Location via proxy:   [ UP ]  
[Report a bug]   [Manage cookies]                

Brentano and Kafka PDF

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 19

Brentano and Kafka

Barry Smith
Department of Philosophy
SUNY Buffalo
phismith@acsu.buffalo.edu

from Axiomathes 8, 1997, 83–104.


For we are like tree trunks in the snow. In appearance they lie
sleekly and a little push should be enough to set them rolling.
No, it can’t be done, for they are firmly wedded to the ground.
But see, even that is only appearance.1

§ 1. The Louvre Circle


There is a narrow thread in the vast literature on Kafka which pertains to Kafka’s knowledge of philosophy
and more precisely to the fruitfulness of attempts to interpret Kafka’s fictional writings in the light of some of
the main ideas of Franz Brentano. Such attempts have been roundly dismissed, not least by Max Brod, who
denied the role of all theory in Kafka’s writings (Kafka ‘spoke in images because he thought in images’). As
Arnold Heidsieck has thoroughly documented in his recent study of the intellectual context of Kafka’s work,
however, Kafka’s fictional writings are
informed by … academic and public debates during the first decade of the twentieth century on
physiology; perceptual, cognitive and linguistic psychology; the philosophy of mind and language;
positive law and natural-law theory; criminal procedure; ethics; and religion. (Heidsieck 1994, pp. 2f.)
Kafka became apprised of and to some degree involved in such debates not least through his school-friends
(including Hugo Bergmann and Emil Utitz), through the courses he attended in philosophy at the Charles
University, courses given inter alia by Brentano’s students Anton Marty and Christian von Ehrenfels, and
through his three-year membership of a discussion-group organized by orthodox adherents of the Brentanian
philosophy in Prague. Heidsieck’s book ‘surveys philosophical theorems that were either intensely contended
or opposed’ by the Brentanists in Prague, and he attempts to show how ‘Kafka embeds them almost serially
in his developing themes and paradigms’ (op. cit., p. 48). Here I shall concentrate on two such
‘philosophical theorems’: Brentano’s doctrine of intentionality, and Brentano’s account of ethical judgment.

1. “Die Bäume”, Kafka 1970, p. 19 (trans. by W. and E. Muir, Kafka 1971, p. 382).

1
As a result of the work of intellectual historians of recent decades we now have what can claim to be
a more or less adequate understanding of that complex cultural entity which was fin-de-siècle Vienna.2 The
outburst of intellectual energy which is encountered in the works of Weininger, Wittgenstein, Kraus, Mahler,
Schoenberg, Loos, Klimt, Hofmannsthal, Musil, Broch, Schnitzler and Freud was, on the one hand, a product
of the quite peculiar cross-fertilization which characterized Austrian intellectual life.3 But it was also, at least
in part, a product of a wider political contagion which marked the later Habsburg Empire. The ideas of the
liberal enlightenment which had sustained the intellectuals of Europe through the eighteenth and nineteenth
centuries had shown themselves, in Austria at least, to be unworkable.4 And the collapse of the liberal faith or,
more generally, of the faith in politics as a mechanism for the improvement of humanity, contributed to a
characteristic introvertedness on the part of Austrian intellectuals, a turning away from society which was also
a turning inward to the nether regions of the isolated individual self.
The present essay is devoted not to Vienna but to Prague, where the same political pressures were at
work, and to the work of Franz Kafka and to the Prague Brentanist movement with which Kafka, in his youth,
had enjoyed a brief contact. A systematic introvertedness is of course evident on almost every page of Kafka’s
writings. It makes itself felt also, however, in the work of the Brentanists, for whom psychology – a descriptive
science of the structures of the individual consciousness – serves as the fundamental discipline, providing the
ultimate theoretical foundation not only for logic and ethics but also for the disciplines of politics and law.5
Kafka entered the German University in Prague in November 1901, and his five years of study consisted
predominantly in never more than halfhearted attendance at courses in law. Originally he had intended to study
philosophy, and in fact a certain number of classes in philosophy were compulsory for law students at that
time. Yet it seems that we can rule out the suggestion that Kafka attended these courses merely in order to
satisfy the university regulations. We have convincing evidence of the fact that Kafka, at that time and for a
number of years afterwards, exhibited a positive interest in philosophy – and specifically in Brentanian

2. See especially the writings of Carl E. Schorske, above all his 1960/61 und 1967 (reprinted in Schorske 1980).

3. This was in part a reflection of the cross-disciplinary nature of university studies as these had evolved in Central
Europe and which Kafka’s own education illustrates in a particularly striking manner. On Austrian polymathy in
general see Johnston 1972, chs. 10 ff, and 19 ff., and Grassl and Smith 1986. It is no accident that the unity of science
movement (Neurath, et al. 1938) should haae had its birthplace in Vienna.

4. Cf. Schorske, op. cit. For a defence of the Schorske thesis against its critics (above all Johnston in his 1972 and
elsewhere), see Nyíri 1982.

5. Cf. Brentano 192, I. 3, and 1934.

2
philosophy – for its own sake.6 He attended also courses in chemistry,7 in legal history, in forensic medicine,
in the history of art and architecture, in German literature, and in economics and political theory.
That Brentano’s influence was felt especially strongly in Prague turns in part on the fact that, for
various personal and religious reasons, he had been treated rather badly by the authorities in Vienna. His
students however were able to obtain posts in universities elsewhere inAustria, and to propagate Brentanian
philosophy to the extent that it acquired the status of a semi-official philosophy of the Empire. Brentano’s
students included, beside Marty and Ehrenfels,8 also Freud, Thomas Masaryk (subsequently founder and first
president of the erstwhile Czechoslovak Republic), Meinong, Husserl, Stumpf and Twardowski. The most
orthodox Brentanists congregated around Marty in Prague, whose circle included also other former students
of Brentano, such as Oskar Kraus and Alfred Kastil. The Prague Brentanists took up the task of developing
and disseminating Brentano’s doctrines with an almost religious fervour. A group of them met regularly in the
Café Louvre (now a sex shop) on the Ferdinandstrasse, for ‘training’ in Brentanian modes of thought and of
philosophical discussion and argument. Hugo Bergmann, Emil Utitz and Oskar Pollak, three close school-
friends of Kafka,9 were all initiated into this circle, and Bergmann, in his turn, seems to have recruited Kafka
himself. There is evidence testifying to the fact that, at least between the years 1903 and 1906, Kafka
frequently attended meetings of what was called the ‘inner circle of Brentanists’.10
As Utitz has described it, the Louvre Circle was a community of thinkers

6. It was almost certainly under the pressure of financial considerations that Kafka elected, finally, to take his degree
in law; cf. Wagenbach 1958, especially p. 242, where there is reprinted a list of the members of Kafka’s final year class
at the German State Gymnasium in Prague.

