Lovejoy Kant
Lovejoy Kant
Lovejoy Kant
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
Mind Association, Oxford University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to Mind
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
IV.-KANT'S ANTITHESIS OF DOGMATISM AND
CRITICISM.
BY ARTHUR 0. LOVEJOY.
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
192 ARTHUR 0. LOVEJOY:
I This third point cannot be dealt with within the limits of this paper.
The proof of it is offered in a forthcomrling article by the present writer
in the Archiv fiur Geschichte der Philosophie.
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
KANT'S ANTITHESIS OF DOGMATISM AND CRITICISM. 193
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
194 ARTHUR 0. LOVEJOY:
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
KANT S ANTITHESIS OF DOGMATISM AND CRITICISM. 195
Erkenntnissvermdi6gen ". Upon this Kant remarked that, if such was the
case then, indeed, "there is no dogmatism in that philosophy, in the
sense in which our Kritik always employs the word " (Reply to Eberhard,
ite Abscbn).
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
196 ARTHUR 0. LOVEJOY:
follows from the logical principle: " Dans toute verite, uni--
verselle ou singuli'ere, necessaire ou contingente, le predicat
est contenu dans le sujet". But while Leibniz thus makes
all judgments analytical in a sense, it is also true that he fully
recognises a distinction corresponding to Kant's distinction
between analytic and synthetic judgments. Some predicates,
are contained in their subjects essentially and inextricably, so,
that, lacking those predicates, the subject would cease to be
itself, would become an inconceivability; in other words, the
concept, as a whole, is made up of a complex of attributes,
some one or more of which are inconceivable without the-
others. In other cases the inclusion of the given predicate
with the several other predicates that make up the essence-
(or definition) of the subject is purely accidental; the several
attributes do not coinhere of necessity. In the latter cases,
the connexion of predicate with subject can only be known a
posteriori; the fornmer class constitute the field where a priori
reasoning is legitimate, and where necessary and eternal
truths are to be looked for. It is, of course, true that Leib--
niz called propositions of this class identical propositions,.
their distinguishing mark being that their opposites involved
self-contradiction. But by identity Leibniz did not really in--
tend to mean mere tautology, and by contradiction he does
not always signify mnerely verbal contradiction. It was, in-
deed, difficult for hin to make out how he could mean any-
thing else; but he was, none the less, firmly persuaded that
the Gruind des Widerspruches is no empty and sterile maxim,
but the fruitful source of important insights; and he especially
(if not always very successfully) exerted hinmself to prove its.
positive utility. Thus he remarks (Gerhardt vii., p. 299)
that though there may seem to be nothing but a cocoysmus-
inutilis in identical propositions, yet levi mutattione utilia inde
axiomnata nascuntur. This, to be sure, is a somewhat na&f way-
of putting it, and the examples which follow are hardly con--
vinicing; but it all shows Leibniz's unwillinciness to take his,
principle in its strict and narrow sense. There are, more--
over, he maintains, two distinct kinds of judgment included
within its range of application: (1) identical judgments, of'
which the opposite is formally self-contradictory, e.g., A is A;-
(2) judgments virtualiter identicae, of which the opposite can
be seen to involve contradiction only per terminorum intellec--
turm et resolutionem-that is, only by an examination of the
whole implicit connotation of the terms involved, showing-
that the two notions are 'incompossible'. It is chiefly these
latter, or " virtually identical," judgments which constitute
the substance of our demonstrative knowledge, and especially-
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
KANT S ANTITHESIS OF DOGMATISM AND CRITICISM. 197
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
198 ARTHUR 0. LOVEJOY:
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
KANT'S ANTITHESIS OF DOGMATISM AND CRITICISM. 199
1 This point has already been clearly set forth by Mr. Russell (Philo-
sophy of Leibiz, ,loc. cit.).
