with Copernicus is important because –
of matter, then Adorno’s position – and by as Meillassoux points out – it contains a
extension that of the Frankfurt School more slippage.
generally – provides a timely model for
It has become abundantly clear that a more fitting
rethinking materialism (and, indeed, Marxism) comparison for the Kantian revolution in thought
today. In order to do so, however, it is neces- would be to a ‘Ptolemaic counter-revolution’,
sary to briefly summarise the central claims given that what the former asserts is not that the
of After Finitude. observer whom we thought was motionless is in
fact orbiting around the observed sun, but on the
Put briefly, Meillassoux’s argument is
contrary, that the subject is central to the process
two-pronged: on the one hand, he suggests, of knowledge. (Meillassoux, 2008a: 118)
it is possible to have determinate knowl-
edge of mind-independent matter; on the If Copernican heliocentrism places reality at
other hand, he insists, one can demonstrate the centre of intellectual inquiry, then Kant’s
that the form of this mind-independent mat- critical turn entails a geocentric counter-
ter is radically contingent. He expounds revolution through which humankind
these views in two steps: (1) Through a becomes the measure of matter. Notwith-
critique of what he calls ‘correlationism’; standing the biases of Meillassoux’s reading
(2) Through a radicalisation of what he (Cole, 2015), his objection serves to frame the
describes as ‘Hume’s problem’. question that he shares with Lenin: how can
As a first step, Meillassoux’s effort to thought grasp mind-independent matter?
show that human beings can grasp mind- Meillassoux seeks to ‘overcome the correla-
independent matter depends on his objections tional obstacle’ from the inside out by show-
to a characteristic of modern philosophy, ing that Kant’s ‘critique of metaphysical
which teaches that ‘we only ever have necessity itself enables … the speculative
access to the correlation between thinking affirmation of non-necessity’ (Hallward,
and being’ – mind and matter – ‘and never 2011: 136). In short, the correlation between
to either term considered apart from the thought and being itself is presented as a mere
other’ (Meillassoux, 2008a: 5). In the main, contingency. As Hallward explains, ‘in order
Meillassoux argues, European philosophers to guard against idealist claims to knowledge
since Kant have mistakenly surmised that of absolute reality’, Kant ‘accepts not only
nothing can be totally a-subjective since the reduction of knowledge to knowledge of
objectivity can only be construed on ‘the facts’, that is, to knowledge of appearances
foundations of the cognition in which it is within certain intellectual strictures; he also
grounded’ (Kant, 1998: 507). He illustrates accepts that this ‘reduction’ is itself nothing
this point by citing a passage from Kant’s but one fact amongst others: ‘another non-
Critique of Pure Reason, which famously necessary contingency’ (Hallward, 2011:
likens the endeavour of critical philoso- 136). In this tacit admission, Meillassoux
phy to ‘the first thoughts of Copernicus’ locates the supposed non-necessity of sub-
(Kant, 1998: 110), the so-called Copernican ject–object dialectics, which are presented as
turn. Whereas, in Kant’s view, traditional incidental to the history of philosophy.
metaphysics assumed that ‘our cognition Immediate access to matter as such is thus
must conform to objects’ (the metaphorical deemed possible.
674 THE SAGE HANDBOOK OF FRANKFURT SCHOOL CRITICAL THEORY
Kant, I. (1998). Critique of Pure Reason. Cam- Meillassoux, Q. (2008b). ‘Spectral Dilemma’, in
bridge: Cambridge University Press. Collapse: Philosophical Research and Develop-
Kluge, O. & Negt, A (2014). History and Obsti- ment IV. Falmouth: Urbanomic. pp. 261–76.
nacy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Osborne, P. (2005). How to Read Marx. New
Krahl, H.-J. (1974). ‘The Political Contradictions in York: Granta.
Adorno’s Critical Theory’, in Telos 21: 164–7. Reichelt, H. (2001). Zur logischen Struktur des
Lange, F.A. (1877). History of Materialism and Kapitalbegriffs bei Karl Marx. Freiburg:
Criticism of its Present Importance. London: ça ira.
Trübner & Co. Richey, L.B. (2003). ‘Editor’s Introduction’, in
Lenin, V.I. (1961). Collected Works, Vol. 14: Pannekoek, A. Lenin as Philosopher: A Critical
Materialism and Empirio-Criticism. Moscow: Examination of the Philosophical Basis of Len-
Foreign Languages Publishing House. inism. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.
Mach, E. (1959). The Analysis of Sensations Rowley, D. (1996). ‘Bogdanov and Lenin: Epis-
and the Relation of the Physical to the Psy- temology and Revolution’, Studies in East
chical. New York: Dover. European Thought 48: 1–19.
Marcuse, H. (2005). ‘New Sources on the Foun- Schmidt, A. (1971). The Concept of Nature on
dation of Historical Materialism’, in Heideg- Marx. London: NLB.
gerian Marxism. Lincoln: University of Schmidt, A. (1973). Emanzipatorische Sinnli-
Nebraska Press. chkeit: Ludwig Feuerbachs anthropologis-
Marx, K. (2000). ‘Theses on Feuerbach’, in cher Materialismus. Munich: Hanser.
Selected Writings. Oxford: Oxford University Schmidt, A. (1974). ‘Friedrich Albert Lange
Press. pp. 171–4. als Historiker und Kritiker des vormarxschen
Marx, K. & Engels, F. (1975). Selected Corre- Materialismus’, in Lange, F.A. Geschichte
spondence. Moscow: Progress Publishers. des Materialismus und Kritik seiner
Marx, K. & Engels, F. (1987a). ‘Anti-Dühring’, in Bedeutung in der Gegenwart. Frankfurt:
Marx & Engels Collected Works, Vol. 25. Suhrkamp.
London: Lawrence & Wishart. pp. 5–298. Schmidt, A. (1977). Drei Studien über Material-
Marx, K. & Engels, F. (1987b). ‘Dialectics of ismus: Schopenhauer, Horkheimer, Glück-
Nature’, in Marx & Engels Collected Works, sproblem. Munich: Hanser.
Vol. 25. London: Lawrence & Wishart. Schmidt, A. (1981). History and Structure: An
pp. 313–612. Essay on Hegelian-Marxist and Structuralist
Marx, K. & Engels, F. (1990). ‘Ludwig Feuerbach Theories of History. Cambridge, MA: MIT
and the End of Classical German Philosophy’, Press.
in Marx & Engels Collected Works, Vol. 26. Schmidt, A. (1984). ‘Der Begriff des Material-
London: Lawrence & Wishart. pp. 353–81. ismus bei Adorno’, in Adorno Konferenz
Marx, K. & Engels, F. (1996). Marx & Engels 1983. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. pp. 14–31.
Collected Works, Vol. 35: Capital, Vol. 1. Schmidt, A. & Post, W. (1975). Was ist Materi-
London: Lawrence & Wishart. alismus? Munich: Kösel.
Meillassoux, Q. (2008a). After Finitude: An Žižek, S. (2012). Less Than Nothing: Hegel and
Essay on the Necessity of Contingency. the Shadow of Dialectical Materialism.
London: Continuum. London: Verso.