7. Wagenbach, op. cit., esp. pp. 106–14 and Neesen 1972.

8. I have provided a brief account of Ehrenfels – the titular father of Gestalt psychology – as an appendix to an earlier
version of the present essay (Smith 1981). Ehrenfels remained a familiar figure in Prague for many years. See e. g.
Kafka’s diary entry for 4 February 1912: ‘Amusing scene when Prof. Ehrenfels, who grows more and more handsome
and who – with his bald head sharply outlined against the light in a curve that is puffed out at the top, his hands
pressed together, with his full voice, which he modulates like a musical instrument, and a confident smile at the
meeting – declares himself in favour of mixed races.’ We know that even as late as 1913 Kafka was still attending
Ehrenfels’ seminars: see the diary entry for 21 October 1913. On Ehrenfels thought and influence see Fabian (ed.)
1986 and Ash 1995. On Brentano’s influence in general see Smith 1994. On Brentano and Freud see Heaton 1981.

9. Bergmann went on to make several important contributions to philosophy, especially on the work of Bolzano and
Brentano; Utitz became a distinguished aesthetician, and Pollak a historian of art. It was Pollak who received and
criticized Kafka’s earliest literary experiments; see Bezzel 1975, Binder 1980, and the references there given.

10. Wagenbach, op. cit.; Neesen, op. cit.; Binder 1966, pp. 58 ff.; Bokhove 1981.

3
in a common struggle, who would meet frequently for evenings of endless discussion. Franz Brentano,
of course, was not himself present. But his powerful shadow fell upon every utterance, whether this
expressed a correct interpretation of his teachings or some objection to them.11
Max Brod, too, was associated with the Louvre Circle. We can deduce that he began to attend its meetings
some time after Kafka himself, and probably before their close friendship had established itself. But Brod
seems never properly to have belonged to the inner circle of Brentanists, and he was in fact ceremoniously
excluded from all dealings with the group after publishing in a Berlin literary magazine a short story which
included a caricature of religious Brentanianism. He himself has provided a description of his expulsion:
As I entered the back room of the Café Louvre everybody was gathered together in a talkative mood,
and a copy of Gegenwart which had come out shortly before the meeting lay on the table. I had arrived
with Kafka. It was Emil Utitz who first made the accusation ... which was debated for some time. A
series of deliberations followed, as if what were taking place were something like a student’s court of
honour. ... And I had no one who came to my defence, though all the participants had by then [October
1905] known me for two years. Suddenly one of them took my side – Kafka. Normally he was so quiet
in company, giving the impression of being almost apathetic ... – But now Kafka whispered across to
me ... that it would be best if we both left, and quit the Brentano circle for ever. And this we did.12
Kafka himself, however, shortly after this event, resumed contact with at least some members of the Louvre
Circle. Two months later he, together with Pollak, Utitz and Bergmann’s mother-in-law Berta Fanta, signed
a dedication to a book on theoretical psychology13 which was presented to Hugo Bergmann ‘in memory of our
common struggles’ on the occasion of the latter’s birthday.14

11. Utitz 1954, cited by Wagenbach, op. cit., p. 107.

12. Brod 1960, p. 260, quoted by Neesen, op. cit., p. 28.

13. The work was Busse 1903, a study of psychophysics (essentially a survey of contemporary treatments of the mind-
body problem).

14. Wagenbach, op. cit., p. 216, n. 426. Berta Fanta had established in her home a regular salon for Prague
intellectuals which was frequented by many of the members of the Louvre Circle. Among the guests at the Fanta
gatherings were not only Kafka, Bergmann, Oskar Kraus, and Ehrenfels, but also Albert Einstein, who was for a time
professor of physics at Prague, Philipp Frank, another physicist and subsequently member of the Vienna Circle, and
the mathematician Gerhard Kowalewski, who has described the Fanta evenings in his autobiography (1950). It was
not only philosophical issues which were discussed; Brod, for example, tells us that on successive Fanta evenings
through the winter of one year a certain Herr Hopf, a professor in Prague and a friend of Einstein, gave a course
combining an account of relativity theory on the one hand with an introduction to Freudian psychoanalysis on the other
(Wagenbach, op. cit, p. 174).

4
It was Kafka’s biographer Klaus Wagenbach who first attempted to show in detail that not only
Brentanian psychology but also Brentanian ethics contributed at least something to determining both the form
and the content of Kafka’s literary work; that through his participation in the Louvre evenings Kafka acquired
techniques which contributed something to the development of the peculiar mode of portrayal of consciousness
which is so characteristic a feature of his literary experiments, and that the philosophical psychology underlying
this process of representation of conscious experience is a version of the descriptive psychology of Brentano.15
As Neesen, in his excellent book on Kafka and Brentano, has pointed out: ‘It would be inexplicable if Kafka
had, over a long period, attended meetings of a circle of philosophers whose subject-matter was of no interest
to him.’16
Wagenbach’s and Neesen’s arguments have been subjected to sceptical scrutiny, particularly by
Hartmut Binder, who points out that even at those points where Kafka’s writings suggest a terminological or
conceptual affinity with Brentanian ideas, the deviations from Brentano are often more significant than the
similarities. Binder is ready to accept the biographical evidence of a more or less sustained contact between
Kafka and the Brentanists, but he argues that many of those aspects of Kafka’s mode of writing and thinking
which might seem to admit of an explanation in terms of a Brentanian influence can more readily be accounted
for on the basis of other, quite independent considerations.17 Kafka and Brentano are, as we have already seen,
representatives of a much wider movement of thought within central Europe at the turn of the century. They
manifest a common subjectivism, a concern with the inner life of the individual subject at the expense of those
aspects of human reality which have their foundation in the outer life of society. It is thus to be predicted that
many of the intellectual strands of what we find in Kafka can be traced back to several independent sources.
With the publication of Heidsieck’s work, however, which offers a wealth of additional supporting textual and
biographical detail to the original Wagenbach-Neesen argument, a scepticism of the sort evinced by Binder has
suffered a heavy blow. What is still needed is a detailed treatment of the relevant philosophical ideas, and this
is what shall be attempted here

15. The Wagenbach-Neesen interpretation has been defended also by Harder 1962. Other works on Kafka and
European philosophy, for example the works of Emrich and Bense, Demetz and Pondrom, listed below, almost
completely ignore the peculiarly Brentanian background in Prague and its quite specific relation to Kafka. Emrich and
Bense content themselves with certain parallels between Kafka’s thought and the Heideggerian Fundamentalontologie,
and Demetz’s essay is an interesting but far too brief account of the specifically Jewish background of Bohemian
intellectuals such as Husserl, Freud and Kafka. Even Pondrom, who presents a number of useful parallels between
Kafka and Brentano’s greatest student Edmund Husserl, centring around the notion of putting the world on trial,
misses completely Kafka’s relation to Brentano.