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
200 ARTHUR 0. LOVEJOY:
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
KANT'S ANTITHESIS OF DOGMATISM AND CRITICISM. 201
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
202 ARTHUR 0. LOVEJOY:
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
KANT S ANTITHESIS OF DOGMATISM AND CRITICISM. 203
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
204 ARTHUR 0. LOVEJOY:
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
KANT' S ANTITHESIS OF DOGMATISM AND CRITICISM. 205
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
206 ARTHUR 0. LOVEJOY:
make them more intelligible to myself " (Kr. d. r. V., first ed.,
pp. 7, 8). In the Prolegomena Kant goes so far as to say that
the notion which serves as the predicate of such a judgment-
is actiually always expressly present to the mind when the
subject is thought; the judgment " expresses nothing in the
predicate but what has already been wirklich gedacht (though
not ausdriicklich gesagt) in the subject ". Leibniz, in his
narrowest definitions, would have avoided such language; for
he at least placed judgments virttaliter identicae side by side
with the purely tautological ones. And occasionally Kant
himself reimembers that concepts sometimes implicitly in--
volve more than one happens, at any given moment, con-
sciously to think in them. He then adds that the predicate
of an analytical judgment may be contained in the subject
in a confused manner," or " without full consciousness '.
What this vague qualification precisely means Kant does not
further explain. It apparently refers, not to the implicit in-
terconnexion of " properties" in the connotation of an idea,
but merely to the fact that people sometimes forget just
what some of the essentialia are that they are accustomed to
signify by a term. The qualification cannot, therefore, be
construed as equivalent to the adinission of the distinctness
and the legitimacy of a priori judgments per attributa.
So far, then, and considering only Kant's principal writings,
we must say, not that Kant rejects the position of the ' dog-
matists,' but that he neglects to face or to oppose it at all.
With a degree of obtuseness rare in history, he entirely failed
to apprehend the distinction that had been the principal re-
sult of the previous half-century of refiexion upon the criteiia
of truth in mathematics and metaphysics-the distinction,
namely, between a priort judgments per essentialia and a
priori judgments per attributta-even though this distinction
contained an answer to just the question which he himself'
declared to be the fundamental one in all philosophy. His
attacks upon his predecessors implied that, having no cri-
terion of truth a priori save the principle of contradiction in
its narrowest analytical sense, they proceeded none the less
(in their ignorance of Hume) to construct an a priori system
of metaphysics. But since the criterion which they used
was quite other, and since their reasons for accepting it had.
been carefully explained, Kant cannot be said to have brought
any pertinent criticism to bear upon their position at all..
The longer treatises nowhere make it certain that, if Kant
had grasped the Wolffian distinction, he would not have
accepted the Wolffian method.
Fortunately, however, Kant was reminded of this dis-
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
KANT S ANTITHESIS OF DOGMATISM AND CRITICISM. 20T
I Ueber eine neue Entdeckmtng, nach der alle Kritik der reittee Vernmuift
entbehrlich. werden soll (1790). To any who wish to understand Kant's
relation to earlier logic and metaphysics, and so to determine his place
in the history of those sciences, this Reply to Eberhard is one of the most
important of his writings-for reasons that are made apparent in the
text. It is, however, full of flounderings and self-contradictions.
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
208 ARTHUR 0. LOVEJOY:
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
KANT'S ANTITHESIS OF DOGMATISM AND CRITICISM. 209
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
2I0 ARTHUR 0. LOVEJOY:
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
KANT S ANTITHESIS OF DOGMATISM AND CRITICISM. 211
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
212 ARTHUR 0. LOVEJOY:
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
KANT'S ANTITHESIS OF DOGMATISM AND CRITICISM. 213
' Note again that this is inconsistent with the admissions which Kant
makes in the Revlii to Eberhard.
15
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
214 A. 0. LOVEJOY: KANT. DOGMATISM V. CRITICISM.
This content downloaded from 142.66.3.42 on Tue, 20 Sep 2016 15:32:33 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms