Mechanistic and Nonmechanistic Science PDF
Mechanistic and Nonmechanistic Science PDF
Mechanistic and Nonmechanistic Science PDF
AND
NONMECHANISTIC
SCIENCE
An Investigation Into the Nature
Of Consciousness and Form
Richard L.Thompson
BALA BOOKS
Lynbrook, New York
Copyright (5) 1981 by Richard L. Thompson.
All Rights Reserved.
Published by Bala Books, Lynbrook, New York.
Printed in the United States of America.
First Edition.
Thompson, Richard, L.
Mechanistic and nonmechanistic science.
Bibliography: p.
Includes index.
1. Science—Philosophy. 2. Physics— Philosophy.
3. Consciousness. 4. Form (Philosophy) I. Title.
Q175.P497 501 81-19842
ISBN 0-89647-014-8 (pbk.) A A C R 2
om ajñāna-timirāndhasya jñānāñjana-śalākayā
caksur unmīlitam yena tasmai śrī-gurave namah
Contents
Introduction 1
P A R T I. CONSCIOUSNESS
1
1 Introduction
mechanistic premise that all phenomena are due to matter acting in ac-
cord with the laws of nature. In biology this premise implies that living or-
ganisms are combinations of material elements, and that they must have
arisen from earlier states of matter by purely physical processes. Since the
goal of mechanistic theorization is to explain as much as possible by the
natural laws, scientists hypothesize that life developed from matter that
existed originally in a disorganized, nonliving form. This hypothesis has
been systematically elaborated, first in the Darwinian theory of evolution,
and then in the theory of molecular evolution. The first of these theories
deals with the origin of higher species from single-celled organisms, and the
second tries to account for the origin of the first living cells from simple
chemical compounds in a "primordial soup."
In psychology the mechanistic premise implies that mind is merely a
name for certain patterns of electrochemical interaction in the brain. This
means that psychological terms such as "purpose" or "meaning" corre-
spond to nothing more than patterns of behavior that arose as evolutionary
adaptations. The mechanistic premise implies that it is pointless to seek an
absolute sense for such terms or to apply them on a universal scale, for the
universe as a whole consists of nothing but an inexorable flux of physical
actions and reactions. Persons are thus reduced to mere subpatterns of an
inherently meaningless universal pattern.
Although many scientists assert that the mechanistic approach of mod-
ern science is correct, many also admit that it leaves them with a feeling of
dissatisfaction. Thus the physicist Steven Weinberg winds up his account of
the big bang theory by describing human beings as the "more-or-less farci
cal outcome of a chain of accidents reaching back to the first three min-
utes," and he concludes that only the quest for knowledge by physicists like f
himself "lifts human life above the level of farce, and gives it some of the
2
grace of tragedy." The bitterness and disappointment in this conclusion
can also be seen in Bertrand Russell's declaration that, because the mecha-
nistic world view has become so solidly established, "only on the firm foun-
dation of unyielding despair can the soul's habitation henceforth be safely
3
built."
The mechanistic world vision tends to create in sensitive individuals such
a sense of existential despair. It denies the very existence of an absolute
dimension of higher purpose that seems essential for the satisfaction of
the inner self. Of course, some people may argue that if we have no pur-
pose in an absolute sense, we can create our own purpose. Yet this answer,
too, is not satisfying, for if we contemplate such manufactured "purpose"
from the mechanistic viewpoint, we see it dissolve into nothing but a
meaningless juxtaposition of physiochemical events.
Introduction 3
Searching
Past the Mechanics
Of Perception
The life sciences are now dominated by the idea that life can be com-
pletely understood within the framework of chemistry and physics. Those
who subscribe to this viewpoint say that we can explain all features of life—
from the metabolic functioning of cells up to the mental phenomena of
thinking, feeling, and willing—as the consequences of underlying chemi-
cal processes. This viewpoint has become so pervasive that it is generally
presented in biology courses as the only valid understanding of life. Thus,
in textbook after textbook we read that "life means chemical and physical
1
organization," and that "all of the phenomena of life are governed by,
2
and can be explained in terms of, chemical and physical principles."
Yet despite the popularity of this view, we can point to at least one
feature of life—the phenomenon of conscious awareness—that is not
amenable to a molecular explanation. The basic phenomenon of con-
scious awareness is the most immediate aspect of our experience, and it is
automatically presupposed in all our sensations, feelings, and thought
processes. Yet even though consciousness certainly exists and is of cen-
tral importance to our lives, the current theoretical framework of biologi-
cal and physical science cannot even refer to consciousness, much less
explain it.
To see this, let us examine the process of conscious perception through
the eyes of modern science. Our examination will take us through several
levels of successively increasing detail, and at each level we will try to as-
certain whether our scientific picture of reality sheds any light on the nature
of consciousness.
First let us consider a man observing a physical object—in this case, a
thermometer. Figure 1 depicts the operation of the man's sense of sight on
the grossest biological level. The process of perception begins when light
reflected from the thermometer is focused on the retina of the man's eye,
forming an inverted image. This light induces chemical changes in certain
retinal cells, and these cells consequently stimulate adjacent nerve cells to
transmit electrical impulses. These cells in turn stimulate activity in other
13
14 Searching Past the Mechanics of Perception
Figure 1. The process of perception begins when light from an object enters the eye
and is focused on the retina. This light stimulates a series of neurochemical reac-
tions that ultimately reach the brain as a systematic pattern of pulses. These in turn
give rise to an exceedingly complex set of electrochemical reactions within the
brain itself. By studying these processes we may learn a great deal about human
behavior. But will such studies enable us to understand the nature of conscious
perception?
nerve cells, and a systematic pattern of pulses is transmitted down the op-
tic nerve. The image of the thermometer is now encoded in this pattern
of pulses.
When these pulses reach the brain, a very complicated response occurs,
involving many electrochemical actions and reactions. Although scientists
at present do not know the details of this brain activity, they are nonethe-
less in substantial agreement about the basic phenomena involved. When
the impulses streaming down the optic nerve reach the brain, they modify
the overall pattern of chemical concentrations and electrical potentials
maintained by the brain's vast network of nerve cells. This pattern is be-
lieved to represent in coded form the specific content of the man's thoughts
and sensory impressions. As time passes, the physiochemical transforma-
tions of this pattern give rise to sequences of electrical impulses that
emerge from the brain along various motor nerves, and these impulses in
Searching Past the Mechanics of Perception 15
Figure 2. Can patterns of neural excitation account for the conscious experience of
seeing?
I'igure 3 depicts some of the minute structures which constitute the inter-
nal machinery of neurons, and of cells in general. When we examine living
cells closely, we find many intricate structures known as organelles. Just
as we can describe the functions of the gross body in terms of the combined
actions of its many component cells, so in principle we can describe the
functions of the cells in terms of these subcellular components. Yet this
does not help us in our attempt to understand consciousness, for it merely
leads to a more complicated account of bodily behavior. As before, there is
no reference to the conscious experience of seeing.
Let us go deeper. What is the essential nature of the cellular organelles?
As we earlier pointed out, the nearly unanimous opinion of modern bio-
chemists is that one can understand all biological structures as combina-
tions of molecules, and all biological processes as the consequences of
Biochemists have found that living cells contain many different kinds of
extremely complex molecules. For example, the Escherichia coli bacte-
rium, one of the simplest unicellular organisms, is said to contain some two
to three thousand different kinds of proteins, each of which consists of
3
thousands of individual atoms. A complete molecular description of a
single cell would therefore be enormously complex, and, in fact, scientists
have not yet come close to providing such a description, even for the E.
coli bacterium.
Yet however complex it might be, a description on this level would con-
sist of nothing more than a long list of statements about the making and
breaking of chemical bonds. Such a list could give us no greater insight into
Searching Past the Mechanics of Perception 19
Figure 5. An electron density map showing the structure of one of the helical
segments of the myoglobin molecule. [Redrawn with permission from R . E .
Dickerson, "X-ray Analysis and Protein Structure," p. 639.]
of symbols. Such symbols, in turn, are simply marks drawn from a finite
alphabet. They may be represented by the internal states of an electronic
computer or by marks on a piece of paper, but they are essentially arbitrary.
Thus Figure 7 gives us a glimpse of the ultimate appearance of a funda-
mental quantum mechanical description of nature when reduced to its ele-
mental constituent terms. In this figure the alphabet of marks consists of
0,1,2, . . . , 9 , A , B , C F, and the rules for their manipulation are ex-
pressed in terms of the internal language of a particular computer. These
rules simply describe certain ways of rearranging patterns of marks to
create new patterns. Finally, in Figure 8, we reach the end of our investiga-
tion of the scientific world view. Here we find both patterns of marks and
the rules for their manipulation encoded as strings of ones and zeros.
At this point we meet with final frustration in our effort to understand
consciousness in terms of modern scientific conceptions. At each stage of
our investigation we have been confronted with a set of symbols that refer
to repeating patterns in the stream of events we observe with our external
Searching Past the Mechanics of Perception 21
10110110101001100000111010101111110010011
10100011100111000101100100010000111101001
00011011010100010110101111001010100011111
10010000100101010101100011110100011101010
00000000010011010010101001010011111010110
Figure 8. The ultimate reduction of scientific description to patterns of marks—
in this case ones and zeros—that correspond directly or indirectly to the outcomes
of physical measurements. Although consciousness is the primary feature of our
existence, by its very nature it eludes description in these terms.
22 Searching Past the Mechanics of Perception
8. The jīvātmās tend to be associated with material bodies, but they are
not dependent on matter and are fully capable of functioning without
material connections.
and the altimeter, even though he still possesses his normal senses and, in
fact, is using them to observe these instruments.
Since the sensory apparatus of the body is composed of matter, this ap
paratus can provide information only about configurations of material .
energy and their transformations. This information may be used to make
indirect inferences about the jīvātmā itself, but cannot directly reveal any
thing about it. Yet Axiom 7 opens up the possibility that the jīvātmā may be
able to directly obtain information about other jīvātmās by using the full *
power of its own natural senses. If this could be done, the perception of
consciousness would not be a strictly subjective affair. A group of persons
who could perceive one another with awakened senses as conscious be
ings, could discuss and study consciousness with the same objectivity that
scientists now bring to bear on the study of inanimate matter.
In this chapter our purpose is only to indicate the possibility of such a di
rect study of consciousness. Practical methods of carrying out such a study
will be discussed in Chapter 9. Here we will close by noting an interesting
feature of one of these methods—the method of bhakti-yoga, which is de
scribed in Sanskrit literatures such as the Bhakti-rasāmrta-sindhu of Śrlla
Rūpa Gosvāml. 7 This method involves the chanting of mantras such as
Notes
1. Elliot and Ray, Biology, p. 67.
2. Villee and Dethier, Biological Principles and Processes, p. 12.
3. Watson, Molecular Biology of the Gene, p. 69.
4. Wigner, "Two Kinds of Reality," p. 251.
5. Huxley, Essays on Some Controverted Questions, p. 220.
6. A . C . Bhaktivedanta Swami Prabhupāda, Bhagavad-gītā As It Is.
7. A . C . Bhaktivedanta Swami Prabhupāda, The Nectar of Devotion.
8. Dirac, "The Evolution of the Physicist's Picture of Nature," pp. 48-49.
Chapter 2
Thinking Machines
And
Psychophysical
Parallelism
Science fiction writers often try to solve the problems of old age and
death by taking advantage of the idea that a human being is essentially a
complex machine. In a typical scene, doctors and technicians scan the head
of the dying Samuel Jones with a "cerebroscope," a highly sensitive instru-
ment that records in full detail the synaptic connections of the neurons in
his brain. A computer then systematically transforms this information into
a computer program that faithfully simulates that brain's particular pattern
of internal activity.
When this program is run on a suitable computer, the actual personality
of M r . Jones seems to come to life through the medium of the machine.
"I've escaped death!" the computer exults through its electronic phoneme
generator. Scanning about the room with stereoscopically mounted TV
cameras, the computerized " M r . Jones" appears somewhat disoriented in
his new embodiment. But when interviewed by old friends, " h e " displays
Mr. Jones's personal traits in complete detail. In the story, M r . Jones lives
again in the form of the computer. Now his only problem is figuring out
how to avoid being erased from the computer's memory.
Although this story may seem fantastic, some of the most influential
thinkers in the world of modern science take very seriously the basic prin-
ciples behind it. In fact, researchers in the life sciences now almost uni-
versally assume that a living being is nothing more than a highly complex
machine built from molecular components. In the fields of philosophy
and psychology, this assumption leads to the inevitable conclusion that
the mind involves nothing more than the biophysical functioning of the
brain. According to this viewpoint, we can define in entirely mechanistic
terms the words we normally apply to human personality—words like
consciousness, perception, meaning, purpose, and intelligence.
Along with this line of thinking have always gone idle speculations about
the construction of machines that can exhibit these traits of personality.
27
28 Thinking Machines and Psychophysical Parallelism
But now things have gone beyond mere speculation. The advent of modern
electronic computers has given us a new field of scientific investigation
dedicated to actually building such machines. This is the field of artificial
intelligence research, or "cognitive engineering," in which scientists pro-
ceed on the assumption that digital computers of sufficient speed and
complexity can in fact produce all aspects of conscious personality. Thus
we learn in the 1979 M . I . T . college catalogue that cognitive engineering
involves an approach to the subjects of mind and intelligence which is
"quite different from that of philosophers and psychologists, in that the
1
cognitive engineer tries to produce intelligence."
In this chapter we shall examine the question of whether it is possible for
a machine to possess a conscious self that perceives itself as seer and doer.
Our thesis will be that while computers may in principle generate complex
sequences of behavior comparable to those produced by human beings,
computers cannot possess conscious awareness without the intervention of
principles of nature higher than those known to modern science. Ironically,
we can base strong arguments in support of this thesis on some of the very
concepts that form the foundation of artificial intelligence research. As
far as computers are concerned, the most reasonable inference we can
» draw from these arguments is that computers cannot be conscious. When
applied to the machine of the human brain, these arguments support a
nonmechanistic understanding of the conscious self.
that specify the program of activity of the computer. Others contain data
of various kinds, and still others are used to store the intermediate steps
of calculations. These numbers can be represented physically in the
memory as patterns of charges on microminiature capacitors, patterns of
magnetization on arrays of small magnets, and in many other ways.
The central processing unit performs all of the computer's active op-
erations. It is capable of performing a fixed number of simple operations
of symbol manipulation. These operations typically include the follow-
ing steps: First, a coded instruction identifying the operation to be per-
formed is obtained from a specified location or "address" in the memory.
According to this instruction, other data may also be obtained from the
memory. Then the operation itself is performed. This may involve reading
a number into the memory from an external device (input), or transmitting
a number from the memory to such a device (output). It may involve the
transformation of a number according to some simple rule, or the shifting
of a number from one memory location to another. Finally, the operation
will always involve the selection of a memory address where the next coded
instruction is to be sought.
The activity of the computer consists of nothing more than the repetition
of steps of this kind, one after another. The specific operations to be exe-
cuted are specified by the instruction codes stored in the passive memory
record. The function of the CPU is simply to carry them out sequentially.
Like the memory, the CPU can be constructed physically out of many dif-
ferent kinds of components, ranging from microminiature semiconductor
junctions to electromechanical relays. The functioning of the CPU is deter-
mined only by the logical arrangement of these components, and not by
their particular physical constitution.
The operation of a computer can be understood most easily by consider-
ing a simple example. Figure 1 illustrates a program of computer instruc-
2
tions for calculating the square root of a number. The thirteen numbered
statements correspond to the list of coded instructions stored in the com-
puter's memory, but here they are written out in English for clarity. There
are also five boxes labeled (1) through (5) that correspond to areas in the
memory intended for the storage of data and intermediate computational
steps. To simulate the operation of the computer, begin by placing a num-
ber, such as 9, in box (1). Then simply follow the instructions one at a time.
When you have completed the last instruction, the square root of your
original number will be contained in box (2). In an actual computer, each of
these instructions would be carried out by the C P U . They illustrate the
kind of elementary operations used by present-day computers (although
30 Thinking Machines and Psychophysical Parallelism
Figure 1. Computer program for computing the square root of a number. To simu-
late the operation of the computer, place the number in box (1) and follow the
instructions, starting with step 1. When step 13 is completed, the square root of the
number (rounded down to an integer) will be in box (2). (In these instructions,
"increment a number" means to add 1 to it, and "decrement a number" means to
subtract 1 from it.)
pose that they are similarly conscious. If this is accepted, then it follows
that consciousness is an objectively existing feature of reality that tends to
be associated with certain material structures, such as the bodies of living
human beings.
Now, when a common person hears that a computer can be "conscious,"
his natural tendency is to interpret this word in the sense that we have just
described. Thus, he will imagine that a computer can have subjective,
conscious experience similar to his own. Certainly this is the idea behind
the fictional stories such as the one with which we began this chapter.
One imagines that the computerized " M r . Jones" is actually feeling aston-
ishment at his strange transformation as he looks about the room through
the computer's TV cameras. This implies that his feeling of astonishment
really exists.
If this is possible for the computerized Mr. Jones, then we are faced with
the situation depicted in Figure 3. On the one hand, the conscious expe-
rience of the computer exists—its subjective experience of colors, sounds,
thoughts, and feelings is an actual reality. On the other hand, the physical
structures of the computer exist. However, we cannot directly correlate
consciousness with the concrete physical processes of the computer, nor
can we relate it to the execution of individual elementary operations, such
as those of Figure 1. According to the artificial intelligence researchers,
consciousness should correspond to higher-order abstract properties of
the computer's physical states—properties described by symbols such
as "thought" and "feeling" that stand at the top of an extensive pyramid
of abstract definitions. Indeed, these abstract properties are the only
conceivable features of our sentient computer that could have any direct
correlation with the contents of consciousness.
Since consciousness is real, however, and these abstract properties are
not, we can only conclude that something must exist in nature that can
somehow "read" these properties from the physical states of the computer.
This entity is represented in Figure 3 by the arrow connecting the real con-
tents of consciousness with higher levels in the hierarchy of abstract sym-
bolic descriptions of the "sentient computer." It must have the following
characteristics:
6
regarded as the most sophisticated of the various forms of behaviorism.
As such, functionalism may seem satisfactory as long as we ignore the exis-
tence of consciousness. But since computer coding says nothing about con-
scious experience, functionalism is completely unable to account for this
essential feature of sentient beings. Thus one advocate of functionalism ad-
mitted in a recent article, "Many psychologists who are inclined to accept
the functionalist framework are nevertheless worried about the failure of
functionalism to reveal much about consciousness. Functionalists have
made a few ingenious attempts to talk themselves and their colleagues out
7
of this worry, but they have not, in my view, done so with much success."
Let us therefore consider a number of theories in which consciousness is
granted a real existence. We will begin by examining the identity theory,
dual-aspect theories, and the theory of psychophysical parallelism. These
theories have many subtle philosophical nuances, but they all share one
key feature that is ruled out by the analysis presented in this chapter. We
can show this by briefly defining these theories:
8
(a) Identity theory. According to the identity theory, both conscious
mental experience and physical phenomena are real. However, mental
and neural events are one and the same, and they are basically physical.
(heories was devised by Spinoza, who held that there is one underlying
substance that has both physical and psychological aspects. Another
theory, devised by Alfred N. Whitehead, features one fundamental pro-
cess that is inherently endowed with "feeling," and that generates both
10
consciousness and physical phenomena. Many of these theories hold
that all physical objects are to some extent sentient, a position known
as panpsychism.
11
(c) Psychophysical parallelism. This theory holds that consciousness
and material phenomena are real, and are correlated with one another in
a one-to-one fashion without any causal connection. John von Neumann
jja ve the following interesting definition of psychophysical parallelism: " I t
is a fundamental requirement of the scientific viewpoint—the so-called
principle of the psycho-physical parallelism—that it must be possible so to
describe the extra-physical process of the subjective perception as if it
were in reality in the physical world—i.e. to assign to its parts equivalent
12
physical processes in the objective environment, in ordinary space."
The common feature of these theories is that they all posit a direct, one-
to-one correlation between the contents of consciousness and material
40 Thinking Machines and Psychophysical Parallelism
phenomena. They maintain that these two things are identical, or that they
are aspects of a third thing, or that they somehow run in parallel. Yet we
have seen that there can be no one-to-one correlation between the contents
of consciousness and the physical phenomena of the brain. Rather, the
correlation that must exist between these two real phenomena is highly
complex, and possesses the indirect character indicated by statements (1)
and (2).
If we posit a one-to-one correlation between the contents of conscious-
ness and certain natural phenomena, then these phenomena must be dis-
tinct from the neural interactions of the brain. This conclusion certainly
contradicts theories (a) and (c), which are intended to show that con-
sciousness can be comfortably accommodated within the framework of
current scientific thinking. This conclusion also contradicts those theories
of type (b) which hold that the underlying "substance" is co-extensive with
matter. (It is interesting to note that Whitehead's process philosophy does
not maintain this, and allows for the existence of extraneural psychic pro-
cesses that transmit information back and forth between the brain and an
13
extraneural sentient self. )
14
Another theory is idealism, which holds that only conscious minds
have actual existence, and that physical objects are nothing but mental
perceptions. This implies that the neurons in our brains must also be per-
ceptions, and the question arises, " I n what mind are they perceptions?" On
the one hand, it is hard to see how the neurons in my brain could be per-
ceptions in my own mind, for I have no direct awareness of them. On the
other hand, if these neurons are perceptions in some other mind, then the
individual conscious self must be distinct from the brain.
Let us go on to consider two other theories called interactionism and
epiphenomenalism. According to these theories, the conscious self is an
entity that is distinct from the body, and that can be influenced by physical
phenomena occurring in the brain. The difference between these theories
is that interactionism allows consciousness to influence the body, whereas
epiphenomenalism does not permit this. According to interactionism, the
conscious self receives sense impressions from the neural apparatus of
the brain, and is able to exert its will on the body by inducing changes in
neural activity. In epiphenomenalism the conscious self is simply a passive
spectator of events that are conducted entirely by physical processes.
Both interactionism and epiphenomenalism are compatible with the
analysis given in this chapter, for we have only considered the transmission
of information from the bodily machinery to consciousness. We should
note, however, that this process of information transmission, as we have
The Conscious Self as a Complete Sentient Personality 41
understood it, is quite different from the processes that many proponents
of epiphenomenalism seem to envision. Advocates of this theory often
convey the impression that consciousness is directly produced by the brain,
as we see in the statement that "the brain secretes thought, just as the liver
15
secretes bile." They suggest that matter in appropriate states of complex
organization automatically generates conscious awareness reflecting that
state of organization.
We have observed, however, that the contents of consciousness cannot
correspond directly with the material configurations of either a brain or a
hypothetical sentient machine. Rather, as we saw in Figures 3 and 4, the
contents of consciousness can only correspond in a one-to-one fashion with
higher-order abstract properties of these configurations. Now, why should
it happen that certain highly abstract features of complex material systems
should come to be represented by real, but nonphysical, conscious percep
tions? It is certainly misleading to compare such a process of representation
with the secretion of bile by the liver.
As we have pointed out in statements (1) and (2), some entity, process,
or law is required that can recognize the appropriate abstract patterns, and
modify the contents of consciousness accordingly. This entity or process
must be nonphysical or transphysical itself, for otherwise how can it either
influence or generate something nonphysical? Furthermore, if it is to be
capable of recognizing abstract patterns, this entity or process must be
endowed with powers of discrimination of the kind we associate with
intelligence.
jīvātmā can ascertain the conditions in its body and bodily environment by
interpreting the physical states of the body's brain.
We realize, of course, that many other interpretations can be offered
for statements (1) and (2). Yet, most of these seem more complicated and
obscure than the simple hypothesis we are presenting here. (Sec Chapter 4
for a discussion of general requirements for a natural law or process that
can generate consciousness.) By presenting the body as a vehicle for the
jīvātmā, this hypothesis enables us to readily understand why nonphysical
consciousness should be associated with complex automata. In addition,
the hypothesis opens up the possibility that we may be able to enlarge our
understanding of the conscious self by direct sensory experience. We shall
therefore briefly discuss this hypothesis and consider some objections that
might be raised against it.