16. Op. cit., p. 34.

17. Binder 1966, pp. 56–91; 1980, vol. I, pp. 287f et passim. Binder’s account is to some degree however flawed by
the fact that he shows little understanding of or sympathy for the Brentanian philosophy.

5
§ 2. The Evidence of Inner Perception.
The philosophy courses for which Kafka enrolled in his first year at the University were as follows:
Winter Semester 1901/02 Ehrenfels: Praktische Philosophie (4 hrs/week)
Summer Semester 1902 Ehrenfels: Ästhetik des musikalischen Dramas (1 hr/week)
Summer Semester 1902 Marty: Grundfragen der deskriptiven Psychologie (3 hrs/week)

By ‘descriptive psychology’ Marty understood the psychology of his teacher Brentano as this is set forth first
of all in his Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint and now in Brentano’s lecture notes published under
the title Deskriptive Psychologie.18 Brentano begins by advancing a fundamental distinction between two sorts
of phenomena, which he calls physical and psychical phenomena respectively. Examples of physical phenomena
are:
a colour, a figure, a landscape which I see, a chord which I hear, warmth, cold, an odour which I
sense, as well as similar formations appearing in the imagination.19
Psychical or mental phenomena, in contrast, are simply our mental acts themselves:
the hearing of a sound, the seeing of a coloured object, feeling warmth or cold, as well as similar states
of the imagination ... the thinking of a general concept (if such a thing actually does occur), ... every
judgment, every recollection, every expectation, every inference, every conviction or belief, anger, love,
hate, desire, act of will, intention, astonishment, admiration, contempt, and so on.
Brentano now distinguishes inner from outer perceptions by reference to their objects: acts of inner perception
are those perceptions that have psychical phenomena as their objects, acts of outer perception those that have
physical phenomena. But this leaves unclear what precisely it might mean to ‘perceive’ a psychical
phenomenon. Brentano did not intend thereby, as we shall make clear below, anything like an introspection
of one’s own inner states of consciousness. He wished, rather, to draw attention to the fact that every act of
consciousness is bound up with its own intrinsic self-consciousness, that a mental event or state which did not
meet this condition would not be a ‘consciousness’ at all. It is not as if – as Brentano’s terminology of ‘inner’
and ‘outer’ perception may unfortunately suggest – this element of self-consciousness is conceived as an
additional act, which would exist in the mind somehow alongside the original outer consciousness. It is, rather,
a merely abstractly distinguishable moment or constituent part of the original consciousness, a moment of a
type that can of necessity exist only as embedded within a larger circumcluding whole of the given sort. The
act-moment of inner perception might best be conceived as an act of living through its object (the

18. See Brentano 1982. For a transcript of lectures given by Marty under this title see Marek and Smith 1987.

19. Brentano 1924, vol. I, pp. 111f (pp. 79f of English edition).

6
corresponding psychical phenomenon), without any exterior target object of the type which is typically
possessed by acts of both outer perception and (if these exist) of introspection.20
Brentano’s thesis of the primacy of inner perception, now, is a claim to the effect that it is the inner
life, the inner perception of psychical phenomena, which can alone yield certain knowledge. The only objects
of which we can have an absolutely secure apprehension are, as he conceives it, the acts and states of our own
consciousness. Of these alone can we assert with an absolutely evident knowledge that they are in reality as
they appear in consciousness. A consequence of this is that our outer perceptions, that is, our experiences of
physical phenomena, may always be deceptive. This thesis represents a form of Cartesianism, in that
Brentano’s arguments for the dubitability of outer perception rest on the same kind of intuitions as do
Descartes’ discussions of perceptual illusion in his Meditations. Brentano’s claims for inner perception as a
source of absolutely secure knowledge, on the other hand, recall Descartes’ claims on behalf of those truths
impervious to systematic doubt which he believed himself to have isolated.21
When we are perceiving outer phenomena, we cannot know with absolute evidence that the object of
our perception is as it seems – we could, e.g., be hallucinating. When living through a particular state of
consciousness, however, we can know with absolute evidence that this state of consciousness exists, and that
it is structured in such and such a way. Illusions and hallucinations are, Brentano claimed, alien to the world
of inner perception when this is properly understood. What he means by this can I think be explained as
follows: absolute evidence is obtained only if a judgment and that which is judged, i.e. for Brentano, that object
whose existence is affirmed, are somehow united in a single whole which is available to consciousness in such
a way that the correctness of the judgment can be grasped directly. Such a unity is impossible for judgments
of outer perception, since there the objects intended are given as being transcendent to the act of judging itself.
Consider, however, judgments of reflexive self-awareness (a thinking exists, a remembering exists, a visual
image exists, and so on). Judgmental contents of this sort are, as we have seen, merely abstractly isolable
moments of more inclusive act-wholes; they are immanent to the corresponding act of judging. Thus the desired
kind of unity between judgment and that which is judged is here already to hand: our experiences of psychical
phenomena are already of themselves experiences having the character of absolute evidence. We can be deluded
in supposing that there is a pattern of red and green (an object of outer perception) in our visual field; but we
cannot be deluded in supposing that we are undergoing an experience of seeming to see a pattern of red and
green. This experience constitutes an object of inner perception the existence of which is given with absolute
evidence in the very experience itself and the concept of delusion can here gain no foothold.22

20. See Küng 1978.

21. Cf. Küng, op. cit.

22. A useful interpretation of Brentano’s arguments here is given by Chisholm in his 1981: see especially Chisholm’s
discussions of empirical certainty (which corresponds broadly to what we have here called absolute evidence).

