Evolution Kurf PDF
Evolution Kurf PDF
Evolution Kurf PDF
Economics, Evolution
and the State
The Governance of Complexity
Edited by
Kurt Dopfer
Professor of Economics, University of St Gallen, Switzerland
Edward Elgar
Cheltenham, UK • Northampton, MA, USA
© Kurt Dopfer 2005
Published by
Edward Elgar Publishing Limited
Glensanda House
Montpellier Parade
Cheltenham
Glos GL50 1UA
UK
Printed and bound in Great Britain by MPG Books Ltd, Bodmin, Cornwall
Contents
List of contributors vii
Introduction 1
Kurt Dopfer
v
vi Contents
Index 351
Contributors
Hans-Peter Brunner, Asian Development Bank, Manila
Uwe Cantner, Friedrich-Schiller-Universität Jena
Kurt Dopfer, Universität St Gallen
Malcolm H. Dunn, Universität Potsdam
Monika Friedrich-Nishio, Institute for Economic Policy Research (IWW),
Karlsruhe University
Hariolf Grupp, Fraunhofer Institute for Systems and Innovation Research
(ISI) and Karlsruhe University
Horst Hanusch, Universität Augsburg
Reiner Peter Hellbrück, Fachhochschule Würzburg-Schweinfurt
Carsten Herrmann-Pillath, Universität Witten-Herdecke
Wolfgang Kerber, Philipps-Universität Marburg
Matthias Klaes, Keele University
Lambert T. Koch, Bergische Universität Wuppertal
Icíar Dominguez Lacasa, Fraunhofer Institute for Systems and Innovation
Research (ISI), Karlsruhe
Andreas Pyka, Universität Augsburg
P. Paolo Saviotti, INRA, Université Pierre Mendes-France, Grenoble
Joachim Schwerin
Gerhard Wegner, Universität Erfurt
Wolfgang Weidlich, Universität Stuttgart
C. Christian von Weizsäcker, Frontier Economics, Köln
Claudia Werker, Max-Planck-Institut für Ökonomik, Jena
vii
Introduction
Kurt Dopfer
1
2 Introduction
INSTITUTIONAL SETTING
The Verein was founded in the year 1873. The activities of the new association
focused on opposing laissez-faire in social policy and the revolutionary social
ideas of emerging socialism. The founders of the association wanted ‘to raise,
educate and reconcile the lower classes on the basis of the existing order’ as
Gustav Schmoller, the chairman of the Verein for many years (1890–1917), put
it. In Schmoller’s time, the Verein für Socialpolitik started to develop into a polit-
ically neutral, interdisciplinary society. (www.socialpolitik.org)
The contributions to this volume are grouped around three major topics:
economic policy. The author defends the view that contrary to attempts to
label Coase as an arch neoliberal, one can identify a commitment to the
primacy of institutional direction rather than decentralised allocation of
resources across markets as the core building block of his outlook on eco-
nomic policy. This leads to an interpretation of Coase’s approach in terms
of a historico-empirical method of comparative institutional analysis,
which calls both for a hermeneutical approach to economic policy evalua-
tion, and constitutes a form of historical economics that offers an ambi-
tious research agenda for attempts to move the conceptualisation of history
in evolutionary economics beyond affirmations of the relevance of path-
dependent processes. What Coase ultimately offers to evolutionary eco-
nomics is the prospect of a morphological analysis that exhibits interesting
parallels to recent developments in evolutionary ‘Evo-Devo’ biology that
have re-established the relevance of ontogenetic approaches to develop-
mental processes.
Andreas Pyka and P. Paolo Saviotti in their chapter examine ‘The concept
of network organisation – biotechnology-based industries as exemplar’.
Technological progress in the biological sciences is now advancing across
such a wide range and at such a pace that no firm can hope to keep up in all
the different areas. Participating in innovation networks offers an alterna-
tive to extremely expensive go-it-alone strategies. This imbalance between
the rate of growth of the biotechnology knowledge base and the capability
of individual firms to access it can explain the persistence of cooperative
R&D in the biotechnology-based sectors at the end of the 1990s. Such
imbalance is not due any more only to the lack of absorptive capacity of
large pharmaceutical firms, because they have meanwhile developed con-
siderable competencies in that field. The authors are proposing that a new
role, that of explorers scanning parts of the knowledge space that LDFs
(large diversified firms) are capable of exploring but unwilling to commit
themselves to in an irreversible way, can be played by DBFs (dedicated
biotechnology firms) in innovation networks. The authors’ simulation
approach attempts to represent the emergence of these two roles as endo-
genous changes in the motivation for participating in innovation networks,
allowing them to become an important and long-lasting organisational
device for industrial R&D.
The contribution by Wolfgang Weidlich deals with ‘Sociodynamics – an
integrated approach to modelling in the social sciences’. Sociodynamics – an
important branch of the emergent field of econophysics – aims at providing
a general strategy for designing mathematical models for the quantitative
6 Introduction
invariant patterns. They apply this concept to the analysis of innovation and
growth, where they demonstrate that the openness of the set of identified
patterns towards a changing environment is a prerequisite for learning.
Their results, which lead to some policy guidelines, serve as a reference
system for innovation policy that meets evolutionary standards.
‘The national German innovation system – its development in different
governmental and territorial structures’ by Hariolf Grupp, Icíar
Dominguez Lacasa and Monika Friedrich-Nishio provides several long
time series of R&D indicators bridging more than 100 years of German
economic history. The ups and downs are put into perspective and com-
pared to important events in the global innovation system. The pertinence
found for the national German innovation system seems to rest in educa-
tional, cultural and language traditions rather than in governance and
territorial coverage, which changed many times. This is possibly due to path
dependence of technological paradigms. The suggested range of indicators
on a national or sectorial level gives a detailed impression of both the extent
and the contents of innovation activities. The empirical base which evolu-
tionary researchers, interested in innovation and economic history-related
questions, can rely on, has been broadened to a large extent, so that there
is no longer a serious empirical gap.
Reiner Peter Hellbrück’s ‘Emergence and diffusion of disastrous inno-
vations – a case study’ examines diabetes care in Germany. There is a con-
sensus among all specialists that diabetes care needs to be improved. Hence,
there has been steady development, improvement, and implementation of
programmes for diabetes care in Germany. In virtually all German lands
there is at least one (legal) health insurance fund which is offering a diabetes
programme. For this purpose special contracts between at least one health
insurance fund and some health care providers have to be signed. These
contracts contain an extra budgeting payment to the health care providers.
Those contracts have the charm for the health care providers of earning,
supplementary to their regular budgets, extra money. Health insurance
funds have in turn been hurt by concluding such contracts when evaluated
on a regulation ruling from 1993 up to 2000. The chapter tries to answer
the following questions: What reasons led to the conclusion of such con-
tracts? Why are these contracts under today’s laws, rules, and regulations a
hazard to health insurance funds and their business? Why did those disas-
trous contracts diffuse at all? Which strategies are chosen to reduce the
hazard to insurance business? Why are these business-harming innovations
not simply stopped?
In his chapter ‘Applying evolutionary economics to public policy – the
example of competitive federalism in the EU,’ Wolfgang Kerber states that
due to the Hayekian knowledge problem it seems often to be very difficult
Introduction 9
1. INTRODUCTION
13
14 Economic evolution as open process
This chapter will be dealing partly with the first and mainly with the second
step. For the third step we refer to the literature.
The methodology suggested is of a rather general character in the
sense that it can be applied on several levels of aggregation, i.e. firms,
sectors or countries. This rather common conception about technological
heterogeneity is applied with respect to the productive structure of a sample
of observations under consideration. We suggest that those structures can
be dealt with looking at (a) the differences in total factor productivity
and (b) the differences in input-intensities, output-intensities and/or output
coefficients.
In order to identify such heterogeneous structures and to track their
development and their change over time we suggest a specific empirical
approach. For this purpose we introduce a two-step analysis consisting of
the non-parametric procedure to construct production or efficiency frontiers
and the Malmquist-productivity index to track the change of this structure
over time.
The plan of the chapter is as follows. In section 2 we will briefly refer to
some theoretical issues describing, firstly, the role heterogeneity plays in the
evolutionary framework; secondly, we ask for the criteria to be applied in
order to determine the analytically relevant heterogeneity in empirical data
and put forward three requirements for the empirical approach to be
employed. In section 3 we refer to the measure total factor productivity, dis-
tinguish our procedure from the traditional way of computing this measure
and briefly introduce the main methodological approach we have chosen in
order to detect heterogeneity and to track its development over time. The
final section 4 summarises our approach and discusses some as yet unre-
solved issues and problems.
Heterogeneity
In economics, there are a number of distinguishing elements of the
neoclassical and the evolutionary approach. Probably one of the most
important ones is the heterogeneity of behaviour, attitudes, characteristics
etc. of agents.4 Thus, what heterogeneity is all about is asymmetry among
the agents in a set. However, it is not at all obvious whether this asymmetry
matters for the description of the state of this set or for its development
over time. In neoclassical approaches one would deny this in general with
the consequence that the theoretical models suggested are characterised by
symmetry of agents or even by a representative agent.5 All the approaches
designed in this way are justified by the attitude that for the final outcome
of a certain process the differences in agents’ behaviour during this process
do not matter – it is just average behaviour which is determining the result
and which analytically is relevant and interesting. Hence, heterogeneity is
of an only temporary nature and as such it is a phenomenon only showing
up during transitory dynamics.
Heterogeneity or asymmetry is a fundamental principle in the theories of
economic evolution. Selectionist approaches, synergetic approaches and
developmental approaches rely on it and discuss how the system’s nature or
structure as well as how its (structural) dynamics is affected or driven by it.
However, in each approach the way heterogeneity affects evolutionary
development is quite specific: in the selectionist approach it is heterogeneity
which is reduced by competition and generated by innovation. In the syn-
ergetic approach it is heterogeneity which brings about specific structural,
self-organising features with respect to learning, cooperation etc. In the
developmental approach, finally, heterogeneity is a matter of stages of
development (to be) passed.
improve performance when the gaps become too large and on leaders when
the gaps become too close; and that it provides for different kinds of learn-
ing processes (imitative and adaptive learning, cross-fertilisation etc.).
In order to account for the heterogeneity of agents driven by and driving
technological change one draws on the close relationship between the char-
acteristics and the behaviour of agents, on the one hand, and the kind of
inputs which, on the other hand, they transform into outputs. In fact, in the
theory of technological change the actors are characterised by the nature,
the level and the degree of their innovative activities – either on the input
or on the output side.
In this respect heterogeneity can be accounted for by the conception of
variety (Saviotti 1996). This concept is based on the number of distin-
guishable elements of a set of artifacts.6 In this sense Saviotti (1996, p. 94)
distinguishes output and input variety, the former being the number of
distinguishable outputs and the latter taking account of the number of dis-
tinguishable types of processes.
However, heterogeneity in general and within the context of innovative-
ness in particular is not only a matter of simply counting distinguishable
elements. Any innovator attempts to perform better than competitors, and
this ‘better’ may show up in providing goods and services with superior
price–quality ratios – compared to those of the competitors. Thus, more
often than not one would like to have a conception which allows for a quan-
tification of the differences on which heterogeneity rests. Hence, with respect
to output variety one would be interested whether the variety observed is
also built upon measurable quality differences (i.e. ‘higher’ and ‘lower’
quality) or whether this variety is found within a more narrow or more broad
range of the specific characteristic under consideration (i.e. ‘more’ or ‘less’
built-in features). Equivalently, with respect to input or production variety
we should have an account of whether the several techniques in use are
rather similar or far different with respect to their efficiency (i.e. ‘more’ or
‘less’ efficient) or their relative input requirements (e.g. ‘more’ or ‘less’
capital-intensive).
An appropriate conception in this respect is found in Dosi (1988,
pp. 1155–7) who is concerned with the asymmetry of activities and distin-
guishes variety as a special case of asymmetry. Both are to be seen in a
context where firms engaged in innovative activities are affected differently
by technological change in terms of their process technologies and quality
(or kind) of output. Whenever firms can be ranked as ‘better’ or ‘worse’
according to their distance to some technological frontier he refers to as
asymmetry. The degree of asymmetry of an industry is then its dispersion
of input efficiencies for a given (homogeneous) output and price-weighted
performance characteristics of firms’ (differentiated) products. For all
Heterogeneity and evolutionary change 17
To state the importance of heterogeneity is one side of the coin, the other
one is to clearly specify in which unit we should measure or observe het-
erogeneity and this in a way that it is also analytically relevant.
To identify heterogeneity in empirical work is not an easy and straight-
forward task at all. In principle, one is facing a similar problem to that the
typological approach is confronted with: what is essential for analysing
the issue under consideration? Whereas the typological approach searches
for some reliable average characteristic, the population perspective is con-
fronted with the task of finding characteristics which are diverse, i.e. het-
erogeneous, and as such essential for performance and the progress of the
population under consideration. Looking for variables which can render
this, one more often than not has to be engaged in rather detailed analyses
of a nearly case-study type. Although the results are often very illuminat-
ing and interesting, it is very often not possible to transfer the methodology
and the results of one study to another one; the aggregation of several
results is often not possible, because the relevant variables are not of the
same type, and so on.
3. Any aggregation from the business unit to the firm, to the sector and
industry, to the regional or even to the macro-economic level is not pos-
sible anymore. The reason for that is quite obvious, because to aggre-
gate the products of different firms in a sector, the products of different
sectors in an economy cannot be accomplished when technical attrib-
utes are used such as pieces, kg, Mb etc.
Generality
As already claimed we are interested in a generally applicable measure which
allows one to track technological change on several levels of aggregation
and in several fields of application. Thus, what we have to accept is a loss of
specificity especially found if one applies the analysis on lower levels of
22 Economic evolution as open process
aggregation often coming close to pure case studies. The loss of specificity,
however, is counterbalanced (and in our view even overcompensated) by the
opportunity to detect more general insights into structure and change
whose driving elements are found on the individual level of actors and firms,
whose collective outcome then shows up in a characteristic manner on the
next level of aggregation and so forth. In this respect the measure of total
factor productivity is applicable to all levels and areas of aggregation when-
ever we have at hand appropriate data on outputs and inputs. The latter we
assume to be satisfied – although we are readily aware of the problem of
whether the data we use in the analysis are at all the appropriate measures
and/or proxies. We do not want to discuss this issue further here.
Construction
Index numbers for total factor productivity (TFP) have found a prominent
application in growth-accounting exercises. There it is aggregate output Y,
prominently GDP, set into relation to an aggregate I of various input
factors, prominently labour and capital:
Y
TFP
I
One can easily apply this measure to lower levels of aggregation such as to
the sectoral level10 and to the firm level. Any change in total factor product-
ivity, in the sense that this indicator rises, is considered as the effect of tech-
nological progress, i.e. that change in output which cannot be accounted for
by a change in aggregate inputs. It is this so-called residual which attracted
so much research especially in the analysis of economic growth. And it is
also this residual that Abramovitz called ‘our measure of ignorance’.
A first question arising in this context refers to whether TFP can be taken
as a measure of technological performance and whether a change in total
factor productivity can adequately account for technological change. Let
us take up this issue accordingly.
Requirements 2 and 3 ask for a method which allows one to determine TFP
in such a way that technological heterogeneity in the sense of asymmetry
and variety shows up. For this purpose we suggest a non-parametric fron-
tier function approach.
uTYj
hj (1.1)
vTXj
Comparison of performance
For doing this, the basic principle of the non-parametric approach is just
to determine the indices hj in such a way that they can be interpreted as
efficiency ratings which implies a comparison of each observation with the
best observation(s). The (relatively) most efficient observations of a sample
26 Economic evolution as open process
min l
st:
Yl Yl
lXl Xl 0 (1.3)
l 0
x2/y
C
A C
Ft
B
O
x1/y
y2/x
D
A
C
C
B
Ft
O y1/x
unit of input x two outputs, y1 and y2. The frontier function is a transform-
ation curve. The performance of an observation C is again evaluated
against this frontier here given by the ratio OC
to OC.20
So far, the observations of sample are considered as using all the same
categories of inputs and to produce all the same kinds of output – although
to a different degree. In addition to that the procedure suggested is readily
able to deal also with more diversity such as observations which use an add-
itional type of input or produce an additional kind of output. This latter is
appropriate if we deal with product innovations. Figures 1.1c and 1.1d
show the kind of technology frontier we get in such cases in the input space
(1.1c) and in the output space (1.1d).
x2/y
C
A
C
Ft
B E
O E
x1/y
Figure 1.1c Extreme input variety and technology frontier in input space
y2/x
D
A
C
Ft
E B
O y1/x
E
The matrices Yl and Xl contain the outputs and inputs of all n observa-
tions except observation l. The modified efficiency measure is *l . For all
below-best-practice observations it is identical to l determined by program
(1.3). However, for all best-practice observations *l is different. It holds
*l 1 and the difference *l 1 can be interpreted as the buffer or lead
observation l holds compared to certain other observations. This *l is a
measure to distinguish observations which with program (1.3) are deter-
mined as not comparable (Cantner/Westermann 1998).
Figure 1.2 states the result of program (1.4) for observation A. The
respective frontier for A in this case is DB and the * A is equal to the ratio
OA
to OA which is larger than 1.
x2/y
Ft
B
O x1/y
For the efficiency measure determined by program (1.5) we get vl l.
Taking the ratio of these two measures, l l vl, states the level of
efficiency which is due to scale with 1 l accounting for that degree of
below best practice which is caused by a size different to the minimum
efficient scale size.
Besides these measures the non-parametric frontier approach does
deliver a number of other measures allowing one to deal with allocative
efficiency, non-radial inefficiencies, specific forms of returns to scale etc.
These are of minor importance in the context of this chapter. More inter-
esting, however, is the dynamic extension of the analysis.
Dynamic analysis
In order to track the structure – determined by the measures introduced
above – it is by no means sufficient to compare the structural results of con-
secutive periods because for each period these measures are of an only rela-
tive type such a comparison makes no sense. Consequently, consecutive
periods have to be set into relation implying that we have to compute rela-
tive measures which compare period t with t
1 and vice versa. Doing this
pairwise for all consecutive periods allows one to track structural change
over time. The procedure chosen for this purpose is based on the Malmquist
index which states a specific observation’s change in productivity between
two periods. A quite interesting feature of this index is that it can be decom-
posed into a measure for technological change and one for catch-up – or, of
course, technological regress and falling behind.
x2/y
At+1 d
At
b
e
Ft
c
Ft+1
O x1/y
0,5
ObOAt OcOAt
A
Mt
1
OdOAt
1 OeOAt
1
lt,t t,t
1
0,5
Mt
1 l
(1.6)
l
t
1,t
l t
1,t
1
l
lt,t t,t
1
0,5
Mt
1 l
l
t
1,t
l t
1,t
1
l
lt,t
t
1,t
1 t,t
1
0,5
l l
l
t
1,t
1 lt
1,t t,t
l
MC· MT. (1.7)
The second line in (1.7) states the decomposition of the productivity change
into technological progress MT and change in the technology gap MC.
Whenever MC1 (MC 1) we find catch-up (falling behind). The second
term is MT and indicates the movement of the frontier. This is measured
twice: first with the factor intensities of l in t, and a second time with
those of l in t
1. With MT1 (MT 1) we have technological progress
34 Economic evolution as open process
ObOAt OeOAt
1 OcOAt 0.5
A
Mt
1
OeOAt
1 OdOAt
1 ObOAt
MC MT.
From this, we can state that the first bracket term measures the change in
the distance of A towards the frontiers Ft and Ft
1. The second term in
brackets takes account of the (geometric) mean change of the frontier part
pertaining to A. In this example both terms will be smaller than 1 indicat-
ing that observation A performed technological progress and was able to
catch up to the frontier.
The second step then tracks this heterogeneity over time and allows for the
following:
4. CONCLUSION
using data which represent economic values – on the output side for
example if one uses sales: then we do not measure the effects on
technology but the economic evaluation of these effects.
● Measurement errors are of considerable influence on the results as
there is no way in which the procedure can deal with this.
5. Finally, the research we attempt to follow aims at shedding some light
on the phenomenon of total factor productivity and its development.
In many applications this is still a black box or residual. To achieve a
better understanding of this residual the procedure suggested might be
an promising way to go.
NOTES
REFERENCES
Solow, R.M. (1957), ‘Technical change and the aggregate production function’,
Review of Economics and Statistics, 39, 312–20.
Stiglitz, J.E. (1987), ‘Learning to learn, localized learning and technological
progress’, in P. Dasgupta and P. Stoneman (eds.), Economic Policy and
Technological Performance, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 125–51.
Wolff, E.N. (1992), ‘Productivity growth and capital intensity on the sectoral and
industry level: specialization among OECD countries, 1970–1988’, working
paper, New York University.
Heterogeneity and evolutionary change 41
APPENDIX
The version of the envelopment form including possible excess inputs and
output slacks reads as
A proportional reduction of inputs (as given by l) does not necessarily lead
to efficiency in the Pareto-Koopmanns sense. To correct for this the remain-
ing excess inputs (s
) and output slacks (s) are taken into account in the
objective function. Vector eT contains only elements 1. (Of course, one
should here distinguish two vectors eT for inputs and output respectively
which contain s and i elements respectively. To ease notation we do not take
account of this. The further analysis is not affected.) is a positive non-
Archimedean small number. Thus, additionally to program (A.1) takes
into account the remaining output slacks or excess inputs. Only then is a
clear-cut selection of efficient and inefficient observations possible.
min lt,s
s.t.:
Ysl Ylt
lXtl Xsl 0 (A.2)
l 0
With these programs T-1 index numbers can be computed for all observa-
tions, with T being the length of the period under investigation.
2. Is the notion of progress compatible
with an evolutionary view of the
economy?
C. Christian von Weizsäcker
2. NORMATIVE INDIVIDUALISM
In a sense it is obvious that the assumption of fixed preferences does not fit
in an evolutionary theory. But I believe it pays to pursue this topic a little
bit further. Obviously biological evolutionary theory in the tradition of
Darwin takes certain things as given. These are the basic natural laws, for
example those of physics. We can wait as long as we want: nature will never
invent the perpetuum mobile because it contradicts basic laws in physics.
But to assume fixed preferences of individuals goes much beyond the
assumption of given physical or chemical natural laws. If we follow Darwin
then there is a great commonality between the nature of humans and the
nature of animals. Behaviour of animals follows certain instincts of those
animals which have turned out in the evolutionary process to be fit for the
survival of that particular species or the genes of that particular species.
Human behaviour in prehistoric times (the ‘Stone Age’) must have followed
the same Darwinian laws. The preferences which have been inherited from
this time have been fit for the survival of the species homo sapiens in these
prehistoric times.13
But one of the conditions for survival of the human species was a certain
flexibility of the human individual. Characteristics specific to the human
species are their ability to plan forward, to use instruments, to produce
instruments, the ability to cooperate on a higher level using developed lan-
guages. These characteristics have been the process of a co-evolution
together with a rising life expectancy, a longer period of infancy which is
characterised by intense learning. From the view of the species as compared
to other species the species has invested much more in individuals. The sur-
vival of the individual has a higher value for the human species than for most
other species because of the substantial investment in this individual. The
mental abilities of the human species enabled it to adapt to quite different
environmental conditions. They meant a particular flexibility which implied
that homo sapiens was able to inhabit a wide variety of climatic zones. All
these factors imply that the share of the total adaptability to changed envir-
onmental conditions which was borne by the individual rather than by the
genes would have to increase. The premium for a higher ability of the indi-
viduals to survive after changing circumstances must have increased.
Under these specific conditions of homo sapiens in prehistoric times it is
highly implausible that preferences, for example preferences for food, have
been fixed once and for all. Much more plausible is the hypothesis that
those individuals had a higher survival value whose preferences were able
to adapt to the specific circumstances, i.e. individuals whose instincts were
sufficiently flexible to adapt behaviour to changed circumstances even
46 Economic evolution as open process
(A; B) ( ) (C; B)
Notion of progress 47
we mean: given that the actual state of the past has been B the agent
prefers A to C. The preference inequality makes sense, because A and C are
compared, given the preferences induced by state B. An inequality like
(A; B) ( ) (C; D) does not make sense, because in evaluating A preferences
are induced by B whereas in evaluating C preferences are induced by D.
Now the axiom of adaptive preferences can be formulated in the follow-
ing way: Let (B; A) ( ) (A; A). Then (B; B) ( ) (A; B).
What is ruled out by this axiom is: (B; A) ( ) (A; A) and at the same time
(A; B) ( ) (B; B) the latter would mean: if the agent is adapted to A he/she
prefers B and if the agent is adapted to B he/she prefers A. In that case the
agent is structurally dissatisfied. It is always better to be where you are not.
Note that you can move the agent between A and B and at each move he/she
feels improved.
Now we observe that in the inequality defining adaptive preferences there
is an asymmetry between A and B. B is preferred to A no matter whether
the past was A or B. We then tend to view a move from A to B to be progress
for the agent. In terms of progress not every pair of choices may be com-
parable. We may have (A; A) ( ) (B; A) and (B; B) ( ) (A; B). Thus it is
not automatically ensured that we can define progress consistently.
Here we now develop a theory. In the next two sections I outline a formal
theory. For adaptive preferences under certain assumptions we can find a
concept of progress which is universally applicable as we are used to it in
a world of fixed preferences. The performance of the economy remains
measurable even though the measuring rod changes with the state of the
economy.
5. THE MODEL14
There is one person who is a consumer of commodity baskets x in the pos-
itive orthant of the n-dimensional Euclidean space RN. We work in a con-
tinuous time model. At each moment t the consumer maximises an
instantaneous utility subject to a budget constraint. But the utility function
U(x) itself depends on past experience as expressed by an n-dimensional
vector q which stands for past consumption. We formalise this dependence
on past consumption in the following way
dq .
q (x q) (2.1)
dt
UU (x; q)
Utilities with different values of q are not comparable; they simply repre-
sent different preferences.
We assume that U is continuously differentiable with respect to x and q.
We now consider consumption paths through time. Among paths x(t)
which are piecewise continuous we define a subset which we call ‘improv-
ing paths’. This description is motivated by an axiom, which allows a
minimum of comparability between different preferences.
Consider a path of vector x through time such that x(0) x0 is the start-
ing point, x(T)xT is the end point and there is a set J with a finite number
of moments of time, called jump points, t1, t2, . . . . . tN such that 0t1
t2 . . . . . . . tN T. Let IT be the interval [0, T] of real numbers. (We
admit the possibility that T 0). Then we consider paths x(t) such that x(t)
is continuous in IT J. We, of course, admit the possibility that the set J of
jump points is empty.
For such paths q(t) is well defined by the differential equation (2.1), if
q(0) q0 is given. Indeed we find the unique solution
t
q(t) e t q0
x(z)ezdz
0
Given that the comparison of utility values for different values of q does
not have an economic meaning the expression U is economically meaning-
less. On the other hand the expression U does have an economic meaning.
If U is positive it means that ‘real income’ increases. For example, if x
comes about by maximisation of U with respect to x subject to a budget
constraint then U 0 implies that either the budget rises or the price index
Notion of progress 49
(in terms of the Divisia index) falls, i.e. that real income rises. Therefore it
is plausible to talk about an improvement if U 0.
We use the following notation for piecewise continuous paths x(t). By
{x(t); q0; T} we mean a path of the piecewise continuous consumption
vector x(t) in the time interval [0,T] such that preferences are determined
by q(t) e t [q0
x(z)ezdz] with the initial value q0.
t
0
We then can talk of an improvement path. It is basically a path in time
{x(t); q0; T} such that U 0 along the whole path and there are either
improvement jumps or there is a subinterval in which U 0 is strictly
positive. A path is called weakly improving, if U 0, wherever it is
defined and utility does not decline at jump points. Note that an improve-
ment path is then weakly improving. But there may be paths which are
weakly improving but not improving. One example is a path along which
U 0.
I now introduce the improvement axiom. Since preferences change
through time welfare economics would become impossible unless we had
some way of normatively comparing consumption paths that do not have
the same preferences. We need some kind of ‘metapreferences’. But I want
to restrict metapreferences to a minimum. The metapreferences in our case
are encapsulated in the following axiom.
Improvement Axiom: Let x0 be a consumption vector and let preferences
be adapted to x0, i.e. q0 x0. Let X1 be a path such consumption remains
constant through time: x1(t)x0 and therefore q1(t)q0. Let X2 be a con-
sumption path also starting with preferences q0 x0 and starting with the
same consumption bundle x0. Let x2(t) be such that X2 is an improving
path. Then the person prefers to walk along the improvement path X2 over
walking along the stationary path X1.
The Improvement Axiom is highly plausible: starting from the same
tastes (as represented by q0) adapted to initial consumption and the same
consumption basket x0 the consumer prefers improvement over constant
consumption even if he or she is aware that tastes adapt to the evolving situ-
ation through time.
If we accept the Improvement Axiom we can, as will be shown, maintain
the concept of progress such that it is consistent with welfare economics –
even with endogenously changing preferences.
We may call this area the area C(x0). For it is obvious that any point in C(x0)
can be reached from x0 by means of a progress path. The consumer simply
must jump from x0 to x and if x is contained in C(x0) then obviously this is
a progress path. Hence we have C(x0) is contained in A(x0). But this means
that the curvature of the indifference hyper-surface which is the lower
boundary of A(x0) is less or at most equal to the curvature of the corres-
ponding indifference hyper-surface which is the lower boundary of C(x0).
Therefore the long-run elasticity of substitution is never lower than the
short-run elasticity of substitution. Hence the adaptation of the prefer-
ences to changed relative prices amplifies the demand reaction for given
preferences. Thus we have built a bridge between the assumption of non-
circularity and the adaptiveness of preferences.
Another form in which make clear the connection between non-
circularity and adaptivity is the following thought experiment. Assume
that preferences are the opposite of adaptive; let us call them anti-adaptive.
This implies that the long-run reaction to a change in relative prices is
lower than the short-run reaction. Take the case of a linear demand func-
tion. The price p of a good is raised whereas all other prices remain the
same. The consumer is compensated for the price change p so that his or
her utility level according to the short-run utility function not only remains
the same but is raised slightly. The required increase in income Y hence
is higher by a level than the amount which would have been required
for keeping utility the same. But due to linearity the compensating Y is
equal to p(x1
x0)/2 where x0 is the quantity demanded before the
price was raised and x1 is the quantity demanded after the price was raised.
Thus for Y we have the following equation Y p (x1
x0)/2
. Hence
we have a slight rise in utility for this person. If now preferences change
but prices remain the same then the resulting change in consumption is
an improvement because the consumer has the choice to keep his con-
sumption as before. Let x2 be the quantity of the good to which con-
sumption converges in the long run after the price has been raised by p.
Because of the assumption of anti-adaptive preferences we have x2 x1.
A part of the primary reduction in demand is reversed. If now the
consumer is sufficiently close to this convergence point x2 we make
another price change, namely that the price is lowered by p so it is again
at its original level. Also the income is changed by Y , where Y is
negative. Y is computed in such a way that it is slightly lower in absolute
value (or slightly higher algebraically) than it would be to maintain
the utility level. The compensating income reduction can be computed as
Y p(x2
x3)2, where x3 is the quantity demanded to which the
consumer jumps because of the price reduction. Because in the long run
the consumer will converge to the original point x0 and because we have
54 Economic evolution as open process
This means that for a sufficiently small 0 we can obtain the inequality
Y
Y 0 . Thus on an improving path we come into a budget situation
which is less favourable than the initial situation. The prices are the same
as in the initial situation but the budget is lower. Now we can finish the
improving path by now raising the budget to its original level. Then the con-
sumer has the possibility to return by an improving path to the original con-
sumption vector. Hence we have constructed an improving path which is
circular. This shows that anti-adaptive preferences do not have the property
of non-circularity of improving paths.
8. ADAPTIVE PARETO-OPTIMALITY
Hence according to traditional theory and using the equilibrium prices the
allocation in the equilibrium maximises the present value of the sum of the
consumption vectors of the m consumers subject to the constraint that we
only look at implementable allocations. Now, because of our Main Theorem
a weakly improving path and an improving path for every person only
touches consumption vectors for which we have V(x)V(x0), where x0 is the
equilibrium consumption vector of the stationary equilibrium. For an
improving path we even have the strict inequality V(x) V(x0). But then in
the classical model, with fixed preferences V(x), the total utility of the
weakly improving path is greater than or equal to the total utility of the sta-
tionary path and the total utility of the improving path is greater than the
total utility of the stationary path. But because the stationary equilibrium is
classic Pareto-optimal this implies that the total paths consisting of these
improving and weakly improving paths cannot be implementable. This
shows that the stationary equilibrium is adaptive Pareto-optimal.