The position of the jīvātmā as the conscious perceiver of the body can be
illustrated by the example of a person reading a book. When a person
reads, he becomes conscious of various thoughts and ideas corresponding
to higher-order abstract properties of the arrangement of ink on the pages.
Yet none of these abstract properties actually exist in the book itself, nor
would we imagine that the book is conscious of the story it records. As we
have indicated in Figure 5, the establishment of a correlation between the
book and conscious awareness of its contents requires the existence of a
conscious person with intelligence and senses who can read the book. Simi
larly, we can most readily understand the relation between consciousness
and certain abstract properties of brain states by postulating the existence
of an intelligent, sentient entity that can read these states.
Now, the objection will be raised that if we try to explain a conscious per
son by positing the existence of another conscious person within his body,
then we have actually explained nothing at all. One can then ask how the
consciousness of this person is to be explained, and this leads to an infinite
regress.
This objection presupposes that an explanation of consciousness must be
mechanistic. But we must simply face the fact that conscious personality
cannot be explained mechanistically. An infinite regress of this kind is in
fact unavoidable—unless we either give up the effort to understand con
sciousness or posit the existence of a sentient entity that cannot be reduced
to a combination of insentient parts.
The reductionistic approach to explanation will not be fruitful when
applied to the conscious self. We will never be able to explain conscious-
' ness by breaking it down into combinations of simple insensate compo
nents. Nor can it be satisfactory to "explain" consciousness by sticking it
The Conscious Self as a Complete Sentient Personality 43
Figure 5. The relation between consciousness and the physical structures of a book.
When a person reads a book he becomes aware of higher-order abstract properties
of the patterns of ink on paper—properties that are not directly present in these
physical structures. This observation suggests an answer to the questions posed in
the captions to Figures 3 and 4. We can answer these questions by positing the exis-
tence of a nonphysical sentient agency that can read the abstract features of the
computer or brain. In the case of the computer there may be no subjective experi-
ence, and no need to postulate such an entity. But since the existence of subjective
experience in humans is indubitable, we cannot avoid the conclusion that some
entity must exist that is capable of reading the physical states of the brain.
44 Thinking Machines and Psychophysical Parallelism
"The conscious self is atomic in size and can be perceived by perfect intelli
gence. This atomic self is floating in the five kinds of air [prāna, apāna,
vyāna, samāna, and udāna], is situated within the heart, and spreads its
influence all over the body of the embodied living being. When the self
is purified from the contamination of the five kinds of air, its spiritual
influence is exhibited." 17
We note that the jīvātmā is said to be extremely minute in size, and to be
located in the region of the heart (rather than in the brain). However, the
jīvātmā does not interact directly with the gross physical structures of the
body. Rather, it interacts with subtle material elements, and these in turn
interact with gross matter in accordance with principles that have yet to be
discovered by present-day physicists and chemists.
This brings us to another objection that is commonly raised against the
theory of interactionism—the objection that the laws of physics must be
violated if a nonphysical conscious entity is able to influence the behavior
of matter. We can respond to this objection by pointing out that because of
computational difficulties, it is nearly impossible to determine whether or
not a complex system really does obey the known laws of physics. Using
quantum mechanics, we have great difficulty analyzing a single molecule of
benzene, and we cannot even begin to predict what will happen in a brain.
Furthermore, developments within the science of physics have led to re
peated revisions in the accepted laws of nature, and we may expect to see
similar revisions in the future. We can only conclude that we have no justifi
cation for rejecting interactionism simply because it contradicts the alleged
universality of a given system of physical laws.
As a final point, we note that the physicist Eugene Wigner has invoked
the principles of current physical theory to argue in favor of an essentially
interactive model of consciousness. Wigner argues that in physics, causa
tion is never a one-way affair. Thus, if consciousness is real, as Wigner
believes, then consciousness must exert some influence on matter. Con
sequently, Wigner concludes that "the present laws of physics are at least
incomplete without a translation into terms of mental phenomena. More
46 Thinking Machines and Psychophysical Parallelism
likely they are inaccurate, the inaccuracy increasing with the increase in the
18
role which life plays in the phenomena considered."
Notes
1. M.I.T. college catalogue, 1979, p. 118.
2. In actual computer applications much more sophisticated methods of
calculating square roots would be used. The method presented in
Figure 1 is intended to provide a simple example of the nature of
computer programs.
Dialogue
On Consciousness
And
The Quantum
A Conversation Between
Dr. Felix Avaroha, Mathematician
Dr. James Yantry, Biologist
Dr. Hans Kutark, Physicist
Who Are Later Joined by Two Physicists,
Dr. Sophus Baum
Dr. Francesco Shunya
This dialogue deals with the question of whether or not modern physics
can provide an adequate description of conscious life. The characters are fic
titious, but most of the views they express have been expounded by various
scientists and philosophers. Sections 3.1, 3.2, and 3.3 are devoted to a dis
cussion of consciousness and the problems of quantum epistemology. In
Section 3.4 the concept of the jīvātmā, or nonphysical conscious self, is in
troduced, and there is a discussion of how the nonphysical self could be
investigated experimentally.
Avaroha: Over the past three hundred years there has been considerable
advancement in many scientific fields, but our understanding of the
nature of consciousness has remained in a completely undeveloped
state. This imbalance in our scientific world view has resulted in a
highly distorted conception of the nature of the conscious self. This
conception is rendered particularly unsatisfactory by the widespread
tendency to attribute universal validity to scientific hypotheses, and to
regard modern science as the only source of true knowledge about the
world.
I propose that we need a science of the conscious self, and that such a
49
50 Dialogue on Consciousness mul thr <Jmiinitm
sider our conscious perception of the color red. You can specify the
wavelength of red light in quantitative terms, and you can also describe
how that light induces certain chemical reactions in the retina of the
eye. You can go o n , at least in principle, to describe a great variety of
consequent physical and chemical transformations in the nerve cells of
the retina and the brain. But at no time in the course of this description
do you say anything at all about the perception of red itself. This per-
ception takes place and is therefore certainly real, but our scientific
theories do not enable us to say anything about it.
Yantry: This problem of consciousness has been discussed at great length
6
by many philosophers, but I don't think it has any bearing on our
theories of physics and chemistry. The general consensus is that con-
sciousness must be generated by matter when it reaches certain levels
of complex organization, as in the brain. Some speak of consciousness
as something distinct from matter, and refer to it as an "epiphe-
nomenon." Others speak of it as an aspect of matter. In any event, the
important point is that consciousness does not exert any influence on
7
the behavior of matter in living systems. This behavior is entirely
determined by the known laws of chemistry and physics.
Avaroha: When consciousness is treated in this way, it occupies a very
awkward and artificial position in our theoretical picture. In the sci-
ence of physics, all other products or aspects of a physical system have
some effect on the behavior of the system as a whole. Why should
8
consciousness be an exception?
I suggest that your characterization of consciousness is inadequate,
and that a valid account must describe how consciousness interacts
with matter. To clear the way for this, I would like to point out that the
physical principles underlying the science of chemistry are not fully
understood. There are serious problems in the theory of quantum
mechanics, which describes the behavior of atoms and molecules.
These problems have been the subject of great controversy, and they
9
have resulted in a great tangle of speculative interpretations, some of
which go to desperate extremes. It is clear that some modification of
the theory is necessary. I would suggest that in making such modifica-
tions, we should keep in mind the requirements for an adequate theory
10
of consciousness.
Yantry: I am not an expert in the theory of quantum mechanics, but I
doubt very much that any of the problems in that field could have any
11
bearing on our established physiochemical understanding of l i f e .
Perhaps, Kutark, you could shed some light on this matter.
52 Dialogue on C Onsiiousnc.w ami ilif Quantum
the man watches, he may see nothing at all for some time. Then, at some
particular moment, he will see a single trail of fog extending in a straight
line from the center of the chamber. Let us begin by considering what
happens within the atom to produce this trail.
Kutark: We can easily explain this in terms of the quantum mechanical
"tunneling" effect. We can imagine that the particle is trapped within the
nucleus of the atom by a potential barrier so high that the particle lacks
sufficient energy to escape. In quantum physics such a particle has a
certain chance of passing through the barrier, even though this is im-
possible from the point of view of classical physics. This phenomenon
is called tunneling, and it is the standard explanation for radioactivity.
Avaroha: This kind of verbal account is often given, but quantum mechani-
cal tunneling is not actually described in terms of a localized particle.
Rather, it is described in terms of a wave. In this case we can visualize
the potential barrier that you mentioned as a partially reflecting glass
54 Dialogue on Consciousness and the Quantum
shell. If some light were trapped within the shell, it would bounce
back and forth repeatedly, but with each reflection some light would
pass through the shell. Similarly, the process of radioactive decay is de-
scribed in terms of a wave that is partially trapped within the nucleus,
and steadily leaks out, spreading uniformly in all directions.
Kutark: It is true that the word "particle" is used in a metaphorical sense in
the quantum theory. Physical descriptions are actually given in terms
of waves, or more generally, in terms of "state vectors" in Hilbert
space, which can be represented mathematically in various ways.
Yantry: I take it that this talk about waves and particles must be related to
the "wave-particle duality" that we often hear about. But your state
ments seem rather confusing. You say that the quantum theory actu
ally describes radioactive decay in terms of a wave, and that the word
"particle" is used metaphorically. Yet I can understand how a particle
can produce a definite track, whereas it is hard to see how a wave that
spreads uniformly in all directions can do so.
Kutark: The answer is very simple. Thus far, we have considered only the
radioactive "particle" itself. To properly describe the cloud chamber
tracks, you would have to extend the physical system at least to the
point of including the atoms of air within the chamber. You would also
have to take into account the interaction between these atoms and the
particle. If you do this, you will find that the state vector of the system
provides a completely satisfactory account of the origin of the tracks.
But in this situation we cannot really call the state vector a wave; it is a
much more complicated mathematical construct.
which specifies how the state of the system changes with the passage of
time. In this equation, the Hamiltonian operator, H, sums up all the
physical laws of cause and effect operating within the system.
Yantry: Naturally, I have seen the Schrodinger equation before, but I have
not studied it in detail. It involves very complicated calculations that
only a specialist can understand. Isn't it possible to make your points
about quantum mechanics using simple examples that can be readily
visualized?
Avaroha: Superficial verbal accounts of quantum mechanics are generally
quite misleading, and may even completely misrepresent the theory.
To really appreciate what is going on in the quantum theory, we must
obtain some conception of how the theory actually describes nature.
In this case, however, it should be possible to present things in a
56 Dialogue on Consciousness and the Quantum
where the Fk(t)'s are state vectors for the radioactive particle itself,
and the Xk(t)'s are state vectors for the rest of the system. If we choose
the X k (t)'s so as to form what is called a " c o m p l e t e o r t h o n o r m a l basis,"
then we can express any Ψ(t) in this way in terms of some suitable set of
Fk(t)'s.
Kutark: You are simply describing the standard m e t h o d of solving differ
ential equations called separation of variables.
Avaroha: That is correct. F o r o u r purposes, however, it is sufficient to
point out that in the q u a n t u m theory the mathematical entities Fk(t)
and Xk(t) for k=1, 2, 3, . . . completely define the state vector of o u r
total physical system at time t.
Yantry: I'm afraid this all seems very abstract. Could you give me some
idea of what these "state vectors" really are?
Avaroha: E a c h Fk(t) refers to the radioactive particle and can be repre
sented as a wave propagating through three-dimensional space. Since
Ψ(t) and the X k (t)'s refer to very complicated systems involving vast
numbers of particles, they cannot be represented in such a readily visu-
alizable form. We will assume that the X k (t)'s are solutions of the
Schr dinger equation for System I I , considered by itself. With this as
sumption you can think of the Xk(t)'s as q u a n t u m mechanical histories
of what will h a p p e n in the system in the absence of the radioactive par
ticle. Likewise, you can think of Ψ(t) as a history depicting what will
happen if the particle is present.
Yantry: Could you explain this in m o r e specific terms?
Avaroha: Yes. Consider this example: Suppose that System II consists of n
molecules of gas located at fixed positions in the cloud c h a m b e r . 1 3 You
can think of these molecules as potential targets for the radioactive
particle. T h e following drawing shows how you might visualize this
situation in terms of classical physical concepts. [See Figure 3.] H e r e
the particle is depicted as a small sphere that has emerged from the
What Quantum Mechanics is Really Saying 57
Figure 3. The process of radioactive decay as it might be visualized from the view-
point of classical physics.
possible X (t)'s, one for each possible arrangement of executed and un-
k
excited states of the n atoms. In this setting the behavior of the total
system of target atoms plus "particle" can be depicted us shown in
Figure 4. Here nine target atoms are shown in the smile positions as in
Figure 4. Part of the state vector for a system of nine target atoms and a radioactive
nucleus. Each target atom can be in an excited state (e) or an unexcited state (u).
The state vector is represented by waves F , F , F , .......,F , corresponding to
0 1 2 511
the 512 possible combinations of excited and unexcited states of the nine atoms.
Each box depicts a combination of excited and unexcited states, and the corre-
sponding wave. These waves can " f l o w " from one box to another if the two boxes
differ in the state of excitation of one atom, and the waves and atoms are lined up
properly. (For mathematical details see Note 24.)
What Quantum Mechanics is Really Saying 59
Figure 3. The circles marked with eor u represent the nine atoms, and
9
four of the 2 =512 possible patterns of excitation are shown.
Corresponding to each X (t), or pattern of excitation, there is an
k
F (t) flows radially out of the radioactive nucleus, and is similar to the
0
the figure. The general principle is that F can generate a wave F if the i j
atom, and this atom lies in the path of F . The figure shows how the F- i
waves, by propagating in this way, can start from X (t), where there 0
are no excited atoms, and eventually reach X (t), where there is a line 3
straight line from the nucleus, and X corresponds to the same chain j
with one additional excited atom at the end, then the F-waves can pass
from X to X if this atom is lined up with the chain. Otherwise they
i j
Yantry: This seems very obscure. Why, if we are dealing with one radio-
active particle, are you considering many different F-waves propagat-
ing through three-dimensional space? Do your successive waves F , 0
of the chain of excited atoms? Also, out of all possible straight chains
of atoms extending from the nucleus, how is it determined which one
will be traversed by these waves?
Avaroha: It is actually incorrect to think of the F-waves as real phenomena
occurring in three-dimensional space. Rather, each F is an abstract k
Avaroha: Are you trying to say that the cloud chamber must be described
in terms of classical physics?
Kutark: Yes. Niels Bohr pointed out that the quantum theory is meaning-
less unless it can be translated into the language of classical physics,
15
which we use to describe our observations of the w o r l d . Therefore,
in the quantum mechanical process of measurement, we must change
from the quantum mechanical to the classical mode of description at
some point. In this case it is natural to do this at the point where the ion
trails, which we describe quantum mechanically, give rise to visible
vapor trails within the cloud chamber.
Avaroha: Is classical physics capable of giving an adequate account of the
structure of matter?
Kutark: No. As you well know, the quantum theory was developed be-
cause classical physics could not successfully describe the atomic
constituents of matter.
Avaroha: Are you saying, then, that it is not possible for us to give an
16
adequate description of the cloud chamber?
Kutark: Not necessarily. We could describe the cloud chamber by means
of quantum mechanics and revert to classical physics at another point
in the process of observation. For example, we could do this at the
point where light reflecting from the cloud chamber was focused on the
retina of the observer's eye. John von Neumann pointed out that the
boundary between the observer and the observed system can be arbi-
trarily shifted, with everything on the observed side being completely
17
describable by quantum mechanics.
62 Dialogue on Consciousness and the Quantum
Avaroha: This procedure leaves the conscious observer on the side of the
boundary where phenomena are to be described in terms of in
adequate classical concepts. If you a r e truly forced to divide the world
into two parts in this way, then it would seem that the quantum theory
is incapable of adequately describing the observer. F u r t h e r m o r e , since
your boundary singles out one potential observer for unique treat
ment, you seem to be introducing an element of solipsism into your
theory. If the quantum theory simply describes one individual's sub
jective impressions of the part of the world external to h i m , 1 8 then it
can provide neither a complete description of reality nor an adequate
account of consciousness.
Kutark: Actually, the observer is irrelevant. Once the observer is brought
into the picture the impression is created that a subjective element has
been introduced into physics. This simply entangles us in muddled
thinking! To maintain scientific objectivity we should exclude all con
scious observers from the physical system and define the measuring!
process in terms of some automatic recording device describable in
terms of familiar, classical physical c o n c e p t s . 1 9
Avaroha: What do we do if we want to give a theoretical account of the ac
tual human observer of our cloud chamber? Are you saying this can't
be d o n e ?
Kutark: Of course it can be d o n e . You can use one comprehensive state
vector to describe the cloud chamber, the human observer, and as
much of his environment as you may wish to include. We should simply
keep in mind that the state vector must be interpreted as an objective
description of physical reality.
Avaroha: Very well, then, let's try to do this. Why don't we adopt our pre
vious notation to this enlarged system? We can refer to the enlarged
system as System I, and let Ψ(t) designate its state vector. Similarly,
we can define System II as the enlarged system minus the radioactive
particle. T h e F k (t)'s and Xk(t)'s can then be defined as before.
If we adopt these conventions, we can view the X k (t)'s as possible
histories of the total system minus the radioactive particle. Most of
these histories will presumably represent matter in various chaotic
states. But if quantum mechanics can actually describe System II
adequately, then some of these histories must represent the formation
of a vapor trail in the cloud chamber, followed by the perception of this
trail by the observer.
Kutark: Yes. For each possible track in the cloud chamber there will be an
X k that represents the formation of that track through condensation.
Threading the Labyrinth of Quantum Epistemology 63
Figure 5. The state vector for the total system, including the human observer. The
five images correspond to five situations of the observer, involving distinct experi
ences and perceptions. The state vector gives nearly equal representation to many
such situations.
(.4 Dialogue on Consciousness and the Quantum
Kutark: We deal with this situation by employing what is known as the "re
duction of the wave function." Essentially, I have already described
this procedure. At the time of observation the state vector Ψ(t) is
replaced by one of its unambiguous components, Fk(t)Xk(t), with a
probability of (Fk(t),Fk(t)). We can also express this by saying that at
the time of observation, Ψ(t) is replaced by the statistical mixture of
states.
state vector Ψ(t) for our total system does not single out any particular
time of occurrence for the event of radioactive decay. Rather, W(t)
is a superposition of Fk(t)Xk(t)'s, representing all possible times of
observation for the track.
The structure of W(t) in this situation is rather interesting. As we
know, each Xk(t) can be thought of as a possible history of events in
System I I . In Ψ(t) each Xk(t) is present to a degree determined by the
magnitude of its coefficient, Fk(t). If Fk(t) is zero, then we can assume
that Xk(t) is not represented in Ψ(t).
I can show by a diagram how a history representing the observation
of a track becomes represented in W(t). [See Figure 6.] Here the his
tory X 0 represents what happens in System II when there is no ion trail
Figure 6. This diagram shows how a history Xn, representing the observation of a
particular track, is added to the total state vector. This is a process involving a
number of intermediate histories, Xk1,Xk2, . . . ,Xkm, that represent the observa
tion of partial tracks of greater and greater length. Here each history is indicated by
a line, and the line is made thicker during the period when that history is repre
sented in the total wave function. Vertical distance between histories designates
similarity, and we can see that a history can be added to the total state vector only at
a time when it is very similar to another history that is already represented there.
Threading the Labyrinth of Quantum Epistemology 67
a=vt, where v is the wheel's angular velocity, and we assume that a=0
when the time t is zero.
Now, in physics we cannot define v with perfect accuracy, and due to
the influence of the environment, v will always fluctuate slightly. As
time passes, however, this uncertainty in the definition of v will result
in a large cumulative uncertainty in a. Therefore, it will be necessary to
repeatedly redefine a. Isn't this situation very similar to the one you
are describing? 25
Avaroha: It is different in a very significant way. In your wheel example,
the repeated reduction or redefinition is necessary because our infor
mation about the physical system is incomplete. In the quantum
mechanical situation, this information is supposed to be completely
specified by the state vector, Ψ(t). The very point I've been trying to
make, of course, is that the state vector does not, in fact, provide a
complete description of the system.
X„ X„
x„ x„
Figure 7. The total state vector. Within any small interval of time, many histories
(Xn1"„,, Xn2, Xn3 . . . ) representing different experiences of the observer are added
to^(/). "
70 Dialogue on Consciousness and the Quantum
terms in the state vector may be very small. The same thing can be
said of the sequence of subsystems you will no doubt want to construct
by isolating successive particles one at a time. The state vector of any
subsystem may exhibit macroscopic ambiguities.
Avaroha: Doesn't this mean that we cannot associate the unique conscious
experiences of the observer with any subsystem of the total system,
including the man's brain or any part of it? Unless we do perform the
operation of reduction, we are likely to meet ambiguities in any sub-
system that contradict the specificity of conscious experience. It does
not help us very much to simply maintain that whenever we speak
of one of these subsystems, we cannot attribute reality to any of its
sub-subsystems.
Kutark: A l l I can really say here is that we have simply become mired in
useless hair splitting. Since science has to be practical, the best thing to
do is revert to a classical or semi-classical description of the system at
30
some p o i n t .
Yantry: I'm relieved to hear you say that Kutark! This entire discussion of
quantum physics seems very bizarre and unreal to me. In biology and
chemistry we have solid, three-dimensional molecular models that are
as real as your bedroom furniture! We also have practical, compre-
hensible mathematical schemes, such as systems of reaction-diffusion
equations, that describe the behavior of these models. Certainly this
represents the soundest approach to the study of living systems.
Kutark: Yet these mathematical systems can be only approximations at
best. I'm afraid the point will be made that our scientific picture of life
is incomplete if we are forced to resort to such approximations.
3 . 4 A D i s c u s s i o n of Contrasting World V i e w s
(Dr. Sophus Baum and Dr. Francesco Shunya have been listen-
ing for some time, and at this point they join the conversation.)
Baum: I would like to point out that in the midst of all these complicated
deliberations, you have overlooked what is at the same time the
simplest and grandest interpretation of quantum mechanics. In this in-
terpretation we completely reject all ad hoc schemes that attempt to
adjust the state vector in a nonphysical way so as to bring it into line
with our narrow, preconceived views of what reality should be.
Rather, we accept the state vector as a complete description of reality
as it is, with all the staggering implications this entails. Reality consists
of an infinite system of bifurcating, noncommunicating universal
A Discussion of Contrasting World Views 73
premāñjana-cchurita-bhakti-vilocanena
santah sadaiva hrdayesu vilokayanti
yam śyāma-sundaram acintya-guna-svarūpam
govindam adi-purusam tarn aham bhajāmi
"I worship Govinda, the primeval L o r d , Who is Śyāmasundara, Krsna
Himself with inconceivable innumerable attributes, Whom the pure
devotees see in their heart of hearts with the eye of devotion tinged
with the salve of love. " 4 3 Of course, we can attain full understanding of
what this description entails only by direct experience, just as we can
< understand the taste of a fruit only by actually eating it.
Baum: It seems that you are simply expounding a religious doctrine here.
How can you seriously introduce such ideas into a scientific discussion?
From the viewpoint of science, such ideas are simply fantastic and un-
verifiable. You can hold them only by taking a blind leap of faith. To
proselytize these doctrines in the guise of science is reprehensible!
Avaroha: It is ironic that you should say this after advocating the multiple
' splitting universe theory, which is indeed unverifiable. In contrast, di
rect verifiability is the whole point of the approach to higher conscious
ness that I have been outlining. It is certainly true that you cannot
' prove the existence of God on the basis of reasoning and a few pieces of
' empirical data—at least, you cannot prove"anything very interesting
about God in this way. But if God is real and the conscious self is en
dowed with suitable innate capacities, then we should be able to know ,
God directly.