7
What are the consequences of Brentano’s doctrine for our understanding of the external world and of
our knowledge of this world? Note that Brentano himself does not deny that objects of outer perception exist
outside our consciousness. Nor does he deny that they are as they appear to us. He asserts only that we have
no unconditioned evidence that they do so exist. The external world, our apprehension of which is built up over
time on the basis of our consciousness of constellations of physical phenomena, is reduced to something that
is merely probable, as contrasted with the absolute certainty of the existence of objects of inner perception. And
where Brentano was called upon to give his best estimate as to the nature of this external world, he turned to
physics, to the world of energy fields, of atoms and molecules; in relation to the normal world of tables and
chairs, people and insects, he embraced a decidedly sceptical attitude.
A close contact with Brentanian philosophy would thus have been conducive to the adoption of a
sceptical attitude in relation to this ordinary world. The Brentanian sceptic will find, like Descartes, that he can
countenance modes of experience in which the external reality projected by consciousness is blurred or
malignantly deformed in the light of the standards of correctness assumed in our ordinary everyday experience.
And as we shall see in more detail below, such variant modes of experience, and the peculiar plasticity of the
world which is their correlate, form a constantly recurring theme in Kafka's writings.

§ 3. Oblique Consciousness
When Gregor Samsa wakes up in the morning he doesn’t just feel like a noxious insect, he is a noxious insect:
that is to say, everything in his outer world is such as to lend support to his belief that this is his new form. For
the external world which is normally taken for granted there has been substituted a quite different world, having
peculiar qualities. At the same time, however, Kafka/Samsa’s inner reality is seen to have hard and firm
outlines which are normally unnoticed. Moreover, Kafka/Samsa’s immobility, his inability to engage in
interactions with the human beings around him, means that more than ever he is thrust into the position of the
dispassionate observer, the empirical psychologist engaged in the business of noticing and recording the play
of psychical phenomena.
From the perspective of our accepted standards of reality, a cleft threatens to open up in the fabric of
Samsa’s experience, due to the fact that the mode of appearance of the objects of his outer world, including
that of his own physical body, does not gear into the reality which seems continually to threaten to break
through whenever he has contacts with (what we think of as) external reality. This cleft is however prevented
from making itself felt by continually shifting reinterpretations on Samsa’s part of the data which comes in.
From the point of view of the Brentanian sceptic a cleft of this kind is potentially capable of appearing
in the experiences of every individual; for most of us it is as if the cleft were securely and, as we assume,
rightly papered over, through the inertial force of commonsensical assumptions concerning external reality. Our
unquestioning acceptance of these assumptions consists, in effect, in this: that at least in principle every datum

8
which emanates from the outer world will be given precedence over our inner expectations, over connections
amongst mental contents whose motivation derives exclusively from internal factors.
It is extremely difficult to give a clear account of this ‘cleft’, since the characteristic features of the
real and the subjective have been switched around by Brentano: it is the inner world alone which now truly has
the character of being real; the outer world of common sense, which we normally take as our standard of
reality, has lost all its former claims to absoluteness – even though at the same time it is not simply denied that
it exists.
Kafka however seems to have succeeded, at least in part, in representing the cleft in literary form. He
does not appeal directly to some process of introspection or direct observation of mental experiences. The very
idea of such a process is, within the Brentanian framework, a spurious one. Observation or attention, mental
processes involving our deliberately directing our gaze towards an object, can, of course arise in the field of
outer perception. But Brentano argues that direct, attentive self-observation of one’s own anger, say, or of any
other psychic phenomenon, is impossible. For as soon as our attention were turned to such phenomena, as soon
as we were truly living in the gaze of observation, the original phenomena would have disappeared: we would
no longer be properly angry or afraid, but rather attentive.
The attempt at introspection thus begins to look very much like the attempt of a dog to catch its own
tail. Whenever we suppose that our own psychic states have become the objects of our attention – that we have
succeeded in the attempt to observe them – we are, Brentano argues, involved in a delusion, which derives from
our having mistakenly assumed that psychical phenomena can play the role of objects in the same way as
physical phenomena, objects which will stand still, as it were, as our attention is focused on them.
Kafka, too, was aware of this impossibility of a non-delusory self-observation:
How miserable is my self-knowledge when compared, say, to my knowledge of my room ... And why?
There is no observation of the inner world as there is of the outer. At least descriptive psychology is
probably on the whole an anthropomorphism, a gnawing away at the limits. The inner world can only
be lived, it cannot be described. – Psychology is the description of the reflection of the earthly world
in the surface of heaven or, more correctly, the description of a reflection which we who are absorbed
completely by the earth think up for ourselves, for no reflection takes place at all, we see only earth
wherever we may look.23
And then again in his diary for 9 December 1913:
Hatred of active introspection. Explanation of one’s soul, such as yesterday I was so, and for this
reason; today I am so, and for this reason. It is not true, not for this reason and not for that reason, and
therefore also not so and so. To put up with oneself calmly, without being precipitate, to live as one
must, not to chase one’s tail like a dog.
And again (l0 December 1913):

23. Kafka 1953, p. 72 (my trans.). Compare Heidsieck 1994, p. 64.

9
It is never possible to take note of and evaluate all the circumstances that influence the mood of the
moment, are even at work within it, and finally are at work in the evaluation, hence it is false to say
that I felt resolute yesterday, that I am in despair today. Such differentiations only prove that one
desires to influence oneself, and, as far removed from oneself as possible, hidden behind prejudices and
fantasies, temporarily to create an artificial life, as sometimes someone in the corner of a tavern,
sufficiently concealed behind a small glass of whisky, entirely alone with himself, entertains himself
with nothing but false, unprovable images and dreams.
Inner perception, then, is resolutely to be distinguished from any kind of introspection. To see the
relevance of this, let us recall Brentano’s definition of inner perception as a consciousness of psychical
phenomena. Such phenomena he demarcates into three classes, which are seen as exhausting all mental
experience: presentations, judgments, and phenomena of love and hate.24 Thus psychical phenomena are either
presentations of landscapes, of colour- und tone-complexes, and so on; or they are judgments (that such and
such an object exists); or they are phenomena of love and hate (a category which includes, for Brentano, all
emotions and feelings, including feelings of will); or they are combinations of these. It is the category of
judgments that most clearly illustrates what is involved in inner perception. In judging something, e.g. that this
pattern of red and green exists, we have before us first of all certain physical phenomena, the objects of our
external perception (in this case the red and green data in our visual field). But then also we are aware of what
is taking place in our mind; we are conscious – obliquely, as it were – of the judgment itself, a certain
psychical phenomenon. Similarly, in seeing directly before us the pattern itself, we are conscious, obliquely,
of our seeing of the pattern. And it is this oblique consciousness, present in all mental experiences whatsoever,
which is what Brentano means by inner perception.
Let us suppose that we now wish to convey the data of inner perception in written form. Recall that
inner perceptions are always, of their nature, dependent moments of more inclusive act-wholes which comprise
also moments of outer perception; the oblique consciousness of a mental act presupposes also that there is some
direct consciousness of the external target of the act. Hence it is impossible to convey the data of inner
perception except in association with an appropriate framework of outer perceptions. We might at first wish
to appeal simply to ordinary experience for such a framework, but this would be to reinforce the established
inertial habits and tendencies of mind; we would become once more absorbed in the outer world, and this would
place almost insuperable obstacles in the way of our bringing to prominence the data of the inner life. For the
attentions of the reader would in such circumstances follow their natural course (would be directed, in effect,
to the external unfolding of the plot). It would seem, however, that the peculiar forms and structures of inner
consciousness might begin to be made accessible, be brought to representation, if the mind of the reader could
somehow be deflected from his settled interest in that which is normally unfolding in a represented normal outer
world. This can be achieved I suggest, if the expected order of the outer world is presented matter-of-factly,