Hence we have built a bridge between traditional concepts and theorems
of general equilibrium theory and welfare economics on the one side and
the concepts and theorems developed with the idea of adaptive preferences
on the other side.
9. PATH DEPENDENCE
But this is what one should expect if one speaks about an evolutionary
philosophy. There are such things as evolutionary dead-ends. These are
ecological equilibria which under a more general point of view are some-
what unsatisfactory but which nevertheless are the result of a local optimi-
sation. Small mutations and random changes will not lead out of this
dead-end. We also have to take into account that speaking of a point of
view from a higher level is theoretically not well-founded as long as we don’t
have a criterion for this higher-level point of view.
But the theory developed here may help us along. The theory is able to
distinguish between two kinds of status quo conservatisms or local equi-
libria. We may have a kind of status quo which, as has been described in
section F of my Thünen Lecture,16 can be criticised and can be explained
as the result of a somewhat mistaken institutional arrangement. It is then
possible to get out of this equilibrium by means of a progress path and to
reach a new equilibrium. The new equilibrium from the point of view of
preferences adapted to the old equilibrium is inferior. But it is better in the
sense that it can be reached by a progress path and that after adaptation of
preferences to the new equilibrium it is preferred to the old equilibrium.
Then there is the other kind of equilibrium or local optimum such that two
states A and B cannot be compared because of the non-convexities which
have been mentioned. Due to these non-convexities there may be neither a
progress path from A to B nor a progress path from B to A. In this case we
must simply admit that A and B are incomparable. That French people pre-
dominantly prefer the French way of life and that Germans predominantly
prefer the German way of life does not automatically mean that we can
establish a ranking between these two countries by means of our theory.
This chapter adds to my Thünen Lecture on welfare economics with
adaptive preferences. In particular I have emphasised the evolutionary
character of this theory. I hope to have provided the basis for evolutionary
economics to develop valuation criteria so that policy advice becomes pos-
sible from the point of view of evolutionary economics. In the long run evo-
lutionary economics may thereby be able to challenge the dominant
position of neoclassic economics in policy advice.
NOTES
1. Moore (1903).
2. Keynes (1949).
3. Spencer (1892–93).
4. von Weizsäcker (1998).
5. Vanberg (1986).
6. Rawls (1971).
Notion of progress 57
7. Sen (1970).
8. Buchanan (1974).
9. Samuelson (1947).
10. Arrow (1951).
11. Mirrlees (1971).
12. Hayek (1976).
13. On this topic Witt (2004).
14. This and the following section correspond to parts of a paper of mine: von Weizsäcker
(2004). There the reader can find the proof of the Main Theorem.
15. von Weizsäcker (2002).
16. von Weizsäcker (2002).
REFERENCES
1. INTRODUCTION
58
Reconciling evolutionary economics with liberalism 59
1. economic policy should concern the welfare of the whole society, which
excludes politics acting systematically on behalf of some individuals or
groups (classes, ethnical or religious groups etc.);
2. the welfare of society concerns the welfare of its members so that indi-
viduals represent the genuine target of state activities;
3. individuals define the criteria of welfare according to their own value
judgments which in normal cases should not be overridden by
Reconciling evolutionary economics with liberalism 61
this normative position makes sense in the medium term, it appears too
moral in the short term, as it were. In the process of market evolution,
individual assets including human capital are permanently revalued,
whereas the creative destructions (Schumpeter) of some assets as a by-
product of innovation is one potential outcome. Market evolution,
however, is fuelled by the incentive of firms (individuals) to search for
new opportunities in order to compensate a loss of income due to a
devaluation of their assets. The outlook of some external compensa-
tion to be paid by the winners would erode this very mechanism so that
the Pareto-criterion may be violated at least in the short term. Applying
this norm in a strict sense would suggest negative judgments of any
market evolution, which does not seem a sensible normative position
from the perspective of evolutionary economics if no other mechanism
of raising the welfare of society is feasible.6 A critical point in particu-
lar is the universality of the Pareto-criterion; once accepted, it is a
general norm and thus applicable to any comparisons of alternative
states concerning welfare positions, no matter whether welfare losses
are a temporary phenomenon in the course of market development. In
the same vein, no attention is given to the question whether welfare
improvements of all individuals need time to materialise. With no such
qualifications the ‘pure’ (in the sense of universal) Pareto-norm must
denounce any market process.
2. Innovators create monopolies by definition; monopoly rents prove to
be the by-product of market evolution and defy interpretation as dead-
weight losses. Again, the transfer of the standard norm ‘welfare maxi-
misation’ to the market process entails inadequacies as long as the
genesis of monopolies escapes attention. Used as a general standard
for market deficiencies, dead-weight losses can only be avoided if the
market process itself comes to a halt, which amounts to an absurd nor-
mative consequence.7 While the evolutionary conception by no means
accepts monopolies in general, it qualifies the analysis of welfare losses
from a more general perspective. Whether welfare losses caused by
monopolies are a case of market failure now depends on assessments
concerning the likelihood of maintaining monopoly profits in view of
potential competitors.
5. CONCLUDING REMARKS
Our considerations have been presented in a sketchy way in order to give a
flavour of the orientation guided by evolutionary economics. Interestingly,
no particular policy recommendations have been devoted to human capital
from an evolutionary perspective, although this notion plays an important
role in the current debate on economic growth. Two reasons can be given
for this omission. Firstly, the public support of scientific knowledge
deserves no specific emphasis inasmuch as this type of knowledge repre-
sents a public good which has limited chances to be produced by private
activities. This type of knowledge defines an indispensable part of eco-
nomic policy which aims at the promotion of economic evolution.
However, evolutionary economics subscribes to standard theory in this
respect and so far has no additional theoretical perspective. A second
reason is given by the revised perspective on human capital which evolu-
tionary economics takes towards the accumulation of knowledge alongside
74 Economic evolution as open process
the market process. Generally, evolutionary economics will not deny the
importance of knowledge but questions the possibility of endowing market
agents from outside with that specific type of knowledge which drives
market evolution. Entrepreneurial activities are based on beliefs about
market opportunities which prompt a specific compilation of knowledge in
order to pursue their economic ideas. In that respect a theoretical observer
lacks the possibility of identifying relevant knowledge which firms can suc-
cessfully apply. From the evolutionary perspective, knowledge results from
entrepreneurial alertness and thus renders more characteristics of eco-
nomic output than input. What economic policy can influence is the insti-
tutional context in which knowledge is accumulated but hardly knowledge
itself. The institutional context, in turn, pertains to the competitive envir-
onment of market agents.16
Our interpretation of evolutionary economics is inspired by Hayek’s
reflections on market evolution (Hayek 1996). The fundamental idea
emanates from the impossibility of describing the economy from the view-
point of a theoretical observer if welfare generation is conceptionalised as
a process of experimenting with welfare. Notably, this perspective leaves the
presumptions of normative methodological individualism unchanged but
arrives at different political conclusions. Evolutionary economics has good
reason to change this perspective in so far as it cannot neglect the role of
innovation for economic welfare. However, if individual choice decides on
the welfare impact of innovations, evolutionary theories have to desist from
supplanting individual choice by outside valuation.
Note that this interpretation of evolutionary economics with regard to
politics differs from that of other scholars working in this field who prefer
a more active role for the state. However, for reasons stated above I suggest
that one reconcile evolutionary economics with economic liberalism.
Besides, the evolutionary perspective holds out the possibility of taking a
fresh approach to liberalism without repeating its dogmatism. If the ele-
ments of welfare are unknown in advance, the whole process of identify-
ing welfare depends on liberty for market agents on both sides of the
market. For lack of external benchmarks, economic policy cannot avoid
accepting the preliminary results of market evolution but has to open the
process for further experiments with welfare. Liberty plays the most
important role here in contrast to ends-oriented criteria on which debates
on economic policy normally focus: the number of innovations as well as
specific technological paths do not represent ends in themselves, even if
theorists or policy makers deem them to be of highest importance for the
domestic eonomy. From an evolutionary perspective, market outcomes are
always imperfect and this very imperfection offers a chance to drive market
evolution.
Reconciling evolutionary economics with liberalism 75
NOTES
1. This contribution has profited from discussions which I had in the Evolutionary
Committee of the Verein für Socialpolitik and with my discussant Lambert Koch; I also
thank Hans Nutzinger, Sven Meth, and in particular Mark Peacock for discussions and
helpful comments.
2. See Vosskamp (2002). An early in-depth criticism of the deductive approach with appli-
cation to standard welfare economics can be found in Albert (1975).
3. Other attempts have been made by Meier/Slembeck (1998), Slembeck (1997) and Koch
(1996).
4. Even the notion of ‘liberal nationalism’ (Tamir 1993) would contradict to the cos-
mopolitan conception of liberalism.
5. This statement slightly modifies Hayek who only speaks of knowledge.
6. This insight does not exclude the support of losers in some dramatic cases of income
losses. The reader may think of older persons who are simply impeded by their age from
reacting to the creative destruction of their human capital, although they might be
willing to do so.
7. See Metcalfe (2003).
8. See, for example, Forndahl/Brenner (2003), Lembke (2002) or Pyka/Küppers (2002).
9. In the late 1970s German industrial leaders were criticised for being too late in identify-
ing the market potential of the new generation of consumer electronics. The reader may
also recall that even the star of IT, Bill Gates, was late in perceiving the overwhelming
importance of the World Wide Web in the early 90s.
10. For a critique see Streit/Mussler (1995).
11. The GMO case is difficult to judge from a liberal point of view: if GMO drive out other
plants via offspring which cannot be controlled, individuals lack choice of opportunities
no matter what economic policy decides; if, on the other hand, GMO are prohibited,
those consumers who prefer this innovation lack choice; in the reverse case, individuals
can not buy non-GMO even if they want; then they are forced into a choice and undergo
a loss of well-being compared to the status quo ante.
12 ‘Picking the winners and helping the losers’ has become the motto of industrial policy
referring to the Maastricht Treaty of the EU.
13. For a more detailed investigation of the bottom-up approach to institutional policy, see
Wegner (2003).
14. For that reason economic policy is well-advised to accept the New Systems Competition
in general; a detailed investigation can be found in Wegner (2004); Sinn (2003) presents
a critique from the perspective of equilibrium theory.
15. Another example of adaptive economic policy which investigates the adaptation of
property rights to novelties can be found in Hutter (1989).
16. A by-product of this perspective on knowledge is the modification of Arrow’s (1962)
public-good analogy which has derived a market failure problem too straightforwardly;
for an investigation see Metcalfe (2003).
REFERENCES
INTRODUCTION
78
Historical economics and evolutionary economic policy 79
argument first made in the context of a proposal to allocate the radio fre-
quency spectrum through an auction mechanism rather than administra-
tive decisions of the US Federal Communications Commission (Coase
1959). In contrast to this deregulative and seemingly anti-interventionist
potential of SC (see Posner 1975), ‘The nature of the firm’ (Coase 1937;
henceforth ‘NF’) – the second article responsible for Coase’s fame – was
written by a self-confessed socialist (Coase 1996, 206; see Campbell and
Klaes 2000), setting up a basic tension underlying Coase’s work which
forms the basis of the reading of SC defended below.
The second and main aim of this chapter is to recover this tension on the
level of economic policy and combine it with the historical perspective
offered in much of Coase’s other – unduly neglected – work in order to
clarify important aspects of evolutionary economic policy. Neither is it
thus the intention of the following discussion to establish Coase as an evo-
lutionary economist, nor to offer a detailed historical exegesis of his numer-
ous writings. Given the widespread tendency to see his work as a neoliberal
institutionalist variation of economic orthodoxy, the present chapter seeks
to open up the debate of its evolutionary potential.
Starting out with a discussion of the concept of institutional direction in
Coase’s work, which is central to its policy dimension, the second section
of this chapter looks at the role of the concept of direction in NF, paying
particular attention to the context in which it was conceived: the contem-
porary debate on socialist economic planning. The third section develops
this analysis further to establish the primacy of institutional direction as
the core proposition of Coase’s economic policy perspective. The fourth
section demonstrates how this primacy of institutional direction is the
direct outgrowth of what will be identified as Coase’s historical economics,
in which developmental thinking assumes a key role. This leads in the fifth
section to a discussion of important parallels to evolutionary economics.
The sixth section, finally, draws together the implications of the preceding
discussion for an evolutionary economic policy.
by that transaction for which marginal marketing and organising costs are
equal.
It is often overlooked that Coase considered this partial analysis only as
a preliminary step that needs to be broadened into the kind of multimar-
ket equilibrium analysis typical of early neoclassical economics (see Blaug
1990). In addition, he explicitly considers transactional indivisibility and
heterogeneity. In this extended analysis, the size of a firm F is determined
jointly by the marketing costs of the marginal transaction, by the cost
structure of the industry to which the firm belongs, and ultimately, due to
the relevance of multiproduct firms (NF, 402–3), by the organising costs
across the whole economy. F grows to the point where the marginal trans-
action is more efficiently executed either across the market or within other
firms. In the latter case, the market is only superseded completely if F is
able, through merger, to internalise all stages of production previously
undertaken elsewhere. Coase sticks thus to the marginal principle, but
rather than doing so out of formal considerations his thinking is driven by
a concern for realistic analysis. Transactions are not assumed to be perfectly
divisible in this form of discrete marginal analysis.
Further qualifications become necessary once the heterogeneity of trans-
actions is taken into account (NF, 396). In general, heterogeneity rules out
speaking of the level of marketing or organising costs in general. Instead,
the particularities of the relevant marginal transaction under each mode of
co-ordination need to be considered. This amounts to the implicit acknow-
ledgement that industries are populated by heterogeneous firms. What is
more, the marginal transaction that determines the efficient boundary of
firm F is not found ex ante, through optimising calculus on the part of the
entrepreneur. Rather it emerges out of a process of trial and error by which
entrepreneurs across all firms continuously test the limits of profitable
expansion.
For our discussion, the following aspects of Coase’s analysis of entre-
preneurial decision making within an overall context of multimarket
moving equilibrium are of particular relevance. First, Coase refused to
follow the turn towards the concept of Pareto-efficiency that took hold of
the increasingly formalist neoclassical tradition of the early decades of the
20th century. A comparatively understood ‘value of production’, as the
yardstick of economic efficiency that he employed across all levels of analy-
sis, be it the individual firm or the economy as a whole, has kept him firmly
grounded in the Marshallian tradition.
Second, Coase did not follow the neoclassical tradition in its assumption
of a priori omniscient and faultlessly economising individuals. One can find
this commitment unambiguously expressed in the following statement,
where Coase distances himself from certain orthodox currents in the new
82 Economic evolution as open process
Our starting point has been to ask the relevance of the work of Ronald
Coase for evolutionary economic policy. The aim was not to portray Coase
as an evolutionary economist, but to investigate his contribution in the
light of possible points of contact that could inform present debates on
evolutionary economic policy. It is a central tenet of the evolutionary
approach that economic policy must be regarded as endogenous to eco-
nomic processes, and this in a way that goes beyond perspectives offered
by conventional political economy (e.g. Okruch 2001). There is a clear par-
allel here to Coase’s insistence that any change desirable from the per-
spective of economic policy must proceed from changes in relevant statute
law and the rules on the basis of which government bureaucracy operates
and impinges on the economy. Coase’s policy proposals rest on the premise
that the proper mode of implementation of economic policy is not the
blackboard but the legal and administrative rules that govern the oper-
ation of markets and the effect of direction in firms: ‘In the real world, to
influence economic policy, we set up or abolish an agency, amend the law,
change the personnel, and so on: we work through institutions’ (Coase
1984, 230).
Acknowledging the primacy of institutional direction in the operation of
markets entails that every policy measure, even if it is aimed at promoting
competition and the setting up and facilitating of market mechanisms,
relies on active institutional design efforts. Procedural and developmental
thinking promotes an awareness of the difficulties associated with attempts
to arrive at institutions that perform better than the existing ones (Coase
1975, p. 60). Not only is clear and detailed understanding of the extant
institutional structure required, but also insights into ‘how a government
92 Economic evolution as open process
organisation does in fact carry out the tasks entrusted to it’ (Coase 1984,
61; orginal emphasis).
A second point of contact relates to the necessary revision of the tradi-
tional interpretation of the framework-setting task of ordo- or neoliberal
economic policy. According to this view, the state should ensure that appro-
priate legal rules and institutional frameworks would be in place to allow
free-market exchange to operate smoothly. To refer to one of the lasting
metaphors of this strategy of defining an active role of the state that goes
beyond being a ‘nightwatchman’, it would be up to the state to define the
rules of the economic game, while the choice of actual moves in the game
would be up to economic agents. The design of economic rules on the con-
stitutional level, aimed at ensuring the efficient operation of free markets,
would allow the state to largely withdraw from the subconstitutional realm
of economic co-ordination and exchange, an argument which side-steps the
traditional mutual exclusiveness of central plan and decentral exchange
(Pies 2000, p. 349–53).
It was the concern of Coase’s contributions right from the beginning to
break up this polarity on the subconstitutional level, too. His solution does
not however consist of an orthogonal positioning of the two alternative
modes according to their mode of operation as done by the German
ordoliberals. Market and direction, while seen as alternative and mutually
exclusive ways of co-ordinating economic activity, are brought into a
complex interplay with each other, interpreting the setting of the rules of
the game as a move in the game itself. On this basis, framework setting con-
stitutes at the same time active engagement in the allocation of economic
resources, and economic policy remains an endogenous factor to consider.
Finally, Coase’s proposal of a historical approach to comparative institu-
tional analysis calls into question attempts to pursue a static comparative
analysis that abstracts from the operation of ongoing economic processes.
Coase did not turn to qualitative analysis out of incompetence in quantita-
tive methods (e.g. Coase 1935, 1946; Coase and Fowler 1935, 1937). In ret-
rospect, the contributions of SC to economic theory seem to justify his
overall inductive approach. Evolutionary economists do not need to be
reminded that Coase ultimately shied away from the consequential next step:
the development of a theoretical framework to address processes of institu-
tional development themselves. Nevertheless, his historical economics pro-
vides a valuable range of avenues to explore in the development of more
sophisticated historico-morphological approaches in evolutionary econom-
ics. Coase’s suggestion of conceiving of institutional change in terms of acts
of imaginative reconstruction requires further elaboration, but invites us to
try to understand and study economic institutions on a hermeneutical basis
that takes seriously the epistemological status of history for human agents.6
Historical economics and evolutionary economic policy 93
NOTES
* This chapter refines arguments published earlier (Klaes 2004b). The present version has
been streamlined and sharpened up at various points, largely in response to discussions
that have taken place since the German paper has been committed to print. I should like
to acknowledge in particular recent discussions with Brian Loasby, and ongoing intellec-
tual exchange and collaboration over the past decade with David Campbell on the
Coasean tradition in law and economics.
1. For a discussion of the concept of transaction costs as such, see Klaes (2000, 2003).
2. It is worth bearing in mind at this stage that while in principle, one may reject the primacy
of direction in the operation of markets with reference to international competition
between states and economic systems, the properties of competition in this public sphere
are fundamentally different from conventional market competition, to the extent that
some commentators regard analogies between the two as ‘completely inadmissible’
(e.g. Sinn 2004, 30).
3. One should note that some of the historical details of Coase’s research have recently
attracted some criticism (e.g. Brian Simpson 1996a, 1996b; Coase 1996).
4. In this context, one should also mention the relevance of the concept of radical uncer-
tainty in NF and the resulting role of flexibility and adaptation of transactional agree-
ments (see Foss 1996, 78).
5. See Vromen’s (1995, pp. 34–40) discussion of the Becker (1962a, 1962b)–Kirzner (1962)
debate, including his criticism of the evolutionary theories of Alchian and Becker, which
also applies to Coase’s position (at least in the context of global criteria of efficiency).
6. See Herrmann-Pillath (2000) for similar conclusions in a related context.
REFERENCES
Coase, R.H. (1946), ‘Monopoly pricing with interrelated costs and demand’,
Economica, 13 N.S., 278–94.
Coase, R.H. (1947), ‘The origin of the monopoly of broadcasting in Great Britain’,
Economica, 14, 189–210.
Coase, R.H. (1955), ‘The postal monopoly in Great Britain: an historical survey’,
in J.K. Eastham (ed.), Economic Essays in Commemoration of the Dundee School
of Economics 1931–1955, Coupar: Angus, Culross.
Coase, R.H. (1959), ‘The federal communications commission’, Journal of Law and
Economics, 2, 1–40.
Coase, R.H. (1960), ‘The problem of social cost’, Journal of Law and Economics, 3,
1–44.
Coase, R.H. (1961a), ‘The British Post Office and the messenger companies’,
Journal of Law and Economics, 4, 12–65.
Coase, R.H. (1961b), ‘Why not use the pricing system in the broadcasting industry’,
The Freeman, 11, 52–7.
Coase, R.H. (1962), ‘The Interdepartment Radio Advisory Committee’, Journal of
Law and Economics, 5, 17–47.
Coase, R.H. (1964), ‘Discussion’, American Economic Review, Papers and
Proceedings, 54, 194–7.
Coase, R.H. (1966), ‘The economics of broadcasting and government policy’,
American Economic Review, 56, 440–7.
Coase, R.H. (1974), ‘The lighthouse in economics’, in R.H. Coase (1988), The Firm,
the Market, and the Law, Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press,
pp. 187–213.
Coase, R.H. (1975), ‘Economists and public policy’, in R.H. Coase (1994), Essays
on Economics and Economists, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 47–63.
Coase, R.H. (1978), ‘Economics and biology: discussion’, American Economic
Review Papers and Proceedings, 68, 244–5.
Coase, R.H. (1979), ‘Payola in radio and television broadcasting’, Journal of Law
and Economics, 22, 269–320.
Coase, R.H (1984), ‘The new institutional economics’, Journal of Institutional and
Theoretical Economics, 140, 229–31.
Coase, R.H (1986), ‘Arnold Plant’, in R.H Coase (ed.) (1994), Essays on Economics
and Economists, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 176–84.
Coase, R.H (1991), ‘The nature of the firm: origin’, in O. Williamson and S. Winter
(eds), The Nature of the Firm: Origins, Evolution, and Development, Oxford:
Oxford University Press, pp. 3–47.
Coase, R.H (1993), ‘Coase on Posner on Coase’, Journal of Institutional and
Theoretical Economics, 149, 96–8.
Coase, R.H (1996), ‘Law and economics and A.W. Brian Simpson’, Journal of Legal
Studies, 25, 103–19.
Coase, R.H. (1998), ‘Comment on Thomas W. Hazlett. “Assigning property rights
to radio spectrum use: why did FCC license auctions take 67 Years?” ’ Journal of
Law and Economics, 41, 577–80.
Coase, R.H and R.F. Fowler (1935), ‘Bacon production and the pig-cycle in Great
Britain’, Economica, 2 N.S., 142–67.
Coase, R.H and R.F. Fowler (1937), ‘The pig-cycle in Great Britain: an explana-
tion’, Economica, 4 N.S., 55–82.
Commons, J.R. (1934), Institutional Economics, reprinted 1961, two vols, Madison,
WI: University of Wisconsin Press.
Historical economics and evolutionary economic policy 95
1. INTRODUCTION
99
100 Self-organisation and networks
that LDFs were committed to the old paradigm, in which all their compe-
tencies were concentrated, and that they could not easily internalise the new
knowledge. Alternatively, LDFs did not have the absorptive capacity
required to internalise the new paradigm and they were not capable of con-
structing it rapidly. A new type of industrial actor, small high-technology
firms, arose to bridge the institutional gap between public research institu-
tions and LDFs. In the specific case of biotechnology such firms were called
Dedicated Biotechnology Firms (DBFs). DBFs were expected to act as
intermediaries between LDFs and public research institutions. In the rest of
the chapter the DBFs performing this role will be called translators. In the
course of time by collaborating with DBFs and with public research institu-
tions, LDFs could construct a knowledge-base and an absorptive capacity
in biotechnology. Once this happened the role of DBFs would have become
superfluous and industrial organisation would return to the traditional
dichotomy between the market and hierarchical organisations.
However, the rate of creation of interinstitutional collaborative net-
works steadily increased all throughout the 1980s and 1990s. In Figure. 5.1
we see e.g. the growth of international collaborations in the biotechnol-
ogy-based industries including only those cases of new collaborations
where the partners come from different countries. The continuous attrac-
tiveness of the networking strategy implies the following two alternatives:
either LDFs have not internalised the new paradigm constituted by
biotechnology or a new role for DBFs has emerged in innovation net-
works.
The analysis of this problem constitutes one of the main objectives of the
present chapter. Looking at Figure 5.2 which shows the number of actors
involved in new collaborations in Europe, this clearly suggests the second
200
150
100
50
0
1980 1985 1990 1995
120
Biotechnology Company
100
Diversified Company
80
60
40
20
0
81 82 83 84 85 86 87 88 89 90 91 92 93 94 95 96 97 98 99
Source: Bioability
alternative, that a new role for the DBFs has emerged. Since the late 1980s
they have clearly dominated the founding of new alliances, often between
DBFs only. Furthermore, by the end of the 1980s, of course also the LDFs
had acquired a knowledge-base in molecular biology (see for example
Grabowski and Vernon 1994) and yet they continued to enter into collab-
orative agreements with DBFs.
The new role for DBFs we hypothesise in this chapter to be linked to the
extremely rapid rate of creation of new knowledge. Even if LDFs have
acquired an absorption capacity for it, the sheer rate of advance is such that
no LDF could keep up with it all. LDFs might thus use collaborative agree-
ments with DBFs in order to keep abreast of new developments that could
turn out to have important economic applications. The alternative course
of action for an LDF would be to invest in research in the same fields of
biotechnology. However, with a very high rate of growth of knowledge this
strategy would involve a very heavy, irreversible and risky commitment.
The collaboration with DBFs constitutes a more flexible and reversible
strategy. It is to be observed that this role does not involve a qualitative
difference in LDFs’ ability to understand molecular biology, but only the
attempt to reach a better trade-off between readiness for action if promis-
ing developments were to emerge in new subsets of the biotechnology
knowledge-space and the sunk costs that need to be faced in order to keep
these windows open. And, it must be remembered that the competitive
advantage of LDFs is not constituted by their ability to understand new
knowledge but by their capacity to combine the different competencies and
complementary assets required to produce a final product. Furthermore, a
rather important share of the new collaborations is occupied by alliances
The concept of network organisation 103
3. THE MODEL
Before we start explaining the basic structure1 of our model some remarks
with respect to the methodological framework will be helpful. In particu-
lar, we are going to use the methodology of the so-called history-friendly
models, originally introduced by Malerba, Nelson, Orsenigo and Winter
(1999). History-friendly models are designed to capture, in a stylised form,
the mechanisms and factors affecting industry evolution, technological
advance and institutional change detected by empirical scholars of indus-
trial economics, technological change, business organisation and strategy,
and other social scientists. Thus history-friendly models can be considered
the natural extension to modelling of qualitative and appreciative theories.
Obviously even in a neo-Schumpeterian approach simulation models
have to introduce a certain degree of abstraction and cannot reflect reality
in all its complexity. The mechanisms built into the formal model have to
be transparent enough, so that the analyst can figure out what the causes
are of the observed effects. Therefore, in the first step of our modelling
effort we have to carefully single out the relevant actors, bring together vari-
ables which are effective in the same direction and combine important
developments and possibilities of action. Nevertheless, adopting the neo-
Schumpeterian approach allows us to put emphasis on crucial features of
innovation processes, such as non-linear dynamics, heterogeneity and true
uncertainty, which are beyond the scope of traditional approaches.
In the following the basic building blocks of our modelling framework
are introduced. In particular, we focus on the way we present the different
agents in our model, the way we capture innovation processes, what we con-
sider to be the prerequisites and consequences of networking as well as the
representation of the economic realm in our simulation.
The agents we are considering in our model are Large Diversified Firms
(LDFs) and Dedicated Biotechnology Firms (DBFs). They are described in
terms of their competencies and capabilities. DBFs possess technological
104 Self-organisation and networks
Competencies
Technological competencies are the components of the knowledge-base
required for building up production and innovation capabilities in a specific
technology. In other words, before firms are able to develop new marketable
outputs they have to develop the respective biotechnological competencies.
Furthermore, technological competencies alone are not sufficient to achieve
economic success with a new product. Economic competencies are neces-
sary in order to successfully produce and market a new commodity.
Examples of these economic competencies are experience in clinical trials,
distribution channels and so on. Obviously this representation is somewhat
simplified. The full range of competencies required by firms to conceive,
develop, produce and market new products is very large and heterogeneous.
However, given that most DBFs at the beginning of their life-cycle do not
possess any economic competencies and that LDFs in the 1970s were gener-
ally unable to acquire the knowledge required to use modern biotechnology,
the representation in terms of technological and economic competencies
adequately describes the difference between our two main groups of agents.
Moreover, we could consider technological competencies as the core com-
petencies (Prahalad and Hamel 1990) of firms and economic competencies
as a large part of the complementary assets (Teece 1986) required to produce
and market a product.
Figure 5.3 shows the development of technological competencies. In the
early phases the building up of the knowledge-base is a difficult process and
progress is hard to achieve. However, after having developed a certain
knowledge-base it becomes easier to learn even more (threshold effect).
Finally, marginal progress becomes progressively more difficult as the
knowledge-frontier existing at a given time is approached. A function of this
type implies variable returns to investment in the creation of new knowledge
within a given field: very low at the beginning, positive and growing in the
intermediate phase before diminishing returns set in as the potential of the
new field has been exploited. The process of building up a knowledge-base
in biotechnology is supported by co-operative arrangements with firms who
are already active in this field – an important part of the respective knowl-
edge base is transferred by networking.
Competencies
Time
Co-operations
LDFs, for example the large established pharmaceutical firms. Until the
end of the 70s their research and development was mainly embedded in the
paradigm of traditional organic chemistry. The coming up of the new
biotechnological paradigm meant a ‘competence-destroying technological
progress’ (Tushman and Anderson 1986) for them, as most of their com-
petencies were threatened by the new ones. In our model this group of
agents is represented in the starting distribution with well-developed eco-
nomic competencies but with almost no technological competencies in
biotechnology.
In the second population we find small start-up companies, often uni-
versity spin-offs specialised in the biotechnology field. This group of
agents, the so-called Dedicated Biotechnology Firms or DBFs, by their
very nature have highly developed technological competencies, but almost
no economic competencies. When they start their existence DBFs depend
on external funds for research and development. Accordingly, in our start-
ing distribution they are represented just as having no economic compe-
tencies but highly developed technological competencies.
Capabilities
Drawing on their competencies firms can accumulate technological capa-
bilities in specific fields which allow them to explore the technological
opportunity-space. The firms in our model act in an environment which
continuously forces them to be engaged in such R&D processes. Not to
innovate means to fall behind in the competitive environment of biotech-
nology. In order to increase the probability of an innovation firms accu-
mulate technological capabilities in the course of time.
Together with the technological competencies the technological capabil-
ities determine the probability of an innovation. The relationship is shown
in Figure 5.4.
To consider the intrinsic uncertainty of innovation processes the innova-
tion probability of a firm is matched in every period with a Poisson-
distributed random number whose mean value is asymptotically reached.
A firm is successful in its innovative efforts only if the innovation probabil-
ity is above the random number.2
Innov. prob.
Capabilities
Competencies
financial support in order to build up your own capital stock etc. In the same
way the distribution amongst different activities (e.g. between investing in
the building up of technological or economic capabilities) is captured by
referring to routines.
3.2 Networking
In order to carry out their innovation processes firms can choose different
strategies. They can either decide to go it alone, which means not to draw
on external knowledge-sources and not to share their own new know-how
with potential competitors, or they can decide to co-operate with other
actors and build up collectively the new capabilities necessary for the intro-
duction of a new commodity. Innovation networks emerge through this
mutual co-operation, which gives rise to channels for knowledge-flows
between the firms participating in the network. In particular, we are con-
sidering the evolution of innovation networks at three levels within the
model: the environmental conditions favouring or inhibiting the growth of
networks, the individual decisions of firms to co-operate or not, and a
matching process bringing together firms willing to co-operate. This
process creates a population of networks with its own dynamics. The for-
mation of any network constitutes an act of birth or entry into the popu-
lation. Conversely, the disappearance of a network constitutes an act of
death or exit. The dynamics of birth and death of networks will be deter-
mined by the specific features of each network and by some features of the
external environment.
Networking decisions
Next, the firms have to decide whether they want to co-operate or not.