Unfortunately, some scientists have unnecessarily ruled out the very
possibility of doing this by propounding universal theories that leave
no room for the conscious self, what to speak of anything higher. By
extrapolating empirical findings beyond all justifiable bounds, they ar
rive at world views that are truly fantastic and unverifiable. Con
templating such views, they come to the inevitable conclusion that "the
A Discussion of Contrasting World Views 81
Notes
15. J a m m e r , p p . 100-101.
18. H e i s e n b e r g , " T h e R e p r e s e n t a t i o n of N a t u r e in C o n t e m p o r a r y
Physics," p p . 99-100.
20. von N e u m a n n , c h a p . V.
from zero. For any given pair of histories this could happen at most
for a brief m o m e n t , and the histories would be expected to diverge
from one another at earlier and later times. Thus weight within the
total state vector will be transferred from one history to another at
times depending on the structure of the histories themselves. This
would result in the development of a total state vector of the form
shown in Figures 4, 6, and 7.
29. J a m m e r , chap. 8.
30. H a n s Bethe (personal communication) has pointed out that due to the
problems involved with the reduction of the wave function, it does not
m a k e sense to try to devise a q u a n t u m mechanical description of living
organisms. He recommends an empirical, semiclassical approach.
3 1 . Dewitt, p p . 3 0 - 3 5 .
32. Dewitt, " Q u a n t u m Gravity: the New Synthesis," p. 744.
33. Nagel, The Structure of Science, chap. 6.
34. von N e u m a n n , chap. VI.
Notes 85
Karl Popper
On the
Mind-Body Problem
A Review
In The Self and Its Brain, the well-known philosopher Karl Popper and
the eminent neurophysiologist John Eccles have collaborated to develop a
theory of mind-brain interaction. Their book contains three sections. In
the first section Karl Popper does two things: he presents a philosophical
analysis of the mind-body problem, and he outlines a basic conceptual
framework for an understanding of the mind as an entity that is distinct
from the brain but that interacts with it. In the second section John Eccles
surveys our current knowledge of the anatomy and function of the brain
and introduces a specific model for the process of mind-brain interaction.
The third section consists of a series of dialogues between the two authors,
in which they explore some of the strengths and shortcomings of their
ideas.
In this review we discuss Popper's analysis of the mind-body problem. In
his portion of The Self and Its Brain, Popper discusses two basic subject
matters: the nature of mind, and the mind's temporal origin. His aim is to
establish that the fundamental features of personality, such as conscious-
ness, thought, emotion, and purposeful action, are not simply patterns of
chemical interaction (as much current scientific and philosophical thinking
would have it) but rather aspects of a real yet nonphysical entity called the
mind. In Popper's view, the mind should be considered neither an aspect
nor a byproduct of physical processes. Instead, it should be regarded as an
independent entity that influences the physical processes of the brain and
that is influenced by them in turn.
While propounding this bold thesis, Popper simultaneously tries very
hard to show how mind can be understood to have originated in a world of
matter governed solely by physical laws. He does this by elaborating a
theory of emergent evolution, which holds that entirely new and unpre-
dictable qualities, processes, and laws can "emerge" spontaneously in na-
ture and thereby completely transform the character of reality. Although
87
88 Karl Popper on the Mind-body Problem
the idea of emergent evolution is not new, Popper has developed it in great
detail and has made it the cornerstone of his philosophy of mind.
Popper maintains that at one time the universe consisted solely of matter
interacting with itself according to laws similar to or identical with those
studied by the physicists. At this time nothing resembling mind or con-
sciousness existed. Then, as matter gradually coalesced into various combi-
nations by purely physical processes, totally new entities appeared and
began to interact with matter in novel yet lawful ways. Thus life emerged,
then dimly conscious animal minds, and finally fully self-conscious human
minds.
Popper holds that the mind is an emergent entity "utterly different from
anything which, to our knowledge, has previously existed in the w o r l d "
(page 553). He has indeed presented a good case for the view that the mind
is real, that it is independent of the brain, and that its properties are com-
pletely different from those of matter (as understood by the chemists and
physicists). However, in his attempt to reconcile this view with the theory
of evolution, he has shown only that evolutionary theory is unable to ac-
count for the origin of the mind. Although Popper has distorted the stan-
dard neo-Darwinian theory of evolution almost beyond recognition, his
system of emergent evolution contributes nothing to our understanding. In
fact, it raises more questions than it answers.
In the end Popper admits his failure: "Now I want to emphasize how
little is said by saying that the mind is an emergent product of the brain.
It has practically no explanatory value, and it hardly amounts to more than
putting a question mark at a certain place in human evolution" (page 554).
After giving a short account of Popper's arguments for the nonmaterial na-
ture of mind, we will show that emergent evolution is, in fact, logically un-
tenable. Then, salvaging some of the good points of Popper's presentation,
we will consider an alternative approach to understanding the nature of the
mind.
One of Popper's most basic arguments for the nonphysical nature of the
mind is that, contrary to the opinions of the behaviorists, conscious subjec-
tive experience is both real and completely unexplained by our concepts of
matter. The existence of conscious awareness is directly experienced by the
conscious self, and this by itself refutes radical materialism, the view that
matter (as understood by modern physics and chemistry) is all that exists.
Popper also points out that living beings, and especially human beings,
exhibit behavior that cannot be reasonably explained in material terms, but
that can be understood very clearly in terms of the actions of mind. For ex-
ample, it certainly seems very remarkable that a lump of matter in the form
Karl Popper on the Mind-Body Problem 89
of a human being should detach itself from its substrate and, say, climb up
the side of Mount Everest. Although one could dabble with explanations
for this phenomenon in terms of cybernetic brain mechanisms, it is very
hard to see in purely physical terms how or why such mechanisms should
ever have come to be. In general, it is hard to explain long-term and elabo-
rately purposeful action—from the building of nests, to the construction of
skyscrapers, to the formulation of philosophical theories—in terms of
intermolecular forces. Yet we can systematically explain these things in
terms of a mind endowed with purpose and desire.
Popper argues that morality and concepts of good and evil cannot be un-
derstood in purely physical terms. We cannot adequately explain these
manifestations by totally denying the existence of consciousness. We also
cannot explain them by any theory that grants the existence of conscious-
ness, but maintains that it cannot influence matter and that matter behaves
entirely in accordance with known physical laws. (There is a wide range of
such theories, including parallelism, the panpsychism of Spinoza, epiphe-
nomenalism, and the identity theory.) Popper holds that the existence of
standards of moral behavior requires a nonphysical mind that can influence
matter.
The same nonphysical mind is necessary to explain our standards of aes-
thetics. In Popper's words, "To assume that Michelangelo's works are sim-
ply the result of molecular movements and nothing else seems to me very
much more absurd than the assumption of some slight . . . violation of the
first law of thermodynamics" (page 544). He also argues that it is only in
terms of the actions of the mind that we can understand—or even talk
about—truth, falsehood, and validity in language. In purely physical terms
these concepts refer to arbitrary patterns of symbol manipulation, and they
play no essential or meaningful role. They can be meaningfully discussed
only in the context of a reality higher than that of material interactions.
Popper further points out that the mind and its attributes play an explana-
tory role in psychology analogous to the explanatory role electrons play in
physics (although there is, of course, no corresponding mathematical de-
velopment in psychology). Thus it is as reasonable to attribute reality to the
mind as it is to attribute it to electrons. We may add in this connection that
behavioral psychology has provided us with remarkably little insight into
the nature of human behavior, its avowed subject. We might suggest that
psychology will make significant progress only by developing an adequate
understanding of the mind as a real entity.
In refuting the theories based on the idea that consciousness exists but
does not influence the behavior of matter, Popper points out that these
90 Karl Popper on the Mind-Body Problem
theories conflict with the Darwinian theory of evolution, for they do not
provide a means whereby natural selection can act to bring about the evolu-
tion of consciousness. Thus the strict Darwinist must either deny the reality
of consciousness or attribute full consciousness to inanimate matter. Other-
wise he must explain why consciousness should develop progressively with-
out the aid of natural selection. This argument should be of interest to the
orthodox adherents of neo-Darwinian evolutionary theory. As we shall
see, Popper himself proposes a very different theory of evolution.
Popper also confronts the challenge that since the known laws of physics
cannot be violated, a nonphysical mind must be ruled out. His main point
here is that the program of reductionism in physics and chemistry is drasti-
cally incomplete. Because of difficulties in computation, we simply do not
know what the quantum theory says about most chemical processes. Also,
there have been many revolutionary developments in physics in this
century, and we may confidently expect more.
Adding a final point, Popper warns of the danger of cutting off healthy
inquiry by prematurely imposing a rigid view based on known physical
principles. In philosophy, this warning applies to the indiscriminate appli-
cation of'Occam's razor as a means of ruling out hypotheses. Popper also
condemns what he calls "promissory materialism," or the argument that
materialistic claims should be accepted because proof for them will surely
be found some time in the future.
Thus Popper gives many arguments indicating that mind must involve a
higher reality—a reality that cannot be reduced to matter as it is under-
stood by modern science. However, when he tries to account for the origin
of this higher reality by means of his theory of emergent evolution, he sticks
essentially to the reductionistic approach, and he is unable to avoid its
shortcomings. We will now briefly outline the theory of emergent evolution
and indicate why this is so.
First we shall consider Popper's concept of "downward causation."
According to this idea, when many parts combine to make a whole, the
whole is an entity in and of itself, and it is capable of acting on each of its
parts individually. The formation of heavy nuclei in the center of a star by
the action of intense heat and pressure is regarded as an example of down-
ward causation, in which the whole star acts on its individual constituent
particles.
This concept amounts to a deceptive way of introducing higher entities
into the material picture without really introducing them. A physicist
would immediately reply that the behavior of the star can be fully explained
(in principle) in terms of the material interaction of its component parts,
without any reference at all to the star as a whole. Thus the concept of
Karl Popper on the Mind-Body Problem 91
laws L' can be expressed by formulas, and thus L can also be represented
mathematically. But what can we say about the meta-law L in Popper's
system, where mental properties may emerge that are qualitatively differ-
ent from anything contemplated in present-day physics? Certainly this
meta-law would also have to be qualitatively different from any of the laws
known to physical science. Indeed, if anything, it would have to possess
qualities even more remarkable than those of the various possible entities
that may emerge under its regulation.
Now, if the meta-law L is not itself an emergent entity, it must represent
a permanent state of affairs, and its qualities must correspond to absolute
Karl Popper on the Mind-Body Problem 93
of the role of the self in the context of a higher, meaningful reality could
lead to practical realization of our true potentialities as conscious beings—
potentialities that presently lie dormant and unexplored.
Popper tends to speak of the self in rather vague reductionistic terms as
some kind of pattern of interaction between the mind and the body. Yet he
also sometimes refers to the self as a real entity. In one passage he says that
"the talk about a substantial self is not a bad metaphor" (page 146), and he
proposes that "selves are the only active agents in the universe: the only
agents to whom the term activity can be applied" (page 538). This is really
Popper's best bet, and one wishes he had the boldness to follow his idea
where it leads and straightforwardly consider the self as a fundamental
entity in its own right.
On the basis of such a hypothesis, a direct investigation of the self as such
is at least a formal possibility. We suggest that only an investigation of this
kind can yield satisfying answers to the basic questions that gave rise to The
Self and Its Brain in the first place. As Eccles points out in one of the
dialogues, " M a n has lost his way these days . . . He needs some new mes-
sage whereby he may live with hope and meaning. I think that science has
gone too far in breaking down man's belief in his spiritual greatness and in
giving him the idea that he is merely an insignificant material being in the
frigid cosmic immensity" (page 558). If we can candidly consider that the
self may be a real, conscious entity in a world with inherent meaning and
purpose, we may hope to come to a practical and coherent world view that
does violence neither to reason nor to our natural spiritual aspirations.
Notes
1. A simple Markov chain is used in this example, but the same argument
could be framed using the more sophisticated laws studied in physics.
2. There are many different ways of formulating such a meta-law. The
basic point is that the meta-law must govern the emergence of certain
"novel" properties, and thus it must be able to deal with these proper-
ties. A law defined in the customary language of physics could not gov-
ern the emergence of consciousness, since consciousness belongs to a
category lying outside the scope of this language. If we suppose that
there are laws of nature governing the emergence of consciousness,
then we must conclude that nature has inherent features falling outside
the realm of discourse of physics. The simplest hypothesis about such
features is, of course, that consciousness itself is an inherent feature of
reality, and not an emergent property.
Chapter 5
Information Theory
And the
Self - organization
Of Matter
In this chapter we use information theory to show that the laws of nature,
as understood by modern science, are insufficient to account for the ori-
gin of life. The basic argument is the following: The laws of nature and
the corresponding mathematical models of physical reality can all be de-
scribed by a few simple equations and other mathematical expressions.
This means that they possess a low information content. In contrast, there
is good reason to suppose that the intricate and variegated forms of living
organisms possess a high information content. It can be shown that con-
figurations of high information content cannot arise with substantial proba-
bilities in models defined by mathematical expressions of low information
content. It follows that life could not arise by the action of natural laws of
the kind considered in modern science.
This argument bypasses the proposition made by many evolutionary
theorists that even though the steps leading to life are improbable, they are
nonetheless likely to happen, given the immense spans of geological time
available. We show that no period of time, from zero to billions of billions
of years, will suffice to render probable the evolution of life from matter by
known physical processes. Indeed, we show that over periods many times
the estimated 4.5-billion-year age of the earth, the probability of the evolu-
- 1 5 0 , 0 0 0
tion of higher life forms remains bounded by upper limits of 1 0 , an al-
most infinitesimal number. This implies that the entire history of the earth
1 5 0 , 0 0 0
would have to be repeated over and over again at least 1 0 times for
there to be a substantial chance that higher living entities would evolve
even once.
At the basis of these figures lies an intuitive reason for the impossibility
of organic evolution. We show that the process of natural selection—the al-
leged mechanism of evolution—must have specific direction if it is to bring
about the development of complex living organisms. Without such direc-
tion, this process is unable to discriminate among random events
(mutations) in such a way as to bring complex order out of chaos. For this
98 Information Theory and the Self-organization of Matter
reason, the standard argument that evolution will occur, given long enough
time spans, is false. Natural selection will lack direction if the causal prin-
ciples underlying this selection, namely the laws of nature, do not have
sufficient information content to specify such direction.
Our fundamental argument is that in a physical system governed by sim-
ple laws, any information present in the system after transformations cor-
responding to the passage of time must have been built into the system in
the first place. Random events cannot give rise to definite information,
even when processed over long periods of time according to simple laws. It
follows that mathematical models based on simple laws cannot account for
the origin of such highly variegated and complex entities as living organ-
isms. Using such models, we can only explain the existence of complex
order here and now by postulating that equivalent complex order was pres-
ent at an earlier time, or was transported into the system from the outside.
These postulates do not account for the origin of such order, but simply
confront us with either an infinite regress or an eternal source of order
containing the information necessary to specify all life forms.
These arguments suggest that the scientific program of describing the
world by mathematical models is severely limited, and can serve only to im-
pede our understanding of nature. This program is based on the conviction
that the simple regularities observed by physicists and chemists in experi-
ments with inanimate matter will suffice to account for every phenomenon
in the world. But since we show here that this program cannot succeed in
accounting for the origin of life, we suggest that a different approach
should be explored. The direct implication of the information theoretic
analysis is that nature is inherently complex, and encodes the designs of liv-
ing organisms—both lower and higher—in some form. Although this in it-
self does not tell us very much, we suggest that it may be fruitful to consider
the possibility that life is built into nature as a fundamental principle, and
represents more than simply a temporary collocation of material elements.
The program of science during the last two or three hundred years has
been to reduce life to matter and to deny the existence of any higher life-
principle transcendental to matter. In this program, the idea that matter is
both simple and conceivable has been essential. But if, as shown here, we
must attribute all the characteristic features of life to matter in order to ex-
plain the origin of life from matter, then we can conclude that this program
has failed.
One way of responding to this failure is to consider the universe as a
whole to be an incomprehensible welter of arbitrary complexities. A more
promising response is to consider that if the natural causes underlying life
must entail all the detailed features of life, then perhaps life—and intel-
The Theme of Simplicity in the Theories of Physics 99
widely believe that a complete physical theory has been established for
phenomena involving moderate masses, energies, and velocities. In par-
ticular, scientists generally believe that the nonrelativistic theory of quan-
tum mechanics is sufficient to account for all the phenomena of chemistry,
and that all the phenomena of life can be reduced to chemistry. (Nonethe-
less, some long-standing controversies about the validity of quantum
mechanics remain unresolved. These were discussed in Chapter 3 . )
According to the physicist John Slater, "The success of exact calculations
for the helium atom and the hydrogen molecule convinced physicists that
wave mechanics provided a framework which was at least in principle capa-
ble of giving theoretical explanations of any desired accuracy for the phe-
3
nomena of atoms, molecules and solids." The idea that life, in turn, is a
molecular phenomenon is summed up by the molecular biologist James
Watson: "We see not only that the laws of chemistry are sufficient for un-
derstanding protein structure, but also that they are consistent with all
known hereditary phenomena. Complete certainty now exists among
essentially all biochemists that the other characteristics of living organisms
(for example, . . . the hearing and memory processes) will all be com-
pletely understood in terms of the coordinative interactions of small and
4
large molecules." Taken together, these statements of Slater and Watson
imply the widely accepted conclusion that life is a quantum mechanical
phenomenon.
The laws of quantum mechanics must be very remarkable if all the char-
acteristics of living beings do indeed depend on them. We will therefore
briefly outline the mathematical structure of the quantum mechanical laws.
Our objective is twofold: first, to clearly define what we mean by simplicity
in a system of natural laws; and second, to clarify the nature of the
hypothetical relationship between the quantum mechanical laws and the
phenomena of life.
First, let us consider the laws of nature in classical physics. These can be
summed up by the following equations:
terial particles, and equations (1) and (2) describe how these numbers
change with the passage of time. In classical physics the function H, which
is called the Hamiltonian, is generally given by a simple formula:
We have written these formulas out in full to show how very simple the laws
of classical physics are. This is quite literally the full extent of the laws of na-
ture as understood in classical physics up to the time of Maxwell. Accord-
ing to those scientists who adhered to the philosophy that nature could be
completely described by mathematical laws, all the phenomena of nature
could be calculated using equations (1) through (5) and initial values of the
q 's and p 's at some arbitrary starting time, t = 0 .
j j
Here the state, or exact physical description, of the physical system is given
by the Hilbert space vector, which can be represented in various ways as
a mathematical function or as a sequence of numbers. The Hamiltonian
function, H, has been adopted from classical physics and now appears as an
operator capable of acting on to produce a new vector. In analogy with
equation (3), H could be given by:
from the earth (volcanic venting), and to radiate heat and light into outer
space. This sums up the initial and boundary conditions for this model.
As another model, one could start with the supposed origin of the solar
system from a cloud of gas. The initial conditions would then consist of a
description of the initial gas cloud, and the boundary would correspond to
an unlimited vacuum surrounding this cloud (if we ignore the influence of
distant stars). In this model the laws of nature would first generate the solar
system, complete with primordial soup, and then generate life in the soup.
Or one might consider a model of the universe as a whole, such as that pro-
posed by the "big bang" theory. Most versions of this theory feature a
superhot soup of subatomic particles as the initial condition of the uni-
verse. (Of course, there are no boundary conditions in a universal model.)
We should observe that the quantum mechanical laws of Figure 1 are not
adequate for the last two of these three models. Since the second model in-
cludes the sun, it must deal with nuclear reactions, and these are not de-
scribed by nonrelativistic quantum mechanics. This model would require
some form of quantum field theory. Likewise, the third model calls for a
theory combining quantum mechanics and general relativity. It will not be
possible to precisely define these models until substantial advances are
made in theoretical physics. Yet it is interesting to note that the existing
equations of quantum field theory are much more streamlined and elegant
than the nonrelativistic equations of Figure 1. Since the general program of
physics is to explain nature in terms of the simplest possible principles, we
can anticipate that physicists will exert every effort to devise universal
equations of motion that are even simpler in form than the quantum field
equations.
We should also observe that the initial and boundary conditions of the
three models are quite simple to describe and that they become progres-
sively simpler as we go from model to model. The basic idea behind current
scientific theories of the origin of life from matter is that one need propose
only a very simple set of conditions to hold in the beginning. After all, the
purpose of such theories is to "explain" all the features of life, and the more
intricate the specifications required for the initial conditions, the less com-
plete the explanation becomes. Many scientists would feel a need to ex-
plain complex initial conditions in terms of some earlier and less complex
state of affairs.
In this regard it is interesting to consider in greater detail the initial con-
ditions that scientists have proposed for the big bang theory. One of the
basic requirements of this theory is that it should account for the distri-
bution of matter in the universe into galaxies and clusters of galaxies. Yet
scientists have noted that an initial superhot plasma will tend not to give
The Theme of Simplicity in the Theories of Physics 107
po = K -l
exp(-H/kT) (8)
11
where H is a Hamiltonian operator.
In this equation, p is called a density matrix. It corresponds to a col-
0
can be done, for example, for cosmic rays or the influx of solar radiation.
Boundary conditions, like initial conditions, must be relatively simple: if
intricate specifications were required for the boundary conditions, then
one would need to explain their origin also.
Once the initial and boundary conditions are defined, the state of the
physical system at each time t between 0 and t can be calculated using the
1
From p we can (at least in principle) calculate the probability, M(X), that
any particular molecule described by a code, X, can be found somewhere in
the system at time t :
x
fairly large, X can be expected to have evolved, but if it is very small the
evolution of X is unlikely.
According to our formal definition of information content, the informa-
tion content, L ( M ) , of the function M is equal to the length of the shortest
computer program that will calculate this function. This length is no greater
than the total length of the programming for all the various calculations we
have just described, and it should correspond to about three or four pages
of tightly packed programming instructions for a model based on an initial
primordial soup evolving in the presence of solar radiation by the laws
given in Figure 1. (We can envision this program as being written in a pro-
gramming language that provides for handling numbers with an arbitrary
number of significant digits. This language and the estimation of L ( M ) are
discussed in Appendix 2.)
We shall see in Section 5.3 that M(X) must be exceedingly small if
L(X), the information content of X, is very much greater than the informa-
tion content of M. The difference between the information in X and that
supplied by the system (represented by L(M)) must be made up by pure
chance, and therefore the probability of X goes down exponentially with
this difference. Thus the evolution of life forms in such a system is extremely
unlikely, for it can be argued that the length of the shortest program
needed to calculate the essential molecular structures of even a "primitive"
living organism should be a great deal longer than three or four pages. This
argument is discussed in detail in the next section.
We should note the ways in which "chance" enters into the function
M(X) for the probability of finding X in the system. There is an element of
randomness in the thermodynamic ensembles defining the initial condi-
tions and the boundary conditions. This is one source of randomness for
the "random" mutations of the theory of evolution, which are supposed to
be due to chance molecular collisions and bombardment by cosmic rays.
Also, randomness is built into the basic structure of quantum mechanics,
since the quantum mechanical states are essentially statistical in nature.
Thus the random mutations of the theory of evolution are automatically
built into our physical models. As we have pointed out before, natural
selection is also implicit in these models, for it is not an independent prin-
ciple, but must simply be a consequence of the underlying natural laws.
As a final point, we would like to mention another class of models that
exhibit the processes of mutation and natural selection involved in the
theory of evolution. These are the cellular automaton models pioneered by
12
John von Neumann. In these models an elemental finite-state automaton
is placed on each square of a large two-dimensional lattice. The state of the
system is given by specifying the states of all the automatons in the lattice.
The system changes in the following way with the passage of time: Let t be
a small, fixed time interval. At the end of each successive interval f, each
automaton changes to a new state in a way which depends only on the states
of the automatons occupying the immediately adjacent squares.
By properly adjusting the states of the automatons in a region of the lat-
tice, one can create an "organism" that functions through the interaction of
the automatons in its constituent cells. Von Neumann has shown that a self-
reproducing organism capable of exhibiting complex behavior (a universal
Turing machine) can be constructed in his cellular automaton model. His
idea was to prove that mechanical systems can exhibit the property of self-
reproduction characteristic of living organisms. This was intended as one
further step in the demonstration that life is a mechanical process governed
by mathematical laws.