24. Brentano, op. cit., Vol. I, Book II, ch. 6.

10
in a step-by-step fashion, but is in some way disrupted. The consciousness of the reader is thereby diverted,
connivingly, into the inner world, but without his clearly realizing that this is what is happening.
Consider, for example, the way in which our attentions become bound up with the inner life of the
narrator in the following passage:
I walked on, unperturbed. But since, as a pedestrian, I dreaded the effort of climbing the mountainous
road, I let it become gradually flatter, let it slope down into a valley in the distance. The stones
vanished at my will and the wind disappeared.
I walked at a brisk pace and since I was on my way down I raised my head, stiffened my body, and
crossed my arms behind my head. Because I love pinewoods I went through woods of this kind, and
since I like gazing silently up at the stars, the stars appeared slowly in the sky, as is their wont. I saw
only a few fleecy clouds which a wind, blowing just at their height, pulled through the air, to the
astonishment of the pedestrian.
Opposite and at some distance from my road, probably separated from it by a river as well, I caused
to rise an enormously high mountain whose plateau, overgrown with brushwood, bordered on the sky.
I would see quite clearly the little ramifications of the highest branches and their movements. This
sight, ordinary as it may be, made me so happy that I, as a small bird on a twig of those distant
scrubby bushes, forgot to let the moon come up. It lay already behind the mountain, no doubt angry
at the delay.25
The narrative of Kafka’s writings is, to a striking extent, a matter of the portrayal of experience from
the point of view of the main protagonist. But Kafka almost never resorts to the expression of any kind of
active introspection. His portrayal of an oblique consciousness of the inner world is achieved, rather, by way
of some contrast with an expected or somehow typical order in external reality, or of some breakdown of the
expected intermeshing of the inner and the outer. The character of dogged literalism of Kafka’s writings seems
therefore to be a device to catch the reader off his guard when the expectations of a natural or reasonable order
in the external world which it arouses are upset. Kafka’s depictions of bare reality are never superfluous, never
introduced for merely ornamental purposes. But nor, either, does he take great pains to achieve any particular
social or psychological realism in his descriptions, especially in regard to his subsidiary protagonists. The
depiction of external reality serves rather the predominant end of allowing some particular aspect of oblique
consciousness to show forth.

§ 4. On Our Knowledge of Right and Wrong


Brentano’s reputation in Austria in the first decades of this century, outside the narrow circle of philosophers
and theoretical psychologists, was principally as an ethical philosopher. His On the Origins of our Knowledge
of Right and Wrong was as familiar in Vienna as was Moore’s Principia Ethica (which it in some ways

25. “Beschreibung eines Kampfes”, Kafka 1970, pp. 207 f. (Eng. trans. 1971, p. 22.)

11
resembles26) amongst intellectuals in Bloomsbury or Cambridge. This popularity was partly a reflection of the
fact that Brentano succeeded, in that work, in capturing the tenor of the world view shared by many central
European intellectuals of his day, and hence it would be surprising if we did not find at least echoes of
Brentano’s ethical ideas in Kafka’s writings.
As already pointed out, three fundamental categories of psychical phenomena are recognized by
Brentano: presentations, judgments, and phenomena of love and hate. Every conscious action is accompanied
by or is fused together with one or more of these phenomena: for example an action of beheading may be
accompanied by an inner perception on the part of the executioner of his own disgust, etc. Now it is easily
supposed that it is to the last of these categories that ethical questions will relate. The criteria which have been
offered by philosophers in terms of which conduct should be apprehended as ethically correct or incorrect have
tended to consist in assertions to the effect that ethical correctness is to be determined in the light of certain
considerations pertaining to feelings and emotions: that action is good which is felt to be good, or which is
accompanied by a good will, or which is conducive to happiness, etc.
The most important of these doctrines is the doctrine of utilitarianism, which asserts that the ethical
rightness or wrongness of an action is measured directly in terms of the pleasure or pain which are its
consequences. This conception of the ethical is of a piece with the doctrines of positivistic naturalism that had
come to predominate amongst philosophers in the nineteenth century, doctrines which rested on a rejection of
the possibility of absolute evidence in the ethical, as in all other spheres. The predominance of positivism in
the German-speaking world was brought to an end at the turn of the century by Husserl and the neo-Kantians,
but it received one of its earliest challenges from Brentano’s work on ethics and more specifically from his
doctrine of the ethical centrality of judgment.
Brentano’s belief in the possibility of absolute evidence derived from his conception of the
implications of the existence of certain variations in the quality of evidence in general, and thus also in the
quality of the mental acts which are the carriers of evidence. Consider, for example, in relation to the
simplest category of psychical phenomena – the category of presentations – the fact that we can hear or
remember or imagine a tone or melody more or less clearly, more or less completely, more or less vividly,
and so on. In relation to each of the given types of presentation there are obvious and undeniable variations
in quality of the associated evidence. While these variations may depend in part upon native ability (good
hearing, for example), they may also depend upon acquired habits or skills (on various forms of training).
Variations in the quality of evidence are equally familiar in the sphere of judgment. Thus we may be
aware, on the one hand, that a particular belief which we have held for many years rests merely on authority
or on custom, on information inadequately checked, or on an emotion or feeling whose grounds have never been

26. Moore’s Preface contains the following passage: ‘When this book had been already completed, I found, in
Brentano’s “Origin of our Knowledge of Right and Wrong”, opinions far more closely resembling my own, than those
of any other writer with whom I am acquainted.’ (pp. xf.). Cf. also Moore’s review of Brentano’s work, published in
1903.

