Alfred Tarski - Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics. Papers From 1923 To 1938 Clarendon Press (1956) 419 464 PDF
Alfred Tarski - Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics. Papers From 1923 To 1938 Clarendon Press (1956) 419 464 PDF
Alfred Tarski - Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics. Papers From 1923 To 1938 Clarendon Press (1956) 419 464 PDF
ON THE CONCEPT OF L O G IC A L
CONSEQUENCEf
(F) If, in the sentences of the class K and in the sentence X , the
constants—apart from purely logical constants—are replaced by
any other constants (like signs being everywhere replaced by like
signs), and if we denote the class of sentences thus obtained from
K by iK ri, and the sentence obtained from X by 6X'\ then the
sentence X ' must be true provided only that all sentences of the
class K f are true.
[F or the sake o f sim plifying the discussion certain incidental
com plications are disregarded, both here and in what follow s.
They are connected partly with the theory o f logical types, and
partly with the necessity o f eliminating any defined signs which
m ay possibly occur in the sentences concerned, i.e. o f replacing
them by prim itive signs.]
In the statem ent (F ) we have obtained a necessary condition
for the sentence X to be a consequenoe o f the class K . The
question now arises whether this condition is also sufficient.
I f this question were to be answered in the affirmative, the
problem o f form ulating an adequate definition o f the concept
o f consequence w ould be solved affirm atively. The only diffi
culty would be connected with the term ‘true’ which occurs in
the condition ( F ). B ut this term can be exactly and adequately
defined in sem antics .1
U nfortunately the situation is not so favourable. I t m ay, and
it does, happen— it is not difficult to show this b y considering
special form alized languages— that the sentence X does not
follow in the ordinary sense from the sentences o f the class K
although the condition ( F ) is satisfied. This condition m ay in
fa ct be satisfied only because the language with which we are
1 See footnote 2 on p. 414.
41# ON T H E CONCEPT OF LOG ICAL CONSEQUENCE X V I
The sentence X follows fisca lly from the. sentences of the class
K if and only if every model of the class K is also a model of the
sentence X .t
I t seems to me that everyone who understands the content
o f the above definition must adm it that it agrees quite well
with com m on usage. This becom es still clearer from its various
consequences. In particular, it can be proved, on the basis o f
this definition, that every consequence o f true sentences must
be true, and also that the consequence relation which holds
between given sentences is com pletely independent o f the sense
o f the extra-logical constants which occur in these sentences.
In brief, it can be shown that the condition (F ) form ulated
above is necessary if the sentence X is to follow from the sen
tences o f the class K . On the other hand, this condition is in
general not sufficient, since the concept o f consequence here
defined (in agreement with the standpoint we have taken) is-
independent o f the richness in concepts o f the language being
investigated.
Finally, it is not difficult to reconcile the proposed definition
with that o f Carnap. F or we can agree to call a class o f sentences
t After the original of this paper had appeared in print, K . Scholz in his
article ‘ Die Wistenschaftslehxe Bc-lzanos, Eine Jahrhundert-Betrachtung’,
AbhancUungen der Fri&s'schen Schule, new series, vol. 6, pp. $99-472 (see in
particular p. 472, footnote 58) pointed out a far-reaching analogy between this
definition of consequence and the one suggested by B. Bolzano about a
hundred years earlier.
418 ON TH E CONCEPT OP LO G IC AL CONSEQUENCE XVI
1 Cf. Carnap, B . (10), pp. 135 ff., especially Tbs. 52.7 and 62.8; Carnap, B .
(11), p. 182, Ths. 10 and 11. Incidentally I should like to remark that the
definition of the concept of oonsequence hare proposed does not exceed the
limits of syntax in Carnap's conception (cf. Carnap, R. (10), pp. 6 £f.). Ad
mittedly the general concept of satisfaction (or of model) does not belong to
syntax; but we use only a special case of this oonoept— the satisfaction of
sentential funotions whioh contain no extra-logioal constants, and this special
case can be characterized using only general logical and specifio syntactical
eonoepts. Between the general concept of satisfaction and the special case of
this concept used here approximately the same relation holds as between the
semantical concept of true sentence and the syntactical oonoept of analytical
sentence.
X V I ON TH E CONCEPT OF LOG ICAL CONSEQUENCE 419
§ 2. T he Ma t r ix M ethod
The definitions in § I afford no criterion that would enable
us to decide in each particular case whether a giv^en sentence 21
is provable in the two-valued or in the intuitionistic calculus.
Such a criterion is provided by the so-called ^matrix method.3
If
D e f in it io n 2 . 8.
M = [ i f , A , *■>, T , Jo, ~ ] and Mx = [ ify, A , »-*•, T , J>,
aretwomatrices a n d ifif £ s IT , then Mxi,s called a subm atrix 0/ M.
I f M is any matrix and Mx is a submairix of
Co b o l la e y 2.9.
M, then ®(M) £ «(M X). [B y 2 . 1, 2.5, 2 . 8]
2 . 10. We denote by ZK the ordered sextuple
D e f in it io n
[ i f , 1, *-*, Jo, where i f = ( 0 , l), x = l-x -\ -x .y ,
s ! T y = x-\-y—x .y ,x J o y ~ x .y ,a n d ~ x = 1—xfor aUx,y e i f .
The follow ing result is well known:
T h e o r e m 2.11. ZK is a matrix and ®(ZK) = 3 ft .1
F or the system 3 ft there is, in contrast to 3 ft. no adequate
m atrix with a finite value system .2 W e can, however, con
struct an infinite sequence o f m atrioes IK*,..., iK „,... with finite
00
value system s such that JX ®(IKn) = 3 ft. W e shall now de-
1
scribe the construction o f this sequenoe .8
Let M — [#^ , B, »-*, t , JU,
D e f in it io n 2 . 12. be a matrix
and A any element which does not belong to if* We put:
(i) i f * = if+ {A }\
(ii) l H * r = I n 7 if X t Y e i f and X +*Y B;
X *+ *Y — A if X , Y e i f and X ++ Y =* B; X *+ *A ~ A for
X e i f * ; A *+*Y * 7 for Y e i f * ;
(iii) X y *Y = X r Y f o r X , Y e i f ; Z r * A = A r * Z = A
for Z e i f * ;
(iv) X L * 7 = X j * Y for X , Y e i f ; Z ^ * A = A<L*Z =-- Z
for Z e H r*;
(v) ~ * X = ~ X if X e i f and ~ X j* B; ~ * X — A if
X e i f and ~-5T = B; r*J*A — ■ —‘B.
The ordered sextuple [ i f *, A , »-**, T * , Jo *, <--'*] is denoted
by M*.
1 2.11 easily results from the well-known theorem according to which the
system 3& is complete. The first completeness proof for is due to Poet, E.
(60), pp. 180
3 Cf. Gddel, K , (23), p. 40.
4 This result is due to Jaskowski, S, (36). (Our account deviates only in in
essentials from that of Jankowski. The operation T of Ja&kcwski is replaced
by the operation * defined in 2.12, which serves the same purpose.)
X V n, f 2 SENTENTIAL CALCULUS AND TOPOLOGY 427
a matrix. We put:
(i) i f n = the system of ordered n-tuples [X lv .., X n] with
X t , . . . , Xn Gi f ;
(ii) A n — [X j,..., X n], where X x — ... — X n = A ;
(Hi) [X » ,...,X J » » [ 7 x,...,Yn] = [X x » Y x,...,Xn » Y n]for
X x,..., X n, !F],..., Yn g ;
(iv), (v) analogously for T and ;
(vi) [X x,..., X n] — [ ~ X 1,..., ~ X n] for X x,...,Xn g i f .
[ i f n, A n, cA, ” , ^ n] is called the ?ith power of the matrix
M and is denoted by ‘ Mn’ .
2.16. I f n is a natural number and M is a matrix,
Co b o l la b y
then Mn is also a matrix and we have ®(Mn) — G(M); if Mx and
Ma are isomorphic matrices, then MjJ and Ma are also isomorphic.