Generally two forms of co-operation are possible:
In the form of co-operation (1) DBFs play the role of translators, while in
form (2) they play the role of explorers. Consequently, the networking
decision depends on the respective competencies and capabilities that firms
The concept of network organisation 109
have accumulated. For example, a small start-up DBF in its early phases
is not able on its own to raise funds for R&D and necessarily has to look
for a partner in order to obtain funding. In the same way established LDFs
which want to become active in the promising fields of biotechnology but
have no internal technological competencies need collaboration partners
experienced in these fields. On the other hand, firms with highly developed
capabilities would not run the risk and share their knowledge with poten-
tial competitors in the stages immediately preceding the introduction of an
innovation.
Matching process
Finally, we have to decide on the mechanism which brings together different
firms willing to co-operate. Although different mechanisms are conceivable
we think that a mechanism which could be labelled ‘success breeds success’
is best suited to our purposes. Success breeds success means that firms
would tend to pick collaborators with the highest technological and/or eco-
nomic capabilities. We are here assuming that firms are able to advertise
their own capabilities and to evaluate those of potential co-operating part-
ners. This seems to be a realistic assumption, especially in the biotech
industry, where firms are ranked on the basis of their technological perfor-
mance, which is advertised by press announcements, publications, patents
and even by the professional standing of the scientists hired by firms,
including the Nobel prize winners present on their scientific committee.
After having introduced the way firms get together in innovation networks
we now have to focus on the consequences of networking. By entering into
a collaboration the agents are exchanging their know-how. This means that
firms can benefit from the efforts of other firms in order to build up their
own capabilities.
Absorptive capacities
The extent to which a firm can benefit from the knowledge-flow available
by co-operation depends on its absorptive capacity (see Cohen and
Levinthal 1989 and Cantner and Pyka 1998). In turn, absorptive capacity
is expected to increase with the firm’s previous experience in co-operation.
This means that external knowledge is not easily integrated within their
own knowledge-stock, but certain prerequisites have to be fulfilled and a
minimum amount of experience is necessary. This also means that the
amount of knowledge which flows within the network is severely limited.
110 Self-organisation and networks
Financial flows
Start-up DBFs with missing economic competencies cannot finance their
own R&D and are obliged to find a co-operation partner. In this case an
LDF co-operating with a DBF is supposed to provide the required research
funding. Another possibility for DBFs to acquire R&D money is to apply
for venture capital, of which we assume an exogenous supply growing at a
constant rate. Access to venture capital is competitive. Amongst the firms
applying only those which show the best record in biotechnological capa-
bilities as well as in previous co-operations are funded.
Knowledge-flows
One of the most important advantages of participating in an innovation
network is the access to channels of knowledge-flow. External knowledge
exerts an impact on the innovation probability function and depends on the
amount of absorptive capacities, as well as on the technological capabili-
ties of the co-operating firms. Participating in an innovation network exerts
a threefold influence: first, the research budget of a firm is reduced due to
co-ordination costs and, in the case of a co-operation with a DBF, by the
financial support of this firm. Second, absorptive capacities are positively
influenced by entering into a new collaboration as the experience with inte-
grating external knowledge is increasing. Finally, external knowledge
becomes available via knowledge-flows between the collaborating firms.
this does not exclude the possibility that firms operating in the same market
can co-operate.
On the final markets firms compete in terms of prices and quality which
are, in a dynamic context, determined by their innovative success. Generally,
one would expect that a successful innovator will be able to attract demand
away from its competitors because consumers can choose between several
goods. These substitution effects are due to price and quality changes which
are the results of the following actions and reactions:
Introducing a new product with improved quality characteristics creates
additional demand allowing the innovator to charge higher prices.
Environmental
conditions for Firm decisions:
networking R&D budget
co-operation
Innovation I:
Actors’ development of Heterogeneous
knowledge- a new technology/product oligopoly
stocks
Innovation II:
Introduction of the new technology/
product to the market
Exit
0.06
0.04
0.02
0
1 46 91 136 Time
No.
LDF/DBF
DBF/DBF
No co-operation
Translator
Explorer
t
0 0
a001 a020 a040 a060 a080 a100 a120 a140 a160 a180 a200 1982 1985 1987 1989 1991 1993 1995
Figure 5.9a Average distance in the artificial world Figure 5.9b Average distance in the real world
116
2
2.5
1.5
2
1.5 1
1
0.5
0.5
0 0
a001 a020 a040 a060 a080 a100 a120 a140 a160 a180 a200 1982 1985 1987 1989 1991 1993 1995
Figure 5.10a Degree of centrality in the artificial world Figure 5.10b Degree of centrality in the real world
The concept of network organisation 117
the real world, their artificial counterpart stays almost on the same level and
also the second peak is unimodal in the real world compared to the bimodal
peak in the artificial world. This difference is basically caused by the different
sizes of the empirical and the artificial populations. The populations in the
simulation run are kept smaller due to computational restrictions.
To rule out the influence of network size, index-oriented measures exist.
Here we measured and calculated the degree of centrality for both of our
worlds shown in Figure 5.10. The degree of centrality measures the asym-
metry in the roles played by various actors in a network. For this aspect of
network activity we also find a broad correspondence of our artificial and
real worlds. The sequence of three peaks can be interpreted as a conse-
quence of the changing role of DBFs in the networking processes. The first
peak is caused by DBFs playing the role of translators supporting the
LDFs in their efforts to overcome the gap between their dominant knowl-
edge orientation and the upcoming new knowledge-base in biotechnology.
The second peak has to be characterised as an intermediate phase, with
some DBFs who have already become vertically integrated producers and
LDFs still mainly concerned with building up competencies in the new
field. The third wave in networking is then caused by a tremendous growth
in the technological opportunity-space, where networking is considered to
be a strategy to cope with the speed and complexity of technological devel-
opment. In this phase DBFs play the role of explorers allowing the large
and established firms to explore a wider range of technological approaches
within biotechnology.
5. CONCLUSIONS
This chapter provides a simulation analysis of the evolution of innovation
networks in the biotechnology-based industries. Since this is an applied
simulation exercise, great emphasis is placed on the characteristic features of
this industry. The results of the simulations are compared to developments
in the real world by applying concepts of graph theory which provide us with
some measurements of the overall network dynamics. Although there are
still some significant differences between the artificial evolution of network
structures and the real-world networks, the results look promising as they
are able to reproduce at least qualitatively some developments which are
observed in reality. The next steps have to be to balance the different mech-
anisms and to find relative weights in accordance with their specific impacts.
Once such weights were attributed, different scenarios could be analysed,
showing the influence of different environments as well as of policy measures
aiming at the establishment of these new biotechnology-based industries.
118 Self-organisation and networks
NOTES
1. The description of the model is given in a non-equation form, not explicitly introducing
into details. Interested readers may obtain a comprehensive description of the model by
writing to the authors.
2. In this respect, a major methodological advantage of simulation studies shows up in the
construction of the innovation processes. Whereas in traditional optimisation models
there is no difference between the modeller and the modelled agents, simulation analysis
allows programming random numbers whose statistical distribution is unknown to the
agents in the model, see Pyka (1999, pp. 189ff.).
REFERENCES
Bogatti, S.P., M.G. Everett and L.C. Freeman (1999), Ucinet 5 for Windows:
Software for Social Network Analysis, Natick, MA: Analytic Technologies.
Burt, R.S. (1980), ‘Models of network structure’, Annual Review of Sociology,
6, 79–141.
Cantner, U. and A. Pyka (1998), ‘Absorbing technological spillovers: simulations in
an evolutionary framework’, Industrial and Corporate Change, 7, 369–97.
Cohen, W.M. and D. Levinthal (1989), ‘Innovation and learning: the two faces of
R&D’, The Economic Journal, 99, 569–96.
Freeman, L.C. (1979), ‘Centrality in social networks, conceptual clarification’,
Social Networks, 1, 215–39.
Grabowski, H. and J. Vernon (1994), ‘Innovation and structural change in phar-
maceuticals and biotechnology’, Industrial and Corporate Change, 3, 435–49.
Kuenne, R.E. (1992), The Economics of Oligopolistic Competition, Cambridge, MA:
Blackwell.
The concept of network organisation 119
Malerba, F., R.R. Nelson, L. Orsenigo and S.G. Winter (1999), ‘History friendly
models of industry evolution: the computer industry’, Industrial and Corporate
Change, 8, 3–40.
Nelson, R.R. and S.G. Winter (1982), An Evolutionary Theory of Economic Change,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Prahalad, C.K. and G. Hamel (1990), ‘The core competencies of the corporation’,
Harvard Business Review, 90, 79–91.
Pyka, A. (1999), Der kollektive Innovationsprozeß – Eine theoretische Analyse
absorptiver Fähigkeiten und informeller Netzwerke, Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.
Pyka, A. and Saviotti, P.-P. (2002), ‘Innovation networks in the biotechnology-
based sectors’, in A. Pyka and G. Küppers (eds), Innovation Networks – Theory
and Practice, Cheltenham UK and Northampton, MA, USA: Edward Elgar.
Saviotti, P.-P. (1998), ‘Industrial Structure and the Dynamics of Knowledge
Generation in Biotechnology’, in Jacqueline Senker (ed.), Biotechnology and
Competitive Advantage: Europe’s Firms and the US Challenge, Cheltenham, UK
and Northampton, MA, USA: Edward Elgar.
Staropoli, C. (1998), ‘Cooperation in R&D in the pharmaceutical industry’,
Technovation, 18, 13–24.
Teece D. (1986), ‘Profiting from technological innovation’, Research Policy,
15, 285–305.
Tushman, M.L. and P. Anderson (1986), ‘Technological discontinuities and orga-
nizational environments’, Administrative Science Quarterly, 31, 439–65.
6. Sociodynamics – an integrated
approach to modelling in the
social sciences
Wolfgang Weidlich
INTRODUCTION
1. PRINCIPLES
1.1
120
Sociodynamics 121
1.2
The micro level of individuals and the macro level of collective evolu-
tion are mutually interdependent. The formalism takes this fact into
account.
1.3
1.4
1.5
Equations of evolution for system states are derived starting from the tran-
sition rates, either on the probabilistic level (including all fluctuations) or
on the deterministic level (for the mean evolution).
1.6
2 FORMAL FRAME
n {. . . ni . . .} (6.1)
122 Self-organisation and networks
where the meaning of mk can for instance be: number of produced com-
modities per unit of time; price of one unit of a commodity; number of
buildings on a site of a city; etc. The multiple of variables
v {n; m} (6.3)
The dynamics of the society is described by transitions from any one given
initial state va to a neighbouring state vb.
Transition rates (by definition probabilities per unit of time proceeding
from state va to state vb) engender the transitions, i.e. they are the ‘driving
forces’ of the transitions. They are induced by the activities of individuals
(e.g. on the migratory, social, economic or political sector).
Since transition rates are by definition always positive definite quantities
they can be written in the form
The master equation, which is compatible with (6.6), reads in its general form:
dP(va; t)
dt
wba(vb; va)P(va; t)
vb
(6.7)
˛
vb
wab(va; vb)P(vb; t)
124 Self-organisation and networks
It can easily be understood that the change with time of the probability va,
i.e. the l.h.s. of (6.7), comes about by two contraproductive processes,
namely:
It should be noted that the master equation, in spite of its easy interpreta-
tion, is not easily solved!
dmk
wk(mk
, m) wk(mk, m) (6.8)
dt
dni
dt
wij(nij, n) wji(nji, n)
j j
(6.9)
We now consider the general procedure for designing selected models and
we present some of their results in terms of characteristic scenarios.
3.1 Migration
and there exist phase-transitions between these cases, which can be studied
in terms of the model.
0.5
y 0
0.5
1
1 0.5 0 0.5 1
x
Figure 6.1a Fluxlines of the quasi-mean values
The stable homogeneous population mixture x0; y 0 of both
populations over both regions is approached.
0.5
y 0
0.5
1
1 0.5 0 0.5 1
x
0.5
y 0
0.5
1
1 0.5 0 0.5 1
x
0.5
y 0
0.5
1
1 0.5 0 0.5 1
x
Introduction of variables
The set of variables consists of material and personal variables.
The material variables are formed by first tessellating the area of city c
and hinterland h into a lattice of sites with co-ordinates i(i1, i2), j(j1, j2); . . ..
Thereupon on each site ‘i’ several units mi(K) of types . . . K . . . L . . . of build-
ings can be erected until eventually the capacity limit Ci is reached. The
multiple
0.50
131
0.50
1
1955 1960 1965 1970 1975 1980 1985
Schleswig-Holstein Rheinland-Pfalz
Hamburg Baden-Württemberg
Niedersachsen Bayern
Bremen Saarland
Nordrhein-Westfalen Berlin
Hessen
Figure 6.5 The estimated regional utilities ui(t) of the Federal Republic of Germany
1
0.50
132
0.50
1
1955 1960 1965 1970 1975 1980 1985
Schleswig-Holstein Rheinland-Pfalz
Hamburg Baden-Württemberg
Niedersachsen Bayern
Bremen Saarland
Nordrhein-Westfalen Berlin
Hessen
Figure 6.6. Key-factor analysis of the regional utilities of the Federal Republic of Germany
Sociodynamics 133
wK
i↑
(m, N) ; wK
i↓(m, N) (6.15)
wi↑(m, N) ; wi↓(m, N) (6.16)
wji(m, N) (6.17)
According to their standard form (6.4), (6.5), the transition rates can and
must be further specified in order to obtain a concrete integrated city and
population evolution model. This has been done in the author’s book men-
tioned in the introduction, from which we take the further concrete results.
dNj()
dt
wji(m, N) wij(m, N)
i i
(m, N) w (m, N) (6.19)
wj↑ j↓
Scenarios
Integrated models of course contain several sectors which may be treated
separately under simplifying assumptions. In the present model, the inter-
action between city- and population-evolution essentially depends on how
city and hinterland provide capacities Cc and Ch, respectively, for a
(perhaps growing) total population.
If on the other hand the capacities Ci of each site i of the city are (for-
mally) kept constant, the evolution of the city configuration must come to
an end when all capacities are exhausted. This case is treated in the follow-
ing scenario.
0.1
x(p,q)
0.05
0
15
13 15
11 13
11
9 9
q 7 7 p
5 5
3 3
1 1
15 15
13 13
11 11
q 9 p
9
7
7
5
5
3
3
1
1
0.06
0.04
y(p,q)
0.02
0
15
13 15
13
11
11
9
q 9 p
7
7
5 5
3 3
1 1
In the – now presumed – case of equal net birth-rates in city and hinterland
the population equations (6.19) are decisively simplified to two equations
for the population shares nc, nh only:
dnc
phcnc
pchnh
dt
(6.21)
dnh
phcnc pchnh
dt
or, because of (nc
nh)1, to one equation for the majority variable n(t)
only:
dn
(pch phc) (phc
pch)n (6.22)
dt
V(n; t) v e(a(t)
b(t)n) b(t)n 1
2
b (t)
1
b(t) (6.25)
e (a(t)
b(t)n) b(t)n
1
b2(t)
1
b(t)
0
2
4
V(n^,t)
6
8
1 0
0.5 100
0 200
n^ 0.5
1 400 300 t
500
Figure 6.9 Development with time of the evolution potential V(n, t) for
growing total population and worsening balance of capacities
between hinterland and city
5
10
V(n^,t)
15
20
25
1 100 0
0.5 400 300 200
0 0.5 600 500
1 700 t
n^
REFERENCES
140
The concept of space in trade 141
There are two main anomalies in neoclassical trade theory (NTT). First,
NTT cannot exhaustively explain the direction of trade in space (or, what
the same thing amounts to, the location of production); second, the explan-
ation of the increasing role of multinational corporations in trade remains
difficult. The latter issue is linked with the former, because one major
research topic is the investigation into the patterns of foreign direct invest-
ment, which also involves spatial patterns of economic activity of those
firms (e.g. exports of foreign subsidiaries). In the past two decades, investi-
gating these unresolved issues has triggered a burgeoning literature, mostly
exploiting synergies between New Trade Theory and (New) Economic
Geography (Krugman 1995; Helpman 1998). The trigger for this effort is
the recognition of the blatant fact that real space does not actually exist in
trade theory (frequently assuming even zero transport costs), which in its
mainstream versions is a theory of the international allocation of produc-
tion as a result of international equilibrium exchange (for a penetrating
criticism, see Dunning 1995).
Let me summarise the main facts, beginning with the problem of spatial
directedness of trade.
If we take a closer look at the arguments that are proposed to resolve these
empirical riddles, so far the most important ones are:
Turning our attention to the second major field of research into open
questions in international economics, the main empirical issues are:
theory is that the impact of factor endowments on trade works via the
pricing of factors which in turn affects goods prices, eventually closing the
total equilibrium system. This raises the question whether the capabilities
of traders to trade can also be treated as a part of that endowment, given
the fact that capabilities to trade can only be measured relative to pairs of
traders who realise the transaction. This is tantamount to asking whether a
relational property of the traders can be priced within the system which
comprises that trading relationship, i.e. the market.
The point of departure in the recent literature is the problem of how to dis-
tinguish between production cost and transaction cost, because the theory
of international trade is exclusively based on the concept of comparative
production-cost advantages. We adopt the conceptual distinction between
transformation cost and transaction cost introduced by North (1990,
pp. 27ff.) who defined the latter as adding up to total production cost. North
himself identified the problem that it is very difficult to distinguish neatly
between both categories on the theoretical level as well as (and even more so)
on the empirical level. The foremost example are the costs associated with
measurement problems in transactions where goods characteristics might
give rise to transaction costs which could be lowered via an appropriate
redesign of the production process, thereby changing transformation costs.
Looking at the problem from the opposite angle, Langlois and Foss (1999)
complain about the neglect of production cost – transformation costs in
North’s terms – in the modern theory of the firm based on transaction cost.
If the concept of production is rooted in the general concept of putting
knowledge to use, there are co-ordination problems in the production
sphere that have nothing in common with the behavioural co-ordination
problems emphasised by transaction-cost economics, namely opportunism.
Therefore, the boundary between the market and the firm cannot be fully
explained by transaction costs.
Hence, our problem can be restated in the straightforward question,
whether the theory of comparative advantage can include production costs
in terms of the sum of transformation costs and transaction costs, which
would imply that the capability to trade is a part of general comparative
advantage.
which are realised by different agents. A gifted trader will realise the trans-
actions at lower cost, thereby making higher profit and possibly appropri-
ating the transaction potential of other, less efficient traders (Wegehenkel
1981). Starting out from this, could we think of that capability in terms of
a ‘factor’ in the sense of neoclassical trade theory?
Structurally, to pose the issue in this way is homogeneous with the
general Gödel problem in the foundation of formal systems, related to the
question whether true statements in a formal language can be decided
within that system. This proved to be impossible because of the self-refer-
ential structure so that decidability is only possible in new, higher formal
language where we can talk about the propositions of the former language.
In the same vein, we ask whether pricing of the transactions forming a price
is possible in the market, with ‘pricing of the transactions’ meaning that the
underlying institutional quality of the transaction is priced, or the capabil-
ities of the agents to realise the transaction. This is the same as asking
whether capabilities to trade can be traded in the market system which is
formed by just these trading relations.4
In NTT, this problem never arises because equilibrium theory presup-
poses the successful arrangement of the entire set of transactions outside
the system. Traders in NTT act autistically. That this assumption is by no
means innocuous becomes immediately obvious when we realise that the
inclusion of the capabilities of traders to trade into the equilibrium system
leads to severe inconsistencies.
The final sentence in the last paragraph means that we would still assume
that the separation between transformation and transaction is viable, so
that in equilibrium traders can optimise the mix of transaction and trans-
formation costs. We cast serious doubts on that. Obviously, the separation
between transformation and transaction is a transaction in turn. Yet, this
new transaction gives rise to transaction costs, too. The difficulties in sep-
arating analytically and empirically between transformation costs and
transaction costs reflect the transaction costs of just that operation in the
real market system. We cannot separate these as observers because the
market does not give rise to such a separation.
Obviously, here we are running into the trap of infinite regress. I do not
wish to overstretch that point, but this kind of infinite regress is sufficient
to conclude that there can be no empirically exact way to measure trans-
action costs unless the separation already exists in the market, so that there
is a price-tag attached to the services needed to realise the transaction. In
particular, we are not able to assess the relative role of the transaction
costs of the original transaction and the transaction costs preventing the
separation between transaction and transformation. That means, for
example, that the boundary between firm and market is indeterminate in
observational terms, because we cannot identify exactly the differential
impact of the relative transaction costs within the firm and across
the boundary as compared to the transaction costs linked with the oper-
ation of just setting that boundary. Even if we were to believe that there is
a clear relation working in reality, we would never be able to observe it
unequivocally.
This infinite regress could never be solved if there is a type of transaction
that cannot be separated from transformation in principle. In order to find
such a kind of transaction, we can start with the most simple case of selling
a good. If we leave legal issues aside, the transaction is only complete if the
buyer is indeed able to use it. That means, the good actually consists of a
good and a service, namely the good proper and the service that leads to
the accomplishment of the transaction.8 This amalgam can be dissected in
many ways, as reality demonstrates, displaying a manifold of arrange-
ments, for example, with the separation between logistics, insurance, retail
activities and other services from the trading transaction proper. Are there
The concept of space in trade 151
trade, and, at the same time, of the difficulties of fitting this phenomenon
into the common factor-proportions-framework.
For reasons of space, I cannot go into the details. Suffice it to say that the
concept of factor belongs to the most elusive categories of economic rea-
soning, because its use results in the construction of highly aggregate
entities that produce ‘factor services’ which are the real substance of inter-
national trade, beyond the surface of the traded goods. If we take the stand-
ard Heckscher-Ohlin definition as a starting point, factors are defined as
being internationally immobile factors of production. Adding related
definitions in the theory of growth, this rather broad definition may be more
circumscribed if we add the property of non-producibility (cf. Woodland
1987).
All these definitions, of course, are highly contentious because in many
uses of the factor concept other, often contradicting definitions inhere. For
example, capital continues to be treated as ‘factor’ even though it is regarded
to be perfectly mobile. Consequently, there is a plethora of possible trade
models including, for example, single-factor models if the criterion of
immobility is applied strictly (see, for example, ‘skills only’ models à la Wood
1994), and, on the other extreme, multifactor models which, for example,
analyse the impact of sector-specific factors on trade. However, precisely
this looseness of definiton results in serious troubles when trying to sep-
arate ‘factors’ from ‘goods’ analytically, if the latter concept encompasses
154 Self-organisation and networks
Which kind of entity might be the stock out of which entrepreneurial ser-
vices flow? The most simple answer, of course, would point toward the
entrepreneurs as a group. However, if we wish to lend more detail to the
analysis of the sources of entrepreneurial capabilities, I propose to treat as
‘factors’ the following three entities, the services of which constitute the
156 Self-organisation and networks
● organisational capital
● collective human capital
● social capital.
All these three entities have one structural feature in common, namely the
fact that relational patterns in neighbourhoods are involved, with neigh-
bourhoods frequently, but not necessarily, referring to spatially close inter-
actions (closeness can result from ‘similarity’ in any other respect, for
example, kinship). This idea refers to certain arrangements of people in
space and time, which are stable and recurrent, and which because of their
complexity cannot be straightforwardly imitated (‘produced’) and trans-
ferred (‘traded’) to another place. This basic insight has already been
achieved, amongst others, by Michael Storper (1995), who argued that
competitive advantages of locations are rooted in non-traded interdepend-
encies between people at certain places. Our concept broadens this insight
to the more abstract structural aspects of social relations between agents,
which are regarded as ‘capital’ that generates entrepreneurial services.13
This capital is the non-intended result of human action, therefore is non-
producible, yet storable, because of its recurrent unintended reproduction,
and it also has the property of non-rivalness of use in time.
Organisational capital is the crystallisation of the competences of the
firm, that are rooted in certain organisational routines, tacit knowledge,
and non-tradable assets which are only reflected in the market value of the
firm as compared to the market price of its constituents. Although this is a
patterned neighbourhood, obviously the firm as a whole can be traded and
transferred in space. However, this presupposes very special competences,
too, as is evident from the many failures, for example, of mergers, acquisi-
tions and foreign direct investment. Hence we may speculate that one of the
crucial ingredients of organisational capital of the firm is the competence
to trade itself, namely to grow into other markets and regions in space-time.
Firms, hence, differ in terms of this special competence which can therefore
be regarded as especially relevant for international trade.
The concept of organisational capital provides a new foundation for the
theory of the multinational corporation, because we regard the stock of
firms in an economy as a base of its competitive advantage in trade. This
is directly mirrored in the fact that trade and FDI are closely enmeshed,
and that intra-firm and intra-industry trade dominate trade the more devel-
oped the nations involved, hence the more complex and diversified their
stock of firms becomes. The country- or location-specific accumulation of
The concept of space in trade 157
sides belong to the same ethnic network and therefore can lower transac-
tions costs because of higher levels of trust (e.g. Landa 1994). Social capital
may also emerge from social structures where indirect channels of commu-
nication and social perception are existent, possibly restricting deviant
behaviour even without a closer relation between the agents proper.
Furthermore, if externalities across transactions are taken into consider-
ation, social capital may be an emergent property of networked transac-
tions, which, however, shows a distinct pattern in space. Those patterns can
be self-reinforcing, because there are direct effects on observed transactions
costs, so that the externalities are eventually internalised in stable patterns
of repetitive transactions.
As we see, all these three forms of capital are to a large extent non-
producible in the sense that there is no direct relation between input, output
and intentional action. The organisational capital of the firm, for example,
is based on tacit knowledge which arises from the accumulation of infor-
mal routines. Since this cannot be imitated easily, it provides the founda-
tion of competitive advantages. The same is true for a singular network
pattern forming social capital, like particular social relations among
traders which cannot be simply rebuilt by other persons who do not have
the same personal history.
In what sense are the three kinds of factors related to the phenomenon
of directedness? This becomes clear if we distinguish three dimensions of
distance that impact on transactions, and if we assign one of the factors to
the special capability to overcome the respective distance.
● Spatial distance can be overcome (amongst other ways) via the use of
organisational capital that enables agents either to shift their focus of
activity (direct investment) and/or supports trade relations. Hence we
expect the pattern of trade to be strongly influenced by the direction
of investment flows and different corporate strategies of market
entry. The most salient empirical phenomenon is the growth of
intrafirm trade, however, one should also pay attention to network-
ing across firms, like strategic alliances.
● Technological distance can be overcome via collective human capital.
Here we refer to tacit differences in the use of technologies across
locations which imply that trade (especially in intermediate prod-
ucts) will be influenced by these indirect characteristics of space.
Technological distance can be measured by comparing absorptive
capacities across locations, if this is not simply reduced to ‘stocks’ of
human capital, but is related to qualitative and structural differences
between knowledge systems. An important empirical case in point are
national systems of innovation which foster the emergence of localised
The concept of space in trade 159
We have tried to set up a general and abstract framework for ETT. The main
achievement seems to be that we do not reject the empirical insights
160 Self-organisation and networks
obtained from NTT, yet put them into a completely different theoretical
approach. We also accept one feature of the NTT approach to trade, that
is, to analyse trade-flows as surface phenomena of deeper structures. These
deep structures refer to properties of locations in space, conventionally
treated as ‘factor endowments’ which generate certain flows of services.
These services we interpret either as factor content or as inseparable, com-
plementary services enabling agents to trade. Our main hypothesis, then, is
that competitive advantages rely on entrepreneurial inputs that are outside
the market system, and which generate the factor contents and services.
More specifically, these are related to technology and transactions.
In the most general terms, I wish to pinpoint the difference between ETT
and NTT by means of Figure 7.1. The theory of comparative advantage
explains trade under the condition of complete knowledge, with the price
system endogenising all relevant determinants of trade. The evolutionary
theory of competitive advantage explains trade as a process generating
knowledge about comparative advantage. This difference is easily illus-
trated in Figure 7.1.
Circle A–E depicts the circular causation of NTT, which is a closed equi-
librium system starting out from points A and B, with the price system
directly revealing the complete information about comparative advantages
in production of different locations. Via the trading activities, which are
basically arbitrage processes, countries are led to further specialise in their
Comparative advantage
of production
Adaptation Opportunity costs as
A reflected in the price
of production
E B system
structures e
d
f Discovery of
C arbitrage
Knowledge about c g opportunities
comparative
b a D
advantage
Realised transactions
of trade
New information
revealed by trade
NOTES
1. This chapter is based on my German book Herrmann-Pillath (2001a), presenting a con-
densed version of some crucial theoretical arguments. Related papers in English are
Herrmann-Pillath (2000b), (2001b).
2. To get an impression, the reader is recommended to visit the homepage of the ‘Academic
Consortium on International Trade’ (www.spp.umich.edu/rsie/acit/), which reflects
the public role of trade economists. The intellectual esprit de corps is reflected in the
fact that there is even a ‘family tree’ of trade economists available in the internet, see
www.econ.lsa.umich.edu/~alandear/tree/index.htm
3. I should emphasise that I regard New Trade Theory as a part of the mainstream
approach, since it sticks to the equilibrium framework, though achieving, at least partly,
an endogenisation of technological change, as in Grossman and Helpman (1991).
4. In economics, Hayek has made the similar point when arguing (1952, see Herrmann-
Pillath 1992) that a system with a certain degree of complexity cannot understand itself
except via a system of higher complexity that allows one to reproduce the system of
lower complexity as well as including at least the additional self-referring relation.
Loasby (2001) also stresses the importance of this fundamental insight for constructing
economic theories.
5. Our use of ‘tradability’, ‘non-tradable’ and related expressions differs a bit from the
common use because we refer to the general property of a good being transferable via
market transactions, both internal and external. In trade theory, these expressions are
162 Self-organisation and networks
would share its own search costs with the other side. Hence, in a fundamental way con-
tracts can never be complete.
12. In modern writings on international trade, these definitional issues have been shifted into
the background, with encompassing monographs like Wong (1995) even doing without
any definition of ‘factors’ in general. There were times when this question received a lot
of attention, as, for example, Caves (1967, pp. 93ff.) illustrates. In the early days of for-
malising the equilibrium trade theory, intellectual giants like Samuelson (1948, 181)
raised very serious doubts on the theoretical role of ‘factors’ in the factor-proportions
theory. All this is simply forgotten today.
13. Related ideas have been developed in the most recent foundational research in evolu-
tionary economics, which focuses on the role of networks as embodying knowledge, with
the seminal work by Potts (2000, 2001).
REFERENCES
Dasgupta, Partha and Ismail Serageldin (eds) (2000), Social Capital. A Multifaceted
Perspective, Washington, DC: World Bank.
Davis, Donald R. et al. (1997), ‘Using international and Japanese regional data to
determine when the factor abundance theory of trade works’, American
Economic Review, 87 (3), 421–46.
Davis, Donald R. and David R. Weinstein (1998), ‘An account of global factor
trade’, NBER Working Paper 6785.
de la Mothe, John and Gilles Paquet (eds) (1996), Evolutionary Economics and the
New International Political Economy, London/New York: Pinter.
Deardorff, Alan V. (1998), ‘Determinants of bilateral trade: Does gravity work in a
neoclassical world?’, in Frankel (1998), pp. 7–22.
Dosi, Giovanni, Keith Pavitt and Luc Soete (1990), The Economics of Technical
Change and International Trade, New York: Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Dunning, John H. (1995), ‘What’s wrong – and right – with trade theory?’
International Trade Journal, 9 (2), 163–200.
Ekholm, Karolina (1998a), ‘Headquarter services and revealed factor abundance’,
Review of International Economics, 6, 545–53.
Ekholm, Karolina (1998b), ‘Proximity advantages, scale economies, and the loca-
tion of production’, in Braunerhjelm and Ekholm (1998), pp. 59–76.
Engel, Charles and John H. Rogers (1999), ‘Violating the law of one price: should
we make a federal case of it?’, NBER Working Paper 7242.
Feenstra, Robert C., Deng-Shing Huang and Gary Hamilton (1997), ‘Business
groups and trade in East Asia, Part I: Networked equilibria’, NBER Working
Paper 5886.
Feenstra, Robert C., Maria Yang and Gary G. Hamilton (1997), ‘Business groups
and trade in East Asia, Part II: Product variety’, NBER Working Paper 5887.
Feenstra, Robert C., Tzu-Han Yang and Gary G. Hamilton (1999), ‘Business
groups and product variety in trade: evidence from South Korea, Taiwan and
Japan’, Journal of International Economics, 48, 71–100.
Foss, Nicolai J. (1993), ‘Theories of the firm: contractual and competence perspec-
tives’, Journal of Evolutionary Economics, 3, 127–44.
Foss, Nicolai J. (1999), ‘Networks, capabilities, and competitive advantage’,
Scandinavian Journal of Management, 15 (1), 1–15.