12
explicitly thought through. On the other hand we may be aware that a belief rests on factual data which we
have subjected to the most thorough checks, or that it rests on immediate evidence (the evidence of inner
perception), either directly or via deductive steps which themselves rest on immediate evidence. The idea of
absolute certainty, of the greatest possible evidence of a judgment – which has nothing to do with the feelings
of certainty by which a judgment may be accompanied – is now obtained by considering, on the basis of an
examination of all possible axes of variation in quality of evidence, that kind of judgment which would, in
suitably propitious circumstances, exhibit the maximum conceivable evidence along each such axis.
Brentano wished to defend the thesis that a judgment’s character of being capable of absolute evidence
is something objective. This thesis Brentano would have interpreted as something non-controversial. For
although some of the axes of variation which we have considered rest on the presence or absence of subjective
features (for example strength of emotional commitment), this presence or absence itself is not in its turn
something subjective. The character of certainty is objective also in that it does not rest on the particular
distribution of dispositions to check one’s premises, to examine arguments, etc., across a given population, nor
upon the techniques of theory construction, etc., in existence at any given stage. That a judgment has the
potentiality for absolute evidence or certainty is something that pertains to the judgment alone, and would
remain the case even if a corresponding insight on the part of judging subjects were never in fact achieved.
Another way of expressing the fact that a judgment has, in itself, the capacity for being executed with
absolute evidence is to say that the judgment is true. For Brentano, the only judgments whose character of
absolute evidence is capable of being realized by thinking subjects such as human beings are judgments relating
to psychical phenomena – but this need not imply that these are the only judgments which are true.27
There is, now, an analogue in the sphere of phenomena of love and hate to the phenomenon of
experienced variations in quality of evidence in the sphere of judgments: phenomena of love and hate, of
approval and disapproval, too, may be executed with a greater or lesser degree of clarity and distinctness, may
to a greater or lesser extent be clouded by alien or conflicting elements. Thus we can isolate an ethical analogue
of the notion of absolute evidence – a notion of an act of love, for example, carried out in such a way as to
partake of the highest possible clarity, immediacy, etc. Whether acts ever do exhibit this character as a matter
of fact is not here at issue: we are concerned merely to establish the coherence of the notion and the consistency
of the picture of the ethical world which it dictates. The ethical analogue of truth is the quality of correctness
hereby determined: those actions are ethically correct which rest, or which could in principle rest, on acts of
love or of approval partaking of the given character of maximal purity. The phenomenon of correct love thus
yields an ultimate foundation for the edifice of ethical knowledge (for the edifice of my ethical knowledge about
the rightness or wrongness of my own actions).

27. From the assumption that only judgments relating to psychical phenomena were true it would follow, of course,
that the world of external objects simply did not exist.

13
The range of actions whose evident character of goodness is yielded in an immediate fashion by this
criterion of correctness may well be very slight indeed (may be confined to examples such as: achieve
knowledge of the truth, encourage friendliness, bring about the best within the widest area you are capable of
influencing). There is clearly no possibility of manufacturing anything like a pair of ethical spectacles which
would enable us to grasp immediately the degree of ethical correctness of an action in those highly complex
circumstances where ethical problems normally arise. How, then, if at all, is the range of Brentanian ethics to
be extended from such simple truisms to the level where it can cope with full-blooded ethical dilemmas in the
day-to-day world?
We note, first of all, that the status of complex ethical problems is no different in principle from that
of correspondingly complex factual problems. It may be only in relation to a comparatively small number of
scientific judgments that a truly adequate evidence is ever achieved: the day-to-day application of science to
the material world rests on the development of habitual practices rooted only partially in this evidential basis.
The serviceability of these expedients masks the fact that in the development of our knowledge of the factual
world there is, at any given stage, a threshold beyond which no evident judgments can be achieved. And what
applies to the sphere of factual judgment applies also, Brentano argues, to the ethical sphere. Here, too, the
continuous need for resolution of complex problems (as faced, for example, by physicians, insurance claim
assessors, judges and political officials), has led to the evolution of complex networks of rules of thumb on
different levels and to the gradual entrenchment of associated customs and conventions, so that the framework
of law as a whole can be said to constitute, from one point of view, a slowly evolving instrument for the
pragmatic resolution of ethical dilemmas in society. The fact that expedients of this kind have to be accepted
in the sphere of ethical practice should not be taken to imply that it is not proper to consider how the threshold
of evidence might in principle be extended. Nor, still more importantly, does it sanction the assumption that
the resolution of ethical problems is – as the positivists believed – merely a matter of convention. Brentano’s
ethical theory is more than anything else an affirmation of the objectivity of ethical value and of the existence
of (perhaps factually undiscoverable) intrinsically optimal resolutions of all ethical dilemmas. Just as a
proposition is, in itself, true or false, independently of our recognition of its truth-value, so an action is ethically
correct or incorrect (or a determinate mixture of the two) irrespective of our apprehension of its moral value.

§ 5. The Inner Tribunal


We can now determine more precisely the role played by judgment, and specifically by evident judgment, in
the ethical sphere. An action is ethically correct if it could in principle rest upon acts of love or of approval
partaking of the character of maximal purity. Now even where it is impossible to establish any direct link
between, say, an action directed towards a loved object and a judgment of the correctness of the underlying act
of love, it may yet be possible to verify the correctness of the given action by indirect means, namely by chains
of (evident) judgments (judgments relating to the psychical phenomena of the subject involved), subject to

14
precisely the criteria of sufficient attestation, clarity, etc., established above. But then the processes which are
involved in certifying the correctness of one’s actions, in passing judgment upon oneself – processes involving
the gathering and sorting of relevant data of inner perception, the testing of conclusions, etc. – turn the inner
life of the ethical individual into something like a court of law.
There is, if one will, a strain of radical inner-directed rigorism that is implied by the Brentanian
approach to ethics, and here Wagenbach sees a quite specific influence on Kafka’s later writings: “The
influence of the Brentano circle ... can hardly be underestimated, especially as an element in the development
of his later ethical rigorism founded on a kind of judgmental necromancy (Urteilsmagie)” (op. cit., p. 116).
As already noted, the generation of Austrian intellectuals which succeeded Brentano manifests an acute
scepticism in relation to the liberal belief in the power of politics to bring about the good. Many members of
this generation embraced ethical doctrines of a resolutely individualistic sort. Kafka’s protagonists, too, are
turned in upon themselves, to the extent that they perceive the machinery of social and political order with
somnambulant incomprehension. Yet their thoughts and actions are not played out within a space which is
ethically empty. They are characterized, rather, by an ever-present ethical confusion (guilt). Where, as above
all in The Trial, a serious attempt is made to break free of this confusion, to substitute light for ethical
darkness, this can be seen to involve just those internal processes which, in the Brentanian framework,
transform the mind of the individual concerned into what amounts to a court of law .