It is therefore interesting to inquire whether self-reproducing "organ-
isms" of the kind von Neumann considered could evolve in his cellular
automaton system in a reasonable length of time. The system's law of trans-
formation with time should determine the natural selection of various forms
of organisms through the same sort of competitive processes envisioned in
ordinary evolutionary theory. The random mutations of evolutionary
theory could easily be introduced through a Markov process, which would
make random changes in the states of the elemental automatons.
One can imagine a scenario in which primitive self-reproducing organ-
The Great Complexity of Biological Form 111
Most of these macromolecules are not being actively studied, since their
overwhelming complexity has forced chemists to concentrate on relatively,
few of them. Thus we must immediately admit that the structure of a cell will,
never be understood in the same way as that of water or glucose molecules.
Not only will the exact structures of most macromolecules remain unsolved,
14
but their relative locations within cells can be only vaguely known.
information are required to specify the member, given that the structure
of the list is known. (A bit is a binary digit of 0 or 1.) This comes to about
300 log 20= 1,297 bits for a typical protein molecule in an E. coli cell. Since
2
an E. coli cell. (In this section we carry out all calculations to several deci-
mal places, and then round off all numbers cited in the text to a few signifi-
cant figures.)
Yet the E. coli bacterium is a very simple organism. In the cells of higher
plants and animals, much larger amounts of D N A are found than in E. coli.
It is estimated that mammalian cells contain some 800 times as much D N A ,
9
yielding an upper limit of about 4.4 x 10 bits for the genetic information
15
content of these cells. Some idea of the size of these numbers can be ob-
tained by considering the number of pages of print required to write down
The Great Complexity of Biological Form 113
such large amounts of genetic coding in full. In a typical book there are
some 70 characters per line and 40 lines per page. This gives us about
4
1.7 x 10 bits per page if we use an alphabet of 64 characters. (Since
log 64=6, we can use 6 bits to encode each character.) At this rate it would
2
take about 330 pages to write down the coding for E. coli, and about
264,000 pages to write down the coding for a mammalian cell.
One of the dogmas of molecular biology (called the central dogma, in
fact) is that all the information needed to specify a cell is contained in the
cell's D N A coding, and that this coded information is not changed except
by random mutations. Of course, D N A cannot generate a functional cell
out of disorganized components by itself, and cells may therefore contain
structural information that is not coded in D N A . Also, the recent discovery
of reverse transcription shows that information can be transferred to the
16
D N A molecules from other molecules in the c e l l .
Nonetheless, the amount of D N A in cells should give us some idea of the
amount of information needed to adequately describe them. According to
the central dogma, the figures we have derived thus far should provide
upper limits for the essential information content of cells. We would now
like to estimate reasonable lower limits. To do this we shall need to con-
sider the variety and complexity of the structures cells are found to contain.
Since some genes in the chromosomes of higher animals apparently exist in
multiple copies, it would seem that the total genetic information content
for these organisms must be lower than the figures suggested by their total
D N A content. This conclusion is also indicated if, as some biologists have
argued, the chromosomes of higher organisms contain many stretches of
17
random, nonfunctional coding.
Yet based on the great complexity of structure visible under the micro-
scope in vertebrate cells, Watson estimates that such cells must be "at least
20 to 50 times more complex genetically than E. coli." By this he means
18
that such cells should contain coding for at least 20 to 50 times as many
kinds of protein molecules as E. coli. We would need between 6,600 and
16,500 pages to write down this amount of coding, based on our 330-page
8
estimate for E. coli. This corresponds to between 1.1 and 2.8 x 10 bits of
information, and between 84,000 and 210,000 proteins, with an average of
300 amino acid subunits apiece.
To determine a lower limit for the genetic information content of cells,
let us consider how information may be distributed among the protein
molecules of a typical mammalian cell. From the figures we have cited,
the lowest estimate for the number of distinct proteins in such a cell is
2,000 x 20=40,000. A protein of 300 amino acids can be specified by a string
of 1,297 bits, or binary 1's andO's . Since the size of proteins can vary, let us
114 Information Theory and the Self-organization of Matter
assign a string of 10,000 bits for each protein. We shall label these strings
Y , . . . ,Y , where N=40,000, and the strings are listed in numerical
1 N
Figure 3. The structure of the bit string, X, representing the amino acid sequences
for the proteins of a typical mammalian cell.
the formula,
Y n = F(w ,X )
n n-1 (11)
where n runs from 1 to N, and w , , . . . ,w are suitably chosen bit strings.
1 N
(Here we define X =1, so that the formula can be applied when n = l. The
0
ated from w and the Y 's that have been already calculated. Each bit
n k
The w„'s are related to L(X), the total information content of X, by the
following inequality:
Here l(w ) represents the number of bits in the bit string w . This inequal-
n n
The Great Complexity of Biological Form 115
5
Suppose for the sake of argument that L ( X ) 6 x l 0 bits. Inequality
(12) can be rephrased as
5 4
If we substitute 6 x 10 for L(X) and 4 x 10 for N, we find that the aver-
age value of l(w„) is no greater than 16 bits. This means that a typical
block Y„ can be calculated exactly from X using no more than 16 bits of
n-1
information.
Now, Y represents a protein molecule built from an average of 300
n
amino acids, and to directly spell out the amino acid sequence of such a pro-
tein requires some 1,297 bits. It is possible, of course, to specify some se-
quences of 300 amino acids with much less information. For example, if a
protein consists of a pattern of 10 amino acids repeated 30 times, then the
protein can be specified by about 43 bits of information. The amino acid se-
quences of actual proteins do not seem to follow any simple rule, however,
and it is therefore hard to believe that they could be consistently generated '
using such small amounts of information.
We can obtain an intuitive idea about the structural requirements of pro-
teins by considering the roles they play in the metabolism of cells. The
exact way these proteins function is far from being known at the present
lime. But it is known that they are able to behave like small computers.
19
Here is an example taken almost at random from Watson: In E. coli there
occurs a sequence of chemical reactions that convert the compound
threonine into isoleucine in five steps, each of which is catalyzed by a par-
ticular enzyme, or protein macromolecule. The first step in this sequence
can occur only with the aid of the enzyme threonine deaminase. When the
final product, isoleucine, has reached sufficiently high concentrations, it
interacts with the threonine deaminase molecules in such a way that they
no longer catalyze the first reaction of the series. This prevents the manu-
facture of more of the product than the cell needs. We may note that each
enzyme is so structured that it catalyzes only a few specific reactions. While
not affecting the rates of other chemical reactions at all, such biological en-
zymes are known for their ability to cause certain chemical reactions to
occur millions of times faster than they will occur under laboratory condi-
tions in which the enzyme is not present. We may also note that threonine
116 Information Theory and the Self-organization of Matter
zyme using the Y - for the other enzyme plus a small amount of additional
n
1 9
We can even go further and let A designate a string of 4.4 x 10 bits rep-
resenting the complete genetic coding of a higher plant or animal. As we
The Great Complexity of Biological Form 117
20
these pages, then we can again perform our calculations. We find that if
5
L ( Y ) 6 x 1 0 , then the average l(w ) must be less than 4 bits. This implies
n
that, on the average, each successive page of the mammalian genetic cod-
ing introduces no more than 4 bits of new information. In other words, the
typical page Y is given by F(w,X ), where w is an integer between 1 and
n n-1
15, and X n-1 represents the preceding pages. This strongly suggests that
5
L ( X ) > 6 x l 0 f o r this X.
At this point the objection might be raised that while A"must indeed have
a high information content, most of this information may well consist of
insignificant nonsense. One reason for supposing this is that molecular
biologists have discovered in the cells of higher organisms sections of D N A
coding that serve no obvious purpose. These sections of coding can pre-
sumably change freely under the influence of mutations, and thus they may
be expected to consist largely of random noise.
This objection can be answered by pointing out that while such random
noise may be present, the structural and functional requirements of living
organisms clearly call for large amounts of meaningful information. This
was the basis for our argument that the information content of mammalian
5
proteins must be at least 6 x 10 bits. In addition, biologists generally find
that structures in living organisms have some important function, even
though it may not be immediately obvious what this function is. This
suggests that most of the D N A coding in the cells of higher organisms
should contain some significant information.
We can conclude that our estimates of minimal information content re-
flect the presence of significant information, but that the strings, X, to
which these estimates refer may also contain some irrelevant noise. We
shall therefore introduce the idea of a symbolic description that represents
essential biological information, while omitting irrelevant details. Our
string of protein sequences is an example of such a description, although it
may have the shortcoming of including some insignificant features of pro-
teins. In general, a symbolic description is a bit string that encodes biologi-
cal information, but which does not necessarily correspond directly to the
genetic coding of an organism. Such a description can omit random noise
that may be present in the genome, while at the same time including an
account of important features of the organism.
At the present stage of biological knowledge, it is not possible to define
in detail an adequate symbolic description of a cell. Yet if a symbolic
description could be formulated that extracted only 24 bits of significant
information from each (17,000 bit) page of the mammalian genome, then
118 Information Theory and the Self-organization of Matter
6
the information content of this description would be at least 6 x 10 bits.
To give a further indication of the complexity of living organisms, let us
now describe a number of different categories of organic structure. The
structures in each of these categories could, in principle, be formally repre-
sented by symbolic descriptions that capture their essential features. Since
these structures tend to be highly complex and variegated, we suggest that
their corresponding formal descriptions must have a large information
content.
We shall consider the following hierarchy of structure and function in
living organisms.
(a) The chemical reactions involved in cellular metabolism. These in-
volve respiration, the synthesis of various chemicals needed in the cell from
food molecules, photosynthesis in plants, and the processes involved in the
orderly breakdown of different molecules. It would appear that most of the
genetic coding of E. coli must be devoted to metabolism, since these bacte-
rial cells do very little but grow and divide in half. Even though E. coli is
one of the simplest of organisms, its metabolic interactions are so intricate
that "the exact way in which all these transformations . . . occur is enor-
mously complex, and most biochemists concern themselves with studying
21
(or even knowing about!) only a small fraction of the total interactions."
That these interactions must be governed by a complex system of logic
rivaling the most sophisticated programs of modern electronic computers
is certainly indicated by the descriptions in Watson's book.
(b) The morphology of cells. The E. coli cell appears to possess a rela-
tively simple gross structure, but many cells, even among the algae and
protozoa, have a very complex morphology. For example, the cilia of
protozoa such as the paramecium have been shown to possess an intricate
structure. The cilia function cooperatively under the direction of versatile
22
cellular control mechanisms to produce a synchronized rowing machine.
They are assembled within the cell according to a regulated program, and the
process of construction must also require complex molecular machinery.
In the cells of higher organisms, we find many examples of complex
morphology. For example, biologists have discovered several kinds of
23
structures that join cells together and enable them to communicate.
These junctions display an elaborate architecture of sheets, tubes, and fila-
ments, and some of them are designed to open and close systematically in
response to cellular conditions. It seems very doubtful that precise plans
for this cellular machinery could be specified by a small amount of informa-
tion. It also seems doubtful that these plans could be generated by adding a
The Great Complexity of Biological Form 119
lew bits of information to, say, the plans for the enzymes regulating the
Krebs cycle of cellular respiration.
(c) The varieties of cells making up the tissues of higher organisms. We
can easily write down a long list of types of cells appearing in diverse bodily
organs. These include muscle cells, nerve cells, bone cells, different kinds
of blood cells, glandular cells, liver cells, epithelial cells, and so forth. The
study of a particular kind of cell can be a whole academic subject in itself,
and doctoral dissertations are frequently devoted to the study of a detail of
a detail of the structure and function of such cells. The complete instruc-
tions for constructing all these cells must be contained in the genetic coding
of any higher organism, at least according to the understanding of modern
biology. There must also be instructions controlling the development of
these cells during the growth of the embryo.
(d) The structure and function of the organs in higher plants and animals.
The various organs of the body perform a vast array of complicated func-
tions, most of which are poorly understood. Examples include the disease-
lighting system of the blood, the image-producing eye and its retina, the
brain, the endocrine gland system, and the heart and circulatory system.
The functions of a typical organ are carried out through the cooperative
interaction of many complex subsystems. For example, the subsystems of
(he eye include the lens, the muscles supporting it, the iris, the cornea, the
retina, the nerve connections, and the muscle system that moves the
eyeball. Many of these subsystems are very intricate. For example, the iris
contains a muscle system for opening and closing the pupil; the lens must be
transparent and shaped so as to focus a sharp image on the retina; the retina
contains systems of cells and nerves designed to detect elementary visual
patterns such as lines and edges; the light-sensitive cells contain complex
chemical systems designed to respond to different colors of light; and so
forth. It would not be surprising if significant amounts of information were
required to represent each of these subsystems as combinations of their
underlying cellular components. In general, we would expect the basic
plans of organs to have a high information content.
(c) The behavior of animals other than man. Many patterns of complex
behavior are exhibited by lower animals. We may note, for example, the
social systems of bees and ants, the spinning of spider webs, and the trans-
continental migrations of birds. Biologists generally think that these instinc-
tive behavioral patterns are built into the genetic material of the organisms. -
This suggests that they must be represented biochemically as a series of
logical " i f - t h e n " instructions similar to the program of a computer.
120 Information Theory and the Self-organization of Matter
5 . 3 I n f o r m a t i o n - t h e o r e t i c Limitations
on the Evolution of Complex Form
In Section 5 . 1 , we discussed the mathematical models of natural phe-
nomena used in modern physics, and pointed out that the fundamental
program of the physicists is to make these models as simple and general as
possible. The basic format for a physical model is as follows: We have a sys-
tem, 5, in which events take place in accordance with a set of natural laws,
F. Generally, F will be defined by a set of differential equations. The sys-
tem S will have initial conditions, S , and boundary conditions, B. These
0
can be calculated, at least in principle, from the equations for the initial
conditions, boundary conditions, and natural laws.
We have argued that simplicity in a mathematical model can be mea-
sured by the amount of coding needed to express the model in a fixed pro-
gramming language. The mathematical models of physics tend to be simple
in the sense that they can be specified by relatively small amounts of cod-
ing. For example, the Schr dinger equation of Figure 1 can be solved nu-
merically by a program occupying less than one solid page of programming
instructions. (This is discussed in greater detail in Appendix 2.) If we allow
four additional pages for initial and boundary conditions, we find that we
can express in less than five pages a model of a primordial planet evolving
in accordance with the laws of chemistry and electromagnetism. The infor-
mation content of P, for this model is no more than 14,000 characters (at
2,800 characters per page), or
L(P )
t 6x 14,000 = 84,000 bits (15)
(Recall that each character in our 64-character alphabet requires six bits.)
From the probability distribution P we can calculate the probability,
t
a function that can analyze the state of the system at time t and report
whether or not the configuration represented by X is present. One can
122 Information Theory and the Self-organization of Matter
define an adequate function of this kind in less than one page of condensed
programming instructions. (Again, see Appendix 2.) This gives us an upper
bound for L(M) of less than six pages, or
The following inequality reveals the implications of these bounds for the
theory of evolution:
C + l o g 2 T + L ( M ) - L ( X )
M(X) 2 (18)
in a universal model.
Putting these values together, we find that
3 2 6 + 2 6 6 + 1 0 0 , 8 0 0 - 600,000 -150,000
M(X) 2 10 (20)
in the system at the end of any day in a 4.5-billion-year period is also much
-150,000
less than 10 . We can conclude that the entire course of events in S
over a 4.5-billion-year period would have to be repeated over and over
again at least 1 0 times for there to be a reasonable expectation that
1 5 0 , 0 0 0
150
1 0 ' is an enormous number, to say the least, it is reasonable to suppose
that X will not evolve within the system in 4.5 billion years.
Now, X could represent the genetic coding for a higher animal, and 5
could be a mathematical model of an earth-sized physical system in which
the evolution of life might be expected to occur. Our conclusion is that
higher life as we know it will not evolve in such a system in any realistic span
of time. For the time t we could have chosen any time period for which L(t)
is small, for the only property of t that affects our considerations is the
number of characters needed to express t in the program for calculating P,.
This means that our t could be anything from one year to billions of billions
of years, and the conclusion expressed in inequality (20) would still hold.
It is often said that while it is highly unlikely that any given complicated
structural part of a living organism will arise by chance, still, given the
immense span of geological time, such organisms are bound to evolve
eventually. Self-reproducing systems of molecules will automatically arise
through the effects of random combination and processes of chemical self-
organization. These systems will be modified by random mutations, and
they will gradually evolve through the culling action of natural selection.
Yet, although this evolutionary picture may seem superficially plausible,
the analysis presented here rules it out in a system characterized by simple
natural laws and simple initial and boundary conditions. The reason for this
is easy to understand. Natural selection is supposed to direct the process of
evolution, but its only source of guidance is the information built into the
natural laws and the initial and boundary conditions of the system. This
means that natural selection can constrain the processes of random combi-
nation and mutation only in a simple way. Natural selection may be able to
impose simple patterns on the welter of randomly distributed molecules,
but in a simple model, complex order can only arise by chance.
For this reason, the theory of evolution can be seen to fail at the very
weak point that has been criticized by so many students of the theory.
Many observers have noted that natural selection has never been ade-
quately defined in evolutionary theory, either in Darwin's original version
26
or in the more recent "synthetic t h e o r y . " According to Darwin, natu-
ral selection means "survival of the fittest," but no one, unfortunately,
has been able to define which creatures are fittest, except by saying that
they are the ones that survive. A similar problem plagues the more recent
definition of natural selection as "differential reproduction."
Evolutionists have always had an intuitive feeling that the ordinary inter-
actions between living organisms would generate forces of selection which,
over long periods of time, would transform simple molecular combinations
into higher life forms. This intuition is based on commonplace examples.
For example, a mutation producing longer legs in a deer might well be
selected because it would enable the deer to escape from predators more
easily. Yet, this is no reason to believe that natural selection would possess
the discriminating power needed to guide the development of a world of
plants and animals from an inanimate primeval slime. What we have shown
here is that in a system governed by simple natural laws, no process is suffi-
cient to do this, whether it be natural selection or any other imagined
process of evolutionary development.
At this point, let us consider one possible objection that could be raised
to our interpretation of inequality (18). We have discussed the question of
whether or not a configuration represented by X could evolve within the
Limitations on the Evolution of Complex Form 125
system S. But do the X's we have considered represent objects of real inter-
est? Suppose, for example, that X represents the exact D N A coding of a
particular cell. Many mutations are believed to have a neutral effect on
cellular development, and many others might affect the cell in a relatively ,
insignificant way. By combining, say, 10,000 mutations of this type in vari-
1 0 0 0 0
ous ways, one could conceivably produce 2 different cells, all nearly
identical in form and function. One might argue that while the evolution
of any one of these cells is highly improbable, it might nonetheless be prob-
able for at least one out of the total collection to evolve. If p is the proba-
bility for the evolution of each individual genotype, then the probability
for the evolution of at least one of the genotypes might be in the order of
2 w s m
p . This probability could be fairly large, even if p were very small.
Perhaps the most comprehensive way to answer this objection is to make
use of the concept of symbolic descriptions that we introduced in Section
27
5 . 2 . Recall that a symbolic description of an organism is a sequence of
coding that specifies significant features of the organism, while omitting
unimportant details. We argued in Section 5.2 that an adequate symbolic
description of a higher organism should possess a high information content,
and we argued that the same could be said of the symbolic descriptions
defining many important general features of living organisms.
The following diagram sums up the relationship between a symbolic
description and the many individual instances to which it refers.
ticular text, this G could produce a printed version of the text by analyzing
any one of the copies. The printed text Y would contain the essential infor-
mation in X , . . . ,X , while omitting all reference to the individual styles
1 n
though these copies may differ greatly from one another in detail.
In the field of biology there are many applications for the concepts of
symbolic descriptions and observation functions. For example, consider a
particular species of animal, such as the horse. Horses vary greatly in indi-
vidual detail. But if there is any meaning to the term "horse," there must be
certain specific information that is common to all normal horses and that
fully defines this category of organic form. It should be possible to ascertain
this information by observing any horse that is not defective in some way,
for otherwise it could not be said that the information truly characterizes
horses. This suggests that there should exist a symbolic description charac-
terizing horses, and an observation function G that can analyze any given
horse and generate this symbolic description.
In general, an observation function can be constructed from any sys-
tematic process of observation that abstracts certain features from ob-
served objects and ignores others. One of the principles of reductionistic
science is that all such processes can be defined mathematically as al-
gorithms. Of course, no one has yet devised algorithms for the kind of
sophisticated observational processes that we are considering here. In this
chapter, however, we will assume for the sake of argument that this is
possible, and we will treat observation functions as computer programs.
(A technical discussion of observation functions is given in Thompson,
(1980).)
If Y is a symbolic description produced by an observation function G,
we can measure the information content of Y by L(Y | G ) . The symbol
L(Y |G) designates the amount of information required to specify Y, given
that G is known. The idea is that we only want to measure information
in Y that is obtained from X , . . . ,X . We do not want to consider any
1 n
probability that some one of the forms X , . . . ,X will evolve within the
1 n
-150 0 0 0
system S. Our conclusion is that since 10 is an exceedingly small
number, it is nearly certain that none of these forms will ever evolve in S. In
the particular case we are considering, this means that no instance of a
horse will ever be found in 5. In general, it means that no form with a sym-
bolic description of high information content can be expected to evolve in a
system characterized by natural laws, initial conditions, and boundary
conditions of low information content.
Let us examine inequality (22) more closely to understand the basic prin-
ciple behind it. First of all, note that the upper bound this inequality places
on M(X ) + . . . + M(X ) will become reasonably large only if we increase
1 n
the complexity of our model to the point where L(M) is nearly equal to
600,000 - 266 - 446 bits, or nearly 36 solid pages of coding. There are
three ways of increasing L(M). One way is to increase the complexity of the
laws of the system. We note, however, that scientists have not yet reached
the point of even considering natural laws requiring 36 pages of coding, and
it is unlikely that such considerations could ever be practical, given the
limitations of the human mind. At any rate, the laws of present-day phys-
ics are based on the Schr dinger equation and a few potentials, and the
fundamental program of physics has been to simplify these as much as
possible.
L(M) might also be increased by increasing the complexity of the initial
conditions or the boundary conditions of the system. As we shall see, this
would amount to building data for the symbolic description, Y, into the
initial or boundary conditions. If specifications for Y were built into the
boundary conditions, then as time passed we would find information for Y
128 Information Theory and the Self-organization of Matter
coming into the system from across the boundary. If such specifications
were built into the initial conditions, it would appear that information for Y
had existed in the system from its very beginning. In either case, the mathe-
matical model provides us with no satisfactory explanation of the original
source of the information for Y. Certainly neither alternative is acceptable
from the point of view of current evolutionary theory.
We can clarify these points by considering the following stronger version
of inequality (22):
C + log2T - L(Y |G,M)
M(X )
1 + . . . + M(X ) n 2' (24)
order for L(Y |G,M) to be much smaller than this, it is necessary to adjust
M very carefully and, in effect, build specifications for Yinto M. Inequality
(24) shows that there can be a reasonable probability of finding an X in the j
system at time t only if L(Y |G,M) is not very much greaterthanc' + log T. 2
This constant is no more than 712 bits, or about 119 characters. This means
that nearly all the information needed to specify Ymust be built into M in
the form of natural laws, boundary conditions, or initial conditions.
This is an appropriate time to consider one objection that might be made
to our arguments. One might point out that the information content of or-
dinary matter is certainly very high. For example, the information needed
to specify the positions of the billions of molecules in a gas must be enor-
mous. How, then, are we justified in saying that L(M) for a physical model
should be small? The answer to this question is that we have described the
initial state of our physical system by means of thermodynamic ensembles
that specify only broad statistical properties of matter. However, we could
also consider a model in which the initial conditions stipulated a particular
arrangement of subatomic particles in a primordial gas.