Frankel, Jeffrey A. (ed.) (1998), The Regionalization of the World Economy,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Goldberg, Pinelopi Koujianou and Michael M. Knetter (1997), ‘Goods prices and
exchange rates: what have we learned?’, Journal of Economic Literature, 35,
1243–72.
Grabher, Gernot (2001), ‘Ecologies of creativity: the village, the group, and the het-
erarchic organization of the British advertising industry’, Environment and
Planning, 33, 351–74.
Grant, Robert M. (1996), ‘Toward a knowledge-based theory of the firm’, Strategic
Management Journal, 17 (Winter special issue), 109–22.
Greenhut, Melvin L., George Norman and Chao-shun Hung (1987), The Economics
of Imperfect Competition: A Spatial Approach, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Grossman, Gene M. and Elhanan Helpman (1991), Innovation and Growth in the
Global Economy, Cambridge, MA/London: MIT Press.
Grossman, Gene M. and Kenneth Rogoff (eds.) (1995), Handbook of International
Economics, vol. 3, Amsterdam: Elsevier.
The concept of space in trade 165
1. INTRODUCTION
168
Economic policy 169
which prevent voters and the elected from including all information rele-
vant in a situation in their decisions (cf. Simon, 1955). And from the per-
spective of public choice theory, self-interest and the power games that go
with it for politicians and interested parties were put forward as grounds
for the necessity of changing perspectives; because, independent of their
role in the economic policy-making process, the choice and decision-
making behaviour of economic subjects does not by any means lead to the
preference for continuously ‘correct’ decisions – quite apart from the fact
that the determination of what could be ‘correct’ is itself confronted with
insurmountable theoretical and practical obstacles (cf. e.g. Frey and
Kirchgässner 1994, pp. 362ff.).
It is however only recently that a problem area which develops at an
earlier stage has increasingly come to the fore. This problem area becomes
obvious when moving away from the customary common-knowledge
assumption which is an implicit part of the formation of theory and which
assumes a predefined econopolitical event or situation. Before the situation
is assessed and alternatives chosen at a macro-economic level, the question
as to how an ‘econopolitical situation’ originates needs to be posed. Here it
can be shown that the results gained from determining the situation, setting
an aim and selecting measures are very dependent on the individual and
societal perception and communication processes which come before them.
It is in these processes that certain problem areas crystallise, the contours
of which gradually become clear at a later stage. This means, in contrast to
the assumptions of many models of economic policy theory, that there are
neither ‘ready-made’ solutions to problems in advance, nor, and this is a
particularly important point, are there ‘ready-made’ problems which just
need to be identified by individual politicians or parties and, depending on
their political couleur, integrated into respective agendas. Very complex
phenomena play a role in the complicated interaction process which deter-
mines at what point in time and at what ‘stage in its development’ an eco-
nomic problem which is initially only perceived by a minority actually
advances to become a problem of economic policy. At the beginning of the
problem process, this includes for example the degree of homogeneity of
perceptions of reality existing in a society, the individual and collective
perception of certain information, the way problems are ‘offered’, i.e.
processed or presented in the media, as well as the effect of historically
grounded path dependencies, inponderable events or accelerating/retarding
frequency dependency effects in the course of the genesis of a problem.
The contexts mentioned here will be developed in four steps focusing in
particular on cognitive aspects: firstly, a short look will be taken at the
general significance of epistemological factors in the analysis of economic
policy, followed by an investigation into the relevance of ‘cognitive maps’
170 Self-organisation and networks
Here, a closer look will be taken at the actual phenomenon, the origin of
problems in the context of economic policy. Firstly, in accordance with
methodological individualism, what happens on an individual level is of
interest – especially considering the fact that there is a deficit in explanation
which needs to be dealt with that comes up in well-known attempts at soci-
ological explanations, which are mainly based on collective phenomena in
the political process (cf. Scharpf 1991; Searle 1995). To examine the indi-
vidual level the concept of ‘cognitive maps’ will be addressed here. This
concept, the development of which is linked to Piaget’s work (Sugarman
1987), combines the above-mentioned concepts with a series of subphe-
nomena in information processing which have not yet been addressed. For
example, an important point is that cognitive maps are highly selective,
Economic policy 173
meaning that pieces of knowledge are linked within them under the same
label in the form of terms for characteristics, prototypes, limiting cases and
examples. At the same time, so-called tacit knowledge is arranged, know-
ledge which is constantly developing and being applied, thus changing in
action and at the same time influencing the human ability to act without
the actor himself or an external observer being able to systematically
describe its structure (for an application-based overview see for example
Hirschfeld et al. 1994; Vowe 1994).
Cognitive maps which help master the complex range of sensory stimuli
play a central role in any cognition and memory process: they form the
framework, so to say, into which newly constructed information is inserted,
to be then complemented by already-organised pieces of knowledge (cf.
Eysenck 1984, p. 324). Thus a referential network is created within which
experiences are condensed into patterns, which themselves then shape expe-
riences. All evaluations, expectations, plans and decisions made by actors
are based on this interdependent linkage of present and past cognitions
(cf. Koch 1996). All economic subjects, whatever role they are playing
at any moment in the process of economic policy, are affected by this sub-
jective prestructuring of perception. Politicians, bureaucrats or voters,
members of whatever social class, the old or the young: in their reception
of information, events and complex situations everyone is subject to the
biological restriction of only being able to perceive what their brain offers
them on the basis of their personal (stored) ‘history’.9 In contrast to the
concept of ‘bounded rationality’, the concept of ‘cognitive maps’10 thus
emphasises not so much the lack of quantity in information gathering as
the unavoidability of path-dependent quality changes in the reception of
information.
Should there be considerable contradictions to the previous subjective
‘reality’ in an individual perceptive situation in the face of certain ‘infor-
mation conditions’, these cognitive dissonances can at the same time
awaken the wish to reduce them. The strength of the stimulus depends on
the estimation of the expected costs and benefits of corresponding activi-
ties.11 The costs can be, for example, to analytically structure and then to
communicate the initially subjectively defined problem (for example, in
discussions or publications), they can express themselves in altered choice
behaviour and they can (this option involves the highest costs) imply a trig-
gering of activity in citizens initiatives, parties or government authorities.
‘Information conditions’ in which cognitive dissonance occurs can on the
one hand be newly created. But on the other hand they can also remain
unchanged and the ambiguity results solely from a recombination of estab-
lished consciousness content which is produced by the apparatus of per-
ception.12 While the latter possibility can occur at any time, the reception
174 Self-organisation and networks
contact with each other, they ‘automatically’, so to speak, alter reality for
the person they are interacting with. They observe reactions to their own
actions and, if necessary, conceptualise recurrent new experiences together
with previous knowledge as cause–effect relationships in new variations or
cognitive maps. The fact that in this situation each individual acts accord-
ing to their own, subjective, schematically coded expectations, aims and
purposes is also termed ‘double contingency’. As we can assume that within
social communities the subjective realities of interactive partners are at
least partly synreferential in advance, actors can also always work towards
orienting the cognitive area of others towards a certain object (cf. Rusch
1994, p. 63). This point represents an important interface where it is
decided whether individually perceived problems at a certain point in
time ever become intersubjective or societal problems. The mobilisation
resources of individual economic subjects play a decisive role here and
there is a wide range of possibilities. Firstly, it depends on the strength of
the intrinsic potential, i.e. on the degree of subjectively perceived dissatis-
faction and on the will to mobilise. Secondly, there must be sufficient mobil-
isation abilities such as the correct selection of communication partners
and the necessary argumentation skills. Here the social position taken on
by the mobiliser is important, as well as the economic and/or political
resources and power potential available to them and the experience already
had with them in similar situations in the past.
When the spark of problem perception jumps from the individual level
to the collective level, a problem subsequently gains a new piece of identity
with each further communication, i.e. its quality by no means remains con-
stant during the diffusion process. Nor is there any guarantee that every
person concerned will interpret a communicated problem in a similar way.
Here the complexity of the subject matter and the quality of the commu-
nication process play an essential role. ‘The more successful orientation
interactions there are and the more reliable they are, the stronger will the
actors be convinced of the common and equal nature of reality’ (cf. Rusch
1994, p. 71). In other words, depending on the situation there can be a
homogenisation of how people interpret reality and problems.
Whether a problem which is perceived and discussed in parts of society
actually becomes an issue in economic policy depends in essence on this
homogenisation process. The more homogenous the perception of a certain
economic target/performance discrepancy and the larger and more power-
ful the dissatisfied group, the higher the probability, all else being equal, that
the problem will be admitted to the political level. In spite of this, no gen-
erally valid if-then criteria can be derived for this step. Historical constella-
tions play a role which need to be evaluated according to what kind of
macro-economic situation a society is in, what other problems are on the
176 Self-organisation and networks
issues list and how urgent they are, and thus what problem perception
and problem treatment capacities are still available at that point in time
(cf. Meier and Slembeck 1994, p. 75). A further very important point to
consider is what institutionally dictated mechanisms facilitate or impede the
problem being admitted to the political level (e.g. constitutional require-
ments for referendum petitions) – a question which will not be dealt with
further here. But even if a certain degree of homogeneity is necessary as a
kind of minimum ‘critical value’ for admitting a problem to the level of eco-
nomic policy, the relativity of this context must be considered. Because in
increasingly untransparent, pluralistic and multicultural societies it will
become generally more difficult to install homogenous, powerful interpre-
tations of problems which are at the same time stable in time and content.
With the acceleration of technological progress and the global diffusion of
knowledge (decreasing ‘knowledge half-life’) as well as the internationali-
sation of the economic and interjurisdictional competition that goes with
it, the relevant problem areas and at the same time the interpretation of
individual problem areas are fanning out more and more. However the
more heterogeneous the prevailing and competing realities are, the more
difficult it is, all else being equal, to make any qualified statement on the
course of problem-admittance processes and thus projections about future
developments in the process of economic policy as a whole.
In the face of this development, one thing is becoming more and more
important: to what extent are initially alien problem areas and interpreta-
tions of problems communicated to the other groups in a society in order
to create a pool of relevant information in common knowledge (intended
reduction of ambiguity)? From the perspective proposed here, such a pool
seems to be a conditio sine qua non for constructive sociopolitical discus-
sion on the solution of problems which come up. It combats to a certain
extent a ‘derationalisation’ of the process of economic policy making. In
accordance with this, the economic policy-making process would be ‘ratio-
nal’ in that what is being communicated about is also what every individual
concerned understands as being what they want to express; therefore, the
more intensively a theme-based process of mutual orientation gets going,
the higher the probability that a problem recognised by many will later be
treated ‘correctly’ or ‘rationally’ – in the view of many.
Let us now take a closer look at the mechanisms and patterns which play
a role in the process of problem diffusion in economic policy. This includes,
above all, the observation that cost–benefit relations which economic
agents are confronted with, if they want to spread an individual view of a
problem, are highly dependent on the established communication struc-
tures within a society. These form the ‘resonance space’ in which problem
interpretations have to prove themselves (cf. Siegenthaler 1994, pp. 177ff.).
Economic policy 177
important role here. If there is latent discontent which has been predomin-
ant in a larger social group for a long time, the course of problem diffusion
will be different than if only a small peripheral societal group sees need for
econopolitical action on a certain issue. Based on a categorisation in
Bennett (1980, pp. 113ff.), various categories of initiation of econopolitical
problems can be differentiated according to the number of people affected
and the extent to which they are affected (cf. Meier and Slembeck 1994,
pp. 68ff.). According to this, one can speak of an interest-group problem if
only a minority in society is affected but this minority organises itself for-
mally on the basis of the high willingness to pay of the individuals con-
cerned. On the basis of the German coal problem in the Ruhr area, the
cognitive determinants which are relevant here become clear: normally this
concerns groups of economic subjects whose individual realities have a high
level of synreferentiality in advance, as they have economic (industry, pro-
fession etc.), social (class, ethnicity etc.) and/or geographical (estate com-
munity etc.) features in common. This means that the costly setting up of
functioning communication structures and the spread of common inter-
pretations of reality are rendered superfluous. In the case of structural prob-
lems, however, there is a large number of affected actors but the individual
is affected to a lesser degree. Even if the motivation to form a formal organ-
isation is weaker for this reason, this type of problem triggering is still just
as significant as the former one. To go back to the planned introduction of
the euro, for example, the political significance associated with it becomes
clear. In the run-up to the Bundestag elections in 1998, the election cam-
paign strategists of the largest German parties saw an above-average level
of uncertainty concerning this issue. From a cognitive-evolutionary point
of view, the reason for this was that in the course of the currency debate each
potential voter had an opinion, but that these opinions were based on com-
pletely different backgrounds concerning knowledge, experience and inter-
est. As a result, it seemed dangerous to commit to a certain strategy at too
early a stage, as public opinion was extremely unstable under the circum-
stances and still is today in connection with this theme.
Only the latter of the ideal types of elite and crisis problems which are
less frequent in reality will be looked at here as this is a particularly inter-
esting phenomenon for the context under discussion. A chaotic situation is
characteristic, after which a coincidental individual event can very quickly
completely change the societal assessment of the situation and thus also the
relevance of possible previously existing problems (interest group, structure
or elite problems) (cf. Kuran 1995). For example, taking a look at public
reaction to a media-effective accident at a chemical production plant,
extremely intense ‘avalanche-like’ protest can be observed in certain cases
– especially if there have been no similar accidents in the recent past. It may
Economic policy 179
even happen that all chemical production plants in a country become time
bombs in public opinion. The decisive consideration here is that the sud-
denly altered assessment of the situation can lead to huge pressure on polit-
ical actors. A social problem is ‘born’ which results in a political necessity
to immediately formulate and implement new aims for a certain area which
has been at most a peripheral issue for a long time as regards social inter-
est. It is obvious what kind of economic consequences such coincidental
individual events can have, for example, for a whole industry. From a cog-
nitive-evolutionary point of view, the interesting aspect to such an example
is that in certain cases the homogenisation of cognitive maps can take place
very quickly and unpredictably. When a large majority has swung towards
a certain view of reality, decisions can be taken which would never have had
a chance of implementation in the past. This is also an aspect which again
makes very clear the significance of the factors ‘coincidence’, evolutionary
self-dynamics and path dependency for the results of the process of
economic policy – phenomena which are often neglected in traditional
approaches.
Political level
Problem admittance
Problem treatment
Figure 8.1 From the origins of a problem to its treatment – sketch of the
process of economic policy making
established solution patterns. The reason for this is that, against the back-
ground of certain cognitive structures, frequency distributions and proba-
bilities are systematically disregarded (cf. Tversky and Kahneman 1982).
Other investigations show that the ability to correctly estimate effect mech-
anisms and reaction-times from the application of the instrument to the
intended effect is also very different for different individuals in complex
socio-economic systems (cf. Dörner 1991). As already mentioned, no
simple input-output prognosis modes can be constructed for these pur-
poses, so the only alternative is to take experience values from comparable
situations. Here, intuition plays an important role; from a scientific point of
view, we are dealing with implicit heuristics that the perception apparatus
offers spontaneously (cf. Six 1987). Typical for the investigation of system-
atically distorted cognition performance is the incorrect assumption that
there are linear cause-effect relations and a disregard of feedback (e.g. self-
destroying and self-fulfilling prophecies), regression and contradictory
effects as well as the creation of consequential problems in other areas of
the system (cf. Dörner 1991; Nisbett and Ross 1980, pp. 124ff.). On the
other hand, causal contexts or intentionalities are often searched for where
the assumption of coincidence and thus the application of probability con-
cepts would be more suitable (cf. Ross 1977, 175ff.). In the end, time-frames
are often wrongly estimated and the present is overvalued in relation to the
future.20 While the above-described ‘anomalies’ generally lead to wrong
dosages when applying instruments, this cognitive failure may explain in
particular overdosage in planning measures. This is because the fact that
measures take effect at a later stage is often misunderstood and it is assumed
that the measure has no effect at all (cf. Dörner 1991, pp. 156ff.). In con-
nection with all of these observations there is empirical evidence that more
experienced people systematically act more successfully in complex deci-
sion-making situations than the less experienced. However, this is only true
under one condition; that both groups of test subjects receive the same
initial information on the concrete situation in their respective experiments.
5. RESUMÉ
This quite cursory analysis (for the reasons stated) of the process of
problem treatment will now be followed by a summary of the results pre-
sented. It was shown that, for an understanding of the process of economic
policy, it can be helpful to take a look at the origin of the problem from a
cognitive-evolutionary perspective, analytically differentiating between the
individual and collective levels, before going over to the treatment of the
problem. Phenomena which can be explained from a psychocognitive
Economic policy 185
perspective have the effect that both the process of problem origination as
well as the process of problem treatment in economic policy often seem to
the observer to be systematically ‘unsystematic’. As problem origination
and problem treatment are always accompanied by complex competition
for influence and power between different interpretations of reality, what is
left over as the final result of this process on a collective level can still only
be an ambiguous and partially contradictory compromise. This results
from the collision of many different ways of thinking, reality models and
ideologies whose foundations, even if they seem incommensurable, are set
in relation to each other. Because it is the motivation of the decision makers
in economic policy to reduce ambiguity on all levels – at least in a democ-
ratic system – in order to become or remain able to act. The extent to which
the left-over residue of ambiguity or cognitive heterogeneity is present in
the phase of problem treatment depends not least on the informal and
formal givens of the sociopolitical system of a country. In an individual
case analysis, the quality of the installed communication structures and the
structure of the democratic involvement and decision-making rules would
need to be investigated here.
In addition, it should be kept in mind that the appearance of such
problem interpretations born out of the societal communication process
and the solution patterns which follow is in no way long-lasting; it rather
shifts according to the extent to which certain events, discoveries or power
shifts help other or new realities to become temporary ‘competitive
successes’. Therefore, a positive theory of economic policy must also the-
matise influential factors of the variability of its categories. It should
understand the societal communication process as an all-encompassing
medium in which econopolitical interests, models and ideologies are trans-
ported, strengthened but also put in their place, thus at the same time
sketching again the process-oriented framework concept, within which
more light can be shed on the respective individual phenomena.
NOTES
1. Molitor, for example, demands: ‘the logic of the econo-political situation entails a divi-
sion into aim, situation and measure. Whether dealing with political tasks concerning
order, stability or distribution, policy should always follow the three steps of interpreta-
tion of aim, analysis of situation and programming of measures’ Molitor (1988), pp. 29.
2. For an overview of the historical genesis of this programme cf. Albert (1977), pp. 181ff.
3. Here it is of no importance whether the machine is trivial or non-trivial: in a non-trivial
machine the output sequence is not only determined by the input sequence and the trans-
formation rule fy(x → y), it is also determined by the rule ( fz), according to which the
transformation function ( fy) is altered. In this way, very complicated input-output
sequences of a higher order are conceivable.
186 Self-organisation and networks
4. Or, as Schiepek (1990), p. 199, criticizes common practice: the attempt is often made ‘to
free scientific descriptions from their cognitive preconditions, i.e. to eliminate the condi-
tions of their feasibility’.
5. Cf. Albert (1977), p. 205, who demands the inclusion of epistemological aspects in a
theory of econopolitical action ‘which should be taken seriously from a realistic point of
view’.
6. ‘Cognitive sciences’ include all disciplines which deal with the phenomena of perception
and cognition, including neurobiology, chemistry, physiology and psychology, other
fields of biology and psychology as well as some areas of philosophy.
7. Perception is the absorbtion of stimuli by sensory cells and organs, inference is the for-
mation of implicit conclusions and attribution is the subconscious allocation of cause
by the brain.
8. In this context Hesse’s reflections on ‘cognitive creativity’ as a basic variable in the theory
of action and economics as well as the consequences of its integration for the explana-
tion of innovation are particularly significant; cf. Hesse (1990). For corresponding con-
sequences in economic policy cf. Koch (1996).
9. In a similar context to the one discussed here, Frey and Eichenberger (1991), p. 75, under
the point ‘Reference Point Effects’, refer to the example of the fear of inflation some
Germans have. It seems to actually make a difference in the evaluation of econopolitical
scenarios whether actors still have (unpleasant) memories of inflation they experienced
themselves or not. People with experience of certain events and developments will sub-
consciously evaluate situations differently than individuals without the same history.
10. These are sometimes called ‘scripts’, or ‘frames’. In all cases these are special types of
complex structural organisations (the terms are also partly synonomous). For example
‘frames’, which will be dealt with later, normally describe organised knowledge struc-
tures that order conventionally determined knowledge of laws and standards which
plays a role in social situations. Cf. Dijk (1997).
11. Cognitive assimilation and accommodation processes play a role in connection with the
motivation to reduce cognitive dissonance or ambiguity. Cf. Meier and Slembeck (1994),
pp. 54ff.
12. In addition to the above-mentioned sources, cf. Pöppel and Edingshaus (1994), pp. 166ff.
on the cognitive-scientific preconditions for this possibility.
13. In this context it can be of interest to analyse the mechanisms of reflexive reality model-
ling, also in advance of elections and votes. Spontaneous actions and institutionalised
procedures (cf. Blondel, 1990) ensure that the actual decisions have been made long
before the formal election or vote takes place. In spite of this, this cognitive-evolutionary
aspect of preparation for votes is often undervalued in expert literature on the subject,
an exception being Slembeck, (1997).
14. Kuran (1995), pp. 189ff. analyses in detail the extent to which private preferences for
example are in a continuous change process depending on private knowledge and public
discussion and the ‘preference distortions’ which result.
15. The word ‘overlapping’ here should not be understood from a set theory or homological
perspective, but rather in an abstract way which refers back to the above-described
reflections on communication theory.
16. Cf. Mueller (1989). The general idea is described that the transaction costs of turning
social or political problems into issues (in the widest sense) are basically communication
costs, using the example of patent-law production in Hutter (1989), p. 187f, examples for
politically motivated ‘problem generation’ (top-down) can be found, for example, in
Scharpf (1991).
17. However this does not exclude the possibility that political oppositions produce ambi-
guity on purpose to hinder the success of the actions of decision makers or to manipul-
ate society’s evaluation of the results of actions.
18. A reference can be made here to Popper’s advocacy of a social technique of ‘piecemeal
social engineering’, which he explains on the basis of the characteristics of such a society
concept. Cf. Popper (1995).
Economic policy 187
19. See, for example, Lindenberg (1993) for an explanation of the framing concept which is
based on the above-described cognitive-scientific results. From an empirical point of
view, Lindenberg refers in particular to investigations carried out by Goffman (1986) as
well as by Tversky and Kahneman (1981). The latter proved in experiments that indi-
vidual decisions for different alternative actions can be extremely dependent on how the
respective possibilities are described. In the experiment the descriptions ‘objectively’ con-
tained the same information, but in some cases the possible profit was emphasised, in
others the danger of loss, cf. ibid, 453ff.
20. Here, the elementary human characteristic of setting every action and experience on a
time-scale can be counterproductive. Because by constructing action sequences, interac-
tion chains and contexts that ‘make sense’ from a procedural perspective, thus turning
singularities into elements of procedures (cf. Vowe 1994, 438), there is always the possi-
bility that incorrect temporal structures will continue to exist as consequential errors in
action planning.
REFERENCES
Ross, L. (1977), ‘The intuitive psychologist and his shortcomings’, in: L. Berkowitz
(ed.), Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 10, New York: Academic
Press, pp. 173–220.
Rusch, G. (1994), ‘Kommunikation und Verstehen’, in K. Merten, S.J. Schmidt und
S. Weischenberg (eds), Die Wirklichkeit der Medien: Einführung in die
Kommunikationswissenschaft, Opladen: Westdeutscher Verl. pp. 60–78.
Scharpf, F.W. (1991), Crisis and Choice in European Social Democracy, Ithaca, NY,
London, UK: Cornell University Press.
Scherer, K.R., C. Vogel and K. Immelmann (1988), ‘Psychobiologie und Politik’, in
K. Immelmann, K.R. Scherer, C. Vogel und P. Schmoock. (eds), Psychobiologie,
Grundlagen des Verhaltens, Stuttgart and New York: Free Press, pp. 803–32.
Schiepek, G. (1990), ‘Selbstreferenz in psychischen und sozialen Systemen’, in:
K.W. Kratky und F. Wallner (eds), Grundprinzipien der Selbstorganisation,
Darmstadt: Wiss. Buchges.
Searle, J.R. (1995), The Construction of Social Reality, London, UK, New York,
US: Free Press.
Siegenthaler, H. (1994), ‘Wege zum Wohlstand: Das Beispiel der USA, der Schweiz
und Brasiliens’, in W. Fischer (ed.), Lebensstandard und Wirtschaftssysteme,
Frankfurt am Main: F. Knapp, pp. 173–212.
Simon, H. A. (1955), ‘A behavioral model of rational choice’, Quarterly Journal of
Economics, 69, 99–118.
Six, B. (1987), ‘Attribution’, in D. Frey und S. Greif (eds), Sozialpsychologie,
Munich: Psychologie-Verlags-Union.
Slembeck, T. (1997), ‘The formation of economic policy: a cognitive-evolutionary
approach to policy-making’, Constitutional Political Economy, 8, 225–54.
Sugarman, S. (1987), Piaget’s Construction of the Child’s Reality, Cambridge, New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Tversky, A. and D. Kahneman (1981), ‘The framing of decisions and the psychol-
ogy of choice’, Science 211, 453–58.
Tversky, A. and D. Kahneman (1982), ‘Causal schemas in judgements under uncer-
tainty, in D. Kahneman, P. Slovic und A. Tversky (eds), Judgement under
Uncertainties, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 117–28.
Vowe, G. (1994), ‘Politische Kognition: Umrisse eines kognitionsorientierten
Ansatzes für die Analyse politischen Handelns’, Politische Vierteljahresschrift,
35, 423–47.
Wallis, J. (1997), ‘Conspiracy and the policy process: a case study of the New
Zealand experiment’, Journal of Public Policy, 17, 1–30.
Weick, K.E. (1986), ‘Organizations as cognitive maps: charting ways to success and
failure’, in: H.P. Sims et al. (eds), The Thinking Organization, Dynamics of
Organizational Social Cognition, San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.
Witt, U. (1992), ‘The endogenous public choice theorist’, Public Choice, 73, 117–29.
9. Why endogeneity is not enough
to explain technological change –
a critique of Paul Romer
Malcolm H. Dunn1
For ten years now, we have been experiencing a renaissance of growth the-
ories in the form of so-called ‘endogenous growth theories’. These claim to
supply us with an empirically substantial explanation of the driving forces
behind the growth-rate of an economy. On the one hand, proponents argue
that, in contrast to the older neoclassical growth theory of the Solow-type,
technological change is no longer treated as a residual value, calculated
by determining the difference between the growth of inputs to the empiri-
cally observed national growth of outputs, i.e. to the social product. Instead
of an assumed exogenous rate of technological change, i.e. a rate that is not
explicitly explained, we have a rate which is attributed to the intentional
actions of profit-maximising agents of an economy, i.e. an endogenous rate.
Another advance, proponents argue, is that endogenous growth theory
coincides better with the observable facts than does the older theory. While
the older neoclassical theory still concluded that per-capita growth rates
had a tendency to converge, explaining this among other things with the
public goods character of technical advances, newer theories assume that
technical knowledge is not ubiquitous. This is why a stable gap in per-capita
growth rates can occur, the closure of which gives rise to the need for eco-
nomic policy. At least some proponents of endogenous growth theory view
their reasoning as a justification for extensive state intervention in the form
of industrial and technological policy measures.
There is no doubt that endogenous growth theory is en vogue and this not
only because one of its founders was awarded the Nobel prize for his work
on rational expectations, but also because the deficits in the area of the
micro-economic foundations of macro-economics are felt more strongly
than was the case 30 or 40 years ago. In spite of or because of the public
appreciation of endogenous growth theory, it must be ‘permissible’ to ask
wherein the advancement of endogenous growth theories actually lies.
Addressing this question is the objective of this chapter. The present inquiry
190
Why endogeneity is not enough to explain technological change 191
HY, L Y
Y(HY, L, x) HYL x(i)1di
0
HYLAx1
Research sector
HA Designs
dAdt · HAA
Notes:
Variables of the model:
A Quantity of designs, dA/dt increase in designs
HA Human capital of the research sector; HY of the consumer sector
L Simple labour
K Capital, measured in units of the end product
Y Standard consumer good
x Equilibrium quantity on the intermediate goods market
Productivity factor effective in the research sector
Quantity of end products ‘sacrificed’ for an intermediate product
Let us begin with a look at the production function (equation 9.1). The pro-
duction of consumption goods (Romer, for reasons of simplification,
assumes a single consumption good (Y)) takes place using the inputs
unskilled labour (L), skilled labour, i.e. human capital (HY) and intermedi-
ate or capital goods (x).
Y(HYL,x) HYL x(i)1di HYLAx1 (9.1)
0
The striking thing about this production function is the assumption that
skilled labour (HY) remains qualitatively unchanged while the production
process undergoes change because of the increase in capital goods input.
In other words, the fact is ignored that a change in the quantity of capital
goods also implies a qualitative change in the production process, which, in
turn, means other skills will be required, skills more appropriate to the
changed work process. In this equation, technical progress has no influence
on the quality of skilled labour. Progress in productivity takes place, one
could say, without so much as touching the human factor of production,
even though this same factor becomes more productive due to the increased
input of intermediate goods.12
Let us look at the last factor in the total economy’s production function,
capital or intermediate goods (x). It is assumed that every increase in
capital or intermediate goods also means an increase in output and that no
productivity relation exists between capital or intermediate goods. Both
assumptions represent a strange abstraction within the context of an expla-
nation for technical progress, because technical progress does not consist
only in the quantitative increase of those intermediate goods used for the
production of a consumption good but also in their qualitative change. In
addition, technical progress can make an intermediate good superfluous or
lead to the replacement of several intermediate goods by a new one.
A decreasing number of intermediate goods can therefore be just as much
an indicator of technical progress as the development of new intermediate
goods (see Hayek 1984).
The fact that – due to technical progress – old products are replaced by
new ones is reversed here: every capital good ever made retains its
effectiveness regardless of technical progress.13 In this way, technological
change appears as a mere increase of the capital goods that go into the
production process, the elimination of technically obsolete capital goods or
their replacement with more advanced capital goods does not take place.
Thus, a very important factor in technological change is left out.
Why endogeneity is not enough to explain technological change 199
Ki x. (9.2)
Let us address the question of how the technical knowledge that goes into
intermediate-goods production is produced. This technical knowledge is, in
contrast to human capital, the non-rivalling factor. This is justified by the
assumption that technical knowledge exists separately from every and any
individual and – as is common in endogenous growth theories – can grow
boundlessly. It is assumed, mainly for the purpose of simplifying the model,
that each unit of technical knowledge corresponds to exactly one unit of an
intermediate good. For this reason, technical knowledge can be described
200 Self-organisation and networks
dAdt HAA. (9.3)
The quote, placed at the end of the critical explanation of the model, is
revealing: unbounded growth is not a result of the inherent argumentation
of the model, but is simply a result of a scantily justified assumption of lin-
earity. Romer regards the assumption of linearity as ‘feasible’, ‘because
there is no evidence from recent history to support the belief that opportu-
nities for research are diminishing’ Romer (1990, p. 84). If one compares
Romer’s model with other endogenous growth models, one will find similar
linearity relations.
Linearity, however, is not exactly typical for technological change, as
long as the change is path-dependent. New technological paradigms in
certain areas of knowledge stimulate an increase in certain areas of
research and lead temporarily to a marked increase in patentable know-
ledge until the paradigm is finally exhausted. Characteristic for techno-
logical change are temporary increases in patents on the basis of a
technological paradigm, which then slowly decrease in number and impor-
tance. In many cases, new paradigms arise to replace the old ones, in turn
triggering a new wave of research activities. At the same time, older patents
are depreciated, both in the technical and in the economic sense. In yet
other cases and because of technical and economic developments, the par-
ticular relevance of ‘older’ patents will be rediscovered. In any case, the
assumption that technical knowledge, like every type of knowledge, is infi-
nite, in no way implies linear relations. Even interruptions and periods of
less innovation activity cannot be ruled out.
Why endogeneity is not enough to explain technological change 205
CONCLUSIONS OF AN EVOLUTIONARY
ECONOMIST
NOTES
1. I thank Ulrich Fehl, Carsten Schreiter, Rainer Klump and Markus Braun for helpful
comments on the German version of this article, which was first published under the
title ‘Wachstum und endogener technologischer Wandel – Eine Kritik des
Wachstumsmodells von Paul Romer aus der Perspektive der Evolutorischen Ökonomik’
in ORDO (2000), 51, 277–99.
2. As is generally known, Morgenstern (1972, 1184) pointed out that the firm, as it is pre-
sented in the textbooks, could easily be replaced by a computer. The same author makes
reference to the fact that the competition of neoclassical equilibrium economics has little
to do with the competition firms have to deal with in the real world. On this point, see
also Dunn (1998).