§ 6. The Case of Joseph K.


The ethically confused individual can resolve his interior dilemma, can lead an ethically contented life, only if
he can reach the point where he can pass judgment over himself. This is possible, only if he knows the extent
of his physical and mental capacities, and if he can apprehend completely the extent of his own limitations and
is blessed with the patience not to want to break through these limitations in a self-delusory way: “Complete
knowledge of oneself. To be able to seize the whole of one’s abilities like a little ball. To accept the greatest
decline as something familiar and so still remain elastic within it.” (Diary entry for 8 April 1912) Or, as Neesen
puts it (op. cit., p. 143): “Only in stillness, in the consciousness of one’s own possibilities and in patient
modesty, can one lead a contented life.”
Kafka’s narrative in The Trial straddles the boundary between law and psychology, above all by
exploiting the ambiguity between judgment as mental act and as legal process. This ambiguity is never
resolved, because our everyday conception of the boundary between the inner and the outer (social) world has
been suspended. A certain set of psychic phenomena – particularly those bound up be with K.’s constant need
for self-justification – can be seen to determine a reality of their own, projected upon or merged with or folded
into ordinary external reality. As Gregor Samsa’s conception of himself and of his body determine his bodily
shape and behaviour in the hybrid ‘outside world’ which he has created, so K.’s continual trial within himself
is also a real trial in the outer world in which K. imagines he is living. Since this world is, in whole or in part,

15
a fabrication – ‘All is imaginary – family, office, friends, the street, all imaginary’28 – so the trial, too, is never
more than partially real (it can attain its sanction only from the mental acts of K. himself) .
We are told at the very beginning of Kafka’s text that the authorities standing in judgment over K. do
not make their inquiries in order to discover guilt. Rather, ‘as it is stated in the law’, they merely ‘follow in the
path of guilt’. K. is arrested; but it is made clear that his arrest should stand in the way of neither his profession
nor of his everyday mode of living. As K. searches for the court he has at first no idea where he is supposed
to go. But then he suddenly remembers the statement that the court would ‘follow in the path of guilt’, and he
sees that from this that ‘it immediately followed that the investigation room had to lie at the top of the flight
of steps that he had chosen by accident’. The court, therefore, is there, where K. himself has ordained that it
should be, as if he were carrying it about with him as part of his personal baggage. And as he is sitting in the
court-room he realizes that the trial itself is a trial only if he recognizes it as such.
Any kind of defence before the court is not actually permitted, but only tolerated – although there is
some dispute even concerning that. And in general the proceedings are not only closed to the public, but also
to the defendant. For it is not the evidence which is actually brought forward in the court that is decisive, but
that which is passed about in the deliberation rooms and in adjoining corridors. There is some probability that
the innocence of the defendant may play a role in any acquittal which may actually take place – though an
acquittal is of course something which rarely happens, and it is never to be achieved by somehow influencing
the judge. When it does happen, however, not only the summons and all the other documents of the trial are
to be destroyed, but also the acquittal and indeed the trial itself are to pass completely out of existence.
In the end K. is told that he himself must come to a decision whether or not to recognize the court. ‘The
court doesn’t want anything of you. It will admit you if you come, and it will set you free if you go.’ And as
K. is being led to his execution he knows that he himself must be his own executioner. Who, then, as K. himself
asks, was the judge, whom he had never seen, and where was the court, at which up to the very end he had
never arrived? The answer, after all that has been said, is clear. The judge, the court and the trial itself are
projections of K.’s own inner experience, projections from the world of inner perception out into the world of
external affairs. And at least one aspect of the shaping force behind this projection is K.’s conviction that
morally correct action demands of him that he somehow attain to an absolutely evident judgment. Because he
thinks that this is something which he can achieve only as the result of some deliberative process, a process
which would presuppose a whole series of investigations and deliberations, and because, as he is dimly aware,
he is himself incapable of realizing such a process in a straightforward way (is incapable of being honest with
himself), he brings about a series of events having the nature of an obscurely perceived legal trial which would
do the job for him. ‘Since one becomes clear about oneself by means of a judgment, and since this judgment
must be passed in the centre of the self, this self itself becomes a kind of tribunal.’ (Neesen, op. cit., p. 205).
‘[S]ince the court is inside Josef K. himself, it becomes understandable that it need not interrupt the ordinary

28. Diary entry for 21 October 1921.

16
course of his life. And for the same reason the court is everywhere where K. searches for it, and also where he
does not expect it.’ (loc. cit.)
Where, as in the Austria of the later Habsburg Empire, respect for society as moral arbiter has been
called into question, this role must be appropriated by the conscience of the individual subject. Where ethical
reward and ethical punishment can no longer be regarded as events in the world, they must be conceived as
residing in the action itself. Guilt and punishment are not two separate things; they are one and identical. And
then it is possible to draw at least this amount of reassurance: that there is no criminal who truly escapes the
punishment which is his due. The philosophical foundations of this introverted world have been described by
Brentano and – still more radically – by Weininger and Wittgenstein. But it is Kafka who has shown most
clearly what it might be like to live in such a world, a world in which the individual subject is driven into
himself to such an extent that the belief in an external order of reality slowly begins to appear as so much
superstition.