[B y 2 . 1, 2.3, 2.5, 2,15]
n « ( ik j -
n=-l
Note 2.19. It is known that this theorem can be improved:
with every sentence 21 a well-determined natural number can
be correlated (depending exclusively on the structure of this
sentence) such that the formulas 2Ie©(IKrJ and 21 e are
equivalent.1
The decision criterion mentioned at the beginning of this sec
tion is provided by 2.11 for the system 3 & and by 2.IB in its
improved form just mentioned for the system
§ 3. T opological Spaces 3
We first recall some familiar topological concepts:
D e f in it io n3.1. A non-empty set 8 is called a topological space
(with fundamental operation ~), if the follovnng conditions arc
satisfied:
(i) if X c S, then X = X c S;
(ii) if X c S and X consists of at most one dement, then X = X\
(iii) i f X c= S and ¥ c S, then X + Y = X + 7 .
Note 3.2. Let S he a topological space and A a non-empty
subset ot S. We now define an operation ~~'A) relative to A by
the formuia X U} A . X for every X c A . On the basis of
3.1 it can then easily be shown that A is a topological spa.ee with
the fundamental operation ~(A'}: such a space is called a sub
space of S.
D efin itio n 3.3. I f 8 is a topological space, , a set X is said to
be open (in S), in symbols X e 0(8), if X = S—8 —X.
D efin itio n 3.4. A subset X of a topological space 8 is said to
be dense (in 8) if X = 8 .
1 See p. 420, note X
3 Another decision criterion for the intuitionistic calculus was given in
Gentzen, G. (18).
3 For what follows ei\ Kuratowski, C. (41), in particular pp. 15 ff., 38, 40,
82 f., 95, and 101 ff.
X V n, § 8 S E N T E N T IA L CALCULUS AN D TO P O LO G Y 429
(26) Bj = 2 i /o r j = 1, 2,..., n.
XeJT*
From (18), (19), (23), (24), and (26) it is seen at once that the
sets 2^ ,,.., Bn just defined satisfy the condition (6 ). B y (IS).
(23) , and (26) we have ■ # * + „ . — Gj1- f ^ B and
consequently A — (1 ?!+ ... ~r~Bn) 5 A —B. H ence b y means o f (9)
and ( 10) we obtain ( 6) and (7). Finally, let us suppose that the
form ula B} 2 A — ...+ i ? n) does not hold for a given
j , 1 < j < n. W e thus have
(3) X = ( S - 7 ) -r (Y -*■ Z) — S - ( S - Y ) - ( S - Y - Z ) .
35t c ® ( 0 (S)).
[B y 1.4, 4.9, 4.10]
T heorem 4.12. For every topological space S and every sen
tence 91 the conditions 91 e 3$t cwd ^ ^91 e ® ( 0 (£ )) are equiva
lent. [B y 1.6 , 4.8, 4.11]
In view o f Ths. 4.8 and 4.11, the double inclusion
35t £ ® (0 ($ )) £ 3*t holds for every topological space S. W e
shall now show that there exist spaces 8 for which (£(0(S)) = 3&
and also spaces S for whioh ® ( 0 ($ )) = 351. In fa ct the first
equality holds if and only if S is an isolated (and thus, so to
speak, a degenerate) space. The second holds for all i?-spaces,
and thus in particular for all norm al spaces which are dense-
in-them selves and have a countable basis (cf. 3.9-3.11).
XVII, § 4 S E N T E N T IA L CALCULUS AND TO P O LO G Y 437
8 - 8 - 8 ^ { x } £ S-{x},
3* s *(om,
whence, on account o f 4.8, <E(0(8)) *= If> conversely, this
latter equality is satisfied, then the system <E(0(iS)) contains
in particular all sentences 91 o f the form 91— ( ^ 93 93) -> 93
(cf. 1.2 (x) and 1.4); in view o f 4.13 the space S is therefore
isolated, q.e.d.
B efore continuing we shall subject the operations -> and -a.
to a relativization (cf. 3.2).