3. These learning effects do not always take place on the knowledge frontier. Rosenberg
(1994), e.g., confirms that technical progress often only then ensues, when previous
knowledge is rediscovered and related to new contexts.
4. Innovation theory speaks in this context of the fact that technological change is path-
dependent and develops continually along so-called natural trajectories. Hanusch and
Cantner (1993, p. 24) point out that the more technological progress is based on firm-
specific know-how, the more one may characterise it as a private good and the easier it
is to appropriate its (temporarily accrued) rents. As self-enforcing mechanisms that
account for the path-dependencies, North (1990, p. 94) following Arthur (1988) men-
tions: ‘(1) large setup or fixed costs, which give the advantage of falling unit costs as
output increases; (2) learning effects, which improve products or lower their costs as their
prevalence increases; (3) coordination effects, which confer advantages to cooperation
208 Self-organisation and networks
with other economic agents taking similar action; and (4) adaptive expectations, where
increased prevalence on the market enhances beliefs of further prevalence’.
5. One of the findings of empirical innovation economics is that ‘The simple equation of a
private stock of intellectual property with total excludability and rivalry, contrasting
with a public stock of intellectual property without excludability or rivalry, (with respect
to the factor-embodied and disembodied knowledge), only holds in a few instances’
(Grupp 1998, p. 462)
6. The occurrence of external effects cannot be equated with market failure. They are rather
an ubiquitous characteristic of market economies. On this, see Sälter (1989).
7. This has to do with the fact that technical knowledge, in the form of acquired skills, flows
from one firm to the other when employees change their workplace or firms co-operate
in R&D projects.
8. See, for a description, Walz (1999).
9. This holds true even when, as in Solow’s model, a constant savings rate is assumed.
However, if the savings rate is dependent on the interest rate, the growth process will
come to a standstill much sooner.
10. As Ramser (1995, p. 238) correctly notes, increasing returns to scale are not necessary
for endogenous growth. It is necessary for one or a group of cumulative factors to exist
which can be produced with constant returns to scale and without the direct or indirect
use of non-reproductive factors. On the same topic, see also Schreiter (1997, p. 89),
Klump and La Grandville (2000) as well as Segerstrom (1999).
11. The relation between the introduction of technical knowledge and the occurrence of
increasing returns to scale can be illustrated in the following way. Let Y denote the output
of any type of good, X the input bundle and A the stock of knowledge, then Y AX.
From this, the relation aYaAX follows, when there is an increase in factor inputs by
the incremental factor a. If the stock of knowledge itself also now increases by factor a,
we have Y*a2AX, where Y* aY . This production function obviously exhibits
increasing returns to scale.
12. This also becomes clear when we consider the fact that human capital is treated as a
constant. The argument that workers cannot be trained ad infinitum is not valid because
the level of human capital is not measured primarily by the duration of training but
rather by the content and skills acquired during training.
13. It has to be noted here, however, that there are, in the meantime, endogenous growth
theories in which qualitative changes, e.g. in intermediate products, are modelled along
a so-called ‘quality ladder’. The improvements in quality due to technical progress cause
a decrease in the costs of consumer-goods production and an increase in per-capita
production (see also Grossman and Helpman 1991, Chapter 4). An endogenous model
of growth which treats, following Schumpeter, the case of ‘creative destruction’, has been
developed by Aghion and Howitt (1992).
14. Romer (1990, 81) expresses this as follows: ‘Equation (9.1) expresses output as an addi-
tively separable function of all the different types of capital goods so that one additional
dollar of trucks has no effect on the marginal productivity of computers. . . . The model
here considers the case in which all durables have additively separable effects on output.
An investigation of complementarity as well as of mixtures of types of substitutability
is left for future work.’
15. The remark that the quality of the end product remains unaffected by technological
change, does not refer to all endogenous growth models. As has already been mentioned
in note 13, the concept of quality ladders is an attempt to formalise the improvement of
goods as a result of technical progress. See also Maussner and Klump (1996, pp. 238–41
and 262–68).
16. Equating technical knowledge with patentable designs overlooks the fact that the know-
ledge process is also based on experimental research within firms. Essential impulses for
patentable knowledge result precisely from the engineering sciences’ analysis of the
industrial production process. It is true that Romer indicates that one could model the
research sector as a research department of the business sector. This is not enough
though, if the knowledge accumulation equation (9.3) is retained.
Why endogeneity is not enough to explain technological change 209
17. One has to agree with Solow (1991, p. 15f., and 1994, 51ff.), when he expresses criticism
aimed at some endogenous growth theories by saying that the scientific research findings,
be they patentable or not, are, for the most part, uncertain. Tietzel (1985, pp. 18f.) points
out this concept’s inconsistency by saying that this would require the predictability of
unknown nomological knowledge, which is, even if infinite information costs could be
lavished on it, totally illogical and impossible, because we would already have to be in
possession of that same knowledge. See also Lachmann (1976, pp. 127f.).
18. ‘The resources that would have been used to produce the forgone output are used instead
to manufacture capital goods’ (Romer 1990, p. 81).
19. Garegnani’s criticism (1970 and 1990) is aimed explicitly at Samuelson’s (1971) attempt
at interpreting the production function as a mere ‘parable’, in which the possibility of a
continual substitution between labour and capital is interpreted as a sign of a change
between different production processes for the production of a qualitatively unchanged
end product with respectively different capital goods.
20. Romer (1990, p. 84) expresses this in the following way: ‘The crucial feature of the spec-
ification used here is that knowledge enters into production in two distinct ways. A new
design enables the production of a new good that can be used to produce output. A new
design also increases the total stock of knowledge and thereby increases the productiv-
ity of human capital in the research sector.’
21. As has been mentioned above, this assumption contradicts a characteristic of empirically
observable technological change, which does not result from the already accumulated
stock of knowledge, particularly because advances in knowledge include the devaluation
of former knowledge.
22. In this sense, the already mentioned contribution of Grossman and Helpman (1991) as
well as that of Aghion and Howitt (1992), which follow Schumpeter’s ‘process of cre-
ative destruction’, must also be described as deterministic. Unfortunately, they cannot
be discussed here. A much more positive assessment of those endogenous growth theo-
ries which cite Schumpeter is given by Klump (1996).
23. On this topic, see especially Heuss (1965), Röpke (1970 and 1977) and Dosi (1988).
24. Competition means, as Morgenstern (1972) asserts ‘struggle with others, . . . fight, . . .
attempting to get ahead, or at least to hold one’s place’. One feels – according to
Morgenstern – absolutely nothing of this true character of competition in equilibrium
economics: ‘The contrast with reality is striking’.
25. Rosenberg (1994, p. 5) puts it succinctly when he says: ‘Instead of proceeding from a
natural starting point where firms possess little or no information and acquire informa-
tion through experience and investment, most economic models of technological change
assume that firms are aware of all the technological options available to them (leading
to a well-defined production function).’ It should be called to mind here that the strong
information assumptions are necessary. This is why Tietzel asserts that there can be no
surprises in equilibrium and Streissler (1980, p. 40) sums up that neoclassical theory has
always been, in principle, a theory of perfect information and certainty.
26. Nelson (1997, 33) expresses himself in a similar way: ‘The new neo-classical growth
models, . . . treat firms in a highly simplified way and barely address institutions, aside
from the “competitive” (or monopolistically competitive) market.’ In another contribu-
tion, Nelson (1994) himself has proven that organisational structures are relevant for
production and distribution.
27. Nelson (1997, 33) sees the continued adherence to the equilibrium approach as the
reason why uncertainties play no role in endogenous growth models. On the topic of
alternative market processes see also Lachmann (1976), Fehl (1986), Gutmann (1995),
and Schreiter (1997).
28. Now and then the necessity of industrial policy interventions is justified with the occur-
rence of positive externalities, which underlie the assumption of constant marginal
returns of capital inputs. However, this justification of the need for government action
rings hollow since decision makers are assumed to have doubtful preference structures
and an unrealistic information level. Weder and Grubel (1993, 491f.) point out that the
use of instruments of industrial policy is often due to particular interests which have
210 Self-organisation and networks
REFERENCES
Grossman, G.M. and E. Helpman (1991), Innovation and Growth in the Global
Economy, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Grupp, H. (1998), Foundations of the Economics of Innovation Theory. Measurement
and Practice, Cheltenham, UK, and Lyme, USA: Edward Elgar.
Gutmann, G. (1995), ‘Wettbewerbstheorie und Wachstumstheorie: Chance für eine
Synthese?’, ORDO, 46, pp. 149–63.
Hanusch, H. and U. Cantner (1993), ‘Neuere Ansätze in der Innovationstheorie
und der Theorie des technischen Wandels: Konsequenzen für eine Industrie- und
Technologiepolitik’, in F.M. Kramer (ed.), Innovationsökonomie und Techno-
logiepolitik. Heidelberg: Springer, pp. 11–45.
Hayek, F.A. von (1984), Der Strom der Güter und Leistungen. Tübingen: Mohr.
Heuss, E. (1965), Allgemeine Markttheorie. Tübingen: Mohr.
Hofmann, W. (1971), Theorie der Wirtschaftsentwicklung. Berlin: Duncker &
Humblot.
Klump, R. (1996), ‘Wachstum und Wandel: Die “neue” Wachstumstheorie als
Theorie wirtschaftlicher Entwicklung’, ORDO, 47, pp. 101–20.
Klump, R. and O. La Grandeville (2000), ‘Economic growth and the elasticity of
substitution: two theorems and some suggestions’, American Economic Review,
90, 281–91.
Krelle, W. (1985), Theorie des wirtschaftlichen Wachstums. Berlin: Duncker &
Humblot.
Lachmann, L.M. (1976), ‘On the central concept of Austrian economics: market
process’, in E.G. Dolan (ed.) The Foundations of Modern Austrian Economics,
New York: University Press, Columbia, pp. 126–32.
Lucas, R.E. (1988), ‘On the mechanics of economic development’, Journal of
Monetary Economics, 22, 3–42.
Maussner, A. and R. Klump (1996), Wachstumstheorie. Berlin: Springer.
Morgenstern, O. (1972), ‘Thirteen critical points in economic theory: an interpre-
tation’, Journal of Economic Literature, 10, 1163–89.
Nelson, R. (1994), ‘What has been the matter with neoclassical growth theory?’, in
G. Silverberg and L. Soete (eds), The Economics of Growth and Technical Change,
Aldershot: Brookfield, pp. 290–324.
Nelson, R. (1997), ‘How new is new growth theory?’, Challenge, 90 (5), 29–58.
North, D.C. (1990), Institutions, Institutional Change and Economic Performance,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Ramser, H.J. (1991), ‘Industriepolitik und Wachstumstheorie’, in B. Gahlen,
H. Hesse and H.J. Ramser (eds), Wachstumstheorie und Wachstumspolitik: Ein
neuer Anlauf. Schriftenreihe des Wirtschaftswissenschaftlichen Seminars
Ottobeuren, 20, 305–27.
Ramser, H.J. (1995), ‘Wachstumstheorie’, in N. Berthold (ed.), Allgemeine
Wirtschaftstheorie, Munich: Vahlen, pp. 235–50.
Richter, Rudolf (1994), Institutionen ökonomisch analysiert, Tübingen: Mohr/
Siebeck.
Robinson, J. (1953), ‘The production function and the theory of capital’, Review of
Economic Studies, 21 (2), 81–106.
Romer, P.M. (1990), ‘Endogenous technological change’, Journal of Political
Economy, 98 (5), pp. 71–102.
Röpke, J. (1970), Primitive Wirtschaft, Kulturwandel und die Diffusion von
Neuerungen, Tübingen: Mohr.
Röpke, J. (1977), Strategie der Innovation, Tübingen: Mohr.
212 Self-organisation and networks
1. INTRODUCTION
215
216 The political economy of complexity
based on rules and unpredictable events. If this holds true, economic policy
need not be haphazard; instead it can harmoniously build upon those pat-
terns of technological and organisational change that can be identified.3
Our analysis will proceed in four steps. We will first discuss in greater
detail the dynamically desirable framework for a learning policy from the
meta-point of view of the theory of economic policy. These methodolog-
ical considerations lead to the identification of types of rules on which
policy should be based if learning is to be institutionalised (section 2).
Building on these results we will then present a practically feasible concept
of learning policy. It depends on the identification of invariant patterns
within the recorded experience of the past and can be interpreted as a
modification of the traditional concept of stylised facts (section 3). In a
third step we will apply our method to one particular example, the
identification of invariant patterns of innovation and growth. This set of
stylised facts serves to describe the ‘regular’ part of socio-economic change
with regard to our concrete topic. In this context we will lay special empha-
sis on the question how open the set of identified patterns is towards a
changing environment or, in other words, what political learning can look
like in this context (section 4). These considerations lead to our fourth step,
in which we discuss how these results can serve as a reference system for
practical innovation policy. We will argue why we view our approach as a
sound basis for the conduct of an evolutionary innovation policy, and we
will discuss some policy guidelines that encompass the notion of continu-
ous learning (section 5). Short conclusions will serve to highlight aspects
for which we see the need for further research (section 6).
called innovation. The last step consists of the diffusion of this idea and its
adoption by other economic agents.5
This linear innovation model is based on the technology-push approach,
which assumes that technological change is supply-driven. However, con-
vincing empirical results show that this linear innovation model does
not correctly reflect economic reality.6 The major reason is that the sim-
plifications within this basic model neglect feedback effects between the
different stages of this process. This is a severe shortcoming, as such effects
are indispensable for understanding the generation and selection of inno-
vations, because the demand side can considerably contribute to both.7 In
particular the problems faced by first-fast adaptors can lead to renewed
questions for basic or applied research. As a result innovation processes are
much more complex in practice.
This insight raises an important question: How can policy cope with the
complexity inherent in processes of technological and organisational
change? Answering this question is difficult, even more so in ever-changing
environments driven by a multitude of parallel processes. To tackle this
problem it seems advisable to first study in greater detail the nature of
dynamic change. Most notably one needs to clarify whether such change
consists of structural elements which obey general rules, whether it is
purely driven by random effects or whether a particular mixture of both
elements dominates. The stronger the rule-driven part turns out to be, the
more feasible becomes an analytical understanding of these processes,
which is a prerequisite for policy making.
In order to assess the characteristics of innovation-driven dynamic
change, we apply the concept of ‘contingency’. This concept originates
from sociology and has recently been introduced into the theory of system
dynamics.8 It is based on an analysis of the dynamic characteristics of
evolving socio-economic systems and encapsulates the idea that the com-
plexity of such systems can be reduced by the systematic evaluation of
past behaviour. Economic agents do not behave erratically, because selec-
tion mechanisms (such as markets) force them to behave in the ‘best pos-
sible’ way. As such selection mechanisms are the same for many individuals
and, moreover, prove to be relatively stable in time and space,9 different
individuals tend to behave in similar ways if faced with comparable
situations.10
Based on these principles one can formulate the hypothesis that similar
behaviour of individuals and groups of individuals – ‘organisations’ such
as firms or other decision-making bodies – translates into similar patterns
of the evolution of different socio-economic systems. The extent to which
this holds true is an empirical question. For the moment it suffices to leave
this extent open (we will however provide an answer in a specific context;
218 The political economy of complexity
If we can agree that the economic problem of society is mainly one of rapid
adaptation to changes in the particular circumstances of time and place, it would
seem to follow that the ultimate decisions must be left to the people who are
familiar with these circumstances, who know directly of the relevant changes
and of the resources immediately available to meet them. We cannot expect that
this problem will be solved by first communicating all this knowledge to a central
board which, after integrating all knowledge, issues its orders. We must solve it
by some form of decentralization.14
The evolutionary policy maker adapts rather than optimizes, and his central
concern is the innovation system, the operation of the set of institutions within
which technological capabilities are accumulated. . . . [J]ust as individuals
operate under the constraints of localized, imperfect and uncertain information
so does the adaptive policy maker.17
And yet, while this view on policy making seems appropriate in the light
of the information problem, it does not grasp the full story. There is no
need to restrict policy making to purely adaptive behaviour in the sense
that it should be strictly reactive to socio-economic change. Method-
ological considerations derived on the basis of Hayek-type arguments in
fact primarily serve as a demonstration of the comparative disadvantages
of political actions which violate the principle of the superiority of decen-
tralised decision making and selection of economic results. They do not
necessitate an adaptive approach. In terms of our discussion of per-se
rules versus rules of reason, the implication is that – while both have com-
parative advantages and disadvantages – from a system perspective the
deficiencies of rules of reason seem particularly severe. We will therefore
focus on a solution which encompasses a compromise between the two
that gives greater relative weight to ex-ante specified per-se rules. In order
to address the latter’s disadvantages we enrich their application with a
dynamic element: in order to avoid the increasing imbalances in time
between unchanging, rigid per-se rules and the continuously evolving
socio-economic process, we institutionalise a learning routine for policy
makers.
Why is the difference between adaptive behaviour and learning so
important and what does it imply? The answer is twofold. Firstly, policy
making can be interpreted as a transformation of – both old and newly
arising – knowledge on socio-economic change into incentives that
influence future behaviour of individuals and firms. It thus contains by
definition a forward-looking perspective, as it tries to shape future events.
Therefore it is backward-looking only to the extent that the accumulation
of knowledge (as a prerequisite of policy making) requires the learned
analysis of past experience. Secondly, policy is in itself best regarded as a
process of trial and error. The stimulation of innovation is subject to great
uncertainty, and policy can fail.18 It thus seems advisable to interpret policy
making as part of an experiment, a process of trial and error that serves to
accumulate knowledge. As a consequence, policy has an important func-
tion even if it fails – as long as politicians learn by their mistakes. ‘Learning’
refers to improved knowledge about the nature of change in the policy field
Innovation and the learning policy maker 221
Kaldor postulated that every model should be able to explain the chara-
cteristic features of the economic process analysed as observed in reality.20
The problem of the scientist was to find that kind of abstraction which best
explained this observed reality; thus, he faced a problem of choice between
different theories. To find a solution Kaldor stated that the researcher had
to identify these characteristic features first. In a second step these features
could serve as a reference system for the evaluation of competing theories.
On this basis he could then choose the ‘best’ theory in a third and final step.
Kaldor summarises what has since become the ‘classical’ idea of stylised
facts as follows:
Practical problem
Formulation of
scientific question
Consensus analysis
Applications
(theory evaluation, policy advice)
The first two stylised facts describe general features of growth processes:
their regional embeddedness and the fact that they are subject to multiple
causality. This second aspect is particularly important for any policy based
on these results. Politicians need to avoid the trap of monism32 and devise
a consistent bundle of measures that reflects the interdependencies between
the individual causal elements which interact and mutually depend on one
another. In order to facilitate a systemic policy approach that takes account
of multiple causality, it is important to assess all candidates for such causal
elements.
This assessment leads to the third to eighth stylised facts. While no
scientific consensus emerged on the role of physical-capital accumulation
or labour, the empirical base gave rise to a negative statement on human-
capital accumulation. A clear majority of experts refuses the hypothesis
that an increase in the rate of human capital accumulation in itself creates
a growth effect. They point however towards an indirect effect. An increase
in human capital proves important if it is employed in basic or applied
research to generate innovation. As a consequence there exists a direct link
between structural variables (the stock of human capital) and flow vari-
ables (the rate of innovation). It is therefore important to take a closer look
at the process of technological and organisational change. This necessity is
underpinned by the result (which was achieved independently from the pre-
vious one, because it was based on a different empirical basis) that the gen-
eration and diffusion of innovation is an indispensable part of the bundle
of causal elements that shape growth paths over time.
We stated in section 2 that the demand side played a significant role in
the complex process of innovation and change. The fifth stylised fact
confirms this view. While a statement that increased demand generally
induces growth is too general to be agreed upon by most economists,
a more refined hypothesis meets the Whaples criterion: market expansion –
notably in geographical terms – fosters innovation, which in turn promotes
growth. Here again, as with regard to human capital accumulation, the
causal chain leads via the innovation process, which is the actual link
between demand and growth.
The following three statements assess this innovation process in greater
detail. It turns out that innovation has a bigger impact on growth than
invention. This is prima facie not surprising, given that innovation implies
the successful marketing of new solutions, whereas invention stresses the
technological dimension of novelty. However there is more to this state-
ment than that. A further implication is that transfer of knowledge
between regions or enterprises that primarily invent to regions or enter-
prises that primarily innovate (and imitate) has good chances of success in
terms of market results. In other words, for successful innovation to take
228 The political economy of complexity
The final step within the flow chart depicted in Figure 10.1 consists of the
formulation of policy advice based on the set of stylised facts identified
before. As indicated in the previous section, the fact that the patterns of
innovation and change are complementary in the sense that they mutually
reinforce one another facilitates this task. It is therefore possible to inte-
grate them into a common reference system for a consistent economic
policy, which proves to be in line with the systemic approach adopted by
evolutionary economists in their analyses of innovation systems. Although
230 The political economy of complexity
general formal rules that reduce transaction costs.42 At the same time,
policy must not attempt to select market outcomes as long as there do not
exist any stylised facts that support specific selection criteria. This means
that policy support should not be dependent on strict criteria that can only
be met by a limited number of economic agents, such as support only for
firms that possess an R&D department.43 The usual critique of untargeted
support does not apply in very early market phases, because the enlarge-
ment of technological and organisational variety is a crucial prerequisite
for the selection of outcomes by the market later on and thus for change
and growth. It therefore reflects the systemic approach described above.
In later stages of market evolution, factors such as increasing returns to
scale in production unfold their effects and lead, in connection with the
stabilisation of consumer tastes, to the reduction of variety and, ultimately,
a certain standardisation of product designs. Routinisation of production
processes and greater formalisation of the organisation within firms and
their supporting innovation system support this maturation. Here as well
these processes need time. Firstly, institutional settings that for instance
shape the flow of information within innovation systems depend not only
on formal laws, but at least as much on informal conduct based on trust
and shared objectives. This process cannot be accelerated without limits, as
it is linked to the change of attitudes within the persons involved, which is
a slow process. Secondly, minor improvements gain greater relative weight
in the innovation process. As their sources differ from those of the bigger
innovative steps that usually coincide with the emergence of new sectors,
the focus of attention shifts as well, towards the diffusion of best practice
and the creation of joint standards.
In the end, markets consolidate and become mature. At this stage, any
policy that aims at fostering innovation reaches its limits. Well-established
ties between the different market players and relatively low uncertainty may
now provide an environment with a functioning market mechanism in
theory that in practice becomes prone to collusion. In other words, the
focus of political attention shifts from fostering the ability to innovate
towards fostering incentives to innovate, which basically means preventing
anticompetitive behaviour. Here, for instance, competition policy might
turn into an effective tool. This insight highlights the need for a policy
mix that goes beyond the realms of a single policy field and calls for
co-operation not only between market players, but also different political
bodies within and beyond innovation systems.
And yet, no matter how sophisticated the design of such a dynamic
policy mix might be, policy based on this systemic approach can fail, too.44
What is important to note, however, is the function of such failures within
our approach. Failures are in themselves an element of learning policy,
Innovation and the learning policy maker 233
6. CONCLUSIONS
This chapter discussed a coherent approach towards the design, imple-
mentation and practical conduct of learning policy. Learning policy is a
method of conducting policy that intelligently builds upon the best avail-
able knowledge at each point in time and uses this knowledge to dynam-
ically modify the set of rules that govern economic behaviour. After an
in-depth discussion of the methodological requirements for such a policy
approach and the development of a practically feasible concept, we focused
our attention on innovation policy to demonstrate how this concept could
be applied in practice. We chose the topic of innovation because of its
pivotal role for socio-economic change and because it is a truly dynamic
process. This particularly enabled us to highlight the openness of our
approach towards changes in the knowledge stock of society. Of course,
this concept can be applied to other policy fields as well.
234 The political economy of complexity
scientific views, but they cannot force politicians to follow their advice. It
thus remains perfectly possible that unintelligent policy prevails, that is
policy that fails to learn from past experience. Only the political sovereign,
the electorate, could effectively sanction such behaviour. It is a question
that still needs to be explored in greater detail which metamechanisms
might be introduced to make ‘unintelligent’ political behaviour, that is
the refusal to learn, costly enough for politicians to trigger changes of
behaviour.
NOTES
1. We are grateful for helpful comments by Friedrich Breyer, Uwe Cantner and Stan
Metcalfe on earlier versions of this paper. The usual disclaimer applies.
2. Corresponding author: Dr Claudia Werker, Max-Planck-Institut für Ökonomik,
Abteilung Evolutionsökonomik, Kahlaische Straße 10, D-07745 Jena, Germany; email:
werker@econ.mpg.de
3. Economic agents’ as well as politicians’ expectations of such patterns may turn out to be
wrong. However, the concept we propose below takes this into account by means of a
feedback loop that translates failed expectations into new knowledge.
4. Cf. Schumpeter (1911/1987), pp. 100f.
5. See, for example, Steinmueller (1994), p. 54, or Fritsch (1991), 198.
6. Cf. e.g. Grupp (1997), pp. 17–20.
7. Cf. Lundvall (1992).
8. See Fulda, Lehmann-Waffenschmidt and Schwerin (1998), pp. 340ff.
9. This statement applies if one takes a functional approach, that is if one does not focus
on superficial historically grown differences between different laws, customs and so on
that govern behaviour but on the (economic) function these institutions perform.
10. For a profound discussion of the concept of contingency, cf. Schwerin (2001), pp. 75ff.
Also note that traditional economics takes this insight to the ahistorical extreme by mod-
elling identical economic agents (‘homo oeconomicus’), whereas chaos theory turns out
to be blind in the other eye by denying any similarity between different individual actions
and the respective outcomes on the system level.
11. Cf. Schwerin (2001), p. 79.
12. Cf. Schmidt (1996), pp. 148ff.
13. A good example is the German antitrust law, which is altered every three to nine years
but nevertheless hardly keeps pace with the changes of competitive behaviour in the
economy; cf. Schmidt (1996), pp. 155ff.
14. Hayek (1945), 524, emphasis in orginal.
15. See Bernholz and Breyer (1984), chapter. 5.
16. Cf. Hanusch and Cantner (1993); Metcalfe (1995); Metcalfe and Georghiou (1997).
17. Metcalfe (1995), p. 418. See also Teubal (1997).
18. For approaches that discuss such a systemic view of policy; cf. Metcalfe (1995); Lipsey
and Carlaw (1996); Metcalfe and Georghiou (1997); and Teubal (1997).
19. Kaldor widely used ideas first developed by Arthur Okun; cf. Kaldor (1985), p. 8.
20. For an introduction into Kaldor’s concept, see Kaldor (1968), pp. 177ff.
21. Kaldor (1968), p. 178.
22. See Schwerin (2001), pp. 92ff.
23. Schwerin (2001), pp. 98ff. Parts of the methodological requirements are omitted here in
order not to overload this introduction to the new concept.
24. Given that, for a certain topic, several mutually exclusive and contradictory theories
exist for which no metacriterion exists which states ex ante what theory is ‘true’, such
236 The political economy of complexity
a consensus is the only way to base practical actions on a sound scientific foundation.
The absence of such a metacriterion in science is obvious, thus the use of stylised
facts as a reference system for theory and policy evaluation serves as a second-best
mechanism.
25. The use of quality filters is advisable, as this restricts the studies to those which have been
put forward in a period of for instance the last ten years. Such a filter could consist in
the exclusive use of publications in top-ranked scientific journals.
26. Cf. Schwerin (2001), p. 114.
27. The consensus analysis becomes even more methodologically sound if it considers only
those hypotheses which have been tested in several studies by using different methods.
28. Schwerin (2001), pp. 133ff.
29. On the comparative advantages of bibliometric research compared to questionnaires
and other direct means of assessing experts’ views, cf. ibid., pp. 118 ff.
30. Cf. Whaples (1995), 139.
31. See Schwerin (2001), p. 179.
32. Landes (1994), 653.
33. For a more detailed discussion of this stylised facts and the implications thereof
cf. Schwerin and Werker (2003), 397ff.
34. Cf. Schwerin (2001), p. 174.
35. Cf. the approach taken in Rosenberg (1994).
36. As indicated in section 4, these features may also be part of other theoretical approaches,
such as innovation-driven models within New Growth Theory.
37. Cf. Metcalfe (1995), p. 418.
38. Cf. Nelson (1995), 67.
39. Ibid.
40. Cf. for instance Nelson and Winter (1982), pp. 76–82.
41. Cf. the following Werker (2003), pp. 285–90.
42. Cf. Metcalfe and Georghiou (1997), p. 25.
43. Cf. Werker (forthcoming).
44. See Metcalfe and Georghiou (1997), 25.
45. Cf. Kuhlmann (1992), p. 125.
46. Cf. Lipsey and Carlaw (1996), p. 269.
REFERENCES
Bernholz, Peter and Friedrich Breyer (1984), Grundlagen der Politischen Ökonomie,
second edition, Tübingen: Mohr (Paul Siebeck).
Fritsch, Michael (1991), ‘Innovation und Strukturwandel’, Das Wirtschaftsstudium,
20, 195–200.
Fulda, Ekkehard, Marco Lehmann-Waffenschmidt and Joachim Schwerin (1998),
‘Zwischen Zufall und Notwendigkeit – zur Kontingenz ökonomischer Prozesse
aus theoretischer und historischer Sicht’, in Gerhard Wegner and Josef Wieland
(eds), Formelle und informelle Institutionen – Genese, Interaktion und Wandel,
Marburg: Metropolis, pp. 327–77.
Grupp, Hariolf (1997), Messung und Erklärung des technischen Wandels. Grundzüge
einer empirischen Innovationsökonomik, Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer.
Hanusch, Horst and Uwe Cantner (1993), ‘Neuere Ansätze in der
Innovationstheorie und der Theorie des technischen Wandels – Konsequenzen
für eine Industrie- und Technologiepolitik’, in Frieder Meyer-Krahmer (ed.),
Innovationsökonomie und Technologiepolitik. Forschungsansätze und politische
Konsequenzen, Heidelberg: Physica, pp. 11–46.
Innovation and the learning policy maker 237
Hayek, Friedrich August von (1945), ‘The use of knowledge in society’, American
Economic Review, 35, 519–30.
Kaldor, Nicholas (1968): ‘Capital accumulation and economic growth’, in Friedrich
A. Lutz and Douglas C. Hague (eds), The Theory of Capital. Proceedings of a
Conference Held by the International Economic Association [1958], London:
Macmillan, pp. 177–222.
Kaldor, Nicholas (1985): Economics without Equilibrium. The Okun Memorial
Lectures at Yale University, Armons NY: M.E. Sharpe.
Kuhlmann, Stefan (1992), ‘Evaluation von Technologiepolitik: Zur Analyse der
Wirksamkeit politischer Techniksteuerung’, in Klaus Grimmer et al. (eds),
Politische Techniksteuerung, Schriften des Instituts Arbeit und Technik 5, Opladen:
Leske und Budrich, pp. 119–35.
Landes, David S. (1994), ‘What room for accident in history? explaining big changes
by small events’, Economic History Review, 47, 637–56.
Lipsey, Richard G. and Kenneth Carlaw (1996), ‘A structuralist view of innovation
policy’, in Peter Howitt (ed.), The Implications of Knowledge-Based Growth for
Micro-Economic Policies, Calgary: University of Calgary Press, pp. 255–337.
Lundvall, Bengt-Åke (1992), ‘User–producer relationships, national systems of
innovaton and internationalisation’, in Bengt-Åke Lundvall (ed.), National
Systems of Innovation and Interactive Learning, London: Pinter Publishers,
pp. 45–67.
Metcalfe, J. Stanley (1995), ‘The economic foundations of technology policy: equi-
librium and evolutionary perspectives’, in Paul Stoneman (ed.), Handbook of the
Economics of Innovation and Technological Change, Oxford and Cambridge, MA:
Blackwell, pp. 409–512.
Metcalfe, J. Stanley and Luke Georghiou (1997), ‘Equilibrium and evolutionary
foundations of technology policy’, CRIC Discussion Paper no. 3, University of
Manchester.
Nelson, Richard R. (1995), ‘Recent evolutionary theorizing about economic
change’, Journal of Economic Literature, 33, 48–90.
Nelson, Richard R. and Sidney G. Winter (1982), An Evolutionary Theory of
Economic Change, Cambridge, MA and London: Belknap Press of Harvard
University Press.
Rosenberg, Nathan (1994), Exploring the Black Box. Technology, Economic, and
History, Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Schmidt, Ingo (1996), Wettbewerbspolitik und Kartellrecht, fifth edition, Stuttgart:
Lucius & Lucius.