Bibliography
Ash, Mitchell G. 1995 Gestalt Psychology in German Culture 1890–1920: Holism and the Quest for
Objectivity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bense, Max 1952 Die Theorie Kafkas, Berlin: Kiepenhauer and Witsch.
Bergmann, Hugo 1908 Untersuchungen zum Problem der Evidenz der inneren Wahrnehmung, Halle:
Niemeyer.
Bergmann, Hugo 1909 Das philosophische Werk Bernard Bolzanos, Halle: Niemeyer.
Bezzel, C. 1975 Kafka-Chronik, Munich: Hanser.
Binder, Hartmut 1966 Motiv und Gestaltung bei Franz Kafka, Bonn: Bouvier .
Binder, Hartmut 1980 Kafka-Handbuch, 2 vols., Stuttgart: Kröner.
Bokhove, Niels 1981 Het sociaal-wijsgerig denken van Franz Kafka, Dissertation, Rijksuniversiteit Utrecht.
Brentano, Franz 1924 Psychologie vom empirischen Standpunkt, 2nd ed., with an introduction by Oskar
Kraus, Leipzig: Felix Meiner (1st ed. 1874); English translation by L. L. McAlister, Psychology from an
Empirical Standpoint, London: Routledge, 1973.
Brentano, Franz 1934 Vom Ursprung sittlicher Erkenntnis, 3rd revised ed., with an introduction by Oskar
Kraus, Leipzig: Meiner (lst ed. 1889). Eng. trans. by R.M. Chisholm and E. H. Schneewind, The Origin
of our Knowledge of Right and Wrong, London: Routledge, 1969.
Brentano, Franz 1982 Deskriptive Psychologie, Hamburg: Felix Meiner. English translation by Benito Müller,
Descriptive Psychology, London and New York: Routledge, 1995.
Brod, Max 1960 Streitbares Leben. Autobiographie, Munich: Kindler .
Brod, Max 1974 Franz Kafka – Eine Biographie, 3rd ed., Frankfurt: Fischer .
Busse, Ludwig 1903 Geist und Körper, Seele und Leib, Leipzig: Dürr.
Chisholm, R. M. 1981 The First Person, Hassocks: Harvester.

17
Demetz, P. 1955 “Kafka, Freud, Husserl: Probleme einer Generation”, Zeitschrift für Religions- und
Geistesgeschichte, 7, 59–69.
Emrich, W. 1960 Franz Kafka, 2nd ed., Frankfurt: Athenäum.
Fabian, Reinhard (ed.) 1986 Christian von Ehrenfels: Leben und Werk, Amsterdam: Rodopi.
Grassl, Wolfgang and Smith, Barry (eds.) 1986 Austrian Economics: Historical and Philosophical
Background, New York: New York University Press, London/Sydney: Croom Helm.
Grassl, Wolfgang and Smith, Barry 1986 “A Theory of Austria”, in J. C. Nyíri, ed., From Bolzano to
Wittgenstein: The Tradition of Austrian Philosophy, Vienna: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky, Dordrecht: Reidel
(1986), 11–30.
Harder, M.-L. 1962 Märchenmotive in der Dichtung Franz Kafkas, Dissertation Freiburg (mimeographed).
Heaton, J. M. 1981 “Brentano and Freud”, in B. Smith, ed., Structure and Gestalt. Philosophy and Literature
in Austria-Hungary, Amsterdam: Benjamins , 161–94 .
Heidsieck, Arnold 1994 The Intellectual Contexts of Kafka’s Fiction: Philosophy, Law, Religion, Columbia,
SC: Camden House.
Johnston, W. M. 1972 The Austrian Mind. An Intellectual and Social History 1848–1938, Berkeley:
University of California Press.
Kafka, Franz 1953 Hochzeitsvorbereitung auf dem Lande und andere Prosa aus dem Nachlass, New York:
Schocken.
Kafka, Franz 1970 Sämtliche Erzählungen, Frankfurt: Fischer.
Kafka, Franz 1971 The Complete Stories, New York: Schocken.
Kowalewski, G. 1950 Bestand und Wandel. Meine Lebenserinnerungen, zugleich ein Beitrag zur neueren
Geschichte der Mathematik, Munich: Oldenbourg.
Küng, Guido 1978 “Zur Erkenntnistheorie von Franz Brentano”, in R.M. Chisholm and R. Haller, eds., Die
Philosophie Franz Brentanos, Amsterdam: Rodopi, 169–82.
Marek, Johannes and Smith, Barry 1987 “Einleitung zu A. Martys ‘Elemente der deskriptiven Psychologie’”,
Conceptus, 21, 33–48, editors’ introduction to extracts from Marty’s lectures (ibid., 49–66).
Moore, G. E. 1903 Principia Ethica, Cambridge: University Press.
Moore, G. E. 1903a Review of Franz Brentano, The Origin of the Knowledge of Right and Wrong,
International Journal of Ethics, 14, 115–23.
Neesen, P. 1972 Vom Louvrezirkel zum Prozess. Franz Kafka und die Psychologie Franz Brentanos,
Göppingen: Kümmerle.
Neurath, Otto et al. 1938 International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, vol. I, no. 1, Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Nyíri, J. C. 1982 "Intellectual Foundations of Austrian Liberalism", in Grassl and Smith, eds., 102–138.
Nyíri, J. C. ed. 1981 Austrian Philosophy: Studies and Texts, Munich: Philosophia.

18
Pondrom, C. M. 1967 “Kafka and Phenomenology. Josef K.'s Search for Information”, Wisconsin Studies
in Contemporary Literature, 878–95.
Schorske, C. E. 1960/61 “Politics and the Psyche in fin de siècle Vienna: Schnitzler and Hofmannsthal”,
American Historical Review, 66, 930–46.
Schorske, C. E. 1967 “Politics in a New Key: An Austrian Triptych”, Journal of Modern History, 39, 343–86.
Schorske, C. E. 1980 Fin-de-Siècle Vienna, New York: Knopf.
Smith, Barry 1978 “Law and Eschatology in Wittgenstein's Early Thought”, Inquiry, 14, 425–41.
Smith, Barry 1981 “Kafka and Brentano: A Study in Descriptive Psychology”, in Barry Smith, ed., Structure
and Gestalt. Philosophy and Literature in Austria-Hungary, Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Smith, Barry 1994 Austrian Philosophy: The Legacy of Franz Brentano, La Salle and Chicago: Open Court.
Utitz, Emil 1954 “Erinnerungen an Franz Brentano”, Wissenschaftliche Zeitschrift der Universität Halle-
Wittenberg, Gesellschafts- und sprachwissenschaftliche Reihe, 4 (1954–55), 73–90.
Wagenbach, Klaus 1958 Franz Kafka. Eine Biographie seiner Jugend, 1883–1912, Bern: Francke.
Weininger, Otto 1903 Geschlecht und Charakter. Eine prinzipielle Untersuchung, Vienna: Braumüller.

19

You might also like