I f 8 is a topological space and A £ 8, then
D e f in it io n 4.16.
for all sets X £ 8 and 7 £ 8 we put:
(i) 7 = A -X -7 ,
(ii) X = X 0 ( — A~~Xj\
A A
L e m m a 4.21. Premisses:
(a) S is a topological space;
05) Bu ...,Bn e<9{8),Bx,...,Bnare non-empty, pair-un.se disjoint
sets, Bx-{- **.~\~Bn “ B and Bx. ... *Bn 2 5
(y) /o r = 1, 2,..., n, SPp is a system of open sets X £ Bp;
(8) if X , Y eSfp (p = 1, 2 ,..., n) and X —T ^ 0 , then
X = Y 2 Bp- B p ,
(e) M = [if''', A , »-», T , JL>, ~ ] is a matrix-,
(£) forp = 1 , 2 , . . . , M„ = [<5% V, A , ^ a matrix
and is isomorphic with M;
(>j) i f is the system of sets X = X x+ ...-| -X n, where
X xe X ti e S?n, and P = [$?, B , A , V , 'A -
x» £>
Conclusions:
(i) Se' is a system of open sets X £ B-,
(ii) if X , Y e 6? and X - Y # 0 , then X ^ Y 2 B - B ;
(iii) P is a matrix and is isomorphic with M77.
Proof. The assertion (i), i.e.
( 1) 9 is a system of open sets X c B,
results easily from (j8), (y), and ( 77); since, b y 3.1 and 3.3, every
sum o f open sets is itself an open set.
In, order to prove (ii) we consider tw o arbitrary sets X ,Y e 9
such that X —Y ^ 0. B y ( 17),
X = X x+ . . . + X n and Y = T1+ ...+ Y n9
where X p, Yp e 9 p for p = 1, 2 ,..., n. Since, in view o f (y) and
{fi), we have X p s Bpi Yp ^ Bp and the sets Bn are pair
wise disjoint we obviously have
x - y - ( z 1+ . . . + x j - ( i i + . . . + r n)
= ( x 1- r 1) + ...+ ( x n- r n);
if, therefore, X —Y ^ 0 , there m ust be aj>, 1 < p ^ n, such that
Xp—Yp # 0 . H ence b y (8) w e get X p—Yp 2 Bp—Bp and
consequently X —Y 2 Bp—Bp, because b y (a) and 3.1 (iii) '
z -r = z1-:r1-f...-fz„-r,,
442 S E N T E N T IA L C A L C U L U S A N D T O P O L O G Y XVH, § 4
- % Flm + - + ( F n(un) f m )
From this with the help o f (7) and 3.1 (iii) we obtain
B y means o f 2,1, 2.15, and 2.16 we infer from (4), (5), (9)—(11)
that B e S? and is dosed under V , A , -v ; hi view o f
B B
(*))> (1)* aJid 4.17 (ii), P is thus a matrix. We also oondude—
again from (4), (6), (9), (10), (11)—that the matrices P and Mn
satisfy the conditions o f the definition 2.3; consequently we have
(12) P is a matrix isomorphic with Mn.
B y (1), (11), and (12), all the conclusions o f the lemma are
satisfied.
L em UA 4.22. Premisses:
(a) 8 is an E-space)
(ft) M is a matrix;
(y) for every non-empty Set Be 0(8) there is a system $P of open
sets X £ A with the following properties:
(Yi) if X, Y e S? and X —Y ^ 0* then X — Y 2 B —B;
(y*) M' *** [ y , B, V , A , ■+*] is a matrix which is isomor-
Jo JB
phic with M.
444 8 E N T E N T IA L CALCULU S AND T O P O LO G Y X V II, § 4
P = [ < ? ,£ , - + , V, A, - ] . ,
B B
B y (a), (/?), ( 1), ( 2 ), and (5 )-(9 ) the premisses o f 4.21 are satis
fied. Consequently we have
( 10) SP is a system of open sets X £ A ;
( 11) if X , Y e S* and X —Y ^ 0, then X —Y 2 B —B;
(12) P is a matrix which is isomorphic with Mn.
XVH , $ 4 S E N T E N T IA L C A L C U L U S A N D T O P O L O G Y 446
L et
(13) and N = A,->, v : A ,
A -cL
B y (a), (l)-(4 ), and (9)—(13), the premisses o f 4.20 hold. Conse
quently,
(14) F is a system of open sets X Q A ;
(15) i f X , Y e J T and X - Y ^ 0, t h e n X - Y 2 A ~ A \
(16) N is a matrix and N = P*.
From (12) and (16) b y means o f 2.14 we obtain
(17) N is a matrix which is isomorphic with (M7*)*.