In such a model, L(M) would be extremely large, and inequality (22)
would not tell us very much. But what should we expect of L(Y |G,M) in
this situation? There are essentially two alternatives. If the arrangement of
our primordial gas were chosen at random, then we would expect the infor-
mation specifying this arrangement to be irrelevant to the construction of
Y, and thus we would expect L(Y |G,M) to be large. According to (24), this
would mean that M{X ) + . . . + M(X ) would be very small. (This line
1 n
bility is practically zero that life as we know it will arise. This K can be
regarded as a universal constant of the physical system that constrains its
evolutionary potential. If any category of form can be characterized by a
simple description having information content less than K, then it is possi-
ble for representatives of that category to arise in the system. But if the
members of the category satisfy a description of higher information content
than K, then they are highly unlikely to evolve.
This applies to categories such as species, classes, and phyla of plants and
animals. It also applies to more abstract categories such as intelligence or
130 Information Theory and the Self-organization of Matter
personality. We can conclude, for example, that personality will not evolve
in a system of low l v a l u e unless we define personality so broadly that it be-
comes practically devoid of meaning. This can be appreciated if we con-
template the list of features of personality given in Section 5.2. Unless
these features can be adequately defined by a description of low informa-
tion content, we cannot expect to see entities that display them arising in
a system of low information content. (Here, of course, we are speaking
of personality as a purely physical phenomenon, in accordance with the
reductionistic philosophy of modern science.)
At this point we would like to briefly discuss some recent theories of the
self-organization of matter. These theories are based on nonequilibrium
thermodynamics and the theory of chemical kinetics, and they have been
28
developed by researchers such as Ilya Prigogine and Manfred Eigen. In
these theories, systems of chemicals are modeled with differential equa-
tions of a kind known as reaction-diffusion equations. By studying such
equations, the theoreticians hope to show how disorganized molecules in a
primordial soup could combine together chemically to produce the first
self-reproducing cell.
Perhaps the most well-known example of this work is Eigen's theory of
29
self-reproducing hypercycles. In this theory, Eigen proposes that systems
of polypeptides and self-replicating R N A molecules will arise sponta-
neously in a suitable chemical soup. A collection of R N A molecules,
R1,...R , will be able to perpetuate itself in the soup if each ft generates
n y
cycles," and he proposes that they might have filled the evolutionary gap
between disorganized chemical compounds and living cells.
Here we will not attempt to discuss Eigen's theory in detail. We will sim-
ply point out that Eigen has not even begun to explain the origin of the self-
reproducing machinery of living cells. In existing cells, the D N A molecules
carrying genetic information are reproduced with the aid of highly complex
and specific enzymes, such as " D N A polymerase" and " D N A gyrase." These
enzymes all perform functions which are apparently necessary for cellular
reproduction, and which frequently involve remarkable feats of molecular
manipulation. For example, recent work suggests that D N A gyrase is able
systematically to break a D N A strand, pass a nearby strand of D N A
30
through the break, and then rejoin the broken strand. Since long D N A
chains automatically become tangled during replication, this capacity to tie
and untie knots in D N A appears essential for cellular reproduction.
A l l these enzymes are manufactured within the cell by an elaborate pro-
cess requiring a large number of proteins and other complex molecules.
Complex Form and the Frustration of Empiricism 131
For example, one step in this process is carried out by structures called
ribosomes that in Escherichia coli have a molecular weight of about 3 mil-
31
lion, and can be broken down into 55 distinct protein subunits. A l l these
proteins are themselves coded in D N A , and they are manufactured by the
same process in which they play an essential role.
Eigen's problem is to show how a stable self-reproducing system could
begin to operate before the development of this elaborate machinery, and
then show how the machinery could gradually evolve by mutation and
32
natural selection. Dixon and W e b b summarize some of the many dif-
33
ficulties that must be overcome in such an attempt, and S m i t h gives
a critique of Eigen's theory. Here we will simply observe that Eigen's
theoretical framework is not adequate for his task. In a model based on
reaction-diffusion equations, each chemical compound is represented by a
continuous function describing its distribution in space and time. In such
models there is no direct way to describe three-dimensional geometrical
structures composed of molecules, even though such structures are very
important in living cells.
For this reason, evolutionary models based solely on reaction-diffusion
equations are necessarily incomplete. Such models cannot readily simulate
processes involving such three-dimensional structures as ribosomes or cell
membranes, and they are even less suited to showing how such structures
may have evolved. At present, there seem to be no mathematical models of
biochemical processes that are both reasonably complete and easy to han-
dle. Hence we have based the analysis in this chapter on the laws of quan-
tum mechanics, even though these laws are difficult to apply in practical
calculations, and are also subject to a number of theoretical drawbacks.
As a final point we note that an analysis of evolution on the basis of in-
formation theory has been carried out independently by Hubert Yockey.
Yockey considered the problem of chemical evolution in a primordial
soup, and he has given estimates for the information content of proteins
34
such as cytochrome-c.
thing we learn seems to make them even more appallingly unique. If human
origins were indeed inevitable under the precise conditions of our actual his-
tory, that makes the more nearly impossible such an occurrence anywhere
else. I therefore think it extremely unlikely that anything enough like us for
39
real communication of thought exists anywhere in our accessible u n i v e r s e .
form that could be based completely on simple natural laws. This explana-
tion seemed to involve fewer inexplicable elements than the hypothesis
of a primordial creator, and many people therefore came to accept it as
scientifically superior.
The analysis presented here removes this objection to natural theology.
We have seen that the origin of complex order can be explained neither by
natural selection nor by any other principle based on simple natural laws.
Natural structures and patterns of high information content are inherently
inexplicable by the reductionistic methods of quantitative analysis. The
H hypothesis that these structures have been generated by a transcendental
intelligent being is therefore in no way inferior to our alternative interpre-
tations (1), (2), and (3) as a theoretical explanation. In addition, this
hypothesis opens up the possibility that if the ultimate foundation of reality
is a sentient being, then it may be possible to acquire absolute knowledge
directly from this transcendental source.
At this point the objection might be raised that this hypothesis is not
proven by our analysis, and that, indeed, we have not rigorously proven
that biological form is characterized by high information content. If the
forms of organisms only seem complex, but actually have low informa-
tion content, then our analysis does not rule out the possibility that they
might evolve with relatively high probabilities. Thus, by adopting interpre-
tation (4), we may be able to save the idea of progressive evolution in a
comprehensible universe governed by simple natural laws.
This approach to the theory of evolution has been adopted by the infor-
mation theorist Gregory Chaitin. According to Chaitin, the fundamental
goal of theoretical biology is
to set up a nondeterministic model universe, to formally define what it means
for a region of space-time in that universe to be an organism. . . , and to
rigorously demonstrate that starting from simple initial conditions, organisms
will appear and evolve . . . in a reasonable amount of time and with high
44
probability.
This program requires living organisms to have low information content,
and Chaitin has therefore proposed that an organism is "a highly inter-
dependent region, one for which the complexity of the whole is much less
45
than the sum of the complexities of its parts."
In order to elucidate Chaitin's proposal, let us refer again to the analysis
presented in Sections 5.2 and 5.3. We showed with inequalities (18), (20),
and (22) of Section 5.3 that no pattern with an information content of more
than 101,392 (= 100,800 + 326 + 266) bits is likely to evolve in our model
system. Our upper estimate in Section 5.2 for the number of proteins in a
Complex Form and the Frustration of Empiricism 137
cell was 210,000. For the sake of argument, let us suppose that a list of
210,000 proteins has an information content of no more than 101,392 bits.
Then inequalities (12) and (13) of Section 5.2 imply that each successive
protein can be specified in terms of the preceding proteins in the list by the
46
addition of only 1.5 bits of new information on the average. In fact, (13)
and (14) imply that for at least 210,000-101,392 = 108,608 values of n, we
will have F(1 ,X _ ) = Y„. In other words, 108,608 of these proteins must be
n 1
and conclude that speculation on these topics is futile. We can agree that
such a conclusion is not at all unreasonable, but we should stress that it en-
tails abandoning all confidence in the theory of evolution as an established
understanding of the origin of life. One might advocate, of course, that we
should admit our present ignorance in this area, while still maintaining the
hope that some day we will show how evolution proceeds by simple laws.
We should realize, however, that biological form may well be characterized
by high information content, as we argued in Section 5.2. If this is indeed
the case, the empirical approach will never be able to provide a simple ex-
planation of life's origins. At best, this approach will be able to produce
only a complex description of natural order. Such a description cannot be
satisfying as an explanation, and, as Bennett's ideas indicate, it can never
49
be possible to actually prove that the description is f i n a l .
These conclusions may seem to be completely negative, but we should
not end this discussion without pointing out that they also have a positive
side. If nature is indeed simple and comprehensible, then it is hard to imag-
ine any other method of studying nature than the empirical method of ex-
periment and calculation. But by showing that nature may not be so simple,
we are opening up the possibility that there may be other valid methods of
obtaining knowledge. If the absolute foundation of reality is a reservoir of
irreducible and inconceivable qualities, then the possibility arises that we
may be able to approach the absolute by methods other than dissection and
measurement. Our empirical analysis of evolutionary theory cannot prove
rigorously that this is so, and it cannot disclose how such an alternative ap-
proach could be practically realized. However, it does show that empirical
reasoning is capable of pointing beyond itself.
We have mentioned the conclusion of natural theology, that the pres-
ence of complex order in nature implies the existence of an absolute intel-
ligence. Although this conclusion is consistent with the results of our
information-theoretic analysis, it is certainly not proven by this analysis.
Nonetheless, the ideas of natural theology are valuable, for they suggest an
alternative to the empirical method of acquiring knowledge. If the absolute
basis of nature is a sentient being and we ourselves are products of this ab-
solute source, then it is possible that we may be able to relate personally
with the absolute.
In this chapter we will not discuss the ramifications of this possibility,
but we mention it simply as a concrete example of the options opened up
by our analysis. If it is to be of real interest, such an approach to absolute
knowledge must be verifiable by tangible, reproducible experience, for
otherwise it amounts to nothing more than empty speculation. Yet the
Notes 139
Notes
9. For example, see O p a r i n , The Origin of Life, and Orgel, The Origins
of Life.
2 1 . Watson, p. 76.
22. Satir, " H o w Cilia M o v e , " pp. 4 4 - 5 2 .
23. Staehelin and Hull, "Junctions between Living Cells," pp. 141-152.
24. Winston, "The M I T R o b o t . "
25. According to a famous conjecture of Sir A r t h u r Eddington, there are
2 5 6 79
exactly 136 x 2 1.6x 1 0 protons in the universe. (Eddington, The
Philosophy of Physical Science, p. 176.) Of course, this should not be
taken very seriously. The important point here is that l o g r w i l l be 2
35. Julian Huxley is one well-known proponent of the idea that evolution
is a progressive process directed by natural selection. See Huxley,
Evolution in Action.
42. This viewpoint is expounded by the logical positivists, who hold that
one can speak meaningfully only of sense perceptions, and that all
other categories are mere verbiage. This philosophy is summarized
by the physicist Yehudah Freundlich as follows: "To us, the statement
that trains have wheels when they are not in the station (when we are
not sensing them) means that at the station they will have wheels. This
is, to us, a very satisfying solution, for having thus defined existence
we proceed to speak of wheels on the train even when it is not in the
station. In general, attributing a property to a system means that cer-
tain predictions about the system can be m a d e . " (Freundlich, "Mind,
Matter, and Physicists," p p . 130-131.) According to this doctrine, the
statement " M a n evolved from a primate ancestor" means that certain
bones may be seen in certain museums. This is far from a satisfying so-
lution to us and, we believe, to many others. Generally, scientists have
sought to acquire insight into the nature of what really exists. If em-
pirical science is indeed unable to provide such insight, we can only
conclude that its pretensions to universality are greatly overblown.
x
convey only log (2 -1) bits of information. This is .87 bits if x = 1 . 5 .
2
49. This would require a formal proof of L(X) N. See note 48.
Chapter 6
Chance and
The Unity of Nature
Throughout human history, philosophers and seekers of knowledge
have sought to discover a single fundamental cause underlying all the
phenomena of the universe. Since the rise of Western science in the late
Renaissance, many scientists have also felt impelled to seek this ultimate
goal, and they have approached it from their own characteristic perspec-
tive. Western science is based on the assumption that the universe can be
understood mechanistically—that is, in terms of numbers and mathema-
tical formulas—and Western scientists have therefore searched for an
ultimate, unified mathematical description of nature.
This search has gone through many vicissitudes, and many times scien-
tists have felt that a final, unified theory was nearly within their grasp. Thus
in the beginning of the nineteenth century Pierre Simon de Laplace could
contemplate Newton's laws and declare that " A l l the effects of nature are
only the mathematical consequences of a small number of immutable
1
laws." By the turn of the century many new concepts and discoveries had
been incorporated into the science of physics, and Laplace's simple picture
of the laws of nature had become superannuated. At about this time, how-
ever, Albert Einstein embarked on a much more sophisticated and ambi-
tious program of unification. His goal was to explain all the phenomena of
the universe as oscillations in one fundamental "unified field."
But even while Einstein was working on this project, revolutionary de-
velopments in the science of physics were rendering his basic approach ob-
solete. For several decades a bewildering welter of new discoveries made
the prospect of finding an ultimate theory seem more and more remote.
But the effort to find a unified theory of nature has continued, and in 1979
three physicists (Sheldon Glashow, Abdus Salam, and Steven Weinberg)
won the Nobel Prize in physics for their effort in partially tying together
some of the disparate elements of current physical theories. On the basis of
their work, many scientists are now optimistically anticipating the develop-
ment of a theory that can explain the entire universe in terms of a single
quantum field governed by a universal force law.
The scientists' search for a unified explanation of natural phenomena
begins with two main hypotheses. The first of these is that all the diverse
143
144 Chance and the Unity of Nature
Figure 1. This device displays a figure of zero or one that can change from second to
second. We shall regard it as a model "universe" and use it to illustrate the concepts
of random events and universal statistical laws.
146 Chance and the Unity of Nature
Let us begin by considering how the concept of chance could apply to this
model universe. For example, suppose we are told that the model universe
obeys the following statistical law:
The zeros and ones appear randomly in the window, independently of one
another. During any given second the probability is 50% that the window will
display a one and 50% that it will display a zero.
5 0 % , we could not agree that these ones were appearing in the window
with a probability of 50%.
In practice it would never be possible for a statistical analyst to say defi-
nitely that a given history does or does not satisfy our statistical law. A l l he
could do would be to determine a degree of confidence in the truth or fal-
sity of the law as it applied to a particular sequence of ones and zeros. For
example, our sample history is 979 digits long. For a sequence of this length
to satisfy the law, we would expect the percentage of ones to fall between
46.8% and 53.2%. (These are the "95% confidence limits.") If the percen-
tage did not fall within these limits, we could take this failure as an indica-
tion that the sequence did not satisfy the law, but we could not assert this as
a definite conclusion.
We have seen that the sample history consists of approximately 50%
ones. This observation agrees with the hypothesis that this sequence satis-
fies our statistical law, but it is not sufficient to establish this, for there are
other criteria such a sequence must meet. In general, if a sequence is to be
considered random or disorderly, we would not expect any particular pat-
tern to appear within the sequence with unusual prominence. This means
that for each positive number n, all of the 2" subsequences of length n
should appear in our sequence with nearly equal frequencies.
For example, if the sample history were indeed a random sequence, we
would expect each of the subsequences 00, 0 1 , 10, and 11 to appear with a
frequency of roughly 25%. In fact, the frequencies of these subsequences
are 25.6%, 24.7%, 25.4%, and 24.3% respectively, and these frequencies
conform with the hypothesis that our history satisfies the statistical law. As
before, we cannot expect the frequency to take on an exact value. We can
at most determine a degree of confidence in our statistical hypothesis by
measuring how closely the observed frequencies of various subsequences
2
match their expected values.
So in practical terms we can interpret our statistical law as an approxi-
mate statement about the relative frequency of various patterns of ones
and zeros within a larger sequence of ones and zeros. If statistical laws were
never attributed a deeper meaning than this, the concepts of randomness
and statistical law might seem of little interest. However, because of an ad-
ditional interpretation commonly given them, these concepts are actually
of great significance in modern science, and particularly the science of
physics. This interpretation becomes clear in the following reformulation
of our statistical law, as understood from the viewpoint of modern physics:
The box contains some apparatus that operates according to definite laws of
cause and effect and that determines which figures will appear in the window.
148 Chance and the Unity of Nature
its apparent randomness results directly from the fact that it encodes a large
amount of meaningful information.
We produced the sequence in Figure 2 by a technique from the field of
communications engineering known as "data compression." In this field,
engineers confront the problem of how to send as many messages as pos-
sible across a limited communications channel, such as a telephone line.
They have therefore sought methods of encoding messages as sequences of
symbols that are as short as possible but can still be readily decoded to
reproduce the original message.
In 1948 Claude Shannon established some of the fundamental principles
5
of communications engineering. He showed that each message has a cer-
tain information content, which can be expressed as a number of "bits," or
binary ones and zeros. If a message contains N bits of information, we can
encode it as a sequence of N or more ones and zeros, but we cannot encode
it as a shorter sequence without losing part of the message. When we en-
code the message as a sequence of almost exactly N ones and zeros, its
density of information is maximal, and each zero or one carries essential
information.
Shannon showed that when encoded in the shortest possible sequence, a
message appears to be completely random. The basic reason for this is that
if patterns of ones and zeros are to be used in the most efficient possible
way to encode information, all possible patterns must be used with roughly
equal frequency. Thus the criteria for maximal information density and
maximal randomness turn out to be the same.
Figures 3 and 4 show the effects of information compression for the mes-
sage encoded in Figure 2. Figure 3 illustrates some of the characteristics of
an uncompressed binary encoding of this message. The bar graph in this
figure represents the frequency distribution for five-bit subsequences, each
representing a letter of the English text. This distribution clearly does not
follow the bell-shaped curve we would expect for a random sequence.
However, when we encode the message in compressed f o r m , as in Figure 2,
we obtain the distribution shown in Figure 4. Here we see that simply by
encoding the message in a more succinct form, we have greatly increased its
6
apparent randomness.
We can conclude that it is not justifiable to insist upon absolute chance as
an explanation of apparent randomness in nature. If a sequence of events
exhibits the statistical properties of randomness, this may simply mean that
it contains a large amount of significant information. Also, if a sequence
exhibits a combination of random features and systematic features, as with
our text before compression, this may reflect the presence of significant in-
Chance and Evolution 153
At this point let us consider how these observations bear on the actual
universe in which we live. Could it be that while focusing on ultimate
mechanistic laws, modern scientists are disregarding some significant in-
formation encoded in the phenomena of nature? In fact, this is the implica-
tion of the sequence in Figure 2 when we decode it and perceive its higher
meaning—namely, as a statement about human evolution. The source
7
of this statement is the prominent evolutionist Theodosius Dobzhansky,
who here expresses a view held widely among researchers in the life sci-
ences. Dobzhansky is visualizing the origin of human life in the context of
an underlying physical theory that involves combined processes of causa-
tion and chance. He is expressing the conviction that although such pro-
cesses have generated the highly complex forms of human life we know,
they nonetheless have a zero probability of doing so.
No one has shown, of course, that the universe as a whole, or even the
small part of it we inhabit, really does obey some fundamental mechanis-
tic laws. Yet suppose, for the sake of argument, that it does. In effect,
Dobzhansky is asserting that from the viewpoint of this ultimate universal
theory, the detailed information specifying the nature and history of
8
human life is simply random noise. The theory will be able to describe only
broad statistical features of this information, and will have to dismiss its
essential content as the vagaries of causeless chance.
/
156 Chance and the Unity of Nature
and we would therefore have to know the sphere's initial direction of mo-
tion with great accuracy to predict its path correctly for any length of time.
For example, suppose the moving sphere is going sixty miles per hour, and
the dimensions of the spheres are as shown in the figure. To predict the
moving sphere's path from bounce to bounce for one hour, we would have
to know its original direction of motion (in degrees) with an accuracy of
10
roughly two million decimal places. We can estimate that a number with
this many decimal digits would take a full 714 pages to write down.
In effect, the number representing the initial direction of the sphere con-
stitutes a script specifying in advance the detailed movements of the sphere
for one hour. To specify the sphere's movements for one year, this script
would have to be expanded to more than six million pages. We can there-
fore see that this simple deterministic theory can provide complete predic-
tions about the phenomena being studied—namely, the movements of the
sphere—only if a detailed description of what will actually happen is first
built into the theory.
We can generalize the example of the bouncing sphere by allowing all the
spheres to move simultaneously and to interact not merely by elastic colli-
sion but by force laws of various kinds. By doing this we obtain the classical
Newtonian theory of nature mentioned by Pierre Simon de Laplace in the
quotation cited at the beginning of this chapter. Laplace and many other
scientists of his time wished to account for all phenomena by this theory,
which was based entirely on simple laws of attraction and repulsion
between material particles.
Let us therefore consider what this theory implies about the origin of life.
Although it is more complicated than our simple example, this theory has
some of the same characteristics. To account for life as we know it, the
theory would have to incorporate billions of numbers describing the state
of the world at some earlier time, and the entire history of living beings
would have to be encoded in the higher-order decimal digits of those
11
numbers. Some of these decimal digits would encode the blueprints for a
future rhinoceros, and others would encode the life history of a particular
human being.
These digits would encode the facts of universal history in an extremely
complicated way, and as far as the theory is concerned this encoded infor-
mation would be completely arbitrary. This might tempt an adherent of
the theory to abandon the idea of strict determinism and say—perhaps
covertly—that the encoded information must have arisen by absolute
chance (see note 8). Yet we have seen that this is a misleading idea, and it
certainly has no place in a theory based solely on causal interactions. A l l we
can realistically say in the context of this theory is that the facts of universal
The Paradox of Unity and Diversity 159
history simply are what they are. The theory can describe them only if a
detailed script is initially added to it.
We can conclude that the prospects for a simple, universal mechanistic
theory are not good. Once we eliminate the unsound and misleading idea
of absolute chance, we are confronted with the problem of accounting for
an almost unlimited amount of detailed information with a finite system of
formulas. Some of this information may seem meaningless and chaotic, but
a substantial part of it is involved with the phenomena of life, and this part
includes the life histories of all scientific theorists. We must regard a theory
that neglects most of this information as only a partial description of some
features of the universe. Conversely, a theory that takes large amounts of
this information into account must be filled with elaborate detail, and it can
hardly be considered simple or unified.
simply resign ourselves to accepting that the world contains a large amount
of incomprehensible complexity that can be described but not explained.
Unfortunately, this conclusion would bar us from ever understanding the
most important features of life, and of human life in particular.
Here we shall set aside the mechanistic paradigm of modern science and
pursue a different approach to the problem of finding a unified cause un-
derlying the phenomena of nature. Our starting point is the observation
that we are already familiar with a phenomenon that simultaneously
exhibits the features of both unity and diversity. This is the phenomenon of
conscious awareness.
Consider what happens when we look out through a window and observe
a distant scene. We are simultaneously aware of distinct elements of the
scene—such as buildings, trees, and clouds—and we are also aware of
our accompanying thoughts and feelings. It is true that our awareness of
the details of the scene may be quite imperfect. (Certainly our memory is
imperfect, for if we are asked to describe the scene after seeing it, we may
be able to give only a very incomplete and distorted account.) Nonetheless,
it must be admitted that while we are observing the scene, our conscious
awareness does simultaneously encompass many separate features.
It may be argued that the eye scans quickly from one part of the scene to
another, and that the apparent unity of the picture we perceive is simply
due to the rapid blending together of numerous distinct picture elements.
However, it is just as hard to account for the unified conscious perception
of events in a temporal sequence as it is to account for the simultaneous
perception of different parts of a picture.
A photograph of the scene consists of many distinct colored grains that
are not tied together in a unified way. The sequence of electrical pulses
emerging from a television camera may represent the scene as a temporal
pattern, but these pulses are also not unified. If the information represent-
ing the scene is processed by a computer, it can be transformed within the
computer's memory into a variety of different forms, and these can succeed
one another at a rapid rate. Yet neither these representations nor their
12
pattern of succession in time will ever exhibit real u n i t y . As we have
observed, information can be compressed only to a certain degree, and the
residue of incompressible information represents intractable diversity that
cannot be treated mechanistically in a unified way.
It is evident that our conscious awareness possesses features of simul-
taneous unity and diversity that are paradoxical from the mechanistic
point of view. We have already observed in Part I that consciousness is a
feature of reality that cannot be explained in mechanistic terms. There we
The Paradox of Unity and Diversity 161
Notes
11. We should note that the unpredictable behavior of the bouncing ball
in our example is a c o m m o n feature of many nonlinear dynamical
models. See, for example, Ruelle, "Strange A t t r a c t o r s , " p p . 126-137.
12. T h e relation between computer operations and self-referential con-
sciousness can be further elucidated by the following thought experi-
Notes 167
On Inspiration
In this chapter we will examine how human beings acquire knowledge in
science, mathematics, and art. Our focus shall primarily be on the forma
tion of ideas and hypotheses in science and mathematics, since the formal
nature of these subjects tends to put the phenomena we are concerned
with into particularly clear perspective. We will show that the phenomenon
known as inspiration plays an essential part in acquiring knowledge in mod
ern science and mathematics and the creative arts (such as music). We will
argue that the phenomenon of inspiration cannot readily be explained
by mechanistic models of nature consistent with present-day theories of
physics and chemistry.
To give a positive alternative to these models, we will continue the proj
ect of outlining the nonmechanistic theoretical system of the Bhagavad-
gītā. Thus far we have introduced the concept of the conscious self or
jīvātmā as an entity distinct from the material body (Chapters 1 and 2),
and we have also introduced the concept of the all-pervading supercon-
scious being or paramātmā. The Bhagavad-gītā shows how the idea of the
paramātmā can be used to construct a model of the interaction between the
conscious self and the material body. As we shall see, this model accounts
for the phenomenon of inspiration in a direct and striking way.
Modern scientists acquire knowledge, at least in principle, by what is
called the hypothetico-deductive method. Using this method, they formu
late hypotheses and then test them by experimental observation. Inves
tigators consider hypotheses valid only insofar as they are consistent with
the data obtained by observation, and they must in principle reject any
hypothesis that disagrees with observation. Much analysis has been di
rected toward the deductive side of the hypothetico-deductive method, but
the equally important process of hypothesis formation has been largely
neglected. So we ask, "Where do hypotheses come from?"
It is clear that scientists cannot use any direct, step-by-step process to
derive hypotheses from raw observational data. To deal with such data at
all, they must already have some working hypothesis, for otherwise the
data amount to nothing more than a bewildering array of symbols (or sights
and sounds), which is no more meaningful than a table of random numbers.
In this connection Albert Einstein once said, "It may be heuristically useful
to keep in mind what one has observed. But on principle it is quite wrong to
170 On Inspiration
divine. What do I say? It knows better how to divine than the conscious
self, since it succeeds where that has failed. In a word, is not the subliminal
6
self superior to the conscious self?" Having raised this question, Poincare
then backs away from it: "Is this affirmative answer forced upon us by the
facts I have just given? I confess that for my part, I should hate to accept
7
i t . " He then offers a mechanical explanation of how the subliminal self,
viewed as an automaton, could account for the observed phenomena of
inspiration.
proposed that the subliminal self must be able to form enormous numbers
of combinations in a short time, and that these could be evaluated sub-
consciously as they were formed, in accordance with the criteria for a
satisfactory solution determined by the conscious mind.
As a first step in evaluating this model, let us estimate the number of
combinations of symbols that could be generated within the brain within a
reasonable period of time. A very generous upper limit on this number is
46
given by the figure 3.2 x 10 . We obtain this figure by assuming that in
each cubic Angstrom unit of the brain, a separate combination is formed
and evaluated once during each billionth of a second over a period of one
hundred years. Although this figure is an enormous overestimate of what
the brain could possibly do within the bounds of our present understanding
of the laws of nature, it is still infinitesimal compared to the total number of
possible combinations of symbols one would have to form to have any
chance of randomly hitting a proof for a particular mathematical theorem
of moderate difficulty.
If we attempt to elaborate a line of mathematical reasoning, we find that
at each step there are many possible combinations of symbols we can write
down, and thus we can think of a particular mathematical argument as a
path through a tree possessing many successive levels of subdividing
branches. This is illustrated in the figure below. The number of branches in
such a tree grows exponentially with the number of successive choices, and
the number of choices is roughly proportional to the length of the argu-
ment. Thus as the length of the argument increases, the number of
46 10(l
branches will very quickly pass such limits as 1 0 and 10 . For example,
suppose we are writing sentences in some symbolic language, and the rules
of grammar for that language allow us an average of two choices for each
174 On Inspiration
100
successive symbol. Then there will be approximately 1 0 grammatical
sentences of 333 symbols in length.
Even a very brief mathematical argument will often expand to great
length when written out in full, and many mathematical proofs require
pages and pages of highly condensed exposition, in which many essential
steps are left for the reader to fill in. Thus there is only an extremely remote
chance that an appropriate argument would appear as a random combina-
tion in Poincare's mechanical model of the process of inspiration. Clearly,
the phenomenon of inspiration requires a process of choice capable of
going more or less directly to the solution, without even considering the
vast majority of possible combinations of arguments.
The requirements that this process of choice must meet are strikingly il-
lustrated by some further examples of mathematical inspiration. It is very
often found that the solution to a difficult mathematical problem depends
on the discovery of basic principles and underlying systems of mathemati-
cal relationships. Only when these principles and systems are understood
does the problem take on a tractable form. Therefore difficult problems
have often remained unsolved for many years, until mathematicians <
gradually developed various sophisticated ideas and methods of argu-
ment that made their solution possible. However, it is interesting to note
that on some occasions sudden inspiration has completely circumvented
this gradual process of development. There are several instances in which
famous mathematicians have, without proof, stated mathematical results
that later investigators proved only after elaborate systems of underlying
relationships had gradually come to light. Here are two examples:
The first example concerns the zeta-function studied by the German
mathematician Bernhard Riemann. At the time of his death, Riemann left
a note describing several properties of this function that pertain to the
theory of prime numbers. He did not give any proof for existence of these
properties, and many years elapsed before mathematicians were able to
find existence proofs for all but one of them. The remaining question is still
unsettled, though an immense amount of labor has been devoted to it over
the last seventy-five years. Of the properties of the zeta-function that have
been verified, the mathematician Jacques Hadamard said, " A l l these com-
plements could be brought to Riemann's publication only by the help of
facts which were completely unknown in his time; and, for one of the prop-
erties enunciated by him, it is hardly conceivable how he can have found it
Some Striking Examples 175
many of the problems that have perplexed philosophers, and it also directly
accounts for the phenomena of inspiration. Most importantly, this expla
nation entails a direct method of obtaining verifiable knowledge about
both localized and universal consciousness.
The description of the interaction between the jīvātmā and the material
body given in the first part of the Bhagavad-gītā may seem perplexing:
"The bewildered spirit soul, under the influence of the three modes of ma
terial nature, thinks himself to be the doer of activities, which are in actual
ity carried out by nature." 1 2 Or again: "The embodied spirit, master of the
city of his body, does not create activities, nor does he influence people to
act, nor does he create the fruits of action. A l l this is enacted by the modes
of material nature." 1 3 Apparently, these statements support the viewpoint
that nature is working entirely in accordance with certain fixed laws, and
that the conscious self can at best be an epiphenomenon affected by the
actions of the material body but unable to affect them in turn.
The Bhagavad-gītā confirms that nature is indeed working according to
laws. But the key to the solution of the mind-body problem lies in under
standing the character of these laws. Physicists tend to conceive of the laws
of nature as a closed set of immutable rules that can be specified by a few
simple equations. According to the Bhagavad-gītā, however, the laws of
nature are like the laws of human society promulgated by a head of state.
Like the laws of the physicists, these laws can also be represented in sym
bolic terms, but unlike them they tend to be highly complex. A n d since the
laws of nature are actually under personal control, they are always subject
to interference and modification.
In the Bhagavad-gītā the Supreme Person, Krsna, describes the laws of
nature in the following terms: "This material nature is working under My
direction, O son of Kuntī, and it is producing all moving and nonmoving
beings. By its rule this manifestation is created and annihilated again and
again." 1 4 Thus although the physicists are right that the material energy is
acting according to rules, they fail to see that these rules have their ultimate
source in a personal director.
We can visualize these rules in terms of a hierarchy. On the lowest level
are the relatively simple laws governing the gross behavior of matter.
These are studied to some extent by physicists and chemists. On the next
level are higher-order laws governing the complex behavior of the living
beings. These laws, sometimes referred to as the laws of karma (action),
are discussed in the Bhagavad-gītā in some detail. Finally, on the highest
level are the direct interventions of the Supreme Person in the course of
natural events. We have discussed in Parts I and II how one can extend
the world view of modern science to encompass such an open»ended hier-
The Interaction Between Consciousness and Matter 179
archy of natural laws. In such a hierarchy the laws on each level are not, of
course, absolute. They are merely approximations subject to refinement
and modification in accordance with higher laws and, ultimately, the
unconstrained will of the Supreme Person.
From the mechanistic viewpoint, such an "unconstrained w i l l " is at best
nothing more than a name for the arbitrary and the inexplicable. Yet the
Bhagavad-gītā describes some additional nonquantifiable factors that can
give us greater insight into the will of the Supreme Person. One of these
factors is the personal interaction between the Supreme and the localized
conscious selves.
In the Bhagavad-gītā Krsna states, "The Supreme Lord is situated in
everyone's heart, O A r j u n a , and is directing the wanderings of all living
entities, who are situated on a machine made of the material energy." 1 5 As
we have already mentioned, the materially embodied jīvātmā is in an
essentially passive state, unable directly to influence the actions of the .
material body. Yet the jīvātmā is conscious of the bodily situation and filled
with desires relating to the outcome of various bodily activities. According
to the Bhagavad-gītā, the Supreme Person perceives the desires of the e m - '
bodied beings and responds to these desires by appropriately controlling
the bodily machinery.
The manifestation of the Supreme Person within the heart of every living
being is known as the paramātmā, or Supersoul. "Although the Supersoul
appears to be divided," says the Bhagavad-gītā, "He is never divided. He
is situated as one." 1 6 This is another illustration of the simultaneous one
ness and multiplicity of the Supreme Person, which we discussed in Chap
ter 6. Since the Supreme Person possesses unlimited consciousness, He is
able to attend simultaneously to innumerable material situations without
becoming confused.
The Supreme Person, as understood from the Bhagavad-gītā, is not
remote from the material world. Rather, He is all-pervading in space and
time and is also transcendental to space and time. This idea may seem para
doxical, but we should note that a similar problem arises when we try to
visualize the reality underlying the laws of nature as conceived in modern
physics. These laws are postulated as spatially and temporally invariant;
but what is it that pervades all space and time and determines that gravita
tion, for example, will operate according to a certain universal force
constant, G?
In our day-to-day experience we desire to perform various physical ac
tions, and we generally find that the body immediately acts in accordance
with our desires. Although we do not understand how our will gives rise to
action, this seems to happen automatically, and we normally take it for
180 On Inspiration
Notes
4. Ibid.
5. H a d a m a r d , p. 16.
6. Poincare, p. 390.
7. Poincare, p. 391.
8. H a d a m a r d , p. 118.
9. H a d a m a r d , p. 120.
The Doctrine
Of Evolution
" A l l reputable evolutionary biologists now agree that the evolution of
1
life is directed by the process of natural selection, and by nothing else."
With these words Sir Julian Huxley summed up the consensus of learned
opinion at the Darwin Centennial Celebration in 1959.
Among the eminent biologists and evolutionists attending the cele-
bration , great confidence prevailed that the origin of living species was now
almost fully understood. Evolutionists had clearly established that all
living organisms had gradually evolved through small variations in form
and function, slowly accumulating, generation by generation, over a vast
span of geological time. Geneticists had shown that all biological varia-
tions arose from random genetic accidents called mutations. Evolutionary
theorists, building on this finding, had clearly identified Darwinian natural
selection as the sole guiding force that sorted out these variations and
thereby molded the diverse forms of living beings. Although many minute
details certainly remained to be worked out, scientists believed they had
arrived at an essentially complete understanding of life and its historical
development.
With this striking unanimity of established scientific opinion reached lit-
tle more than two decades ago, perhaps we are surprised to hear that the
theory of evolution has recently become the focus of a great controversy
among evolutionists themselves. The last few years have seen the estab-
lished theory of mutation and natural selection increasingly challenged by
critical studies and dissenting interpretations of the evidence. The theory
has clearly shown itself unsound, although scientists have thus far been
unable to devise an acceptable new theory to replace it.
Recently this controversy became a near battle, when some 150 promi-
nent evolutionists gathered at Chicago's Field Museum of Natural History
to thrash out various conflicting hypotheses about the nature of evolution.
After four days of heated discussions (closed to all but a few outside ob-
servers), the evolutionists remained convinced that evolution is a fact.
Unfortunately, however, they could not reach a clear understanding of
just what this fact is. According to a report from The New York Times, the
183
184 The Doctrine of Evolution
forms required by his theory must have existed, but they had left no recog-
nizable traces in the fossil deposits known in his time. Darwin suggested
that further research would undoubtably uncover many of these missing
forms, and their discovery would vindicate his theory.
For many years orthodox evolutionary opinion has adhered to Darwin's
basic views. But dissenting voices have increasingly been heard. At the re-
cent meeting of evolutionists in Chicago, Niles Eldridge, a paleontologist
from the American Museum of Natural History in New York, declared,
3
"The pattern we were told to find for the last 120 years does not exist."
Despite intense effort, several generations of paleontologists have found
few examples in which one fossil species seems to transform gradually into
another, and some researchers say none at all have been found.
As a result, Eldridge, Steven J. Gould, and several other prominent
paleontologists now propose that species have not actually arisen by a slow
process of transformation. As an alternative, they have devised what they
4
call the theory of "punctuated equilibrium." According to this theory,
evolutionary changes take place in short bursts separated by long periods
during which the forms of living organisms remain static. A typical species
will arise from an earlier species in a "geological microsecond"—a period
of a few thousand years that appears like an instant from the multimillion-
year perspective of geological time. Also, a species will not arise through a
gradual modification of its parent population. Rather, it will arise when a
Figure 1. The Darwinian theory of evolution states that species have developed
gradually, as illustrated by the branching tree pattern (a). But the fossil record does
not substantiate this pattern of development. As a result, some paleontologists
have introduced the "punctuated equilibrium" model, shown in (b), in which the
transitions between species are officially invisible.
186 The Doctrine of Evolution
tiny group that has been isolated from the main population, perhaps by a
geographical barrier, is rapidly transformed.
One consequence of the theory of punctuated equilibrium is that it
makes the evolution of species officially invisible. On one hand, we cannot
expect the fossil record to show how a new species evolved, for the evolu-
tion takes place in a tiny population during a geological "microsecond." On
the other hand, we cannot expect to see a new species evolve within the re-
corded span of human history, for a geological microsecond of 10,000 to
50,000 years is still immensely long when measured in human lifetimes.
Of course, we may possibly observe small-scale changes in organisms,
like those produced through controlled breeding, or like the famous
change in color exhibited by the peppered moths of industrial England. Yet
such changes are known to be reversible, and at most they result in only
minor variations within a species. For example, settlers introduced domes-
ticated rabbits into Australia in 1788, and some escaped and flourished in
the wild. Despite the effects of breeding by humans, these domesticated
rabbits were still classed as rabbits, and today their descendants have
5
reverted to their ancestral form: they look exactly like wild rabbits.
Explaining superficial variations of this kind is not the* real problem con-
fronting evolutionists. The real problem is explaining how higher forms of
plants and animals have arisen from lower forms, and how these in turn
have arisen from inanimate matter. No large-scale transformations of this
kind have ever been observed within the brief span of human history. The
orthodox Darwinian theory maintained that such transformations should
be directly visible in the fossil record. But the theory of punctuated equilib-
rium says we should not expect even the fossil record to show these trans-
formations. In fact, the actual process that brings about new species of life
has always been invisible. Now, in the new theory propounded by Eldridge
and Gould, this process is held to be invisible even in principle.
Even though the transitional stages between species are officially invisi-
ble according to the punctuated equilibrium model, one might still wonder
whether or not the fossil record shows a large-scale progression from primi-
tive to advanced life forms that appears reasonably continuous. When we
examine a half-tone picture under a magnifying glass, we see an array of
disconnected dots; but when we view the picture at a distance, these dots
seem to merge together to form a continuous image. Similarly, we might
expect the disjointed succession of life forms in the fossil record to merge
The Fossil Record and the Origin of Higher Plants 187
Period
boundaries
Epoch in millions
Era Period numbers of years
onward, the angiosperms have been the dominant land plants throughout
the world.
In contrast, in the strata antedating the Albian epoch paleontologists
have found very little unambiguous evidence for the existence of flowering
plants. There are some fossils, which suggest that angiosperms may have
8
existed in the Jurassic and Triassic periods. However, the compilers of
the standard reference used to draw Figure 2 apparently did not feel that
this evidence justified the inclusion of Jurassic or Triassic angiosperms in
their list of fossil families. In fact, according to this reference, two families
of angiosperms date from epochs 23 and 2 1 , and all other families appear in
epoch 20 or later.
Here we seem to have "punctuated equilibrium" with a vengeance. In a
span of some 12 million years, the flowering plants rise from a position of
complete insignificance to one of world dominance. Could this be due to an
exceedingly intense burst of evolutionary diversification? In fact, the gen-
eral opinion of paleontologists is that the angiosperms could not have
evolved so quickly. The prevailing view is that the angiosperms must have
gradually evolved in some part of the world where, for many millions of
years, they left no significant fossil remains. Then in the late Cretacious
The Fossil Record and the Origin of Higher Plants 189
period they suddenly migrated en masse into the regions where their
remains are now found in abundance.
According to the paleontologist Daniel Axelrod, "The belief that early
angiosperm evolution took place in upland regions, in areas sufficiently re-
mote from lowland basins of deposition to have precluded their occurrence
9
in the record, is now generally conceded." Axelrod argues that upland re-
gions tend to be subjected to intense erosion, which quickly destroys any
fossils that might accumulate there. This implies that with the exception of
very recent highland deposits that have not yet been eroded, the highlands
of the world have not been represented in the existing fossil record.
Axelrod suggests that the entire evolutionary history of the flowering
plants took place in these unrecorded upland areas. He observes, "The an-
cestral group that gave rise to angiosperms has not yet been identified in
the fossil record, and no living angiosperm points to such an ancestral al-
10
liance." He also notes that the fossil record gives no indication of the
evolutionary relationship between different types of flowering plants: " I n
addition the record has shed almost no light on relations between taxa at
ordinal and family l e v e l . " " A l l evidence of these evolutionary relation-
ships was presumably obliterated by the erosion of the highlands in which
the early angiosperms exclusively lived.
Now, flowering plants may well have flourished in the highland regions
of the world prior to the Albian epoch of the Cretacious. However, it is
completely unscientific for paleontologists to try to save the theory of
evolution by maintaining that they evolved there. If this procedure is al-
lowed, then the theory of evolution becomes unfalsifiable. When evidence
for the evolution of a particular life form is lacking, it is easy to propose that
the missing evolutionary steps took place under circumstances that pre-
cluded the formation of a permanent record of the process. Such vacuous
proposals can explain anything, but for this very reason they have no place
in a scientific account of the world. Unfortunately, as we have already seen
in our discussion of the theory of punctuated equilibrium, it has become a
standard practice for paleontologists to claim that critical evolutionary
steps have occurred without leaving a record.
Now that we have identified one unscientific practice of the evolution-
ists, it may not be out of place here to point out a complementary practice
that is also unscientific. This is the procedure of setting aside and ignoring
evidence that does not fit into a particular evolutionary scheme. For exam-
ple, many paleontologists believe that the angiosperms must have had a
long evolutionary history prior to the Cretacious period, and thus they
would be willing to accept earlier fossil evidence of flowering plants. But
The Fossil Record and the Origin of Higher Plants 191
what would they say about evidence for the existence of flowering plants,
say two billion years ago?.
12
According to the standard scenario presented in textbooks and popu-
13
lar accounts , all higher vascular plants, including the angiosperms,
evolved from the psilophytes, an extremely primitive type of plant that
flourished in the upper Silurian and lower Devonian periods. The preced-
ing periods of the Paleozoic era are represented in the fossil record only by
marine deposits, and evolutionists generally suppose that life had not yet
ernerged from the seas during these periods. Prior to the Cambrian period,
the fossil record is very scanty, and evolutionists maintain that throughout
most of this time, life existed only in the form of single-celled organisms
14
such as algae and bacteria.
Yet there is evidence that flowering plants may have existed during this
time. According to a report in Nature, angiosperm pollen has been found
in Pre-Cambrian rock on the frontier between Venezuela and British
15
Guiana. This rock has been dated by radiometric methods, and has been
16 7
assigned ages of 2,090 m i l l i o n and 1,710 m i l l i o n ' years.
If this report can be taken at face value, it completely upsets the accepted
scientific picture of the origin and evolution of life. If flowering plants were
existing at a time far antedating all known remains of higher organisms,
then the standard evolutionary interpretation of the fossil record must be
mistaken. The obvious implication is that there must have existed Pre-
Cambrian continental regions that were occupied by many different types
of higher organisms, but that were totally destroyed in the course of time.
Such regions can, of course, be compared with the "highlands" posited by
Axelrod to explain the sudden appearance of the angiosperms in the more
recent portion of the fossil record. In this case the evidence directly implies
the existence of such regions, but it still leaves us in the dark as to the mode
of origin of the higher organisms that lived there.
It is perhaps not surprising that evolutionists do not accept evidence that
so blatantly contradicts their theories. Yet the report we have just dis-
cussed is not an isolated instance. There are, in fact, many reports of pol-
len and spores from sedimentary formations antedating the periods in
which the evolution of higher plants is commonly believed to have taken
place. Indeed, there are evolutionists who have accepted some of this evi-
dence and have tried to incorporate it into various modified evolutionary
schemes.
An example of this is provided by a paper by Axelrod that appeared in
18
the journal Evolution in 1959. Therein he cites several reports of spores
and fragments of wood that have been assigned to the Cambrian period.
192 The Doctrine of Evolution
Some of these spores were found in Kashmir and have been identified as
pteridophytes (ferns), pteridosperms (seed ferns), and gymnosperms (the
19
category of plants including the conifers, or pine trees). Axelrod uses this
and other evidence to completely overturn the standard theory that higher
plants have evolved from Silurian and Devonian psilophytes. He argues
that the different groups of higher plants must all have evolved indepen-
dently from algal ancestors in the Cambrian or earlier. (Axelrod does not
mention, by the way, that angiosperm pollen has also been reported in the
20
Cambrian strata of Kashmir. )
These proposals have apparently not found widespread acceptance, for
current textbooks still expound the psilophyte theory. This becomes espe-
cially interesting when we consider one particular piece of evidence that
Axelrod cites to disprove this theory. According to him, some of the early
Devonian psilophyte fossils are accompanied by fossils of Callixylon logs
21
that are up to three feet in diameter. Callixylon is a type of conifer. One
would think that this fact, if true, would certainly cast doubt on the theory
that all higher plants are descended from these psilophytes.
We can conclude that there is considerable uncertainty anil ambiguity in
our current knowledge of the origin and ancient history of the higher
plants. The fossil record can only be made to support an evolutionary inter-
pretation by the introduction of unverifiable hypotheses. There are also
cases where evidence conflicting with established evolutionary scenarios
seems to have been ignored, or even suppressed. We note that similar
points can also be made about the fossil record of past animal life, although
we do not have enough space to discuss this here.
of motion that specifically carries the nematocyst to the worm's dorsal re-
gion. These are both complex procedures. Yet for the flatworm to take ad-
vantage of the hydra's nematocysts, it would seem that many complex
arrangements of this kind must be present simultaneously.