Schumpeter, Joseph A. (1911/1987), Theorie der wirtschaftlichen Entwicklung: Eine
Untersuchung über Unternehmergewinn, Kapital, Kredit, Zins und den Konjunk-
turzyklus, seventh edition, published first in 1911, unchanged reprint of the
fourth edition of 1934 Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.
Schwerin, Joachim (2001), Wachstumsdynamik in Transformationsökonomien.
Strukturähnlichkeiten seit der Industriellen Revolution und ihre Bedeutung für
Theorie und Politik, Köln: Böhlau.
Schwerin, Joachim, and Claudia Werker (2003), ‘Learning innovation policy based
on historical experience’, Structural Change and Economic Dynamics, 14,
385–404.
Steinmueller, W. Edward (1994), ‘Basic research and industrial innovation’, in Mark
Dogson and Roy Rothwell (eds), The Handbook of Industrial Innovation,
Aldershot, UK and Brookfield, US: Edward Elgar, pp. 54–66.
238 The political economy of complexity
It is always difficult to record the history of events that have not yet run their course
and whose outstanding players are all still living. . . . Events appear different, once
they are concluded; different again, while they are still developing. In both
instances, the aims of the reporter also differ. Gustav Struve (1849/1980, p. 290)
1. METHODOLOGICAL INTRODUCTION
239
240 The political economy of complexity
period since 1850. Prior to the 1960s, innovation phenomena were described
using other definitions: archives, libraries and research institutions as well
as documents from management, personnel departments or production
centres show terms which are different from those used according to present
standards (for example, ‘laboratory’ might be described as ‘establishment’,
‘experimental factory’).
According to today’s view, the concept of a specific research process
which leads to measurable innovation and which requires personnel and
financial expenditure, is based on Bernal’s (1939) farsighted and clearly
analysing work. Bernal distinguished the role of public research expend-
iture from that of civil research and, – as things stood – from that of the
war industry. The first statistics on expenditure for ‘industrial research’
by British companies are found in the annexes to his works. As reported
by Freeman (1992, p. 3), the definitions used by Bernal during his lectures
at the London School of Economics were brought to international com-
mittees (by Freeman himself as well as by others), which, in the 1960s,
worked for another standardisation of definitions, which led to a first
paper about the measurement of output of research and development
(Freeman 1969).
Consequently, the empirical framework underlying this chapter will be
determined using the current definitions and concepts. These may have had
other meanings in the past, but this ‘anachronism’ must be accepted.
Language is used by any historiography including the hermeneutic one;
however, as language develops over time, definitions may arise, disappear,
or change their meanings. Consequently and independently of the method
applied, any historiography is anachronistic to a certain degree (Lorenz
1997, p. 364). Former innovators were not masters of today’s historical
knowledge, nor of information about present innovation processes –
knowledge and information which we have acquired from our observa-
tion post.
Therefore, the definitions found in the leading OECD manuals4 from the
1990s will be used. Cliometrics are also more concerned with anomalies
than with constantly ongoing, inconspicuous processes. If a structural
breakage is found in a time series, this could point to a statistical artifact
arising from the change of definitions and conventions used. Consequently,
structural breakages5 found must always be interpreted and categorised in a
qualitative way. The problem of anachronism – if not avoided – can thus at
least be moderated. Intertemporal shifts of emphasis as an explanation of
structural breakage are all the more permissible since a functional innov-
ation model serves as an additional basis (see Grupp 1998), working on the
assumption that different innovation-oriented processes can be influenced
by all types of research and development (R&D).
The national German innovation system 243
This chapter is divided into a national (this section) and a sectoral level
(see the next section). For the definition of ‘national innovation systems’,
see Grupp 1998, p. 244. From a historical point of view, modifications of
the territorial situation (population, and so on) may not be ignored.
Therefore, from an empirical point of view it is essential to consider, for
example, the size of the Empire or of each federal territory. Not only is the
German Democratic Republic considered here, but also Saarland, the
Corridor, East Prussia and other areas. Territorial changes which took
place can be considered on the basis of today’s statistical procedures, so
that such data series, a priori, do not have to be absolutely consistent with
a territory (also refer to Hoffmann 1965, pp. 2 f.). However, it must be
pointed out that the omission of smaller districts (such as Alsace-Lorraine
from 1871 to 1917) in most cases brings in its train less important errors of
estimation than the big variances in the series of the whole territory of the
German Reich (Hoffmann 1965, p. 3).
6
Percentage of public budget
5
FRG
4
United Germany
3
Empire
2
1 GDR
0
18 0
55
18 0
65
18 0
18 5
18 0
18 5
18 0
95
19 0
05
19 0
19 5
19 0
19 5
19 0
35
19 0
45
19 0
19 5
19 0
19 5
19 0
75
19 0
85
19 0
95
00
5
7
7
8
8
9
1
1
2
2
3
5
5
6
6
7
9
18
18
18
19
19
19
19
19
19
20
Note: The numbers for United Germany before the unification in 1990 are artificially
composed by weighted average values between West Germany and the GDR.
1.0
0.8
0.7
0.6
0.5
0.4
Other science expenditures
0.3
0.2
0.1
0.0
18 0
18 5
18 0
18 5
18 0
18 5
18 0
18 5
18 0
19 5
19 0
19 5
19 0
19 5
19 0
19 5
19 0
19 5
19 0
19 5
19 0
19 5
19 0
19 5
19 0
19 5
19 0
19 5
19 0
95
5
5
6
6
7
7
8
8
9
9
0
0
1
1
2
2
3
3
4
4
5
5
6
6
7
7
8
8
9
18
Figure 11.2 Government expenditure for science, divided into the publicly
financed R&D share and other scientific tasks
246 The political economy of complexity
a great deal of scientific expenditure by the Empire was used for defence
tasks shortly after the foundation of the Reich. During the Weimar
Republic and the Third Empire, the R&D share of the total of scientific
expenditure continued to fluctuate at around 20 per cent (industrial
research not included).
A quick increase in the R&D share of scientific expenditure occurred
when research in certain areas was allowed again in the young Federal
Republic, after the signing of the Treaty of Paris in 1955: at times it reached
70 per cent and has only declined due to the recent reunification.
Prior to the Second World War, the relatively insignificant role played by
R&D within the scientific world is also shown by the distribution of funds
to the different institutions. During the decades preceding and following
the foundation of the Empire, the lion’s share of approximately 70 per cent
of the total public scientific expenditure is accounted for by all types of uni-
versities. Empire agencies and other institutions were established over time,
so that the universities’ share of scientific expenditure decreased to about
35 per cent at the beginning of the 20th century. Now, a little more than 20
to 30 per cent goes to these institutions charged with varied tasks, and
almost 10 per cent is accounted for by pure R&D institutions.
During the entire period before and between the two World Wars, a small
but significant and strongly varying amount of public expenditure went to
functions other than institutional support. The non-institutional support
is described as ‘project-specific scientific expenditure’ by Pfetsch (1982,
p. 113); this could be misunderstood, since part of it consisted of public
grants and support given to a wide range of projects and not only R&D
projects. They ranged from ‘Scientific efforts for opening up Central
Africa’, the publication of archives, international contributions to the sur-
veying of the earth, measures to combat typhoid fever or infant mortality,
to financial support for congresses.
Until the First World War more attention was generally given to scientific
support on an industrially relevant level, as well as to scientific application
(Pfetsch 1974); however, it would be incorrect to conclude that a major part
of these funds were granted to private companies, as can be shown for the
period following the Second World War. Industry was more interested in a
proportional increase in public support of production-relevant branches of
science (consequently, in the creation of external effects upon science-based
industries, Pfetsch 1974, p. 107) than in the support of their own R&D.
Of course scientific expenditure was borne exclusively by the German
states until the foundation of the Empire; afterwards, the central power
moderately supported the total public science budget by 20 per cent. Only
during the Republic of Weimar did this share grow considerably (see
Figure 11.3). After the occupation of Germany at the end of the Second
The national German innovation system 247
1.0
0.9
0.7
0.6
0.5
0.4
0.3
0.2
World War the Federal Government could not play its prior role again, all
the more so since several research areas were prohibited (research in the fields
of armament, nuclear science, chemistry and aviation). However, federal
institutions systematically increased their influence on science until the level
during the Third Reich was reached again. Since the recent reunification,
federal administration has been slowly but surely withdrawing from
scientific support.
Consequently, it must be noted that, following critical upheavals such as
the foundation of the Empire, and the First and the Second World Wars, the
Federal states had always begun to take over important tasks of scientific
support and were later relieved by the central power. The events following
the foundation of the Empire, which were called ‘getting empired’ by Pfetsch
(1974, p. 105), occurred in a hesitant way on complex scientific-political
levels. The results were manifold forms of co-operation between private,
mixed and individual government institutions and Empire authorities. The
same can be observed since 1945 under completely different political cir-
cumstances: the Federal Government only slowly became a dominant and
central supporter and organizer of the scientific system, its scientific expend-
iture diminishing both on an absolute and on a relative level only after the
reunification. Again this points to persistent basic structures in the national
innovation system. The only historical exception is the reunification of 1990:
whereas the Federal Government played a dominant role as a central
248 The political economy of complexity
1400
1200
Former FRG
1000
800
DM
GDR (PPP)
600
GDR (PPP minus subventions)
400
200
0
1971197219731974197519761977197819791980198119821983198419851986198719881989
structures remained basically the same as before the war, requiring similar
amounts of public support.
10 000
1000
100
1900 1910 1920 1930 1940 1950 1960 1970 1980 1990 2000
Note: The thin drawn lines represent the exponential growth rates for the main growth
periods as explained in the text.
80 000
70 000
Number of publications
60 000
Simulation with exponential growth
50 000
40 000
30 000
20 000
10 000
0
45 50 55 60 65 70 75 80 85 90 95
19 19 19 19 19 19 19 19 19 19 19
From 1974 to 1990, SCI publications from West and East Germany can
be compared electronically.8 This period is characterised by moderate
growth of publication activities (‘century standard’). In the 1970s, the share
of East German publications was approximately 16 to 17 per cent.
However, if one compares East and West Germany, both the proportional
shares of population and the proportion of R&D staff is almost 30 per
cent, so that scientific publications from the German Democratic Republic
are less represented in the US-based database. The proportion of East
German publications had constantly diminished to reach 13 per cent by the
end of the 1980s; and there is no answer to the question as to whether the
representation in the database was worse or if the output efficiency of East
German research activities continued declining until reunification.
Measured by its publication output, the profile of GDR research resem-
bles that of the former Federal Republic. In proportion to worldwide
average shares, researchers of both parts of Germany published much more
than a pro rata share in the research areas of energy and nuclear technol-
ogy, chemistry, solid-state physics and microbiology. A weaker level than
the worldwide average was shown in information science, engineering,
environmental research and public health, as well as in other biomedical
subjects. According to our estimation, this structural similarity could be the
reason for such a strong diminution of publication activities on an all-
German level following reunification. Integration did not affect differently
specialised East and West research systems, but only research systems with
The national German innovation system 253
that of attention received: it was found that those research areas which are
not internationally spread are significantly more noticed by the profes-
sional world than the publications with a higher degree of international-
isation. No such correlation can be found for West German research. It is
possible that hierarchy and cadre selection mechanisms played a role
regarding access to Western periodicals.
100%
80%
Business expenditures for R&D
60%
40%
20%
0%
48
50
52
54
56
58
60
62
64
66
68
70
72
74
76
78
80
82
84
86
88
90
92
94
96
98
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
Figure 11.7 Development of government and industrial R&D expenditure
in relation to each other from 1948–2000
is possible in the different branches, which influences not only the forms of
organisation but also researchers’ liberties and practical work.
90 000
80 000
Simulation with exponential
growth
70 000
Number of patent applications
60 000
50 000
40 000
30 000
20 000
10 000
0
1812182218321842185218621872188218921902191219221932194219521962197219821992
person reaches one of the highest levels in comparison with the United
States, Japan and the European Union.
Diverging from this rough rule, growth is observed during the Weimar
Republic phase until the beginning of the Third Reich, followed by a very
deep setback during the Second World War, which is distinctly more serious
than that during the First World War, and a return to the average rate by
approximately 1960. Another boom follows until 1975 when deep recession
takes place which is only overcome in the mid 1990s.
No investigation has yet discovered whether these growth cycles only
have economic causes. The economic boom after the foundation of the
Empire is well-known (Ziegler 2000, p. 201); the same is true for the serious
recession following the oil crisis in 1973 straight after the economic
miracle. The question remains as to whether the reduction of innovation
activities at the beginning of the Third Reich was only due to economic
reasons or to a modified practice of patenting (for example by stronger
observance of secrecy due to the early war economy, or by the expulsion
or migration of Jewish scientists). Further, the question is asked as to why
the growing R&D budgets granted after the Second World War did not
lead to an increase in patent activities. Obviously this decrease of patent
efficiency is due to an economic calculation which is not exclusively driven
by R&D inputs.
Up to now, global indications have been made about patent documents
of national and international actors. By international actor it is understood
258 The political economy of complexity
First, the publication history of the two selected areas, electrical technol-
ogy and chemistry, will be summarised. One problem is the tracking of
publication activities in the fields of electrical technology and chemistry
prior to 1974, the period for which no online data base is available. To
resolve this problem, the corresponding monographs were submitted
to manual analyses, which made the period from approximately 1924
onwards accessible. Because this process was undertaken beyond the year
1974, the manually obtained figures can be extrapolated to the data base
level. First analyses support the earlier hypothesis: during the 1960s and
early 1970s, the growth of publication activities in chemistry was higher
than it was later on, so that a synchronism of scientific publication activ-
ities and the economic success of mass chemistry (base) could be
confirmed (Figure 11.9).
An extension of the historical period shows a rapid growth of publication
activities in the field of electrical technology since the 1950s, reaching its peak
from the middle to the end of the 1960s, then again in the mid-seventies. This
development is followed by a decrease of publications to reach a relatively low
level in 1981, then by another period of growth. Consequently, the present
study of data records is substantially supported and completed by manual
tracking up to the Weimar Republic. The manual method probably has an
even higher explanatory power, since the continuous completion of inventory
262 The political economy of complexity
250 000
200 000
Chemistry
150 000
100 000
50 000
Electrical engineering
0
24
29
34
39
44
49
59
64
69
84
99
5
9
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
19
Figure 11.9 Development of German publications in the fields of electrical
technology and chemistry, from 1924 to 1999 (early figures
extrapolated)
data records (like in the case of the SCI) could lead to artefacts. Although the
SCI strives for transparency with the selection procedures of periodicals
entering the data base, quantitative conclusions for individual subjects are
not always possible (Testa 1997).
Publication activities in the fields of electrical technology and chemistry
show interesting subject-specific deviations from the average trends of
publication activities in all scientific disciplines in Germany (Figure 11.9).
In contrast to the upward development shown by electrical technology
prior to and following reunification, which takes an anticyclical course
compared with global publication activities, the growth of publication
activities in chemistry is reduced synchronously with the publication
activities in all scientific fields in the middle of the 1970s. Presumably the
anticyclical development of publication activities in the area of chemistry
can be linked to the division of basic material chemistry into specialised
and fine chemistry which took place in the 1970s, followed by bio-
technology. The anticyclic boom of publication activities in the area of
electrical technology could be linked to the appearance of the present
information and communications technology, and could be interpreted as
its scientific predecessor. First analyses of the development of R&D
expenditure in chemistry and electrical technology industries support this
thesis.
The national German innovation system 263
2500
Low-voltage technology
2000
High-voltage technology
1500
1000
500
0
1882 1892 1902 1912 1922 1932 1942 1952 1962 1972 1982 1992
25%
20%
15%
Chemistry
10%
5%
Electrical engineering
0%
1885 1895 1905 1915 1925 1935 1945 1955 1965 1975 1985 1995
Figure 11.11 Share of the total patent publications about national patent
applications held by electrical technology and chemistry
266 The political economy of complexity
During the period of reconstruction after World War II, the number of
patents in the area of chemistry increased, reaching more than 20 per cent,
but was hit by a severe crisis following 1967. Since approximately 1970 –
when the proportion had dropped to less than 10 per cent – the share of the
total number of patents held showed moderate growth to approximately
12 per cent. These high shares of national patent inventory reveal that the
fields of electrical engineering and chemistry were and remain leading indus-
trial sectors. They show above-average expansion, and their global economic
importance is characterised by continuous growth (Ziegler 2000, p. 240).
Analogous with electrical technology, chemistry can also be divided into
patent-statistical classifications (for example organic chemistry, plastics,
pharmaceutical substances, biochemistry, detergents and agrarian chem-
istry. Innovation activities in these six fields show extremely different
degrees of development. Both of the first two fields show a continuous
increase in the total number of chemistry patents (in spite of cyclical
differences in detail), whereas the smaller fields of chemistry, described in
the category ‘other fields’, which was very significant from approximately
1880, started to grow from about 1970 (Figures 11.12 and 11.13). This only
points to different definitions concerning ‘other fields’.
An attempt to subdivide these ‘other fields’ shows the spectacularly high
share of biochemistry in the total number of chemistry patent applications
prior to the turn of the century. This surprising development is explained
45%
40%
Organic chemistry
35%
All other
30%
25%
20%
15%
10%
Resins
5%
0%
1883 1893 1903 1913 1923 1933 1943 1953 1963 1973 1983 1993
35%
30%
25%
20%
Biochemistry
15%
Pharmaceutical
10%
Agro-chemistry
5%
Detergents
0%
1883 1893 1903 1913 1923 1933 1943 1953 1963 1973 1983 1993
Figure 11.13 Breakdown of the ‘other fields’ in the total number of patent
publications in the area of chemistry
268 The political economy of complexity
100%
Fat, oil and wax
90%
Alcoholic beverages
80% Vinegar and its processing
Processing of enzymes or
70%
micro-organisms
60% Side products of fermented solutions
Micro-organisms or enzymes
50%
Pitching
40%
Processing of alcoholic beverages
30%
Processing of fat
20%
Beer brewing
10%
0%
Biochemistry 1900 Biochemistry 1998
The results show that more important foreign inventions were realised in
the area of electrical technology than in chemistry. The proportion of
foreign inventors in the area of electrical technology corresponds approxi-
mately with the average of all technical areas; that is, it regressed from more
than 35 per cent (1902) to approximately 20 per cent by 1928 and to
10 per cent by 1942. In the area of chemistry, the situation is different:
foreign inventors always played a minor role (1902: 20 per cent), however,
this ratio was slightly reduced (1942: 13 per cent).
Regarding the historical statistics of the selected sectors, it is concluded
that, under conditions of a relatively low level of knowledge exchange with
foreign countries, a branch suffers less from periods of crises and autarky
and that, on the other hand, intense knowledge exchange with foreign
countries leads to correspondingly sensible change. This will certainly have
important effects on the organisation of innovation activities, which should
be analysed on the level of individual institutions (companies as well as
research institutes).
The patent statistics of the German Democratic Republic can also be
divided both on a technical and on an institutional level. For example,
studies exist showing the extent to which the Humboldt University of East
Berlin applied for patents in the areas of chemistry and electrical technol-
ogy. According to this, chemistry had become one of the most prominent
research areas of the GDR in approximately 1990, whereas electrical
The national German innovation system 269
This look back into the historical times of innovation reveals many inter-
esting perspectives: for instance the present globalisation trends in R&D
may now be interpreted as a renaissance of the times around 1900: before
the autarky and war situations in national socialist Germany the innovation
system was internationalised in a similar way as today but possibly not to
the same quantitative extent. Yet the logistic and travel possibilities for
exchange of knowledge are much better today than a hundred years ago.
Most astonishingly the German innovation system was very stable
although it witnessed several political system changes in the past century.
The total amount of government spending on science and innovation fol-
lowed similar quantitative tracks after its formation in the 19th century,
after the First World War and after the Second World War. The respective
central powers were no strong pillars in science and technology. On the
contrary, the science and technology operation was maintained and recon-
structed by the German states before the central power found ways to estab-
lish itself as dominating. However, considerable differences are observed
when regarding the strong role of enterprises in innovation after the Second
World War which was – in pecuniary terms – not as visible before. Only
after reunification in 1990 was the acting power the federal government at
a time when enterprises were largely dominating the financing of R&D.
This was definitely different a hundred years ago.
In terms of the basic sectoral structures in science and technology, the
strong and the weak sides were almost the same whatever regime and terri-
torial boundaries existed. This persistence of the innovation system points
to a resistant innovation culture in and around Germany which may not be
influenced too much by external shocks or incentives be it in monetary or
institutional form. If technology and innovation policy intends to change
the German innovation culture in its basics one probably needs other gov-
ernment methods than those being used up to today. Even the isolation of
the former GDR and its subjection under the communist regime could not
change much.
There seems to be a specific German understanding of the opening and
development of technology trajectories. The industrial research system in
270 The political economy of complexity
Germany was one of the first in the world to be formed and developed.
Other countries followed that pattern more or less closely. Yet the subjects
of research seemed to be different between the countries and remained
largely constant over long periods. Obviously the technical and scientific
elites in Germany succeeded in following their interests in any political
system collectively. For the research and education policy this means that
soft factors like group identity, schools of thought and personal exchange
are more reliable and more efficient government instruments than the trad-
itional monetary incentive systems. This sustainable culture imprint can
only be analysed and detected in historical time series.
Innovation is no ‘reality’ whatsoever, and it is not considered as existing
‘in itself’; instead, innovation activities are only constituted by the specific
method of scientific approach. An historical object of investigation about
innovation activities is not ‘given’, instead, it is ‘imposed’ on the researcher,
that is, he/she must establish a measurement concept. An operationalisa-
tion considered as ideal could lead to an exorbitant cost of collection,
whereas a less adequate method could have favourable effects on both the
process and the results of measurement. This applies particularly to evolu-
tionary innovation research, where results are not always shown by a
formal mathematical model. Here, the keyword of an ‘appreciative’ theory
was created. Based on such an approach, absolutely no immediate, con-
stituent measuring directives can be derived either. Consequently, it is
necessary to construct corresponding indicators for insufficient ‘tailor-
made’ theoretical constructs. Although this procedure could be considered
wearisome, there is no other option.
The suggested range of indicators on a national or sectoral level gives a
detailed impression of both the extent and the contents of innovation activ-
ities during more than the past hundred years. The empirical base which
evolutionary researchers interested in innovation and economic history-
related questions can rely on, was broadened to a large extent, so that there
is no longer the possibility of a serious empirical gap. On the one hand,
many of the questions raised by evolutionary theory cannot yet be studied
on an empirical level. On the other hand, however, the inverse is equally
correct: empirical findings have become available, discovering structures
which could be picked up by the theoretical side for further construction of
theoretical thought.
On the future research agenda should be many more such longitudinal
studies of innovation systems. The basic findings for Germany should be
compared to other countries which possibly suffered less from territorial
and political changes. The data used in this article should exist in other
countries as well and may be brought to the surface. Also we need more sec-
toral studies in order to work out typologies of innovation development
The national German innovation system 271
NOTES
1. This chapter was drafted and presented to the International Joseph A. Schumpeter
Conference in April 2002. An earlier abridged version was published in Shavinina (2003).
The chapter is based on a much more detailed volume by the same authors in German
language (Grupp et al. 2002).
2. See also the contributions included in Müller and Rüsen (1997).
3. Cf. Machlup (1960/61), Grohmann (1988) and Grupp (1998).
4. According to these (OECD 1992, 1993), technological innovations comprise new prod-
ucts and processes and significant technological changes of products and processes.
5. Maddison (1982, p. 2 and p. 83) talks about system shocks. Gerschenkron (1943) points
to the pervasive institutional powers that may overcome external shocks for decades.
6. More precisely, ‘research share’ means the ‘R&D share’ of the total expenditure for
science and technology.
7. Personal communication Dr. Eugene Garfield, founder of the Institute for Scientific
Information, Philadelphia, 14 October 2000.
8. Due to the delay in appearance of scientific publications following submission, no quan-
titative cutback in literature production by the researchers of German Democratic
Republic institutes can be perceived until the end of 1990 (Weingart et al. 1991, p. 4).
9. Recently, surprisingly similar results were also found using other methods.
10. In 1928, 358 member companies were registered in the central association of elec-
trical technology and electrical industry (Zentralverband Elektrotechnik- und
Elektroindustrie, ZVEI).
REFERENCES
Albrecht, E., O. Dohnert, M. Schneider and H. Bourcevet (1991). ‘DDR-forschung
im internationalen vergleich unter zugrundelegung der patentstatistik’, Report
for the Science Council, Sektion Wissenschaftstheorie und Wissenschaftsorgan-
isation, Berlin: Humboldt University.
Anonymous (E. W. H.) (1925). ‘Output of scientific papers’, Nature 116 (2908),
pp. 129–30.
Anonymous (1986). ‘Das kaufkraftverhältnis zwischen d-mark und mark in der
DDR 1985’, DIW-Wochenbericht 21/86, 53, pp. 259–68.
Bannock, G., R.E. Baxter, and E. Davis (1998). Dictionary of Economics, 6th
edition, London: Penguin.
Bernal, J.D. (1939). The Social Function of Science, London: George Routledge &
Sons.
Boch, R. (ed.) (1999). Patentschutz und Innovation in Geschichte und Gegenwart,
Frankfurt a. M.: Peter Lang.
Dohrn-van Rossum, G. (1999). ‘Erfinder und erfinderschutz im spätmittelalter und
in der frühen neuzeit’, in Boch (1999), pp. 39–50.
Erker, P. (1990). ‘Die verwissenschaftlichung der industrie: zur geschichte der indus-
trieforschung in den europäischen und amerikanischen elektrokonzernen
1890–1930’, Zeitschrift für Unternehmensgeschichte 35, pp. 73–94.
272 The political economy of complexity
Fogel, R.W. (1964). Railroads and American Economic Growth, Baltimore: The
Johns Hopkins Press.
Freeman, C. (1969). ‘Measurement of output of research and experimental devel-
opment’, Statistical Reports and Studies, Paris: UNESCO.
Freeman, C. (1992). The Economics of Hope, London: Pinter Publishers.
Freimann, K.-D. and A.E. Ott (eds) (1988). Theorie und Empirie in der
Wirtschaftsforschung, Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr.
Gascoigne, R. (1992). ‘The historical demography of the scientific community’,
1450–1900, Social Studies of Science, 22, pp. 545–73.
Gerschenkron, A. (1943). Bread and Democracy in Germany, Ithaca: Cornell
University Press.
Grohmann, H. (1998). ‘Die statistische Adäquation als Postulat einer
sachgerechten Abstimmung zwischen Theorie und Empirie’, in Freimann und
Ott (1988), pp. 25–42.
Grupp, H. (1998). Foundations of the Economics of Innovation – Theory,
Measurement and Practice, Cheltenham, UK and Lyme, USA: Edward Elgar.
Grupp, H. and U. Schmoch (1992). Wissenschaftsbindung der Technik, Heidelberg:
Physica-Verlag.
Grupp, H., U. Schmoch and S. Hinze (2001). ‘International alignment and scientific
regard as macroindicators for international comparisons of publications’,
Scientometrics 51(2), 359–80.
Grupp, H., I. Domínguez Lacasa and M. Fredrich–Nishio (2002), Das Deutsch
Innovationssystem seit der Reichsgründung, Heidelberg: Springer–Physica
Publishers.
Hetmeier, H.-W. (1990). ‘Öffentliche ausgaben für forschung und experimentelle
entwicklung 1987’, Wirtschaft und Statistik 2/1990, pp. 123–29.
Hinze, S. and H. Grupp (1995). ‘Ein rückblick auf wissenschaft und technik in der
ehemaligen DDR: ostdeutschlands forschungs- und entwicklungspotential’, in
Holland and Kuhlmann (1995), pp. 41–86.
Hoffmann, W.G. (1965). Das Wachstum der Deutschen Wirtschaft seit der Mitte des
19. Jahrhunderts, Berlin: Springer.
Holland, D. and S. Kuhlmann (1995). Systemwandel und industrielle Innovation,
Heidelberg: Physica.
Hoyningen-Huene, P. (1999). ‘Kommt die physik der wahrheit immer näher?’
Physikalische Blätter 55(3), 56–8.
Irvine, J., B.R. Martin, and A. Isard, Ph. (1990). Investing in the Future, Aldershot,
UK and Brookfield, US: Edward Elgar.
König, W. (1995). Technikwissenschaften – Die Entstehung der Elektrotechnik aus
Industrie und Wissenschaft zwischen 1880 und 1914, Chur: G+B Verlag Fakultas.
Lorenz, Ch. (1997). Konstruktion der Vergangenheit, Köln: Böhlau.
Mabe, M. and M. Amin (2001). ‘Growth dynamics of scholarly and scientific jour-
nals’, Scientometrics 51(1), 147–62.
Machlup, F. (1960/61). ‘Idealtypus, wirklichkeit und konstruktion’, Ordo – Jahrbuch
für die Ordnung von Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft 12, 21–57.
Maddison, A. (1982). Phases of Capitalist Development, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Marschall, L. (1999). ‘Industrielle Biotechnologie im 20. Jahrhundert –
Technologische Alternative oder Nischentechnologie?’ Technikgeschichte 66, (4),
277–93.
The national German innovation system 273
Müller, K.E. and J. Rüsen, (eds.) (1997). Historische Sinnbildung, Reinbek: Rowohlt.
North, M. (ed.) (2000a). Deutsche Wirtschaftsgeschichte, München: C.H. Beck.
North, M. (2000b) Einleitung, in North (2000a), pp. 11–14.
OECD (1992). Oslo Manual: Proposed Guidelines for Collecting and Interpreting
Technological Innovation Data, Paris: OECD.
OECD (1993). Frascati Manual 1992. 5th Revision, Paris: OECD.
Pfetsch, F.R. (1974). Zur Entwicklung der Wissenschaftspolitik in Deutschland
1750–1914, Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.
Pfetsch, F.R. (1982). Datenhandbuch zur Wissenschaftsentwicklung, Köln: Zentrum
für historische Sozialforschung.
Roscher, W. (1886). Grundlagen der Nationalökonomie, 18th ed., Stuttgart:
J.G. Cotta’sche Buchhandlung.
Schmoch, U., G. Licht, and M. Reinhard (2000). Wissens- und Technologietransfer
in Deutschland, Stuttgart: Fraunhofer IRB Verlag.
Schmoch, U. and U. Sass (2000). ‘Erfassung der technologischen Leistungsfähigkeit
der östlichen Bundesländer mit Hilfe von Patentindikatoren’, Report for the
Federal Ministry BMBF, Karlsruhe: FhG-ISI.
Schumpeter, J.A. (1911/1964). Theorie der wirtschaftlichen Entwicklung, München
and Leipzig, quoted from the 6th edition, Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.
Schumpeter, J.A. (1942/1975). Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy, New York,
quoted from the German translation, 4th edition, München: Francke.
Shannina, L.V. (2003) (ed). International Handbook on Innovation, New York:
Pergamon–Elsevier, pp. 1018–43.
Smith, J.K. jr (1990). The Scientific Tradition in American Industrial Research,
Technology & Culture 31, 121–31.
Stolper, G., K. Häuser, and K. Borchardt (1964). Deutsche Wirtschaft seit 1870,
Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr.
Struve, G. (1849/1980). Geschichte der drei Volkserhebungen in Baden 1848/1849,
Bern: von Jenni; quoted from the revised reprint, Freiburg: Rombach.
Testa, J. (1997). The ISI Database: The Journal Selection Process, Essay No. 1,
Philadelphia, Institute of Scientific Information.
Wagner-Döbler, R. and J. Berg (1996). ‘Nineteenth-century mathematics in the
mirror of its literature: a quantitative approach’, Historia Mathematica
23, 288–318.
Weingart, P., Strate, J. and M. Winterhager (1991). Bibliometrisches Profil der
DDR, Report for the Science Council, Universitätsschwerpunkt Wissenschafts-
forschung, University of Bielefeld.
Wengenroth, U. (1997). Der Beitrag des Staates zu Forschung und Entwicklung in
Deutschland seit der Reichsgründung, Manuscript.
Ziegler, D. (2000). Das Zeitalter der Industrialisierung, in North (2000a),
pp. 102–281.
12. Emergence and diffusion of
disastrous innovations – a case
study
Reiner Peter Hellbrück1
INTRODUCTION
The central statements are the following: (a) If the ‘circumstances corres-
pond with each other’, then and only then there can be innovations.2 Thesis
(a) says that there have to be various conditions present and met so that
their combination is sufficient for an innovation. The following conditions
are met in the case study: (b) the increase of knowledge is essential,
nonetheless it is not yet sufficient to explain the emergence and diffusion of
the organisational innovation; (c) the organisational innovation corres-
ponds to the preferences of decision makers and supporters; (d) the danger
of disastrous consequences for competing firms adopting an organisational
innovation are not sufficient to prevent its diffusion; (e) regarding the
broader consensus about the societal advantages of an organisational inno-
vation, the potential harm to business can be neutralised and moreover
transformed into a competitive edge.