In view o f (14), (15), and (17) the p roof o f Lem m a 4.22 is
com plete.
L em m a 4.23. I f 8 is an E-space, then for every natural number
n the matrix 0 ( 8 ) contains a submatrix which is isomorphic
with IKn.
Proof. B y means o f an inductive procedure we shall establish
a logically stronger conclusion, nam ely
( 1) for every non-empty set A e d)(8) there is a system 3T of open
sets X c; A with the following properties:
(i) if X 9 Y e 3T and X —Y ^ 0, then X —Y 2 A —A;
(ii) N - [AT, A , - k V , A , -v-] is a matrix isomorphic with
jA a
IKn-
In fa ct b y 2.17 and 4.19, ( 1) holds for n = 1. Assuming that
( 1) is satisfied for a given natural n we apply 4.22 (with M = IKn)
and w ith the help o f 2.17 we easily see that (1) also holds fo r n -j-l.
I f we now put A = 8 in ( 1) we at once obtain the conclusion o f
the lem m a from 2.8, 3.1, 3.2, 4.5, and 4.18.
T heobbm 4.24. I f 8 is an E-space, then G (Q (S )) = 3 ft.
Proof. B y 4.23 there is for every natural n a subm atrix Nn
w hich is isom orphic w ith IKn. N ow , if 31 e © ( 0 (# )), then b y 2.9
and 2.7 we have 31 e ® (N „) = ®(IKn) for n = 1, 2,... and con
sequently, b y 2.18,31 e 3 ft. A ccordingly, © ( 0 ($ )) £ 3 ft; hence
b y 4.9 we at on ce obtain © (O (8)) = 3 ft, q.e.d.
446 S E N T E N T IA L CALCULUS AN D T O P O L O G Y X V II, § 4
Iv T = S —S—X —Y
(X v Y is thus the smallest regular open set which includes X
and Jr). It can then be shown that the matrix
O '(S ) = [ 0 '( £ ) , 8, V A , -V]
XVn, $ 4 S E N T E N T IA L CALCULU S A N D T O P O L O G Y 44«
Note 5 . 2* I t can be shown that form ulas (iii) and (vi) in 5.1
can be replaced b y the follow ing equivalent conditions:
(iii') there is an element u e R such that
x = y+u = u + y;
D e f in it io n 6.7. IfRisaB<xdeanring,th&nforanyI, J e S { R )
we put
(i) y x-,
XeJ'(,R?J.Xcj
(ii) / V J = TT Xi
XeSa$)J+J£X
(Hi) l A J — I .J (the intersection of I and J):
(iv) ^ i = i-+{o} (= 2 x).
' M K I X X -W '
Prom 6.1, 5.6, and 5.7 we easily obtain
C o r o l l a r y 5 .8 . For every Boolean ring R we have
(i) {0}, R e J(R), and in fact {0} is the smallest and R the
largest ideal in R;
(ii) if I, J e*f(R) then I -> J , I v J , I A «/, - v / are ideaZs jR,
in fact I J is the largest ideal X for which I .X £ J and ^-1
the largest ideal X for which I .X = {0}, moreover, J V J is the
smallest ideal which includes I and J> finally IA J is the largest
ideal which is included in I and J ♦
D efin ition 5.9. The ordered sextuple [,/(2 ?), R, V , A , ^ ],
where R is a Boolean ringy is denoted by I(i?).
The follow ing well-known theorem exhibits a close form al
connexion between B oolean algebra and topology1:
T heorem 5.10. A normal topological space JBX, which satisfies
thefollowing conditions, can be correlated with every Boolean ring R :
(i) there is a function F which maps the system S(R) onto the
system &(RX) in such a way that the formulas
Ic:J and F{I)czF{J)
are equivalent for all / , J e*f(R) (in particular J^({0}) = 0 and
F(R) = B*);
(ii) R x is isolated if and only if R is atomistic;
(iii) R* is dense in itself if and only if R is atomless;
(iv) R x is a space with a countable basis if and only if R is
denumerable.
1 See Stone, M. H . (68).
462 S E N T E N T IA L CALCULUS A N D TO P O LO G Y XVU, f 6