It is hard to see how complicated, interlocking arrangements such as the
microstomum's defensive system could have evolved by many small steps
in the traditional Darwinian manner. Darwin himself maintained, " I f it
could be demonstrated that any complex organ existed which could not
possibly have been formed by numerous, successive, slight modifications,
25
my theory would absolutely break d o w n . " Yet what possible sequence of
intermediate forms could span the gap between an ordinary flatworm and
a flatworm capable of deploying stolen nematocysts for its own defense?
It would seem that we are confronted with one of two alternatives: either
(1) some of these hypothetical intermediate forms must have useless or
deleterious features, or (2) some of these forms must be separated by large
gaps corresponding to many simultaneous modifications. It is quite pos- *
sible that a series of intermediate forms of the kind required by Darwin
simply does not exist.
Many organs are so complex that we do not clearly understand how
they work. One might think that evolutionists would refrain from offering
evolutionary explanations for such organs. Unfortunately, it is precisely
in these cases, where our understanding is vague and incomplete, that
evolutionists seem most eager to explain origins by waving the wand of
Darwinian natural selection. For example, one prominent exponent of the
evolutionary viewpoint has argued in a popular presentation that a mere in-
26
crease in size can transform an ape's brain into a human b r a i n . He claims
this could be accomplished by the natural selection of a series of slight pro-
longations of the period of foetal brain growth. But can a mere increase in
brain size account for the difference in mentality between human beings
and apes? It is possible to entertain such fantasies only because we are now
almost entirely ignorant of how the brain works.
Simpler organs are easier to analyze, and we can frequently see, as we
did in the case of microstomum, that they are not amenable to explanation
by traditional evolutionary concepts. To illustrate this, we will briefly
consider three additional examples of simple organ systems.
Our first example is provided by the statocyst of a certain species of
27
shrimp. The statocyst is a hollow, fluid-filled sphere built into the
shrimp's shell. It is lined with cells bearing pressure-sensitive hairs, and it
contains a small weight. The weight tends to sink and press against the
downward portion of the sphere, thus enabling the shrimp to tell up from
196 The Doctrine of Evolution
down. Curiously, the weight is a small grain of sand that the shrimp picks
up with its claws and inserts into the statocyst through a small hole in its
shell. Since the statocyst is built into the shell, the shrimp has to do this
every time it moults.
Now, by what intermediate stages could the shrimp's statocyst have
arisen? Both the statocyst and the behavioral pattern involved in picking
up the grain of sand are quite complex, and neither is of any use without the
other. Even if the statocyst had evolved with a built-in weight and then had
lost this feature by a mutation, the appearance of the insertion behavior
would require a leap involving the coordination of many variables.
For our second example we turn to the bacterium Escherichia coli, an
organism that is thought to be very low on the evolutionary scale. Each
E. coli bacterium possesses several long, helically curved fibers (called
28
flagella) that enable it to s w i m . Each flagellum is connected at one end to
a kind of motor built into the bacterial cell wall. When these motors rotate
in a certain direction, the flagella rotate in unison and act as propellers to
drive the bacterium forward through the water. When the motors rotate in
the opposite direction, the flagella separate and change the orientation of
the bacterium by pulling in various ways. By systematically alternating be-
tween these two modes of operation, the bacterium is able to swim from
undesirable to desirable regions of its environment.
Some investigators have proposed that the motors are driven by a flux of
29
protons flowing into the c e l l . According to them, each motor consists of
a ring of sixteen protein molecules attached to an axle and a stationary ring
of sixteen proteins built into the cell wall. Protons are steadily pumped out
of the cell by its normal metabolic processes. As some of these protons flow
back into the cell through the pairs of rings, they impart a rotary motion to
the movable ring. Since the motor can operate in forward or reverse, there
must be some mechanism that adjusts the configuration of the molecules in
the rings so as to reverse the torque produced by the flow of ions.
Although the exact details of the E. coli's molecular motors have not yet
been worked out, we can see that their operation depends on the precise,
simultaneous adjustment of many variables. Even though these motors are
fairly simple in structure, it is very hard to imagine a continuum of useful
forms spanning the gap between a motorless cell and a cell with a fully func-
tional motor. It is quite possible that no such continuum of forms exists, or
that such a continuum must involve intermediate structures much more
complicated than the existing molecular motors. In any event, we presently
have no idea how the E. coli's motors could have evolved. Indeed, the
problem becomes even more difficult when we consider that these motors
The Ressurrection of the Hopeful Monster 197
are useless without their control systems, and the control systems are
useless without the motors.
For our final example we consider a kind of marine invertebrate called a
sea slug. Certain of these sea slugs are able to steal the nematocysts from
sea anemones (a marine creature similar to the hydra) and use them for
3
their own defense. " Their system is quite similar to that of microstomum,
except that instead of transporting the nematocysts by special migratory
cells, the sea slugs move them into position by sweeping them through
narrow ciliated tubes that pass from their stomachs to their backs.
Now, the sea slug is a mollusc, and therefore cannot be closely related
to the flatworm, microstomum. Evolutionists customarily explain the exis-
tence of similar traits in ostensibly unrelated organisms by invoking the
idea of convergent evolution. According to this idea, the forces of evolu-
tion will automatically produce similar effects in similar circumstances. But
the problem we face here is that by the hypothesis of gradual evolutionary
change, we cannot explain the origin of the defensive system of either the
sea slug or microstomum.
I am in thick mud; the orthodox would say in fetid abominable mud. I believe I
am in much the same frame of mind as an old gorilla would be in if set to learn
the first book of Euclid. The old gorilla would say it was no manner of use; yet
14
I cannot keep out of the question.
In our artificial genetic system, the numbers in parentheses play the role
of regulatory genes, and the phrases play the role of structural genes. If we
mutate the regulatory gene (4), changing it to (3), we shall observe a
change in Darwin's statements similar to the aristapedia mutation of fruit
flies. (We invite the reader to try this and observe the effects.) Also, when
we examine the genetic system closely, we find that a mutation has changed
one regulatory gene to ( ). If we convert this gene to (6), Darwin's state-
ment apparently acquires an entirely new sentence, although all that has
actually happened is that the complete text of the original has been
restored.
We can thus see that various kinds of large-scale effects result from
mutations in the regulatory genes of our artificial system. Yet all of these
effects have one thing in common. They all involve the manipulation of ma-
terial already present in the genetic system. To induce the system to
produce something entirely new is a different matter.
For example, we invite the reader to try to find mutations that will ex-
pand Darwin's remarks to include the following statement from his Origin
of Species.
Such a hoof, which is fitted to the limb like a die protecting the third phalanx,
can without rubber or springs buffer impacts which sometimes exceed one
ton. It could not have formed by mere chance: a close examination of the
structure of the hoof reveals that it is a storehouse of coaptations and of or-
ganic novelties. The horny wall, by it's vertical keratophyl laminae, is fused
with the podophyl laminae of the keratogenous layer. The respective lengths
of the bones, their mode of articulation, the curves and shapes of the articular
surfaces, the structure of bones (orientation, arrangement of the bony layers),
the presence of ligaments, tendons sliding with sheaths, buffer cushions,
navicular bone, synovial membranes with their serous lubricating liquid,
all imply a continuity in the construction which random events, necessarily
36
chaotic and incomplete, could not have produced and maintained.
The author of this description is observing that the horse's hoof has many
complex, intricately interrelated features that can hardly be accounted for
by random mutations in either structural or regulatory genes. To design a
regulative gene system that would allow for the quick production of such an
elaborate structure, much work would be required—perhaps as much
work as would be needed to design the hoof completely from scratch. Here
our engineer would have no recourse but to directly confront a difficult
problem in complex design. This, of course, is possible for an intelligent en-
gineer, but no one has yet shown how it could be accomplished by a blind
evolutionary process.
The baleen whales provide another example of how regulative genes could
202 The Doctrine of Evolution
groping for such a theory in the realms of speculation and vague conjec-
ture. We are therefore led to ask: In the absence of both observation and
theory, what has convinced scientists to accept what we can only call the
doctrine of evolution?
One important line of reasoning that has led many persons to adopt an
evolutionary point of view could be called the argument by negative theol-
ogy. Darwin himself used this argument extensively, and since his time it
has been a mainstay of evolutionary thought.
In a recent popular book, the paleontologist Steven J. Gould presents
one form of the negative theological argument in these words: " O d d ar-
rangements and funny solutions are the proof of evolution—paths that a
sensible God would never tread but that a natural process, constrained by
38
history, follows perforce." The general form of the argument can be out-
lined as follows: " G o d must have certain characteristics, X, and therefore
v
He would have created a certain sort of world. Since the world as we see it i s
very different from this, it must be that there is no God. Since the only
alternative to divine creation that we can think of is evolution, life must «
have arisen by some kind of evolutionary process."
This argument has two basic forms. One of these is the traditional ar-
gument from evil against the existence of God. According to this argu-
ment, the existence of many kinds of suffering, both in the human species
and in the plant and animal kingdoms, is inconsistent with the idea that
the world was created by an all-powerful, benevolent being. In contrast,
such suffering seems to fit naturally into the evolutionary world view. %
The second form of the argument is that many features of living organ-
isms would not, as Gould says, be designed by a "sensible G o d " and must
therefore be due to evolution. An example of this sort of argument is pro-
vided by Darwin's work with orchids. Darwin observed that the petals of
these flowers are deployed in many remarkable arrangements, which in-
sure that visiting insects will carry pollen from one flower to another. Yet
since modified petals, rather than a completely novel kind of structure, are
used in these arrangements, Darwin argued that divine creation was ruled
out and that the orchids must therefore be products of evolution. In the
words of Gould, " I f God had designed a beautiful machine to reflect his
wisdom and power, surely he would not have used a collection of parts
39
generally fashioned for other purposes."
What can we say about these arguments? We can immediately dismiss
both versions of the negative theological argument as scientifically un-
sound, for they are based on completely speculative ideas about the pur-
poses of God and the methods He uses to achieve them. We have pointed
204 The Doctrine of Evolution
out before that while reasoning that rests on a finite set of material observa
tions may confirm a given theory about God, such reasoning cannot prove
the theory to be true. The same observation can be made about negative
arguments that depend on a particular theological theory. In the negative
theological argument the initial premise, "God must have certain charac
teristics, X," has never even been clearly formulated by the evolutionists,
and such a premise has certainly never been proven by them, either by logic
or by induction from observations. It is also hardly necessary to point out
that the second premise of this argument—the premise that evolution is the
only alternative to divine creation—has also never been proven.
The negative theological argument is dependent on a painfully naive and
limited conception of God, and it collapses as soon as a more satisfactory
conception is introduced. We have already seen an example of this in our
discussion of the horse's toes and the embryonic teeth of the whale.
Evolutionists argue that a "sensible G o d " would never produce such aber
rations, but we have seen that these bodily structures can readily be inter
preted as byproducts of the design strategy of a master engineer. The key to
this interpretation is the realization that God does not necessarily intend
the material world as an exhibition of His finest worksmanship.
What is the purpose of the material world? The evolutionists have
adopted a mechanistic world view that excludes the very idea of purpose,
but at the same time some of them cling to a certain conception of what
God's purposes would be if He existed. Yet theirs is not the only conception
that is possible. To demonstrate this, we will outline the understanding of
the purpose of the material world presented in the Bhagavad-gītā.
According to the Bhagavad-gītā, one can understand the purpose of the
material creation through the concept of free will. The natural relationship
between the jīvātmā and Krsna is one of loving reciprocal service, and love
can exist only for one who has freedom. The jīvātmā is free to turn away
from his relationship with the Supreme Person and seek to be independent,
and Krsna creates the material world as a place where the jīvātmā can do
this. Here the jīvātmā becomes temporarily forgetful of his true nature and
40
transmigrates from body to body in various species of life.
Therefore, the material world is a place of suffering. The conditioned
living beings, deprived of their central object of devotion, inevitably have
clashing interests, and become intense sources of misery for one another.
This misery is a byproduct of the more fundamental misery of ignorance
and forgetfulness that characterizes the material world, and is exhibited in
various degrees of severity in various forms of embodied life.
The bodies of the living species are temporary vehicles designed to ac
commodate sentient beings in various states of forgetful consciousness.
Evolution and Negative Theology 205
Since all of these forms represent limitations on the true nature of the
jīvātmā, it is not surprising that they should be crafted in a rough and ready
manner. It is also not surprising that the living species should show sys
tematic similarities in bodily structure. A l l organic forms correspond to
states of consciousness of one fundamental type of being, and, in principle,
they can all be understood systematically in psychological terms.
According to the Bhagavad-gītā, the miserable conditions in the ma
terial world are due neither to malevolence nor to poor design on the part of
the creator. Rather, they are consequences of the free will of the jīvātmā
himself, and they can be alleviated on an individual basis by the proper
exercise of free will. In Chapter 9 we will discuss this in greater detail. Here
we simply note that the negative theological argument of the evolutionists
does not apply to the world system of the Bhagavad-gītā—at least, not as
the argument stands. Evolutionists would do well to examine the hidden
metaphysical assumptions of their argument, and consider whether or not
such an argument can serve as the basis for a scientific theory.
If we closely examine the negative theological argument, we find that it
seems to originate not from logical considerations, but from a sense of deep
dissatisfaction with the theological conceptions that form its real founda
tion. These conceptions are inherited from Western religious systems that
the evolutionists, beginning with Darwin, have emphatically rejected. Pre
sentations of the theory of evolution are often permeated with an attitude
of contempt for these religious systems, and the negative theological argu
ment, in particular, often takes the form of an emotional tirade directed
against the idea of divine creation.
When we consider the irrational character of such presentations in light
of the observational and theoretical weaknesses of evolutionary thought,
the "theory" of evolution seems little more than a poorly reasoned intellec
tual reaction against a spiritual tradition that was perceived as inadequate.
Unfortunately, it has also been an entirely futile reaction, for the evolu
tionists have succeeded neither in providing a genuine alternative source of
spiritual knowledge nor in establishing a workable material explanation for
the origin of life.
The role the negative theological argument plays in the theory of evolu
tion becomes clear when we consider the historical context in which this
theory arose. When Darwin published his Origin of Species in 1859, scien
tific thought in Europe had been dominated for many years by an approach
to spiritual knowledge known as natural theology. According to this ap- -
proach, one can deduce from observations of natural phenomena that the
world has been created by a supremely intelligent, benevolent, and all- ,
powerful being. Pointing to the highly organized plans of living beings, the
The Doctrine of Evolution
being. But the answer to this problem is not to deny the existence of such a
being and to seek explanations solely in familiar physical principles. This is
the fallacy of the drunk who lost his keys near the doorstep of his house but
would search for them only under a streetlamp because the light was better
there.
Notes
3. Ibid.
4. Gould and Eldridge, "Punctuated Equilibria: T h e T e m p o and M o d e of
Evolution Reconsidered," p p . 115-151.
7. Ibid.
8. A n d r e w s , Studies in Paleobotany, chap. 6.
11. Ibid.
35. D a r w i n , p. 184.
36. G r a s s e , p. 5 1 .
38. Ibid., p p . 2 0 - 2 1 .
39. Ibid.
CONCLUSION
Chapter 9
The Epistemology
Of Transcendental
Consciousness
In a letter to Max B o r n , Albert Einstein expressed his faith as a physicist:
You believe in the God who plays dice, and I in complete law and order in
a world which objectively exists, and which I, in a wildly speculative way,
am trying to capture. I firmly believe, but T hope that someone will discover
a more realistic way, or rather a more tangible basis than it has been my lot
to do.'
to account for them must be just as complex and arbitrary as the patterns
themselves.
While the complex bodily structures of living organisms cannot be con
cisely explained in mechanistic terms, at least they can be quantitatively
described. In Part I of this book, however, we discussed another feature of
life—the phenomenon of conscious awareness—that is not even touched
upon by descriptions of the measurable behavior of matter.
We customarily associate consciousness with certain states of activity in
"conscious living bodies," but since we directly perceive our own con
sciousness, consciousness must be more than just a name for particular pat
terns of behavior. One may say that this perception is subjective, but if we
are to avoid the position of solipsism, we must accept the consciousness of
others to be an objective fact of nature. This objectively existing conscious
ness must be distinguished from the behavior of matter. Indeed, if we
analyze the functioning of material systems such as the brain, we see that
the contents of our consciousness cannot be correlated in a one-to-one
fashion with measurable events in such systems. (See Chapters 2 and 3.)
Consciousness is thus a feature of reality that is impossible to capture by
mechanistic laws, either simple or complex.
The phenomena of consciousness and complex form stand as insurmount
able obstacles blocking any attempt to capture the world by a quantitative
theory. To find a successful approach to understanding reality, we must
therefore depart from the mechanistic framework of modern science. In
this book we have taken a step in this direction by outlining an alternative,
nonmechanistic world view based on the Bhagavad-gītā, the Bhāgavata
Purāna, and other Vedic literatures of India.
The world view of the Bhagavad-gītā is based on the postulate that con
scious personality is the ultimate basis of reality. Thus far we have intro
duced some of the elements of this world view by briefly describing two
fundamental categories of conscious beings. The first category has a sin
gle member—the unique Supreme Person, Krsna, who is the primordial
cause of all causes, and who is directly conscious of all phenomena. The
second category consists of the innumerable localized conscious beings, or
jīvātmās. The jīvātmās are irreducible conscious persons, and they are
qualitatively the same as the Supreme Person. Yet they differ from the
Supreme in that they are minute and dependent, whereas the Supreme
Person is unlimited and fully independent.
The nature of the jīvātmās is discussed in Chapters 1, 2, and 3, and the
Supreme Person is described in Chapter 6. Chapter 7 discusses the rela
tionship between the Supreme Person, the jīvātmās, and the material
The Epistemology of Transcendental Consciousness 213
senses of the jīvātmā are not limited to picking up information from the
sensory apparatus of a particular material body. Indeed, a jīvātmā in this
situation is considered to be in an abnormal condition, and can be com
pared to a person who has become so engrossed in watching a television
program that he has forgotten about his own existence, and has accepted
the flickering two-dimensional image on the television screen to be the all
in all. The jīvātmā is capable of directly perceiving both other jīvātmās and
the Supreme Person, although in the bodily state of existence, he is pre
vented from doing this by his preoccupation with the fascinating show
presented by the bodily senses.
It follows that our model can be verified if a way can be found to re
awaken the full cognitive capacities of the conscious self. In this chapter we
will outline a practical method of doing this known as bhakti-yoga, or devo
tional service. We will present this process as a method of obtaining reliable
knowledge about aspects of reality that are inaccessible by traditional
methods of scientific research. We should note, however, that bhakti-yoga
is not simply a method of obtaining knowledge. Rather, it is a means
whereby each individual conscious self can attain the ultimate goal of his
existence.
relationship develops between the person and Krsna. One secondary con
sequence of this relationship is that by directly contacting the Supreme
Person, the person is placed in touch with the source of all knowledge.
The goal of bhakti-yoga is to purify the person's consciousness so that his
natural relationship with the Supreme can be reawakened. This comes
about through the performance of practical devotional service to Krsna.
Just as a lame person can regain the ability to walk by practicing walking,
so a person in material consciousness can revive his relationship of loving
service to Krsna by actually beginning to practice such service. This can be
accomplished if an initial link can be established that enables the person to
actually serve Krsna through the activities performed by his material body.
A number of important considerations are involved in establishing this
link, and we will discuss these briefly, one at a time.
First we shall discuss the bearing of a person's inner attitudes on his
chances for success in the search for knowledge. The world view of modern
science rests on the idea thatjiature is a product of impersonal processes
that lie within the reach'bf human understanding. Following this idea, *
many scientists view nature as a passive object of conquest and exploita-
tion, and they try to extract the secrets of nature forcibly by the power of
their minds and senses. The theories of modern science are consonant with ,
a domineering and aggressive attitude, and it can be argued that their
development has been strongly influenced by a desire to accommodate
such an attitude.
In contrast, bhakti-yoga is based on the idea that nature is the product of
a supreme intelligence that is beyond the understanding of the human
mind. The approach of bhakti-yoga is not to dominate this intelligence, but
rather to cooperate with it. It is not possible for a person to acquire
real knowledge about Krsna by the power of his limited mind. The key
to bhakti-yoga is that by the mercy of Krsna, such knowledge is readily
available to a person who approaches H i m with a sincerely favorable
attitude.
The quality of this attitude is indicated in the following statement spoken
by Krsna to Arjuna in the Bhagavad-gītā:
Always think of Me and become My devotee. Worship Me and offer your
homage unto Me. Thus you will come to Me without fail. I promise you this
because you are My very dear friend. 3
favorable attitude toward the absolute, then by the mercy of the absolute,
the person's internal and external circumstances will gradually be so ad
justed that absolute knowledge becomes accessible to him. The essential
element is the change in attitude. In the beginning a person may have only
the vaguest conception of what the absolute truth may be, but if he adopts
a truly positive attitude toward the absolute, then he will eventually be
able to reciprocate personally with the absolute in a mutual relationship of
love and trust.
This brings us to our second consideration. If a person is initially limited
to his ordinary bodily senses as sources of information, then how can he
make the first step in obtaining transcendental knowledge? Also, if his
ultimate objective is to serve the transcendental Supreme Person, then
how can he do this when his activities are limited to the manipulation of
matter? The answer to these questions is that Krsna is able to reciprocate
with an embodied jīvātmā in two important ways—internally as the all-
pervading Supersoul, and externally through the agency of another em
bodied person who is already connected with H i m in a transcendental
relationship.
Such a person is known as a guru, or spiritual master. The guru is
described in the following way in the Bhagavad-gītā:
Just try to learn the truth by approaching a spiritual master. Inquire from him
submissively and render service unto him. The self-realized soul can impart
knowledge unto you because he has seen the truth. 4
Since the guru is in direct contact with Krsna, he can act as Krsna's repre
sentative. The guru can make information about Krsna available to the
people in general through the medium of the written and spoken word, and
he can also accept service on behalf of Krsna. According to the system of
bhakti-yoga, a person can begin to serve Krsna by accepting a genuine
guru, hearing about Krsna from him, and rendering service to him. Service
to the guru is accepted by Krsna as direct service to Himself, and He recip
rocates by enlightening the person with the knowledge that he needs to
make further advancement on the path of bhakti-yoga.
The process of bhakti-yoga is summed up by the following statement in
the Caitanya-caritāmrta:
Krsna is situated in everyone's heart as caitya-guru, the spiritual master
within. When He is kind to some fortunate conditioned soul, He personally
gives that person lessons in how to progress in devotional service, instructing
the person as the Supersoul within and the spiritual master without. 5
In the initial stages of this process, the aspiring candidate depends almost
Faith, Subjectivity, and Verifiability 217
entirely on the guidance supplied to him externally through the guru. How-
ever, through service to the guru, the candidate's link with Krsna is estab-
lished, and his own natural relationship with Krsna is gradually awakened.
At this point we should make a few observations about the role of faith in
bhakti-yoga. It is often said that religion is based either on subjective ex-
periences that cannot be verified by other persons, or on received doctrines
that cannot be verified at all. The charge is therefore made that religion is a
matter of blind faith. We should stress that this charge does not apply to the
process of bhakti-yoga, for bhakti-yoga is based on verifiable observation.
It is true that the realizations attained by this process cannot be verified by
means of ordinary sense perception. But they can be verified by other
persons who are also capable of exercising their higher sensory capacities.
In Chapter 3 we illustrated this point by the example of two seeing per-
sons observing a sunset in the presence of a congenitally blind person. The
seeing persons are able to discuss what they see, and each will feel confi-
dent that both he and the other person really are witnessing a sunset. If
necessary, they can confirm this by consulting other seeing persons. In
contrast, the congenitally blind person cannot verify the existence of the
sunset, and he is probably unable to form a realistic conception of what it
would be like to see it. He can either accept the existence of sunsets on
blind faith, reject their existence with equal blindness, or else declare '
himself to be an agnostic.
One might say that it is unfair for a few people to lay claim to knowledge
that can only be obtained by methods not available to people in general.