Case studies are only rare in economics. Usually the method of the par-
ticipating observation is chosen. This case is different; it relates to the
author’s own personal work experience in the German health-care system.
This working experience relates to the years 1998 until 2000 and the author
also participated actively in some projects. The time-frame before July
1998, which is the main focus of this analysis, has neither been actively
influenced nor affected by the author.
The focus is an organisational innovation and accompanying improve-
ment innovations in diabetes care in Germany between the years 1993 and
2000. This care needs, according to experts’ opinion, to be improved (Mehl,
Becker-Berke und Müller-de-Cornejo 2000, p. 6 and Bertram 1999). An
impression of problems caused by diabetes shows the following facts:
approximately 1800 persons become blind annually, 9000 diabetes patients
need to undergo enduring dialysis, 28 000 patients need amputations, and
274
Emergence and diffusion of disastrous innovations 275
there is a three to four times higher risk of coronary heart diseases. Eighty
per cent of the people with diabetes receive orally administered antidiabetic
medical treatment (Laschet 1998).
Due to the problems of diabetes, in early 1993 contracts concerning
diabetes patients were concluded between some health insurance funds
and Regional Associations of Statutory Health Insurance Physicians
(Kassenärztliche Vereinigung) which can be seen as precursors of rules
and regulations to the current contracts (Mehl, Becker-Berke und Müller-
de-Cornejo 2000, p. 9). Nowadays, contracts concerning better supply for
diabetes patients can be found in each of Germany’s federal states: between
the years 1993 and 1998, 23 diabetes contracts were counted (Landgraf et al.
1999, ii). However, contracts can be distinguished between old and new
types where the latter cover more knowledge about the long-run problems
and consequences of diabetes. Information about the disease diabetes as well
as the characteristics of different kinds of diabetes contracts will be summed
up in the upcoming section ‘Diabetes Contracts’.
In the year 1997, additional regulations were introduced by the Statutory
Health Insurance Reorganisation laws (GKV3-Neuordnungsgesetze, GKV-
NOG1 and GKV-NOG2). These revisions particularly concerned the
so-called ‘Modellvorhaben’ (model projects) and ‘Strukturverträge’ (struc-
ture contracts) whereby health insurance funds and Regional Associations
of Statutory Health Insurance Physicians were permitted projects to try
new organisational forms which were not allowed under the regular law.
These changes did not however trigger the new diabetes contracts. These
changes in regulation will be described later on in the ‘Regulation’ section
of the chapter.
Surprisingly, the organisational innovation was not introduced by the
Allgemeine Ortskrankenkasse (AOK) (a big health insurance fund) which
had the main influence in the development and introduction of the ‘second-
generation’ diabetes contracts. The model was brought up first by an AOK
competitor, the Barmer Ersatzkasse (BEK). The introduction of this new
idea will be further discussed and explained in the ‘Emergence’ section.
Additional health insurance funds, the innovator health insurance fund
AOK included, are still practising in the ‘second-generation’ diabetes con-
tracts. In the ‘Diffusion’ section the question of why the diabetes contracts
were disastrous will be discussed and why those types of contracts still
diffused. The section ‘Continuation’ is dedicated to the question why the
diabetes contracts were not simply cancelled and which strategies were
adopted to avoid harmful consequences or even to switch the disadvantage
into a competitive edge. The most important insights are summed up in the
section ‘Conclusions’.
276 The political economy of complexity
DIABETES CONTRACTS
REGULATION
To improve and develop statutory health insurance, health insurance funds can
examine benefits, measures, and procedures (even as models) based on the regu-
lation of this section. Its goal should be to implement incentives to supply
benefits at a reasonable price and not to waste scarce resources. (§63, SGB V
1993)
For the most part, the legislator had the implementation of elements of
private health insurance in mind. For example, according to §65 SGB V
1993, an opportunity for health insurance funds was given, saying they
could choose reimbursement of expenses instead of benefits in kind6 to
their insured.
Sections §§63 to 64 of the SGB V were completely restated in 1997 by the
GKV-NOG2. In particular, the objective had changed through this legal
amendment.
To improve the quality of care and the economical supply of health care, health
insurance funds and their associations can either carry out or arrange models
according to §64 concerning procedures, organisation, financing, and reim-
bursement within the framework of its legal task. (§63 SGB V 1997)
Concerted action gives recommendations to the treatment sectors and also to the
variation of compensation. Recommendations can be given for the duration of
one year and for a longer period too. The recommendations have to be formed
such that an increase of the contribution rate will be avoided except where the
necessary medical care cannot be guaranteed even if scarce resources are being
used effectively (principle of contribution-rate stability). (§141, 2 SGB V 1997)
This paragraph was included in the SGB V 1997 due to some activities of
the Federal Association of Health Insurance Funds BKK (BKK means
firm health insurance fund). In the mid 90s, this association set up a ‘phys-
ician network with combined budgets’ (Müller, Richard, and Schönbach
1999). Its aim was the realisation of cost savings through the co-ordination
of medical activities.
In 1993, the health-structure law brought an additional important reform
for health insurance funds. The responsibilities of health insurance funds
and members’ voting rights were changed so that future competition
between health insurance funds became more and more fierce. However, this
competition between health insurance funds did not take place until the
year 1997. Without additional regulation it was feared that health insurance
funds would compete for insurants with low risk of sickness. To prevent this,
the Risk Structure Compensation Scheme (Risikostrukturausgleich abbre-
viated by RSA) was introduced (§266 SGB V 1993). No matter what char-
acteristics a person admissible to the German Statutory Health System has,
health insurance funds should have no incentive to prefer low-risk insurants.
280 The political economy of complexity
EMERGENCE
Diabetes contracts of the first generation were signed and closed before and
after the year 1997, when competition between health insurance funds
intensified considerably (Meierjürgen 1994). Mehl, Becker-Berke and
Müller de Cornejo (2000) talk about the precursor of the second-generation
diabetes contracts: diabetes contracts in Brandenburg and Saxonia for the
year 1993. These contracts already included extra budgeting payments to
furnish diabetic services and training achievements. The first diabetes con-
tract of the second generation took effect in 1998; it was concluded between
the BEK (innovator health insurance fund) and the Associations of
Statutory Health Insurance Physicians in Westphalia-Lip. Shortly after
that, the innovator fund AOK concluded a second-generation diabetes con-
tract with a minor health insurance fund (agricultural health insurance
company) and the Associations of Statutory Health Insurance Physicians
in Thuringia.
However, why did the diabetes contracts come into existence at all? There
were several reasons. First of all, diabetes was back in everyone’s mind and
interest due to the St Vincent Declaration. Moreover, through the fall of
the Berlin Wall in East Germany a development was unleashed which led
to the first-generation diabetes contracts. Insufficiencies and inefficiencies
Emergence and diffusion of disastrous innovations 281
pure economic reasons. Then, family doctors felt certain not to lose
patients for long periods to more highly qualified persons (specialist
physicians).
4. Parallel to this development, alternatives for NIDDM treatment were
internationally examined for years in a long-term study (especially in
Great Britain) in the framework of the famous UKPDS (start of the
recruiting of test persons in 1977). This study showed that a better
metabolism leads automatically to a significant reduction of subse-
quent diabetes diseases. For example, with the exception of cataracts
it showed that diabetes-dependent complications could be decreased
as a result of a person’s lower blood pressure (Adler, Stratton, Neil
and Yudkin 2000). This study confirmed hypotheses held for a long
time and based on epidemiological studies (Ärzte-Zeitung 1998). In
1993, a guideline for the treatment of IDDM and a standard for the
treatment of NIDDM already existed. At the beginning of the 90s and
based on requests by a board of experts (Sachverständigenrat für
die konzertierte Aktion im Gesundheitswesen) this progress was
handed to German scientific-medical research institutes (AWMF) to
develop medical guidelines. Since then, the AWMFs have already
published several hundred guidelines. Due to the diverse quality of the
established AWMF guidelines, the Federal Medical Association
(Bundesärztekammer) and the Federal Association of Statutory
Health Insurance Physicians (Kassenärztliche Bundesvereinigung)
founded the Centre for Quality Assurance (Ärztliche Zentralstelle
Qualitätssicherung) in the mid 90s to ensure the quality of medical
guidelines (Ärztliche Zentralstelle Qualitätssicherung 1998). This
health-political development resulted in an increasing interest by
German physicians in assuring quality care (see also Hellbrück 1997 for
additional information concerning quality assurance from an eco-
nomic point of view).
5. On the initiative of the Federal Association of Health Insurance
Funds AOK (AOK-BV) the Medical Advisory Council on Diabetes
(Wissenschaftsrat Diabetes) was founded. However, a National
Association of Health Insurance Funds may not become active
without legal permission. According to §217 SGB V 2000, a National
Association of Health Insurance Funds has to fulfil its legal tasks. The
legislator firmly determined in §73, 1c SGB V 1993 that the content and
extent of the medical care of family doctors is to be defined by the
Federal Associations of Health Insurance Funds and the Federal
Association of Statutory Health Insurance Physicians. This was the
basis for the Federal Association of Health Insurance Funds AOK for
defining family doctors’ competencies. This paragraph was not only
Emergence and diffusion of disastrous innovations 283
used as an acting base but also as an essential impulse for the foundation
of the Medical Advisory Council on Diabetes whereby the Federal
Association of Statutory Health Insurance Physicians became, contro-
versially to the legal order, not directly involved.
To found the Medical Advisory Council on Diabetes, some prepara-
tory work started in 1996. Representatives of self-help groups, the pres-
ident and additional representatives of the German Diabetes Society,
the president of the Scientific Society of Family Doctors, representa-
tives of Associations of Statutory Health Insurance Physicians, repre-
sentatives of hospitals and family doctors and diabetes experts, and
representatives of the AOK formed the Medical Advisory Council on
Diabetes. Other health insurance companies were not represented.
With this composition it is still active today, i.e. the organisations men-
tioned send further representatives, however it came to personnel
changes. In January 1997 the Advisory Council on Diabetes began with
the definition of the treatment corridors. The definition of the treat-
ment corridors, which first included the family doctors and diabetic
specialists and which were expanded to the the in-patient sector in
1999, were based on insights of EbM.
6. Without the large stake of the persons involved, the development and
diffusion of the diabetes contracts of the second generation would not
have been possible. In the AOK there were personalities who, due to
personal concern, made the improvement of diabetes care their task.
As diabetes is present in virtually every family, the same incentive may
be present in other organisations too. For many years a representative
of a Health Insurance Fund AOK strove for the improvement of dia-
betes care. For training a representative of the Federal Association of
Health Insurance Funds AOK was sent into the Health Insurance
Fund AOK and made subordinate to the representative mentioned.
Both representatives laid claim to ‘copyright’ in the diabetes agree-
ments of the second generation. From this co-operation and/or from
co-operation of the Federal Association of Health Insurance Funds
AOK with representatives of the Eastern Health Insurance Funds
AOK, the philosophy of the second-generation diabetes contracts was
developed. Hesse’s (1990) idea according to which the emergence of
knowledge passes several selection stages, thus approaches reality.
7. Within the Federal Association of Health Insurance Funds AOK the
diabetes contracts were disputed. The department manager responsible
refused the conclusion of the diabetes contracts of the second-
generation, however without success. How is this to be explained? The
governing board of the Federal Association of Health Insurance
Funds AOK (Verwaltungsrat des AOK Bundesverbandes) had taken
284 The political economy of complexity
DIFFUSION
hidden. In the Medical Advisory Council on Diabetes there were beside sci-
entists and representatives of the AOK also representatives of the Regional
Associations of Statutory Health Insurance Physicians, who were the only
contracting parties of health insurance funds at that time in out-patient
treatment. Furthermore, representatives of family doctors were on the
Medical Advisory Council on Diabetes, and they had expressed a great
interest in a demarcation of the family doctors from medical specialists.
On what legal basis were diabetes agreements concluded? A playing field
was opened to the health insurance funds by allowing model projects
in order to accomplish such projects or to conclude contracts with
Associations of Statutory Health Insurance Physicians for supplying
benefits, for example prevention programmes, which were not statutory
benefits (§63, 2 SGB V 1997). Diabetes contracts of the second generation
were usually concluded on this legal basis. There were two reasons for this:
(1) the financing risks of the health insurance funds were limited to eight
years by law (this rule based on the GKV-NOG2 in 1997); (2) additionally,
without extra budgeting payments, the conclusion of diabetes contracts
would not have been possible and §63 SGB V (1997) created this very pos-
sibility.
Nevertheless contribution-rate stability was to be considered. This
meant that health insurance funds and Regional Associations of Statutory
Health Insurance Physicians had to shape their agreements about remu-
neration in such a way that a rise of the contribution rate was usually
excluded. If necessary medical supply was not possible even after ‘exhaus-
tion of economic reserves’, increasing contribution rates were however
allowed. The reason for this rule was increasing contribution rates in the
past (i.e. before 1997) which, as regards the policy, were sometimes dammed
up by drastic means (for example by the strict budgeting of the in-patient
sector by the Health Structure Law (Tuschen and Quaas 1995).
Contribution-rate stability was however not violated, if there were ‘add-
itional expenses caused by a model project being balanced by savings due
to that model project. This balance has to be proven’ (§63, 3 sentence 2 SGB
V 1997). This formulation permits two interpretations: (a) increasing
expenses and savings temporarily fallen apart or (b) increasing expenses
and savings taking place at the same time. Since the primary reason for the
diabetes contracts was to avoid subsequent diseases, it was to be assumed
that additional expenses result today and possible savings arise tomorrow.
The conclusion of contracts based on §§63–65 SGB V 1997 with extra
budgeting payments would not have been possible with a strict interpret-
ation of the legal basis. The contracting parties (in particular the health
insurance funds) had despite the possibility of the cancellation of regula-
tions laid down in Chapter 4 SGB V 1997 to consider contribution-rate
Emergence and diffusion of disastrous innovations 287
stability. But the formulation in §63, 3 sentence 2 SGB V 1997 left open
whether savings have to be proven ex post or ex ante. In the diabetes con-
tracts extra budgeting payments were agreed upon that were to be disbursed
during the run-time of the model projects. Thus the financing risk of the dia-
betes contracts had to be borne by the contracting health insurance funds.
On the other hand, to convince their member physicians, the Associations
of Statutory Health Insurance Physicians had to insist on extra budgeting
payments, otherwise the conclusion of second-generation diabetes contracts
would have not been possible. As in 1998 health insurance funds could only
conclude diabetes contracts with Associations of Statutory HealthInsurance
Physicians on the basis of §§63–65 and 73a SGB V (1997), extra budgeting
payments were inevitable for the conclusion of diabetes contracts. Though
§64, 2 SGB V 1997 permitted the conclusion of model projects between
health insurance funds and contract physicians (i.e. physicians allowed to
treat insurants of health insurance funds) without participation of of the
Associations of Statutory Health Insurance Physicians (the so-called quorum
regulation), the condition for this was the definition of the principles for exe-
cuting model projects between Federal Associations of Statutory Health
Insurance Funds and the Federal Association of Statutory Health Insurance
Physicians (§64, 2 sentence 1 SGB V 1997) which was never realised.
Why, however, were diabetes contracts concluded at all although the
financing risk was borne exclusively by the contracting health insurance
funds? It was referred to the large amount of diabetic persons (5 to 6 million
are diagnosed in Germany) and the associated treatment costs as well as
on the associated savings potentials (Mehl, Becker-Berke und Müller-
de-Cornejo 2000, p. 5 and Ahrens 1997). As early as in November 1997,
before the negotiations of the AOK for diabetes contracts in Thuringia
were finished, the chairman of the managing committee of the Federal
Association of Health Insurance Funds AOK did not leave any doubt
during a public event that the AOK would conclude diabetes contracts of
the second-generation (Ahrens 1997, p. 51).
Were the diabetes contracts of the second generation disastrous at all if
evaluated from the viewpoint of the Health Insurance Funds as announced
in the heading of this contribution? The answer to this question is simplified
by defining the term ‘disastrous’. Disastrous innovations are in our context
business-damaging. Being business-damaging has two dimensions: on the
one hand the competition of health insurance funds into private health
insurance companies and on the other hand the competition within the
group of health insurance funds are affected. A health insurance fund
behaves in a business-damaging way, if its competition position worsens
compared to other health insurance funds or to private health insurance
companies.
288 The political economy of complexity
CONTINUATION
At the end there is still the question, why diabetes contracts were not can-
celled by health insurance funds as the negative effects were identified. The
answer to that question cannot be given with complete certainty. It is pos-
sible that the harm to the companies hasn’t been recognised. Against this
interpretation is the fact, that within the Federal Association of Health
Insurance Funds AOK and BEK criticism arose, which included the effects
of diabetes contracts on competition.
The following interpretation is more likely. The Regional Associations of
Statutory Health Insurance Physicians were, without any doubts, interested
in continuing these contracts. If a diabetes contract had been cancelled by the
Health Insurance Funds, a public éclat initiated by the Regional Associations
of Statutory Health Insurance Physicians would certainly have happened.
Additionally, the personal interests of the decision makers were not nega-
tively affected, and/or the harm to the business was evaluated as too small.
This point of view is supported by the fact that the first AOK diabetes
contract of the second generation in Thuringia was over on 31 March
2001. An ensuing contract is being negotiated and till its conclusion the
existing contract will be used. Another fact is that diabetes contracts of
the second generation in general replaced diabetes contracts of the first
generation. It looks as though existing extra-budgeting payments paid for
290 The political economy of complexity
CONCLUSIONS
Altogether we can say, firstly, that the knowledge increase was not sufficient
for the innovation (thesis (b)). Secondly, the changing legal conditions in
the Statutory Health Insurance Reorganisation laws in 1997 cannot be
regarded as the cause either for the emergence or the diffusion of the
second-generation diabetes contracts as these changes were after the first
developments of the second-generation diabetes contracts. On the contrary
292 The political economy of complexity
NOTES
1. I would like to thank Frank Engelmann for his helpful comments. The first translation of
the German original (Hellbrück 2003) was made by some busy students: Christian Haas,
Patricia Wlodarczak, Dirk Enskat, and Ina Wunderlich; nevertheless, I am responsible for
Emergence and diffusion of disastrous innovations 293
the remaining errors. This work reflects solely the opinion of the author. The chapter
relates to the developments up to May 2001.
2. Statement of Albrecht Dietz, a ‘Schumpeter’ entrepreneur.
3. ‘GKV’ is the abbreviation for statutory health insurance.
4. In Germany we distinguish various types of health insurance funds (§§143–171
SGB V 1997): Allgemeine Ortskrankenkassen (AOK), Betriebskrankenkassen
(BKK), Innungskrankenkassen (IKK), See-Krankenkassen, Landwirtschaftliche Kran-
kenkassen, Bundesknappschaft, Ersatzkassen. Each health insurance fund is a member
of exactly one type which is determined by law.
5. The date given shows the time of the publication in the federal law paper. In most
cases, the day of publication and the date of introduction and enforcement are not the
same.
6. Benefits in kind are one principle of the German statutory health system. Everybody
should pay according to his abilities and everybody should get equal access to the health
care system and equal health care. To accomplish this, benefits in kind are seen as funda-
mental; reimbursements would break the principle as healthier people would not pay
anymore according to their abilities.
REFERENCES
Adler, A., I. Stratton, H. Neil and J. Yudkin (2000), ‘Association of systolic blood
pressure with macrovascular and microvascular complications of type 2 diabetes
(UKPDS 36): prospective observational study’, British Medical Journal, 321,
412–19.
Ahrens, H.J. (1997), ‘Ökonomische Anreizsysteme – Herausforderungen und
Chancen’, in AOK-Bundesverband (ed.), AOK im Dialog; Qualität und
Wirtschaftlichkeit – Neue Wege gemeinsamer Verantwortung, Bonn, pp. 49–54.
Ahrens, H.J. (2001), Pressekonferenz zu AOK im Dialog ‘Weiterentwicklung des
Risikostrukturausgleichs’, Berlin, 15 March 2001, AOK-Bundesverband.
Andersen, H. and J. Schwarze (1999), ‘Kassenwahlentscheidungen in der GKV’,
Arbeit und Sozialpolitik, 53, 10–23.
Ärzte-Zeitung (15 September, 1998): ‘Endlich Klarheit für die Behandlung von
Typ-II-Diabetikern in der Praxis’.
Ärztliche Zentralstelle Qualitätssicherung (1998), ‘Checkliste “Methodische
Qualität von Leitlininen” 1. Version: Gültigkeit: 1.2.1998–31.1.1999’, Deutsches
Ärzteblatt, 95, B-2014-B-20116.
Becker, J. (1999), ‘Drei-Klassen-Medizin darf es nicht geben’, Gesundheit und
Gesellschaft, 2, 44–5.
Bertram, B. (1999), ‘Zusammenarbeit von Hausarzt und Augenarzt in der
Diabetikerbetreuung. Kommunikation unerläßlich’, Deutsches Ärzteblatt, 96,
B-2450-B-2454.
Bundesministerium für Gesundheit (2000), ‘Begründung zum Entwurf eines
“Gesetzes zur Strukturreform der gesetzlichen Krankenversicherung” im Jahr
2000’.
Hellbrück, R.P. (1997), Qualität und Ausgaben in der medizinischen Versorgung – Von
Qualitätssicherung und Kosteneffizienz zu mehr Wettbewerb im Gesundheitswesen?,
Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.
Hellbrück, R.P. (2000), ‘EDV-gestütztes Qualitätsmanagement in Praxisnetzen’,
Das Gesundheitswesen, 62, 511–15.
Hellbrück, R.P. (2003), ‘Entstehung und Ausbreitung geschäftsschädigender
294 The political economy of complexity
1. INTRODUCTION
296
Applying evolutionary economics to public policy 297
1. There can be no doubt that the large efforts of the EU to complete the
European internal market by breaking up many barriers to national
markets and to introduce competition in many industries, which for
decades were monopolized in the member states (as e.g. telecommuni-
cation and energy markets), were a huge success. In that respect the poli-
cies of the European Commission (internal-market programme) and
also the European Court of Justice (‘Cassis de Dijon’ judgment) to
enforce the four basic freedoms (freedom of goods, services, labour, and
capital) by removing national non-tariff barriers to trade were very
helpful. This was carried out partly by introducing the principle of
mutual recognition of national regulations and partly by (minimum)
harmonization of regulations. To some degree also European Monetary
Union with the introduction of the Euro as single currency can be
seen in this perspective of promoting the European internal market.
Consequently, many efforts on the EU level that simultaneously implied
a pushing back of the competencies of the member states, were impor-
tant for enforcing competition of European markets.
2. But the observed tendencies to centralization in the EU are also evalu-
ated very critically both by European citizens and politicians on one
hand and by economists and legal scholars on the other. Increasing
dangers of intransparency and lack of monitoring by the citizens,
bureaucratization, and mounting rent-seeking problems are suggested
(Vaubel 1995, 1997). There are widespread preferences in the European
population for a high degree of decentralization that limit considerably
the acceptance of additional shiftings of competencies to the Euro-
pean level. The increasing heterogeneity within the EU – due to the
enlargement by mostly much less developed Middle and East
European countries – will reinforce this problem. So the introduction
of the principle of subsidiarity in the Treaty of Maastricht can be seen
as an important political sign against too quick and often too
unreflective tendencies of centralization and harmonization in the EU.
But the problem of the best vertical allocation of competencies between the
EU and the member states is still unsolved. How is it possible to maintain
a high degree of decentralization and heterogeneity within the EU without
impeding the achievement of the aim of European integration? This has
remained an open question both in public and academic discussions.
Applying evolutionary economics to public policy 299
on public goods and taxation. Implicitly it was assumed that the legal
framework was the task of the central (national) level. But within the
EU it has become a crucial question, to what extent legal rules and
regulations have to be centralized/harmonized or can also remain on a
more decentralized level. This also raises the problem of the extent and
effects of processes of regulatory competition.
upon Paretian welfare theory. The dominant criteria for the vertical allo-
cation of competencies, regional scope of the utility of public goods
(spillover effects/externalities), economies of scale-effects and the extent of
regional homogeneity/heterogeneity of preferences, can be consistently
deduced from the neoclassical theories of public goods and taxation – as
well as the dominant aim of efficient allocation follows from Paretian
welfare theory. The same is true for most approaches to interjurisdictional
and regulatory competition. Tiebout’s model of the competitive provision
of local public goods was the exact transfer of the model of perfect com-
petition to the market for local public goods.5 Most of the theoretical dis-
cussion about interjurisdictional competition (and, particularly, tax
competition) as well as regulatory competition are such welfare-theoretic
neoclassical analyses. This implies that the outcome of interjurisdictional
and regulatory competition is compared with the perfect theoretical
solution of allocative efficiency. And according to market-failure theory,
any allocative inefficiency and therefore any deviation from the optimal
outcome of the perfect competition model leads to the diagnosis of a
failure of interjurisdictional or regulatory competition. Thus it seems to be
the obvious conclusion that interjurisdictional (or regulatory) competition,
and therefore also competitive federalism, is no viable approach, leading to
the policy recommendations of the centralization of competencies or the
harmonization of regulations.
One kind of fundamental critique to this neoclassical market-failure
argumentation is the well-known critique of Demsetz (1969), comparing
situations in the real world with the fictitious approach of the model of
perfect competition (‘nirvana approach’). This method leads to the diag-
nosis of ubiquitous market failure and therefore the suggestion of ubiqui-
tous state intervention or the entire abolishment of competition. Rather, a
more differentiated methodological approach along the lines of Demsetz’s
concept of ‘comparative institutional analysis’ seems to be appropriate:
his classical standard book Fiscal Federalism (Oates 1972), although he did
not integrate this effect into his consequently elaborated welfare-theoretic
neoclassical approach to federalism. The same is true for other new contri-
butions to federalism as, for example, Breton’s Competitive Governments
(1996, p. 233), who, for example, used the external benchmark mechanism of
Salmon (1987), which goes back to the theory of rank-order tournaments
and is linked to the concept of yardstick competition.14 Thus the importance
of the innovation dimension of public policies and its reference to federalism
is increasingly emphasized in economic theories of federalism.
Oates (1999) took the opportunity in his comprehensive survey article on
fiscal federalism in the Journal of Economic Literature to stress the advan-
tages of experimentation in decentralized federal systems and claims the
necessity of an entire research programme for the study of innovation and
imitation processes of public policies in federal systems. After the diagno-
sis of the problem of imperfect knowledge about appropriate public pol-
icies, he develops the perspective of federalism as ‘laboratory federalism’.
‘In a setting of imperfect information with learning-by-doing there are
potential gains from experimentation with a variety of policies for address-
ing social and economic problems. And a federal system may offer some
real opportunities for encouraging such experimentation and thereby pro-
moting “technical progress” in public policy’ (Oates 1999, 1132).
It is particularly remarkable that Oates, who in the first part of his survey
article argues consistently within a neoclassical welfare-theoretic frame-
work, assesses the advantages of decentralized experimentation in some
cases as so large that they can dominate neoclassical arguments for cen-
tralization. As an example, he uses redistribution policy. First, he repeats
the neoclassical argument of traditional federalism theory that redistribu-
tion policies, aiming to help the poor, should be allocated to the central
level, because in the case of decentralized redistribution policies a ‘race to
the bottom’ problem should be expected due to the mobility of the rich and
poor between lower-level jurisdictions, leading to an inefficient low level of
redistribution. Although Oates does not deny this argument, he is in favour
of a decentralized redistribution policy (Oates 1999, 1131), because he esti-
mates the advantages of decentralized experimentation with different redis-
tribution policies as so high that they overcompensate potential negative
effects of ‘race to the bottom’ problems.
But these implicitly evolutionary arguments have been developed
without an explicit reference to the established literature on evolutionary
economics. Oates neither uses Hayek as a reference for the knowledge prob-
lems he wants to alleviate by his ‘laboratory federalism’ nor does he apply
an evolutionary concept of interjurisdictional competition, which he could
have used for integrating experimentation and innovation, imitation
310 The political economy of complexity
within the EU, the question increasingly arises whether legal rules should
be harmonized with the long-term perspective of a uniform European law
or whether there also might be advantages from the diversity of legal rules.
In this discussion on uniformity vs diversity of law, legal scholars also devel-
oped the argument that a decentralized legal system, which allows for
variety and experimentation with new legal rules, can have considerable
advantages in comparison to an entirely centralized, uniform legal system.17
Also, in regard to legal rules – as institutional solutions for solving transac-
tion and cooperation problems – it cannot be assumed that the best legal
solutions have already been found. And from an evolutionary perspective,
a permanent stream of new problems emerge, which require a high adapt-
ability of the legal system. Consequently, searching for legal innovations is
necessary. Therefore a decentralized legal system (legal federalism), in
which parallel processes of experimentation with legal innovations, mutual
learning and a quick correction of inappropriate legal solutions are pos-
sible, might be much more innovative in the long run than a centralized legal
system. This can be true, in particular, if it also allows for competition
among legal rules (regulatory competition).
One famous example of regulatory competition was already mentioned
in section 3 – competition among corporate laws in the US.18 The federal
states have the competence in corporate law in the US. Since within the US,
the so-called ‘incorporation theory’ determines that the federal states
mutually each accept the corporate law of the others, firms have the choice
to incorporate in any of the federal states without having any restrictions
in regard to their location within the US. So firms can choose freely
between the corporate laws of 50 federal states. This situation has led to an
intensive regulatory competition between the corporate laws of the federal
states, which it has been possible to observe for decades. The incentives of
the states are ‘franchise taxes’, which incorporated firms have to pay.19 In
the US, there have been many studies of this regulatory competition among
corporate laws, focusing on the question whether it has led to a negative
‘race to the bottom’ or to a positive ‘race to the top’. Although there are
adherents of both claims, nowadays most scholars hold the opinion that
the positive effects prevail. Particularly interesting is that this regulatory
competition can be primarily described as a dynamic process of innovation
and imitation of new legal rules leading to a step-by-step improvement of
the corporate laws. Therefore in this special discussion about the evolution
of US corporate laws, evolutionary arguments from innovation economics
were applied to regulatory competition. These arguments encompassed
the advantages of experimentation with different legal rules, but also
Schumpeterian argumentation patterns on dynamic processes of innova-
tion and imitation, path-dependency argumentations due to critical-mass
312 The political economy of complexity
There is a large uncertainty about the final state of the European Union,
after the process of European integration is finished. The danger is that the
Applying evolutionary economics to public policy 315
traditional idea of the nation state, in which nearly all kind of economic
policies are ‘naturally’ allocated to the central (i.e. national) level, will be
simply transferred to the EU, implying that the EU is seen as a new ‘nation
state’ in the traditional sense. From this perspective, it seems evident that in
the long run the central European level should have the same competencies
for public policies as the traditional nation states had in the past. This
would lead to a much stronger centralization of competencies and harmon-
ization than it is being discussed now. Within the European Union not
much scope would remain either for decentralization or variety. It can be
suggested that this is also a consequence of the lack of alternative concepts
of European integration that do not equate European integration with uni-
formity and harmonization.
The concept of competitive federalism is an alternative concept for
European integration that aims at the development of an institutional
structure for a federal multilevel system of jurisdictions in Europe, which
attempts to combine integration with decentralization and the potential for
maintaining variety.23 If we understand integration – in the tradition of the
judgment of the European Court of Justice – as the removal of barriers to
the mobility of individuals, firms, goods, services and production factors
(‘basic freedoms’) within the EU, and want to pursue the aim of as much
decentralization as possible (principle of subsidiarity), then both aims can
only be attained simultaneously within a multilevel system of jurisdictions
that is based upon the concept of competitive federalism (Kerber 2000b).
The crucial contribution of evolutionary economics to this reasoning is
that evolutionary arguments about the necessity, mechanisms and deter-
minants of innovation processes in regard to the provision of public goods
and regulations are very important for the elaboration of the long-term
advantages of a higher degree of decentralization within the EU – in com-
parison to purely neoclassical arguments.
It is not possible here to elaborate on specific argumentations and draw
conclusions about the appropriate vertical allocation of competencies in
the EU from this perspective. But a few general implications can be briefly
sketched:
NOTES
1. See, e.g., Koch (1996), Wegner (1996, 1997), Slembeck (1997), Meier and Slembeck
(1998), Witt (2003), and the contributions in Pelikan and Wegner (2003).
2. See Oates (1972, 1999) and Breton (1996).
3. See, e.g., Oates and Schwab (1988), Siebert and Koop (1990), Sinn (1990, 1997, 2003),
Kenyon and Kincaid (1991), Sinn (1992), Vanberg and Kerber (1994), Frey and
Eichenberger (1995), Streit and Mussler (1995), Sun and Pelkmans (1995), Bratton and
McCahery (1997), Kerber (1998, 2000b), Streit and Wohlgemuth (1999), Feld (2000),
Kollman, Miller and Page (2000), Van den Bergh (2000), Wellisch (2000), Esty and
Geradin (2001), Besley and Coate (2003).
4. See, in particular, Siebert and Koop (1990), Hauser and Hösli (1991), Woolcock (1994),
Sun and Pelkmans (1995), Streit and Mussler (1995), Sinn (1997), Gatsios and Holmes
(1998), Kerber (2000b), Van den Bergh (2000), Esty and Geradin (2001), Heine and
Kerber (2002), Kerber and Budzinski (2003), Marciano and Josselin (2003).
5. The assumptions of Tiebout’s model are nearly identical to the assumptions of the
perfect competition model, e.g. in regard to the homogeneity of public goods and juris-
dictions, perfect market transparency, and atomistic structure of the jurisdictions.
6. See, e.g., Brennan and Buchanan (1980), Besley and Coate (2003), and Wilson and
Wildasin (2004).
7. See Hayek (1945, 1978, 1996) and Wegner (1996).
8. As examples for arguments from political science, see Inman and Rubinfield (1997) and
Weingast (1995).
9. See, e.g., Vihanto (1992), Vanberg and Kerber (1994), Frey and Eichenberger (1995),
Streit (1996), Kerber (1998, 2000a), Streit and Wohlgemuth (1999), Heine and Kerber
(2002), Wohlgemuth (2002); for a comparison of neoclassical and evolutionary
approaches to systems competition, see Windisch (1998). For an integrated evolutionary
concept of competition, which encompasses both Schumpeterian and Hayekian argu-
ments, see Kerber (1997).
10. These considerations are also directly linked to the general Hayekian approach of cul-
tural evolution, which suggests that a process of variation and selection of rules might
lead to the development of superior rules and institutions (Hayek 1973; Vanberg 1992).
11. For the following, see in more detail Kerber (1998, 2000a); for the general advantages of
experimentalism from the perspective of economic policy, see also Okruch (2003).
Applying evolutionary economics to public policy 319
12. Please note that sequential experimentation processes, in which particular policies are
implemented, and after evaluation maintained or modified, are possible also on the
central level. The advantage of decentralised competencies is that here parallel experi-
mentation processes and simultaneous mutual learning are possible, which can be
expected to lead to a much faster growth of knowledge.
13. See, e.g., Besley and Case (1995), Bodenstein and Ursprung (2005) and for a short
overview Schnellenbach (2004); the basic ideas go back to Salmon (1987).
14. It would be worthwhile to analyse the widespread concept of yardstick competition in
regard to its implicit evolutionary character, which cannot be done here.
15. See for this mainly empirical political science literature on the diffusion of policy inno-
vations, e.g., Walker (1969), Gray (1973, 1994), Canon and Baum (1981), Berry and
Berry (1991), Berry (1994), Nice (1994), Rogers (1995), Sparer and Brown (1996),
Mintrom (1997), and Clark (2000).
16. See in more detail Rose-Ackerman (1980), Mukand and Rodrik (2002), Strumpf (2002).
17. See, e.g., Kötz (1986, p. 9), Behrens (1986, p. 26), Parisi and Ribstein (1998, p. 238); for
advantages of experimentation in regulatory competition, see Streit and Mussler (1995),
Ogus (1999), Kerber (2000a), Van den Bergh (2000), Kerber and Budzinski (2003); from
a more critical perspective, see Kieninger (2002). The basic ideas of ‘laboratory federal-
ism’ stem from early legal scholars in the US (see Oates 1999, p. 1132).
18. See, e.g., Romano (1985, 1998), Bebchuk (1992), and Easterbrook and Fischel (1996).
19. See Romano (1985). Delaware, for example, which is the market leader in this market for
corporate law, is financing a considerable part of its budget by this franchise tax.
20. Recently, this US debate on the effects of regulatory competition between corporate laws
has become relevant in regard to the EU. The so-called ‘Centros’ decision of the
European Court of Justice of 1999 has triggered off an intensive discussion among legal
scholars, of whether the ‘Incorporation theory’ should also be implemented within the
EU. Contrary to the present situation, this would imply the mutual recognition of cor-
porate laws and open up the long-term perspective that in the future firms in Europe
might choose also freely between the corporate laws of different European countries
leading to regulatory competition among the corporate laws of the member states of the
EU (Wouters 2000, Heine and Kerber 2002). For an analysis of the workability of this
regulatory competition in regard to potential path dependencies see Heine and Kerber
(2002), who apply explicitly evolutionary concepts of innovation economics (technolog-
ical paradigms of Dosi) to legal evolution and regulatory competition.
21. For preliminary catalogues of criteria for the vertical allocation of competencies in
regard to regulations, see Grundmann and Kerber (2002), Kerber and Heine (2002), Van
den Bergh (2002) and Kerber and Grundmann (2006).
22. See, for example, Grundmann and Kerber (2002) for an application on the problem of
centralization and decentralization of contract law in the EU, Van den Bergh and
Camesasca (2001, pp. 125–65) and Kerber (2003b) in regard to competition law, and
Heine and Kerber (2002) and Heine (2003) in regard to corporate law.
23. For attempts to apply competitive federalism to the EU, see e.g. Kirchner (1998), Frey
and Eichenberger (1999), and Kerber (2000b, 2003a).
24. For a plea for a more pragmatic view of economic policy (with explicit reference to
Dewey and additional literature), see Okruch (2003).
REFERENCES
Bebchuk, L.A. (1992), ‘Federalism and the corporation: the desirable limits on state
competition in corporate law’, Columbia Law Review, 105, 1435–510.
Behrens, P. (1986), ‘Voraussetzungen und Grenzen der Rechtsfortbildung durch
Rechtsvereinheitlichung’, Rabels Zeitschrift für ausländisches und internationales
Privatrecht, 50, 19–34.
320 The political economy of complexity
Berry, F.S. (1994), ‘Sizing up state policy innovation research’, Policy Studies
Journal, 22, 442–56.
Berry, F.S. and W.D. Berry (1991), ‘Specifying a model of state policy innovations’,
American Political Science Review, 85, 573–9.
Besley, T. and A. Case (1995), ‘Incumbent behavior, tax-setting, and yardstick com-
petition’, American Economic Review, 85, 25–45.
Besley, T. and S. Coate (2003), ‘Centralized versus decentralized provision of local
public goods: a political economy analysis’, Journal of Public Economics, 87,
2611–37.
Bodenstein, M. and H.W. Ursprung (2005), ‘Political yardstick competition, eco-
nomic integration, and constitutional choice in a federation’, Public Choice
(forthcoming).
Bratton, W.W. and J.A. McCahery (1997), ‘The new economics of jurisdictional
competition: devolutionary federalism in a second-best world’, The Georgetown
Law Journal, 86, 201–78.
Brennan, G. and J.M. Buchanan (1980), The Power to Tax: Analytical Foundations
of a Fiscal Constitution, Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Breton, A. (1996), Competitive Governments: An Economic Theory of Politics and
Public Finance, Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.
Canon, B.C. and L. Baum (1981), ‘Patterns of adoption of tort law innovations: an
application of diffusion theory to judicial doctrines’, American Political Science
Review, 79, 178–94.
Clark, J. (2000), ‘Policy attributes and state policy innovation’, Southeastern
Political Review, 28, 3–25.
Demsetz, H. (1969), ‘Information and efficiency: another viewpoint’, Journal of
Law and Economics, 12, 1–22.
Dowding, K., P. John and S. Biggs (1994), ‘Tiebout: “A Survey of the Empirical
Literature” ’, Urban Studies, 31, 767–97.
Easterbrook, F.H. and D.R. Fischel (1996), The Economic Structure of Corporate
Law, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Esty, D.C. and D. Geradin (eds) (2001), Regulatory competition and Economic
Integration: Comparative perspectives, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Eucken, W. (1952), Grundsätze der Wirtschaftspolitik, Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.
Feld, L. (2000), Steuerwettbewerb und seine Auswirkungen auf Allokation und
Distribution:Eine empirische Analyse für die Schweiz, Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.
Frey, B.S. and R. Eichenberger (1995), ‘Competition Among Jurisdictions: The
Idea of FOCJ’, in L. Gerken (ed.), Competition Among Institutions, Basingstoke
and London: Macmillan, pp. 209–29.
Frey, B.S. and R. Eichenberger (1999), The New Democratic Federalism for Europe,
Cheltenham, UK and Northampton, MA, USA: Edward Elgar.
Gatsios, K. and P. Holmes (1998), ‘Regulatory Competition’, in P. Newman (ed.),
The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law, vol. 3, London and
Basingstoke: Macmillan, pp. 271–5.
Gray, V. (1973), ‘Innovation in the states: a diffusion study’, American Political
Science Review, 67, 1174–85.
Gray, V. (1994), ‘Competition, emulation, and policy innovation’, in L.C. Dodd and
J. Calvon (eds), New Perspectives on American Politics, Washington, DC: CQ
Press, pp. 230–48.
Grundmann, S. and W. Kerber (2002), ‘European system of contract laws. A map
for combining the advantages of centralised and decentralised rule-making’, in
Applying evolutionary economics to public policy 321
New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law, vol. 1, London and
Basingstoke: Macmillan, pp. 364–70.
Röpke, J. (1977), Die Strategie der Innovation, Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.
Rose-Ackerman, S. (1980), ‘Risk taking and reelection: does federalism promote
innovation?’, Journal of Legal Studies, 9, 593–616.
Salmon, P. (1987), ‘Decentralisation as an incentive scheme’, Oxford Review of
Economic Policy, 3, 24–42.
Schnellenbach, J. (2004), Dezentrale Finanzpolitik und Modellunsicherheit: Eine the-
oretische Untersuchung zur Rolle des fiskalischen Wettbewerbs als Wissen gener-
ierender Prozess, Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.
Siebert, H. and M.J. Koop (1990), ‘Institutional competition. A concept for
Europe?’, Aussenwirtschaft, 45, 439–62.
Sinn, H.-W. (1990), ‘The limits to competition between economic regimes’,
Empirica – Austrian Economic Papers, 17, 3–14.
Sinn, H.-W. (1997), ‘The selection principle and market failure in systems competi-
tion’, Journal of Public Economics, 88, 247–74.
Sinn, H.-W. (2003), The New Systems Competition, Malden, MA: Blackwell.
Sinn, S. (1992), ‘The taming of Leviathan: competition among governments’,
Constitutional Political Economy, 2, 177–96.
Slembeck, T. (1997), ‘The formation of economic policy: a cognitive-evolutionary
approach to policy-making’, Constitutional Political Economy, 8 (3), 225–54.
Sparer, M.S. and L.D. Brown (1996), ‘States and the health care crisis: the limits and
lessons of laboratory federalism’, in R.F. Rich and W.D. White (eds), Health
Policy, Federalism, and the American States, Washington, DC: Urban Institute
Press, pp. 181–202.
Streit, M.E. (1996), ‘Systemwettbewerb im europäischen Integrationsprozess’, in
U. Immenga, W. Möschel and D. Reuter (eds), Festschrift für Ernst-Joachim
Mestmäcker: zum siebzigsten Geburtstag, Baden-Baden: Nomos, pp. 512–35.
Streit, M.E. and W. Mussler (1995), ‘Wettbewerb der Systeme und das Binnenmarkt
programm der Europäischen Union’, in L. Gerken (ed.), Europa zwischen
Ordnungswettbewerb und Harmonisierung, Berlin: Springer, pp. 75–107.
Streit, M.E. and M. Wohlgemuth (eds) (1999), Systemwettbewerb als Heraus-
forderung an Politik und Theorie, Baden-Baden: Nomos.
Strumpf, K.S. (2002), ‘Does government decentralization increase policy innova-
tion?’, Journal of Public Economic Theory, 4, 207–41.
Sun, J.-M. and J.J. Pelkmans (1995), ‘Regulatory competition in the single market’,
Journal of Common Market Studies, 33, 67–89.
Tiebout, C.M. (1956), ‘A pure theory of local expenditures’, Journal of Political
Economy, 64, 416–24.
Vanberg, V. (1992), ‘Innovation, Cultural Evolution, and Economic Growth’, in U.
Witt (ed.), Explaining Process and Change. Approaches to Evolutionary
Economics, Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan Press, pp. 105–21.
Vanberg, V. and W. Kerber (1994), ‘Institutional competition among jurisdictions:
an evolutionary approach’, Constitutional Political Economy, 5, 193–219.
Van den Bergh, R. (2000), ‘Towards an institutional legal framework for regulatory
competition in Europe’, Kyklos, 53, 435–66.
Van den Bergh, R. (2002), ‘Forced harmonization of contract law in Europe: com-
munication from the Commission on European Contract Law’, in S. Grundmann
and J. Stuyck (eds), An Academic Greenpaper on European Contract Law, The
Hague, London, New York: Kluwer Law International, pp. 249–68.
324 The political economy of complexity
Van den Bergh, R.J. and P.D. Camesasca (2001), European Competition Law and
Economics: A Comparative Perspective, Antwerp: Intersentia.
Vaubel, R. (1995), The Centralisation of Western Europe: The Common Market,
Political Integration, and Democracy, London: Institute of Economic Affairs.
Vaubel, R. (1997), ‘The constitutional reform of the European Union’, Consti-
tutional Political Economy, 7, 317–24.
Vihanto, M. (1992), ‘Competition between local governments as a discovery proce-
dure’, Journal of Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 148, 411–36.
Walker, J.L. (1969), ‘The diffusion of innovation among the American states’,
American Political Science Review, 63, 880–99.
Wegner, G. (1996), Wirtschaftspolitik zwischen Selbst- und Fremdsteuerung – Ein
neuer Ansatz der Wirtschaftspolitik, Baden-Baden: Nomos.
Wegner, G. (1997), ‘Economic policy from an evolutionary perspective’, Journal of
Institutional and Theoretical Economics, 153, 485–509.
Weingast, B.R. (1995), ‘The economic role of political institutions: market-
preserving federalism and economic development’, Journal of Law, Economics
and Organisation, 11, 1–31.
Wellisch, D. (2000), Theory of Public Finance in a Federal State, Cambridge, MA:
Cambridge University Press.
Wilson, J.D. and D.E. Wildasin (2004), ‘Capital tax competition: bane or boon’,
Journal of Public Economics, 88, 1065–91.
Windisch, R. (1998), ‘Modellierung von Systemwettbewerb: Grundlagen,
Konzepte, Thesen’, Jahrbuch für Neue Politische Ökonomie, 17, 121–54.
Wohlgemuth, M. (2002), ‘Evolutionary approaches to politics’, Kyklos, 55, 223–46.
Woolcock, S. (1994), The Single European Market: Centralization or Competition
Among National Rules?, London: Royal Institute of International Affairs.
Wouters, J. (2000), ‘European company law: Quo Vadis?’, Common Market Law
Review, 37, 257–307.
14. Can evolutionary economics
make a billion $ difference for
60 per cent of the world’s poor
in Asia?
Hans-Peter Brunner*
325
326 The political economy of complexity
Asia, Nepal and the Indian state of West Bengal. This chapter does not
intend to present complete institutional economics and evolutionary math-
ematical models. For those I refer to the literature (for example Allen and
Brunner, 2001; Adams, Brunner and Raymond, 2003; Brunner and Allen,
2005). Rather it is the key institutional and evolutionary concepts that can
lead to novel solutions to empirical issues encountered in development
practice. Concepts are embedded in analytical methods. Method can be
mapped onto an evolutionary spectrum, as I will do in section 4 of the
chapter. The spectrum starts with ‘simple’ neoclassical methods with
restrictive assumptions and extends to ‘complex’ adaptive-learning models.
Even simple methods can help explore key institutional and evolutionary
concepts to act on in practice. For example in the Nepal case, we used a neo-
classical CGE model, which was modified to consider transaction-cost
reductions in the financial sector as the drive for economic change. The
Nepal information-economics issues were then examined from a different
angle with a dynamic game-theoretic model. Finally we progressed along
the evolutionary spectrum with the application of an evolutionary spatial
and non-linear feedback-loop model in the example of West Bengal. This
because the issue we felt required higher complexity of analysis, and fur-
thermore because we had the luxury and money to accumulate the requi-
site quality and quantity of data to test such a model. Models are always,
and to a degree, partial representations of the cloud of reality they depict.
Knowledge is really about knowing what simplifications can be made in
practice without compromising on results. Models should be detailed
enough to capture all the important causal real-world relationships that
explain outcomes of development. Policy actions spring from fruitful
analysis of underlying causes of underdevelopment.
Do evolutionary actions lead to significantly different outcomes from
actions that may have been taken, or not taken, on the basis of, let us say,
neoclassical concepts and empirical approaches in a field of analysis? Two
Asian Development Bank (ADB) investment examples illustrate that,
indeed, evolutionary concepts when embedded appropriately in a variety of
methods, have the power to make a big difference for economic develop-
ment in Asia and in the effectiveness of resource use by the ADB and its
borrowers. Making institutional and evolutionary economic analysis
policy-relevant also means relating different methods and concepts to the
methodological and concept frameworks of decision makers, who are still
largely steeped in neoclassical economics. The West Bengal example shows
how an essentially evolutionary analysis can be related back to traditional,
simple decision models of cost-benefit analysis.
Can evolutionary economics make a difference? 327
Institutional Economics
problem, are high, while most loans are small and short-term. Levine
(1997) offers conditions for formal financial market viability, but in prac-
tice agricultural lending is very commonly non-viable for private-sector
credit institutions. Consequently, the formal credit sector is severely con-
strained in its ability to meet the requirements of rural development, at
least with current institutional arrangements, in-built incentives, and poor
information systems. The common response of governments and inter-
national donors has been to offer subsidised credit, set credit quotas by type
of loan, peg an array of interest rates, and target special groups such as
women or the poor. The outcome has usually been very low or even nega-
tive rates of social return on the one hand, and ultimate insolvency for the
institutions on the other.
What institutional analysis offers, in conjunction with careful measure-
ment of true transaction costs and informational asymmetries, is not only
an understanding of the workings of the informal and formal mechanisms,
but the hope of appropriate institutional design that can improve loan
delivery and recovery from formal agencies.
The system’s institutional and incentive failures are associated with use
of extremely primitive technologies and resistance to the adoption of new
skills and tools, oftentimes out of a misguided sense, shared by manage-
ment and labour, that their jobs are at risk. Nepal’s financial system oper-
ates largely on a manual basis. This leads to costly and cumbersome
procedures as well as poor service delivery. Payment and settlement systems
are not fully computerised and no electronic funds transfers are possible. It
may take up to 30 days to have a cheque cleared if it was issued outside
Kathmandu and as a result, the economy is largely ‘cash and carry’ based.
Moreover, the absence of information technologies in all areas of the finan-
cial sector makes information collection costly and unreliable, and hinders
effective monitoring and supervision. Nepal’s ADBN, for instance, is at
least three years behind in generating credible income statements and
balance sheets.
reform in Nepal will release extra resources for savings and investment.
‘Comprehensive reform’ means mutually reinforcing institutional and
legal developments involving the Ministry of Finance, Central Bank
(Nepal Rastra Bank), the Nepal Stock Exchange, commercial banks,
joint-venture banks, multinational banks, finance companies, and rural
development banks, including the Agricultural Development Bank of
Nepal, co-operatives, and NGOs.
Financial reform has a widespread effect on informal credit markets in the
rural sector. Nepal’s rural credit market is dominated by the informal sector.
In repression, access of rural firms or households to financial institutions is
limited and the local money-lenders charge rates of interest that may reflect
market power. Increased competition with formal-sector financial institu-
tions will, over time, increase lending-flows and offer lower rates. The
opening of rural savings windows by formal agencies will enhance savings-
flows throughout the financial system, raising Nepal’s aggregate savings rate.
In addition to the pro-poor effects on employment and income genera-
tion through more efficient capital allocation, the introduction of tech-
nologies will increase transparency and reduce rent-seeking opportunities
of individuals through monopolisation of information. Access to informa-
tion is often excessively priced for the poorest segment of the population.
The use of information technologies also allows for a more efficient fran-
chising and distribution system, and greater bargaining power for the orig-
inal producer against traditional intermediaries who often collect excessive
margins at the expense of the original producer.
In sum, the institutional immaturity of Nepal’s financial sector has pro-
duced the effects that arise from factor appropriation, in this case capital:
reduced co-operation with the other factors, labour and land, investment
tilted towards capital-intensive and unproductive projects; resulting under-
employment and poverty; and, chronic formal and informal credit market
segmentation. While the methods used in the analysis of factor appropria-
tion of returns are on the ‘simple’ side of the evolutionary spectrum, the
empirical application of institutional and evolutionary concepts to Nepal’s
financial sector problems makes a real and measurable difference.
The ADB has responded to the technological and institutional challenge
in the financial sector in Nepal. A series of technical assistance projects
amounting to over $10 million are aimed at improving financial and
corporate governance. This means improving disclosure standards, training
the accounting and auditing professions, updating and completing the legal
framework of the financial sector, and training the judiciary and attorneys
in commercial law and enforcement of contracts in the market framework.
It means modest investment of $10 to $20 million in the information infra-
structure of the financial sector, including an electronic payment system,
Can evolutionary economics make a difference? 333
Firms exist of course not in the abstract but are real, run by entrepreneurs
and helped by people. Variety, for example reflected in differences in
Can evolutionary economics make a difference? 335
Development-policy Responses
Potential
degradation
Spatial pattern of
natural resources
Resource Comparative
use advantage
Comparative Resources
advantage use
Population Investment
growth
system is not taken as being fixed necessarily, but instead as being the result
of an ongoing evolutionary process. Most importantly, it introduces three
behaviours through the use of ‘attractiveness’ which are the demand attrac-
tiveness, migration attractiveness and investment attractiveness. These are
the mechanisms by which small differences in price, incentives and pro-
ductivity can be amplified through self-reinforcing processes, eventually
leading to a spatial restructuring of the system. Economic incentives and
investment attractiveness create the opportunity of employment, increase
the vacancies and raise labour productivity, leading to increases in employ-
ment levels and wages. The improved income-earning opportunity will
alter relative economic conditions among the regions and increase migra-
tion of the workforce, which in turn will alter relative investment behaviour
of sectors.
The model considers how the lower prices of delivery result in con-
sumers spending their gains on extra consumption that, in turn, generates
more jobs. The model therefore responds to the reduced prices by examin-
ing how much the different income classes are affected and how they may
choose to spend the resulting income. Savings will affect income groups
differently, as those that spend more save more in absolute terms, but the
poor will be able to buy more food, and also if jobs available in the indus-
trial and service sectors increase, then this will also increase the income of
some of the poor.
338 The political economy of complexity
The model uses three sectors (k) for its operation: agriculture, industry
and services. One of the first steps therefore was to aggregate the data
concerning transport into these categories.
The flows of goods are generated by the fact that the spatial distribution
of demand does not coincide with that of supply. For example, the city of
Calcutta clearly requires large quantities of food, but has no agricultural
land available to produce it. The cost of transportation, however, acts as a
‘net loss’ to the ‘utility’ of consumers, since they must pay for it, but only
because they want the goods that it brings.
The model allows us to follow the manner in which the increased demand
from each point falls onto the different zones of production and leads to
the possibility of increased production. This in turn requires jobs to be
created and filled, which means that people must be available to fill them.
The demographic increase in each zone provides a growing number of
people seeking jobs, but this may be insufficient in some zones, and too
great in others. The actual growth of active, filled jobs therefore reflects the
changing distribution of population between the zones, and the migratory
flows that tend to reflect the job opportunities. Moreover, different wage
levels available in the sectors will also allow growth in a higher-paying
sector at the expense of a lower-paying one. Another factor that is import-
ant is the availability of land for economic activities. For example, clearly
there is a very large demand for agricultural products in Calcutta, but there
is no space to make fields and grow crops and so instead, jobs are not
created and filled (despite the demand) and food is transported into the city.
The model takes into account these different factors, and calculates
where economic growth will occur, by sector and zone. This allows us to
track the changes in employment for the 33 different spatial zones in West
Bengal, and to use this as a base for a comparison with the changes that
occur when different transport infrastructure projects are implemented.
The model runs these mechanisms over the 33 different spatial zones, and
also for the different sectors of the economy. Population is attracted to
places of perceived employment opportunity and this allows vacancies to
be transformed into jobs. This increases the local income, and hence the
demand emanating from the zone.
The non-linear dynamic model will generate changes resulting from the
reduced prices of goods in different zones, adjusting supply and demand
arriving at each zone to equality, and changing the distribution of jobs to
reflect the relative locations of the demand and of transportation costs. By
running the model with no modifications in the transportation-matrix
costs, we can generate a ‘base scenario’. This can then be compared with a
run in which the costs of transportation have been changed as a result of
some investment in an infrastructure project.
Can evolutionary economics make a difference? 339
The model can then compare various differences between the two simu-
lations. First, there is the amount of ‘extra income’ available for spending
in any particular zone. This can further be broken down into that arising
for the poor, medium and rich income-groups. In addition however, we can
see the difference in the distribution of jobs over time. This changes the
income distribution within each zone and changes the proportions of the
different income groups. It also changes the overall income generated in a
zone, and hence contributes to the benefits.
The data supplied were the comparative transportation costs in 2015,
with or without the project, and again in 2025 with and without the
project. The ‘with or without’ differences reveal the spatial distribution of
consequences of the project, the impacts on employment, and on the
different income groups of the zone. For 2015, the overall gain is some
40 000 jobs. These extra jobs can immediately translate into a gain for the
poor of each zone. This is because these are ‘new jobs’ in addition to those
that would have existed without the infrastructure investment. For deci-
sion-making purposes, when we take out these results from the evolution-
ary model into the simple conceptual frame of a cost-benefit analysis, we
can find a difference in results resulting from the use of a more complex
model. If we multiply the 40 000 by the average wages per job, then we find
about 600 million Rs per year. In addition to this, there are the effects on
external trade, and also the savings in consumption costs as a result of the
cheaper transportation. These two effects add up to a nominal consumer
surplus for 2015 of about 19 billion Rs. For 2025, the extra jobs generated
are estimated at about 117 000, which are worth about 1.7 billion Rs. The
consumer surplus attributed to investment multiplies to 50 billion Rs. by
2025.
Interpolating the continuing growth of the investment benefits between
the first investment year 2002, and 2025 (a gestation period of some 20 to
30 years is normal in large infrastructure projects), one gets a cost/benefit
stream as shown in Table 14.1. The stream is discounted at 12 per cent, and
results in a net present value (NPV) of about 28.9 billion Rs. In the table,
I have separated out the benefit stream calculated for the poorer section of
West Bengal’s population. As a percentage, a share of 21.5 per cent of the
overall benefit stream accrues to the poor.
What difference does the evolutionary approach employed make to the
outcome? We would know, had a conventional cost-benefit model been
used in parallel. In fact, the transportation consultant used a conventional
linear trade, transport and logistics model, as outlined in Figure 14.2.
Linear traffic forecasts induce transport-cost savings (consumer surplus).
In addition, a reduction in transport logistics costs induces demand for
both domestically consumed and internationally traded goods. The latter
340 The political economy of complexity
Logistics chain
performance
Logistics chain exports, base –
performance (Rs, duration)
domestic, base – – Stuffing/de-stuffing
(Rs, duration) – Waiting
– Loading/unloading – Port handling costs
– Transporting – Shipping costs
– Modal seams – Agency costs
– Damaged/stolen goods – Packing costs
Transport
infrastructure,
operational, procedural
improvements
Logistics cost
Logistics cost
savings – domestic
savings – exports
movements
decision maker using the output of these individual projects would con-
clude that it was wise to not invest in the lowest-return project, so as not
to lower the average return on investment. This however has the effect that
one corner-stone project along the entire transport and trade chain is
eliminated, with dramatic effects, as the largest part of the multiplier gains
are lost. The evolutionary model did take into account the multiplier
gains that accrue to the whole system by combining the four investments
in one model, and achieving a combined EIRR on combined investment
of some 20 billion Rs. This is an extra NPV of $500 million (which is
equivalent to $5 billion in nominal benefits, with an estimated 21 per cent
going to the poor)!
As significant as the differences between the use of an evolutionary and
a neoclassical approach turned out to be, it should be noted here that the
evolutionary model was much less of an evolutionary model than would be
ideally wanted. Although the model used increasing returns from invest-
ment, and was based on geography and positive agglomeration and
network effects, it fell short in not modelling behavioural differences among
actors, such as employers along the trade corridor. The model lacks in
reality because it cannot generate learning among actors, and it does not
allow for qualitative systems-change based on actors’ creativity and on a
selection process taking hold. Such a model extension has been proposed
by Allen and Brunner (2001) and Brunner and Allen (2005). Would such
an extension be worthwhile, given the already large gain from using a
simpler non-linear dynamics model? Let us now discuss the issue of geo-
graphy and modelling. How close to reality can (or should) we get without
getting lost in the complexities?
Can evolutionary economics make a difference? 343
1. That we can define a boundary between the part of the world that we
want to ‘understand’ and the rest. In other words, we assume first that
there is a ‘System’ and an ‘Environment’.
2. That we have rules for the classification of objects that lead to a rele-
vant taxonomy for the system components, which will enable us to
understand what is going on. This is often decided entirely intuitively.
3. The third assumption concerns the level of description below that
which we are trying to understand, and assumes all phenomena are
either all identical to each other and to the average, or have a diversity
that is at all times distributed ‘normally’ around the average.
4. That the individual behaviour of sub-components can be described by
average interaction parameters.
The crucial difference that marks out evolutionary (complex) systems con-
cerns assumption 3. This assumes that all firms of a given type, ‘x’ say, are
either identical, equal to the average type; or have a diversity that remains
normally distributed around the average type. This means that for such
models ‘sectors’ or statistical aggregates of ‘firms’ are used as variables
reflecting the ‘average properties’ of the included firms. But in reality, the
microdiversity of behaviours among individual firms in any particular
part of the system is the result of the history of local dynamics occurring
in the system. This local history concerns the local mechanisms by which
knowledge, skills, techniques and heuristics are passed on to new individ-
uals over time. The existence of microdiversity will necessarily lead to an
evolutionary learning process of economic development. If there are firms
Complexity Successive assumptions Simplicity
Reality X X
Z Z
Y Y
344
Changing taxonomy Catalytic sets Stability, resilience,
Learning models… bifurcations,
Creativity + Selection Selection attractors, chaos…
Soft systems
Literature, history, The system just
descriptions… Systems change RUNS. But the
qualitatively... modeller can
Events, and Processes make experiments
Systems diverge…
Figure 14.3 Assumptions made in reducing complexity to simplicity, in order to obtain understanding, and
predictability – providing the assumptions hold
Can evolutionary economics make a difference? 345
with higher and lower productivity then the higher ones will be gradually
amplified, while those with lower productivity are suppressed, and the
‘average’ for the whole population of firms increases productivity (Allen
and McGlade, 1987; Brunner, 1994; Caballero and Hammour, 2000). This
is the mechanism by which adaptation takes place. This demonstrates the
vital part played by exploratory, non-average behaviour, and shows that,
in the long term, evolution selects for firms with the ability to learn, rather
than for populations with optimal, but fixed, behaviour. Economic trans-
formation therefore should really be modelled by these fully evolutionary
models.
As mentioned before, models are always, and to a degree, partial repre-
sentations of the cloud of reality they depict. Models should be detailed
enough to capture all the important causal real-world relationships that
explain outcomes of development. Evolutionary complexity, however,
reduces predictability as non-linear causal relationships, externalities,
network effects, and geography lead to multiple equilibria. Outcomes are
path-dependent, in part matter of chance. In arguing with Krugman (1997)
on the utility of complex models, one needs to show that complex and real-
istic approaches yield results which formalised models in a simple setting
cannot. The West Bengal example shows that models that are complex, and
even those that may take into account heterogeneity of actors, can be tested
for results. Yet even simple models as applied to the analysis of the finan-
cial sector in Nepal, once enriched with institutional concepts such as
transaction costs, yield significant power to make a big difference for eco-
nomic development in Asia and in the effectiveness of resource use by the
ADB and its borrowers.
NOTES
* The author alone in his personal capacity, not the Asian Development Bank, is responsible
for the article’s content. The author thanks the participants of the Wartensee seminar and
is particularly grateful to Kurt Dopfer and John Adams as well as an anonymous referee
for their helpful comments. The usual disclaimer applies.
348 The political economy of complexity
REFERENCES
351
352 Index