However, this charge is actually more applicable to certain fields of
modern science than it is to bhakti-yoga. For example, physicists use multi-
million-dollar particle accelerators and elaborate techniques of mathe-
matical analysis to demonstrate the existence of certain "fundamental"
particles. Yet the common man has no access to such expensive equipment,
and he does not have the knowledge needed to properly use it. Since these
assets are very difficult to acquire, the common man has no choice but to
accept the findings of the physicists on faith. Nonetheless, the physicists are
confident that they can verify one another's observations, and they would
not accept the charge that their conclusions are invalid because they cannot
be checked by laymen.
For a given class of observations to be considered objective, the general
rule is that there must be a group of responsible people who are capable of
218 The Epistemology of Transcendental Consciousness
capable of doing this. Since the jīvātmā with uncontrolled senses has no
direct access to the Supreme Person, he is prone to indulge in fanciful
speculations that simply lead him further and further from the truth.
and even though this material system can function independently of the
brain, it tends to become dependent on the brain for the execution of
certain data-processing operations.
Taken together, the material body and mind can be regarded as a kind
of false self in which the real self rides as a passenger. This false self is not
conscious in its own right. Both the brain and the material mind can be re-
' garded as mechanisms for symbol manipulation comparable with man-
made computers. The "thoughts" of the material mind are mere patterns of
' symbols, and they become represented by actual thoughts only when they
are perceived by the jīvātmā. The tendency of the embodied jīvātmā, how
ever, is to accept the thoughts, feelings, and desires of the material mind
as his own, and thereby to falsely identify himself as the dramatic persona
represented by these patterns of symbols.
Since the material mind is the director of the material senses, control of
these senses can be achieved by controlling the mind. Since most of us have
never made a real effort to practice such control, we may tend to under
estimate both its importance and the difficulties involved in achieving it.
We may obtain some idea of these difficulties if we consider the powerful
role that habits of thought and action play in our normal activities. The
material mind is a reservoir of elaborate programs that govern everything
from gross movements to subtle attitudes, and thus our mental life consists
of a succession of conditioned thoughts and feelings that unfold inexorably
according to their own internal logic and the stimuli of the senses.
Since we normally tend to identify the material mind with the self, we
have no real idea of what it would be like to be free from this endless torrent
of mundane images and associations. This is indicated, however, by the
following statement in the Bhagavad-gītā:
For one who has conquered the mind, the Supersoul is already reached, for he
has attained tranquility. To such a man happiness and distress, heat and cold,
honor and dishonor are all the same. 8
Once the material mind is under control, the natural senses of the jīvātmā
are free to directly perceive the Supreme Person.
Service to Krsna can take many forms, but of these the most fundamen
tal are the processes of sravanam and kīrtanam, or hearing and chanting.
To awaken one's relationship with Krsna, it is necessary first to hear about
Krsna, and this is also a form of devotional service. One of the principle
themes of this book has been that the absolute truth is not void, but is full
of variegated attributes. The Supreme Person, Krsna, possesses unlimited
personal qualities, and He also engages in unlimited transcendental ac
tivities in reciprocation with innumerable jīvātmās who live in His associa
tion in a state of pure consciousness. By hearing about the attributes and
pastimes of Krsna, the materially conditioned jīvātmā is reminded of his
own natural relationship with Krsna. This provokes in him a desire to know
more about Krsna, and it simultaneously decreases his attachment to the
affairs of the material bpdy and mind.
The philosophy of bhakti-yoga holds that knowledge of the absolute
must descend directly from the absolute. Krsna is the original source of all
material forms, and He is also the origin of the written information which
forms the external subject matter of bhakti-yoga. This subject matter exists
in the form of scriptures that either are produced directly by Krsna Him
self, or are written by persons who are directly linked with Krsna in a tran
scendental relationship. The Bhagavad-gītā is an example of a scripture
of the former type, and the Bhāgavata Purāna and Caitanya-caritāmrta
are scriptures of the latter type. As we have pointed out, the subject matter
of bhakti-yoga is preserved and disseminated by the community of quali
fied gurus and sadhus, whose role in the regulation of knowledge can be
compared with that of the community of experts in a scientific field.
Unlimited amounts of information about Krsna can be encoded in the
form of sequences of symbols. However, since Krsna is absolute, informa
tion about H i m is different from ordinary information describing configu
rations of matter. In our ordinary experience, patterns of symbols can be
arranged according to the conventions of a language, so as to represent
certain events in a limited region of time and space. When we perceive
this information by hearing or reading, we are able to interpret the coded
patterns, and as a result we become aware of a mental image of the events.
The Process of Sravanam 223
This mental image is something quite different from the events them
selves. However, when the jīvātmā interprets information describing the
Supreme Person, the resulting mental images actually bring the jīvātmā
in direct contact with the Supreme Person. Since Krsna is absolute, ma
terial images and sounds representing Krsna are nondifferent from Krsna
Himself, and this can be understood directly by the jīvātmā. Such under
standing cannot, of course, be simply a matter of material symbol manipu
lation. It directly involves the higher sensory and cognitive facilities of the
conscious self.
Since this point is quite important, let us explore it in greater detail. Ac
cording to the philosophy of the Bhagavad-gītā, nothing is different from
Krsna, yet nothing is Krsna except for His own primordial personality.
Krsna is the cause and the essence of all phenomena, and in this sense all
phenomena are identical with Krsna. Yet the phenomena of this world are
merely external displays projected by Krsna's will, and His real nature is
His eternal personality. As we argued in Part I I , the absolute is highly spe
cific, and therefore Krsna can be represented by certain symbolic patterns
and not others. By means of these patterns, Krsna can introduce Himself to
the conditioned jīvātmā, and thus these configurations are nondifferent
from Krsna in a direct personal sense. By perceiving such configurations,
the jīvātmā is reminded of Krsna, and by Krsna's mercy he is allowed to see
Krsna directly by his own higher vision.
This explanation may convey some idea of how the embodied jīvātmā,
who is normally restricted entirely to material modes of sense perception,
can begin to perceive the transcendental Supreme Person. In this initial
stage, the jīvātmā's perception of Krsna may seem to be completely depen
dent on the interactions of matter, but the essence of his experience is not
material. We can begin, to understand this by considering the ideas that
matter itself is a manifestation of Krsna, and that material perception is
simply a limited, impersonal way of seeing Krsna.
In the highest stage of realization the reciprocation between the jīvātmā
and Krsna has nothing to do with the material manifestation. This relation
ship is not dependent on the material body of the jīvātmā in any way, and it
continues after the body has ceased to exist. According to the philosophy of
bhakti-yoga, the material manifestation represents only a minor aspect of
the total reality. There is a higher realm that is inaccessible to material
sense perception, but is nonetheless full of variegated form and activity.
Here we are concerned with the question of how a materially embodied
person can acquire absolute knowledge, and so we will not try to discuss
this higher realm in detail.
224 The Epistemology of Transcendental Consciousness
The Sanskrit term mantra refers to a pattern of sound that has a purifying
effect on the mind. This particular mantra is composed of three'names of
the Supreme Person. Grammatically, the mantra is in the vocative case,
and its meaning is to address the Lord by calling out His names.
These names are examples of symbolic patterns that directly represent
the Absolute Person, and therefore have an absolute, inherent meaning.
According to the philosophy of bhakti-yoga, Krsna's names are nondiffer-
ent from Krsna Himself, and by chanting and hearing these names, one is
brought into personal contact with Krsna. This can be directly appreciated
by persons whose higher sensory capacities have been awakened. For
others, the chanting of these names purifies their consciousness and
thereby brings about this awakening.
The results of chanting the names of the L o r d can be obtained by the use
of any names that are actually connected with the Supreme Person, and are
not mere concoctions of the material imagination. The significance of this
chanting was described as follows by Śrī Caitanya Mahāprabhu, the great
teacher of bhakti-yoga who appeared in India in the fifteenth century:
O my Lord, Your holy name alone can render all benediction to living beings,
and thus You have hundreds and millions of names, like Krsna and Govinda.
In these transcendental names You have invested all Your transcendental
energies. There are not even hard and fast rules for chanting these names. O
my Lord, out of kindness You enable us to easily approach You by chanting
Your holy names, but I am so unfortunate that I have no attraction for them. 1 2
The Process of Kirtanam 225
The purport of this statement is that due to the blindness caused by his
preoccupation with the material mjnd and senses, the conditioned jīvātmā
will initially feel very little attraction to chanting the names of the L o r d . Yet
by regularly chanting these names and following the regulative injunctions
of bhakti-yoga, this blindness can gradually be cured, and one can attain
the stage of loving reciprocation with Krsna.
Since the ultimate goal of this chanting is the development of love, it
must be carried out with an inner attitude that is compatible with this
emotion. Śrī Caitanya Mahāprabhu goes on to describe this attitude as
follows:
One should chant the holy name of the Lord in a humble state of mind, think
ing oneself lower than the straw in the street; one should be more tolerant
than a tree, devoid of all sense of false prestige, and ready to offer all respect
to others. In such a state of mind one can chant the holy name of the Lord
13
constantly.
It may not be possible for a person who has no direct knowledge of the
Supreme Person to immediately understand what it might mean to love the
Supreme. However, it is possible for him to lay the groundwork for such
understanding by adopting a nonexploitative attitude toward the Supreme
Person and His creation. Indeed, this is the key to the process of bhakti-
yoga. To one who wishes to exploit the Supreme, the Supreme will remain
unknowable. But if one truly gives up the desire for such exploitation, then
the Supreme Person will reveal Himself by His own mercy.
In the letter quoted at the beginning of this chapter, Einstein declared
that his goal was to capture the absolute truth. The absolute truth cannot be
captured forcefully by a minute part of the absolute, but according to the
philosophy of bhakti-yoga, the absolute can be captured by love. Once this
love is attained, direct knowledge of the absolute will be readily available,
but paradoxically, the development of this love is not compatible with the
desire for knowledge or power. Knowledge is indeed a byproduct of the
process of bhakti-yoga, but it cannot be the goal of that process, for the key
to the process itself lies in the fundamental reassessment of one's innermost
goals.
Although this reassessment may be superficially simple to describe, to
carry it out requires a deep insight into one's own psychology. By bringing
the inner self into personal contact with the absolute, the process of bhakti-
yoga enables one to attain this insight. By this means the absolute can be
captured—once all desire to conquer the absolute has been forsaken.
226 The Epistemology of Transcendental Consciousness
Notes
1. F r e n c h , ed., Einstein, p p . 275-276.
13. Ibid., p. 4 1 .
Appendix 1
A Discussion of Information Theory
The measure of information content used in Chapter 5 is the subject of
a field of study called algorithmic information theory. In this appendix
we will discuss the definitions and theorems from this field that we used in
Sections 5.2 and 5.3. We will present a brief summary of important results.
Additional details can be found in Thompson, (1980), which contains a
study of observation functions from the viewpoint of information theory.
A general review of algorithmic information theory can be found in
Chaitin, (1977).
To define information content we must first establish a fixed computer,
C. We assume that C accepts as programs bit strings P written in a particu
lar programming language similar to BASIC. Let R denote the rational
numbers. A program P is said to compute the n-ary function X: R" > R
on the computer C if the computer calculates X(Y1, . . . , Y n ) as output,
given values Y1, . . . ,Yn ε R as input. (If n = 0 then X is a constant and
there is no input.)
Any suitably powerful programming language can be used to define a
measure of information content. However, we have made certain assump
tions about the programming language that simplify the algebra of algo
rithmic information theory. We will introduce some of these assumptions
as we go along, and the remainder can be found in (Thompson, 1980). We
will assume that programs are written in an alphabet of 64 characters, each of
which can be encoded as a 6-bit string. These include the symbols 0 9
and A, . . . ,Z. We assume that the language has a system for encoding any
integer 0 x<2n with a string of no more than n + 6 log 1 0 (n) + 12 bits. We
also assume that the computer can handle rational numbers and integers
with arbitrarily many significant digits.
Let X: R" > R be an n-ary function that is computable by C. The in
formation content of such a function has been defined by A . I . Kolmogorof
(1968), G. Chaitin (1977), and others to be
L(X \C) = min{l(P) : P computes X on C} (25)
Here l(P), the length of P, is the number of bits in the bit string P.
We can see from this definition that information content is not an abso
lute, but is dependent on the particular computer, C. Yet for any C the
227
228 Appendix 1
n
even though there are 2 numbers in this range. The conventions of our
programming language for the coding of integers imply that
(Corollary 1.
Suppose that M is the same as in Proposition 1. Then, given the same
A Discussion of Information Theory 229
assumptions on X,
C + V + L ( M ) - L ( X )
M(X) 2 (31)
This corollary follows from Proposition 1 and (28) with m = 0 and F =M. l
Inequality (18) of Section 5.3 follows from (31) with r = 3 0 . The require-
30 9
ment that r = 3 0 simply means that (18) applies only for L(X)<2 10 .
Let X , . . . ,X be non-negative integers, and let G be a function
1 m
also pointed out that L(Y |G) could be taken as a measure of the amount
of observable information that is derived by G from the X 's, but is not j
(32)
L(Y |G) in (32). This represents the amount of shared information in the
X 's that is independent of F . . . ,F .
j l n
Proposition 2.
Let M be a probability measure on the integers, 0 x < N . Suppose that
M takes on rational values, and that N can be expressed in 15 or fewer
characters.
If X is a set of integers, 0 X . . . ,X <N, and J(X|M)<2 for some
1 m
r
(33)
where c'=337 +3.62r.
This is proven in T h o m p s o n , (1980), and it also holds w i t h
J(X |M,F . . . ,F ) in place of J(X |M).
1 n
Corollary 2.
With the same assumptions as in Proposition 1,
(34)
230 Appendix 1
This corollary also follows using (28). Inequalities (24) and (22) in Sec-
tion 5.3 follow directly from (33) and (34). (Again, we choose r=30.) In
Thompson, (1980) the properties of J ( X ) are analyzed, and a number of
examples of observation functions are discussed.
In Section 5.2 we argued that if a long bit string has a low information
content, then there must exist a strong interdependence among its parts.
Now we shall show how this can be formally established. Let X be a m
bit string of length hm, and suppose that X is divided into substrings
m
X =1 and
0
h
X k + 1 = 2 X +Y
k k + 1 (35)
for each 0 k<m. (Since X may begin with leading zeros, we place a 1 in
m
and
h -1(w)
I(2 X+ Y)>2 I(X) (36)
This F can be called the generating function. (F was used in Section 5.2
with the parameter h suppressed for convenience.)
Our application of F in equation (11) of Section 5.2 was based on the
following proposition.
Proposition 3.
Let Y . . . ,Y be as in (35), and suppose that L(X )
1 m m N. Then there
are bit strings w , . . . ,w such that
1 m
A Discussion of Information Theory 231
zeros to this w, if necessary, so that its length equals K . Then (38) will
n
be satisfied.
To show (37), note that I(X ) is no greater than the number of strings X'
0
with L(X') N, and that this is no greater than 2 . Now let n = L(X ) N.
N
m
We have seen that the generating function F can be defined very simply.
However, an inspection of the definition will show that it is not possible to
compute F in practice. In fact, as matters stand, F cannot be computed at
all. It can be shown that even though L(X) is a precisely defined function,
there does not exist an algorithm that will compute L(X) for any value of
X. (This is discussed in (Chaitin, 1977).) This means that L(X) is what is
known as an uncomputable or "nonrecursive" function. Since F is defined
in terms of L, it is not surprising that F is also uncomputable.
232 Appendix 1
Our question is, " H o w can the function F reel off successive descriptions
of complex organs and biological processes under the guidance of such mi-
nute amounts of information?" If we suppose that F can do this, then we
must conclude that the mere repetition of a few simple computational
steps, if prolonged over a long enough period, will generate the kind of
complex patterns found in living organisms. Furthermore, given the direc-
tion provided by the w -'s, the specific patterns of life as we know it will be
j
233
234 Appendix 2
the particles are bound by gravitation near the box's center. (This can be
accomplished by introducing a fixed gravitational potential.) These as-
sumptions mean that the boundary of the system can be regarded, in effect,
as an infinite vacuum. Since our model does not allow for nuclear inter-
actions, a source of heat and light is necessary, and this can be provided by
introducing a fixed source of electromagnetic radiation.
We assumed that electrons have a spin of V2, but we neglected the spins of
the nuclei, which were treated as charged point masses. We did not intro-
duce any relativistic correction terms, and we used a cutoff to bound the
Coulomb potential, 1/r, for r<e. We also introduced a frequency cutoff by
using a finite number of modes of oscillation, q . Finally, we introduced a
n
As we have pointed out in Section 5.3, the probability for the evolution
of recognizable higher forms is practically zero in a model of such low in
formation content. Even if the model were started with an initial popula
tion of primitive self-reproducing automata, no higher forms recognizable
to us could be expected to evolve. A process of natural selection is to be
expected in a population of self-reproducing automata that must compete
for space and resources. One might therefore imagine that some kind
of "higher intelligence" might gradually evolve. Yet if this happened,
the "intelligence" would be so alien that it would be meaningless to call
it by this name. In general, no representative of a class of forms is likely
to evolve if the class is characterized by a description of high information
content.
As a final point, let us consider how M(X) might be defined for our quan
tum mechanical model. To define M(X) we would first have to devise a
coding scheme whereby molecular configurations could be represented by
integers, X. A necessary condition for two atoms to be bonded together in
a molecule is that their nuclei should be situated within a certain distance of
one another. This distance will depend on the types of atoms and the type
of bond being considered. The pattern of bonds in a particular molecule
can thus be represented as a network of internuclear distances.
Let us suppose that the nuclei in our quantum model have coordinates
Q1 . . . ,QN where N<M. Using our coding scheme, we can define a
function B x ( Q 1 . . . ,Q N ) which will equal 1 if some subset of the nu
clear coordinates Q 1 . . . ,Q N satisfy the spacing requirements for the
molecule specified by X. This function will otherwise be set equal to 0.
The function B x can be used to estimate the probability that the mol
ecule described by A'exists within the physical system. If the system is in
the quantum mechanical state, V, let
(44)
where the integral is taken over all the variables of Since Bx defines a
necessary (but possibly insufficient) condition for the existence of the
molecule X, M(X,Ψ) gives an upper bound on the probability that this
molecule exists in the system.
A given arrangement of Q1 . . . ,QN can represent only a limited
number of molecular configurations. There should be a number T for
which
(45)
Notes 237
The Bx we have been considering can be expressed in less than a half page
of coding, and thus L(B) need be no more than half a page, or 8,400 bits. In
Section 5.2 we allotted a full page for this term so as to allow for a more
sophisticated function, Bx.
The constant represents the number of symbols needed to express (44),
plus some other odds and ends. The time must be considered in our esti
mate of L(M) since it enters into the calculation of the state of the system.
L(t) will be negligible, however, for times ranging from 0 to billions of
billions of years. We have seen that L (natural laws) is about one page
in our model. If we allow four pages for the definitions of the initial and
boundary conditions, we obtain the upper bound on L(M) given in (16) of
Section 5.3.
Notes
6. C o d d , Cellular Automata.
Bibliography
239
240 Bibliography
Darwin, Charles. The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin. Vol. 1. New
York: D. A p p l e t o n , 1896.
G o u l d , S t e p h e n J . a n d E l d r i d g e , Niles. " P u n c t u a t e d E q u i l i b r i a : T h e
T e m p o and M o d e of Evolution R e c o n s i d e r e d . " Paleobiology. Vol. 3,
1977, p p . 1 1 5 - 1 5 1 .
Schr dinger, Erwin. What is Life? and Mind and Matter. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1967.
Shklovskii, Iosif S. and Sagan, Carl. Intelligent Life in the Universe. San
Francisco: H o l d e n - D a y , 1966.
Tax, Sol and Callender, Charles, eds. Evolution After Darwin. Vol. 3,
Issues in Evolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1960.
T h a k u r , Bhakti Siddhanta Saraswati. Shri Brahma-Samhita. Madras,
India: Sree Gaudiya M a t h , 1958.
T h o m p s o n , Richard. "A Measure of Shared Information in Classes of
P a t t e r n s . " Pattern Recognition. Vol. 12, no. 6, D e c e m b e r 1980,
p p . 369-379.
Wigner, Eugene P. "Two Kinds of Reality." The Monist. Vol. 48, 1964,
pp.248-264.
Wilson, Edward O. On Human Nature. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 1978.
Wilson, E. G r a n t . The Mystery of Physical Life. New York: Abelard
Schuman, 1964.
249
250 Index
H i d d e n variables, 70 Karma, 1 8 0 - 1 8 1 , 2 1 4
Histories, q u a n t u m mechanical, Kirtanam, 224
66-68 Kolmogorof, A . I . , 227
H o r s e s : information c o n t e n t of, 127; Krsna, 79, 80, 8 2 , 1 6 1 , 163, 164,
toes of, 198, 200-201 178-179, 181, 204, 212, 214-218,
Hrsikeśa, 161. See also K r s n a 221-225. See also S u p r e m e Person
Huxley, Julian, 6, 183
Huxley, T h o m a s , 22 Laplace, Pierre Simon d e , 143, 158
H y p o t h e s e s , 169-170 Laws of n a t u r e . See N a t u r a l laws
Laws of physics. See N a t u r a l laws
Identity t h e o r y , 39 Layzer, David, 107
Infinite regress: in explanation of Life: as chemical process, 13, 100;
conscious self, 42; in e x p l a n a t i o n of as fundamental principle of n a t u r e ,
origin of life, 98 98; detailed discussion of origin
Infinity, 162 of, C h a p . 5; i m p r o b a b l e as a result
Information c o n t e n t , 97; defined, 105, of physical processes, 122-123. See
227; n o t a t i o n for, 109, 227; u p p e r also Evolution; Consciousness;
b o u n d s o n , for p r o t e i n s , 112-113; Jīvātmā
lower b o u n d s o n , for genetic
coding, 114-116; and evolution, M a c r o m u t a t i o n s , 197, 198. See also
122-129; S h a n n o n ' s formulation Mutations
of, 152; and r a n d o m n e s s , 152, 211; M ā d h a v a , 161. See also Krsna
of universal t h e o r y , 159; of uni Madhva, 7
verse, 161; s h a r e d , 229; of physio- Mahāmantra. See Mantra
chemical m o d e l , 233-237 M a m m a l s : D N A in genes of, 112;
Information theory: general discus information c o n t e n t of p r o t e i n s in,
sion of, C h a p . 5; a n d c h a n c e , 116; evolution of, ruled o u t , 127
152-153; technical discussion of. Mantra, 25, 224
A p p e n d i c e s 1 and 2 M a t h e m a t i c a l proof, 170, 173-174
Initial conditions, 105-108, 127-129, M a y r , Ernst, 193
132, 134, 237; as script, 158 M e a n i n g , 74, 89, 165. See also
Inspiration, C h a p . 7 Purpose
Intelligence: artificial, 28, 3 3 ; M e a s u r e m e n t p r o b l e m , in q u a n t u m
complexity of h u m a n , 120; mechanics, 6 0 - 6 1
origin of, 176; a n d design of bodily Mechanistic world view, 27; m e a n i n g
plans, 201-202; evolution of, 236 not definable in, 7 4 , 1 6 4 - 1 6 5 ;
Interactionism, 40, 44-45 limits us to correlating m e a s u r a b l e
Iśopanisad, 162 quantities, 77; defined, 143; c a n n o t
e n c o m p a s s conscious awareness,
Jīvātmā, 8; axioms for, 2 3 - 2 4 ; senses 160; c a n n o t be complete and
of, 2 4 - 2 5 , 4 1 - 4 2 , 213-214, 217, unified, 162-163; excludes
220, 223-224; investigation of 44, p u r p o s e , 204
7 7 - 7 8 ; size of, 45; and its inter M e m o r y , of c o m p u t e r , 2 8 - 2 9
action with the body, 177-181; and M e t a b o l i s m , 118
its relationship with K r s n a , Meta-laws, and emergent evolution, 92
204-205,212-225 Microstomum, 193-195, 197
252 Index